Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

As If God Existed: Religion and Liberty in the History of Italy
As If God Existed: Religion and Liberty in the History of Italy
As If God Existed: Religion and Liberty in the History of Italy
Ebook618 pages14 hours

As If God Existed: Religion and Liberty in the History of Italy

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Religion and liberty are often thought to be mutual enemies: if religion has a natural ally, it is authoritarianism--not republicanism or democracy. But in this book, Maurizio Viroli, a leading historian of republican political thought, challenges this conventional wisdom. He argues that political emancipation and the defense of political liberty have always required the self-sacrifice of people with religious sentiments and a religious devotion to liberty. This is particularly the case when liberty is threatened by authoritarianism: the staunchest defenders of liberty are those who feel a deeply religious commitment to it.


Viroli makes his case by reconstructing, for the first time, the history of the Italian "religion of liberty," covering its entire span but focusing on three key examples of political emancipation: the free republics of the late Middle Ages, the Risorgimento of the nineteenth century, and the antifascist Resistenza of the twentieth century. In each example, Viroli shows, a religious spirit that regarded moral and political liberty as the highest goods of human life was fundamental to establishing and preserving liberty. He also shows that when this religious sentiment has been corrupted or suffocated, Italians have lost their liberty.


This book makes a powerful and provocative contribution to today's debates about the compatibility of religion and republicanism.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateSep 9, 2012
ISBN9781400845514
As If God Existed: Religion and Liberty in the History of Italy
Author

Maurizio Viroli

Maurizio Viroli is professor emeritus of politics at Princeton University, professor of government at the University of Texas, Austin, and professor of political communication at the University of Italian Switzerland in Lugano. His many books include Niccolò's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli (Hill & Wang) and Redeeming "The Prince": The Meaning of Machiavelli's Masterpiece (Princeton).

Read more from Maurizio Viroli

Related to As If God Existed

Related ebooks

European History For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for As If God Existed

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    As If God Existed - Maurizio Viroli

    AS IF GOD EXISTED

    AS IF GOD EXISTED

    RELIGION AND LIBERTY

    IN THE HISTORY OF ITALY

    Maurizio Viroli

    Translated by Alberto Nones

    Copyright © 2012 by Princeton University Press

    Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street,

    Princeton, New Jersey 08540

    In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street,

    Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW

    press.princeton.edu

    Jacket Art: Allegory of Good Government, 1338–40 (fresco),

    Ambrogio Lorenzetti (1285–c. 1348). Location: Palazzo Pubblico,

    Siena, Italy. Courtesy of Bridgeman Art Library.

    All Rights Reserved

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Viroli, Maurizio.

    [Come se Dio ci fosse. English]

    As if God existed : religion and liberty in the history of Italy / Maurizio Viroli;

    translated by Alberto Nones.

    p. cm.

    Includes bibliographical references (p.      ) and index.

    ISBN 978-0-691-14235-7 (hardcover : alk. paper)

    1. Liberty—History. 2. Religion and politics—Italy—History. 3. Religion

    and state—Italy—History. I. Title.

    JC599.I8V5713 2012

    320.94501’1—dc23

    2012015124

    British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available

    This book has been composed in Sabon LT std.

    Printed on acid-free paper. ∞

    Printed in the United States of America

    1  3  5  7  9  10  8  6  4  2

    To Gabriella, Giulia, Simona, and Tino

    After all, the man who does not believe in God also feels, in the end, that his morality is like a religion, although he does not like to abuse this term. He feels it is some sort of religion, for it is something he is ready to discuss, but with the certainty that no one will convert him. He has grown old with that faith; he has spoken with many people; he has put his ideas to all tests and comparisons. He knows well that his force of persuasion is meager, that his arguments should always be renewed, and that he has something to learn from each and every interlocutor. But all this no longer affects the firmness of his faith. In this sense, he belongs to a church, which admits of no betrayal on the part of its clerics. To work for this church, to promote the increment of its believers—this is the most proper job for a man. In this job lay the worth and value of his whole existence.

    —Guido Calogero, La scuola dell’uomo, 1939

    CONTENTS

    PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH EDITION

    Introduction

    PART I A REPUBLICAN CHRISTIANITY

    1 Republics Protected by God

    2 Images of the Civil Religion

    3 Republican and Monarchical Religion

    4 A Religion That Instills Virtue

    5 Sacred Laws and Sacred Republics

    6 Republican Religion and Religious Reform

    7 A Religion to Live Free

    8 Within the Soul

    9 The Twilight of Republican Religion

    PART II RELIGIOUS REBIRTH AND NATIONAL EMANCIPATION

    10 Without God

    11 After the Revolution

    12 The New Alliance

    13 Literature and Hymns of the Religion of Liberty

    14 Apostles and Martyrs

    15 Masters

    16 Regrets and the Quest for New Faiths

    PART III THEY GOT TOO CLOSE TO THE LIGHT

    17 Two Clashing Religions

    18 In the Name of Christ

    19 Inner Liberty

    20 The Religion of Liberty

    21 A Religion That Instills Hope

    22 The Religion of Duty

    23 As If God Existed

    24 Only a God Can Expel a God

    25 Leaving Life

    26 Twilight

    NOTES

    INDEX

    PREFACE TO THE ENGLISH EDITION

    THIS EXPLORATION OF Italian history offers English-speaking readers a general, valuable lesson on the relationship between liberty and religion. My study focuses on three experiences of social and political emancipation in Italy: the free republics of the thirteenth to sixteenth centuries, the Risorgimento, and the antifascist Resistenza (also called the Second Risorgimento). Grand and noble as they were, none of these experiences resulted in long-lasting liberty: early modern city republics were all (with the exception of Venice) consumed and destroyed by open or veiled forms of tyranny, and by the mid-sixteenth century Italy fell under foreign domination; the liberal state created by the Risorgimento collapsed sixty years later under the yoke of the fascist regime; and the Italian Republic that was born in 1946 and was to a considerable degree the expression of the antifascist struggle has degenerated into Silvio Berlusconi’s court system.¹ Italy, to aptly describe its political identity, is a country marked by fragile liberty.

    In each case, religious sentiments and language played a fundamental role. City-republics were sustained by a civic religion that combined in a rather innovative way classical and biblical themes. The Risorgimento was preceded and accompanied by a religious renaissance made possible by the rediscovery and reinterpretation of Christianity, as well as the elaboration of various forms of religion of duty or religion of humanity. The antifascist movement found inspiration in the religion of liberty framed by Benedetto Croce and other political writers.

    The corruption and decline of political liberty, too, has been related to religious conceptions and practices. City-republics were first enervated by the degeneration of Christianity into a religion that fiercely opposed civic virtue, and then inundated by the religion of the Counter-Reformation with its fervor for appearances and exteriority along with its moral teaching founded on docility, submission, and simulation. Fascism triumphed over the liberal state, proclaiming a new religion of the nation. To a considerable degree, the decline of the democratic republic is a consequence of the neglect and destruction of what was left of the civil religion of the Risorgimento and Resistenza. Italian history, then, seems to teach us that good religion produces political liberty, whereas irreligiosity, or bad religion, produces tyranny and domination. The words good and bad here refer only to the moral and political content of religions.

    This book challenges the well-established view that Italian political thought of the Renaissance drew its language from classical Greek and Roman texts, and only to a negligible extent from biblical and religious sources.² The truth is that as early as the thirteenth century, one of the most important sources of humanist political thought can be found in prehumanist tracts on civil government—a wealth of biblical references and religious arguments invoked to elucidate the nature of republican government.³ All these texts make abundant use of biblical quotations to stress the sacred dimension of the republican regime as well as to argue for peace and concord. They speak with the selfsame voice to emphasize that republics need God’s help, and that to obtain it, rulers must sincerely fear God and protect the Catholic faith. To urge the podestà (the highest magistrate of the city) to wholeheartedly respect human and divine laws, the author of one of the oldest tracts on republican government cites Matt. 5:14–16: You are the light of the world. A city set on a hill cannot be hid. Nor do men light a lamp and put it under a bushel, but on a stand, and it gives light to all in the house. Let your light so shine before men, that they may see your good works and give glory to your Father who is in heaven. The ruler who oppresses his subjects from an excessive desire for power, on the contrary, spreads darkness on the earth and extinguishes the love for God in the hearts of the citizens.

    Italian political theorists and jurists relied on both classical and biblical sources. Brunetto Latini’s highly influential Livres dou Tresor (ca. 1260), for instance, begins its section on politics by citing Aristotle’s view that the government of the city is the noblest and highest science, and the noblest occupation on earth, and then turns to Cicero’s definition: the city is an association of men who live in the same place and in accordance with a single law.⁴ But then he rapidly refers to the Old Testament to emphasize that all dominions and dignities are conferred on us by our sovereign Father, who, in the sacred order of earthly things, wanted the cities’ government to be founded on three pillars, that is, justice, reverence, and love. Reverence for God, he enjoins, quoting the apostle, is the only thing in the world that augments the faith’s merits and overcomes every sacrifice.

    Prehumanist and early humanist political writers contended that rulers must devoutly practice the political virtues of justice, fortitude, prudence, and temperance, as well as the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity. They contributed to creating a republican religion founded on the beliefs that the commune is under the protection of God, Christ, and the patron saints, and that divine help is the true bulwark against sedition, discord, tyranny, and war—the mortal enemies of republican liberty. The man who undertakes the task of governing acquires a dignity that increases his likeness to God, and impels him always to follow both the political and the theological virtues. Prominent among these virtues are charity—love for God and men—and justice, understood as God’s command. The principles of republican government, therefore, were not only moral and political maxims dictated by reason and prudence but also religious principles.

    Rather than expelling God and Christian religion from acceptable political discourse, Italian republican theorists and republican governments put them at the center of public spaces. The most spectacular evidence is the iconography in the public buildings of Italian city-republics like the Palazzo Publico in Siena, the Palazzo Vecchio in Florence, and the Palazzo Ducale in Venice. Ambrogio Lorenzetti’s Buongoverno (1339–41) openly instructs Siena’s rulers and citizens that the holy virtue of justice draws inspiration from divine wisdom—indeed from the Book of Wisdom—and that the supreme magistrate must follow the theological virtues of faith, hope, and charity. Siena’s republican elite was so far from secular that it gave money to see its city described and exalted as the city of the Virgin. In the Anticappella, again in the Palazzo Publico, Taddeo di Bartolo’s Cycle of Famous Men (1413–14) features Aristotle as the proper guide for learning the principles of good government. But Aristotle and the great Roman republican heroes are accompanied by the image of Religion, who issues an unequivocal Christian injunction: Omne quodcumque facitis in verbo aut in opera / In nomine domini Iesu Christi facite (Whatever you do in words or deeds / Do it in the name of Jesus Christ).

    Florentine republican iconography, too, was for the most part inspired by religious and biblical sources. One of the symbols of Florentine republican ideology was in fact David, the biblical hero who, alone and armed only with a sling, decides to confront the gigantic Goliath and overcomes him. Another was Judith, the woman who killed Holofernes, chief of the Assyrians, oppressors of the Jews. David’s and Judith’s bronze statues, carved by Donatello, were prominently displayed in the Palazzo Vecchio. To leave no doubt about the religious character of their popular government, Florentine leaders decided in 1494 to inscribe in the Palazzo Vecchio Girolamo Savonarola’s motto proclaiming that the Great Council was given by God, and anyone who tried to undo it, would come to no good.⁶ They also agreed, again following Savonarola, to declare Christ King of Florence.

    The Venetians went even further. In the late sixteenth century, in the Palazzo Ducale, they installed nothing less than a gigantic representation of paradise executed by Tintoretto so as to bring the kingdom of heaven in the Great Council Hall. As has been aptly remarked, the civic message of the painting was clear: In a supreme statement of the grandeur, power and piety of one of the longest lasting republics in history, all the important decisions of state would be made under the auspices of Christ and the Virgin and with the inspiration of the heavenly hosts.⁷ Can this be interpreted as a radical expulsion of God from the public sphere?

    Religious themes are also visible in the works of humanist political thinkers. It is true that, as has been noticed by scholars, there are few biblical references in Petrarch’s Qualis esse debeat qui rempublicam regit.⁸ Yet his political poems abound in religious references. In one of them, in which he exalts Cola di Rienzo’s ephemeral republican experiment in Rome, he copiously resorted to the Bible: When you send your Spirit, / they are created, / and you renew the face of the earth (Ps. 104:30). Then I saw a new heaven and a new earth, for the first heaven and the first earth had passed away, and there was no longer any sea. . . . And he who was seated on the throne said, ‘I am making everything new!’ (Rev. 21:1–5).⁹ In his famous canzone Italia mia, benché il parlar sia indarno, Petrarch appeals to faith in the ruler of the universe as the last remedy and only hope for Italy’s afflictions. When the case required it, as in his political attack against Friar Iacopo Bussolini, who seized power in Pavia, Petrarch did not hesitate to infuse his text with an impressive succession of biblical citations.¹⁰

    Leonardo Bruni does not use biblical citations in his Laudatio Florentinae Urbis, but he invokes God’s protection (and that of the Virgin and Saint John the Baptist) over the city and its popular government in two fundamental parts of his oration: the exordium and the peroration. In another equally meaningful text, the Oratio in funere Johannis Strozzi (1427), Bruni expresses yet another tenet of republican political theology when he assures us that the soul does not die, and that the reward for virtuous deeds goes beyond the brief span of life on earth. On the basis of this argument, he then confidently proceeds to explain that the valiant citizens who sacrifice their lives for their homeland and liberty obtain their fellow citizens’ love on earth as well as eternal beatitude in heaven.¹¹

    Coluccio Salutati, chancellor of the Florentine Republic from 1375 until his death in 1406, and the most towering representative of Italian civic humanism, often invoked God in official and semiofficial letters, and attributed the wise deliberations of the Florentine people in the most dramatic moments of the city’s turbulent life to God’s benevolent intervention.¹² When he praises the excellence of civil laws, he promptly stresses that the purpose of man is not to know God but rather to obtain eternal beatitude through good deeds performed on earth.¹³ In his powerful defense of Florentine liberty, the Invectiva contra Antonium Luschum (1403), Salutati relies heavily on theological-political considerations, beginning with his affirmation that all Florentines are resolved to defend, with God’s help, their most sweet liberty, a celestial good more precious than all the world’s treasures. We have inherited our liberty, Salutati remarks, from our fathers, but we regard it as God’s highest gift and trust that God loves free peoples. Therefore, even if the human mind cannot grasp divine justice’s decrees, it is absurd to think that God will strike down those people who protect liberty on earth and reward the tyrants who offend against it.

    Niccolò Machiavelli, too, the alleged champion of the pagan and secular trend of republican political thought, illustrated a number of fundamental political arguments in religious terms. To reassure princes who deploy cruelty effectively, he writes that they can remedy their standing both with God and with men. To enhance the persuasive power of the Exhortation that ends The Prince, Machiavelli rephrases the biblical Book of Exodus. When he tries in 1521 to lure Cardinal Giulio de’ Medici to commit himself to the grand task of gradually restoring republican institutions in Florence, he confidently uses the conventional trope of God’s love for the founders and reformers of republics.

    Appeals to God and political arguments based on the scriptures flourished during the last Florentine Republic of 1527–30. God was constantly invoked as the city’s protector, the vindicator of the rights of free peoples against the ambitions of kings, emperors, and popes, and the supreme guarantor that the merits of good citizens serving the common good will be properly recognized. Florentine republicans never failed to stress that God was the founder and foundation of their precious liberty—the founder because he gave Florence liberty, and the foundation because only his grace conferred on the city could grant Florentine people the moral strength and wisdom to prevail against the most powerful enemies of liberty.

    Italian republican language of the thirteenth to sixteenth centuries was probably less biblical than that of the seventeenth to eighteenth centuries, but it was deeply religious—that is, inspired by a particular type of religiosity that I describe in this book as civic Christianity. The main principles of the religious sentiment that flourished in Italian republics were that God is charity and charity is God, and that God has created human beings in his image and likeness. From these beliefs followed the moral as well as political command that it is a Christian duty to defend republican liberty and diligently serve the common good.

    Also in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries republican political writers were hoping to resurrect a religion that taught citizens to love liberty and discharge their civic duties. Some of them searched within the Christian tradition for a God who was a friend of political liberty; others, for a brief interlude, tried to implant a new civic religion in Italy modeled after Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s religion civile; still others framed a religion of duty or liberty compatible with, though not identical to, Christian religion. They worried above all about the damaging effects of bad religion as well as the absence of religious sentiment, because they believed that without religion or with a bad religion, republics would be short-lived.¹⁴

    This study also claims that the Italian Risorgimento was anticlerical yet religious. Its most representative political and intellectual leaders, along with the militants who committed themselves to the cause of Italian unity and independence, were all fiercely opposed to the temporal power of the church as well as to the enervating religious and moral education that the Italian clergy had spread over the peninsula. They were also guided and sustained, though, by a religious conception of life that took different forms—reformed Catholicism, Protestantism, New Christianism, religion of humanity, religion of duty, and religion of progress—but taught one and the same principle: namely, devotion to liberty as a sacred duty.

    Just as it is plainly untrue that the Italian Risorgimento was totally secular and even irreligious, it is equally wrong to contend that it was indeed religious in the sense that it produced a nationalist or political religion. Focusing on the locus of profound tropes (spazio delle figure profonde), proponents of a cultural approach have identified in the discursive practices of the Risorgimento the conception of the nation understood as a community of combatants united in a sacred commitment to uphold the quasi-metaphysical entity of the patria/nazione (fatherland/nation), whose distinctive features are kinship (parentela), love/honor/virtue (amore/onore/virtù), and sacrifice (sacrificio), with its grim complements of pain, death, and mourning. The trope of kinship, it should be noted, reveals that the nation was imagined as a community of progeny (comunità di discendenza) that reaches back to great figures of the past who belong by nature to the community they have illuminated with their deeds. It also indicates that the biological nexus between generations and individuals, summarized in the word blood, was regarded as a fundamental feature of the nation. In addition, the religious connotation of the Risorgimento’s nationalism clearly emerges from the relentless use of religious words like regeneration, apostolate, faith, resurrection, holy war, and crusade.¹⁵

    This approach is both praiseworthy and limited. It is praiseworthy insofar as it reminds us that the Risorgimento was not just a political process; it also was sustained by stories, myths, and images that motivated strong passions. The profound tropes of lineage, honor, love, virtue, and sacrifice are particularly powerful in this regard because they connect to primary facts of human experience, such as birth/death, love/hatred, and sexuality/reproduction, and are related to centuries-old discursive practices. It is limited because it obscures a number of specific traits of the political language of the Italian Risorgimento in general and its religious dimension in particular. The profound tropes do not allow us to see, to begin with, the fundamental distinction between patriotism and nationalism.¹⁶ Giuseppe Mazzini and other prominent moral and political leaders of the Risorgimento extolled the ideal of patria, or nation, understood as an association of free and equal citizens that must recognize, respect, and defend its civil, political, and social rights as well as the liberty and dignity of all nations and peoples. They also forcefully rejected the commitment to a nation interpreted as an organic cultural and ethnic community that must protect and affirm itself through purification, the elimination of alien elements, both within the nation and through conflict with other nations.

    It is one thing to preach love, devotion, faith, and sacrifice in relation to the universalistic ideal of the patria, and quite another to speak of love, devotion, faith, and sacrifice as regards the particularistic ideal of the nation. In the first case, we have a civil religion centered on the political and moral value of liberty, which sustains liberal and republican institutions; in the second instance, we find a political religion centered on the principles of cultural or ethnic homogeneity and uniqueness, designed to uphold domestic political and social discrimination or aggressive foreign policy. The political language of the Risorgimento, needless to say, presents nationalist features as well, but it is historically incorrect to assert that it was a nationalist political religion.¹⁷

    For a proper understanding of the religious dimension of the Italian Risorgimento, I maintain in this study, the most reliable intellectual mentors are still the great historians of the twentieth century, particularly Adolfo Omodeo and Croce. Both stressed that the Risorgimento proclaimed a universalistic conception of the nation that had nothing in common with the nationalist ideology of fascism, and indeed was unequivocally opposed to it. Because they got the distinction between patriotism and nationalism right, Omodeo and Croce also correctly understood the difference between the fascist political religion and the religious sentiment of the Risorgimento. In the Manifesto of the Antifascist Intellectuals that he composed in 1925 against Giovanni Gentile’s Manifesto of the Fascist Intellectuals, Croce wrote:

    We oppose abandoning our old faith for this chaotic and obscure religion: for two centuries and a half, our faith has been the soul of the Italy that was rising again, modern Italy. That faith was composed of love of truth, aspiration for justice, generous human and civil sense, zeal for an intellectual and moral education, solicitude about liberty, the force behind and guarantee of every advancement. We look at the men of Risorgimento, those who acted, suffered, and died for Italy, and it seems to us that they are offended and concerned by the words and deeds of our adversaries, and admonish us to keep their flag flying. Our faith is not an artificial and abstract contrivance or excitement of the mind provoked by uncertain and badly understood theories, but is the possession of a tradition that has become a disposition of the emotional, mental, and moral habits.¹⁸

    If we misunderstand the specific features of the patriotism that largely pervaded the Risorgimento, as the most recent scholarship does, we also miss the moral and political connection between the Risorgimento and the religion of liberty of the antifascists of the 1920s and 1930s.¹⁹ Colleagues and friends have remarked that the religion of liberty concept must be viewed as an analogy. If they mean by this that the real thing is revealed religion, and that the religion of liberty is similar but not quite the real thing, the argument strikes me as rather weak. For the antifascist militants who lived by it, the religion of liberty was as sincere and thus real as the religion of the believers in revealed religions. One could certainly make the opposite case—namely, that the religiosity of the majority of the Italians who followed the Catholic religion then was a mere facade, whereas the religion of liberty was deep and authentic. The truth of religions does not consist in the alleged or pretended authority of their founders, nor in the magnificence of their rituals, and even less in the number of believers or the religions’ longevity. It consists only in their power to inspire deeds that are consistent with the principles they proclaim. On this score the religion of liberty stands the test quite well.

    That being said, it is surely correct to assert that the religion of liberty notion is a metaphor or analogy. But political thought is full of metaphors and analogies. The great Leviathan, the mortal God, laws are but chains, and the idea that the prince must be able to imitate both the lion and the fox are but a few examples. Metaphors and analogies elegantly describe political reality, give persuasive power to arguments, and effectively convey the meaning of concepts. The metaphor or analogy of the religion of liberty is, in my opinion, especially felicitous. It expresses the idea of a devotion to liberty that motivates a serious commitment and even self-sacrifice, if necessary. It also uncovers the inner dimension of liberty that lives, when it does live, in the minds of human beings independently of political and legal institutions.

    But if we are talking about a moral commitment to the principle of liberty, why, as a number of my colleagues have asked, do I use the word religion at all? My reply is that as a historian, I have a duty to be faithful to the language used by the political writers I have been studying. To redescribe as moral what they have called religious would simply amount to producing bad historical narration. I am not prepared to perpetrate such an intellectual sin. Nor do I see a powerful theoretical reason for the redescription. It is perfectly legitimate to assert that to have moral principles means to have an inward persuasion of their truth or value, and to live by them even at the cost of self-sacrifice. Yet what would be the net intellectual gain?

    The religion of liberty originated as a recognized as well as recognizable moral and political language in the context of fascist Italy. It would be incorrect, however, to regard it as just a mirrorlike image of the fascist political religion. Rather, it was a response and alternative to it. Or better still, it was a completely different picture painted with the same colors. Proponents and advocates of the religion of liberty, like fascist ideologues, used the words devotion, faith, resurrection, and martyrdom. But what they meant to do was destroy the totalitarian regime and its religion, and replace them with a free political regime and a new civil religion. The documents I found indicate that the religion of liberty was particularly effective in its struggle against fascism precisely because it used the same words with different meanings.

    The presence of religious interpretations of liberty in all the experiences of political liberation I examine here suggest that these kind of movements tend to assume a religious content and produce a religious language. One reason for this is that without a religious dimension, movements of social and political emancipation lack the necessary resources to persist in struggles that may easily go on for years, face dangers, and overcome tragic and devastating defeats, moments of despair and hopelessness, and the sense of futility about one’s own and everybody else’s efforts. Des peuples religieux ont pu être esclaves; aucun people irréligieux n’est demeuré libre, Benjamin Constant (1767–1830) wrote in De la Religion.²⁰ I find his words convincing. The achievement and defense of political liberty require a disinterested sentiment at the heart of the willingness to sacrifice oneself. Any morality that is alien to the religious sentiment cannot motivate the sacrifice of one’s life. The religious dimension affects the nature of the movement itself, the very content of the liberation. What kind of emancipation can movements attain when they are guided by leaders and militants who are not religiously devoted to liberty—that is, who have not chosen liberty as the highest principle of their life?

    The religion of liberty is especially necessary under extraordinary circumstances, when one must resist totalitarian regimes, oppose massive violations of human rights, defend one’s country against an external invasion, and struggle against organized crime and widespread political corruption. In these cases, self-interest and moral convictions based on rational evaluations (whatever they might be) are insufficient to generate the energies needed for any chance of prevailing. On examination, though, a religion of liberty is also necessary under the ordinary conditions of a free polity to help citizens discharge their civic duties. No democratic republic, no matter how strong, can impose a respect for civic duties through the mere threat of legal sanctions or by appealing to citizens’ self-interest. In addition to both, one needs some kind of inward persuasion, usually described as an obligation to one’s own conscience. Experience shows that a sense of duty is more solid when connected to a religious sentiment, be it in the form of a revealed religion (if it teaches the right civic message) or a religion of liberty not based on revealed religion.²¹

    If this is the case, political wisdom suggests that it is crucial to dedicate serious efforts and resources to keep alive (where it exists), resuscitate (where it is languishing), or generate (where it has never existed) a religion of liberty. It also advises us not to wait for exceptional circumstances. Citizens who love liberty with all their soul, and possess a civic spirit and moral courage, do not appear on command. They must already be there with their moral resources intact, like a well-trained army. One must cultivate in ordinary times the civic resources that are needed in the extraordinary ones. It is indeed hard to believe that citizens unable or unwilling to discharge their normal civic duties (paying their taxes, participating in elections and public life, remaining loyal to the constitution, caring for public spaces, and properly remembering the efforts and sacrifices of previous generations) will rise to the occasion when they are asked to make hard sacrifices and even put their lives at risk. This is, in my view, the political wisdom to be drawn from the Italian political and intellectual history I have reconstructed in this book.

    AS IF GOD EXISTED

    INTRODUCTION

    IN THE REPUBLICS of the late Middle Ages, in the Risorgimento, and in the struggle against fascism, Italian liberty was the work of religious men and women. Many of them possessed a sincere Christian faith, often quite distant from or in stark contrast with the teaching of the Catholic Church; others did not believe in any revealed religion but instead were believers and apostles—sometimes martyrs—of a religion they called a religion of duty or religion of liberty. Both the former and the latter people, regardless of the theological content of their convictions, were religious because they lived their lives as a mission—that is, with devotion to the ideal of liberty.

    A cleric will object that true religion is only that which affirms, on the basis of a revelation, the existence of a transcendental God; some secular people will protest that there is no need to see religion as devotion to a moral ideal. To the cleric’s critique, one can simply answer that his argument is arrogant and irrelevant: arrogant, for he dares to say to those who lived for the religion of duty or the religion of liberty that theirs was not a true religion; irrelevant, for his critique does not change the historical fact that there were people in Italy who lived according to those religions he considers false. A similar answer holds for the narrow-minded secular person: it is a historical fact that there were people who considered themselves religious because they lived with absolute devotion to the moral ideal of liberty; the layman is free to identify as morality what they lived as if it were a religion, but his position, just like that of the cleric, is intellectually weak.

    Shedding light on the multiple bonds that tied religion and liberty allows us to better understand Italy’s history. First, it helps us understand that Italy’s city-republics were supported by a particular kind of civic Christianity that cultivated charity, and hence the principle that only a good citizen, who loves and serves the common good, can be a good Christian. That kind of civil Christianity also preached that Christian virtue is strength—not the strength to endure oppression while resigning oneself to corruption, but the strength to resist those men who want to impose their dominion, as well as the bad custom of placing particular and personal interests above the public good. It also affirmed that of all forms of government, the republican one is the most pleasing to God, for God created us in his own image, and thus wants us to be free. It advocated a sacred respect for the laws. It taught that the citizen who governs well and serves the common good with all his strength renders himself godlike and deserving of perennial glory. Indeed, the conflicts that opposed Italian republics and the Church of Rome against one another were not only political ones but also conflicts between two interpretations of Christianity. When the Florentine magistrates of the fourteenth century challenged the papal interdict by saying that they loved their fatherland more than their souls, they were not, nor did they feel they were, pagan or atheist; they were true Christians fighting against the corrupt Christianity of the papacy. At the root of the first experiment in Italy’s history in political and civil liberty, there was therefore a civic interpretation of Christianity.

    And yet notwithstanding the intensity and spread of such a civic understanding of Christianity, even the best scholars of republicanism have failed to see it, or have noted only a few aspects of it. The great works on Italian republicanism—one could dare to say—seem to echo the observation of Alexis de Tocqueville regarding Europe as a whole at the beginning of the nineteenth century: those who are interested in republicanism are not interested in religion, and those who are interested in religion are not interested in republicanism. The religious dimension of Italian republicanism is thus almost completely absent from the comprehensive narrations of Italian political thought. The history of the birth, development, and decline of the first form of the religion of liberty in the postclassical world is still to be written.

    In the chapters of Die Kultur der Renaissance in Italien dedicated to the Italian republics, Jacob Burckhardt, for instance, confines himself to noting that the legend of Venice’s sacred founding was obviously mythical, and that in Venice, the state—although it had absorbed the church more than any other state—really had some sort of ecclesiastical element to it, and its living symbol, the doge, walked with quasi-priestly character and pomp in the twelve solemn processions (the so-called andate) in which he participated. In the chapters on religion, Burckhardt underlines the well-known Italian unbelief, and emphasizes that at the height of the Renaissance, the attitude of the upper classes toward the exceedingly corrupt church was a deep, mocking discontent mixed with resigned submissiveness. Of Girolamo Savonarola, he writes that he was the most unsuitable candidate for the role of republican prophet, for his true ideal was a theocracy. All of Savonarola’s thinking can be epitomized in the motto Jesus Christus Rex populi Florentini S.P.Q. decreto creatus, which was renewed by his partisans in 1527; his connection to the world was dogmatic, and he had a tyrannical temperament. The most solid religious beliefs remained those of pagan origin. Generally speaking, just as in politics and culture, Italians display a marked subjectivism as far as religious matters are concerned. The only hint of the relationship between republican ideals and the Christian religion is negative. Burckhardt mentions the case of Pietropagolo Boscoli, who was sentenced to death because he plotted against the Medici, lords of Florence, and on the eve of his execution implored his confessor to get Brutus out of his head and help him die as a Christian.¹

    In The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance, another fundamental study, published for the first time in 1955, Hans Baron observes that according to the humanists, the ancient poets (Virgil in primis) anticipated the Christian religion, and much of pagan polytheism survived in Christianity, especially in regard to the worship of the saints. Above all, Baron emphasizes the threat that classicism posed to Christianity, the church, and even republican values. He insists on the importance of the secularization of politics for the birth of the city-state, but makes no mention of the existence of a republican religion.² To a great extent, the same gap features in John Greville Agard Pocock’s monumental reconstruction The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition, published in 1975, and still a landmark study for documenting the links between Florentine and Anglo-Saxon republicanism. Pocock maintains that the Aristotelian ideal of the citizen that was reborn in Florence in the early modern age sets itself "in a paradoxical though not a directly challenging relation with the Christian assertion that man was homo religiosus, formed to live in a transcendent and eternal communion, known, however, by the ominously political name of civitas Dei."³

    The ancient ideal of homo politicus, Pocock explains, "is one in which man asserts his nature and his virtue through political action. The human type that is closest to it is the homo rhetor, whereas the most antithetical type is the homo credens." On the basis of these assumptions, Pocock argues that for Machiavelli, the civic ends—including the virtue of citizenship—are divorced from the ends of redemption. Furthermore, he holds that Machiavelli believed Christian virtues and civic could never coincide, and, consequently, the "implications of the vivere civile are becoming pagan, secular, and time-bound; it [civic life] is most itself in a world where there is no religion but augury and no values that transcend those of this life."

    Three years later, in The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, Quentin Skinner proposed a timely reconsideration of the religious problem in Italian republicanism. He emphasizes that Dante, in his polemics against the temporal claims of the papacy, already affirms that liberty is God’s greatest gift to human beings. Skinner also rightly reminds us that Marsilius of Padua (1275–1342), in his Defensor Pacis, clearly explains that the papacy’s temporal power is at loggerheads with the teachings of Christ and the apostles, elaborating a coherent defense of the communes’ right of full independence from the church.⁵ In the chapter dedicated to the relationship between rhetoric and republican liberty, Skinner cites a number of examples drawn from the thirteenth-century chroniclers to demonstrate how attacks from the enemies of republican government went against intellect and against God’s will. And when he comments on the advice books for the podesta, he notes that one of the most frequent prescriptions was to fear God and honour the Church. The most eminent figures among Florentine civic humanists, Coluccio Salutati and Leonardo Bruni, not only qualify republican liberty as holy but also affirm that free peoples are under divine majesty’s protection.⁶

    Contrary to Burckhardt’s interpretation, Skinner shows that the humanists reject Saint Augustine’s idea that men cannot raise themselves to virtue. He writes that beyond any doubt, Petrarch is a fervently Christian writer, who transmitted to the early Quattrocento humanists an essentially Christian view of how to analyze the fundamental concept of virtus. Following Petrarch, Skinner asserts, Leon Battista Alberti integrates the Aristotelian theory of virtues with two principles that reflect unmistakably Christian values: first, that we must never congratulate ourselves on acquiring any of these ‘great and excellent virtues’, since we must recognise that this ability has been ‘instilled in our souls’ by God; second, no one can in consequence be said to be following a truly virtuous life unless his ‘excellent deeds’ are performed not merely with ‘manly firmness’, but also with ‘a love of righteousness’ and a constant desire to commend himself to his Maker. Christianity also represents the conception of virtue and glory that the humanists disseminated in the fourteenth century: they continue to insist, Skinner writes, on the fundamental Christian doctrine that the vices are to be avoided simply because they are evil, and the virtues pursued for no other reason than that they are good in themselves. At the same time, in contrast to Augustine, the humanists contend that a virtuous man must pursue honor and glory, conscious that honor is a wonderful thing, fame is lovely" and glory divine.

    Republican political writers were neither pagans nor atheists but rather maintained an interpretation of Christianity that opposed both the doctrine and the practice of the church, and, in many respects, that advanced by Augustine. Machiavelli himself, who charges the church with having extinguished a love of liberty among the men of his times (and especially among Italians), acknowledges that Christianity—if rightly understood—teaches that one must love one’s fatherland and have the strength to defend it. His argument is directed against a Christianity that exalts humble and contemplative men, and not against the Christianity that kept alive the love of liberty typical of the pagan religion. Even Italian historian Francesco Guicciardini—who, if only a particular interest had not prevented him from doing so, would have loved Luther, and would have enjoyed seeing the wicked priests’ power finally reduced—resolutely denied any intention to derogate from the Christian faith and divine worship.

    The interpretative perspective that Skinner reopened must be enriched, which entails better outlining the specific character of republican Christianity. First, we must study the central role of charity as the foundation of patriotism and of devotion to the common good, and better examine the way in which the Florentine political writers understood the relation between republican liberty and Christianity. When Machiavelli extols liberty and the security of the republic as supreme political values—and remarks that when the security of the country is at stake, there ought not to enter any consideration of either just or unjust, merciful or cruel, praiseworthy or ignominious; indeed every other concern put aside, one ought to follow entirely the policy that preserves its existence and maintains its liberty—he is not expressing anti-Christian values.⁹ That liberty comes before any other consideration was a well-rooted principle of Florentine republican Christianity. Late fourteenth-century republican magistrates, who decisively administered the war against the pope and yet felt they were true Christians, were the first to disseminate the phrase to love one’s fatherland more than one’s soul. Whether or not Machiavelli was a Christian within his heart is another matter, but the principle that the fatherland must be preserved by any means can hardly have sounded anti-Christian to the ears of both the elite and the people of Florence.

    Starting in the sixteenth century, this civic or republican Christianity almost entirely disappeared from Italian culture and customs. In this book, I do not examine why and how that interpretation of Christianity was set aside or repressed. I simply note that another religion—the religion of the Counter-Reformation—took its place: it was a religion that no longer taught people to love liberty, fight with all their strength against tyranny and corruption, and live religion as an inner faith that translates into a concrete reality in the world. On the contrary, it preached respect for the authority of the pope and secular princes, resignation to oppression and corruption, and the belief that the external practices of worship are sufficient for saving one’s soul. Whereas republican Christianity was a faithful companion to liberty, the religion of the Counter-Reformation was the key ally of the powers and powerful people holding Italy hostage for centuries. A good religion makes people free; a bad one or the absence of religiosity makes people into slaves. This was the warning Machiavelli issued in the Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio when republican liberty and Italian independence were on the wane. All the free peoples of antiquity and those few of Machiavelli’s times, like the Germans of the free cities, were religious; all irreligious peoples, or those

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1