Sie sind auf Seite 1von 3

Deterrence

Deterrence reasoning in a phrase, the ‘rationality of irrationality.’


Yet that line of reasoning only posed another paradox:
Deterrence means threatening punitive retaliation if the deterrer was hotheaded, why would the attacker
to prevent a foe from attacking. It differs fundament- be prudent?
ally from defense, which means threatening to fight Even if the threat of retaliation ruled out nuclear
back if attacked and deny an attacker its objectives. war, that seemed to leave the world safe for war waged
The heart of the distinction is whether it would make by other than nuclear means. That was a source of
sense to carry out the threat. gnawing anxiety for the USA, which was committed
Although the idea of threatening war to prevent war by treaty to deter any attack by the USSR on its allies
is as old as the balance of power, deterrence was not in Western Europe. It did not have the capability to do
just a new word for that old idea. The idea of that by conventional military means alone, at least in
deterrence originated with the atomic bomb. It was the 1950s, so it chose to rely on the threat to initiate
first formulated in 1946 by Bernard Brodie, who tried nuclear war. That threat was potentially suicidal.
to capture what was revolutionary about the advent of Some strategists insisted that ‘extended deterrence,’
the nuclear era. First, a nuclear warhead was not a as that threat came to be called, would work if the
weapon, in Brodie’s view, but a terrorist device, whose USA had nuclear superiority. Thomas Schelling (1966)
blast and radiation effects made it inherently indis- questioned whether superiority assured that the
criminate. Second, the atomic bomb brought home the weaker side must yield to the stronger. It was impos-
fact of mutual vulnerability in a way that aerial sible, he insisted, to raise the risk of a nuclear war for
bombardment had not. Before the nuclear era, a the other side without raising it for oneself. He spoke,
state’s armed forces had to be defeated before the state instead, of a ‘competition in risk-taking.’ Extended
and its centers of population could be held hostage or deterrence still might work if Soviet leaders could not
destroyed at will. Once nuclear warheads were mated be sure the USA would shrink from first use of nuclear
to missiles in the late 1950s, the state and its populace weapons in the event of war. Schelling (1960) called it
were defenseless. The balance of terror differed in ‘the threat that leaves something to chance.’ Such a
fundamental respects from the prenuclear balance of cosmic bluff prompted a preoccupation with ‘credi-
power, according to Brodie. ‘The first and most vital bility’ and a willingness to run seemingly irrational
step,’ he wrote, ‘for the age of atomic bombs is to take risks to shore up an incredible threat. McGeorge
measures to guarantee ourselves in case of attack the Bundy (1983) came up with a less demanding alter-
means of retaliation. Thus far the chief purpose of a native,‘existential deterrence.’ So long as a state
military establishment has been to win wars. From possessed nuclear arms, Bundy argued, it had a latent
now on its chief purpose must be to avert them.’ These ability to use them, even if it did not explicitly threaten
prescient insights became a matter of considerable to do so. The mere existence of these arms and the
scholarly discourse. Regrettably they had little in- incalculable costs of a nuclear war exerted a cautionary
fluence on nuclear policy. effect on potential foes.
Other strategic thinkers took a more forceful tack.
British strategist Basil Liddell Hart (1946) first formu-
lated the idea of graduated deterrence, carefully
1. Deterrence in Theory calibrated to threaten greater costs to an attacker
without generating all-out war. Still others debated
The logic of deterrence, as Brodie and others whether military forces or civilians were the most
recognized, is inherently paradoxical. To deter nuclear appropriate targets for nuclear attack. This line of
attack, it is deemed necessary to threaten nuclear thought culminated in the baroque escalation ladder
retaliation. Inasmuch as the cost of a nuclear war is of Herman Kahn (1960) and the contention of some of
prohibitive, neither side would risk it. Yet that rational his followers that the USA could deter any aggression
calculus conveniently overlooks the irrationality of if it somehow had ‘escalation dominance,’ or military
retaliating for a nuclear first strike with a nuclear superiority at every level of violence, short of all-out
second strike. Retaliation makes no sense unless the nuclear war. Yet the idea of waging limited nuclear
second strike could eliminate the other side’s nuclear war and controlling escalation raised the question of
forces and prevent it from launching another strike of how a nuclear war could stop, short of a dead end.
its own. That deadly logic led Brodie to the para-
doxical conclusion that what made deterrence work
was the possibility that it might fail, making it prudent
for neither side to tempt fate. The same logic led other 2. Deterrence in Practice
strategic thinkers to conclude that for deterrence to
work, it could not be mere bluff. The threatener had to Deterrence, in short, did not work very well in
be willing to carry out the threat. For that to happen, theory. What happened in practice was in many ways
nuclear retaliation had to be automatic or mad. worse. Deterrence did not govern the production,
Herman Kahn (1960) captured the sense of that line of deployment, or military plans for nuclear arms (Ball

3542
Deterrence

1978). The number of Soviet and US warheads vastly theory on the grounds that it was psychologically
exceeded what was needed for deterrence. The war- naive and operationally uninformed. Robert Jervis
heads themselves were initially deployed in ways that (1974), John Steinbruner (1976), and Scott Sagan
made them vulnerable to attack. Dispersing them on (1993) are leading exemplars of these approaches.
land and at sea reduced, though did not eliminate their One side’s strategy depended on the other’s. So did
vulnerability, and made command-and-control all the its security. Their interdependence was the central
more precarious. Because of the chance that the cosmic feature of game theory. Whether the game of chicken
bluff could be called, each side drew up detailed war or the prisoner’s dilemma was the appropriate ana-
plans to destroy the other. Those war plans fully reflect logy, many scholars who formulated the logic of
the deadly logic of deterrence: in the event that war deterrence drew heavily on game theory for their
breaks out, nuclear arms confer enormous, some say insights.
decisive, advantage on the side that strikes first. The One consequence is that deterrence is largely de-
most urgent targets were the other side’s nuclear forces ductive and only weakly grounded empirically. An-
and especially their command-and-control. Concern other reason for its weak evidentiary base is that
about a disarming first strike led the USA to keep nuclear history everywhere remains cloaked in secrecy.
some of its bombers airborne at all times and to put Without knowledge of the details of nuclear planning
others on alert, ready to take off at a moment’s notice. and operations, it is difficult to determine how
It did the same with its missiles. This hair-trigger much nuclear strategy is informed by deterrence the-
posture, and the delegation of authority that it ory, if at all. A more fundamental reason why the
necessitated, raised the risk of loss of nuclear control evidence for deterrence is less than compelling is the
in a crisis. Schelling (1960) called this predicament ‘the epistemological difficulty of proving why something
reciprocal fear of surprise attack.’ As first one side and did not happen in order to demonstrate that deterrence
then the other began mobilizing forces, the very steps worked. The obvious counter to the contention that
taken to deter a nuclear war might provoke one. Far nuclear deterrence kept the USSR out of Western
from exerting a cautionary effect on preparations for Europe is that it never intended to invade in the first
war, that fear led both sides to a massive buildup of place.
arms, conventional as well as nuclear, which did little Because the side that is losing could still destroy the
to calm the fear. side that is winning, safety in the nuclear era lay in
That had important implications for theorizing cooperation between enemies. That interdependence
about deterrence. Although some theorists saw mutual made nonsense of traditional strategic thought. It also
deterrence as a source of stability in international called into question the very idea of strategy as a
politics, others saw it as potentially unstable in the rational relationship between means and ends. War, in
extreme. The first group emphasized the need to theory, if not always in practice, ‘is controlled by its
demonstrate the capability and will to wage war, lest a political object,’ Clausewitz had reasoned. Conse-
potential aggressor doubt a state’s strength or resolve. quently, ‘the value of this object must determine the
By this way of thinking, conciliation was dangerous sacrifices to be made for it in magnitude and also in
because it might be mistaken for weakness or irreso- duration.’ But what objective could possibly sustain
luteness. A second group of theorists were led to a the full measure of sacrifice in a nuclear war? As
renewed appreciation of the security dilemma, an idea Lawrence Freedman (1981) concludes, ‘The position
dating back to Thucydides, who noted that attempts we have reached is one where stability depends on
by one side to enhance or demonstrate its military something that is more the antithesis of strategy than
might prove self-defeating. By alarming its rival and its apotheosis—on threats that things will get out of
leading it to respond in kind, these measures would hand, that we might act irrationally, that possibly
leave both sides less secure. Such a vicious circle could through inadvertence we could set in motion a process
generate an arms race, or worse, trigger pre–emptive that in its development and conclusion would be
war. These theorists saw the need to couple coercion beyond human control and comprehension.’ Nuclear
with conciliation, lest the interaction spiral out of strategy, understood this way, was a contradiction in
control. To some scholars, the difference between the terms.
deterrence and spiral logic depended on each side’s
perception of the other’s intentions. See also: Diplomacy; Genealogy in Anthropology;
Where perception matters, so does the danger of War: Causes and Patterns
misperception. The fear that war is imminent is
sometimes irrational. Once it takes hold, it is not
amenable to a cool calculation of costs. The possibility
of pre–emptive war calls into question two major Bibliography
premises of most theorizing about nuclear deterrence, Ball D 1980 Politics and Force Leels. University of California
that statesmen will behave rationally in the heat of the Press, Berkeley, CA
moment and that they can control the operations of Brodie B 1946 The Absolute Weapon. Harcourt, Brace, New
their armed forces. This led to critiques of deterrence York

3543
Deterrence

Bundy M 1983 The Bishops and the Bomb. In: New York Reiew examples are Ross’ studies of the impact on drunk
of Books 10 : 30 driving of the British Road Safety Act and of Scand-
Freedman L 1981 The Eolution of Nuclear Strategy. St. Martin’s inavian-style drunk driving laws (Ross 1982).
Press, New York
The great proportion of interrupted time series
Jervis R 1976 Perception and Misperception in International
Politics. Princeton University Press, Princeton NJ studies have examined the impact of drunk driving
Kahn H 1960 On Thermonuclear War. Princeton University laws or of police crackdown, on drug markets, dis-
Press, Princeton, NJ orderly behavior and drunk driving. A less extensive
Liddell Hart B H 1946 The Reolution in Warfare. Faber and literature has also examined the impact of gun control
Faber Ltd., London laws and ordinances. Excellent reviews of these studies
Sagan S D 1993 The Limits of Safety. Princeton University are available from Sherman (1990) and Ross (1982).
Press, Princeton, NJ Both reviews conclude that interventions are gen-
Schelling T 1960 The Strategy of Conflict. Harvard University erally successful in generating an initial deterrent
Press, Cambridge, MA
effect. One exception may be interventions that in-
Schelling T C 1966 Arms and Influence. Yale University Press,
New Haven, CT crease sentence severity. If judges or juries believe that
Steinbruner J D 1974 The Cybernetic Theory of Decision. the penalties are too harsh, they may respond by
Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ refusing to convict guilty defendants with the result
that the policy increases rather than deters the targeted
L. V. Sigal behavior. Indeed, Ross concludes that efforts to deter
drunk driving with harsher penalties commonly fail
Copyright # 2001 Elsevier Science Ltd. for precisely this reason. Sherman and Ross are also in
All rights reserved. agreement that the effect is generally only transitory:
the initial deterrent effect typically begins decaying
Deterrence: Legal Perspectives even while the intervention is still in effect. However,
in some instances, the decay is not complete even
The criminal justice system (CJS) dispenses justice by following the end of the crackdown.
apprehending, prosecuting, and punishing law-
breakers. These activities also project a threat of 1.2 Perceptual Deterrence Studies
punishment. Deterrence occurs when some would-be
law breakers conclude that the price of crime is
prohibitive. General deterrence refers to the crime 1.2.1 Summary of findings. The perceptual deter-
prevention impact of the threat of punishment on the rence literature examines the relationships of per-
public at large. Specific deterrence refers to the impact ceived sanction risks to either self-reported offending
of punishment on persons actually punished. The or intentions to do so. This literature was spawned
actual experience of punishment may alter an indi- by researchers interested in probing the perceptual un-
vidual’s perceptions and opportunities. Also, persons derpinnings of the deterrence process.
for whom general deterrence has failed may be Perceptual deterrence studies have focused on ex-
systematically different than the population at large. amining the connection of illegal behavior to two
For both these reasons specific deterrent effects may categories of sanction variables, the certainty and
be smaller than the subject of this article, general severity of punishment. The certainty of punishment
deterrent effects. refers to the probability that a crime will result in
punishment whereas severity refers to the seriousness
of the consequences to the punished individual, such
as prison sentence length.
1. A Brief Reiew of Research on General Perceptual deterrence studies have been based on
Deterrence three types of data: cross-sectional survey studies,
Deterrence research has evolved in three distinctive panel survey studies, and scenario-based studies. In
and largely disconnected literatures—interrupted time cross sectional survey studies individuals are ques-
series, perceptual, and ecological studies (Nagin 1998). tioned about their perceptions of the certainty and
severity of sanctions and either about their prior
offending behavior or future intentions to offend. For
example, Grasmick and Bryjak (1980) queried a
1.1 Interrupted Time Series Studies
sample of city residents about their perceptions of the
Interrupted time series studies examine the impact of risk of arrest for offenses such as a petty theft, drunk
targeted policy interventions such as police crack- driving, and tax cheating, and also about their
downs or implementation of statutes changing pen- intention to commit each of these acts in the future.
alties. The best-designed studies mimic important In panel survey studies the sample is repeatedly
features of a true experiment—a well-defined treat- surveyed on risk perceptions and criminal behavior.
ment regime, measurement of response before and For example, Paternoster et al. (1982) followed a
after treatment and a control group. Two classic sample of students through their three-year tenure in

3544

International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences ISBN: 0-08-043076-7

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen