Sie sind auf Seite 1von 27

STEVEN CROWELL

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

1. PHENOMENOLOGY BETWEEN ANALYTIC AND CONTINENTAL


PHILOSOPHY

Writing in 1945 Maurice Merleau-Ponty asked, What is phenomenology? and observed that it may seem strange that this question has still to be asked half a century after the rst works of Husserl (Merleau-Ponty 1962, vii). One hundred years after the publication of Husserls Logische Untersuchungen the question has a different ring to it. In 1945, in Paris, to ask what phenomenology is was to ask about the undisputed fons et origo of the leading philosophical currents of the time, and thus the question had much the same anxious undertone that Michael Dummetts question about analytic philosophy had, some fty years later, in the philosophical milieu of Oxford (Dummett 1993). Today, though, the question is likely to be asked only by an undergraduate seeking a denition that will obviate the need to read, or by a non-philosopher making the phenomenologist uncomfortable at a social gathering. Among those who profess Continental philosophy, some answer to the question will generally be taken for granted as obvious, while among professors of analytic philosophy there reigns a widespread indifference to the answer. Either way, the question does not get asked. This situation is regrettable, but the interesting circumstance that two books bearing the title Introduction to Phenomenology were published in 2000 suggests that it may be changing. Perhaps the complacency that has lately surrounded the topic of phenomenology in both Continental and analytic circles may be giving way to an interest in taking a fresh look at a philosophical approach that has connections to both. These two Introductions could not be more different. Dermot Moran presents detailed accounts of major phenomenological thinkers on a scale that has not been attempted since Herbert Spiegelbergs The Phenomenological Movement, while Robert Sokolowskis far shorter work consigns reference to individual philosophers to an appendix and proceeds topically. Moran offers a developmental account of phenomenology as the story
Synthese 131: 419444, 2002. 2002 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

420

STEVEN CROWELL

of deviations from Husserl, expertly laying out the biographical and historical relationships, as well as the philosophical conicts. Sokolowski, in contrast, makes no reference to biography and history, concisely amalgamating founding ideas and defensible deviations into a unied picture of what phenomenology is. Thus where Moran for the most part adopts the stance of impartial historian, writing about disputes in phenomenology without taking sides in them, Sokolowskis writing exemplies phenomenology by defending a distinctive position within it. Both books are beautifully written, both are crafted to be accessible to those trained in analytic philosophy, both are deeply philosophically informed. And because their different excellences complement one another, when taken together they provide the sort of introduction to phenomenology that the times demand. And yet, their appearance brings out an ambiguity that was already present in Merleau-Pontys own answer to the question and that continues to grumble in many of todays philosophical discontents. For on the one hand, confronting the diversity of what passed under the heading phenomenology in 1945, and looking to historical precursors, Merleau-Ponty was moved to suggest that phenomenology can be practiced and identied as a manner or style of thinking . . . before arriving at complete awareness of itself as a philosophy; yet, on the other hand, this very phenomenology is said to be accessible only through a phenomenological method (Merleau-Ponty 1962, viii). The rst observation suggests a loose tradition, a set of practices with family resemblances to one another, a cluster of relatively independent voices, while the latter suggests something different: an orientation toward a common set of issues dened by commitment to a relatively explicit protocol; a mentality willing to limit itself to what can be pursued methodologically and to leave alone all that cannot be; in short, something like a research program. There is little doubt that phenomenology is a manner or style of thinking, but is there a phenomenological research program? This is the question I shall pose to our two Introductions, since it seems to me that the answer is of some consequence for understanding the options facing philosophy in the twenty-rst century. Why does this question matter? One reason concerns the relation between phenomenology and analytic philosophy. Though few would agree with his account in all details, it seems that Michael Dummetts view of this relation is widely shared: because it was able to make the linguistic turn, analytic philosophy could establish itself as a viable program of research into meaning; because it was unable to make the linguistic turn, phenomenology could not. By adhering to its twin axioms the belief, rst, that a philosophical account of thought can be attained through a

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

421

philosophical account of language, and, secondly, that a comprehensive account can only be so attained (Dummett 1993, 4) analytic philosophy could get a grip on the non-psychological domain of thought, otherwise unavailable for reasoned inquiry. Phenomenology, by contrast, followed Husserl in the generalization of the notion of Sinn from linguistic acts to all intentional acts for instance, perception and could not, therefore, take the linguistic turn, since language can play no special part in the study and description of these non-linguistic animators of non-linguistic mental acts (Dummett 1993, 27). Though Dummett does not quite say so, his criticisms of Gareth Evans suggest that failure to take the linguistic turn condemns phenomenology to being a mere tradition whose practitioners [adopt] a certain philosophical style and [appeal] to certain writers rather than to certain others and not a research program (Dummett 1993, 45).1 It is clear that Husserl would not have been pleased by such an assessment. But if, on the contrary, it were possible to identify something like a phenomenological research program, might it not have implications for all those excommunicated analytic philosophers (such as Evans, John McDowell, or Christopher Peacocke) for whom reection on thought, or even perception, independent of linguistic expression, has a central role in their theories? The question matters for another reason as well, this one arising within Continental philosophy. Of late there has been a urry of writing devoted to telling the story of this hybrid genre, the narrative impulse here, as in the case of analytic philosophy, responding to anxieties about identity.2 Despite their many differences, these stories largely turn on how phenomenology is understood and how its impact on twentieth-century European thought is assessed. Though extensive review of this literature would take us too far aeld, a glance at some of the issues will show what is at stake in our question. One issue over which the narratives differ concerns the historical scope of the term Continental philosophy. Some writers for instance, McNeill and Feldman, Critchley, Kearney, and West stress a nineteenth-century genealogy. In Wests terms, Continental philosophy is the outcome of a series of critical responses to dominant currents of modern western and Enlightenment philosophy (West 1996, vii) and to Kant in particular such that the names of Schelling, Hegel, Marx, Kierkegaard, and Nietzsche loom large. In these narratives the question of whether phenomenology is a viable research program is rather incidental to the identity of Continental philosophy. Some may acknowledge that the phenomenological movement . . . would radically transform and revitalize Continental philosophy (Kearney and Rainwater 1996, 3), but it is no more central to its identity

