Sie sind auf Seite 1von 13

PHILOSOPHY'S ROLE VIS-A-VIS BUSINESS ETHICS

Note from the Editor. Richard Rorty's invited address to the 2005 annual meeting of the Society for Business Ethics prompted extensive comments from and discussion by those attending the meeting. In light of this, Professor Rorty's address is reprinted here, and is followed by invited responses from three past presidents of the Society for Business Ethics, and a brief concluding comment from Richard Rorty.

IS PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS? Invited Address to the Society of Business Ethics Annual Meeting, August 2005

Richard Rorty

Abstract: If, like Hegel and Dewey, one takes a historicist, anti-Platonist view of moral progress, one will be dubious about the idea that moral theory can be more than the systematization of the widely-shared moral intuitions of a certain time and place. One will follow Shelley, Dewey, and Patricia Werhane in emphasizing the role of the imagination in making moral progress possible. Taking this stance will lead one to conclude that although philosophy is indeed relevant to applied ethics, it is not more relevant than many other fields of study (such as history, law, political science, anthropology, literature, and theology). hilosophy has a glorious past and an uncertain future. That is why, when thinking about our role in intellectual life, we philosophy professors prefer to look backward. Doing so lets us see ourselves as the successors of Plato, St. Augustine, Spinoza, Kant, Marx, and Nietzsche. Those men imagined new shapes that the lives of individuals and communities might assume. Thinking of ourselves as their heirs helps us imagine that we might shape the human future. When we turn from the past to the present, however, we remember that we are not being paid to foment intellectual or social revolutions. We have been hired by colleges and universities to be responsible professionals, content to work within a well-defined area of expertise. As philosophy became one more academic discipline, it became harder for philosophers to do something bold and original. For the more 2006. Business Ethics Quarterly, Volume 16, Issue 3. ISSN 1052-150X. pp. 369-380

370

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

original and imaginative a philosopher is, the less she looks like a skilled, welltrained, disciplined professional. You cannot professionalize imaginativeness. The professionalization of philosophy began about two hundred years ago, in a period when the modem research university was beginning to take shape. That period, the time of Hegel and Humboldt, was also philosophy's acme. Since then, philosophy has gradually lost prestige. It has become invisible to the general public, and has drifted off the radar screens of most intellectuals. The principal reason for this marginalization is that the so-called "warfare between science and theology" has tapered off. By and large, science has triumphed. Despite occasional flare-ups, such as the current assault on evolutionary biology, most Westerners who read books are content to let their view of the universe be shaped by the natural sciences. Religious faith has been revised, by most educated believers, so as not to conflict with the stories scientists tell. As long as the warfare between science and theology lasted, there was an important role for philosophical theories to play. For thinkers like Hobbes, Spinoza, Hume, Kant, Hegel, Mill, and Marx all confronted an urgent question: how can the moral idealism common to Platonism, Judaism, and Chistianity survive affer we have accepted a materialist account of the way the universe works? What is the place of moral ideals in a clockwork universe? As long as those questions dominated intellectual life, philosophical theories about the nature of reality and about the scope of the limits of human knowledge were still relevant to felt needs. The question of whether human beings were more than just clever animals remained urgent. In recent times, however, the question "what is it to be a human being?""what makes human beings special?"has lost its urgency. That question has been replaced by two others. The first is political: "How can we create a better world for our descendants to inhabit?" The second is existential: "What sort of person shall I try to become?" This change resulted from an increased awareness of the possibihty of radical historical change, and from an increased tolerance for human diversity. In the course of the past two centuries, historians, novelists, and anthropologists have helped us reahze that the human future need not resemble the human past. The philosophers ofthe seventeenth and eighteenth centuries shared with Plato and Epicurus the assumption that the human situation was essentially the same at all times and places. But we modems have come to think that there is no single Good Life for Man. We no longer take for granted that all the members of our species share an unchanging essence, and that knowledge of this essence can help us decide what to do with ourselves. Plato invented philosophy by postulating the existence of unchanging essences. So the changes in the intellectual life of the West have, in the course of the last two centuries, produced a spate of radically anti-Platonic philosophies. The historicism that Marx took over from Hegel was thefirstradical break with Platonic essentialism. Marx's thesis that philosophers should stop trying to understand the world and start trying to change it epitomized the intellectuals' new-found willingness to tum away from metaphysics in favor of politics.

Is PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS?

371

Nietzsche's existentiaHsm was the counterpart of Marxism at the level of the private individual. "If you have a virtue," Nietzsche said, "let it be your virtue." His point was that virtue not should be thought of as a matter of conforming to antecedent norms but rather of being faithful to one's own project of self-creation. In the hundred-odd years since Nietzsche wrote, anti-Platonist movements with names like "pragmatism," "existentialism," and "postmodernism" have prohferated. The burden of all of them was pretty much the same: there are no unchanging essences to be grasped, only new ways of describing both ourselves and the universe to be invented. Anti-Platonists are often accused of relativism. Doubting the existence of something transcultural and ahistorical that can provide guidance for moral choice, these accusers say, amounts to denying the existence of absolute values. But we know that slavery and torture are absolutely, objectively, wrong. So, they argue, there must be something that makes them soif not the Will of God, than the Moral Law, or Reason, or some other secular surrogate for the divine. Anti-Platonists like myself, the people sometimes described as "post-modem relativists," do not accept the correspondence theory of truth. So we have no use for the notion of a belief being made true by the world. We think that adding "absolute" to "wrong" or "objective" to "truth" is an empty rhetorical gesture. It is just a way of pounding on the podium. Saying that torture is absolutely wrong does nothing to still doubts about whether to save the city by torturing the terrorist. Everybody agrees that it is absolutely wrong to refuse sick children medical help, but nobody agrees on how the doctor's bill is to be paid. When decisions get tough, invoking notions like "absoluteness" and "objectivity" does nothing to make them easier. Philosophers' claims to have Truth and Reason on their side resemble theologians' claims to know the will of God. Such claims are advertising slogans rather than arguments. God has provided no algorithms for resolving tough moral dilemmas, and neither have the great secular philosophers. Urging that there is something that makes actions wrong or moral behefs true is an empty gesture. For we have no way of getting in touch with this purported truth-maker save to seek coherence among our own moral intuitions. Though truth and wrongness are not relative notions, justification is. For what counts as justification, either of actions or of beliefs, is always relative to the antecedent behefs of those whom one is seeking to convince. Anti-slavery arguments that we find completely persuasive would probably not have convinced Jefferson or Aristotle. Our best arguments against torture would probably not have budged the devout and learned prelates who ran the Holy Inquisition. That is why we are somedmes tempted to say, misleadingly, that a certain practice is right in one culture and wrong in another, or that a certain astrophysical theory was true for Aristotle but false for Newton. The reason this turn of phrase is misleading is that all we really mean is that, given his other behefs, Aristotle was perfectly justified in accepting a false theory. Analogously, the Mongol horde was perfectly justified in gang-raping the women of Baghdad, given their other behefs. Their behavior was, to be sure, wrong. If there were such a thing as absolute justification, we could say that it was absolutely

372

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

unjustified. But there is no such thing. Justification is a relation between beliefs and other beliefs. What can be justified to one audience cannot be justified to others. We are no closer to absolute justification for our moral beliefs than was Genghis Khan. We justify our actions and beliefs to each other by appealing to our own lightsto the intuitions fostered at our own time and place. The Mongols did the same. Philosophy, however, got its start when Plato insisted that there was such a thing as absolute justificationthat "the light of reason" was equally accessible to all reflective human beings. Whereas empirical inquiry into how things work depends on contingent availability of relevant evidence, Plato thought that we akeady had within us all the data needed for moral deliberation. The Platonic idea that we can learn how to be morally infallible by seeking coherence among our beliefs survives in the Kantian idea that a Nazi or a mafioso could, if he reflected long enough, break out of the culture in which he had been raised by detecting his own irrationality. A similar view is presupposed by philosophers who claim that training in philosophy permits you to become clearer about your moral concepts. Eor these philosophers, as for Plato and Kant, you can escape from the limitations of your background by exercising your innate rational powers. One great divide in contemporary philosophy is between people who still believe something like this, and those who, like me, believe nothing of the sort. For us, there is no particular connection between right action and clear thinking. There were clear-thinking Nazis and muddled saints. There is no connection between skill at justifying one's beliefsrhetorical effectivenessand having the right beliefs. Being able to have the right beliefs and to do the right thing is largely a matter of luckof being bom in a certain place and a certain time. For purposes of having true beliefs about the movements of heavenly bodies, Aristotle was bom at a bad time and place and Newton at a better one. Eor purposes of knowing whether either torture or sodomy is a moral abomination, all of us were bom into a better culture than were those who worked for the Inquisition. For those of us who hold this view, the obvious problem is how to think of moral progress. If there is nothing of the sort that Plato postulatedan underlying sense of right and wrong that is common to all human beings at all times and placescan we still say that we have made moral progress since the days of the Inquisition? If we do not have a faculty called "reason" that can be relied upon to help us make the right moral decisions, how can we make sense of the claim to make better decisions now than when we were callow adolescents? The best answer to these questions, I think, is that individuals become aware of more altematives, and therefore wiser, as they grow older. The human race as a whole has become wiser as history has moved along. The source of these new altematives is the human imagination. It is the ability to come up with new ideas, rather than the ability to get in touch with unchanging essences, that is the engine of moral progress. John Dewey quoted with approval Shelley's dictum that morality only "arranges the elements that poetry has created."'

Is PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS?

373

Moral progress is not, on this pragmatist view, a matter of getting clearer about sometbing that was there all the time. Rather, we make ourselves into new kinds of people by inventing new forms of human life. We make progress by having more altematives to consider. We are as trapped in our time and place as Genghis Kban was in bis, but we know mucb more about the possibilities open to buman beings than he did. Our descendants will, if civilization endures, be familiar with many more sucb possibilities. They will thereby bave become wiser, and morally better, tban we ourselves. ******************** Anyone wbo holds the view of moral progress I bave been offering will be dubious about the relevance of training in tbe academic discipline of philosophy to applied ethics. People witb views like mine are inclined to see training in philosophy as no better or worse a preparation for work in business etbics, or in bio-medical ethics, tban training in antbropology, or social psycbology, or theology, or intellectual history, or comparative literature. For advanced study in any of these fields helps the student to envisage new possibilities. In thinking about the relevance of philosophy to applied ethics, it helps to remember what people wbo take a PhD in philosophy actually leam. Typically, they bave to take courses and pass examinations in four tields. The first of these is usually labeled "metapbysics and epistemology." Tbis term is interpreted so as to cover pbilosopby of language and pbilosopby of mindtwo specialties frequently described as "the core areas of philosophy." The other threefields,typically treated as peripheral, are logic, the history of philosophy, and etbics. We philosophers share symbolic logic with the mathematicians, the history of philosophy with the intellectual historians, and ethics witb practically every other discipline in humanities and tbe social sciences. The logicians talk mostly with each other, and rarely with specialists in any of the other philosophical sub-fields. The best bistorians of philosophy are tbe ones who spend most of their time reading books by non-philosophersbooks that fill them in on tbe political, social, and cultural background of the great dead philosophers about whom they write. When it comes to ethics, about balf of those wbo specialize in tbisfieldspend at least half tbeir time reading books written by political scientists, law professors, and bistorians. Tbe other balf tend to specialize in metoethicsthe study of metaphysical and epistemological questions relevant to judgments of value, rather tban of tbose judgments themselves. Metaphysics and epistemology are no more relevant to applied ethics tban is astrophysics or neurophysiology. The same goes for metaetbics. Work in tbat subarea of philosophy revolves around tbe question "What is the place of value in a world of physical particles?" It is dominated by debates between tbose wbo tbink that true moral judgments are made tme by something real and those who do not.

374

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

But that dispute is as irrelevant to any practical issue as the dispute between those who claim that free will is an illusion and those who claim that it is real. Philosophy professors who take an interest in metaethics typically describe themselves as "naturalists." One of them, Philip Pettit, describes his fellow naturalists as holding that "A naturalistic, more or less mechanical image of the universe is imposed on us by cumulative development in physics, biology and neuroscience, and this challenges us to look for where in that world there can be room for phenomena . . . [such as] consciousness, freedom, responsibility, goodness, virtue and the like." The difficulty of this question, Pettit continues, makes "philosophy today probably more challenging, and more difficult, than it has ever been."^ Naturalists like Pettit see the contemporary Anglophone philosophical community as split between naturalists and quietists. People like me think that we should try to move out from under Plato's shadow, and stop worrying about the nature of reality or the possibility of knowing the true nature of the real. Brian Leiter accurately describes the position of Wittgensteinian quietists like myself when he writes that, on their view, "Philosophy has no distinctive methods and philosophy can solve no problems; philosophy becomes a kind of therapy, dissolving philosophical problems rather than solving them. One way it dissolves them is through the history of philosophy, which shows us how we came to think there were such things as philosophical problems and philosophical methods in the first place."' That is a good description of my own metaphilosophical outlook. We quietists think that the main task of philosophy these days should be to complete the process of secularizing cultureto convince people to stop looking for God-surrogates. We hope that they will stop identifying moral duty with obedience either to divine commands or to what Platonists and Kantians think of as "the commands of reason." For us quietists, the right question is not "what is real?" or "what is rational?" but "what is it useful to talk about?" If talking about gravitational attraction helps us predict the movements of heavenly bodies, then there is no point in asking whether gravity is a real entity or a heuristic fiction. If the Helsinki Declaration of Human Rights seems likely to form the basis for a global consensus about the limits of governmental power over individuals, there is no point in asking whether human beings really do have the enumerated rights or whether rights-talk is, as Bentham said it was, "nonsense on stilts." So when the naturalists profess puzzlement about how justice andfi-eedomfitinto a world made up entirely of electrons and protons, we quietists protest that ethical deliberation serves one purpose and talk about physical particles a quite different purpose. There is no reason why vocabularies developed for these two different purposes should mesh, and no need for them to be linked up. On the quietist view, we need neither a theory about the ultimate nature of reality nor one about the scope and limits of human knowledge. So we need neither epistemology in general or metaethics in particular. So if quietism replaced naturalism as the dominant mode of philosophical thought, the areas of philosophy presently thought of as "core" gradually would wither away.

Is PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS?

375

What would training in philosophy look like after a quietist victory? It is easy to imagine elementary logic being handed over to the rhetoric and communication department, and advanced logic to the mathematicians. Then all that would remain of the traditional four fields of philosophy would be the history of philosophy and moral philosophy. But these are the areas that are already least professionalized, and most thoroughly intertwined with other disciplines. The history of philosophy is of little value when studied in isolation from social, political, and economic history. Moral philosophy that does not bear on questions about whether and how to change our political and social institutions is equally pointless. So, if we quietists eventually win out over the naturalists, there will be little room for the idea of specifically philosophical expertise. The only distinctive characteristic of our profession will be that we philosophy professors will still have a thorough acquaintance with a particular set of great dead thinkers. Our knowledge of Plato, Aquinas, Kant, and Mill will be deeper and wider. Those of us who agree with Shelley that the great instrument of the moral good is the imagination treat the great dead moral philosophers not as people who put forward theories that can be tested against the data provided by contemporary moral intuitions, but as people who helped create such intuitions. They did so by dreaming up new ways of living an individual human life, and new social Utopias in which human beings might better flourish. Adopting this attitude toward the mighty dead would mean reading Kant as having offered a way of coming to terms with Newton and with the French Revolution while preserving all that was worth saving in Christianity. It would mean reading Mill as having helped us realize that morality should stop trying to regulate sexual behavior and concentrate on the need for individual diversity. It lets us see Mill's arguments against the subordination of women as a much more important contribution to Westem philosophy than the refinements he made in Bentham's original formulation of utilitarian ethics. We can stop treating Kant and Mill as mighty opposites, propounding incompatible moral theories, and view them as social engineers who tackled different jobs at different sites.

Let me now try to relate the point of view I have been sketching to trends of thought within business ethics. The emphasis I have been placing on the role of imagination follows a line of thought familiar from the work of Patricia Werhane. But I am inclined to adopt a more radical stance than hers. Werhane says that she realized that "ignorance of moral theory and lack of moral reasoning skills" were not enough to explain "why ordinary, decent, intelligent managers engage in questionable activities and why these activities are encouraged or even instigated by the climate or culture of companies they manage." This realization, she says, led her to realize that "something else was involved: a paucity of what I have come to label 'moral imagination.'"" Her book argues that "moral imagination is a necessary but not sufficient condition for creative managerial decision-making."^ I suspect that

376

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

it may, in fact, be sufficient as well. I think of moral imagination not as a supplement to moral theory and moral reasoning skills, but as pretty much all you need. Although an acquaintance with moral theory may sometimes come in handy, you can usually get along quite well without it. The principles formulated by thinkers like Kant, Mill, and Rawls provide handy little summaries of various subsets of our moral intuitions.* Invoking such principles speeds deliberation, but it does little to help with the tough casesthe ones where intuitions conflict. When it comes to "moral reasoning skills," I am less certain than Werhane that there are such things. The only skill I can think of that might fill the bill is the ability to proliferate distinctions as needed. Such proliferation permits us to reinterpret principles and rules so as to make them say what we want. Law schools and philosophy departments both provide excellent training in distinction-drawing. But developing greater skill in this area is as likely to lead us to do bad things as it is to do good things. There is no teachable skill that will help you sort out your moral intuitions so as to come to the right conclusion. Neither law school nor philosophy school can be relied upon to improve a student's moral character. Werhane defines "moral imagination" as "the ability in particular circumstances to discover and evaluate possibilities not merely determined by that circumstance, or limited by its operative mental models, or merely framed by a set of rules or rule-governed concerns."' I would argue that an increase in this ability is what has made us better people than Genghis Khan, or Aristotle, or Kant. We do not have better moral theories than these people did, nor are we more skillful at moral reasoning, but we are able to envisage possibihties for human hfe that never crossed their minds. None of the three, for example, ever thought very hard about what it would be like to have been bom a woman. Had Genghis Khan done so, the Mongol occupation of Baghdad might have included just as much plunder, but perhaps not quite so much rape. Had Kant been able to take Mary Wollstonecraft's book seriously, women might not have had to wait quite so long to get the vote. I have argued in the past'* that an increase in benevolence^in willingness to take the needs of others into accountis possible only when people have enough security and leisure to imagine what it must be like to be someone quite different from themselves, or in a very different situation than their own. Such exercises in imaginative sympathy have been essential to moral progress. Consider what happened when men began to thitik about what it must be like to be a woman, masters to put themselves in the shoes of slaves, owners in the shoes of workers, and straights in the shoes of gays. Except for the odd sociopath, we all feel mildly benevolent toward some peoplethe people most like ourselves. We have no trouble treating such people decently, except when doing so would entail too great a sacrifice on our own part. But moral progress occurs when benevolence is stretched to cover people whom those exercising power had never really thought of as members of the moral community. That stretching is the work of what Werhane calls "the moral imagination." Whenever we widen the circle of people who we think of as "much like ourselves," we find ourselves imagining changes in institutions and practices that

Is PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS?

377

would serve the hitherto neglected needs of these newly enrolled members of our moral community. When theyfinishedreading Uncle Tom's Cabin, some plantation owners began asking whether the economy of the South might nor survive the end of chattel slavery, and to envisage altemative modes of production. After reading Dickens and Zola, some factory owners began to rethink their ideas about the relations of labor and management. When they read Harriet Taylor, some influential British males began wondering what it might be like to sit in Parliament next to a woman, or to accept punishments meted out by a female judge. Then they began musing on what might need to be done to make such novelties feasible. Whento use Werhane's leading examplecorporate executives leamed about what Aaron Feuerstein did at Maiden Mills, they began to revise their notions about how such crises might be dealt with. Werhane's way of thinking chimes with Ronald Duska's claim that "Stories and hagiography will be the business ethics of the new millennium."' I take Duska to be suggesting that the principal products of the business ethics community should be, on the one hand, inspiring stories about business heroes, suitably complemented by horror stories about business villains. That view seems a plausible corollary of Werhane's claims for the role of the imagination. Instead of discussing definitions of the virtues or candidates for the role of a universally valid principle, business ethicists might do better to think of themselves as social engineers working on site-specific projects. The two most useful tools for such work, I suspect, are narratives, whether historical orfictional,and what Laura Nash calls "context-specific guidelines such as the Sullivan principles.'"" The importance of drawing up such guidelines is, I should imagine, uncontroversial. But what Nash calls "the importance of narrative as a moral medium" may be less widely acknowledged. Yet I am sure she is right when she says that "The field of business ethics needs to explore and develop modes of story. . . . How else to understand the existence of Mexican slave labor in the middle of Brooklyn?"" How else, one might continue, come to understand differences in the relation between govemment and business in Germany, in Japan, and in China? How else might one grasp the implications of what Joanna Ciulla describes as the mass layoffs, in the US, of "middle-aged white men in suits by 'field-of-dreams' companies" like AT&T and IBM.'^ How else understand the relation between capital and labor in the contemporary USa country in which eleven million illegals who are available for hire at ludicrous wages can claim no protection from the police? Stories about crawling across miles of desert in the hope of making it to Los Angeles, or about what became of all those laid-off white men in suits, are essential to understanding the relation between contemporary American business and American society as a whole. Stories about what happens to Chinese peasants who become illegal residents of Shanghai are essential to understanding the globalization of the economy. Such stories will do the same sort of work that was done in the past by the novels of Dickens and Zola, not to mention those of Jack London, Theodore Dreiser, Sinclair Lewis, Ayn Rand, and Tom Wolfe. Executive autobiographies that

378

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

are honest chronicles of events and decisions, rather than mere public relations exercises, serve tbe same purposes. So do corporate histories. For whether a narrative is historical or fictional does not matter as much as whether it enables the reader to put herself in tbe shoes botb of those making difficult business decisions and of those affected by such decisions. The business etbics community, I suspect, does not need people witb a tborougb knowledge of moral theory as mucb as it needs people who have a joumaUst's nose for a good story, and a novelist's talent at spinning it. No particular training is required to dig out and to narrate such stories. So I doubt tbat it matters whether a business etbicist starts adult life as an accountant or an anthropologist, as a congressional staffer or a classical philologist, as assistant to a regional sales manager or as a PhD in philosophy. Just as hospital ethics committees now include MDs, RNs, MBAs, and PbDs in every discipline under the sun, so the business etbics community should welcome people with as many different backgrounds as possible. I can sum up my answer to my title question by saying: philosophy is as relevant as lots of other academic disciplines to applied ethics, and perhaps a little more than most, but not much more.

********************
I would like to close my remarks by glossing a few sentences from Ed Hartman's Organizational Ethics and the Good Life. Given what I have said already, it is obvious tbat I agree witb Hartman when he says "some of our central ethical principles are more ephemeral than we may have supposed; tbey depend on how people are motivated and will change as people's motivation changes. Over time saints and artists and philosophers and managers too will make us rethink what our interests are."'' Hartman and I both make much of the fact that our sense of the possibilities open for human beings bas changed as history bas rolled along, and will go right on changing, in unpredictable ways. Tbese cbanges will come from the creative imagination, rather than from rational reflection or from empirical discoveries. It follows fi'om this view tbat, as Hartman says, "If we want to know what tbe right ethical principles are, we mustfirstknow what the good communitynot the ideal community, but the best we can tbink of^is like." '* I take this to mean that wefirstdream up a sketch of a better world, and only then try to formulate some principles which, if acted upon, might bring that world into existence. Rational argumentation about moral issues always lags behind. Reason can only follow paths tbat the imagination has broken. It seems to me that tbe most difficult task that faces us at the present time is finding a substitute for the communist Utopia that Marx envisaged. Visions of that Utopia stirred the imagination of half tbe world for more than a hundred years. Millions of honest and brave men and women died trying to bring it into existence. Tbe collapse of communism has left us witbout any vision of comparable scope and power. Nobody now bas doubts about tbe need for market economies. But the unfaimess produced by tbe operation of tbose markets is just as appalling as tbe Marxists said it was. Nobody,

Is PHILOSOPHY RELEVANT TO APPLIED ETHICS?

379

to my knowledge, has yet produced a plausible scenario in which this unfairness is gradually rectified, and in which social justice becomes possible on a global scale. Justified resentment at this unfairness is quite likely to produce social and political chaos. The gap between the rich and the poor in the US is steadily widening. If it widens much further, both American democratic institutions and American imperial power will be in danger. But that gap is trivial compared to the one that separates eighty million middle-class Chinese urbanites, shopping till they drop, from eight hundred million Chinese peasants, living without hope. Yet both of these contrasts between social classes within individual nations seem insignificant when compared with that between the average life-chances of a child bom in either the US or China and those of a child bom in the backwoods of Benin or of Bolivia. The vast majority of the human race remains at the mercy of jungle capitalism. The sorts of horrors described by Dickens and Zola are still with us. Nothing that has happened in the last hundred years would lead Marx to revise his dictum that the history of the human race is the history of class struggle. At the beginning of the twentieth century, businessmen like Henry Ford imagined ways in which the US might become a relatively classless society. Some of those dreams actually came true, at least for that bdef shining moment in US history that historians now describe as the Great Leveling. Ford, hke FDR and Walter Reuther, gUmpsed possibilities for industrial capitahsm that had been beyond Marx's and Lenin's imagination. I hope that now, at the beginning of the twenty-first century, at least a few executives of the great multinational corporations are thinking about the need to create a global economy that will, far down the road, make possible global social justice. These men and women are the people with the best sense of the directions in which economic forces are presently driving the nations, of where the real levers of power are to be found, and of the possibilities that remain open for both govemments and business enterprises. If none of them are dreaming up idealistic, Utopian scenarios for the formation of a morally decent global society, it is unlikely that such a society will ever come into existence. Perhaps the business ethics community will provide an environment in which such dreams are encouraged.

Notes
L John Dewey, "Art As Experience," in The Later Works of John Dewey, vol. 10 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1987), 348. The quotation is from Shelley's "A Defence of Poetry," wiiere Shelley also writes that "The great instrument of moral good is the imagination." 2. Philip Pettit, "Existentialism, Quietism, and the Role of Philosophy" in The Future For Philosophy, ed. Brian Leiter (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 306. 3. Brian Leiter, "Introduction" to The Future of Philosophy, 2. 4. Patricia Werhane, Moral Imagination and Management Decision Making (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), ix. 5. Ibid., 13.

380

BUSINESS ETHICS QUARTERLY

6. I have defended this view of moral principles in "Ethics Without Principles," an essay included in my Philosophy and Social Hope (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 2002). See also "Trapped between Kant and Dewey: The Current Situation of Moral Philosophy," in New Essays on the History of Autonomy: A Collection Honoring J. B. Schneewind, ed. Natlies Brender and Larry Krasnoff (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 195-214. 7. Werhane, Moral Imagination, 93. 8. See "Human rights. Rationality and Sentimentality" and "Feminism and Pragmatism," both included in Richard Rorty, Truth and Progress (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998). See also "Justice as a Larger Loyalty," in Justice and Democracy: Cmss-Cultural Perspectives, ed. Ron Bontekoe and Marietta Stepaniants (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1997), 9-22. 9. Ronald Duska, "Business Ethics: Oxymoron or Good Business?" Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1) (January 2000): 128. 10. Laura Nash, "Intensive Care for Everyone's Least Favorite Oxymoron: Narrative in Business Ethics," Business Ethics Quarterly 10(1) (January 2000): 283. 11. Ibid., 282. 12. Joanna CiuUa, "On Getting to the Future First," Business Ethics Quarterly 10( 1) (January 2000): 54. 13. Edwin M. Hartman, Organizational Ethics and the Good Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 111. 14. Ibid., 85.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen