Measure Theory
Citation from Rudins book, [11, Chapter 1: Towards the end of the 19th
entury it
be
ame
lear to many mathemati
ians that the Riemann integral should be repla
ed by
some other type of integral, more general and more
exible, better suited for dealing with
limit pro
esses. Among the attempts made in this dire
tion, the most notable ones were
due to Jordan, Borel, W.H. Young, and Lebesgue. It was Lebesgue's
onstru
tion whi
h
turned out to be the most su
essful.
In a brief outline, here is the main idea: The Riemann integral of a fun
tion f over an
interval [a; b
an be approximated by sums of the form
n
X
i=1
f (ti ) m(Ei );
where E1 ; : : : ; En are disjoint intervals whose union is [a; b, m(Ei ) denotes the length
of Ei and ti 2 Ei for i = 1; : : : ; n. Lebesgue dis
overed that a
ompletely satisfa
tory
theory of integration results if the sets Ei in the above sum are allowed to belong to
a larger
lass of subsets of the line, the so-
alled \measurable sets," and if the
lass of
fun
tions under
onsideration is enlarged to what we
all \measurable fun
tions." The
ru
ial set-theoreti
properties involved are the following: The union and the interse
tion
of any
ountable family of measurable sets are measurable; : : : the notion of \length"
(now
alled \measure")
an be extended to them in su
h a way that
286
10
2 A.
An algebra
[A is
alled a -algebra if for all
ountable families fAn j n 2 Ng with An 2 A
we have
An 2 A.
n2N
n2N
An =
n2N
A n
(d) The family P(X ) of all subsets of X is both an algebra as well as a -algebra.
(e) Any -algebra is an algebra but there are algebras not being -algebras.
(f) The family of nite and
onite subsets (these are
omplements of nite sets) of an
innite set form an algebra. Do they form a -algebra?
Elementary Sets in Rn
10.1
287
Measure Theory
3. If x > 0 we have
x (+1) = (+1) x = ( 1) (
x ( 1) = ( 1) x = (+1) (
1) = +1
1) = ( 1) (+1) = 1:
4. If x < 0 we have
x (+1) = (+1) x = 1
x ( 1) = ( 1) x = +1:
5. 0 1 = 1 0 = 0.
The set
I = f(x1 ; : : : ; xn ) 2 Rn j ai xi bi ; i = 1; : : : ; ng
is
alled a re
tangle or a box in Rn , where either stands for < or for where ai ; bi 2 R.
For example ai = 1 and bi = +1 yields I = Rn , whereas a1 = 2, b1 = 1 yields I = ?.
A subset of Rn is
alled an elementary set if it is the union of a nite number of re
tangles
in Rn . Let En denote the set of elementary subsets of Rn .
En is an algebra but not a -algebra.
Proof. The
omplement of a nite interval is the
union of two intervals, the
omplement of an innite
interval is an innite interval. Hen
e, the
omplement
of a re
tangle in Rn is the nite union of re
tangles.
S
The
ountable (disjoint) union M = n2N[n; n + 21
is not an elementary set.
Note that any elementary set is the disjoint union of
a nite number of re
tangles.
Denition 10.2 Let B be any (nonempty) family of subsets of X . Let (B) denote the
interse
tion of all -algebras
ontaining B, i. e.
(B) =
\
i2I
Ai;
where fAi j i 2 I g is the family of all -algebras Ai whi
h
ontain B, B Ai for all i 2 I .
Note that the -algebra P(X ) of all subsets is always a member of that family fAi g
su
h that (B) exists. We
all (B) the -algebra generated by B. (B) is the smallest
-algebra whi
h
ontains the sets of B.
Lemma 10.1 For any non-empty family B of subsets of X , (B) is a -algebra over X .
We have ( (B)) = (B). If B1 B2 then (B1 ) (B2 ).
288
10
B B
1
The Borel algebra is the smallest -algebra whi
h
ontains all boxes in Rn We will see
that the Borel algebra is a huge family of subsets of Rn whi
h
ontains \all sets we are
ever interested in." Later, we will
onstru
t a non-Borel set.
Proof. We give the proof in
ase of R2 . Let I" (x0 ; y0 ) = (x0 "; x0 + ") (y0 "; y0 + ")
1 I 1 for n 2 N.
denote the open square of size 2" by 2" with midpoint (x0 ; y0 ). Then I +1
2
Let M R be open. To every point (x0 ; y0) with rational
oordinates x0 ; y0 we
hoose
the largest square I1=n (x0 ; y0 ) M in M and denote it by J (x0 ; y0).
n
We show that
M=
[
x0 ;y0 )2M; rational
J (x0 ; y0 ):
(x,y)
0 0
(a,b)
I 1 (x0 ; y0 ) I 2 (a; b) M:
n
Sin
e (a; b) 2 I n1 (x0 ; y0 ) J (x0 ; y0 ), we have shown that M is the union of the
ountable
family of sets J . Sin
e
losed sets are the
omplements of open sets and
omplements
are again in the -algebra, the assertion follows for
losed sets.
10.1
289
Measure Theory
Remarks 10.2 (a) We have proved that any open subset M of Rn is the
ountable union
of re
tangles I M .
(b) The Borel sets in Rn are exa
tly the sets whi
h
an be built by
ountable unions or
interse
tions of open or
losed sets.
(
) The Borel algebra (En ) is equal to the -algebra generated by the family G of open
sets in Rn ,
f. Homework 34.2.
Let us look in more detail at some of the sets in (En). Let G and F be the families of
all open and
losed subsets of Rn , respe
tively. Let G be the
olle
tion of all interse
tion
of sequen
es of open sets (from G), and let F be the
olle
tion of all unions of sequen
es
of sets of F. One
an prove that F G and G F . These in
lusions are stri
t. Sin
e
ountable interse
tion and unions of
ountable interse
tions and union are still
ountable
operations, G ; F (En)
For an arbitrary family S of sets let S be the
olle
tion of all unions of sequen
es of sets
in S, and let S be the
olle
tion of all unions of sequen
es of sets in S. We
an iterate the
operations represented by and , obtaining from the
lass G the
lasses G , G , G ,
: : : and from F the
lasses F , F , : : : . It turns out that we have in
lusions
G G G (En)
F F F (En):
No two of these
lasses are equal. There are Borel sets that belong to none of them.
10.1.1
Denition 10.4 (a) Let A be an algebra over X . An additive fun
tion or
ontent on
A is a fun
tion : A ! [0; +1 su
h that
(i) (?) = 0,
(ii) (A [ B ) = (A) + (B ) for all A; B 2 A with A \ B = ?.
(b) An additive fun
tion is
alled
ountably additive (or -additive in the German
literature) on A if for any disjoint family fAn j An 2 A; n 2 Ng, that is Ai \ Aj = ? for
S
all i 6= j , with n2N An 2 A we have
[
n2N
An =
X
n2N
(An ):
290
10
Notation. We write
An in pla e of
n2N
n2N
ountable additivity reads as follows
9 n 2 N : x 2 Ang) = nlim
!1
(fx 2 X j
n
X
k=1
(Ak ):
( A ) =
1; x0 2 A;
0; x0 62 A
( A ) =
+1;
n;
n
X
i=1
(Ii ); if A =
n
X
i=1
Ii :
R ! R dened by
((0; x);
x 0;
((x; 0);
x < 0;
denes an in
reasing fun
tion on R su
h that = if is
ontinuous from the right.
(x) =
10.1
291
Measure Theory
n
X
k=1
Ak =
n
X
k=1
2 A.
(e)
n
[
k=1
Ak
n
X
k=1
(Ak );
if Ak 2 A, k = 1; : : : ; n, ( is nitely subadditive).
(f) If fAk j k 2 Ng is a disjoint family in
1
X
k=1
A and
1
X
(Ak )
k=1
1
X
k=1
!
Ak 2 A. Then
Ak :
Proof. (a) is by indu
tion. (d), (
), and (b) are easy (
f. Homework 34.4).
(e) We
an write
n
[
k=1
n
[
k=1
Ak = A1
Sin e is additive,
[ A n A [ A n (A [ A ) [ [ An n (A [ [ An
n
[
k=1
Ak =
n
X
k=1
(Ak n (A1 [ Ak 1 ))
(Ak ) =
n
X
k=1
Ak
1
X
k=1
n
X
k=1
) :
(Ak );
Ak :
Proposition 10.4 Let be an additive fun
tion on the algebra A. Consider the following
statements
292
10
we have nlim
(An ) = (A).
!1
(
) For any de
reasing sequen
e An
An
+1
An
, An
+1 , An
2 A, with
1
[
n=1
2 A, with
(b)
! ( ) ! (d).
An = A 2 A
1
\
n=1
An
2 A and
( A ) =
1
X
k=2
(Bk ) = nlim
!1
n
X
k=2
(Bk ) = nlim
!1
n
X
Bk = nlim
(An ):
!1
k=2
(b)
1
(Bn ) =
Thus,
1
X
k=1
(Ak ) =
n
X
k=1
1
X
k=1
Ak
is additive
n
X
k=1
(Ak ) n!1
! ( A ) =
1
X
k=1
Ak ;
Ak .
(A1 n An ) n!1
! (A1 n A);
Proposition 10.5 Let be in reasing and the orresponding Lebesgue{Stieltjes ontent on E1 . Then is ountably additive if and only if is ontinuous from the right.
Proof. Let be
ountably additive and a 2 R. Fix a > 0. By Proposition 10.4 (
) for
any de
reasing to a sequen
e (bn ) we have
10.1
293
Measure Theory
(a; b =
k=1
(ak ; bk
with a disjoint family [ak ; bk ) of intervals. By Proposition 10.3 (f) we already know
((a; b)
1
X
((ak ; bk ):
k=1
(10.1)
We prove the opposite dire
tion. Let " > 0. Sin
e is
ontinuous from the right at a,
there exists a0 2 [a; b) su
h that (a0 ) (a) < " and, similarly, for every k 2 N there
exists
k > bk su
h that (
k ) (bk ) < "=2k . Hen
e,
[a0 ; b
1
[
(ak ; bk
k=1
1
[
(ak ; k )
k=1
is an open
overing of a
ompa
t set. By Heine{Borel (Denition 6.11) there exists a nite
sub
over
[a0 ; b
N
[
(ak ; k );
k=1
hen e (a0 ; b
N
[
(ak ; k ;
k=1
((a0 ; b)
k=1
((ak ; k ):
2k
N
X
k=1
N
X
k=1
((ak ; bk ) +
((ak ; bk ) + 2"
((a; b)
1
X
k=1
1
X
k=1
"
2k
+"
((ak ; bk ) + 2"
((ak ; bk ):
"
294
10
Corollary 10.6 The
orresponden
e 7! () from Example 10.1 (d) denes a bije
tion
between
ountably additive fun
tions on E1 and the monotoni
ally in
reasing, right
ontinuous fun
tions on R (up to
onstant fun
tions, i. e. and +
dene the same
additive fun
tion).
Histori
al Note. It was the great a
hievment of Emile
Borel (1871{1956) that he really
proved the
ountable additivity of the Lebesgue measure. He realized that the
ountable
additivity of is a serious mathemati
al problem far from being evident.
10.1.2
Here we must stop the rigorous treatment of measure theory. Up to now, we know only
two trivial examples of measures (Example 10.1 (a) and (b)). We give an outline of the
steps toward the
onstru
tion of the Lebesgue measure.
Constru
tion of an outer measure on P(X ) from a
ountably additive fun
tion
on A.
Theorem 10.7 (Extension and Uniqueness) Let be a
ountably additive fun
tion
on the algebra A.
(a) There exists an extension of to a measure on the -algebra (A) whi
h
oin
ides
with on A. We denote the measureP
on (A) also by .
(b) This extension is unique, if X = 1
n=1 An , An 2 A, and (An ) < 1 for all n 2 N.
(Without proof)
Remarks 10.3 (a) The extension theory is due to Caratheodory (1914). For a detailed
Rn
Using the fa
ts from the previous subse
tion we
on
lude that for any in
reasing, right
ontinuous fun
tion on R there exists a measure on the -algebra of Borel sets. We
all this measure the Lebesgue{Stieltjes measure on R. In
ase (x) = x we
all it the
Lebesgue measure. Extending the Lebesgue
ontent on elementary sets of Rn to the Borel
algebra (En ), we obtain the n-dimensional Lebesgue measure n on Rn .
Completeness
A measure : A ! R+ on a -algebra A is said to be
omplete if A 2 A, (A) = 0, and
B A implies B 2 A. It turns out that the Lebesgue measure n on the Borel sets of
10.1
295
Measure Theory
Remarks 10.4 (a) The Lebesgue measure is invariant under the motion group of Rn .
More pre
isely, let O(n) = fT 2 M(n n; R) j T t T = T T t = En g be the group of real
orthogonal n n-matri
es (\motions"), then
n (T (A)) = n (A); A 2 A ; T
n
2 O(n):
(fx1 ; x2 ; : : : ; xn ; : : : g) =
1
X
n=1
(fxn g) = 0:
296
10
(e) There are un
ountable sets with measure zero. The Cantor set (Cantor: 1845{1918,
inventor of set theory) is a prominent example:
( 1
X ai
=
3i
i=1
ai 2 f0; 2g ;
1
2 1
Cn+1 = Cn [
+ Cn :
3
3 3
Clearly,
n
n+1
2
2
2
(C1 ) =
:
(Cn+1) = (Cn ) = =
3
3
3
By Proposition 10.4 (
), (C ) = lim (Cn) = 0. However, C has the same
ardinality as
n!1
f0; 2gN = f0; 1gN
= R whi
h is un
ountable.
10.2
Let
A be a -algebra over X .
Denition 10.5 A real fun
tion f : X ! R is
alled A-measurable if for all a 2 R the
set fx 2 X j f (x) > ag belongs to A.
A
omplex fun
tion f is said to be A-measurable if both Re f and Im f are A-measurable.
A fun
tion f : U ! R, U Rn , is said to be a Borel fun
tion if f is (En)-measurable,
i. e. f is measurable with respe
t to the Borel algebra on Rn .
A fun
tion f : U ! V , U Rn , V Rm , is
alled a Borel fun
tion if f 1 (B ) is a Borel
set for all Borel sets B V .
Note that fx 2 X j f (x) > ag = f 1 ((a; +1)). From Proposition 10.8 below it be
omes
lear that the last two notions are
onsistent. Note that no measure on (X; A) needs to
be spe
ied to dene a measurable fun
tion.
Example 10.2 (a) Any
ontinuous fun
tion f : U ! R, U Rn , is a Borel fun
tion.
Indeed, sin
e f is
ontinuous and (a; +1) is open, f 1 ((a; +1)) is open as well and hen
e
10.2
297
A-measurable).
fx j f (x) ag =
n2N
Sin
e f is A-measurable and A is a -algebra, the
ountable interse
tion on the right is
in A.
(a) ! (d) follows from fx j f (x) ag = fx j f (x) > ag
. The remaining dire
tions are
left to the reader (see also homework 35.5).
! R be A-measurable.
Then fx
Proof. Sin e
[
q2Q
and all sets ff < q g and fq < g g the right are in A, and on the right there is a
ountable union, the right hand side is in A. A similar argument works for ff > g g.
Note that the sets ff g g and ff g g are the
omplements of ff < g g and ff > g g,
respe
tively; hen
e they belong to A as well. Finally, ff = g g = ff g g\ff g g.
It is easy to see (
f. homework 35.4) that for any sequen
e (an ) of real numbers
lim a
n!1 n
n!1
(10.2)
Proposition 10.10 Let (fn ) be a sequen
e of A-measurable fun
tions on X . Then sup fn ,
n2N
inf fn , lim fn , lim fn are A-measurable. In parti
ular lim fn is measurable if the limit
n!1
n!1
n2N
n!1
exists.
Proof. Note that for all a 2 R we have (
f. homework 35.4)
fsup fn ag =
ffn ag:
n2N
Sin
e all fn are measurable, so is sup fn . A similar proof works for inf fn . By (10.2),
lim n!1 fn and lim n!1 fn , are measurable, too.
298
10
Let (X; A; ) be a measure spa
e and f : X ! R arbitrary. Let f + = maxff; 0g and f = maxf f; 0g
denote the positive and negative parts of f . We
have f = f + f and j f j = f + + f ; moreover
f + ; f 0.
Corollary 10.12 Let f is a Borel fun
tion if and only if both f + and f are Borel.
10.3
We dene the Lebesgue integral of a
omplex fun
tion in 3 steps; rst for positive, simple
fun
tions, then for positive measurable fun
tions and nally for arbitrary measurable
fun
tions. In this se
tion (X; A; ) is a measure spa
e.
10.3.1
f=
n
X
i=1
i A ;
i
where Ai = fx j f (x) =
i g. It is
lear, see homework 35.2, that f measurable if and only
if Ai 2 A for all i. Obviously, fAi j i = 1; : : : ; ng is a disjoint family of subsets of X .
We denote the set of simple fun
tions on (X; A) by S; the set of non-negative simple
fun
tions is denoted by S+ . It is easy to see that f; g 2 S implies f + g 2 S, maxff; g g 2
S, minff; gg 2 S, and fg 2 S.
10.3
299
For f =
n
X
i=1
i A
2S
dene
Z
X
f d =
n
X
i=1
i (Ai ):
(10.3)
The
onvention 0 (+1) is used here; it may happen that
i = 0 for some i and (Ai ) =
+1.
Remarks 10.5 (a) Sin
e
i 0 for all i, the right hand side is well-dened in R.
(b) Given another presentation of f , say, f (x) =
value as (10.3).
m
X
j =1
dj B ,
j
m
X
j =1
(1) X A d = (A).
R
R
(2) X
f d =
X f d.
R
(3) X (f + g ) d = X f d + X g d.
R
R
(4) f g implies X f d X g d.
10.3.2
0 s1
! [0; +1 be measurable.
s f.
sn (x) n!1
! f (x), as n ! 1, for every x 2 X .
2
y
f
E24
1/2
a
E11
E12
F1
b
E12 E11
1
;
0;
E11 = f
2
1
1
E12 = f
;1 ;
2
F2 = f 1 ([1; +1) :
3/4
300
10
Eni = f
1
i 1 i
n ; n
n 2n
X
i
and put
sn =
and Fn = f 1 ([n; 1)
i=1
2n
E + nF :
n
ni
Proposition 10.8 shows that Eni and Fn are measurable sets. It is easily seen that the
fun
tions sn satisfy (a). If x is su
h that f (x) < +1, then
0 f (x)
sn (x)
1
2n
(10.4)
If
f uniformly on X if f is bounded.
Denition 10.7 (Lebesgue Integral) Let f : X ! [0; +1 be measurable. Let (sn (x))
be an in
reasing sequen
e of simple fun
tions sn
onverging to f (x) for all x 2 X ,
lim sn (x) = sup sn (x) = f (x). Dene
n!1
n2N
Z
X
f d = sup
n2N
Z
X
s n d
(10.5)
and
all this number in [0; +1 the Lebesgue integral of f (x) over X with respe
t to the
measure or -integral of f over X .
The denition of the Lebesgue integral does not depend on the spe
ial
hoi
e of the
in
reasing fun
tions sn % f . One
an dene
Z
X
f d = sup
Z
X
Observe, that we apparently have two denitions for X f d if f is a simple fun
tion.
However these assign the same value to the integral sin
e f is the largest simple fun
tion
greater than or equal to f .
Proposition 10.15 The properties (1) to (4) from Lemma 10.13 hold for any nonnegative measurable fun
tions f; g : X ! [0; +1,
2 R+ .
(Without proof.)
10.3
301
10.3.3
j f j d < 1:
f d =
u d
u d + i
v d i
v d:
(10.6)
These four fun
tions u+ , u , v + , and v are measurable, real, and non-negative. Sin
e
we have u+ j u j j f j et
., ea
h of these four integrals is nite. Thus, (10.6) denes
the integral on the left as a
omplex number.
We dene L1 (X; ) to be the
olle
tion of all
omplex -integrable fun
tions f on X . It
is sometimes desirable to dene the integral of a measurable fun
tion f : X ! [ 1; +1
to be
Z
Z
Z
+
f d = f
f d;
X
if at least one of the integrals on the right is nite. The left side is then a number in
[ 1; +1.
R
Note that for an integrable fun
tions f , X f d is a nite number.
f d
j f j d:
(b) f is -integrable if and only if there exists an integrable fun tion h with
j f j h.
(
1 f +
2 g ) d =
1
R
f d + 2
Z
X
g d:
g on X , then X f d X g d.
It follows that the set L (X; ) of -integrable
omplex-valued fun
tions on X is a linear
spa
e. The Lebesgue integral denes a positive linear fun
tional on L (X; ). Note that
(b) implies that any measurable and bounded fun
tion f on a spa
e X with (X ) < 1
(d) If f
is integrable.
302
10
f d =
A f d:
10.4.1
Denition 10.10 Let P be a property whi
h a point x may or may not have. For
instan
e, P may be the property \f (x) > 0" if f is a given fun
tion or \(fn(x))
onverges"
if (fn ) is a given sequen
e of fun
tions. If (X; A; ) is a measure spa
e and A 2 A, we say
\P holds almost everywhere on A", abbreviated by \P holds a. e. on E ", if there exists
N 2 A su
h that (N ) = 0 and P holds for every point x 2 E n N .
This
on
ept of
ourse strongly depends on the measure , and sometimes we write
-a. e. For example, if f; g are measurable fun
tions, we write f g if f = g -a. e. on
X . This means (fx j f (x) 6= g (x)g) = 0. This is indeed an equivalen
e relation. Note
that f = g a. e. on X implies
Z
Z
f d =
g d:
(f
g ) d =
(f
g ) d +
X nN
(f
Xf
d = 0 if and only if f = 0 a. e. on X .
Denition 10.11 Let (X; A; ) be a measure spa
e. For 1 p < 1, Lp (X; ) denotes
the set of A-measurable fun
tions f on X su
h that j f jp 2 L1 (X; ). For f 2 Lp (X; )
set
kf kp =
Z
X
1
j f j d :
p
(10.7)
R
From Proposition 10.17 it follows that kkp is not a norm, in general, sin
e X j f jp d = 0
implies only f = 0 a. e. However, identifying fun
tions f and g whi
h are equal a. e. ,
(10.7) denes a norm on those equivalen
e
lasses.
Let N = ff : X ! C j f is measurable and f = 0 a. e. g: Then N is a linear subspa
e
of Lp (X; ) for all all p, and f = g a. e. if and only if f g 2 N.
10.4
303
Denition 10.12 Let (X; A; ) be a measure spa
e. Lp (X; ) denotes the set of equivalen
e
lasses of fun
tions of Lp (X; ) with respe
t to the equivalen
e relation f = g
a. e. that is,
is the quotient spa e. Lp (X; ) is a normed spa e with the norm (10.7).
The following theorem about the monotone
onvergen
e by Beppo Levi (1875{1961) is
one of the most important in the theory of integration. The theorem
holds for an arbitrary
R
in
reasing sequen
e of measurable fun
tions with, possibly, X fn d = +1.
lim
f d
n!1 X n
f d:
! [0; +1
Z X
1
X n=1
f n d =
1 Z
X
n=1 X
2 N,
and f (x) =
fn d:
Example 10.3 (a) Let X = N, A = P(N) the -algebra of all subsets, and the
ounting
measure on N. The fun
tions on N
an be identied with the sequen
es (xn ), f (n) = xn .
Trivially,Rany fun
tion is A-measurable.
What is N xn d? First, let f 0. For a simple fun
tion gn , given by gn = xn fng , we
1
X
R
obtain gn d = xn (fng) = xn . Note that f =
gn and gn 0 sin
e xn 0. By
Corollary 10.19,
n=1
f d =
1 Z
X
gn d =
1
X
xn :
N
n=1
n=1
R
P
Now, let f be arbitrary integrable, i. e. N j f j d < 1; thus 1
n=1 j xn j < 1. ThereP
1
fore, (xn ) 2 L (N; ) if and only if xn
onverges absolutely. The spa
e of absolutely
onvergent series is denoted by `1 or `1 (N).
N
304
10
n=1 m=1
amn =
1
1 X
X
m=1 n=1
amn :
Proof. Consider the measure spa
e (N; P(N); ) from (a). For n
fn (m) = amn . By Corollary 10.19 we then have
Z X
1
1
X
f (m)
fn (m) d = f d =
(a)
X
X n=1
m=1
| {z }
f (m)
1 Z
1 X
1
X
X
=
fn (m) d =
amn :
X
n=1
n=1 m=1
2 N dene fun tions
1 X
1
X
m=1 n=1
amn
f d; A 2 A
Besides the monotone
onvergen
e theorem the present theorem is the most important
one. It is due to Henry Lebesgue. The great advantage,
ompared with Theorem7.7, is
that (X ) = 1 is allowed, that is, non-
ompa
t domains X are in
luded. We only need
the pointwise
onvergen
e of (fn ), not the uniform
onvergen
e. The main assumtion here
is the existen
e of an integrable upper bound for all fn .
!R
or into
(1) fn ! f as n ! 1 a. e.
(2) j fn j g a. e.
Z
(3)
Then
g d < +1.
j f j d < 1 and
lim
lim
f d = f
n!1 X n
X
n!1 X
j f n f j d = 0:
d;
(10.8)
10.4
305
Note, that (10.8) shows that (fn ) onverges to f in the normed spa e L1 (X; ).
Example
10.4 (a) Let An 2 A, n 2 N, A1 A2 be an in
reasing sequen
e with
[
An = A.
n2N
If f 2 L1 (A; ), then
Z
Z
lim
n!1 An
f d =
f d:
lim
n!1 An
f d = nlim
!1
Z
X
A f =
A f d =
Z
A
f d:
However, if we do not assume f 2 L1 (A; ), the statement is not true (see Remark 10.6
below).
(b) Let fn = n(0;1=n) be dened on (0; 1). Then fn ! 0 pointwise, however
Z
1
0
fn d = 1 6!
1
0
0 = 0:
Note, that fn is neither monotoni
nor dominated by any integrable fun
tion g .
10.4.4
Proposition 10.22 Let f be a bounded fun
tion on the nite interval [a; b.
(a) f is Riemann integrable on [a; b if and only if f is
ontinuous a. e. on [a; b.
(b) If f is Riemann integrable on [a; b, then f is Lebesgue integrable, too. Both integrals
oin
ide.
Let I R be an interval su
h that f is Riemann integrable on all
ompa
t subintervals
of I .
(
) f is Lebesgue integrable on I if and only if j f j is improperly Riemann integrable on
I (see Se
tion 5.4); both integrals
oin
ide.
Remarks 10.6 (a) The
hara
teristi
fun
tion Q on [0; 1 is Lebesgue but not Riemann
integrable; Q is nowhere
ontinuous on [0; 1.
(b) The (improper) Riemann integral
Z 1
sin x
1
dx
onverges (see Example 5.9); however, the Lebesgue integral does not exist sin
e the
integral does not
onverge absolutely.
306
10
10.4.5
Fubini's Theorem
Theorem 10.23 Let (X1 ; A1; 1 ) and (X2 ; A2; 2 ) be -nite measure spa
es, let f be an
A1
A2-measurable fun
tion andR X = X1 X2.
R
(a) If f : X ! [0; +1, '(x1 ) = f (x1 ; x2 ) d2 , (x2 ) = f (x1 ; x2 ) d1, then
X2
Z
X2
(b) If f
(x2 ) d2 =
X1 X2
f d(1
2 ) =
2 L (X;
) then
1
X1
X1
'(x1 ) d1 :
Z
X 1 X 2
f d(1
2 ) =
Z
Z
X2
X1
A
A denotes the smallest -algebra over X , whi
h
ontains all sets A B ,
A 2 A and B 2 A . Dene (A B ) = (A) (B ) and extend to a measure
on A
A .
Here
Remark 10.7 In (a), as in Levi's theorem, we don't need any assumption on f to
hange
the order of integration sin
e fR 0. In (b) f is an arbitrary measurable fun
tion on
X1 X2 , however, the integral X j f j d needs to be nite.
Bibliography
[1 I. Agri
ola and T. Friedri
h, Globale Analysis (in German), Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn,
Brauns
hweig, 2001.
[2 Glen E. Bredon, Topology and geometry, Graduate Texts in Mathemati
s, no. 139,
Springer-Verlag, New York, 1997.
[3 R. Courant, Dierential and integral
al
ulus I{II, Wiley Classi
s Library, John Wiley
& Sons, New York et
., 1988.
[4 J. Dieudonne, Treatise on analysis. Volume I { IX, Pure and Applied Mathemati
s,
A
ademi
Press, Boston, 1993.
[5 J. Elstrodt, Ma- und Integrationstheorie, third ed., Springer, Berlin, 2002.
[6 O. Forster, Analysis 1 { 3 (in German), Vieweg Studium: Grundkurs Mathematik,
Vieweg, Brauns
hweig, 2001.
[7 K. Konigsberger, Analysis 1 (English), Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, New
York, 1990.
[8 S. Lang, Undergraduate Analysis, se
ond ed., Undergraduate texts in mathemati
s,
Springer, New York-Heidelberg, 1989.
[9 J. Marsden and A. Weinstein, Cal
ulus. I, II, III, Undergraduate Texts in Mathemati
s, Springer-Verlag, New York et
., 1985.
[10 P. V. O'Neil, Advan
ed
al
ulus, Collier Ma
millan Publishing Co., London, 1975.
[11 W. Rudin, Real and Complex Analysis, International Student Edition, M
Graw-Hill
Book Co., New York-Toronto, 1966.
[12
[13 M. Spivak, Cal
ulus on manifolds, W. A. Benjamin, New York, Amsterdam, 1965.
[14
308
BIBLIOGRAPHY
[15 C. von Westenholz, Dierential forms in mathemati
al physi
s, se
ond ed., Studies in
Mathemati
s and its Appli
ations, no. 3, North-Holland Publishing Co., AmsterdamNew York, 1981.