422

STEVEN CROWELL

than is structuralism, for example. This approach can produce queer anachronisms, however for instance, the claim that Kants philosophy may be said to be the point at which so-called Continental thought begins to diverge from Anglo-American analytic philosophy (McNeill and Feldman 1998, 1), or that it is with and after Hegel that it begins to make sense to speak of Continental and analytic (West 1996, 3). Hence, a second set of writers including Embree et al., Ihde, and May locates the core of Continental philosophys identity in the twentieth-century. The term itself emerged in the United States in the 1970s as a way to identify the growing number of practitioners of a diverse cluster of contemporary philosophical styles generally arising in Europe phenomenology, existentialism, hermeneutics, critical theory, deconstruction, and so on.3 And for this second group of writers, what holds Continental philosophy together lies in the relation, however critical, of all these various movements to Husserls phenomenology. Hence the question of whether phenomenology can be taken to be a research program, as Husserl proposed and if not, why not is central to the identity of Continental philosophy. A second issue concerns whether the narrative is constructed as development and progress or as decay and decline. In the former (not surprisingly, more common) sort, Husserls phenomenology generally plays the role of a terminus a quo whose liberatory potential must be freed from its scientistic prison. Todd May (1997, 1820) judges Husserls project to be essentially the same as Descartes, and his story emphasizes the departures from this project, culminating in the structuralist inversion of it the primacy of structure over consciousness that characterizes Continental philosophy today. Brogan and Risser (2000, 23) speak of a turn from pure phenomenology in the direction of hermeneutic phenomenology, and nally of a shift from phenomenology to poststructuralism. Kearney (1994, 13) holds that many concerns of Continental thought culminate in a radical anti-foundationalism, though some, like Husserl, nd this renunciation of the metaphysical quest for absolute grounds regrettable. A corollary of this narrative is a rejection of the very notion of a philosophical research program as scientistic. Continental philosophy is more an art than a science (Kearney 1994, 2). It is a style of philosophizing that proceeds historically and works beyond the perspective or objective of obtaining eternal truths (McNeill and Feldman 1998, 2). In its critique of Enlightenment rationality, it is the distant relation of those metaphysicians, moralists, and believers so caustically dismissed by Hume, . . . unwilling to abandon the concerns and insights animated by these modes of experience (West 1996, 4). Critchley and Schroeder (1998, 1213) get to the heart of the matter here: Continental

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

423

philosophy recognizes the complicity between scientic culture . . . and nihilism and thus seeks to preserve philosophys indigenous concern with meaning.4 The very idea of a philosophical research program of normal science is antithetical to philosophy since the latter is essentially critical: the responsibility of the philosopher . . . is the production of crisis (Critchley and Schroeder 1998, 12). The philosopher should rather, in Kearneys words, take risks to say the unsayable with an inimitable voice (Kearney 1994, 4). Nevertheless, before moving on to the second sort of narrative it should be noted that even within a eld that is largely given over to poststructuralist concerns and issues, the term phenomenology can still serve as a marker of legitimation. Why, for instance, has there been such heat generated around the question of a theological turn in French phenomenology with Dominique Janicaud arguing that philosophizing about the unapparent, the radically other, and so on, transgresses the boundaries of phenomenology, while Michel Henry, Jean-Luc Marion, or Emmanuel Levinas insist that such inquiries remain phenomenological?5 Here it would seem that a certain authority inheres in phenomenological investigation that elevates the inimitable voice beyond a mere style or manner of inquiry to something like rigor. No doubt this clinging to the term phenomenology signies, in part, the uneasiness that someone who denes philosophy as revelation or transgression must feel in the connes of an academic career. But there is more to it than that, as can be seen by considering an example of the second sort of narrative, in which the story is one of decay and decline. Acknowledging that there are large and contentious debates about its core ideas, Robert DAmico nevertheless believes that analytic philosophy has remained . . . a philosophical movement, whereas the continental tradition has largely ceased to be one (p. 253). His reasons for this judgment are several, but central is the claim that phenomenology was not able to constitute itself into a genuine philosophical research program what DAmico calls a philosophical tradition. What distinguishes a philosophical tradition from traditions in general and makes talk of a research program plausible here are the normative features DAmico attributes to it: First, as a kind of inquiry a philosophical tradition requires constraints. Others must be able to arrive . . . at the same conclusions on these topics in such a way that those conclusions follow, in some fashion . . . from either defended or broadly uncontroversial assumptions. Otherwise one has merely a single thinkers personal vision. Second, a philosophical tradition requires an open horizon of issues, problems, and possible clarications. It cannot consist of only the founding texts.

424

STEVEN CROWELL

Third, it must also be clear how to go on and do what the founding texts did. On all counts the promising beginning made by Husserl has been abandoned, replaced by a Continental philosophy whose intent is to be against the possibility of philosophy that is, to be free from the constraints of necessity, generality, and universality, which, once discredited, allow a thousand owers to bloom (p. 254). In DAmicos narrative of decay and decline, then, phenomenology once more serves as the terminus a quo, this time for movements that have abandoned what was distinctively philosophical about it. But for our question it is important to note that the developmental perspective whether of progress or decline can be empirically and historically accurate enough without thereby demonstrating that the development reects a necessary consequence of the phenomenological beginning. That (some) post-phenomenological Continental philosophers reject the idea of a philosophical research program does not mean that phenomenology must fail to be one. On the contrary, the fact that serious phenomenological work is being done around the world strongly suggests that DAmicos pessimistic judgment on phenomenology (leaving aside the question of Continental philosophy) may be an artefact of his narrative perspective.6 It will be useful, then, to examine where DAmico thinks phenomenology went wrong namely, in the transition from Husserl to Heidegger. This will give us a set of benchmarks for assessing the answers that the Introductions give to our question. On DAmicos account, Husserls phenomenology aimed to be a research program that would contribute to the inextinguishable task of philosophy, whose core lies in certain metaphysical and epistemological questions (pp. 254, 23). Above all, Husserl held that philosophy was an autonomous form of inquiry that could not be superceded by results in other sciences. This is expressed philosophically as a sharp distinction between what is empirical and what is a matter of a priori necessity, and phenomenology stands as a counter-current to all movements that blur or reject this distinction that is, as a counter-current to what Husserl called naturalism. Husserl was not content merely to offer arguments against epistemological naturalism a theory of knowledge masquerading as empirical science (p. 7). Rather, he sought a methodology of philosophical research that, employed in the spirit of communal investigation and mutual criticism, might succeed in clarifying the terrain that epistemological naturalism approached so obscurely namely, intentionality. Once Husserl saw through the impasses of Brentanos approach and recognized the importance of meaning (Sinn; later the noema), he designed the phenomenological method specically for its anti-naturalistic exploration.

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

425

According to DAmico that method consists of three central elements. There is, rst, an epoche or reduction in which all theoretical claims, hypothetical explanations, or philosophical special pleading are to be bracketed in favor of what Husserl calls Evidenz. The grasp of Evidenz, the seeing of phenomena as they give themselves from a rst-person stance, is the second element in the method (p. 17). Husserl held that an epoche of theories, together with a commitment to unprejudiced evidential description the principle of phenomenological neutrality or presuppositionlessness could lead to agreement and so adjudicate disputes in much the way that strictly empirical evidence resolves scientic disputes. Because of its neutrality regarding explanatory hypotheses and its reective rst-person stance, DAmico labels Husserls strategy an epistemological internalism, yet he is aware that it is no psychological internalism since the Evidenz of phenomenology does not consist exclusively in matters of fact but includes essences, or a priori necessities. The third central element in phenomenological method is thus the procedure for grasping these essences. DAmico objects to Husserls designating this procedure eidetic intuition, or seeing, since it appears to be pure conceptual analysis, that is, nothing more than grasping abstract matters of conceptual and logical necessity (pp. 15, 17). Be that as it may, on this basis phenomenology can have an indirect impact on the philosophical disputes about which it otherwise remains neutral, since the necessities involved are constraints on possibility and thus can demonstrate that some philosophical positions [such as naturalism] are epistemologically idle (pp. 17, 23). Before moving on to see what becomes of the method in Heideggers hands, we should note that DAmico judges that already Husserls version fails to be a distinctive research program. For while Husserls claims about essential structures of experience may indeed be correct, they do not seem to require, let alone actually emerge from, his method; phenomenological intuition neither establishes nor defends such conclusions any more securely than does ordinary, pedestrian conceptual analysis. Further, to speak of intuition here is highly misleading, since to see a conclusion as inconsistent or a claim as incoherent is to grasp the reasoning involved. To invoke intuition has the unsalutary effect of implying that once the essences are exhibited in this way one is thereby absolved from any further defense or argument (p. 250). Clearly, then, if we are to address this rejection of phenomenologys claim to being a viable research program an assessment that echoes Dummetts we will have to consult our Introductions on the question of phenomenologys account of the relation between argument and intuition and ask whether phenomenologys eidetic method

426

STEVEN CROWELL

is indeed indistinguishable from conceptual analysis.7 First, however, we must see how Heidegger ts into the story. As do many commentators, DAmico construes Heideggers embrace of ontology as a betrayal of central elements of Husserls research program. Though he recognizes that Heidegger shared many of Husserls convictions for instance, that philosophy is nothing psychological or subjective; that it has to do with the a priori; that it is anti-naturalistic his way of establishing these points was not phenomenological, according to DAmico, but metaphysical. When Heidegger introduced Dasein in place of Husserls transcendental ego he broke with the central methodological tenet of phenomenological neutrality and opted for simply another version of presuppositional philosophical debate. According to DAmico, the feature that Heidegger nds distinctive of Dasein that it is essentially characterized by understanding of Being is not the result of phenomenological analysis but a philosophical postulate (pp. 83, 59). Thus, while he sees virtue in Heideggers distinction between ontic (empirical) and ontological (a priori metaphysical) matters, he insists that it is vastly underargued in Being and Time and is, furthermore, incompatible with its supposed phenomenological derivation (pp. 252, 85). For later Continental philosophy, Heideggers break with phenomenological neutrality meant that what Husserl attacked as the bewitching routine of resurrected metaphysics would not only replace his dream of philosophy as rigorous science, but do so under his name (p. 43). Ironically, the very same ontological move to Dasein had the effect of opening the door to epistemological naturalism as well. This is because Dasein is characterized as factic historical being-in-the-world rather than as a transcenental ego. Though for Heidegger this was not a rejection of the a priori, it had the effect of blurring Husserls distinction between fact and essence, a blurring that, according to DAmico, later poststructuralists, textualists, historicists, and hermeneuticists would exploit into Continental philosophys own version of epistemological naturalism. The result was the now-familiar rejection of anything like an autonomous form of philosophical inquiry (p. 254). Finally, Heideggers style further exacerbated the rift between the purported method of descriptive seeing and the results obtained. DAmico nds no discernable connection between Heideggers substantive claims in Being and Time and the analyses that supposedly yield them (p. 67).8 After Being and Time, therefore, Heidegger supposedly drops this methodological pretense altogether and ushers in the current period in which thought becomes altogether a matter of inimitable voice.

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

427

This brief review of DAmicos narrative has yielded a framework, and a set of desiderata, for approaching what our two Introductions have to say about phenomenologys claim to being a philosophical research program. How do they frame what has proved to be the crucial transition from Husserl to Heidegger, from transcendental philosophy to ontology? Can it be understood as belonging to phenomenology without sacricing the elements of phenomenological method (epoche, reective Evidenz, eidetic intuition) that support its claim to be a research program? Can a different story in which phenomenology is not subordinated to a narrative about Continental philosophy be told in which it continues to live up to DAmicos desiderata for a research program: that there be genuine constraints on what can be said, rather than just personal visions; that there be a common set of problems, not just founding texts; and that there be a clear method or sense of how to go on, normal science and not merely the production of crisis? In Dermot Morans Introduction these questions are addressed specically in narrative terms. It thus provides a convenient place to begin.
2. DERMOT MORAN S HISTORICIST PHENOMENOLOGY

At the outset of his ambitious book, Moran describes several features that he takes to be characteristic of Husserls phenomenology. His account lines up pretty closely with DAmicos:9 First, phenomenology is neutral or presuppositionless, that is, it practices an epoche. In genuine phenomenological viewing, we are not permitted any scientic or philosophical hypotheses (pp. 5, 9, 11). Second, this epoche is in the service of a return to concrete lived human experience in all its richness a return carried out descriptively in reective, rst-person grasp of Evidenz or originary presentative intuition: givenness as the dative element in experience (pp. 5, 1011). Third, it seeks the a priori, or essences, through eidetic intuition a kind of conceptual clarication that does not examine the role of concepts in a language but relies on self-evident givenness of insights in intuition (p. 9). This implies a eld of research variously identied as intentionality, consciousness, or meaning that Moran sums up this way: The manner in which the world comes to appearance in and through human beings. Phenomenologys conception of objectivity-for-subjectivity is arguably its major contribution to contemporary philosophy (p. 15). For this reason phenomenology remains the most profound critique of naturalism as a philosophical program, a challenge to all third-person attempts to explain consciousness in terms of natural science (pp. 21, xiv).

428

STEVEN CROWELL

However, if we ask whether these features of Husserls phenomenology are features of phenomenology tout court, the answer we get from Moran is nuanced and highly qualied. Indeed, the very structure of his book an introduction to phenomenology as a way of doing philosophy and . . . an introduction to the philosophies of some of its most able practitioners (p. 3) systematically obscures our view of the question. On the one hand, Moran insists that even if phenomenology is a distinctive way of doing philosophy, it is important not to exaggerate . . . the extent to which phenomenology coheres into an agreed method. Husserls claims to be founding a new science have not been borne out by subsequent developments in philosophy. Phenomenology never came to be a movement in the sense that Husserl intended (pp. 3, 189, 21). Hence Moran apparently believes that phenomenology is not a philosophical research program Phenomenology cannot be understood simply as a method, a project, a set of tasks; in its historical form it is primarily a set of people and for this reason he structures his book around what this set of people took to be the phenomenological programme for the future of philosophy (pp. xiv, 3). And yet, what is implied in saying that phenomenology cannot simply be understood as a method, and that in its historical form it is what phenomenologists made of it? This seems to entail something like a normative core that constitutes phenomenology as a disciplined practice and not just a list of names (p. 14). Indeed, though Moran most often writes as an objective historian (thus making it hard to tell when he is narrating an element of empirical history or asserting a normatively necessary transformation in his own voice), there is a strong normative component in his conception of phenomenology. This is clear in his selection of gures to treat for instance, his brilliant inclusion of Hannah Arendt demonstrates that one need not actually have identied oneself as a phenomenologist in order to be an able practitioner and it is clearer still in his treatment of some of these gures. There are denite ahistorical constraints on what people can take the phenomenological program to be, as is evident in Morans chapters on Sartre and Levinas. Sartre is judged guilty of emptying out the phenomenological method until it is no more than a form of creative intuition or artistic insight into the world, while his ontology is said to be a speculative metaphysics of a very traditional kind, the very kind repudiated by Husserl and Heidegger, and the phenomenological tradition generally (pp. 363, 385). Thus a certain sort of methodological seeing, as well as metaphysical neutrality, seem to be normative for any phenomenology. About Levinas Moran is even more blunt. While Levinas certainly had a role to play in the history of phenomenology, it is un-

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

429

clear how [his] phenomenology of alterity can be a phenomenology at all (p. 352). As did Janicaud, Moran bases this judgment on the paradoxical nature of a phenomenology of what cannot show itself; it therefore implies commitment to some version of the principle of Evidenz and intuitive self-givenness. How are the normative and historical aspects of Morans approach to be brought coherently together? There seems to be a kind of phenomenological historicism at work that might be summed up as: Phenomenology transformed is still phenomenology. Phenomenology does seem to be a research program, but one whose essential features emerge historically and were not present all at once with Husserl. Indeed, Moran denes phenomenology as an enterprise begun and elaborated by Husserl and then radically transformed by Heidegger, appropriately devoting half the book to these two thinkers (p. 4). We are thus brought back to the relation between Husserl and Heidegger, and our question becomes: in Heideggers radical transformation of phenomenology, according to Moran, can we identify (as DAmico could not) the elements of a continuing philosophical research program a program to whose normative features Moran himself occasionally makes appeal? According to Moran, when Heidegger takes up the phenomenological program he rejects three central facets of Husserls phenomenology: First, against Husserls suspicion of world-view philosophy Heidegger argues that phenomenology must be attentive to historicity or the facticity of human living. Second, against Husserls emphasis on description Heidegger argues that all description involves interpretation. And third, against Husserls transcendental idealism Heidegger identies phenomenology with ontology. The consequence is that after Husserl, Heidegger immediately reintroduced the historical and relative into phenomenology (pp. 2022). But everything depends on how and in what form the historical and relative are reintroduced. For it was precisely here, according to DAmico, that Heidegger opened the door to epistemological naturalism by undermining the sharp phenomenological distinction between fact and essence, the empirical and the a priori. In such a case it would not be Husserl, as Moran asserts, who never satisfactorily resolved the way in which fact and essence are entwined in my own self-relation (p. 179), but rather Heidegger, since his move from transcendental idealism to the hermeneutics of facticity would amount to abandoning the only basis upon which the distinction could be maintained. Does Moran provide a view of Heideggers turn to the historicity and facticity of human being that is compatible with his apparently normative view of the anti-naturalism of phenomenology?

430

STEVEN CROWELL

Like DAmico, Moran considers Husserls transcendental idealism to be an epistemological internalism. In contrast, he takes Heideggers transformation to be a move toward externalism (p. 193). One way of understanding this is to say that, for Heidegger, it is impossible to clarify meaning and intentionality without taking the world into account. This cannot be meant in the sense of a causal theory of reference, however, for this would import ontic or empirical explanatory hypotheses into philosophy a move that Heidegger rejects. On Morans account, Heideggers sort of externalism remains phenomenological because, rather than appealing to anything outside the phenomenological space of appearing (itself no longer seen as belonging to consciousness), it invokes the fundamental . . . relation between Dasein and Being (p. 194). The trick, however, is to say how this notion of Being can be given phenomenological sense; otherwise its claim to be other than a metaphysical postulate, on the one hand, or a naturalistic explanans, on the other, will evaporate. Unlike DAmico, Moran is clear why Heideggers Being is not a metaphysical postulate. Where the tradition conceived being ultimately as an entity, Heidegger sees phenomenology as making inquiry possible into the manner in which the structures of Being are revealed through the structures of human existence (p. 197). Being belongs to the phenomenon qua phenomenon; phenomenology is ontology. However, if one asks about the method of this inquiry, Morans historicist thesis about Heideggers transformation of phenomenology makes it difcult to decide whether the relation between Dasein and Being does not collapse into a non-philosophical empiricism after all. On the one hand, Moran recognizes that Heidegger wants to map out the transcendental conditions that make human existence (Dasein) possible, and that he does so on the basis of the appearing or disclosure of things (pp. 197, 194). Heidegger thus embraces phenomenologys principle of Evidenz or givenness, as well as its orientation toward the eidetic or a priori. On the other hand, Moran argues that on Heideggers interpretive transformation of phenomenology there is no presuppositionless description; rather, the descriptive project is impossible unless it is situated inside a radically historicized hermeneutics (pp. 278, 20). But are these conceptions compatible? Wont the latter end by rendering the former otiose in the manner of epistemological naturalism or historicism showing how all putative a priori structures are nothing but (temporary) historical products? Moran notes that Heidegger ultimately gave up on the transcendental project abandoning it as a residue of both his and the traditions theistic past (pp. 208, 260). But it is not clear whether Moran thinks that Heidegger

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

431

also gave up on a phenomenological research program. It seems that he might hold that view, since he argues that Husserls attempt to achieve essential insight eventually became distorted into Heideggers gnomic way of letting meanings appear (p. 188). But if that is so, what is the difference, in Heidegger, between transforming phenomenology and abandoning it? It is nally hard to say what is implied for phenomenology as a research program when Moran correctly describes the historical situation as one in which, after Being and Time, Heidegger rejected the straitjacket of transcendental philosophy, or when he reports that Heidegger turned [phenomenology] into anthropology (pp. 198, 90). If this is not to amount to epistemological naturalism, must we not assume that a path to the intuitive grasp of the a priori is still available after the turn to interpretation? And must we not afrm the possibility of a kind of neutrality an epoche of explanatory theories at least even if the idea of abandoning all ones Vor-urteile is chimerical?10 That Moran believes that at least a quasi-transcendental claim remains possible for phenomenology perhaps essential to its program is suggested by his treatment of Gadamer. Here too Moran emphasizes Gadamers break with Husserl, his desire to get at the event of understanding without reducing it to a subjective or epistemological framework. Nevertheless, as a phenomenologist Gadamer is also producing a kind of transcendental description of the conditions which make understanding possible, and he is not as far removed from his neo-Kantian and Husserlian heritage as he often claims (pp. 250, 283). Is this a good thing? Well, if transcendental philosophy is a straitjacket, then probably not. But Moran is wary of an excessive historicism, judging that Gadamers embrace of historical relativism may also be a signicant weakness in his philosophy (p. 286). We are returned to the central question: how did Heidegger reintroduce the historical and relative into phenomenology without running afoul of this judgment? If Heidegger did radically transform phenomenology, must it nevertheless not retain the core elements that we have seen constitute it as a research program, elements that tie it to a transcendental rather than a naturalistic philosophical outlook? The delicacy of this issue is evident, nally, in Morans discussion of Merleau-Ponty, who has provided the most original and enduring contribution to post-Husserlian phenomenology in France (p. 391). The key to Merleau-Pontys contribution is that his access to Husserls unpublished research manuscripts allowed him to see that Husserls researches into transcendental phenomenology . . . developed side by side with his interest in intersubjectivity and the embodied subject and that for Husserl, these were complementary modes of access to the one domain of transcendental

432

STEVEN CROWELL

subjectivity and intersubjectivity (pp. 67, 80). In Merleau-Pontys hands this becomes the quest for what Moran calls the living bond between consciousness and world, the unity that precedes their conceptual dissociation. But doesnt this very quest, insisting on the irreducibility of the real world, break with the above-noted complementarity of Husserls project? In fact, in confronting Merleau-Ponty Moran must give up his claim that phenomenology is anti-naturalistic: Merleau-Pontys outlook may be characterized as a kind of dialectical naturalism; it is naturalistic in that it sees human beings as integrated into the natural order (p. 403). But does it then remain phenomenological (especially if it is also dialectical)? Rather than untie this knot, Moran shifts terms: phenomenology does not object to naturalism per se but to reductive scientism (p. 433). This may be so, but then, when we are told that Merleau-Ponty signicantly expanded the scope of phenomenological method and removed it entirely from the domain of introspection by reinterpreting the Husserlian reduction as leading back to the pre-predicative and incarnate wellsprings of our experience back to the Lebenswelt (p. 419), we can only wonder how this phenomenology manages to fulll the desiderata that keep it a philosophical method. Merleau-Pontys late work might well seem, to some, to be far along the road to an artistic intuition or personal vision. How, then, does Morans picture of phenomenology fare against DAmicos charge that it does not constitute a research program? On the objection that Heidegger fatally opens the door to metaphysics with his claim about Daseins ontic-ontological distinctiveness, Moran helps us see that Heideggers transformation of phenomenology need not have this consequence. Heideggers ontology can be metaphysically neutral since the question of Being is not distinct from the phenomenological question of the appearing of things; its externalism does not exceed the phenomenological correlation of objectivity-for-subjectivity. With the charge that Heidegger opens the door to epistemological naturalism, however, Moran has more difculty. On the one hand, he holds that Heidegger remains anti-naturalistic, as does phenomenology after him. On the other hand, he allows that the program is transformed in anthropological and historicist directions going so far, with Merleau-Ponty, as to embrace a kind of naturalism for phenomenology. In the end it becomes questionable whether Moran is entitled to this view of phenomenologys essential anti-naturalism, given his critique of transcendental philosophy. Without a clearer account of how the naturalistic version of phenomenology can retain apriority it will be hard for Moran to argue, against DAmico, that phenomenology does not necessarily devolve into the sort of epistemological naturalism characteristic of post-structuralism.

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

433

Finally, it does seem that in spite of his caveats Moran wants to present phenomenology as a kind of research program. Levinas, Derrida et al., are held up to standards imposed by a normative conception of the phenomenological method. Some, but not all, of their concerns are deemed phenomenological; hence phenomenology must have a perhaps evolving set of common problems and not just founding texts. And there is apparently a distinctive and communicable sense of how to go on rather than merely personal visions. Nevertheless, Morans historical mode of introducing phenomenology particularly the crucial Heideggerian transformation systematically obscures the question of what, specically, remains essential to this research program. Because the question of the relation between transcendental and ontological phenomenology is treated narratively, we cannot really understand how, if at all, post-Husserlian phenomenology could be a research program a distinct and normative framework for philosophical inquiry though Moran implies that it is. To get a clearer answer to that question we turn to our second Introduction.
3. ROBERT SOKOLOWSKI S ARISTOTELIAN PHENOMENOLOGY

For Moran, the phenomenological movement is a thoroughly modernist outlook: Husserl attempted to overcome crude Cartesianism by a radical rethinking of the Cartesian project itself (pp. 3, 16). For Robert Sokolowski, in contrast, phenomenology is something that restores the possibilities of Ancient philosophy, even while accounting for new dimensions such as modern science (pp. 62, 202203). This difference in estimating the character of phenomenology as a mode of thinking accounts for the major difference in the way the two Introductions view the Husserl/Heidegger relation. Moran, like DAmico, identies Husserl with internalism and emphasizes Heideggers embrace of a kind of externalism namely, the idea that intentionality cannot be understood on the basis of what is immanent to consciousness but must take the world into account. If overcoming Cartesianism by more Cartesianism fails, then a radical transformation of phenomenology is required to get the job done: the lesson to be learned from Husserls reduction is, as Merleau-Ponty (1962, xiv) put it, the impossibility of a complete reduction. For Sokolowski, however, Husserls basic insight is that intentionality is already beyond any internalism: everything is outside. Phenomenology recognizes the reality and truth of phenomena being perceived is nothing mental, but a way in which things can be. The way things appear is part of the being of things. . . . Things do not just exist, they manifest themselves as what they are (pp. 12, 14). This conception of phenomena

434

STEVEN CROWELL

leads Sokolowski to suggest paradoxically, given the way this relation is usually understood, but nevertheless correctly, in my view that what most impressed Heidegger was the fact that in Husserl the Cartesian or modern epistemological problem had been dissolved and overcome (p. 216). For the same reason, the Heideggerian move to ontology does not appear as a radical transformation of the phenomenological project but as an elaboration of something implicit in Husserls breakthrough.11 If for Moran the move from transcendental phenomenology to ontology represents a decisive swerve in phenomenology, Sokolowski sees transcendental phenomenology as ontology. Thus Sokolowski incorporates Heideggerian ontology into the horizon of Husserls transcendental program. Does he thereby also succeed in avoiding DAmicos twin objections: that Heideggers ontological motif opens phenomenology both to dogmatic metaphysics and to epistemological naturalism? We shall approach this question by looking rst at what Sokolowski holds to be essential to the transcendental program. It shall appear that while Moran was able to deal adequately with the charge of metaphysical dogmatism but had difculty with the re-emergence of epistemological naturalism, Sokolowskis rm commitment to transcendentalism decisively blocks the latter but with its Aristotelian inspiration does not fare so well with the former. That Sokolowski holds phenomenology to be a consistent, viable research program is clear. The very structure of the book not a comment on Husserl, but an introduction on the model of Husserls own, showing how phenomenology can continue to make an important contribution to current philosophy, its intellectual capital . . . far from spent testies to that, as does his view that phenomenologys great strength as a movement is that it presents to us not only obvious major gures but also a wide range of minor writers, those who ll out the possibilities in the niches and corners of the phenomenological style of philosophy (pp. 2, 225). But does Sokolowski endorse the elements of this research program that we have seen to characterize it? It would appear so. For though the terms he uses are Husserlian in origin, the program they delineate is taken normatively and is not understood as tied to those terms themselves or to the philosophy of Husserl or any other single thinker.12 What, then, is it? First, phenomenology is dened as the study of human experience and of the way things present themselves to us in and through such experience (p. 2), acknowledging its focus on intentionality, or what Moran called objectivity-for-subjectivity. Second, phenomenological analysis is description of the manifold that is proper to a given kind of object, in contrast to causal explanation (p. 31, 115). Third, this description seeks

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

435

necessary truths, or essences, and proceeds by eidetic intuition (p. 183). Fourth, intuitive Evidenz or self-givenness is epistemically primary: Evidenz is the successful presentation of an intelligible object, . . . of something whose truth becomes manifest in the evidencing itself. . . . It is the moment when something enters into the space of reasons (p. 161). Fifth, phenomenology employs an epoche of all scientic and metaphysical theories, since in the phenomenological attitude we suspend all the intentionalities that we are examining. We neutralize them (p. 48). And nally, the phenomenological attitude is reective, since in it we make the appearances thematic and study the relation between a thing and its appearances (p. 50). Sokolowski identies this relation with what Heidegger called the ontological difference thereby signalling how Heideggers talk of Being will be given phenomenological sense, in contrast to earlier metaphysical senses. Given this outline of a research program, can Sokolowski convincingly address the objections that we have seen raised against phenomenology by DAmico and others? On the question of whether phenomenology is concerned with a set of common problems rather than simply being a matter of founding texts, the answer is clear. For Sokolowski phenomenology deals with the classical problems of philosophy. Its great aim is to reactivate the philosophical life in our present circumstances. It is able to reinvigorate Ancient insights and offer a distinctive approach to issues in philosophy of science, language, and mind because it deals so well with the problem of appearances. Sokolowski extensively examines three central contributions of phenomenological analysis: part/whole, identity-in-manifolds, and presence-and-absence. With the exception of the last, which Sokolowski argues is original in phenomenology, these have long pedigrees and wide philosophical implications. Finally, Sokolowski holds that phenomenologys greatest contribution is to the most traditional philosophical problem of all: the nature and scope of reason (pp. 25). On the question of whether there is a clear sense of how to go on Sokolowski provides a nuanced answer. If by method is understood anything like an algorithm for producing results or a test-procedure that could compel agreement, then phenomenology is not a method. The very idea of method is said to be a modern prejudice, arising not from the desire for truth but for the mastery of truth. In contrast, a philosophical research program like phenomenology must depend on the habituated mind more than on method (pp. 164165). Nevertheless, this habituation is not arbitrary, and its development presupposes another sense of method the

436

STEVEN CROWELL

skillful or expert exercise of a distinct way of going on as in Aristotles account of virtue. This is the basis of Sokolowskis response to the third question. Is phenomenological practice subject to constraints on what can be asserted, or is it essentially a matter of personal visions with no reasonable expectation that others should come to the same results? For Sokolowski, phenomenological analyses are beholden throughout to the constraint of Evidenz; phenomenology is nothing but the critical and receptive response to the way things show up for us. Though such a constraint appears to be unpredictable and unmasterable thus being a disappointment to rationalists like DAmico it is for Sokolowski that without which the subsequent concept of proof makes no sense. The rationalist claim that the only source of truth is proof that the presentation is not enough to establish truth (p. 164) contravenes the essence of reason in which the truth of propositions (the correctness that is to be preserved in valid arguments) derives from the self-manifestation, or disclosure, of things themselves.13 Seeing provides constraints on saying, and others can be brought, though not compelled, to see. Philosophy is a kind of research that can employ, but cannot wholly restrict itself to, argument. This is further supported by Sokolowskis account of how phenomenological analysis is governed by the constraint of essential insight or eidetic intuition. Essences are achieved by imaginatively varying examples until impossible variations are seen, thereby revealing necessary connections as a priori limits on the example (p. 184). This is not just a matter of conceptual analysis that is, of linguistic rules that govern our vocabulary but rather derives from our experience of objects (p. 173). Is such imaginative variation subject to criticism and correction, then, or does phenomenology reduce to a series of obiter dicta? Here Sokolowski points out that we correct mistakes in eidetic intuition by talking with others about them (p. 183). As with experiments in empirical science, phenomenological thought experiments must be reproducible. Hence the need for phenomenological publications. And just because my communication with others about these insights is not limited proffering proofs, but includes any way in which I can lead them to see what I have seen, this does not mean that no constraints are acknowledged. The familiar practice of offering counter-examples, crucial to conceptual analysis, feeds on the more original capacity for eidetic intuition; thus if we can get straight about what this practice involves, we should also be able to address the objection that there is no compelling connection between phenomenological method and the a priori truths it claims to grasp.

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

437

First, however, we must return to the question of whether Sokolowskis conception of the phenomenological research program in which Heideggers ontology is taken to be a consistent elaboration of Husserls impulse rather than its radical transformation can avoid dogmatic metaphysics and epistemological naturalism. Because Sokolowski does not see the contrast Moran found between Husserls transcendental ego and Heideggers factic and historical Dasein (insisting, rather, that the transcendentality of the human being is part of its phenomenological constitution), the door to epistemological naturalism remains pretty tightly shut. Though his view is controversial, I shall not stop to examine it here because the question of whether Sokolowski has kept dogmatic metaphysics at bay is rather more instructive. Let me try to get at the problem in terms of a distinction between reective and rst-order claims. The metaphysical postulates that the epoche is designed to neutralize are essentially rst-order claims about what things are; in this sense, they are equivalent to the sort of scientic claim upon which epistemological naturalism depends. Phenomenology, in contrast, is a reective enterprise in which, as Sokolowski states, we suspend all the intentionalities we are examining (p. 48). Its neutrality means, rst, that it refuses to use any rst-order claims as premises (presuppositions), and, second, that it does not subsequently leave the terrain of reection on how things show up (appearances, modes of givenness) to make any rst-order claims. Were it to do so it would immediately stand in competition with rst-order sciences. If, therefore, phenomenology is ontological, the concept of being at issue must gain its sense on the level of reection itself, be tied to the kind of evidence available there.14 Now Sokolowskis claim that phenomenological reection suspends all rstorder intentionalities acknowledges the rst part of the neutrality thesis: phenomenology makes no use of naturalistic or metaphysical postulates. But what about the second part of the neutrality thesis: can phenomenology move beyond reection to make rst-order metaphysical claims? Without pretending to do justice to the subtlety of Sokolowskis presentation here, it appears that he does want to move beyond phenomenological neutrality. On the one hand, Sokolowski works with what I would call a purely phenomenological (hence neutral) concept of being as when he claims that the way things appear is part of the being of things (p. 14). Manifestation belongs to being; what it means to be X is constituted in and through the evidence in which it gives itself. To do ontology in this sense it is not necessary to abandon the level of reection, and no rst-order claims are made. On the other hand, Sokolowski does seem to make such claims, as though phenomenological neutrality were merely

438

STEVEN CROWELL

the rst step in a broader onto-theological agenda. For instance, from the phenomenological truth about us that we are datives of manifestation Sokolowski feels entitled to say, apparently thanks to a perfectionist assumption, that we exercise our humanity most fully . . . when we use words, and that this is what our minds are supposed to do (pp. 89, 93, 181). It is hard to know what phenomenological evidence could support this perfectionist premise, but even if one could make the case by construing essences not just as eidetic necessities but as normative excellences (that is, as Platonic Ideas), Sokolowski makes other claims that seem to transcend phenomenological evidence altogether. For instance, he asserts that the transcendental ego, the dative of manifestation, is already there in the fetus, and that this early self is already something of a player in the game of truth (p. 121). Arguments based on phenomenological evidence can perhaps be made for these claims, but they appear to me to go beyond the resources of the phenomenological research program itself. If Sokolowskis Aristotelian grasp of the phenomenological project leads him to advocate a form of rst-order metaphysics,15 this nevertheless does not seem to be a necessary consequence of the phenomenological stance itself. Sokolowski is eloquent about the imperialism of modern philosophys attempt to try to correct everything radically throw over the truths of common sense from its own methodological resources (p. 191). But it may well be that the price one pays for the neutrality that corrects this modern prejudice includes renouncing metaphysics in the Aristotelian mode a rst-order discourse about the ultimate principles of things. With this, however, I have moved beyond an inquiry into whether a phenomenological research program is possible and have begun to argue about what this possibility, once established, entails. Further movement in this direction must be resisted. Instead let us conclude by posing a nal question to our Introductions, one that returns us to Dummett: given the possibility of a phenomenological research program, what is it good for? Can its method be seen to generate philosophical insights that can be had in no other way?
4. PHENOMENOLOGY, MEANING , AND CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS

Both phenomenology and analytic philosophy are distinguished from traditional philosophy by a focus on meaning. Dummett, we recall, locates the split between the two approaches at that point where Frege limits the concept of meaning to linguistic meaning, while Husserl generalizes it to all intentionality, whether linguistic or not. The result is the concept of the noema, the intentional object that is the topic of phenomen-

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

439

ological reection. Subsequent controversy over the phenomenological approach to meaning (and connected issues in philosophy of mind, language, and knowledge) has often turned on the interpretation of what Husserl understood the noema to be. A widespread view the one adopted by Dummett was initially proposed by Dagnn Fllesdal (1966). On this account the noema is an abstract entity that mediates reference to the object intended in any given act in much the way that Freges Sinn determines linguistic reference. This view has some basis in Husserls text, but as Moran does a good job of showing, there is basis for several other interpretations (pp. 158160). If the purposes of his Introduction do not permit Moran to take sides in this debate, this is not at all the case for Sokolowski. For him, to treat the noema as a Fregean Sinn, an entity distinct from the thing itself, is to miss the point of the phenomenological approach to intentionality altogether. On Sokolowskis view, the noema is any object of intentionality, any objective correlate, but considered from the phenomenological attitude; it is not a sense that refers us to the object, but the object itself (pp. 6061, 194). The noema is just the object considered as it gives itself in its specic modes of givenness; to speak categorically, it is the object considered as a structure of part/whole, identity-in-manifolds, and presence-and-absence. The question, then, is what this view of the noema contributes to the phenomenological account of meaning. Sokolowski argues that there are two kinds of reection propositional reection, which grasps meanings, and noematic reection, which grasps noemata and that the latter reaches deeper than the former: to stop with a clarication of meaning is not yet to get to truth (p. 196). These claims are supported by an eidetic phenomenological analysis of how, pace Dummett, language depends on thinking: the reason we can use language is that we are capable of the kind of intending that constitutes categorical objects (p. 91), a kind of intending that grasps the articulations of perception. Language arises when I take a specic sort of stance to what is thus constituted being pulled up short, I take a distance from the categorially formed object and transform it, via the emergent attitude of propositional reection, into a state-of-affairs, something merely deemed (judged) to be X. I have transformed it into a meaning: the meaning, the sense, arises in response to this new attitude and it was not there beforehand doing its epistemological work of relating us to the world (p. 100). Analytic philosophy stops at a reection on this meaning but cannot get at the level of categoriality that underlies it, a level that is available only to phenomenology, that is, to noematic reection made possible by the phenomenological reduction (p. 92).

440

STEVEN CROWELL

On Sokolowskis reading of the noema, then, phenomenology embraces the world directly and can provide what analytic philosophy cannot, namely, an account of language itself within the broader horizon of nonlinguistic modes of experience. It should be noted, however, that from the standpoint of a theory of meaning, Sokolowski purchases phenomenologys advantage over analytic philosophy at the price of agreeing with Dummetts anti-Husserlian thesis that all meaning is linguistic meaning: The phenomenological reduction turns objects into noemas. Propositional reection, in contrast, turns objects into senses (p. 192). This may well be too high a price to pay. Philologically, it overlooks the fact (one that Moran appropriately highlights) that for Husserl the concept of meaning serves essentially at both levels: central to the noema is what Husserl calls noematischer Sinn noematic meaning and this sort of meaning is not at all a function of propositional reection. More substantively, to elide this duality of meaning by contrasting noema and meaning as absolutely as Sokolowski does is to lose the phenomenological resource that allows us to understand what happens when, as Sokolowski says, in categorial intentions the things we perceive become elevated into the space of reasons (p. 94). It is not merely that the categorically intended object is there for us in its structure of part/whole, identity-in-manifold, and presence-absence, but that these structures constitute the thing as something, as meaningful though not yet propositional. While it is correct to say that the noema is not an abstract entity, it is nevertheless the structure of noematic meaning that constitutes the reective topic of the phenomenological research program, not the unadorned thing-itself of Aristotelian realism, as Sokolowsis bifurcation of the two reections seems to entail. To show why this sort of critical stance neither rules out an ontological idiom in phenomenology nor returns us to some form of psychological or Cartesian/Kantian idealism is itself one of the crucial problems that belong within the scope of the phenomenological research program. But, nally, can phenomenologys reversal of Dummetts thesis about the relation between thought and language based on the claim that there is a necessary and asymmetrical relation of dependency between the two really be said to follow from the phenomenological method, that is, from eidetic intuition or seeing of essences, rather than (as DAmico charged) merely being a case of ordinary, pedestrian conceptual analysis? At this point the phenomenologist is entitled to ask: but what is ordinary, pedestrian conceptual analysis? DAmico himself is rather vague here, claiming that to grasp conceptual necessities say, the incoherence of the claim that there can be a presentation of color that is not extended is simply to grasp the reasoning involved (p. 250), and not any sort of intuition of

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

441

essences. But what sort of reasoning is that? It does not seem to be a matter of reasoning about linguistic rules. As Sokolowski puts it, philosophy deals with coherence the rules of what concepts can be blended with others but coherence is not merely a matter of linguistic rules that govern our vocabulary but a matter of our experience of objects (p. 173). Conceptual analysis may indeed consult what we tend to say about what it means to be a friend or how we use terms like belief or desire. But it will typically also proceed by appeal to counter-examples in which some situation in the world, and not just linguistic usage, is invoked. When one encounters incoherence in this way, thereby establishing a necessary condition for some concept, can this be understood without acknowledging the role that a kind of direct insight, based not on ratiocination but on imaginative variation, plays here? Though this activity would not be a matter of explicit proof, it would nevertheless seem to be essential for creative work in philosophy, whether analytic or phenomenological. And one may call it conceptual analysis if one wishes, but then conceptual analysis contains an ineradicable moment of eidetic intuition. It appears that only ignorance informs the view that phenomenologys results are nothing but conceptual analysis. One might more justly say that there is conceptual analysis only because there is phenomenology, even though its practitioners dont recognize themselves as phenomenologists. Of course, Dummett has a far more specic suggestion for what is required here. The very obscurity of the notion of concept (Fregean thought) calls forth the twin axioms of analytic philosophy: If it is his theory of meaning which determines what a philosopher counts as an elucidation or analysis of a concept (Dummett 1960, 435), analytic philosophy stakes its claim on the view that a theory of meaning is at bottom a theory of linguistic meaning. To this the phenomenologist might reasonably respond with a question: Is it really so obvious that a theory of even linguistic meaning can be developed in abstraction from the wider terrain of phenomenological reection? J. E. Malpas (1992), for instance, has shown how Donald Davidsons theory of meaning requires augmentation by phenomenological analyses, and Dummetts optimistic claim that we have now reached a position where the search for such a theory of meaning can take on a genuinely scientic character (Dummett 1975, 454) appears, thirty years later, at best premature. The point is not that analytic philosophy is a bankrupt research project after all, time will tell (Dummett 1975, 458) but the claims that phenomenological results are really disguised language-analysis, or that the theory of meaning that best supports actual creative work in philosophy is a theory of linguistic meaning, have by no means been established. Phenomenology

442

STEVEN CROWELL

would seem to be a coherent research program, and whether it continues to prove productive will depend, above all, on the talent of those who take it up.

NOTES
1 See especially Dummett (1993, 137143) for the critical discussion of Evans. 2 A partial list would include Kearney (1994), Kearney and Rainwater (1996), West

(1996), May (1997), Critchley and Schroeder (1998), McNeill and Feldman (1998), Glendinning (1999), Brogan and Risser (2000), and Critchley (2001). 3 See especially Ihde (1986, 126) and Embree (ms). Critchley and Schroeder (1998, 4) gets the history of the term right: it is not used as a professional self-description before the 1970s, and it happened in the USA before Britain. In the postwar period, Continental philosophy was broadly synonymous with phenomenology in American universities. As an undergraduate at the University of California at Santa Cruz 197074, I recall that Maurice Natanson would teach Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre and others under the rubric Recent European Philosophy. The term Continental philosophy was not yet in general use. Embree (ms, 2) claims that I personally originated the current use of Continental in 1978 when I became the rst editor of the book series that the Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology, Inc., sponsors at Ohio University Press dubbing it Series in Continental Thought. 4 See also Critchley (2001), where this view is thoughtfully elaborated in terms of the two cultures and the idea that philosophy strives not for knowledge but for wisdom. 5 See Janicauds ground-breaking essay, The Theological Turn in French Phenomenology, and other texts collected in Prusak (2000). 6 Embree et al. (1997) provides ample evidence for its claim that given its spread into other disciplines as well as across the planet, phenomenology is arguably the major philosophical movement of the 20th Century. 7 See below, Section 4. 8 However, DAmicos almost unbelievably ill-informed interpretation of what these claims and analyses are is evidence enough that this part of his thesis is unsupportable. See his discussion of Heideggers distinction between Bendlichkeit and Verstehen (pp. 7072), for a particularly glaring example. 9 It also corresponds well to what Embree et al. (1997, 12) identies as accepted by most phenomenologists, regardless of discipline, tendency, or period namely, justication of cognition with reference to evidence; the belief that not only objects in the natural and cultural world but also ideal objects . . . can be made evident; focusing inquiry on the correlational structure of intentionality (here called encountering) in a reective approach; the priority of description in universal, a priori, or eidetic terms over explanation by means of causes, purposes, or grounds; and debate over the possibility or usefulness of the transcendental phenomenological epoche and reduction. 10 Indeed, it might be argued that this is not far at all from Husserls own view of the matter. As for Heidegger, he understood that to speak of pre-suppositions was strictly speaking to speak of theoretical postulates, and he interpreted Husserls epoche this way. See Heidegger (1987, 9395), and the discussion in Crowell (2001, 13336).

IS THERE A PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH PROGRAM?

443

11 Though Sokolowski does not go into details in such matters, he suggests that Heideg-

gers ontological elaboration may have been enabled by his deep interest in Aristotle and his ability, superior to Husserls own, to see Husserls achievement in the broader context of the history of philosophy. Husserls breakthrough was something radically new and cannot be seen as continuing a tradition that had taken shape before him (p. 211), but some of its philosophical implications could better be appreciated by Heidegger, who was a far more sophisticated reader of the history of philosophy (pp. 217218). 12 Sokolowski does not comment on these terms as though they were alien to [his] own. [He] uses them (p. 2). Nevertheless, he judges that phenomenologys established terminology is a handicap for the phenomenological movement. Its terms tend to become fossilized and provoke articial problems. They substantialize what should be an aspect of being and of the activity of philosophy. The very name phenomenology is misleading and clumsy (p. 226). 13 Borrowing a theme that is more distinct in Heidegger than in Husserl, Sokolowski argues that there are two kinds of truth, the truth of correctness and the truth of disclosure. The former begins with a statement being made or a proposition being held, which we then go on to verify. The latter is simply the display of a state of affairs, that is, the simple presencing to us of an intelligible object, something as something. Given the phenomenological relations between signitive intentions and intuitive fulllments, therefore, the truth of correctness depends on the truth of disclosure (pp. 158159). 14 I would argue that this is a purely formal requirement deriving from the claim of neutrality itself. How this is related to traditional versions of realism and idealism is an important question that lies beyond the scope of this essay. Some discussion can be found in Crowell (2001), but the issues are far from settled. 15 Moran noted this sort of move in Sartre, but one can cite texts from Heidegger, Eugen Fink, Merleau-Ponty, Michel Henry, and others, in which the limits of the phenomenological research program are sprung in the direction of uncritical metaphysics.

REFERENCES

Brogan, W. and J. Risser (eds): 2000, American Continental Philosophy, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN. Critchley, S.: 2001, Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Critchley, S. and W. Schroeder (eds): 1998, A Companion to Continental Philosophy, Blackwell, Oxford. Crowell, S.: 2001, Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning: Paths Toward Transcendental Phenomenology, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL. DAmico, R.: 1999, Contemporary Continental Philosophy, Westview Press, Boulder, CO. Dummett, M.: 1975, Can Analytical Philosophy be Systematic, and Ought it to Be?, in Truth and Other Enigmas, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1978. Dummett, M.: 1993, Origins of Analytical Philosophy, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Dummett, M.: 1960, Oxford Philosophy, in Truth and Other Enigmas, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1978. Embree, L.: ms., Husserl as Trunk of the American Continental Tree. Embree, L. et al. (eds): 1997, Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

444

STEVEN CROWELL

Fllesdal, D.: 1966, Husserls Notion of Noema, Journal of Philosophy 66, 680687. Glendinning, S. (ed.): 1999, The Edinburgh Encyclopedia of Continental Philosophy, University Press, Edinburgh. Heidegger, M.: 1987, Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie, Gesamtausgabe Bd. 56/57, ed. Bernd Heimbchel, Klostermann, Frankfurt. Ihde, D.: 1986, Consequences of Phenomenology, State University of New York Press, Albany, NY. Kearney, R. (ed.): 1994, Routledge History of Philosophy Volume VIII: Twentieth-Century Continental Philosophy, Routledge, London. Kearney, R. and M. Rainwater (eds): 1996, The Continental Philosophy Reader, Routledge, London. Malpas, J. E.: 1992, Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning, University Press, Cambridge. May, T. (ed.): 1997, Twentieth-Century Continental Philosophy, Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River, NJ. McNeill, W. and K. Feldman (eds): 1998, Continental Philosophy: An Anthology, Blackwell, Oxford. Merleau-Ponty, M.: 1962, Phenomenology of Perception, tr. Colin Smith, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. Moran, D.: 2000, Introduction to Phenomenology, Routledge, London. Prusak, B. (tr.): 2000, Phenomenology and the Theological Turn: The French Debate, Fordham University Press, New York. Sokolowski, R.: 2000, Introduction to Phenomenology, University Press, Cambridge. West, D.: 1996, An Introduction to Continental Philosophy, Polity Press, Cambridge. Department of Philosophy Rice University MS14 P.O. Box 1892 Houston TX 77251-1892 U.S.A. E-mail: crowell@rice.edu

Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen