Sie sind auf Seite 1von 13

CHAPTER

35

HANBALI THEOLOGY

JON HOOVER

THE modern study of Han.bali theology was initially plagued by the problem of viewing
Hanbalism through the eyes of its Ash`arite opponents. I. Goldziher (d. 1921) and 0. B.
Macdonald (d. 1943) labelled the Hanbalis 'reactionary' and bemoaned the harm that
they had done to the cause of a conciliatory Ash`arite orthodoxy.1 he work of H. Laoust
(d. 1983) and G. Makdisi (d. 2002) turned the tide of scholarship t ,ward closer examination of Hanbali texts on their own terms and deeper understai ding of Hanbalism
in its historical context. Makdisi in particular argued that Hanbali,in had a disproportionate impact on the development of Islamic theology because it iv; the only Sunni
school to maintain a consistently traditionalist theological voice. kn. Makdisi, the
iaribalis were the 'spearhead' of a wider traditionalist movemen:. in,...dieval Islam
:rgainst the rationalism of Mu`tazili and Ash`arite Kalam (Makdisi 1962-3; -)81). Aspects
of Makdisi's narrative require modification, especially as some leading Hanbalis of the
fifth/eleventh and sixth/twelfth centuries were more rationalist than earlier' thought, but
the main thrust of his argument still stands. It may be added that Hanbali theology has
also had a disproportionate impact on modern Islamic theology. "fhe WAhhabi movement in Arabia and contemporary Salatism have appropriated and spic.id. the iwology
of the eighth/fourteenth-century scholar Ibn Taymiyya far beyon,' the conli9es of the
modern Hanbali school of law. This chapter begins with the formation early development of Hanbalism in order to clarify Makdisi's claim, and it cor E.ty stirveyitlg
key F,Ianbalt figures from Ahmad b. .Hankal in the third/ninth cen wry. to lho `Abd
Wahhab in the twelfth/eighteenth and giving extended attention to the unique theology
of Ibn Taymiyya.

I THE FORMATION OF HANBALISM


The Hanbali law school originated in the 'Abbasid capital Baghtdici i, the late ninth
and early tenth centuries CE as the most rigorous heir of the trade onalist movement

626 'JON HOOVER

that had emerged nearly two centuries carlier. The triditionaiists 1i:inured the collection and study of ljadith, and they sought to ground Islamic Ectici Ind 1iri.ctice solely
in the Quran and hadith reports from the Prophet Mulaamin.ii his Ciimpanions, and
their Successors. Opposite the traditionalists were the more torninant proponents of
ray (common sense' or 'rational discretion'). Advocates of ra r, iicd degree on
Qur'an and tladith, but they also located religious authority in existing toslim practice, general notions of upright conduct from the past, and the corr,iA red opinion of
prominent scholars of the day. Traditionalists and proponents of ra 'y came into conflict by the late second/eighth century, and, in response to traditionalist pressure, the
advocates of ray began adjusting their jurisprudence toward traditionalist positions
and grounding it in the precedents of an eponymous founder and hadith reports from
the Prophet to a far greater extent. The Hanafi law school emerged through the course
of the third/ninth and fourth/tenth centuries by vesting authority in a body of jurisprudence ascribed to its eponym Abil Hanifa (d. 150/767) and in turn linking these rulings
to Prophetic hadith. The notion that law should be based on hadith from the Prophet,
but not hadith from the Prophet's Companions and Successors, was argued by al-Shafil
(d. 204/820), the eponym of the Shafil law school, and he worked to interpret the Qur'an
and the ljadith so that it correlated with received legal practice. Al-Shafil's position may
be called 'semi-rationalist' because he made more room for reasoning by analogy (qiyas)
than did the pure traditionalists. Be also favoured a ruling derived by analogy from a
Prophetic hadith over a report from a Companion or Successor, and, in this, al-Shafi'l
Was at odds with Abmad b. Hanbal (d. 241/855) (Melchert 1997; Fiallaq 2009: 36-71).
Ahnnad was the most prominent traditionalist of the third/ninth century and the
eponym of the Hanbali school. He gave priority to health from the Companions
and Successors over analogy, and he also sought to prevent people from recording
his opinions because, in his view, Islamic doctrine and law should be based in the
revealed sources, not a later scholar like himself. Such a rigorist methodology proved
untenable in the long run, and, in a shift away from pure traditionalism, Ab5 Bakr alKhallal (d. 311/923) gathered Ahmad's views into a vast collection to form the textual
foundation for the Hanbali school. A little later, Ab5 Qasim al-Khiraqi (d. 334/945(-. 4031
6) produced the first handbook of Hanbali jurisprudence, and Ibn H3
1013) worked to reconcile conflicting views within these preceding Hanbali sourcus
(Melchert 1997; al-Sarhan 2011: 96-107). In the realm. of legal theory (ustil al-fiqh),
Abn Ya`la (d. 458/1065) carried forward al-Shafir i's project of correlating the law to
the Qur'an and the Ijadith with unprecedented thoroughness and consistency.
pressing the claim that the law corresponded to the literal (zahir) sense of revelation,
he elided the historical and hermeneutical process by which the law came into existence. The point was to rationalize the equation of revelation with prescribed belief
and practice as inherently obvious (Vishanoff 2011). For most Hanbalis, affiliating
with the school meant following the rulings attributed to Ahmad b. Hanbal loyally,
much as Shafils followed the rulings of al-Shafil and Hanafis the rulings of Abu
klanifa. However, being Hanbali could also mean engaging in creative jurisprudence
(ijtihcid) according to Ahmad's traditionalist method without necessarily following

"., Lo 627
_
ti is rulings. This is the sense in which ibn 'fayrniyya considered iiinsell Hanbali. As
a creative jurist (mujtahid), Ibn Taymiyya did not hesitate to cri:cize Ahmad's rulings, but he nonetheless claimed loyalty to the Hanbali school 1 'id Ali)inad's juristic
inethod (al-Matroudi 2006).
The classical Sun ni law schools were committed first and foremo!.i to the study of their
ycspective jurisprudential systems, and by the fifth/eleventh ceim Sunni orthodoxy
c...nsisted most fundamentally in belonging to a school of law, Odic religi.iits groupings
such as Sufis and Murtazili Kalam theologians had to take their plak es w Rhin this structure in order to protect themselves from traditionalist persecution. The Mu`tazili theologians found refuge in both the Hanafi and Shafil schools, but, with time, Mu`tazilism
died out among Sunnis and continued on only among Shns. Shah' ism appears to have
been semi-rationalist in both jurisprudence and theological doctrine in the late third/
ninth century before confining itself to jurisprudence in the course of the fourth/tenth.
hafils of semi-rationalist persuasion in theology eventually took up Ash`arite Kalam.
)the/ Shafils were traditionalist in theology and took their theological lights from the
limbalis. This is apparent in biographical dictionary entries describing such scholars as
`Shafil in law, Hanbali in principles of religion' (shcifirtyyat al-fiqh, hanbaltyyat
As M.akdisi observed, the El anbalis were the most consistently traditionalist in both law
and theology. Traditionalists within the Shaffi and Ha.nati law schools also opposed
Kalam. However, they did not voice their criticism as openly in order to safeguard the
unity of their respective schools. As we will see, some Hanbali scholars drew on .Kalam
and later the philosophy of Ibn Sina in their theologies, but, on the whole, the Hanbalis
were the most vociferous in propagating traditionalist theological doctrines (Melchert
1997; Makdisi 1962-3; 1981).

II EARLY HANBALi THEOLOGICAL


DOCTRINE
A number of texts used to depict the doctrinal views of Alamad b. Hanbal in past
search are evidently not his. It has been shown recently that the six creeds attributed to
111.11 in the biographical dictionary Tabaqat al-hanabila of Ibn Abi (d. 526/1133) (see
Joust 1957 for locations; three are translated into English in Watt 1994: 29 -40) go back
to diverse traditionalist sources in the third/ninth and fourth/tenth ci.lituries rather than
thmad himself. The creeds were apparently linked to him at a later date, probably to
consolidate his position as the seminal authority for Hanbali doctrine. Another work, alRadd 1- Jahmtyya wa-I-Zanadiqa ('Refutation of the Jahinis and the Irreligious'), may
go back to Alamad in earlier forms. However, the final edition (trans. in Seale19,4:9,6 u5) includes substantial rational argument against non-traditionalist doctrines, and it
was probably written in the fifth/eleventh century to rally Ahmad to the side of Hanbalis
coking to justify rational argument in theology (al-Sarhan 2011: 29 -54).

628

C'VER

Iv Iiina.4s may- still be It



be :lil t:1'E

Prior to
, !oiarfli of the

/^r.^ Uthniu
led t pia kiftd::!?: .

iich then
liovs.evor, tipHti
;
..'iluf ,;1.-irp;
in ills: ...a:1y

;:iMaiph
:::111.iries, but It:, eschide, !
radier than the fourth (al-Sarhan 20i !: ;Ii :s also likely that Ahmad, like other traditionalists of his day, had no qualms about
speaking of God in creaturely or corporeal terms, so long as there were Qur'an or
iexts in support. He affirmed for example that the 'God created Adam in
his form (.514ra)' meant that God created Adam in God's form, which implied that God
himself had a form or shape like that of Adam. To Kalarn theologians this constituted
the grave error of assimilating God to creatures (tashbih, also called 'anthropomorphism' in much scholarship). Taking their cue from 'There is nothing like [God], and.
He is iill-Hearing and all-Seeing' (Q 42; later Hanbalis such as al-Barbahari (d. 329/
941) sought to avoid the charge of assimiliationism by denying any likeness between
God's attributes and those of creatures while yet affirming that God indeed had the
attributes mentioned in revelation. This 'noninterventionist' (Swartz 202) or `noncognitive' (Shihadeh 2006) approach refused to inquire into the modality (kayj) of God's
attributesa position known as balkafa or kayf ('without how')or to interpret the meaning of the attributes in any way. 'ale texts should be passed over without comment (imrar). Some scholars have identified this kind of non-interventionism
:n Alamad b. H anbal as well (e.g. Abrahamov .1995: 366 -7). .! lowever, there is no evidence that Ahmad affirmed the balkafa doctrine explicitly (Williams 2002; see also
Melchert 2o11).
Questions of tashbih and the status of Kalam theology were at the centre of the
Inquisition (millria) initiated by the 'Abbasid caliph al-Ma'ninn in 218/833 and famously
resisted by Ahmad It has been often said that al-Ma'rnrin imposed the created
Qur'an on judges and leading religious scholars to support Mu`tazili &dam. However,
the Nilu'tazilis were not the only or even the main beneficiaries of the Inquisition.
doctrine of the created Qur'an was also known among followers of Alai, Hanifa
going back to the master himself, and the Inquisition sought primarily to support the
Hanafis, as well as other rationalist and semi-rationalist currents, against an increasingly assertive traditionalism. In the face of al-Ma'mun's Inquisition, Ahmad b. Hanbal
would affirm only that the Qur'an was the word of God. No Queanic verse or l'aadTtli
report stated explicitly that the Qur'an was created (makhlaq), and Alamad discounted
on principle the Kalam reasoning supplied for the doctrine. Ahmad was subjected to
imprisonment and flogging under al-Ma'intan's successor al-Nlu`tasim, but the later
caliph al-Mutawakkil brought the Inquisition to a gradual halt from 233/847 to 237/852.
In a letter to al-Mutawa.kkil, Ahmad did go a bit beyond the witness of the texts to affirm
that the Qur'an was also 'uncreated (ghayr makhlaq), and he added that anyone who
efosed to affirm this was an unbeliever. 'The failure of the Inquisition marked a major

yi:sk !ion .trid he c,iliphate'..; gamkt For ..


.ner;ted froin I he Inquisition hero of the traditionalist ,.- :herr
[4;H:.; 196o 6; Madelting 1974; 897).
ho aid ....as :.or his con:plc:L. sli.;intett..,,t po!:tis...ii ; (t' lived a quiet
md he Ulle,-,icted (siliog autho:ities ilitie .i,; ring .snd
14,iiih4lis were mii6: niore ,Lstiv 71,1
cons: i, ined powet !Ai
;11t r, riii
eai2,11..j:::.;
....C;AUCY , 't1,,11:1. I IR: .oust famous figure in I lie first half of the ioirth/tenth v was
lien/ al-Barbahari, author of a comprehensive crec. !al statement Sharh, al,,uitna (in ibn Abi Yala 1952: ii. 18-45). He was implicated in Han.bali attacks on Shafil
Jurists and purveyors of vice and innovation (bid`a), and he often went into hiding to
escape the authorities. Al- Barbahari may have been involved in riots that began in 317/
919 over interpretation of the divine address to the Prophet Muhammad 'Perhaps your
Lord will raise you up to a praiseworthy station' (Q 17: 79). Al-Barbahari understood this
that God would seat Muhammad on the 'Throne beside Himself whereas semir ionalists of the timeincluding followers of the renowned Qur'an commentator alTabari (d. o/923)preferred to interpret this metaphorically as Muhammad's right
to intcrcede for grave sinners (Melchert 2012). With the Bityid takeover of Baghdad in
334/945, 1:1:inbali animosities turned against the Shils as well, and Hanbalis engaged
in numerous attacks on Shiris, Ka/cirn theologians, and others well into the seventh/
thirteenth century. M. Cook attributes this Hanball social power to their great nums and a weakened state. Additionally, with the rise of the Bilyids and then later the
Sal juq amquest of Baghdad in 447/1055, the H, anbalis and the 'Abbasid caliphs found
common cause in undermining those foreign rulers (Sabah 1981: 101-20; Cook 2000:
115-28).
A key fourth/tenth-century author on H.anbali theological doctrine beyond alBarbahari was Ibn Batta (d. 387/997). lbn Balla composed al-lbana al-kubra, a large collection of traditions on belief, the Qur'an, God's predetermination, and other doctrinal
matters. He also wrote al-lbana al-ughra, a shorter creedal text that is also amply supplied with supporting traditions (ed. and trans. in Laoust 1958). A brief survey of this
treatise will serve to summarize the key points of early Hanbali doctrine.
I bn Balla begins al-lbana al-sughra with a long exhortation to adhere to the comrnunizy (jam-4 'a) and the Sunna of the Prophet and to avoid division and innovation. Then,
he mentions belief (itncin), which is affirming what God says, cor:imands, and prohibits
and putting this into practice. Unlike the Murji'is for whom beiIef depends on confession alone, belief can increase or decrease according to one's deet .s. 'It God wills' should
be added when affirming that one is a believer, not out of doubt t.ver one's religious status as a believer, hut because the future is unknown, Ibn Batta affirms that the Qur'an is
the Word of God, and he deems it uncreated no matter where it is found, even written
on the chalkboards of children. Not one letter is created, and wh.ever deems otherwise
is an unbeliever worthy of death. God's attributes mentioned in , cycaled texts must be
affirmed. Among other things, God is living, speaking, powerful, wiseind knowing. He
LiO/cs Ste and death, and He speaks and laughs. Believers will also see Cod on the Day
- r

630 ION HOOVER

of -at rrection. Ibn Batla does not mention balkafa with this list attributes, but he
it later when affirming God's descent each night to the loweA heaven. This,

s. .acmcd wi, hout .1:41(ii;g Low (.'01;1) tiitila). In opposition to


.11'd 1 , ,:tazi17. doctrine iliat lunuans their own at is. tta affirm,.
i)();11:401)j and ace-..ii.dinig to thc
le pes On to affirm numerous cli...rnetits of
di,: toinb, the weighing oftlectls ales ai t he it..CS411'1',21:!
intercession for believers, and so on. The latter part of the treatise extols the virtues of
the prophets and the Prophet Mubainmad's Companionsespecially Abu Bakr, `Umar,
`Uthman, and 'Ali, in that order to oppose the Shils--and treats several matters of practice. Overall, al-lbana al-sughra provides very little explanation or rational argument. It
is largely a series of affirmations supported with Qur'anic verses and hadith reports.

III HANBALi THEOLOGY FROM THE


ELEVENTH CENTURY TO THE THIRTEENTH
Research on Hanbali theology in the fifth/eleventh to seventh/thirteenth centuries remains spotty, but it is readily apparent that this period marks a new departure
as some of the leading Hanbali scholars of the time adopted Kalam views and argumentation. The earlier Hanbali Abu 1-I-Jusayn al-Munadi (d. 335/947) had advocated
metaphorical interpretation (ta 'wil) of God's attributes, and the lost Sharh ow al-din
of Ibn Hamid may have been a Ka/am-style work (Swartz. 2002: 61, 94). But it is from
Ibn Harnid's student Abu Yala Ibn al-Parra' (d. 458/1066), the most prominent Hanbali
of his time, that we have our first extant Hanbali Kalam manual, al-Mu`tamad uszal
al-din, a summary of a larger lost work by the same title. Typical of Kalam manuals,
al-Mu`tamad first outlines the foundations of knowledge and explains that the initial
human obligation is reasoning (nazar) to knowledge of God. The book then outlines
the basics of Kellam atomism, proves the existence of God from the origination of the
world, arid treats, among other things, God's attributes, God's creation of the world and
human acts, prophecy, eschatology, belief, and the Imamate. Abu Yala adopts Ash'arile
positions on a number of issues in al-Mu `tamad. For example, he bases the obligation
to nazar on revelation as do the Ash'arites, not reason as held by the MuTazilis, and he
employs the Ash`arite notion of acquisition (kasb) to give humans responsibility for the
acts that God creates in them (Gimaret 1977:161-5). Abu Y)la also wrote two other theological works that are extant: Ibtal li-akhbar al-sifat and Kitcib al-Irnan, The
Kitab al-Iman, also known as Masa 51 al-iman, is a detailed treatment of belief and the
status of believers and bad sinners. (bpi al-ta'wilat is a lengthy work on the interpretation of God's corporeal qualities.
Abu Ya`la's approach to God's corporeal qualifications seeks to mediate between
Kalam rationalism and Hanbali traditionalism. In al-Nfu'iamad, he joins the Kolan:

theologians in arguing that God cannot have a body ("ism). I hu/ ,x&
corporeal qualifications such as eyes, hands, face, and
mean that
body ,, art:;. Yet, .Abil Yala also rejt..cts metaphorical interpihmi ion ("a 'le FT) i,1
tjUaiiii: iOntiind he in aintain.s that i hey are simply attributi . some
(fihat.:1 Jud .4herm; added (zii 'itl) to God's essence (Abti -; -()). al:;;)
i n AO
-fa .teilat. For example, he affirms that
I-Ik
and ula lie seen, as stated in the kifailith. ins
!per:,
:- :thir), Abu Yala explains, but without interpreting it furtlicr ic imply opens
Iiia mouth or that He has body parts such as molars or an uvula, and without interpreting it metaphorically to mean God's grace and generosity. God's laughing is an attribute
(sifa), but its meaning (ma`na) is not understood (Holtzman 2010: 186-7). Despite Abu
Yalia's attempt to avoid corporealism (tajsim) on the one hand and ta'wil on the other, he
and his teacher Ibn Haruki later came under sharp attack from fellow Hanbali scholar
Ibn al-Jawzi for crass literalism and corporealism.
Aba YaTa's foremost student was Ibn 'Aqil. (d. 513/1119), a precocious reader of
Kalam alongside his Hanbali legal studies. With the death of his patron in
460/1067-8, Ibn 'Aqil suffered under the intrigues of rival Hanbali jurist Sharif
TaTar (d. 470/1077) and was eventually forced to retract his Mu'tazili writings in 1072,
as well as his sympathies for the Sufi martyr al-Hallaj (d. 309/922). G. Makdisi ties Ibn
'Aqil's retraction to the 'Abbasid Caliph al-Qadir's (d. 422/1031) earlier promulgation of
a traditionalist Hanbali creed as official doctrine of the caliphate and interprets it as the
culmination of traditionalist ascendancy in Baghdad: [The retraction] represents the
triumph of the Traditionalist movement supported by the caliph lie, against Rationalist
MuTazilism, on the decline, and a militant Rationalist Ash'arism, on the ascendant'
thanks to support from the Saljuqs (Makdisi 1997: 14; also Mikdisi 1963). As Makdisi
indicates, the traditionalist battle with Kalam was not done, ant Ash`arism continued
to rival Hanbalism for centuries to come. Ibn 'Aqil's major work ill theology al-Irshadfi
arid al-din is not extant. Otherwise, it appears that Ibn `A.q11, post- retraction, was moderately rationalist within a traditional Hanbali doctrinal .fratrework and advocated a
limited use of ta'wil (Makdisi1997),
Mention of Ib.n 'Aqil's interest in al-I-Jallaj raises the question of Hanbali-Sufi relations, especially as Hanbalis have often been seen to be opponents of Sufism. This
reputation derives from the later Hanbali polemic of Ibn al--Jawzi and Ibn Taymiyya
against innovated practices and doctrines linked to Sufism, although not against
its ideal of a spiritual path to God. Han.balis and Sufis share common origins in traditionalist currents of renunciant piety, and, like other traditionalists, early Sufis studied 171,adith and rejected Kalam. As the legal schools formed from the late third/ninth
century onward, Sufis affiliated largely with semi-rationalist schools such as the Shafil
,Ind the Maliki. However, Sufi relations with the traditionalist IJanbalis, were generally
good. Traditionalist Sufi writers such as Abil Nu'aym al-Isfahani (d. 430/1038) included
klarnad b. Hanbal among the pious saints (aw/iyal of past generations, and some
itotable Sufis were Hanbalis including 1bn 'Ata' (d. 309/921-2 or 31.1/923-4), who was
for defending al-Hallaj, 'Abd Allah al-Ansari (d. 481/1o/t9-ind the eponym of

632 JON HOOVER

,,, 1 althe Sufi or. k.hd


' al are borli ,ii..iii:jeance for Y. ' halt Al Ati-zi'iri bati-led
As1J'arit. il , e0logans 1:1 !...horas-tii, Ind out o: A m,: his io
les a ti.i1J aild well cr,,J,ani, ,(1..,:'.1W;11:.:11E of traal
trios
fli1:0!1,11! . ! rine ii
J.1-1 I, '
.1.1i:r
Tii, most ,;ophisticat-il Jorih.Jli
.
(d. 527/1[12), author of al-laah ji
, inanual similar in length and stritclure to Abil Mu'tamad, and it reats God's
corpt weal qualifications in much the same way, To take God's eyes, for exailiple, Ibn alZaghtini denies that God's eye consists of a fleshly eyeballGod's eye is not an originated body. Yet, he also disallows interpreting God's eye metaphorically along Kalatii
lines as God's 'protection'. Rather, God's eye is an attribute to be taken literally without
assimi.lationism or modality (tbn al-Zaghimi 2003: 291-4). With his, tbn al-Zaghimi
sought to find his way between corporealism and ta'wil, but it failed to please his foremost student Ibn al-Jaw.zi.
Ibn al-Jawzi W. 597/1201) was the leading Hanbali scholar and preacher of h.is day. He
initially opposed the Ash`arites and Mu`tazilis, partly because they were aligned with the
Saljuq sultans, but, as Saljuq power waned and the 'Abbasid caliphate revived, he took
a more relaxed attitude toward Kalam and eventually drew on Kalcim argumentation
to produce his fullest theological work, Kitab Akhbdr al-sijat, in the late 1.18os or early
1190s. This book contains a stinging condemnation of assimilationism and corporealisto
within the Hanbali school, and it probably contributed to his banishment to Wasit
590/1194 (Swartz 2002: 33-45). Ibn al,o wrote a similar but shorter work called
the Daf shubah al-tashbih (trans. 'Ali 2oo6), oh) known as al-Baz achl ,,,b.
The targets of ibn al-Jaw/1'3 Akithar are three of the mos! prominent
Hanbalis of the preceding two oracles-1bn Hamid, Abu Yalla, and Ibn
whom he accuses of interpretirg (1od's corporeal qualifications literally and disallowing metaphorical interpretation. In a strongly rationalist tone, Ibn al-Jawzi explains that
reason apart from revelation knows God's existence, God's unity, God's necessary attributes, the originated quality of the world, and prophecy. Reason also knows that God is
not a body; otherwise He would be subject to temporality. Thus God cannot be said tu
have corporeal attributes in any literal sense.
Then, in Kitab Akhbar ibn al-Jawzi sets forth two approaches to God's corporeal qualifications: non-interventionism for the masses and metaphorical interpretation
(ta'wil) for the scholars. The error of the Kalam theologians is to subject the public to
their dialectic because it only sows doubt and spreads heresy, Rather, God has spoken
to the masses in language that they can undiTstand and readily accept, and, in public.
God's corporeal qualifications such as His hands and eyes should be read in the texts and
passed over as they are without comment (am:4r). Taking aim at Alla Ya`la, Jawzf
declares that nothing further should be said about what kind of attributes these qualifi
cations might be fri.g. essential (dhati) or additional (za'id) to the essence) or about their
literal meaning. However, among the scholars, Ibn al-jawzi explains, God's corporeal

clualifications should he i-einierp,-,ocd inetaphorically .k ^.'|,


ri.as(-.n, that is, to deny that h,a; a body. The bulk if
.;i0t is 111,..1-1
ond reinterprinion orJ and I tex is po,
-ems.1pu elitimr that ta 'w1; i.s only for be schola,--; , e
iy Ibn al 1^,,,-J.Ji i.lispla):; cot
ism la hi:. book, and ins objective
.,_PLtatiil of tilc !,C1,1:01 it1 i.yes
scholars. tbn al-Jawzi claims ijie highly regarded .'d:Iroad b. 1,-1Jal:-/cil for the
ontionism that he advocates for the masses, and he rejects layr T.1 'i,ihall attenipii. at
literality as deviant corporealisrn (Swartz 2002: 46-64, 27-138).
lbn al-Jawzi's polemic did not escape Hanbali criticism, Abu i-ijadl al-Ahhi (d. 634/
1236) wrote a diatribe that may have helped get the senior Haaliali scholar exiled to
Wasit. Al-Althi takes Ibn al-Jawzi to task for his elitist advocacy 'w.i/ and calls him to
repentance. There is, however, no evidence that Ibn al-Jawzi ever recanted (Swartz 2002:
282-97). Later on, sometime after 6o3/12.06, the Syrian Hanbali jurist .1bn Q.uclama (d.
620/1223) wrote his Tahrtrn al-nazar ji kutub ahl al-kalarn in which he discusses the
retraction of Ibn `Aqil at length. No mention is made here of Ibn al-Jawzi, but it seems
likely that Ibn Quelama had him and his admirers in mind (Swartz 2002: 42,62),
Ibn Qudarna's Tahrirn al-nazar provides a lengthy refutation t and 11 repeatedly sets out the traditionalist H anbali position on God's attrilaa tes. ..iting the aut horny of Ahmad b. Hanbal, Ibn Qudama explains that corporeal pici ions of God in the
Qur'an and the Hadith must be accepted as true without saying anything more or less.
God is described as He has described Himself, and the texts are passed over as they
are without comment (imrar) and without inquiring into modality (./..,.irj) or meaning
(ma `na. ). Ib.n Qudama also claims that whatever God's attribute.; -miglit mean is of no
practical import, and believing in them in ignorance is the correct path. If one wants to
inquire into something, Ibn Qudama argues, one should inquire into jurisprudence, not
the attributes of God (Makdisi 1962).
Hanbalism weakened in Baghdad after Ibn al-Jawzi, and the Mongol destruction of
the city in 1258 dealt the H anbalis a further setback. Damascus took over as the intellectual centre of Hanbalism with Ibn Qudama being one of its great early figures. Damascus
was'dominated by S.hafi'is, and H anbalis could not exercise the same so(- ial and political
power that they had enjoyed in Baghdad. Nonetheless, the Damas,:enc anbalis thrived
and eventually produced the most creative theologian in the Hari-mil tradition and one
of the greatest minds in medieval Islam: Ibn Taymiyya.

IV IBN TAYMIYYA
11, n Taymiyya (d. 728/1.328) is at times portrayed as anti-rationolisi due to polemic
against the main claimants to reason in his day: Ash`arite and Mil ta,fli th.a6- igy, Aristotelian logic, and the Aristotelian-Neoplatonist jalsiiiir lho .'11na. iwever,

W34 JON HOOVER

( 635

it has keen .:),ide clear that rbni Tay)nivya did

not reic,

r reason as hut argued for its

:,,3 ), i,,....co:r.i....oparcat that his

of 1).101.1/.11.d piJet: It was


piAlatly i:na! ive and
;le
rcot
,:nstrual
ot
God
:. cad vookal in .t intid
f:lisaftr and giv
:4:
:to
tr)a
1g
ott
both
(
lo,)vcr
Ira nil In
';';;
Oka,

01.1(:11),
;:tinc0 old
:). y ) it); rt;iiiiccd co, oo itt)prei_c.detticd in iltc school
(el Omani zoio; Hoover zo..., Ozervarli
ar). not found et,ewhere in
%A! 3S 11 ,1.

201o).

The theological world in which Ibn Taymiyya worked was permeated with philosophized Ash`arite .Kalcim, especially that of Fa.khr al-Din al-Rad (d. 606/1209). Ibn
Taymiyya read al-Razi with his students, and he wrote extensively against al-Razi's
ideas. His major works Dayan talbis al-jahrniyya and Dar' ta 'amid al-rag/ w^-/-nag/
both respond directly to al-Razi's thought. The former work refutes al-Razi's book Asas
al-tacidis on the metaphorical interpretation of God's corporeal attributes. The latter
work Dar' ta`cirud confutes the 'Rule of Metaphorical Interpretation' *Man al-ta'wd)
espoused by al-Ghazali and al-Razi, which gives reason precedence over the literal
meaning of revelation when the two contradict. Although Mu`tazili Kalam had died out
in Sunni Islam by the eighth/fburteenth century, it lived on in Imami Shil theology, and
ibn Taymiyya's large refutation of Shfism Minhaj al-sunna al-nabawiyya directly rebuts
Mu'tazili notions of divine justice.
In addition to the tomes just mentioned, ibn Taymiyya wrote several other large
works, including major refutations of Christianity and Aristotelian logic, and important
treatises on Sufism, political theory, and prophecy. While a few of Ibn Taymiyya's works
may be dated with precision, many cannot, and change or development in his thinking
is often difficult to establish. However, his thought is remarkably consistent and coherent, and it is thus with some confidence that we may speak of a characteristic Taymiyyan
theology that retained its essential contours throughout the course of his scholarly life.
Except where indicated otherwise, the following overview of Ibn Taymiyya's theology is
based on my own writings (Hoover zoo4; 2007; zoioa; see also Laoust 1939; Bell 1979).
As Ibn Taymiyya saw it, the fundamental problem of his time was that God was no
longer worshipped and spoken of correctly. A great many Muslims had strayed from
true theological doctrine and proper religious practice and fallen into the errors of
philosophers and Ka/um theologians, as well as Shils, Sufis, Christians, and others.
The solution was to return Islam to its sources, the Qur'an, the 8adith, and the doctrine and practice of the Salaf, the first two or three generations following the Prophet
Mubammad, before the religion was corrupted by error and sectarian division. In Ibn
Taymiyya's view, the accumulated judgements and the consensus of later scholars were
subject to error, and they had to be measured against the doctrine of the Salaf.
At the core of Ibn Taymiyya's polemic against .Kalam and f alsafa is the subordination of metaphysics to ethics and the theoretical to the practical. Kalam and falsafi
reverse the order. Both disciplines reason from the nature of reality to thc existence of
God. God's unity, and God's attributes and eventually to prophecy and the practical

,:ii,h,gations that follow on from that. For ibn Taymiyya, th apf)::- to rLice wor:)ip a God at the fore Tal:ing his cue from the rioter of hons 'ton wvc.,-,rship; You alone we :11K ':or help' (Q 1: 5), Ibn Tayrniyytt :hat k
of worship. praist, And love is prior !:) (Iotrs exclitstv:: creation of tIte wot
;:id provision of htlp fi- His servants. (,:t k the sole :he tor
L.))),, ro ya this .inetapItyslcal fi.Ifows on from :it,: ft):::idational
iod's ore-eminent worthiness ')1 of)ciiience and pro:Ne. to tr,..:os P:
woryhip God alone because of who Cod is in Himself and ;iot simply because /(x
alone creates and sustains. Here is how Ibn Taymiyya distinguishes Kahim from his own
method, which he takes to be that of the Qur'an;
The distinction between the Quednic and the kalam theological methods is that God
commands worship of Him, a worship which is the perfection of the soul, its prosperity, and its ultimate goal. He did not limit it to mere affirmation of Him, as is the
purpose of the kalam method. The Qur'an relates knowledge of Him and service to
Him. It thus combines the two human faculties of knowledge and practice; or sensation and motion; or perceptive volition and operation; or verb:El and practical. As
God says, 'Worship your Lord: Worship necessarily entails knowledge of Him, having penitence and humility before Him, and need of Him. This is the goal. The ktficirn
method secures only the benefit of affirmatio.n and admission"( xists:nce.
(Quoted in Ozervarli zoio: 89)
ti:inTaymiyya also speaks of the priority of worship and ethics over met aphysics in theo:rigical terms that later became widespread among Wa.hhabis and modern Salafis. He
!istinguishes two rawhids, or two ways of confessing God's unity. Ibn faymiyya's first
hriv/ifd is that of God's divinity (ulribiyya). Al-tawhid al-ulahiyya signifies God's sole
%.,orthiness to be a god, that is, God's sole right to be an object of worship (Ybada). Al:awhid al - uhThlyya is exclusive worship of God that refuses to give devotion and love to
1nything or anyone else. Then flowing out from this is the second tawhid, the tawhid of
lordship (rubUbiyya). God's lordship refers to His creative 'ower, and al-tawhid
(d-rubUbiyya means confessing that God is the only source of .1teL! !aeings. For Ibn
,-'aymiyya al-tawhid al-ulithiyya is logically prior to al-tawhid -1-rububiyya: God in
limself in His pre-eminent worthiness of love and worship comes first.
Ibn Taymiyya's practical turn effectively transforms theology into an aspect of Muslim
jurisprudence. He rejects the commonplace medieval distinction between the principles (ustii) of religion and the branches (furin, in which the principles treat theological doctrines like God's existence and attributes from a theoretical perspective and the
branches discuss religious obligations such as prayer and fasting from a practica), legal
vantage point. Rather, for Ibn Taymiyya, the principles treat those matters of greatest
importance in both theological doctrine and religious practice, and the branches deal
with lesser matters of detail. Moreover, theological beliefs and r.ligious Trochees are
both practical matters concerned with correct worship of God, iind theology is prirnarily about getting the language of praise and worship right, not establishing the existence
of God.

636

ve^ pOt1: tti'S


;Ind !ead to , 0:11
, leCortlW ith both revelation :A nil r,:ason,

, va .6 hoick i:e for riiason and its .:3[,:v:Ity !,


I; and !IL view raason , 10 i.it y opt:Ini511,,-.. I !.e
.:/m,

hat .:virii
.111

rrc) . e

it mit as it

re.tks
';,j-b.!La

i hat
P
love
etin
i'.::istoteiati
terms, 'lb , :
,'i
Sp,
lug;

nendit
frames
the
natur,d
constitution
as
an
innate
potency
toward
the
religion
of
iiyya
t Lim at birth that is actualized as the human being develops; the role ot prophecy and
revelation is then to perfect the natural constitutfit; and help it overcome corruption.
For Ibn Tayrniyya, reason and the natural constitution on the one hand and revelation
on the other do not contradict. They both come from the same source, and they provide
much the same information and argument. Rational minds and natural constitutions
can know the existence of God and the proper human end apart from roelation, but
when they encounter revelation they immediately recognize it as true and congruent
with what they already know. .t.bn Taymiyya observes that Ka/am theologians and philosophers confine revelation to information that cannot be attained by reason, and he
...ounters that revelation includes not merely information but also rational argument.
1-1f.velation contains the correct proofs of reason, and reason recognizes the truth of revelation. In making the claim that revelation and reason agree, fbn Taymiyya is trying to
take the rational high ground away fromfiilsafa and Kalam, which he believes are based
on faulty foundations and lead to misguided conclusions.
A case in point is the Kalam proof for God's existence. 'The Kalam proof in simplified
form assumes that the world is made up of indivisible atoms and the accidents that subsist in them. Accidents are temporally originating (hadith), andthis is keyanything
in which something temporally originating subsiststhe atommust also be tempo
rally originating. Seeing that all atoms are temporally originating, and in view of the
Kalam conviction that an infinite regress of temporally originating events is impossible,
the world as a whole must have been originated in time. Having proved that the world
had a beginning, the Ka/4m argument concludes that it required a Maker who was not
originated but eternal.
fbn Taymiyya often dismisses this proof and its talk of atoms and accidents as unnes essarily complex. Yet, apart from a bit of complexity, it can be difficult to see why he
would find it so problematic. However, the proof is based on two postulates that are
incompatible with Ibn Taymiyya's theological vision: the impossibility of an infinite
:egress and the notion that something in which temporally originating events subsist
is itself tinnporally originating. As will become apparent, Ibn Taymiyya has no objection to an infinite regress. His iiwn view of God as perpetually creative from eternity
entails an infinite regress of created things. Additionally, his temporally dynamic view
of t iod implies that originating events subsist in God's very essence. Ibn Tayrni) ya cannot accept the Kalam postulate that originating events render their host substrate temporally originating because he himself posits temporality in the essence of God. In his

!::10t., that it !

:us own

' ii,lis attributes and which lie a isciis,e,


f it(' i , d God's attribu:ii:s),
n!ic:!t1,61. or :Ion-, .?t: nttiviNtn, but
!..,:cr 6n. lint TAy.rtityya's
i.eqn :he i:, anies and :ntri6u:es
ft.
;;!f.ma i

ravoa.
without, on use hand, inquiring into t heir 'nodality c.,sinulating
fraslittili) or likening (tamtial) them to the attributes and names of creiullyzs, or, on the
other hand, stripping them away (tartf/) from God with metaphorical interpretation.
iad is affirmed as all-Hearing, all-Seeing, but there is nevertheless nothing like Him (Q
az: 'This applies equally to all qualifications given in the Qur'an. and the Ijadith, from
iod's 'willing' to God's 'laughter' and God's `sitting' on the Throne. Ibn Taymiyya rejects
h:a Kahim practice of reinterpretation (ta'w11) and dismisses the distinct ion between the
(7,ihir) and the metaphorical (majaz) upon which it is bas:,:d, "ro tJ- c ine of ibn
t'ilyntiyya's examples, Ash`arite Kalam theologians reinterpret t ind's metaphori: ally as God's 'will' on the grounds that speaking of God's love literally would assimilate Him to creaturely qualities; God cannot be ascribed with crtiatu rely passions like
lave. Ibn Taymiyya retorts that this reinterpretation in fact involves both likening and
tripping away. First, the Kalcim theologians imagine the love ascribed to God to be like
iuman love in a literal sense and thereby conclude that 'love In ry be ascribed to
tTh id. Then, to free God of the untoward passions of human love, :hey strip God of His
' :i.: by calling it instead `will: The only reasonable course, according to !liin Taymiyya, is
::1:iffirin all of God's names and attributes equally and without modality. The only simiarity between the names and attributes of God and the names :ind ributes of creatures are the very names.
The non-interventionism of a If anbali like Ibn Qudama stopped at point and for: iade full ier inquiry into the nieimings of God's attributes because they were of no pracical consequence. God's names and attributes must be passed of er without inquiring
i , ito their meaning (imrar). Ibn Taymiyya, on the contrary, believes that the meanings
matter, and this propels him on to a wide-ranging project of theological hermeneu:ic:i. He discards the Kalam device of Will/ and places in its stead a project of linguistic
' ,,i;tiiry (*sir) that seeks to interpret God's attributes and names in ways that he deems
nraiseworthy. While humans may know nothing about God's names and attributes
'xcept the names, these names still evoke meaning in the human mind, and this meaning impacts human response to God for good or ill, depending on the character of the
portrayal. For Ibn Taymiyya it is thus imperative to give sense to God's names and attrib,tes that will evoke love and praise for God and ward off scepticism and disdain. This is
(lie aim of Ibn Taymiyya's whole theological endeavour, and his foremost difficulty with
cival theological visions is that they fail to give God sufficient praise.
An instructive example of how this works is Ihn. Taymiyya's contrast of. ill's own notion
tt God's justice (WI) with that of the Ash.'arites and the Mn'tazilis. In i he . voluntarisin
fthe Ash`arites, God's justice consists in whatever God wills, with :out i:onsideration of

638 JON HOOVER

cause or wise purpose, God is just to punish hurrhios for the b- thaa He creates in
them, and he would even lo pu wu6c.,.11 F' ,.ymiyya rejects
trt, argue
a as c,';): icio, ts and uipa,oi-tily ,a. .
oi fact be uujest iod p.:11sti bad tilt
.;1,,au.aa
. i

Anki !C..1;!.;

for :iced:, and pimisitinent had


tirv,; ot.a.:t1:d. : ins, ice
ta:/iii


Taymiyya
G.
id
.uid
humansand because it makes
universe--both
.1 plurality of creators
God look .1;)olish. God ill. his foreknowledge knows that humans will commit evil deeds
with the creative power that He gives them, and yet He stupidly gives it to them anyway.
'this, Ibn . faymiy-ya remarks, is like one person giving another a sword to fight unbelievers when he already knows that the other person will use it to kill a prophet. In sum,
Ibn Taymiyya castigates both the Mu`tazilis and the Ash`arites for depicting God in an
unworthy manner. While God cannot be subjected to human moral standards because
He is wholly unlike creatures, He must nonetheless be spoken of with the highest praise.
For Ibn Taymiyya, this means that God's justice consists in `putting things in their places'
in accord with His wise purpose (hikma), and, in one of his late texts, he affirms with Ibn
Sina and al-Ghazali that God has created the best possible world.
Ibn Taymiyya also sets forth a mechanism for deriving God's names and attributes
rationally. While he disallows use of the juristic analogy (qiyas) and the categorical syllogism in theology because they bring God and creatures into direct comparison, he does
permit their use in an afirtiori argument (qiyas af-aw/a). In accord with the Queanic
assertion that God is ascribed with the 'highest similitude' (al-mathal la) (Q 16: 6o),
Ibn Taymiyya claims that God is all the worthier (awla) of perfections found in creatures
than are the creatures themselves because He is their cause and source. Thus, using a
fortiori reasoning, God is all the worthier of being ascribed with perfections found in
creatures such as power, life, sight, and speech. Similarly, G od is all the worthier of being
disassociated from anything considered imperfect in creatures, and the pinnacle of perfection in God is for His attributes to be unlike those of creatures entirely. Ibn Taymiyya
sums it up thus: ` [God] is qualified by every attribute of perfection such that no one
bears any likeness to Him in it' (quoted in Hoover 2007: 65). On this basis Ibn Taymiyya
ascribes to God a wide range of attributes that he deems perfections in humans including laughter, joy, and movement. These attributes are of course attested in revealed texts,
but Ibn Taymiyya maintains that they are apparent from reason as well. Moreover, God
must be ascribed with such attributes of perfection. Otherwise, He will be regarded as
imperfect and unworthy of worship.
Ibn Tayrniyya's view of what constitutes God's essential perfectionperpetual, temporal, and purposeful activitysets him apart from practically the entire preceding
Islamic tradition. Elements of his formulation are found in Karrami theology, Fakhr
al-Din al-Razi, and the philosopher Aba 1-Barak8t al-Baghdadi (d. 56o/1165), but tbn
'Fayniiyya surpasses all of these in developing a consistently dynamic understanding of
God. According to Ibn Taymiyya, God has been acting, creating, and speaking by His
will and power for wise purposes from eternity (min al-azal). God's acts subsist in His
0.)1M);',1t: rn'ard

very essence, and in tc mporal succession. He -..r.:tvs ;


be quai l-y) acts subs:sting in Him on.e after another' (t:10' ,'.'d
Y;). ihn ya rarely uscs lie term iemporaily
qualify ;od's acts, 'T.-eteri- io:; to tr.' i , ISIC.td of God's
,!.
language Joser to tic ! does i;:dicat(.,
..lnporality, and he takes it upon t'; elute the 'Its
`-itbmstiag i it (
In maintaining that Cod bas been creating from eternity, Ib ri Tay I V , ';; Alt a
middle position between thefaisafa of Ibn Sind on the one hand ..nd on the other.
Ibn Taymiyya agrees with the Jalsafa tradition that God's perfection entails eternal productivity. To posit a starting point in God's creative action, as does Kaiam, implies that
God was imperfect prior to beginning to create and subject to change when He switched
from not creating to creating. Moreover, an efficient cause or preponderator (murallih)
was needed to tip the balance in favour of God beginning His creative :L.' ivity, Resisting
this argument, Ash`arite Kalam held that it was in the very nature 4 (;lcfs eternal will
to preponderate or cause creation to begin at a certain point; no additional cause need
be posited. tbn Tayrniyya rejects this. Nothing can arise without a prior cause. Ibn Sina
concluded from these considerations that God's eternal productivity entailed the emanation of an eternal world. Ibn Taymiyya affirms similarly that God's perpetual creativity entails that there have always been created things of one sort or another, However,
he has no patience for Ibn Sina's emanation scheme and its hierarchy of eternal celestial
spheres. In agreement now with the Ka/am tradition, he denies that any created thing
can be eternal. Rather, created things by definition come into -..xistence in time after
they were not. To make sense of his position, Ibn Taymiyya (list itici, ishes between the
genus (jins) of created things on the one hand and individual tlings on the other.
The genus is eternalthere have always been created things of nie sort or another
but each individual created thing originates in time. Additionally, God does not create
new things out of nothing but out of prior created things, and this present world that
God created in six days (Q 7) was preceded by and created out of prior worlds. Ibn
Taymiyya's view of creation is remarkably close to that of the phi le sop!i Ibn Rushd, but
it is not clear whether there was direct influence.
Regarding God's speech, .lbn Taymiyya rejects the Ash`arite ooct ri 1 -f of the eternal
Qur'an, but he does not follow the Mu`tazilis in calling the Qur'in ei timed. Instead, he
holds that God has been speaking from eternity by His will and po, ver arid that God's acts
of speaking subsist in God's essence. As with created things, the of God's speaking is eternal while His individual speech acts are not. However, it is not said that God's
speech acts are created. This is because they subsist in God's essen , .c, not outside of God.
Thus, God's individual speech acts are neither created nor eternal, and, likewise, God's
speech in the Qur'an is 'uncreated' (ghayr makhlaq) but not etei pal. ..%3 IS apparent, the
!erm 'uncreated' does not mean timeless eternity for Ibn Taymiyya. ilather, it distillishes God's acts from created things in the world. On the verbal !eve!, lbn Td:,-.11iiyyil is
ful to the traditional Hanbali doctrine of the Qur'an's uncrealednessind he .1;tints
:hat his position is that of Ahmad b. blanbal. But his introduction tcmiloi al seiii:enee

640

JON HOOVER

dnr!,,
into the s :6-tc Ai God :na
F, 1r,lc...-,11. ( in a debai vitt ..s..sn a cite, ttcs.iiit
.d ,tok

...tethtit
..;tfocc.; t.
ya
r 'tt

11'.:1,11Q:.,1

f 1.1.1r Cr,...1:11;CS act :iEIF

e
:~ ^. e

than a khig -rind his


timt . Yt2t. tha.: Icing mit..;',It dko refrain from
i - ort:cri Ind L'4. hit subt<Att t.tnapota,t..tcd to rise up : ainst
c,od
ifmt ctich tttxtimpies Tc

.1 ,1d

'C. `;01.0.-01, OfF,Cing


1..111 it+ ii)

i'; -4ithotat illy itf ity a Ti' the to,ot- ikftt:


Asinari inch as al Rai and Sayi al-Din al ,A (ii. n11/1233) dtny :hat ( lod creates
for iiirposes or causes in :ler to render Ge,!'s 66iti if the world i cely icvatuitous.
In this Ash`arite voluntarism, God has no tic,,al olike wiirld, and the i.voi lel is st rictly the
product of God's sheer will. Ibn Taymiyya does not interpret Ciid's independence or
iaitticiency apart from the world in this voluntarist sense. Instead, he explains that God's
suilkiency consists in needing no help in creating the world, and he follows Ibn Sind in
giving priority to God's self-intellection and selt-love and making that the ground for
the rest of existence. We see this for example in Ibn 'Eaymiyya's statement: 'What God
loves of worship of Him and obedience to Him follows from love for Himself, and love
of that is the cause of [His] love for His believing servants. His love for believers follows
from love for Himself' (quoted in Hoover 2007: 99). Here, God's self-love is the ground
for all other love. God does not need human love, and, likewise, God does not need the
creation. Nevertheless, human love and the whole of creation follow necessarily from
God's love ion Himself and from His perfection.
The nec..i-oity with which God's acts flow from God's perfection would appear to obviate rpality- of God's choice. Ibn Taymiyya responds, however, that it is possible for
*"u p cedetermined to occur through God's will and power. God's will and power
arc means by which the concomitants of God's perfection are brought into existence.
1bn irayiniyya writes, 'It is not impossible that something, which is necessary of occurrence because the decree that it must inevitably be has preceded it, occur by... His power
and His will, even if it is among the necessary concomitants of His essence like His life
and His knowledge' (adapted from Hoover zoioa: 66).
A similar question arises at the level of human acts. If God predetermines and creates
all human acts, how are humans to be held accountable for their deeds? Following in
the steps of Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, Ibn Taymiyya affirms that the human act is real and
that humans undertake their acts by means of their own will and power. Nonetheless,
it is God who creates the human will and power, and it is by means of these that He
necessitates human acts. Nothing occurs independently of God's will and creation. lbn
-l'ayiniyya denies any contradiction in this formulation, and when pressed on the point,
he sometimes switches from the perspective of God's creation to the human perspec live of responsibility to evade the inference that humans cannot be held accountable
for deeds that God creates. Faced with a similar paradox between God's ccfnmand to
do good deeds and God's creation of bad deeds, Ibn Taymiryia appeals to :..;od's wise
purpose :he creation of all things and suggests ways of rri itigatinr, the difficulty. He

;.;1
f;!''.I.k. 1" Ci

AVOUid his

r uff,,,,e.

V HANBAL1 THEOLOGY FROM THE


FOURTEENTH CENTURY TO THE EIGHTEENTH
The early eighth/fourteenth century was an especially fertile period for Fjanbali theology, and two figures beyond ibn Taymiyya are worthy of flute. Najm alDin (d. 716/1316), was something of an eccentric amonti Ijanlialis. Arriving in
Damascus from Baghdad in 704/1304-5, he was briefly a student if 11.in Tay m iyya before
it:0\ring on to Cairo the next year. He wrote a commentary on parts of he Bible and a
r,2fiatation of Christianity, and he was accused of Shil sympathies in i,ter life. He is well
known among modern Muslim legal theorists for his bold ap7ui to beni.ilit
over revealed texts in law formulation, although it seetns that this had i ttk impact in his
own time. He also wrote a non-extant defence of logic and Kalath: ,naf
al-mantiq .wa-l-kaldm, His last work, al-Isharat al-ilcihiyya, is a commentary on Qur'anic
verses relating to principles ofjurisprudence andtheology (Heinrichs 1960- .2.00.1).
Al-Tufl's eccentricity is readily evident in his Dar' al-yawl al-qabih, wal-taribih,. He refutes the Nlu`tazili views that reason discerns the ethical value of acts
and that humans create their own acts independently of God's :ontrol, and he argues
that God determines and creates all acts. Yet, he notes that the t. iiir`anic evidence supporting God's determination of human acts is not unequivocal. ;ortic verses also indicate human responsibility and choice, which implies that the Q , lean is contradictory.
\'h.`, al-Tati does with this observation may be unique among Muslim theologians.
le. suggests that contradiction in the Qur'an is in fact a proof for the prophethood of
Mol.lammad. Everyone agrees that Muljammad was eminently in . clligent and that i rad
ligent authors will necessarily work to remove all contradictions from their writ trigs.
Seeing that the Qur'an contains contradiction, it is evidently not 'rum Muhammad and
must be from God. It might be objected that Muhammad introduced contradiction
inio the Qur'an as a ruse, but al-Tufi insists that intelligent al ithi irs would never judge
introducing contradiction intentionally to be in their interest (Shiliadch 2006).
The second major eightlliti)urteenth-century figure beyond I bn raynt i vya 'dB forestudent Dm Qayyim al- lawziyya (d. 751/135o). While remaini,1); faithful to the blsic
urs of his teacher's theology, he wrote more systematically with greater literary

642 VON I";

A 1:1;101.11.
(TY:: healing alinicots
Ind :Imlay of
*);:ta.:.les to ,:t.it1Ci.1
ng ,k
C

sola.fi
iC CCMc.'0r:+111.11
u^ or tileologic.1 -sues if.!,1!;ve intel ice1:.

i10011
,1 ,;11 ill:: Asia

, 111111:31.t +1r .

=C

ea71,"
C111,1 j1alge (10''.11:11.SCUS
explains, among other things, God's wi.a. purposes in tbe creation of !lie diverse phenomena of this world (Holtzman 2009: /09-10, 216-17; Boni and I lollztnan 2010: 25-6).
TwO of ffin al-Qay-yim's later books, written after 1345, are among the fullest treatments
of their respective theological topics in the Islamic tradition. Shifcil al-`ald fleshes out
the contours of Ibn Taymiyya's theodicy at great length. The first half elaborates God's
determination and creation of all things, and it explains that, while God creates human
acts, humans are the agents of their acts and therefore responsible for their deeds. The
second half of the book argues that God creates all things for wise purposes in a causal
sense. Evils are in fact good in view of God's wise purposes in creating them, and pure
evil does not exist. Ibn al-Qayyim then outlines, in detail far exceeding anything found
in Ilan Tayrniyya, the wise purposes that God has in creating everything from poisons to
disobedience, and even Iblis (Perho 2001; Hoover 2010b).
The second work, Ibn. al-Qayyim's al-,Sawariq al-mursala, is a massive refutation of
the presuppositions underlying Kaldm metaphorical reinterpretation. Only the first
half of the work is extant, and resort must be made to the abridgement Mukhtasar alsawa`iq al-mursala of Shams al-Din b. al-Mawsili (d. 774/1372) to gain a sense of the
whole. Writing along Taymiyya.n lines, Ibn al-Qayyim denies that reason and revelation
ever contradict in the interpretation of God's attributes. I le attacks the Kalam notion
of metaphor (majaz) at great length and defends the reliability of traditions providing
information about God's attributes (Qaclhi 2010).
IHanbali theology in the centuries following Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya has not been
studied carefully (for surveys, see Laoust 1939: 493-540; Laoust 196o-2004), but it
appears that Ibn Taymiyya's thought was not highly influential within the school, at
least not until the Taymiyyan-inspired revivalism of the nineteenth century in Iraq,
Syria, and Egypt. Even in his own day, Ibn Taymiyya's circle of students was small (Bori
2010), and Lianbalis have never embraced his theology as school doctrine. However,
Ibn Taytniyya's ideas did find their best-known pre-modern advocate in Ibn 'Abd alWahhab (d. 1206/1792), a Hanball scholar in central Arabia.
'Taking his cue from Ibn 'Paymiyya, Ibn 'Abd al-Wahhab drew a distinction between
taw*/ al-ruhubiyya, the affirmation that God is the sole creator of the world, and
tawhid al-ulithlyya or tawhid alitbada, the exclusive devotion of worship and service
''..d according to the divine law. Ibn 'Abd al-Wahhab likewise gave priority to the
ethical/legal tawhid al- ulithiyya over the mere confession of God as Creator in taw,i)id
al-rububiyya, and he narrowed the scope of tawhid al-tillthiyya to exclude a wide
range of popular practices such as saint veneration, tomb visitation, and magic. lbo

Niad was .:darr.a;u pi :iictices had to be


(:iti: ) Ind k:radi,:at?1, ,uld lie ,.Iligneci with the ce-ziral lbian em;.
!,) h* 11ctiLJgical i-zion into practi,
throtio'n :619.
:fl ry. T}
:4 ,- 1:di ...t:110, the modern :tate
the
hos been Ills!rLm icnt 41 in spreadino

101

%:',)1117;i1) far beyond. :is lior,Tars, especially in !lie


,u:s 1999).

BIBLIOGRAPHY
_
'Abd al-Qadir al-Jilani (1995). Sufficient Provision for Seekers of the Pith (Al-Chunya
Taffy al-Haqq). Trans. M. Holland. 5 vols. Houston: Al- P,:b1 Mg.
`Abd al-)adir al-Jilani (1999). Al-Ghunya turiq al-haqq. Ed, 1::11:1 r-js ai-Harastani. 2
vols. Beirut: Dar
Abrahamov, B. (1995). "The bi-la kayfa Doctrine and its Foundations in Islamic licology.
Arabica 42:365-79.
Abu va.la Ibn al-Farm` (1974). Kitab al- mu`tarnad ji usal al-din. Ed. Wadi Z. Haddad.
Beirut: Dar el-machreq.
Abit Ya'1,1 1bn al- Farra (1989-9oa). 11)4 al-ta'wilat li-akhbar al-sitat. Ed. Abii 'Abd Allah
Muhammad b. Hamad al-Hammild al-Najdi. Kuwait: Maktabat Dar al- 'Juan'. al-Dhahabi.
Abil `tali Ibn al-Farra' (1989-9ob). Masall al-iman. Ed. Saud 'Alit' aljAziz Khalaf.
Riyadh: Dar al 2asima.
Ahmad Hanbal (attrib.) (1973). Al-Radd
a-l-jo;a Cairo: al-Matba'a
al-salafiyya wa-maktabatuha.
'Ali, 'Abdullah bin Fl amid (trans.) (2006). Abd al-.Rahrnan Ibn atlawzi: The Attributes of God.
Bristol, UK: Amal Press.
d-A.nsari al-liarawi, 'Abd Allah (1998). DilaMM al-kalam wa-ahlih, I 1. jabir 'Abd Allah
b. Muhammad b. 'Uthinan al-Ansari. 5 vols. Medina: Maktabal al4;:iuraba' al-Athariyya.
WI, J. N. (1979). Love Theory in Later ,Hanbalite Islam. Albany, NY: :31.' N Prcss.
C. (201o). 'Ibn `Taymiyya wa-jama'tuhu: Authority, ColAL.t IA Consensus in Ibis
Ta.ymiyya's Circle In Y. Rapoport and S. Ahmed (eds.), Ibn and His Times,
Karachi: Oxford University Press, 23-52.
!iori, C., and L. Holtzman (2010), 'A Scholar in the Shadow ; Jod 1.-loltzman (eds.),
A Scholar in the Shadow: Essays in the Legal and Theological Mc v/ /^ " V' .1`'*' alCawziyyah. Oriente Moderno monograph series, 90/1: 13-44.
:ook, M. (2000). Commanding Right and Forbidding Wron ,,,,-
hoagia
(...:,imbrisige: Cambridge University Press.
-.Aber, H. (1994). 'The Quran as a "Shibboleth" of Varying Conecrtl,.-,:15, ,Jr0-:,, ,.
A ath
Century Hanbalite-Ash'arite Discussion and its Theological in :II,' Protocol ibn
Qudama Israel Oriental Studies 14: 249-95.
Gimarct, (1977).'Theories de l'acte humain dans l'ecolebanbalite.
o{ B. (2009). Shan.,i: Thcory, Practice, Tr s ations.
Press.

1 .:iiiversity

644 ION HOOVER

P ;;::0 ?!.'vya
10 a. stina. stajtf,..iJ 11

Theodicy Opr:snisin.
yis ; ncology ot a Personal
;.3-...r.. 1. 1. , ..%.tr, by His Will cud
,iid it)1. uCie Voluntary Attributes:. In Y. Rapoport al S. Ahmed (eds.), Ibn
;:!,IiiJaa; 1,HICS. Karachi: Oxford University Press, 55-77.
God's Wise Purposes in Creating flails: Ihn Qayynn al-Gawziyyah's
1.))'
!,f E:ames and Ali rj LCIT.11:'''. In C. Burl and L. Holtzman (eds.), A Scholar in the
at4 rowziyyah. Oriente
I .:.s.rys in the Legal and Thought ofthu s ;
[no fionograph series, 90/1:113 14,
Abu 1.-Husayn MuhammaJ..1 (1952). Tabaqat J:d. Muhammad klamid
Cairo: !Ma tba jat al-sunna al-mulaammadiyya.
k a tia I .p;8). il ProfOssio.:: foi crIbn Batta [al-l/inc if ju.;11,,il. Ed. and trans. FL Laoust.
),onascus: Institut irau iS ii Damas.
lbr, (1990. Dap/H&c/1a: -Ws/thin bi-akdff al . ,,, al af. Amman: Dar
al Lia;:i al: Nlawawi.
'hi (2.,:o1). A Mc:Ili- I.:it Cr ,tique of Anthroponlorphiou
. A i.t.,1:cal Edition of ,ne AJ -abic Text with Translat i ,o.

sk.h !rit' ,7(1-

Swxrtz.
Jim - iawd L006). The Ai; ributes ,Tod (Dar Shubah Al-Tasidalt
Al)(1,itlah bin 1:larnid Ali. It isi.01, UK: Amal Press.
wa 1-mu
lbn Qa:y jtn al-Jawziyya (1987-8). Kitab al-sawa`iti al- Innrsala
Ed. 'Ali b..Muharnmad Allah. 4 vols. RE, !lir Ii`Asima.
wi
Ibn Qayyim. al-Eawzayya (2004). Mukhtasar al saw.i i ii oeursata
Al-li,isau b. 'Abd al-Rahman almu`attila. Abridgement Muhammad b.
`Alawi. Riyadh: Maktabat adwa j atsalaf.
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya (2007). Al-Kajiyya al-shajiyya ji 1-inti s. ar al-najiyya. Ed.
Muhammad b. Abd al-Rahman al2Arifi eta!, 4 vols. Mecca: Dar A/am
al-Jawziyya (2008). Shifa' rnasa al-qader'wa-l-qaciar wa-l-hikma wa-I1,11d Ed. Ahmad b. Salila b. Al! al-Samdani and All b. Muhammad h. `Abd Allah al-dAjlan. 3
101s. Ilir adh: .Dar
Ibn :,jayyitn al-Jawziyya (2010-11). mifikaij dar al-sdada. Ed, Abd al-.Ralatnan b. Hasan
b. Utid. 3 outs. Mecca: Dar 'Adam al-fawald.
lb a 0.110,Ain :962). Ibn.Qudarnds Censure of Speculative Theology riltlarfrn al-ruazarl. Ed. and
tams. 1. Makdisi. London: Lii,r.ac.
wa al-naql. Ed. Muhammad P. had Udlifli. ii vols.
"111 iyya (1979-83). Dar -
Riyadh: lamfat NI ulaaminad b. Sa`fid al-!slInicv; a.
::iyijyya (1986). Minha) ai.sunna al-nabawiyya I. lu,;.l 1,aialti al ilQarlarlyva. Id
1,'..:3;w1n3 Rashad Salim. 9 vols. Riyadh: Jami`at itl-Imain Muhammad b. Su'fiti

Jfr !.
ff:irr.:11:
jte t
1. )57). 'Les Premieres P, :dcssions de thi , irbalitc-d
3:

aoust, 11, (1958). La Profession de foi Patta. Da1113.A:US:.Instilut de Damas,


irtust, it. (i96o - zoo4).`Hantibilal In .Encyclopaedia of Islam. New edo 462.
'..!adel:mg, W. (1974). 'The Origins of the Controversy Concerning ill.: Cia:at,...al of he Koran:
j'!arral (ed.), Orient:lint hispanica. Leidina: Brill, 504-25 [!1r':r. i W. Madelung,
.-:./lo,4s and Sects in Al..diTal Is/un, Ton. ion... Viriorum
(;. (1962). Ibn Qudarnds l iour of Speculative Theology. 1 01, 1,,,n;
k11;si, G. (1962-3). Ash'ari and the Ash`arites in Islamic Religious listtirv: Islamica
1..7: 37-80 and 18: 19-39 [Repr. in 0. Makdisi, Religion, Law and I
1,H Thire, UK: Variorum, 199i, Part IJ.
1`.1:1ixdisi, G. (1963). /1:n 11!iil et ta resurgence de l'Islam traditionalist: 7).:mascus:
Ins:Mut Francais de Damas.
G. (1973). "The Sunni Revival: In D. S. Richards (..8.1.)',:!,
11s Cord: I .assirer,155-68.
( 979). The Hanbali School and Siifistn: flo1,170 :le 11 J o; i .poiola de
(it, !::,i/Istas 15: 115-26 [Repr. in C. Makdisi, Rhgioo, Law W:fi
f
I ilop:hire, UK: Variorum, 1991, Part V].
0.11)8'). isnon: In M. 1.. Swart.: I:.1.1Ntudics
( ford
t,iiersity Press, 216-64.
997). Ibn 'Agit: and Cairarc in 1 ,.-;.sical

i \Jai oudi, A, H. (2006). The 1..litilba/rSchool.ij Lite anil
l's.
10,1: H.LIC,'..f.,
Ad; her!, C. (1997). The Formation of the Stow; N 3'. 'U if In,: 41 .
C
I ...Kt.!): Brill..
H. bet t, C. (2006). Ahmad Ibn 1Ianbal. Oxford:

14.:ih!rt, C. (2011). "`Cod rested Adam in His image-.


I- i--24.
:` icnsTl: C. (2012), 41 Ijafbaharf. Encyclopaedia of 111. Ldit s1 bv
i tenis Matringe. John Nawas, Everett Rowson, Brill Online, 2013. I , ersil
is August 2013 .littp://referenceworks.brillonline.com/entries/c- yclor:i,01.1 -.if !slam-3/
al-barbahari-001\1_22944>
M idiot, J. R.(1994). Ibn Tayrniyya: I ...tire a

;:e l'Universite Catholique de List:vain.


hot, Y. I. Mamnik lieolop,jan's ( joninh ithiry on Ay; d.U.if, Itililv)ya:
.3 Translation of a Pact oi
dr!!!1 of lbn Tayrn,) v,:. jraroduction,
).:;:t and :):4,pendices: kn.:71,1,f N:::::(11cs 14: 149-203 (Pitri' I 3, 309-63
I: J.

`Th,Taytniyya's , , v ,r k
ie.apo: , ort and S. Allmed
1.1

T11H

1:'11.1CS he
K anh'i 1 i;

Criiic1srn
Thnes.

!, I 1(i3

.;iiv Pr r8 i
`.;9').I I! . .
, o
ViON, on Predestination:
C irisi 1.qi yclutions 12: 61-.70.
(196o-zoo4). "orahhisibiyya: In Ettcyclopuerna 1.,!L11!. New edn., xi. 39-45.
es, E. (n9). 'The Walihd5iyya and Sufism in the Eighteekith Century: In F. de Jong and B.
Radtke (eds.), Islamic Mysticism Contested: Thirteen Centuries of Controversies and Polemics.
Leiden: Brill, 145-61.
Qadhi, Y. (2010). -The Unleashed Thunderbolts" of Ibn Qayyim al-Ciawziyyah: An
Introductory Essay: In C. Bori and L. Holtzman (eds.), A Scholar in the Shadow: Essays in the
Legal and Theological Thought of Ibn Qayyim al-Cawziyyah. Oriente Moderno monograph
series, 90/i: 135-49.
Sabari, S. (1981). Mouvements populaires a Bagdad a repoque 'abbaside, ixe-xie siecies.
Maisonneuve.
al-Sarhan, S. S. (2011). 'Early Muslim Traditionalism: A Critical Study of the Works and
Political Theology of Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: Doctoral dissertation, University of Exeter.
Seale, M. S. (1964). Muslim 'Theology: A Study of Origms with Reference to the Church Fathers.
London: Luzac.
Shihadeh, A. (2006). "three Apologetic Stances in Theological Cognitivism,
Noncognitivism, and a Proof of Prophecy from Scriptural Contradiction'. Journal of
Qur'anic Studies 8:1-23.
Swartz, M. (2002). A Medieval Critique of Anthropomorphism: Ibn al-,rawzi: kit ab .Akhbar
as-Sifat. A Critical El/lion of the Arabic Text with Tran.,lation, Intp.;duction and Notes.
Leiden: Brill.
Tiff', Najm al-Din (2002). Al-Isharat ira l-mabaljith al-usidiyya. Ed. Abu `Asim
Hasan b, 'Abbas b. Qutb. 3 vols. Cairo: al-Fa:ray al-haditha.
Tan, Najm al-Din (2005). Dar' al-qawl al-qablh wa al-taqbfit, Ed. Ayman Shihada.
Riyadh: Markaz F:aysal.
Vishanoff, D. R. (2011). The Formation of Islamic Hermeneutics: How Sunni Legal Theorists
Imagined a Revealed Law. New Haven: American Oriental Society.
Watt, W. M. (1994). Islamic Creeds, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Williams, W. (2002). 'Aspects of the Creed of Imam Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: A Study of
Anthropomorphism in Early Islamic Discourse: International Journal of Middle East Studies
34: 441-63.

THE OXFORD HAND KOOK OF

ISLAM IC
THEOLOGY
Edited by

SABINE SCHMIDTKE

2_0?

OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen