Sie sind auf Seite 1von 13

Time Lag: Motifs for a Phenomenology

of the Experience of Time


BERNHARD WALDENFELS
Ruhr-Universitt Bochum
The time lag in question here may be understood in two ways: as a shift in
time itself, and as a corresponding shift in signication. The following consid-
erations begin with a general orientation as to the ordering of time; then they
cross over to specic phenomenal elds in which time unfolds its eVect.
1
1. Logos of Time
The logos of time is to be understood as the way we think time, talk about it,
represent it and present it, and all of this with reference to an experience of
time that like all phenomena is to be brought to utter its own meaning.
2
The oldest discourse on time is found in myow. Chronos is known as a god
who devours his own children, a god older than Zeus. Here time is portrayed
as a power that in coming to be and passing away, in aging, manifests itself as
a deterioration and disintegration of forces. Some of this lives on in poetry:
Make haste Chronos! Out of the rattling trot!in Goethe Chronos is apos-
trophized as coachman and entreated in his distant proximity. In Virginia
Woolf s Mrs. Dalloway it is Big Bens chime that scans the course of the day
within the novel.
3
Or nally Octavio Paz in his Piedra del Sol: mientras el tiempo
cierra su abanico [while time folds its fan shut].
4
The inuences and con-
sequences of time are older than the logos, which responds to the work of time,
seeks to reclaim an order from this work.
107
108 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
The classical ordering of time that has been determining our thinking for cen-
turies develops particular coping strategies that work against times power.
Three fundamental aspects of this may be distinguished.
(1) In the rst place there is the attempt at a certain demythologization. Time
appears no longer as a who or what presided over by a time-sovereign or an
anonymous temporal power; rather time appears as a how, as mode, as schema.
Time dbuts in something or in someone, no longer under its own direction. On
the one hand Aristotle composes the great prelude: he derives a physical time
from cosmic kinesis. On the other hand there is Augustine, who develops a psy-
chic time from the lived time of the soul. This psycho-physical duality reaches
up to the present day. Time is cordoned oV as long as the question What is
X? or Who am I? does not eo ipso carry a temporal or spatial accent. What
emerges in time is not something that temporalizes itself. In modern terms,
identity does not mean in the same breath time identity, in the sense that today
one is accustomed to speaking of place identity. Identity remains timeless in its
very core.
(2) The mode of time is repeatedly subjected to binary schemata of order, such
as outer and inner, fsiw and psyche, material and form.
(3) Time itself is thought as a member of an opposition. The most pregnant oppo-
sitions are those of time and space (following after one another in succession
versus standing out from one another in extension), of time and eternity
(owing vs. standing, temporal ux vs. nunc stans). In this way the force of
time is tamed: one is at the mercy of time as a human being, but not as a think-
ing being.
The classical ordering of time gradually gives way to a radical experience of time
the consequence of which is that the logos turns into a logos of the aesthetic
world.
5
This leads to a transformation of the classical representation of time.
(1) Time is henceforth more than an attribute of things or a way of experienc-
ing the soul; it is also more than the form of intuition for a transcendental sub-
ject. Time is no longer reduced to a mere modality, since it has a decisive part
in the formation, shaping, and realization of something (object), of someone
(subject), and of meaning (orderings). These three moments, still divided
between three worlds by Karl Popper, have their respective temporal ways of
being. Temporality turns out to be a generator of identity. (2) Time no longer falls
under binary schemata; it proves to be diVering in the sense of a holding up, shift,
or postponement. (3) Time frees itself from the opposition to timeless instances;
it becomes entangled in itself in the form of a self-reference that leads to a self-
doubling and self-duplication. Thus Husserl remarks at the beginning of his
time lectures,
6
that the perception of a temporal object has itself temporality,
that perception of duration presupposes duration of perception; and Merleau-
Ponty speaks in his late writings of a temporal vortex.
7
Here emerges with
TIME LAG
109
increasing and varying radicality a phenomenology of time in which time folds
chiasmatically over what it determines: as consciousness of time and time of
consciousness in Husserl; as being and time as well as time and being in
Heidegger; as esh of time and time of the esh in Merleau-Ponty; as time of
the other and alterity of time in Levinas and Derrida; as time of narrative and
narrated time in Ricur. Equally worth mentioning are human-scientic
authors such as L. Binswanger, E. Minkowski, E. Straus or V. von Weizscker
in whose work the pathology of time takes on particular weight. In a broader
sense the attempts of Bergson and Whitehead to think lived time together with
a modern biology or cosmology belong within this sphere as well. Finally we
should point to the fact that the conception of time in classical physics, which
in many ways also has a part to play in the philosophical theories of time, has
itself undergone substantial revisions. For instance, the theory of relativity has
done away with the representation of a temporal receptacle and an absolute
time, and deals with time-spaces, with a dependence upon movement in the
measuring of time. We come upon new forms of time, upon times dependent
on the internal state of a system, upon a time that is an operator and lends
the arrow of time a new signicance.
8
In what follows I shall restrict myself to looking for a way through the eld
of time experience, orienting the search according to two central problems
tightly intertwined with one another. The one problem concerns the self-refer-
entiality already mentioned, which is not only restricted to time but returns
equally in phenomena such as esh, language, or self, and prevents a hierarchic
ordering of the phenomena. The other problem concerns the indirect mode of
access required when something withdraws from precisely those orderings in
which it is conceptually grasped. Here Wittgensteins distinction should be
remembered, his diVerence between saying and showing, which do not coin-
cide; or the late Merleau-Ponty, who establishes with regard to philosophy that
elle fait voir par des motsit shows by words, it shows what does not per-
mit of being directly said.
9
One can hardly better formulate the task of a phe-
nomenology. In the same place Merleau-Ponty places philosophy alongside
literature (as well as politics): no absolutely pure philosophical word is what
this means. Philosophy works in parallel to the arts, which perform (auf fhren)
in colors, sounds, movements and scenes what philosophy demonstrates
(aufweist). This does not signify a simple conation of categories, but rather a
considerable proximity that also nds expression in the phenomenological
analyses of time. It comes across in the following spheres of problems, which
one could ascribe to a kind of minimal art of time.
110 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
2. Time of Speech
Since in philosophy we are thus concerned with making time visible in words,
speech may stand at the beginning.
10
The following considerations do not fol-
low the route of a linguistic turn, which discovers much but also conceals
things of importance. They are not so much about a return to language as a
penetrating into language, and indeed penetrating to the point where language
is more than mere language. As far as the time of speech is concerned, it takes
place at diVerent levels.
At the rst level we are dealing with time as spoken about, which belongs to
what is said. The tested means of a grammar of time belong to linguistic artic-
ulation. This begins with the tenses of the verb, of the =ma, which Aristotle
says co-indicates time.
11
It continues with the adverbs of time, like now, just
(now); today, this year; earlier, later; often, seldom etc., that have since been
formalized in a temporal logic. If factors of time only belonged to the topic of
speech, then speech itself together with all its law-givers and authorswould
remain intact. The logic of time has developed a variety of strategies for detem-
poralization, strategies that in referring to a timeless validity perpetuate classi-
cal ideas of order.
These detemporalization strategies fail when we change over to the level of
saying, where time as spoken about swings back upon itself in the form of time
of speech. More precisely, what is going on here is a doubling of time that corre-
sponds to the doubling of instances of speech in . Benveniste.
12
I promise you
(now) that I will come tomorrow (on May 13). Here two tenses appear: the now
of the promising, and the datable later of the promised. It is not at all the case
that the act of promising appears earlier than the announced keeping of the
promisingthis would only hold for a report speaking about the promising.
The reason why the act of promising does not appear earlier is that the act as
such does not at all happen in time. Rather it opens up a time in which the
speaker is obligated to something or other. One might think of inaugural
events, when legal contracts are closed or constitutions given. The inaugural
event takes place at a zero point, as Husserl calls it,
13
that is not to be found
like just any given point within a system of coordinates. A promise could not
be repeated, a vow not be renewed, if it had passed away like a datable event
occupying a place in a eld of time or on a time line. Certain anniversaries lose
their signicance when all they keep alive is a historical reminiscence. In short,
promising is not part of the promised but rather signies a surplus of saying in
what is said, a surplus said along with what is said without coming up in this.
Of course all this goes not only for acts of promising but also for threats, con-
gratulations, and even for assertions. These too commit the speaker in such a
way that taking them back means more than just a contrary assertion.
TIME LAG
111
We touch upon a further level as soon as we confront saying with an other
saying. This leads to a peculiar time lag. The usual time lag arises when we
change over from one time system to another. At some point we adjust our
watch; and at some point the inner, eshly clock adjusts as well. Yet time lag
in speech says more, namely, that speech is shifted in relation to itself and does
not exactly coincide with itself. We are never entirely at the top of time; rather
we arrive upon the scene a little late, and our speech reverberates against us
like an echo of ourselves. Our speech would only be fully at home with itself if
there were a rst word without before, a last word without an after. Only then
could the word fully collect itself and overcome every dispersal.
Is there a rst word? Jorge Sempruns novel What a Beautiful Sunday,
14
the rst
chapter of which is entitled Zero, begins in the following way: He had the
feeling he had perceived a vague movement. Some sort of crunching of whirled
up snow. Is this how the novel begins? Certain things have already happened
before the narrative starts. Quel beau dimanche! Which Sunday? A Sunday in
Buchenwald. Some sort of crunching? Maybe beneath the wheels of a truck
at the fork in the road in the barracks. And so it proceeds, forwards and back-
wards. A rst word would be one that responds to nothing: not to an idea, not
to a terror, not to an allure . . .
And a last word? At the end of the novel the narrator gets into exchanging
words with a fellow captive whom he calls Jehova. He breaks oV this conver-
sation because he fears an appropriate Bible verse. There must be many
beautiful, appropriate Bible verses on darkness. But I didnt feel like having
something about darkness read to me in Jehovas voice. I just prefer
Giraudoux. . . . I feel like spending the rest of this Sunday with himthis
Sunday, which will be followed by others. So no last word. The last word would
be one that permitted of no further expectation, that had no harassment to fear,
that no one could call into question . . .
In the aporia of rst and last word we observe what Husserl goes through at
the level of primordial impression. The originary impression would be a hori-
zonless atom of sensation. It could only be thought as point in thought, as
ideal limit,
15
because this thinking presupposes that something is experienced
as such, thus in an inceptual repetition. What is only once is not at all (einmal
ist keinmal ). This also holds for horizonless speech. Only the unarticulated cry
remains as limit case, the cry that tears the weave of speech and has no mean-
ing; it at most hints at this meaning in pleasure or pain, in a sound close to
falling silent.
Accordingly, time lag means that speaking begins somewhere else, in the
realm of a pre-language, a pre-predicative, a pre-discursive realm. The hyphen
points to a threshold of experience, not to an unblemished ground of experi-
ence untouched by any language. Language is by no means everything, as some
112 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
would have us think; but this is not because there is something else next to it.
It is rather because it precedes itself and oversteps itself, because in this sense
it has itself a esh and does not just speak about the esh.
3. Time of the Senses
Should there have been an experience of time then time must be in some way
referred to the senses, thus to something that aVects us, that is given to us and
waits for our response. Yet here begin new diYculties.
Can we assume a perceived time that we see, hear and touch, or that we at
least see, hear, touch along with something other? Then we would face the ques-
tion of what we understand by perception, and how far time works its way into
perception itself. If we restrict perception to a passive receiving or registering,
then we only have to deal with physical data, with impressions or objects that
are actually present in perception and accordingly may be reduced to the punc-
tualness of the temporal moment without doing justice to the running oV of
time. The transition to psychic time promises to save us, since the psyche is
able to represent what is not present as well as what is not actual. It does this
by arranging its own lived experiences in such a way that they follow after one
another in succession or hold together in one another at the same time, as
opposed to the standing out from one another of spatial things. With this tran-
sition to a distentio animi, to an intuition-form of the inner sense or to an unex-
tended dure in Augustine, Kant, and Bergson, we get into the oppositions
already mentioned, where inner sense and with it time are privileged over outer
sense and space. This privilege springs from an augmentation of the present.
By collecting itself in itself and returning to itself from its dispersal, spirit
approaches an omnipresence in which time is increasingly done away with.
This privileging of the inner over and against the outer is expressed in the tra-
ditional hierarchic ordering of the arts, which rise up from the nadir of the ne
arts through the art of tone up to a pure art of words. This spiritualization
entails a corresponding despatialization and detemporalization.
A revision that leaves behind the internalization as well as the externaliza-
tion of time takes shape as soon as we proceed from the eshliness of the senses.
Here the alternatives passive givenness and active positing lose their power.
Perception, anchored in a eshly here and now, is carried out as self move-
ment, as kinasthesis. This traditional expression that Husserl takes up does not
mean sensation of movement, but rather sensing that moves itself.
16
In looking,
listening, feeling, tasting, or sniYng, my esh responds to that which comes to
the fore, occurs to me, surprises me and aVects me in the esh. In perception
the world is staged and not simply registered in its details. Time is involved in
this in many ways, already, for example, in the time of the look (des Blicks), in
the glimpse of a moment (Augen-blick), which approximates the time of speech
TIME LAG
113
already mentioned. The look, which receives its motive impulse from some-
where else, precedes itself and comes back to itself in the form of a glimpse
ahead and back (eines Vor- und Rckblicks). In his Phenomenology of Perception
Merleau-Ponty describes in vivid colors the temporality of seeing:
For us the perceptual synthesis is a temporal synthesis, and subjectivity, at
the level of perception, is nothing but temporality, and this is what enables
us to leave to the subject of perception his opacity and historicity. I open my
eyes on to my table, and my consciousness is ooded with colors and con-
fused reections; it is hardly distinguishable from what is oVered to it; it
spreads out, through its accompanying body, into the spectacle which so far
is not a spectacle of anything. Suddenly, I start to focus my eyes on the table
which is not yet there, I begin to look into the distance while there is as yet
no depth, my body centers itself on an object which is still only potential,
and so disposes its sensitive surfaces as to make it a present reality. I can thus
re-assign to its place in the world the something which was impinging upon
me, because I can, by slipping into the future, throw into the immediate past
the worlds rst attack upon my senses, and direct myself towards the deter-
minate object as towards a near future. The act of looking is indivisibly
prospective, since the object is the nal stage of my process of focusing, and
retrospective, since it will present itself as preceding its own appearance, as
the stimulus, the motive or the prime mover of every process since its begin-
ning. The spatial synthesis and the synthesis of the object are based on this
unfolding of time.
17
The temporality of the senses may be illuminated from yet another perspective,
namely by proceeding from the movement form rhythm.
18
Rhythm, in its origi-
nal etymological sense a kind of owing, designates since Plato the ordering of
movement (tjiw tw kinsevw) that gives form and measure to movement.
19
This continues in Aristotle when in the Physics he determines time as number
of movement according to the before and after. The counting in question here
presupposes countable, discrete units, and rhythm fullls just this function of an
articulation of movement. Rhythm accounts for the return of the same, which is
measured out in beats. Were all things to remain the same, to ow into one
another; if nothing stood out in contrast to something else, then there would
be no rhythm. One would always be stepping into the same river, and even
this sameness would have nothing from which it could stand out. In this sense
rhythm takes on an elementary function of supporting order. Rhythm enjoys
particular attention in the sphere of periodically and cyclically returning life
processes, and in the sphere of acoustic art, which as Melos and Rhythmus goes
as far as the sound of words. Gestalt theory ultimately extended forms of move-
ment to all the senses. Such forms are neither purely physical nor purely psy-
chical; the formation of forms is played out between things and esh and
reaches beyond both of these, as in the case of a rhythmically varying motoric
of color vision.
20
Valry concludes from this: It is impossible to think a rhythm.
114 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
He illustrates this claim in an experiment: Hold still and try to represent a
rhythm. Impossible. I knew someone who believed that he could do this and
kept the beat with his eyelids. Or with twitches in the muscles of his mouth.
21
But it goes beyond this straightforward return. The return of the same pre-
sents itself at the same time as return of what is not the same. What is initially deci-
sive in this is that as articulation of times running oV, rhythm produces order
and alters it. If we attend to the genesis of order, rather than grounding our-
selves in an already completed order, then rhythm means not only There is
something that repeats itself ; it also means There is something only in the fact
that it repeats itself. This is how we come to see an order coming to be (entste-
hende) behind the existing (bestehende) order. Something is not identical, but
becomes identical; it becomes identied in the fact that our experience continu-
ally comes back to something as something.
22
Repetition makes same what is not
same. In this sense repetition means an altering repetition, a return as the same
of what is not the same.
23
In contrast to what Plato says,
24
rhythm never rises
to a pure eurythmy, but is instead always interspersed with moments of an
arrhythmia.
Modern music, whichlike modern art in general moves in diVerent ways
along the limits of order, operates not only with syncopies that disrupt the beat
but also with counter-rhythms or overlapping rhythms, which release a het-
erophony. The rhythm of the senses ultimately comes out in language as well,
in fact at the level of a prelanguage that moves just this side of the mean-
ing threshold although it always brushes against this. For something to be able
to return as something, there must always already be something that returns.
Accordingly, language acquisition begins with the presemantic recognizing of
phonic forms and written images. Hearing speech and seeing writing always
extends into speaking and writing, with its meaning projections and validity
claims. The rhythmic at work here leads to an open formation of meaning and
of self that goes through the senses. This sense [Sinn] of the senses always has
a temporal aspect.
4. Time of Forgetting and Remembering
In forgetting and remembering we are immediately met with the powerful
eVectivity of time and not only with its order. Here forgetting gains a priority:
without forgetting, no remembering. Forgetting is an unwieldy phenomenon; it
does not t into the current schemata of meaning and validity. Forgetting con-
cerns us, but it will not be understood as intentional act or rule-governed com-
portment. It has neither a meaning upon which we are intent, nor is it subject
to a rule that is ours to follow; and yet it means more than an erasing of traces
that merely prevents any eVect. Forgetting belongs to all that happens to us,
that runs into us like an accident. It has a peculiar sense of in between. What
TIME LAG
115
is forgotten does not coincide with past facts, which cannot be undone.
Forgetting is not freely at our disposal, and yet it unsettles us. It may only be
described as loss loss of a knowing, a being able to, or feelingor as a dark-
ening, withdrawal. To the extent that it unsettles us, the forgotten is there and
not there; it comes close to what Freud describes as repression.
Yet not every forgetting disconcerts us. One may distinguish diVerent grades
of forgetting to which diVerent levels of past correspond. There is the normal for-
getting of what was once available. This concerns a kind of unlearning in which
learning is undone. What made an impression on us loses its striking charac-
ter. To be distinguished from this is a prior forgetting (Vorvergessen) of that which
was never consciously lived through or even planned. These are things such as
ones own childhood, dreams, states of intoxication and delusion, or the holes
in memory that we swirl around as in a whirlpool from which we can never
fully extricate ourselves. Finally, there is in the background an originary forgetting
(Urvergessen) in which the prior forgetting reaches its outermost limit, as in the
case of birth where, according to Plato, we drink from the river Lethe.
Expressed less mythically, this presents an originary past that was never pre-
sent.
25
This originary forgetting manifests itself as an originary, irrevocable
form of delay that determines our existence through and through and gives it
the temporal index of an apriori perfect.
26
This irrevocable delay repeats itself
in all decisive occurrences whose eVect precedes our registration or interpreta-
tion of them, our coping with them. It repeats itself with particular intensity in
the belated eVect of those traumatic experiences that shackle us to the past.
There is the further question concerning the location of forgetting. Like all
experience, forgetting too takes place right now. It breaks into experience like
an accident, a lapse, as in Plato. Forgetting approximates those things that
occur to us, that strike usthese things in our experience that surprise usin
that it happens to me, befalls me. I come up in forgetting, but in the dative of
giving and taking, not in the nominative of a renowned perpetrator. Forgetting
would not especially unsettle us if the present enclosed us like a mussel. But a
closed present only comes to be through the shielding that in an extreme case
erects a bulwark to protect us from the past breaking in. When, on the other
hand, we assume with Husserl that every present perception crosses over into
retention, this means that when we hold onto something in memory we are
looking for a holding up, a stop, that we cannot nd in the present. Forgetting
does not begin just any time and any place; it begins here and now. We hold
onto in memory what threatens to slip our minds, what we do not have rmly in our
grasp.
27
Because forgetting does not break into a secure enclosure of con-
sciousness from the outside, it occurs as nearly total failure only in the limit
case of fainting or the eVect of shock. The gradual erosion triggered by forget-
ting presents itself as undiVerentiation, as deformation, as loss of relief.
28
Once
again, forgetting points to the peculiarity of the esh. Only he or she who is
116 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
not fully in consciousness can forget. The simultaneity of self-reference and
self-withdrawal that makes up consciousness explains why time eVects, why it
changes us, why we undergo it before we mesh with it. As gardiens du pass
the eshly members are only a vanguard of consciousness; they are not under-
lings under order to carry out their guardian role.
Remembering, just as little as forgetting, does not begin with an act, with, for
instance, an act of observation or with a new programming. Something occurs
to me again in the same way that something occurs to me at all. Remembering
is awakened, not made. In this the foreign comes into play, that which does not
stem from our own initiative. Recollecting, which may be neither forced nor
summoned under order, does not, any more than does forgetting, present itself
as intentionally directed act or rule-governed comportment. Recollecting begins
as taking up again, as putting on again, as reprise, as an nalambnein, as it is
called in the Platonic texts on anamnesis. More recent attempts to replace the
old storage model of memory with constructs and to turn remembering into a
pure observers category
29
miss entirely the experience of time, from which even
the building contractor is not free. The simple reversal: It is not memories
that come from the past but rather the past that results from memories
30
signies no more or less than a philosophy of presence in constructivist cloth-
ing. Reservations emerge equally with regard to the reduction of forgetting to
a not being able to remember, a reduction that equates forgetting with lack-
ing competence and limited capacity. This technical domestication of time does
not even allow for the question of whether something is worthy of remember-
ing, whether it could validate a claim to memory. Neglecting the experience of
time has as consequence that the technology of memory and the moralistic view
of remembering largely run alongside one another, as if remembering were
a mixture of storage capacity, developmental programming and good will. This
renders the penetration of the past, the obsession with something past,
totally harmless.
31
5. Time of the Other
The temporal shifting we have already encountered in our own speech grows
stronger when we consider how proper and foreign speech interpenetrate one
another. Here temporality gains a further dimension. The social character of
time comes to the fore, that which makes us speak of contemporaries, of ances-
tors and descendants. The commemoration of remembering already falls into
this new dimension. It is in this context that Levinas opposes to the synchrony
of meaning a dia-chrony that lifts the classical dia-logue oV the hinges of a unied
logos.
32
Even in classical dialogue, as this is presented to us in all its glory from
Plato to Gadamer, there is denitely a time lag, since the giving and taking of
TIME LAG
117
the word alternate. Yet this lag is only a relative one, a temporary movement
within a continual occurrence of meaning. The here and now is coordinated
and synchronized with respect to one and the same thing [Sache] itself , which
reveals itself in diVerent aspects and perspectives; or it is refuted with respect
to validity claims intended to be tested in argument. The reciprocity of per-
spectives, according to Alfred Schtz; the reversibility of standpoints, according
to Jean Piaget: these insure that proper and foreign voices, proper and foreign
look, forfeit their foreignness within a dialectic of sameness and otherness. This
continues in the classical conception of history as world history, which medi-
ates the proper (Eigenes) and the foreign in a collective work. What counts is the
net yield. A universal-pragmatic formalization of reason changes nothing of the
fact that the foreign demand becomes neutralized.
As opposed to this, diachrony means that between foreign demand and proper
response, between foreign and proper speech there is a gaping hiatus that inter-
rupts the common ux of speech. The dash, which separates demand and
response from one another, may not be turned into a hyphen. The foreign
demand signies an originary going-before that is not to be anticipated from the
present, whereas the proper response appears with an equally originary belated
quality not to be overcome within the present. In this sense the response, which
begins somewhere else, always has something traumatic about it. What is
inscribed within experience, carved into it, does not freely unfold like a dawn-
ing bloom. The entwined incipit of modern novels also conveys something of the
suVering from beginning, from the pain of remembering that in the Socratic
maieutic is compared not in vain to labor pains. The oft-cited pyow myow
means more than the pragmatic building of character through hardship or a
method of trial and error. It means that every learning bears in itself the traces
of an enduring, of something foreign that may not be unlearned.
Synchrony, which amounts to a unied chronology, suYces only as long as
the exchange of thoughts and wills remains within an order. It loses its syn-
thetic power where the limits of order are transgressed. Where something comes
to expression in language that is not previously found in it we run up against some-
thing unexpected. It comes to breeches in time that make our experience of time
fall apart into heterochronies.
33
Time thresholds, which we never leave behind,
enable and require that one not only need time but also give time; that one
even give what one does not already have; that there be something that is not
already on stable ground.
All in all we live temporally, just as we exist in the esh. There is no
timeless or eshless outside, although the occurrence of time itself is inter-
spersed with delays, postponements, with ritardandos of every kind. Time
diVerentiates itself; it compresses itself into the present yet does not culminate
in it. This inner diVerentiation has as a consequence that we nd ourselves here
118 BERNHARD WALDENFELS
and now and at the same time somewhere else and at some other time. This
is where the split continually opens up for other times: not a nunc stans, but a
nunc distans.
Translated by Derrick Calandrella
The Pennsylvania State University
NOTES
1. The following text goes back to a lecture I held on December 17, 1998, at the Universitt
Frankfurt/Main in the context of the graduate college Experience of Time and Aesthetic
Perception. I would like to thank the organizers Hans-Thies Lehmann and Burkhardt
Lindner.
2. Edmund Husserl, Husserliana (The Hague: Martinus NijhoV, 1950 V.), vol. 1, 16, 77. Hereafter
cited as Hua.
3. Here compare the interpretation of the time novel in the second volume of Paul Ricoeurs Time
and Narrative, trans. Kathleen McLaughlin and David Pellauer (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1988).
4. Octavio Paz, Sunstone, The Collected Poems of Octavio Paz 19571987, trans. Eliot Weinberger
(New York: New Directions, 1987), 11.
5. Hua 17: 297.
6. Hua 10: 22.
7. On Merleau-Pontys conception of time compare my Wirbel der Zeit, written with Regula
Giuliani (forthcoming).
8. Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers, Order out of Chaos: Mans New Dialogue with Nature, 1st ed.
(Boulder: New Science Library, 1984).
9. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1968), 266.
10. For more on this theme see chap. 3 of my Vielstimmigkeit der Rede. Studien zur Phnomenologie des
Fremden, vol. 4 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1999).
11. Cf. On Interpretation 3: =ma d stin t prosshmanon xrnon.
12. mile Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistics, trans. Mary Elizabeth Meek (Coral Gables:
University of Miami Press, 1971), 219.
13. Hua 4: 158.
14. Jorge Semprun, What a Beautiful Sunday! trans. Alan Sheridan (San Diego: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, 1982).
15. Hua 10: 40.
16. Erwin Straus, The Primary World of Senses: A Vindication of Sensory Experience, trans. Jacob
Needleman (New York: Free Press of Glencoe, 1963).
17. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith (New York: Humanities
Press, 1962), 239.
18. For more on this, see chap. 3 of my work Sinnesschwellen. Studien zur Phnomenologie des Fremden,
vol. 3 (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1999).
19. Cf. Laws 664e665a.
20. Cf. Kurt Goldstein, The Organism. A Holistic Approach to Biology Derived from Pathological Data in Man
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1963).
TIME LAG
119
21. Paul Valry, Cahiers (Paris: Gallimard, 1973), 1340.
22. Hua 1: 18.
23. On this formulation, which I have chosen in conscious connection to Nietzsche, cf. my Order
in the Twilight, trans. David Parent (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1996), 36.
24. Republic 400 cd.
25. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, 242.
26. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit, 7th ed. ( Tbingen: Max Niemeyer, 1953), 85.
27. Hua 3: 122.
28. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, 197.
29. Foreward to Gedchtnis, ed. Siegfried J. Schmidt (Frankfurt am Main, 1991).
30. Ibid., 34.
31. On the responsive character of forgetting and remembering, which in the following section also
proves extremely relevant, cf. my Antwortregister (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1994), chap.
III, 5.
32. Cf. Emmanuel Levinas, Otherwise than Being or beyond Essence, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Duquesne:
Duquesne University Press, 1998), passim.
33. Husserl already spoke of retention and perception as being diVerently timed [verschiedenzeitig]
(Hua 10: 205).

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen