Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

John Dewey's Ecology of Experience
John Dewey's Ecology of Experience
John Dewey's Ecology of Experience
Ebook312 pages5 hours

John Dewey's Ecology of Experience

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

John Dewey’s philosophy is becoming extremely relevant for our times. From being one of the best-known thinkers in the world in the early 1900s, Dewey’s ideas went into near oblivion for decades. Now it seems that his philosophy was well ahead of his time. Most notably, he created a new philosophy of experience that enables us to rethink our place within nature.

The main innovation of Dewey’s thinking was his new way of understanding the experience of all living beings. Influenced by the theory of evolution, he understood experience as a continuously developing interaction between acting individuals and their environments. From this perspective, Dewey detected the fragmentation of experiences inherent within the modern way of life. The tools he developed to counter this are based upon learning collectively from individual experiences.

John Dewey’s Ecology of Experience reveals the relevance of Dewey’s ideas for our contemporary social, political and ecological crises. It creates a comprehensive picture of his thinking on human psychology, education, ethics, science, art and religion. In its conclusion, the book assesses the main theme in his political philosophy: the democratic way of life.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateJan 11, 2019
ISBN9789528054771
John Dewey's Ecology of Experience
Author

Kai Alhanen

Kai Alhanen is a philosopher and director of Dialogue Academy, Helsinki, Finland.

Read more from Kai Alhanen

Related to John Dewey's Ecology of Experience

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for John Dewey's Ecology of Experience

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    John Dewey's Ecology of Experience - Kai Alhanen

    CONTENTS

    Introduction

    Life and Experience

    The Philosophical Conception of Reality in Antiquity

    The Modern Conception of Experience

    Starting Points for Reconstructing Philosophy

    Experiencing Is Interaction

    Action Directs Experiencing

    The Development of Experience

    Human Experience

    The Development of Experience in Cooperation

    Desire, Memory, and Imagination

    Intelligence

    Linguistic Meanings, the Human Mind, and Communication

    Learning as the Ethics of Living

    Reflection and Inquiry

    Learning and Education

    Ethics of Experimental Learning

    Changing Ideals

    Science as a Guardian of Ideals

    Richness of Ideals in Art

    Novel Religiousness

    The Democratic Way of Life

    Individual, Communities, and Society

    Democratic State and Capitalistic Economy

    Challenges of Public Action

    The Ideal of Democracy

    Appendix: Dewey’s Works and Studies on His Philosophy of Experience

    Notes

    Bibliography

    Acknowledgements

    Index

    INTRODUCTION

    This book aims to rescue the concept of experience. In our continually changing world it has become increasingly difficult to grasp the meaning of our various experiences. Although our knowledge of the world and our technical means of controlling the environment have progressed, our understanding is nevertheless compromised by the way in which the integrity and uniqueness of our experiences are undermined. Although our knowledge of the world and our technical means of controlling the environment have progressed, the integrity and uniqueness of our experiences are undermined. As a result, our understanding of our experiences has become greatly compromised. This is largely due to the demands of economic and technological efficiency that we have allowed to control our lives. Consequently, we conform to a short-sighted mode of acting that leaves us with insufficient time and space for reflecting on our experiences and comprehending them in a more profound sense. Our hectic way of life reduces our experiences to superficial and fleeting thrills that do not connect with one another to form a meaningful continuum. At the same time, human agency is increasingly subjected to the narrow perspective of techno-scientific power exercised by experts, thus fragmenting the unity of human experience into narrow and disconnected domains. This leaves us unable to understand what is happening to us and to our environment. To counter these effects, we need to deepen our understanding of what human experience is. Only after this has been established can we even begin to comprehend the significance of our experiences within the current world situation.

    American philosopher John Dewey (1859-1952) recognized many of the trends that led to the current situation which now jeopardize our comprehension of the significance of our experiences. According to Dewey, what exacerbates these problems is that Western thought is governed by a misguided notion of the very nature of experience. In fact, Dewey aimed to create a new kind of conception of human experience, which became the basis of his pragmatist philosophy.

    In Dewey’s view, it is particularly harmful to understand experience as a psychological and purely subjective process, and to assume that its structures and contents are separate from both the natural world and one’s socio-cultural environment. Similarly, Dewey contends, we have severed experience from action, denying ourselves the understanding of what either fragments our experiences or makes them meaningful and unified. The mere accumulation of knowledge does not in itself develop our experience unless we supplement it with appropriate action and thereby grasp its consequences in practice. If we do not realize that our action thoroughly shapes our experiencing, we are also unaware of the developmental possibilities that lie within our experiences and are thus unable to deliberately affect what kind of world and human life we create through our actions.

    This faulty conception of experience, according to Dewey, not only plagues philosophy, but affects all areas of life: education, morals, the economy, labor, politics, science, art, and religion. The beliefs, theories, and practices that govern society are thoroughly imbued with it. Dewey thought this was strongly evident in the ways in which new generations were educated. Western education separates theory from practice. At the same time, it emphasizes individuality and individual accomplishment that are cut off from the physical and socio-cultural environment. Education also directs students into a twofold mode of acting: either to pursue rigid, externally-established goals or to select educational content arbitrarily according to their own engrained habits or momentary impulses.

    Dewey believed that a misguided understanding of experience and the social practices that reinforce it prevented the development of creative cooperation, or in other words, constituted a barrier to a truly democratic way of life. He made it his philosophical mission to point out and solve the deeply rooted problems in the Western conception of experience, and in so doing to renew human co-existence. In order to achieve this, Dewey created a new conception of experience that was based on fundamental interaction between individuals and their environments, the experimental nature of human action, and the constant development of experiencing.

    Upon beginning his work in philosophy in the 1880s, Dewey approached human experience from the perspective of German idealism. His original aim was to bring together the new experimental psychology with religious views on the divine and spiritual foundation of the world. He abandoned these idealistic inclinations, however, after becoming acquainted with the interpretation of human psychological functions advocated by his countryman William James (1842-1910), who emphasized the biological basis of experiencing and its continuous development in action. Dewey began to study human development as a process of which the core was man’s ability to learn from his experiences. In the 1890s he worked as a professor in the recently founded University of Chicago, gathering around him a group of talented researchers and students. This research community formed The Chicago School that began to develop a new pragmatist philosophy. Pragmatism was a movement based on the theories of Charles Sanders Peirce and William James that emphasized the testing of intellectual ideas in practical action. Dewey relocated to New York’s Columbia University at the beginning of the 1900s where he became one of the leading proponents of pragmatism in the United States and elsewhere. His views on the practical nature of knowledge were discussed and debated in universities around the world.

    Dewey’s contemporaries in academic institutions did not, however, understand the new philosophy of experience on which his pragmatism was founded. On the one hand, he was accused of being a crude scientific naturalist who reduced human thought, values and ideals to objective physical and biological facts of nature, and on the other hand he was labeled an idealist who denied the facts of nature and claimed that nature itself is merely a manmade intellectual construction. Dewey responded to both accusations by carefully explaining what he actually meant by experience. He was aware that the reason why his philosophy of experience was constantly misinterpreted was because his critics drew conclusions according to false conceptions engrained in Western thought concerning the nature of human experience. The peculiarity of Dewey’s conception of experience in relation to that of his contemporaries was one of the main reasons why interest in his philosophy within academic research had become almost nonexistent by the mid twentieth century.

    Dewey aimed to practice and test his philosophy of experience in both private and public activities of his life. For example, he fully participated in taking care of and educating his six children, which was very unusual in his social environment. The leading principle that he and his wife, Alice, held onto in raising their children was to support their natural curiosity and to encourage them to reflect on their experiences together with their parents. In order to test his philosophy of experience in practice, Dewey founded a laboratory school within the University of Chicago, which attracted worldwide interest. Here he developed a form of teaching based on questions prompted by the children as they interacted with their environment, which they then resolved in experimental situations together with their teachers. The children cultivated plants, made clothes and built camps that resembled the dwellings of the original settlers in America, for example. While carrying out these activities they also familiarized themselves with physics, chemistry, biology, geography and history. The experiences that pupils and teachers gained in cooperation, and the subsequent garnering of knowledge, intertwined seamlessly in the daily life of the school.

    Societal tensions and programs of political reformation also provided Dewey with opportunities to develop his philosophy of experience. He was active in many political movements that demanded economic and social justice, the protection of individual rights, and equality between genders, communities and races. His contribution to these movements was both intellectual and practical. He also presented the theoretical fundamentals of social reformation deduced from his philosophy of experience and helped political activists to plan and carry out socio-political forays. After the First World War, Dewey’s horizons broadened beyond the United States of America. He was invited to lecture and to assist with social reforms – usually in the area of education – all around the world. Reformists in Japan, China, the newly founded Soviet Union, Mexico, Turkey and South Africa, among other countries, invited him to examine their national circumstances and to present his views on the changes that were needed. The world wars also made Dewey determined to work towards achieving worldwide peace, cooperation, and justice. Behind all these intentions was his experience-based and politically radical view of democracy as a learning process that unites all people.

    Perhaps the most impressive manifestation of Dewey’s view of democracy came in 1937. At the age of 78, he agreed to lead an international commission to investigate the veracity of charges made against the former communist leader Leon Trotsky. Trotsky had had to flee Stalin, who had risen to power in the Soviet Union, and established a home in Mexico with the assistance of artist couple Diego Rivera and Frida Kahlo. The accusations made by Stalin’s government regarding assassination plots aroused the interest of people all over the world, and questions about their accuracy prompted heated political debate and violent conflicts. Dewey was asked to be the president of an independent commission investigating the issue. He interrupted his work on his massive book on logic in order to travel to Mexico, despite receiving death threats. After extensive investigation the Dewey Commission proclaimed Trotsky innocent of the charges made against him in Moscow. The task was both physically and mentally hard for Dewey, not to mention dangerous. He nevertheless saw it as his duty to ensure that Trotsky – a man whose philosophical views and political action he strongly opposed – was given fair treatment. It is acts such as this that most clearly embody Dewey’s conception of democracy, with open human cooperation at its core.

    Since the 1980s, a new kind of interest in Dewey’s philosophy has slowly emerged along with American neo-pragmatism, especially the writings of authors such as Richard Rorty and Hilary Putnam, who praise him as their philosophical hero. It has begun to seem as if many of Dewey’s ideas – especially his conceptions of knowledge and scientific action, learning and education, as well as public action and democracy – were considerably ahead of their time. Despite their newfound enthusiasm however, many philosophers who have returned to Dewey’s work still shun his conception of experience. Richard Rorty, perhaps his most influential defender, has suggested that we should completely abandon Dewey’s outdated conception of experience and replace it with the contemporary philosophy of language. This view has also generated strong opposition, however, and a number of researchers who have delved into Dewey’s work have begun to defend his philosophy of experience. Richard J. Bernstein, Thomas M. Alexander and Robert B. Westbrook in particular argue in their broad and perceptive research that Dewey’s conception of experience is a crucial and completely coherent point of departure into his entire philosophy.¹

    *

    Dewey’s philosophy of experience has come to assume a great deal of current relevance with the regard to burning questions of our age and contemporary academic research. It is my belief that these two developmental paths are not separate but support one another. However, I have not written this book primarily as an academic statement on the details of Dewey’s philosophy, but, on the contrary, I wish to engage a larger audience in the key ideas of his philosophy of experience.

    In this book, I will therefore consider Dewey’s thinking as a whole. I do not differentiate or analyze his writings case by case, but rather investigate the deeper and more fundamental levels that underlie them. In fact, I can find no finalized theory of experience in any one of his works. As I see it, Dewey develops his central conceptions of experience within the contexts of different themes, keeping his conception open and malleable to the various challenges of modern life. In order to outline his philosophy of experience more broadly, therefore, it is necessary to examine and follow several different lines of thought that run through his writings on psychology, education, ethics, politics, art, logic, the philosophy of science, and metaphysics. Dewey presents his conceptions as criticism of and responses to the ingrained philosophical conceptions of Western thought, which presents a challenge to the task of describing his philosophy of experience detached from these different contexts. While challenging, it is nevertheless possible because certain of Dewey’s basic insights and analyses permeate all the above-mentioned fields. It is necessary to formulate this kind of general conception of experience in order to clearly illustrate the special characteristics of his philosophical ideas. Only in this light is it possible to fully understand how fundamental and radical a change Dewey’s philosophy brought about in our ways of conceptualizing experience.

    The novelty of Dewey’s philosophy, even for us today, could be summed up by calling his conception of experience ecological, even though he never used that term himself. Because Dewey’s thought is founded upon the interactive relation of dependence between a living being and its environment, its identification with ecological thought is clearly apparent. Dewey studied the development of experience from the perspective of the acting of living beings, his understanding of which was significantly influenced by biology and the theory of evolution. It must be stressed, however, that Dewey’s ecological conception of experience in no way reduces human experience to biology, nor does it support a social-Darwinist interpretation of communal human life based on the dynamics of competition and struggle. Instead, Dewey’s thought leads us to investigate, from multiple perspectives, what kinds of connections link human life and culture with other living and non-living beings.²

    The main thread of this book is Dewey’s aim to show how his new conception of experience facilitates our understanding of the ways in which human beings are connected to nature as a whole. At the same time, I will bring into relief the central idea that connects the different areas of his philosophy, namely the thought that experience evolves as a learning process in which individuals continually apply new meanings to what they have experienced. According to Dewey, the most refined form of this process is the democratic way of life. To clarify these ideas, I will analyze Dewey’s philosophy of experience step by step, starting in the first chapter by bringing together from various contexts Dewey’s views regarding the modern conception of experience that still dominates our thinking and acting. This task requires delving into certain stages of the history of Western philosophy that Dewey considered pivotal. My aim here is to draw a coherent picture of how he understood and interpreted the historical development of the conception of experience.

    Towards the end of the first chapter I will investigate the starting points from which Dewey formulated his own philosophy of experience. I will go on to explain the main features of this philosophy with the aim of presenting it in the broadest possible form. With this in mind, it is therefore necessary to pay special attention to the aspects that can be broadened to include all living things that have experiences. Although Dewey did not comprehensively explain his conception of experience from such a general perspective, I believe that concentrating on the features that connect the experiences of all living things is the best way to illustrate the fundamental basis of his philosophy, as well as his ambitious attempt to discredit the modern harmful division between nature and culture that still dominates Western thought.

    The second chapter deals with Dewey’s conception of what separates human experience from the experiences of other living beings. I pay attention here to the characteristics of human experience that, according to Dewey, direct its development. This opens up a pathway for examining the essential features of human experience: socially formed habits, desires that develop in action, intelligent thinking, linguistic meanings, the human mind, and the communication of experiences.

    In chapters three, four and five I aim to show how Dewey extended the main ideas of his conception of experience to different areas of human life. I start from the core question of his philosophy: How can a person learn from his experience? From this I move on to examine Dewey’s aims to renew the popular conceptions of education and morality and our communal practices. I then examine his views on how science, art and religion depict ideals of the good life. In conclusion I assess the significance of Dewey’s conception of experience from the perspective of the main theme in his political philosophy: a democratic way of life.

    In my writing I use the terms experiences, experience and experiencing in the following ways. When I write about experiences I usually mean singular experiences regarding an event or thing confined by time and place. In everyday speech we refer to such singular experiences when we ask: What do you see from the window? or What did you do yesterday? When I use the word experience in its singular form I refer to the vast reserve of experience that a person or some other living being has accumulated as a whole, commonly called life experience. The expression experiencing refers to how we experience things. We might be asked, for example: What was your experience of that situation? Because Dewey thought that all experiencing included these three dimensions – singular experiences, accumulated experience and ways of experiencing – it is not a question of a strict conceptual division, but rather one of adapting to the context.

    *

    Although it has been more than 60 years since Dewey’s death, he was in many ways our contemporary – in some ways perhaps more so than in his own day. What is especially powerful in his work is his profound view on experience that takes shape in interaction between humans and nature, which may be simultaneously extremely open and malleable but does not consequently need to be arbitrary and chaotic. His philosophy of experience sheds new light on many aspects of our current way of life and the problems attributable to our societal action, offering solutions to these problems and pointing out promising directions for development. At the same time, Dewey demands that philosophy goes beyond the activities of intellectual hair-splitting and ironically inflected criticism that occur at a distance from everyday activities, thereby connecting philosophy to life and cooperation between people.

    Dewey developed his philosophy in an atmosphere of tension between the threats and opportunities of the modern world. In his thinking he was characteristically hopeful about developments but also rigorously took into account the drawbacks and problems of modern life. He emphasized the significance of philosophy to all people and promoted it as a device for revolutionary societal change. He considered one of its most important tasks to be the creation of an intellectual and practical vision of the future that would also move people emotionally. Dewey’s hopefulness and his incorporated practicality were his strengths, and it is this combination that distinguishes him from many other great thinkers of the twentieth century, several of whom were prone to cynicism. My aim in this book is to maintain the hopeful tone of Dewey’s philosophy and his aim to focus our vision on future possibilities – even when existing conditions are bleak and foster complacency and despair.

    I also intend to adhere to Dewey’s conception of philosophy, which for him is not a separate discipline or field of technical specialization but a form of thought that serves and challenges all sciences and human practices. My objective is to create a clear and coherent whole that is of interest not only to philosophers but also to people who are active in certain fields, such as educational professionals, scientists, theologians, social scientists, artists, and politicians. Promoting a profound understanding of experience in different areas of life is a necessary task for all thinking people. Only through a shared effort can we save our experience from the powers that shatter it, utilize the opportunities offered by the present and turn the direction of our communal life away from destruction to a direction that strengthens and enriches life.

    1

    LIFE AND EXPERIENCE

    Dewey’s philosophy of experience is largely based on the insightful analysis of the biggest problems within Western thought, as well as the consistent attempts to renew our conception of the nature of the experience of all living beings – especially humans. Dewey’s interpretations of the history of philosophy constitute an integral part of his own philosophy of experience, and through them he traces the starting points and presuppositions of the prevailing conception of experience. Dewey presents his own philosophy as a criticism of predominant ideas of experience with a view to exposing how deeply certain philosophical conceptions are engrained in our thinking and our practical lives. Thus, the focus of his interpretations is not on the philosophical speculations that hover above people’s daily lives, but on the theories by which they construct their conceptions of both themselves as experiencing beings and of the world as the object of experience.

    Dewey’s views on the history of philosophy should not be understood as scholarly research into the history of philosophy or the history of ideas. Nor did he attempt to reveal what philosophers aimed to achieve in their particular writings. He was interested, rather, in the critical analysis of the present; his aims being to examine the general currents of Western thought in order to point out and untangle the knots in modern thinking. Dewey worked like a Wittgensteinian philosopher of language, guiding the contemporary thinker out of the cul-de-sac of established conceptions. At the same time his take on things was nevertheless historical, and thus comes close to Michel Foucault’s idea of a critical history of thought. Dewey sheds light on certain basic conceptions that have broadly affected central areas of Western societal life, such as education, morals, religion, science, art, economics, and politics. The conceptions of many individual philosophers are in fact more diverse and profound than the general theses which have

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1