Sie sind auf Seite 1von 38

Will Dudley sets Hegels Philosophy of Right within a larger systematic

account and innovatively deploys the Logic to interpret it. The author
shows that freedom involves not only the establishment of certain social
and political institutions but also the practice of philosophy itself. n the
second half! Dudley reveals how "iet#sches discussions of decadence!
nobility! and tragedy map onto an analysis of freedom that criti$ues
heteronomous choice and %antian autonomy! and ultimately issues in a
positive conception of liberation. n a provocative conclusion! Hegel and
"iet#sche are portrayed as complementary! emphasi#ing different aspects
of freedom and modes of philosophical thought! but concurring in the view
that freedom is in part attained through philosophical thin&ing. n boldly
bringing Hegel and "iet#sche together into a conversation! something that
is rarely attempted! Dudley has developed a set of original interpretations
that will be of considerable importance to students of these philosophers!
and more generally to political theorists and historians of ideas.
'("T)"T* +c&nowledgments List of Te,ts! Translations! and
+bbreviations ntroduction- .reedom and Philosophy /. The *ignificance of
.reedom- .rom Politics to Philosophy
0. 'ompeting 'onceptions of .reedom Liberal .reedom %antian .reedom
1. Hegel and "iet#sche
2. 3oals and *tructure of the 4oo& page ,iii ,v / / 1 1 2 5 6 part i.
freedom in and through hegels philosophy / The Place of .reedom in
Hegels Philosophy /. The Parts of Hegels *ystem- Logic! "ature! *pirit
0. The Logical 'oncept of .reedom
1. The Philosophy of *pirit as an +ccount of .reedom
4. Structure and Method of Part 1
The .reedom of Willing- Hegels Philosophy of Right
/. The Logical 'oncept of 7udgment 0. The nitial 'onception of the Will
and ts Development
1. The 8oral 'onception of the Will 2. The ncomplete .reedom of the
8oral Will
5. The Institutions of Ethical Freedom: Family, Ciil Society,
State Freedom !eyond "illin#: From the Philoso$hy of %i#ht
to &!solute S$irit
/. The Place of Willing in the Philosophy of *pirit 0. The Logical 'oncept of
Purposiveness i,. The ncomplete .reedom of Willing 2. .rom Willing to
+rt! Religion! and Philosophy
4 Freedom throu#h 'e#el(s Philoso$hy
/. +rt! Religion! and Philosophy- (vercoming the *ub9ectivity of Willing 0.
Philosophy as 'onceptual *ystemati#ation 1. .reedom through *ystematic
Philosophy 2. )pilogue- Reconciliation! Resignation! Theory and Practice
part ii. freedom in and through nietzsches philosophy
5 The Place of Freedom in )iet*sche(s Philoso$hy
/. "iet#sches Lac& of *ystem 0. "iet#sches :nsystematic +ccount of
.reedom The .reedom of Willing- Decadence and "obility
/. The Decadent .ailures to Will .reely- Two Types of *ic&ness
Disgregation- The :nfreedom of "ot Willing
The Morality of Selflessness: The Incom$lete Freedom of
"illin# )othin#
The 'ontagious 'ircle of Decadence
0. .rom Decadence to "obility- 'onvalescence Destruction of the 8oral
Will
The +an#ers of +estruction )o!le 'ealth: The Esta!lishment
of a Free "ill Freedom !eyond "illin#: From )o!ility to
Tra#edy
/. The ncomplete .reedom of "obility Destruction of the "oble Will-
Healthy Reinfection
The Dangers of Destruction Redu, 4eyond "obility and Decadence- The
)ndless 'ycle of *ic&ness and 'onvalescence
0. Tragic 3reat Health +ffirmation out of (verfullness +mor .ati and
)ternal Return The 3lad Tidings of Worldly *elf;Redemption
.reedom through "iet#sches Philosophy /. The Language of Tragedy
as a 'ondition of .reedom 0. Philosophy as a *ource of Tragic
)3 < =ol. />! Hegels Philosophy of 8ind!
)L < =ol. 6! The )ncyclopaedia Logic! tr. T. .. 3eraets! W. +. *uchting! and
H. *. Harris ?ndianapolis! nd.- Hac&ett! /@@/A.
)" < =ol. @! Hegels Philosophy of "ature! tr. +. =. 8iller ?(,ford-
'larendon! /@5>A.
3P < =ols. /6B0>! Lectures on the History of Philosophy! tr. ). *. Haldane
and .rances H. *imson! vols. /B1 ?+tlantic Highlands! ".7.- Humanities
Press! /@52A.
P3 < =ol. /0! ntroduction to the Philosophy of History! tr. Leo Rauch
?ndianapolis! nd.- Hac&ett! /@66A.
Ph3 < =ol. 1! Hegels Phenomenology of *pirit! tr. +. =. 8iller ?(,ford-
(,ford :niversity Press! /@55A.
PR < =ol. 5! )lements of the Philosophy of Right! ed. +llen W. Wood! tr. H.
4. "isbet ?'ambridge- 'ambridge :niversity Press! /@@/A.
R < =ol. /C! Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion! tr. ). 4. *peirs and 7.
4urdon *anderson! vol. / ?of 1A ?+tlantic Highlands! ". 7.- Humanities
Press! /@52A. WL ?vols. / and 0A < =ols. D and C! Hegels *cience of Logic!
tr. +. =. 8iller ?+tlantic! Highlands! ".7.- Humanities Press! /@C@
"TR(D:'T("- .R))D(8 +"D PHL(*(PHE "o idea is so generally
recogni#ed as indefinite! ambiguous! and open to the greatest
misconceptions ?to which therefore it actually falls a victimA as the idea of
freedom - none in common currency with so little appreciation of its
meaning. Hegel/ /. The *ignificance of .reedom- .rom Politics to
Philosophy Hegels remar& is as true today as it was /5> years ago-
freedom! one of our most common and powerful concepts! is used ?and
misusedA with e,traordinarily little appreciation of its significance. Worse!
Hegel is wrong to say that freedoms openness to misconception is
Fgenerally recogni#ed.G "ot only is freedom poorly understood! but we are
falsely confident that we do understand it. This doubly unfortunate
condition dissuades people from underta&ing needed investigations into
the meaning of freedom. *uch investigations are needed because! across
much of the world! the concept of freedom plays an important role in the
organi#ation of peoples lives. People strongly desire freedom! and
therefore support governments! programs! policies! and candidates that
they perceive to advance its cause. 4ut what people perceive to advance
the cause of freedom depends upon what they understand freedom to be.
+nd thus what people understand freedom to be! even if their
understanding is not e,plicitly articulated! matters a great deal to the way
they live. +s Robert Pippin has put it- 8odern agents can be said to be by
and large committed to the right! truly authoritative modern norm!
freedom! and so an e$ual entitlement to a free life! but suffer from the
indeterminacy that the mere notion of freedom leaves us with. ?+s the
twentieth century has made clear! libertarian! welfarist! socialist and
totalitarian pro9ects all claim a commitment to the supreme principle of
freedom.A0 /
0 ntroduction- freedom and philosophy
Philosophers who thin& about freedom therefore have an opportunity to
ma&e a contribution not only to! but also beyond! their discipline. 8ost of
the time! the analysis of abstract concepts is far removed from the
concerns of anyone but professional academics. With freedom it is
otherwise. 4ecause developments in the understanding of the concept of
freedom have an impact not only on the discipline of philosophy! but also
on the ways in which individuals and communities structure their lives!
freedom is a topic on which philosophers may do professionally
respectable wor& while also entertaining the hope that their labor may be
of some relevance to the wider world. f philosophers thin& about the
meaning of freedom! and if such thin&ing improves our understanding of
the conditions of our social and political liberation! then we all have a
better chance of living more freely. (f course! philosophers do not have a
monopoly on thin&ing about freedom. .reedom is at issue across the
humanities and the social sciences. To ta&e but two preeminent e,amples
from recent scholarship- the sociologist (rlando Patterson ?in his two;
volume study! .reedom in the 8a&ing of Western 'ulture and .reedom in
the 8odern WorldA and the historian )ric .oner ?in The *tory of +merican
.reedomA have both e,plored the importance of the concept of freedom in
the lives of nonacademics.1 4ut whereas such sociological and historical
studies tend to focus on how freedom has in fact been understood! and on
how such understandings have in fact shaped the world! a distinctly
philosophical investigation must determine how freedom ought to be
understood! and how the world must be shaped if freedom is to be
reali#ed in it. The concept of freedom is thus one of the most important
points of intersection between the traditional branches of theoretical and
practical philosophy. .reedom is of theoretical interest because we can
wonder what freedom is! and whether or not we are capable of being free.
+nd it is of practical interest because! given that we are capable of being
free! and that being free is desirable! we can wonder how to live in such a
way that this capability is most fully reali#ed. f philosophers thin& about
the meaning of freedom! however! they will discover an even deeper
connection between freedom and philosophy. Thin&ing about freedom
reveals that its conditions of reali#ation include not only certain social and
political developments but also the practice of philosophy itself. n other
words! philosophy is directly as well as indirectly liberating- philosophy
contributes indirectly to freedom by articulating the social and political
conditions of its reali#ationH but philosophy also contributes directly to
freedom because freedom is not only something about which philosophers
thin&! but also something that is produced through philosophical thin&ing.
introduction- freedom and philosophy
1 0. 'ompeting 'onceptions of .reedom The claim that philosophy is a
liberating activity is li&ely to be met with s&epticism! if not outright
derision. (ne of my main goals in this boo&! therefore! is to e,plain and
defend it. n order to do so! will have to argue that freedom ought to be
understood or conceived in a certain way! and that other conceptions of
freedom are deficient by comparison. 8a&ing such an argument re$uires a
standard by which to 9udge competing conceptions of freedom. The
standard will use is that of comprehensiveness. (ne conception of
freedom ?+A is more comprehensive than another ?4A if! and only if! two
criteria are met- first! + must include and e,pand upon the freedoms
included in 4H and second! the newfound freedoms included in + must
rectify a specific limitation or dependence from which the supposedly free
sub9ect can be shown to suffer in 4! and thus serve as the condition of the
freedoms included in 4! without which the latter would prove to be
illusory. n moving from one conception of freedom to another that is
more comprehensive! nothing is lost and something is gained. "othing is
lost because the more comprehensive conception retains the freedoms
included in the less comprehensive conception. *omething is gained
because the more comprehensive conception e,pands and improves upon
the less comprehensive conception by recogni#ing that the freedoms
included in the latter are necessary but not sufficient conditions of
freedom. We therefore ought to understand freedom as comprehensively
as we can. t is my contention that we are able to do so by drawing on
and bringing together the wor& of Hegel and "iet#sche. The
interpretations of their wor& that form the bul& of this boo& will show that
freedom! most comprehensively understood! re$uires not only the
development of certain social and political structures! but also the activity
of philosophy itself. n preparation for these interpretations! want to
consider very briefly the two most important conceptions of freedom on
which Hegel and "iet#sche build! but which they also critici#e for being
insufficiently comprehensive. The first and less comprehensive of these
two is that of liberalism. The second! which is more comprehensive than
that of liberalism but still less comprehensive than those of Hegel and
"iet#sche! is that of %ant.2 liberal freedom + free;man is he! that in those
things! which by his strength and wit he is able to do! is not hindered to
do what he has a will to. HobbesD
2 introduction- freedom and philosophy Liberalism understands freedom
as the ability of a person to do what she chooses to do! with as few
e,ternal impediments as possible. *uch freedom has come to be called
FnegativeG liberty- it is freedom from the interference of others! a lac& of
e,ternal constraint.C "egative liberty is represented in the common
e,pression! Ffree as a bird.G +nimals are ta&en to en9oy an enviable
degree of negative liberty because they are unconstrained by the social
ties! conventions! and laws to which humans are sub9ect. +mong animals!
birds represent the paradigm of negative liberation because they can fly!
and so are less constrained by geography and even gravity than other
animals. Thus animals in general! and birds in particular! are thought to be
free in this sense because they can do what they choose to do! with fewer
constraints than humans e,perience. The liberal conception of freedom is
remar&ably simple and! not coincidentally! remar&ably powerful. t is li&ely
the response most people would give if as&ed for a definition of freedom.
+nd! therefore! it has enormous political significance. This significance was
recently demonstrated in +merican politics by the dramatic ascent of the
Republican Party to its first congressional ma9ority in nearly half a century!
a development that was e,plicitly billed by its leaders and proponents as
Fthe freedom revolution.G5 ntellectually! this revolution turned on two
ideas that are at the core of liberalism- first! that government e,ists to
secure the freedom of its peopleH and second! that freedom consists of
individuals ability to act on their choices with a minimum of e,ternal
constraint. These ideas were con9oined with a belief that the government
of the :nited *tates! by e,panding the public sphere to encompass
matters that should have been left to private choice! had itself become a
hindrance to! rather than the protector of! the freedom of its citi#ens.
3iven this belief! and their commitment to and particular understanding of
freedom! Republican leaders drew the logical conclusion that the
government of the :nited *tates should be scaled bac& B its budget cut
and its programs reduced B and then redirected to what they understood
to be its core functions- the protection of freedom from international
threats through the provision of a national defense! and the protection of
freedom from domestic threats through the provision of police and
prisons. Running on this platform! the Republican Party en9oyed a
spectacular electoral triumph in /@@2! one that illustrates the importance
of freedom to voters! the connection between a theoretical conception of
freedom and a practical political program! and the intuitive appeal of the
liberal conception of freedom. &antian freedom Will is a &ind of causality of
living beings insofar as they are rational! and freedom would be that
property of such causality that it can be efficient introduction- freedom
and philosophy independently of alien causes determining it . . . What!
then! can freedom of the will be other than autonomy! that is! the wills
property of being a law to itself I . . . Hence a free will and a will under
moral laws are one and the same. %ant6 D %ant critici#es liberalism on the
ground that the ability to act on ones choices with minimal e,ternal
constraint is a necessary but not a sufficient condition of freedom.
.reedom! %ant argues! re$uires not only that individuals be allowed to act
in accordance with their choices ?which is all that liberalisms
understanding of freedom involvesA! but also that they be genuinely
responsible for those choices themselves. +nd the capacity for such
responsibility re$uires that individuals be endowed with free will- at least
some choices must be determined not by causes e,ternal to the will
?which include! for %ant! an individuals own desiresA! but rather by the
wills respect for the universal moral law that it gives to itself. n short!
whereas liberalism understands freedom as the persons unfettered ability
to do what she chooses! %ant insists that freedom must be understood as
the wills ability to determine autonomously what the person chooses to
do. (n %ants view! then! animals are not free at all. +nimals! and most
especially birds! may well e,perience fewer constraints on the e,ecution of
their chosen actions than humans do. 4ut to call their actions Fchosen!G
%ant argues! is seriously misleading. +nimals lac& rationality! and
conse$uently lac& autonomy. The causes of all of their actions are e,ternal
to them! originating not in choices determined by autonomous willing but
rather in heteronomous instincts. There is nothing for humans to envy!
therefore! in the negative liberty en9oyed by animals! for without rational
and autonomous willing! such negative liberty fails to be freedom. %ants
view might seem to have several obvious disadvantages in comparison to
that of liberalism. .irst! it is notoriously complicated- the liberal
understanding of freedom can be presented in a few pages! but a good
e,plication of %antian freedom re$uires a boo&;length study.@ *econd! it
confounds common sense- liberal freedom involves doing what one
chooses! but %antian freedom involves sub9ecting oneself to moral laws
even in the absence of any desire to do so! and thus doing what is
re$uired simply because it is re$uired. To ordinary ears this sounds not
li&e freedom! but rather its opposite. Third! it is metaphysical- the sub9ect
of liberal freedom is the person! but the sub9ect of %antian freedom is the
will! a mysterious &ind of noumenal causality that can never be
e,perienced but that must be effective if moral agency is to be possible./>
.ourth! and finally! the lin& between this metaphysical freedom of the will
and the social and political freedom of the person is deeply problematic. n
particular! for %ant a rational agents freedom! since it resides in the
noumenal will! is independent of the agents physical and C introduction-
freedom and philosophy political situationH though he would grant that
starvation or slavery ma&es it harder to ignore heteronomous motives!
there is still no phenomenal situation that a noumenally free agent is not
obligated! and therefore able! to overcome. The most %ant might say ?and
not without difficultyA is that some political systems and cultures are more
conducive than others to their citi#ens being able to ignore phenomenal
motivesH but social and political arrangements can never be essential to
human freedom for him.
"onetheless! the %antian conception of freedom is superior to that of
liberalism! and for the reason %ant himself provides- one may meet the
liberal standard and yet fail to be free. +lthough independence from
constraint or interference is an indispensable element of freedom! upon
reflection it is shown to be incomplete- may! li&e an animal! be free to do
what choose while it is still the case that my choices! and so my actions!
are not truly my own. may choose to smo&e because am addicted!
may choose to attend college because have been raised in a particular
way! or may choose to eat because am hungry. n each of these cases!
even if my ability to act is unconstrained! my FchoiceG is driven by factors
over which have little or no control! and therefore remain dependent in
a significant sense. %ant thus shows that the acting and choosing of
persons is truly free only if such actions and choices are determined by
autonomous willing. n other words! the %antian conception of freedom is
more comprehensive than the liberal conception.
.irst! %antian freedom includes liberal freedom! because the a#ent
,hose choices are determined !y autonomous ,illin# is not considered
free unless it is also the case that his attem$ts to act on those choices
are su!-ect to minimal e.ternal constraint.
*econd! the %antian conception e,pands upon that of liberalism by
providing for freedom of the will! which the liberal conception does not
include. +nd
Third! such freedom of the will is the condition of genuine freedom
of choice- even if the li!eral su!-ect is free to act u$on her choices
,ithout constraint, her choosin# itself remains e.ternally determined, a
limitation that is rectified only if she is ca$a!le of autonomous ,illin#.
Thus nothing is lost and something is gained in moving from conceiving of
freedom as the persons unfettered action to conceiving of freedom as the
wills autonomy or self;determination. "othing is lost because the idea
that freedom re$uires negative liberty is preserved. 4ut something is
gained because the conception of freedom as the autonomy of the will
recogni#es and responds to the fact that negative liberty is a necessary
but not a sufficient condition of freedom. .reedom re$uires autonomous
willing and unconstrained actingH the latter fails to be free without the
former! and both are contained in the %antian conception.
1. Hegel and "iet#sche +lthough the %antian conception of freedom
is more comprehensive than that of liberalism! it is still not comprehensive
enough. n the same way that reflection upon freedom of action reveals its
limitations and its reliance on freedom of the will! reflection upon freedom
of the will shows that it too is limited and depends upon yet another &ind
of freedom. *uch reflection! and the development of a sufficiently
comprehensive conception of freedom that rectifies the limitations of
willing! are the wor& of this boo&. 8ore accurately! the wor& of this boo& is
to e,amine the reflections of Hegel and "iet#sche upon freedom of the
will! and to show that they independently produce complementary results!
which can be brought together to yield a conception of freedom more
comprehensive than that of %ant.
2 Hegel and "iet#sche!
will argue! both adopt %ants strategic move against liberalism!
whereby he shows that its particular understanding of freedom depends
upon a further &ind of freedom for which it is unable to account. 4ut they
then turn this move against %ant himself. n the same way that %ant
shows that acting persons are truly free only if their choices are
determined by a free will! Hegel and "iet#sche show that willing can be
truly free only in virtue of an activity other than itself. That is! although
self;determination of the will is a more comprehensive conception of
freedom than unfettered action! it rests on yet another &ind of freedom!
without which willing fails to be genuinely self;determining. t is this
conclusion that produces the deep connection between freedom and
philosophy! for the liberating activity that Hegel and "iet#sche identify as
the condition of free willing is the practice of philosophy itself. Thus Hegel
and "iet#sche ultimately show us not only that freedom is a central topic
of consideration in philosophy! but also that the most comprehensive
freedom is achieved through philosophical practice. Philoso$hy is
li!eratin# in / two distinct senses.
First! it is indirectly li!eratin# because it is !y means of $hiloso$hy
that ,e are a!le to determine ,hat it is to !e free! and thus to
determine the conditions of liin# freely.
n other words! philosophical thin&ing is a condition of genuinely
free willing! because freedom cannot be willed in the absence of a
philosophical determination of what freedom isH philosophy yields
theoretical results that must be applied practically in e,tra;philosophical
spheres! the social and political spheres in which we live and act.
Second! $hiloso$hy is also directly li!eratin#, !ecause one of the
theoretical results it yields is the idea that an im$ortant $art of !ein#
free is liin# $hiloso$hically. n other words! it is not only the social and
political applications of philosophys theoretical results that are liberating!
but the practice of philosophy itself.
This much! will argue! 'e#el and )iet*sche a#ree u$on.
4ut they also disa#ree in several important respects. .irst!
although they share the view that %antian autonomy is not a sufficiently
comprehensive conception of freedom! their reflections e,pose
0limit ,ill1 different limitations to ,hich ,illin# is su!-ect.
different ways in which the %antian conception of freedom must be
modified and enlarged
*econd! because they e,pose different limitations of willing! Hegel
and "iet#sche identify different ways in which the %antian conception of
freedom must be modified and enlarged.
J$hiloso$hical practice! inK Third and finally! although these
modifications and enlargements result! in both cases! in an understanding
that freedom involves philosophy! Hegel and "iet#sche do not understand
philosophical practice in the same way! and so have different
understandings of the ways in which this practice is liberating.
;K8y conclusion will be that the different responses of Hegel and
"iet#sche to %ant prove to be complementary. Their central point of
agreement B that %antian autonomy is an insufficiently comprehensive
conception of freedom B teaches us that freedom involves not only acting
and willing! but also practicing philosophy. 4ut the different ways in which
they arrive at this result! and the different interpretations that they give to
it! teach us that our conception of freedom as philosophical practice must
be still more comprehensive than that provided by either Hegel or
"iet#sche alone. We need a theoretical understanding of freedom that
incorporates the insights of both Hegel and "iet#sche into what the
activity of philosophy involves! and a philosophical practice that
incorporates the complementary models of philosophical activity that the
te,ts of Hegel and "iet#sche e,emplify.
2. 3oals and *tructure of the 4oo& With this boo& hope to ma&e a
contribution both to the pro9ect of understanding freedom! and to the
pro9ect of understanding the te,ts of Hegel and "iet#sche. f am right!
the two tas&s are interrelated- our understanding of Hegel and "iet#sche
is helpfully guided by attending to their attention to the problem of
freedom! and our understanding of freedom is furthered by the insights
gained from that e,egetical wor&. To the e,tent that am successful! this
boo& should contribute to philosophical scholarship in several ways. .irst
and foremost! it should draw attention to the fact that a comprehensive
treatment of the problem of freedom cannot be provided by liberal political
theory or by %antian moral philosophy. nstead! hope to show! the
freedoms these discourses treat are dependent upon the more
comprehensive freedom of philosophical thin&ing. The primary
conse$uence of this is that FpracticalG discussions of politics and morality
must be connected to FtheoreticalG wor& on the nature of thought.
*econd! since this more comprehensive conception of freedom and my
conclusions about its conse$uences will be produced by bringing Hegel
introduction- freedom and philosophy @ and "iet#sche together! this boo&
should also contribute to the history of philosophy. +lthough interest in
both Hegel and "iet#sche continues to increase in the )nglish;spea&ing
world! there is still relatively little wor& that relates the two./1 Third! my
interpretation of Hegels conception of freedom is importantly different
from other treatments of the topic. do not confine myself to the
Philosophy of Right! but instead argue that Hegels account of ob9ective
spirit needs to be read within the conte,t of his philosophy of spirit as a
whole B in particular! we must understand the limitations to the freedom
of willing that Hegel identifies! and the role that he envisions for art!
religion! and philosophy in overcoming them./2 8oreover! in reading the
Philosophy of Right and the other parts of the philosophy of spirit ma&e
use of the Logic! and try to show how the introduction of logical
considerations leads to an improved understanding of Hegels conception
of freedom./D .ourth and finally! my interpretation of "iet#sche as
continuing the efforts of %ant and Hegel to determine the conditions of
freedom brings him into direct engagement with 3erman dealism. argue
that "iet#sches discussions of decadence! nobility! and tragedy can be
mapped onto an analysis of the conditions of freedom that offers criti$ues
of both heteronomous choice and %antian autonomy! and that ultimately
issues in a positive conception of liberation. The structure of the boo& has
been determined by its goals. .ollowing this introduction! the body of the
wor& is divided into two parts! the first devoted to an interpretation of
Hegel! the second to an interpretation of "iet#sche. These interpretations
are followed by a conclusion! in which attempt to show how the insights
of the two parts can and must be thought together. The structures of the
two parts are $uite similar. )ach is composed of four chapters. The
opening chapters of both Part and Part locate the concept of freedom
in the te,ts of Hegel and "iet#sche! respectively! and present my
approach to reading those te,ts. Hegels wor&s! of course! comprise a
system! so 'hapter / identifies the places where freedom appears in that
system! and e,plains both how those occurrences relate to each other!
and how their systematic interrelation bears on my interpretation of
them./C "iet#sches wor&s! of course! are unsystematic! so 'hapter D ?the
opening chapter of Part A e,plains both how have reconstructed an
account of freedom from them! and how their lac& of systematicity bears
on that account. The second chapters of both parts are concerned with
freedom of the will- 'hapter 0 presents Hegels analysisH 'hapter C
presents "iet#sches. 4oth of these analyses produce positive results by
negative means- they determine the conditions of freedom of the will by
identifying the limitations of various types of willing that fail to achieve it.
n Hegel! this /> introduction- freedom and philosophy analysis ta&es the
shape of a criti$ue of what he calls the moral will! and results in the
conclusion that a truly free will is an ethical one! one belonging to a citi#en
of a rational political state. n "iet#sche! the sub9ect of criti$ue is what he
calls the decadent will! and the conclusion drawn is that the possessor of a
free will is one who is a member of a noble community. Whereas the
second chapters of the two parts determine the conditions of freedom of
the will by identifying the limitations that incompletely free types of willing
cannot overcome! the third chapters determine the limits to which even a
free will is sub9ect. This negative wor& again provides positive rewards!
this time in the form of a determination of the re$uirements of freedom
that willing cannot meet. 'hapter 1! which presents Hegels analysis!
demonstrates that although ethical citi#enship in a rational state is the
most complete freedom that willing can provide! this political activity has
limitations that only the activities Hegel discusses in absolute spirit B art!
religion! and philosophy B can overcome. 'hapter 5! which presents
"iet#sches analysis of the limits of free willing! demonstrates that
freedom re$uires the transformation of noble individuals and communities
into what he calls tragic ones! in which liberation is increased by forsa&ing
noble autonomy in favor of an openness to being affected by that which is
e,ternal and alien. The concluding chapters of Parts and e,amine the
roles that philosophy! as Hegel and "iet#sche understand and practice it!
has to play in overcoming the limitations of willing and leading us toward
the most comprehensive possible freedom. 'hapter 2 presents Hegels
understanding of philosophy as conceptual systemati#ation! illuminates it
by reflecting on the systematic conceptual development that we have seen
Hegel perform in 'hapters 0 and 1! and considers the senses in which this
systematic practice may be said to be liberating. 'hapter 6 presents
"iet#sches understanding of philosophy as the genealogical destabili#ation
and transformation of established conceptual systems! illuminates it by
reflecting on the philosophical genealogy that we have seen "iet#sche
perform in 'hapters C and 5! and considers the senses in which this
genealogical practice may be said to be liberating. These concluding
chapters thus attend not only to the differences between Hegels and
"iet#sches understandings of philosophy! but also to the differences
between the ways in which their own philosophical practices e,emplify
these understandings. 4ecause what Hegel and "iet#sche say is that the
practice of philosophy is liberating! how each of them practices philosophy
is revealing of what they understand freedom to be. n other words! the
different philosophical styles of Hegel and "iet#sche amount to differences
of philosophical substance as well! and an e,plication of their substantive
views cannot ignore the styles in which those views are e,pressed./5
introduction- freedom and philosophy // The stylistic differences between
Hegel and "iet#sche bear not only on the substance of the $uestion of
freedom! but also on the styles in which the two parts of this boo& have
been composed. +lthough my discussions of Hegel and "iet#sche are
structured $uite similarly! they are noticeably different in style. These
differences are mandated by the e,egetical goal of producing ade$uate
interpretations of both Hegel and "iet#sche. 3iven that Hegel and
"iet#sche differ so mar&edly in style! and given that these differences are
not merely stylistic! there is no single interpretive style ade$uate to the
wor& of both thin&ers. Rather than force one style onto both
interpretations! then! have tried instead to find for each interpretation
the style best suited to it. +s a result! my interpretation of Hegel is
recogni#ably Hegelian! with respect to both its conceptual vocabulary and
its internal organi#ation and subdivision. 4y contrast! my interpretation of
"iet#sche is! if not recogni#ably "iet#schean ?for such a style is not
particularly well suited to the &ind of careful e,egesis and analysis that
aim to produceA! at least not Hegelian. have provided it with an
organi#ation that is intended to be faithful to "iet#sches te,ts and
vocabulary while also illuminating the $uestion of freedom! which is one of
the things thin& those te,ts and that vocabulary are best able to do. The
boo&s conclusion brings together the complementary results of Parts
and to produce a conception of freedom that is more comprehensive
than either Hegel or "iet#sche! when read without reference to the other!
is able to provide. This conception! li&e those of Hegel and "iet#sche!
retains the understanding that freedom involves free willing and
unfettered acting! but recogni#es that the possibility of both of these
activities ultimately depends upon the practice of philosophy. This
liberating practice is now understood! however! to encompass both
Hegelian conceptual systemati#ation and "iet#schean genealogical
destabili#ation of established conceptual systems. The conclusion! and the
boo&! ends by suggesting briefly how the liberation afforded by such
philosophical practices relates bac& to the liberation of the social and
political sphere with which our interest in freedom begins. .R))D(8 "
+"D THR(:3H H)3)L* PHL(*(PHE / TH) PL+') (. .R))D(8 "
H)3)L* PHL(*(PHE Hegel thin&s that there is nothing more important
for us to understand! and nothing that we understand more poorly! than
freedom. n fact! his whole philosophical system! in all its incredible
breadth and detail! can be understood as a single e,tended demonstration
of the importance and meaning of freedom. 8oreover! Hegels philosophy
is not only about freedom! but also claims to be productive of it- in the
course of his philosophical investigation of what it means to be free! Hegel
arrives at the view that freedom depends upon the practice of philosophy.
:nderstanding this view! which is the central aim of Part of this boo&!
re$uires us to e,amine what Hegel has to say about freedom! philosophy!
and their interconnection. This chapter prepares for that e,amination by
locating freedom within Hegels system. *ection / provides a brief
overview of the three main parts of Hegels system- logic! the philosophy
of nature! and the philosophy of spirit. *ection 0 e,plicates the concept of
freedom developed in the Logic. *ection 1 then draws on that logical
concept to e,plain why the entirety of the philosophy of spirit should be
understood as an account of freedom. t also briefly discusses the parts of
the philosophy of spirit! and the place of the Philosophy of Right within it.
*ection 2 concludes the chapter with some remar&s on the structure and
method of the rest of Part ! which interprets Hegels account of freedom!
both within and beyond the Philosophy of Right! in order ultimately to
understand why and how Hegel considers the practice of philosophy to be
liberating. /. The Parts of Hegels *ystem- Logic! "ature! *pirit .reedom
ma&es its first appearance in Hegels philosophy before his system proper
even begins- the Phenomenology of *pirit! which serves as an introduction
to the system! is an account of the elevation of consciousness to a
standpoint that Hegel characteri#es as free! the standpoint of the
speculative philosopher. The speculative philosopher engages in /D /C part
i- hegels philosophy conceptual thin&ing! and Hegel claims that in virtue
of such thin&ing she is free./ The attainment of the standpoint of the
speculative philosopher mar&s the transition from the introduction to the
system properH the Phenomenology prepares the way for the free
conceptual thin&ing that transpires in the logic! the philosophy of nature!
and the philosophy of spirit. These three main parts of Hegels system are
distinguished from each other by the &ind of thing they endeavor to thin&
or comprehend. Logic see&s the conceptual comprehension of thought
itself- it studies the pure concepts with which thin&ing beings thin&.0 n
contrast to logic! the philosophies of nature and spirit see& the conceptual
comprehension of beings that have an e,istence e,ternal to thought! a
real e,istence in space and time. Together they thus comprise what Hegel
calls Realphilosophie. The philosophy of nature attempts to comprehend
those beings that can 9ustifiably be called natural! and the philosophy of
spirit attempts to comprehend those beings that can 9ustifiably be called
spiritual. .reedom not only describes the condition of the speculative
philosopher! but is also one of the concepts that she comes to thin& as she
moves through philosophy. .reedom first arises in the Logic! where it
mar&s the important transition from the logic of essence to the logic of the
concept.1 This logical concept of freedom is then assumed by the
speculative philosopher throughout the Realphilosophie! in the course of
her attempts to comprehend natural and spiritual beings. n virtue of the
very meanings of FnatureG and Ffreedom!G natural beings prove to be
those that are incapable of being freeH the purview of the philosophy of
nature is limited to that which Fe,hibits no freedom in its e,istence! but
only necessity and contingency.G2 +nd in virtue of FspiritG being defined as
that which is not merely natural! spiritual beings and free beings then
prove to be one and the sameH the philosophy of spirit proclaims at its
outset that Fthe essential . . . feature of spirit is freedom.GD .reedom thus
en9oys e,traordinary prominence in Hegels system- it is the condition
attained by the speculative philosopher at the end of the PhenomenologyH
it is one of the crucial concepts that such a philosopher thin&s in the
Logic H it defines the philosophy of nature! as that which is conceptually
e,cluded from itH and it defines the philosophy of spirit! as that which it is
concerned to comprehend. 4ut identifying the prominence of freedom in
Hegels system is not the same thing as understanding it. To do so! we
have to turn to the Logic! which provides the concept of freedom that is
assumed throughout the Realphilosophie. The Logic is relevant to the
philosophy of spirit ?and to the philosophy of natureA because Hegel
understands the concepts it studies to be the conditions of all thin&ing
whatsoever- we cannot help using them whenever we thin& about
anything at all. This means that Hegels attempt to thin& about or
conceptually comprehend spiritual beings in the place of freedom in
hegels philosophy /5 the philosophy of spirit employs concepts developed
in his Logic. n particular! Hegels attempt to comprehend the freedom of
spiritual beings employs the concept of freedom developed in the Logic.
*o to understand his account of what it is to be a free being with a real
e,istence B that is! a spiritual being B we must first understand his
account! found in the Logic! of what it is to be free simpliciter. +lthough
this discussion may seem abstract and difficult to readers unfamiliar with
Hegels Logic! it is indispensable to Hegels entire account of freedom! and
so to my entire interpretation of that account! and therefore cannot be
avoided. have endeavored! however! to ma&e it as brief and clear as
possible! and to provide e,amples that illuminate the conceptual
distinctions at issue. 0. The Logical 'oncept of .reedom .reedom is
determined in the Logic as the overcoming of necessity. "ecessity itself is
determined as Fthe merely internal! and for that reason merely e,ternal!
connection of mutually independent e,istences.GC That the connection
between two things is merely internal means that although being
connected to the other is constitutive of what each thing is! this fact is not
evident- FThe identity of the two things that appear bound in necessity!
and which! for that reason! lose their independence! is at first only an
inner identity that is not yet present to those who are sub9ect to
necessity.G5 This ma&es the connection merely e,ternal in the sense that it
is not understood to be an intrinsic feature of the things it connects.6
Rather! the connection is understood to be an accidental relation obtaining
between Fmutually independent e,istences.G Plainly put! a thing is unfree!
or sub9ect to necessity! when it is bound to something that is e,ternal to
itself and thus irrelevant to ma&ing it what it is. *uch an e,ternal bond
prevents the thing from being self;determining! and so from being free.
(ne of Hegels e,amples is the planets- all are connected in a system of
orbits! but at the same time this connection does not ma&e them what
they areH each planet is the planet that it is! all by itself! and its
participation in a system with other planets is an additional feature!
e,ternal to that which ma&es it what it is.@ 8ars would still be 8ars! in
other words! even if =enus did not e,ist! and thus the bond between their
orbits involves the two in a relationship of necessity and e,ternal
determination that restricts the independence of both. f necessity is a
relationship in which mutually independent or e,ternal things are bound to
and determined by each other! and freedom is the overcoming of
necessity! then freedom would seem to be achievable in one of two ways-
either the bonds between the mutually e,ternal things could be cut! so
that the things no longer restrict each otherH or the /6 part i- hegels
philosophy e,ternality could be overcome ?internali#edA! so that the things
remain bound but understand that being bound to each other is
constitutive of what they are. n the latter case! freedom would be
achieved because a things independence cannot be threatened by that
which ma&es it what it isH in fact! if a thing can be what it is only in virtue
of being bound in a particular way! then that bond actually ma&es possible
its independent e,istence as the thing that it is. 4ut the former option B
the cutting of the bonds which might appear to be the more intuitive!
fails to solve the problem. +s long as the relata continue to e,ist! they
must remain related! even if their relation is only that of things trying to
escape! or unwilling to ac&nowledge! any relation between themselves.
Thus the attempt to sever all connection fails! leaving the two things both
bound and e,ternal to each other! and so unfree. Whereas the planets are
bound together in necessity! which they can never overcome! an e,ample
of the failed attempt to achieve such overcoming through the cutting of
bonds can be found in the inveterate bachelor who avoids all long;term
relationships. *uch a person understands his identity to be what it is
independent of other people! and thus views long;term relationships as
restrictive and limiting. +lthough he may enter into them for various
reasons B out of loneliness or se,ual desire! perhaps B he can never
e,perience them as constitutive of a union that creates and sustains his
identity and thus ma&es possible his liberation. (n the contrary! he
necessarily e,periences long;term relationships as diminishing his
freedom! which he therefore believes he can find only through their
dissolution. 4ut such dissolution is always imperfect- it transforms the
bachelors relationship to his former partner but cannot eradicate it. +s
Hegel puts it- Fthe person who flees is not yet free! for in fleeing! he is still
determined by the very thing from which he is fleeing.G/> *ince the
cutting of the bonds fails to liberate! freedom can be produced only
through a demonstration that the bound elements are not truly e,ternal to
each other! through ma&ing manifest the fact that their identities are
reciprocally constitutive. "ecessity becomes freedom not by severing
bonds! but by developing a different understanding of the character of the
things bound. They must come to be seen not as entities independent of
one another! e,ternal to and restrictive of one another! but as distinct
parts internal to a larger! self;determining whole that encompasses them
and their interconnections. n this new understanding! both the whole and
its parts are seen to be free. The whole is free because in being bound to
its parts it is bound only to itself. The parts are free because! even though
they are bound to other parts and to the whole! these bonds are now
understood to be internal to the nature of the parts themselvesH it is
understood that each part is what it is only in virtue of being a part of the
whole. This means that the parts could not even be themselves without
being bound to the other the place of freedom in hegels philosophy /@
parts of the whole! which means that! instead of constituting e,ternal
restrictions on each other! the parts actually constitute the other parts
themselves.// The ultimate difference! then! between a necessary relation
and a free one is that in the latter the bonds of the former have been
comprehended as internal to the very nature of the things bound! which
means that the things bound have been comprehended as internal to each
other./0 Thus Hegel writes that the process of necessity is the overcoming
of what is present at first as rigid e,ternality! so that its inwardness is
revealed. What this process shows is that the terms that appear initially to
be bound together are not in fact alien to one anotherH instead! they are
only moments of one whole! each of which! being related to the other! is
at home with itself ?bei sich selbstA! and goes together with itself ?mit sich
selbstA. This is the transfiguration of necessity into freedom./1 Whereas
the planets and inveterate bachelors are bound in necessity ?no matter
how desperately the latter try to escape it or how loudly they proclaim
that they haveA! Hegel considers the entry into a loving marriage to be an
e,ample of the transformation of a necessary bond into a free one.
Partners who enter into such a marriage! according to Hegel! change their
self;understanding- they come to understand themselves not as
individuals with preestablished and separate identities who are
accidentally connected to each other! but as members of a union in which
their very identity as individuals is constituted. 8arriage gives one Fself;
consciousness of ones individuality within this unity . . . so that one is
present in it not as an independent person but as a member.G/2 This
transformation of self;consciousness internali#es the bond between the
partners! by ma&ing e,plicit the fact that their bond is intrinsic to what
they are- Fthe union of the natural se,es! which was merely inward Lprior
to marriageM. . . and whose e,istence was for this very reason merely
e,ternal! is transformed into a spiritual union! into self;conscious love.G/D
4ecause this internali#ation of an e,ternal bond is the logical criterion for
the transformation of necessity into freedom! the entry into a loving
marital union allows partners to e,perience themselves as freely bound
together. The internali#ation of the e,ternal that mar&s the movement
from necessity to freedom also amounts! for Hegel! to the transfiguration
of the finite into the infinite. He defines the finite as Fwhatever comes to
an end! what is! but ceases to be where it connects with its other! and is
thus restricted by it. Hence the finite subsists in its relation to its other!
which is its negation and presents itself as its limit.G/C 3iven this
definition! it is immediately apparent that any two finite things are
mutually e,ternal in the sense already discussed. The fact 0> part i-
hegels philosophy that each serves as the others limit means that the
character of each is understood to be fundamentally independent of that
of the other. 'onse$uently! the connection between the two can only
function as a restriction on both. .inite things are bound to and
determined by each other in necessity! not in freedom. *ince finite things
are bound in necessity through being connected to other finite things that
lie beyond their limits! the transfiguration from finitude to infinity could be
sought in two ways. These alternatives correspond precisely to those
previously considered as ways of overcoming necessity- either the
connection could be severedH or it could be internali#ed! through the
recognition that it constitutes the things that it connects in virtue of
constituting the limits that ma&e them what they are. +s before! the first
option fails to solve the problem. Disconnecting two finite things may shift
the limits of each! but it cannot help but leave both limited. +nd! Hegel
points out! this is true no matter how often the operation is performedH at
best! the repetition of disconnection can produce an infinite series of
altered relations between things that remain perpetually finite. .amously!
Hegel writes that Fthis infinity is spurious or negative infinity! since it is
nothing but the negation of the finite! but the finite arises again in the
same way! so that it is no more sublated than not. n other words! this
infinity e,presses only the re$uirement that the finite ought to be
sublated.G/5 t is therefore only the second option! a finite things
internali#ation of its connection to its other! and thereby its recognition
that it and its other are reciprocally constitutive! that produces genuine!
rather than spurious! infinity. n a genuine infinity there are no longer any
strictly finite elements that limit and restrict each other! but only elements
that are moments of the whole! and therefore are what they are only in
that self;determining whole and in their relations to its other moments.
:sing phraseology identical to that which mar&s the passage from
necessity to freedom! Hegel says that Fthe genuine infinite . . . consists in
remaining at home with itself ?bei sich selbstA in its other! or! when it is
e,pressed as a process! in coming to itself ?#u sich selbstA in its other.G/6
Returning to our e,amples! we can see that the mutually e,ternal planets
are irredeemably finite! the inveterate bachelor achieves only negative or
spurious infinity! and the marriage partners achieve a genuine infinity. The
infinitude of the bachelor is negative or spurious because even if he were
to abandon or deny his connection to an infinite number of partners! he
would never alter the fundamental finitude of his situation. :nable to find
himself at home in a union with another person! he clings to his
independent identity and thus continues to e,perience human
relationships as the imposition of necessity rather than as the condition of
freedom. 4ut the marriage partners! in transforming their understanding
of their relationship! from that of an arrangement in which they happen
the place of freedom in hegels philosophy 0/ to have 9oined their
independent identities to that of a union within which their shared
identities as members are created and sustained! cease to e,perience
each other as restrictive or limiting. nstead! they e,perience themselves
as mutually constitutive of the whole that ma&es them who they are! and
within which they are thus at home. The conclusion to draw from this brief
investigation of the Logic is this- for Hegel! freedom results from the
transfiguration of the finite into the infinite! and this transfiguration ta&es
place through an internali#ation of the e,ternal. 4y means of this process!
one being discovers that its identity lies in being a member of a union with
another being that it once e,perienced as alien and restrictive. + being is
liberated! that is! not by fleeing from what seems to be foreign to it! but
through a reconciliation with its other that demonstrates that their mutual
estrangement is not insuperable. .reedom thus re$uires attaining self;
determining individuality by renouncing independence- in Hegels terms! it
re$uires achieving identity;in;difference! the contradiction embodied in
genuine love that the bachelors understanding cannot grasp./@ 1. The
Philosophy of *pirit as an +ccount of .reedom Hegels logical discussion of
freedom! and the e,amples used to illustrate it! show that freedom is
available only to certain &inds of beings. (nly a being capable of
internali#ing its e,ternal limitations! of achieving a genuine infinity by
overcoming the apparent finitude of both itself and its other through a
demonstration that the two are members of a larger! self;determining
unity! can be free. .or Hegel! this means that no merely natural being is
capable of freedom. "atural beings! on his account! Fare more or less
mutually independent e,istencesH true! through their original unity they
stand in mutual connection! so that none can be comprehended without
the othersH but this connection is in a greater or less degree e,ternal to
them.G0> Hegels contention is that Fin a greater or less degreeG all merely
natural beings are li&e the planets- interconnected and bound together as
elements of a whole ?the universe! and various smaller wholes within itA!
yet mutually e,ternal at the same time. He e,presses this contention in
the claim that Feven in the most perfect form to which nature raises
itself . . . LitM does not attain. . . to complete victory over the e,ternality
and finitude of its e,istence.G0/ This claim that natural beings are
perpetually finite and sub9ect to e,ternality! together with his analysis of
these concepts in the logic! allows Hegel to conclude that Fnot freedom
but necessity reigns in nature.G00 f e,ternality! finitude! and therefore
necessity are the definitive characteristics of natural beings! then freedom
is available only to those beings that are not merely natural. Hegel calls
such beings spiritual! 00 part i- hegels philosophy and his account of
them in the philosophy of spirit begins! as we have already seen! with the
claim that Fthe essential . . . feature of spirit is freedom.G This claim
should not be ta&en to mean that Hegel believes in the e,istence of a
mysterious and free being! which he calls Fspirit.G Rather! his claim is that
of the perfectly ordinary beings with which we are familiar! all and only
those that can 9ustifiably be called FspiritualG can 9ustifiably be called
Ffree.G (f course! this does not tell us when we are 9ustified in calling an
ordinary being Fspiritual.G 4ut it does at least indicate that the pro9ect of
understanding Hegels account of freedom coincides with the pro9ect of
understanding his account of spirit- the entirety of Hegels philosophy of
spirit is an attempt to develop an ade$uate understanding of the
conditions under which a being can 9ustifiably be called spiritual! and thus
free. The philosophy of spirit begins by conceiving of spiritual beings as
simply as possible- spiritual beings are those that are not merely
natural.01 This should not be ta&en to mean that spiritual beings are
supernatural! for on Hegels account everything spiritual is also natural.
.or e,ample! human beings ?who are spiritual in Hegels senseA are also
animals ?which are naturalA. 4ut our animality cannot account for our
freedom. (n the contrary! in Hegels view it is the fact that humans are
not merely natural! but also spiritual! that gives us the freedom that
animals lac&. *ince the definitive characteristic of natural beings is the
insuperability of their mutual e,ternality! the implication of understanding
spiritual beings as not merely natural is that spiritual beings are those that
are capable of internali#ing their connections to everything that initially
seems to be alien to them! and therefore those for which nothing is
irreducibly e,ternal- We must designate as the distinctive determinateness
of the concept of spirit! ideality! that is . . . the process of turning bac&
?NurO c&&ehrenA B and u the accomplished turning bac& ?Nur
uc&ge&ehrtseinA B into itself from its O other . . . What we have called the
ideality of spirit LisM this triumph ?+ufhebungA over e,ternality. . . )very
activity of spirit is nothing but a distinct mode of leading bac& ?NurO
c&fuhrungA what is e,ternal to the inwardness u which spirit itself is! and it
is only by this leading bac&! by this ideali#ation or assimilation! of what is
e,ternal that it becomes and is spirit.02 Thus Hegel claims that! although
Fnot freedom but necessity reigns in nature!G Fthe substance of spirit is
freedom! that is! the absence of dependence on an other! the relating of
self to self.G0D This initial understanding of the spiritual! however!
immediately issues in a conceptual contradiction- spiritual beings are
conceived as free in virtue of being not merely natural! but as long as
spiritual beings are conceived as merely not;natural they cannot be free.
To be not;natural is the place of freedom in hegels philosophy 01 to be
related to what is natural as to something e,ternal and independent!
which is to be finite and connected to nature in necessity rather than in
freedom. +s Hegel puts it- F+t first! spirit stands in relationship to nature
as to something e,ternal! and in this mode it is finite consciousnessH it
&nows the finite and stands over against nature as an other B for! to begin
with! spirit e,ists as finite spirit. 4ut . . . as finite LspiritM is conceived in
contradiction with itself. *pirit is free.G0C *piritual beings must therefore
be reconceived in a way ade$uate to their freedom. (n the one hand!
spiritual beings must continue to be conceived as not merely natural! so
that their difference from natural beings! in virtue of which they are
capable of overcoming necessity! is preserved. 4ut on the other hand!
spiritual beings must not be conceived as merely not;natural! in virtue of
which they would be finite and sub9ect to necessity. Ta&en together! these
two re$uirements entail that spiritual beings must be conceived in such a
way that they internali#e their connection to the natural world and thus
come to be at home within it! but without lapsing bac& into a merely
natural e,istence. *piritual beings must be conceived in such a way that
they achieve freedom through a positive reconciliation with the merely
natural world from which they differ! rather than through a negative flight
from it.05 The process of revising the conception of the spiritual until
spiritual beings are understood to be reconciled with the natural world
while preserving their difference from it comprises the entire philosophy of
spirit.06 +t each stage in this process! spiritual beings are conceived in a
way that is thought to be ade$uate to their freedom. 4ut reflection shows
each of these conceptions! e,cept for the last! to be contradictory-
spiritual beings are thought both to be free! and to be sub9ect to
e,ternalities that limit their freedom. *uch contradictions force further
revisions that overcome the specific e,ternalities to which spiritual beings
have been thought to be sub9ect. This process! and with it the philosophy
of spirit! ends only when a conception of spirit has been developed in
which spiritual beings are no longer sub9ect to e,ternality! and so are truly
selfdetermining and free- FThe entire development of the concept of spirit
presents only spirits freeing of itself from all its e,istential forms that do
not accord with its concept! a liberation which is brought about by the
transformation of these forms into an actuality perfectly ade$uate to the
concept of spirit.G0@ The conceptual development that comprises the
philosophy of spirit ta&es place in three parts! which Hegel calls
sub9ective! ob9ective! and absolute spirit. +ll three are presented in
condensed form in the final third of the )ncyclopedia. 8ore detailed
e,positions of the last two are also available. (b9ective spirit is presented
in the Philosophy of Right and the lectures on the philosophy of history.
+bsolute spirit is presented in the lectures on aesthetics! religion! and the
history of philosophy. 02 part i- hegels philosophy *ub9ective! ob9ective!
and absolute spirit thus present a series of attempts to conceive spiritual
beings in a way that is ade$uate to their freedom.1> *ub9ective! ob9ective!
and absolute spirit appear in a determinate order because the conception
each presents internali#es the e,ternality to which spiritual beings are
sub9ect in the preceding conception. This se$uence of conceptions is thus
a se$uence of progressive internali#ations! through which spiritual beings
are ultimately conceived in a way that is ade$uate to their freedom.
4ecause the freedom of spiritual beings is ade$uately conceived only at
the end of the philosophy of spirit! and because the philosophy of spirit
ends with absolute spirit! we can conclude that Hegel understands spiritual
beings to be most fully free in the activities that absolute spirit considers-
the activities of art! religion! and philosophy. 8oreover! because
philosophy is the last of these activities to be considered! we can conclude
that it is through the practice of philosophy that Hegel considers the
liberation of spiritual beings to be complete. Hegel thus claims that
philosophy is Fthe highest! the freest! and the wisest configuration of
spirit.G1/ 4ut &nowing that Hegel believes the practice of philosophy to
complete the liberation of spiritual beings is not the same thing as
understanding why he holds this belief. Part of this boo& provides an
interpretation of Hegels account of the freedom of spiritual beings that
ultimately e,plains why and how Hegel believes the practice of philosophy
to contribute to and complete our liberation. The final section of this
chapter e,plains how that interpretation will be carried out. 2. *tructure
and 8ethod of Part We can now see that to understand Hegels account
of freedom we need to understand his account of absolute spirit and the
activities it presents. 4ut in order to understand how spiritual beings are
liberated by art! religion! and especially by philosophy! we need to
determine the specific &inds of e,ternality that these activities overcome.
This amounts to determining the e,ternalities to which spiritual beings
remain sub9ect at the highest stage of ob9ective spirit. (b9ective spirit!
which considers spiritual beings as willing beings! itself has three main
parts- abstract right! morality! and ethical life. To determine the
e,ternalities that remain at the end of ethical life! we need to understand
the liberation that ethical life does in fact afford. +nd finally! in order to
understand this! we need to determine the specific &inds of e,ternality
that ethical life overcomes! which amounts to determining the
e,ternalities that remain at the end of morality and the reasons that the
willing sub9ect as conceived in morality! or the moral will! necessarily fails
to overcome them.10 the place of freedom in hegels philosophy 0D Part
addresses these problems in the order in which they arise in the course of
the development of Hegels philosophy of spirit. 'hapter 0 analy#es
Hegels account of the freedom of willing in the Philosophy of Right. This
analysis centers on morality! and shows that the moral will is internally
contradictory- the very features in virtue of which the will is supposed to
be free in morality prevent it from being so by ensuring that it remains
plagued by e,ternality. *pecifically! it shows that the content of the moral
will is inevitably e,ternal to its form. + by;product of this analysis is thus
an understanding of Hegels famous criticism that the %antian conception
of the autonomous will! which Hegel ta&es to be a moral one! is FemptyG
or FformalG and therefore provides an insufficiently comprehensive
conception of freedom. 4y negative implication! this analysis also
demonstrates how the will must be reconceived in ethical life if it is to
liberate itself by internali#ing the limitations to which it is sub9ect in
morality. 'hapter 1 pic&s up where 'hapter 0 leaves off! with the
assumption that at the highest stage of ethical life! that of the rational
state! the spiritual sub9ect is conceived in such a way that it is as free as
the activity of willing can possibly ma&e it. t then analy#es the limitations
of willing! to show that even at the highest stage of ob9ective spirit the
spiritual sub9ect is conceived in a way that remains internally
contradictory- the activity of willing! through which the spiritual sub9ect is
supposed to overcome the e,ternality of nature! actually ensures that this
e,ternality persists. +gain negatively! this analysis indicates how the
spiritual sub9ect must be reconceived in absolute spirit if it is to be
liberated from the e,ternality endemic to all willing. 'hapter 2! with which
Part concludes! e,plores the ways in which the activities of absolute
spirit! and especially philosophy! overcome the e,ternalities that remain at
the end of ob9ective spirit. This e,ploration finally shows us how Hegel
understands the most comprehensive freedom of spiritual beings! and how
he understands the practice of philosophy to contribute to and complete
this liberation. +t this point readers might benefit from referring to the
accompanying figure! which provides a s&eletal drawing of Hegels system.
The figure identifies both the location of Hegels account of freedom within
his system! and the elements of that account on which Part focuses. The
analyses in Part ma&e sense of the sections of the philosophy of spirit
with which they are concerned by employing the conceptual
determinations found in Hegels Logic. +lthough this approach re$uires
engaging in a number of abstract and difficult logical discussions! such
engagement is both necessary and rewarding. t is necessary because!
whether or not Hegel is right that the concepts developed in his Logic
must be used to comprehend spiritual beings! he does in fact so use
themH and it is rewarding because! given that Hegels philosophy of spirit
0C part i- hegels philosophy Philosophy ?conceptual comprehension ofA
Logic Realphilosophie ?beingsA ?pure conceptsA "ature ?unfree beingsA
*pirit ?free beingsA .inite nfinite *ub9ective (b9ective ?willingA ?'hapter
1A +bsolute +bstract Right 8orality ?'hapter 0A )thical Life +rt Religion
Philosophy ?'hapter 2A ncreasingly comprehensive conceptions of the
freedom of spiritual beings .reedom in Hegels system does use those
logical concepts! our grasp of the philosophy of spirit is improved when we
attend to that use. The first step in such analyses is to identify the logical
concepts most relevant to understanding the section of the philosophy of
spirit being analy#ed. This identification cannot be made by see&ing ?or
imposingA a formal pattern of correspondence ?one;to;one! or otherwiseA
between the developments in the Logic and those in the philosophy of
spirit. Rather! one must attend $uite carefully to the details of Hegels
te,ts- in the passages of the philosophy of spirit with which one is
concerned! it is often possible to find pointers ?both e,plicit and implicitA
to relevant sections of the Logic H and in passages of the Logic! it is
possible to find clues to the interpretation of various parts of the
philosophy of spirit. the place of freedom in hegels philosophy 05 (nce
this wor& is done! the second step is to use the identified logical concepts
to understand both the e,ternalities to which spiritual beings remain
sub9ect in the conception under consideration! and the reconceptions that
are necessary to overcome those e,ternalities and increase their
freedom.11 have tried to ma&e my discussions of the Logic as clear and
concise as possible! and to illustrate them with helpful e,amples. Where
have not provided e,amples in the course of these logical discussions it is
because ta&e the subse$uent discussions of the relevant portions of the
philosophy of spirit to serve as the most helpful illustrations. 0 TH)
.R))D(8 (. WLL"3- H)3)L* PHL(*(PHE (. R3HT The goal of this
chapter is to understand Hegels conception of the freedom of willing.
:nderstanding this conception re$uires understanding its development out
of Hegels criticisms of two other conceptions of the freedom of willing!
that of liberalism and that of %ant! which he deems insufficiently
comprehensive. Hegels criticisms of liberal choice and %antian autonomy!
and his own more comprehensive conception of the freedom of willing! are
presented most fully in his Philosophy of Right. The ntroduction develops
and critici#es the liberal conception of freedom as choiceH the second main
section! on morality! develops and critici#es the %antian conception of
autonomyH and the third and final main section! on ethical life!
incorporates choice and morality into Hegels own conception of the
freedom of willing as participatory citi#enship in a rational state. The heart
of this chapter therefore consists of an analysis of these crucial sections of
the Philosophy of Right. 8orality is the particular focus! because it is the
penultimate stage of ob9ective spirit. .or this reason! understanding the
e,ternalities that limit the freedom of willing sub9ects in morality is the
&ey to understanding the liberation of those sub9ects in ethical life. )thical
life! as the final stage of ob9ective spirit! provides the most comprehensive
conception of the freedom available to the willing sub9ect. :nderstanding
the finitude or incomplete freedom of the moral will! and its liberating
reconception in ethical life! re$uires understanding parts of Hegels
discussion of the concept of 9udgment in the Logic. *ection / therefore
provides a brief account of the logical concept of 9udgment. *ection 0
turns to the Philosophy of Right to consider the development of the moral
conception of the will out of the conceptions presented in the ntroduction
and abstract right. *ection 1 identifies the defining features of the moral
will and compares them to those of 9udgment. *ection 2 shows how the
finitude of the moral will is related to the finitude of 9udgment! and then
e,amines three separate attempts of the 06 the freedom of willing-
hegels philosophy of right 0@ moral will to overcome its finitude! again
using relevant sections of the Logic to help understand their failures. This
allows us to conclude that the moral will is insuperably finiteH specifically!
as long as the willing sub9ect is conceived as having the features
distinctive to 9udgment! its content is necessarily e,ternal to itself. The
section ends with a brief loo& at how the concept of 9udgment develops
into that of syllogism! and how this development illuminates the one that
ta&es place in the transition from morality to ethical life. *ection D
concludes the chapter by e,amining the institutions of ethical life B the
family! civil society! and the state B that complete the liberation of the
willing sub9ect./ /. The Logical 'oncept of 7udgment 7udgment appears in
the last of the three main sections of Hegels Logic! the sub9ective logic! or
the doctrine of the concept. The sub9ective logic is itself divided into three
sections B sub9ectivity! ob9ectivity! and the idea B each of which is further
subdivided. (ur concern is with sub9ectivity! of which the 9udgment ?das
:rteil A is the second moment. The first moment of sub9ectivity is the
concept ?der 4egriff A! and the third moment is the syllogism ?der
*chlussA. The most basic form of 9udgment! with which we are all familiar!
is the 9udgment of identity- F* is P.G Hegel points out that such a 9udgment
has two essential! and mutually contradictory! features. .irst! it is divided
into two parts! the sub9ect and the predicate! which are held to be
independent of and therefore e,ternal to each otherH second! and at the
same time! those parts are asserted by the 9udgment to be implicitly
identical or mutually internal. n addition to being a two;part relation of
sub9ect and predicate! the 9udgment is also! Hegel suggests! a three;part
relation of universality! particularity! and individuality. This is what it
shares with the concept and the syllogism! which are also composed of
these three moments. The concept! the 9udgment! and the syllogism are
differentiated by the distinct ways in which these three moments are
interrelated in each of them.0 n the concept! universality! particularity!
and individuality are understood as being immediately identical to each
other. +s immediately identical! these Fmoments of the concept cannot be
separated.G1 This means that they must be thought as a single unity! that
none of the three can be understood apart from the others- Fsince in the
concept their identity is posited! each of its moments can only be grasped
immediately on the basis of and together with the others.G2 The
interrelation of universality! particularity! and individuality is otherwise in
9udgment. Hegel calls 9udgment the particular moment of sub9ectivity! by
which he means two things. .irst! in 9udgment universality! 1> part i-
hegels philosophy particularity! and individuality are understood to be
separate from each other. )ach of the three is now understood to be what
it is independent of the character of the othersH they are not understood
to be immediately identical.D *econd! and at the same time! the three
moments are understood to be related to each other in 9udgment in such
a way that they are inseparableH they are understood to be implicitly
identical.C The lin& between thin&ing of 9udgment in terms of sub9ect and
predicate! and thin&ing of it in terms of universality! particularity! and
individuality! lies in the fact that the sub9ect of a 9udgment is an individual!
and the predicate is a universal. 8ore specifically! the sub9ect is a concrete
unity of particular determinations ?which ma&es it an individualA! and the
predicate is a universal determinacy attributed to the sub9ect! in virtue of
which their identity is posited in the copula! the is.5 'onsider! for e,ample!
the following 9udgment- FThis is a tree.G This is an individual sub9ect! with
a number of particular features ?it is tall! wide! old! brown and green!
living! composed of wood and leaves! and so forthA. Tree is a universal! a
determinate predicate that applies to more than one individual ?not only
to this! but also to that! that! that! and so forthA. s lin&s the two!
identifying the universal determination FtreeG with the individual thing in
$uestion. 4ut if the sub9ect is the moment of individuality! and the
predicate is the moment of universality! nothing in the 9udgment e,plicitly
represents the moment of particularity. +lthough it is understood that the
sub9ect and predicate are lin&ed in virtue of the former having the
particular features that define the latter! these particulars are not specified
or e,pressed in the 9udgment itself. nstead! their place is ta&en by the
copula! the is! which lin&s the sub9ect and predicate as the particulars
would! but without reference to the particulars themselves. This ma&es
the copula the &ey to 9udgment! because it produces both the
inseparability and the separation of the sub9ect and the predicate! the
individual and the universal! that define this logical form. t produces
inseparability more obviously! because in asserting that each half of the
9udgment is the other it identifies the two. 4ut it also produces separation!
because its assertion of the identity of the sub9ect and the predicate is
merely an assertion. That is! the copulas promise that the 9udgments
sub9ect and predicate are identical is not fulfilled within the 9udgment
itself. *uch fulfillment would depend on a demonstration that the
particular features defining the universal predicate do indeed belong to the
individual sub9ect. 4ut the 9udgment! in replacing the moment of
particularity with the empty copula! provides no such demonstration.
7udgment thus lin&s its sub9ect and predicate in a way that leaves them
separatedH instead of identifying a determinate! internal connection of
sub9ect and predicate! 9udgment simply implies the e,istence of such a
connection through an indeterminate is. The indeterminacy of the 31p is!
therefore! leaves the individual sub9ect and the universal predicate! and
the particulars that should unite them! all mutually e,ternal! and the
promise of their implicit identity as yet unredeemed- F*ub9ect and
predicate are considered to be complete! each on its own account! apart
from the other- the sub9ect as an ob9ect that would e,ist even if it did not
possess this predicateH the predicate as a universal determination that
would e,ist even if it did not belong to this sub9ect.G6 'onse$uently! as
initially conceived! 9udgment is a self;contradictory logical form! asserting
the identity of its moments in a way that produces their separation. This
means that the sub9ect and the predicate of the 9udgment are mutually
e,ternal! and so are finite and bound in necessity! rather than in freedom.
(vercoming this finitude! we have seen! re$uires a demonstration that the
elements of the 9udgment are not truly e,ternal to each other. (vercoming
the lac& of freedom built into the structure of 9udgment thus re$uires
ma&ing good on the promise of 9udgment- the claim that its elements are
implicitly identical. The development of the concept of 9udgment in the
Logic therefore amounts to a se$uence of attempts to overcome this
contradiction in the initial conception of 9udgment by replacing the
e,ternal and indeterminate copula with a particular bond internal to both
the universal and the individual moment- FTo restore LtheM identity of the
concept! or rather to posit it! is the goal of the movement of 9udgment.G@
With this basic understanding of the relations between universal!
particular! and individual that define the initial conception of 9udgment!
and of the process of transforming these relations that defines the
development of this conception! we can now turn our attention to the
concept of the will and its development in the Philosophy of Right. 0. The
nitial 'onception of the Will and ts Development The Philosophy of Right
presents a series of conceptions of the will that develops in the course of
Hegels attempt to thin& the will as truly free. The series contains four
main conceptions of the will! which are presented and developed in the
four main sections of the boo&- the introduction! abstract right! morality!
and ethical life. )ach conception of the will is initially thought to be
ade$uate to the concept of the free will! but upon e,amination is shown to
suffer from limitations built into the very features that define it. This
situation! which Hegel calls a contradiction ?since what the thing is
contradicts what it is supposed to beA! forces a reconception of the will.
*pecifically! the will must be reconceived in a way that preserves the
freedom of the prior conception while overcoming its limitations. The new
conception is then defined by those features that allow it to overcome the
limitations of the preceding conception ?and that ultimately determine its
own limitationsA./> 10 part i- hegels philosophy The moral will is thus
defined by the features that allow it to overcome the limitations of the
conception of the will presented in abstract right. dentifying its defining
features therefore re$uires understanding the limitations inherent in
abstract right! and the features of abstract right that produce those
limitations. Those features of abstract right! however! develop specifically
in response to the limitations built into the features of the concept of the
will presented in the ntroduction. :nderstanding abstract right in order to
understand morality thus re$uires understanding the ntroduction as well.
.ortunately! our study of the ntroduction and abstract right need not be
comprehensive. 8ost important is to pay attention to the shifting relations
among the universal! particular! and individual moments of the will in the
course of its development. This is because 9udgment! as we have 9ust
seen! is defined by a specific &ind of relation of universality! particularity!
and individuality. We will therefore identify the connection between
9udgment and the moral will by recogni#ing this specific relation of
universality! particularity! and individuality as constitutive of the moral
will. n the following discussion of the ntroduction and abstract right!
then! we will emphasi#e the evolving relations between the universal!
particular! and individual moments of the will that define its ongoing
development! and that ultimately issue in the conception of the will that
defines morality. n the ntroduction to the Philosophy of Right! the will is
conceived as the faculty of choice. +s such! it is understood to have three
basic moments or aspects. .irst! there is the moment of abstraction! or
indeterminacy- the will is free because it can abstract from any particular
choice! because it is not bound to pursue any particular interest. *econd!
there is the moment of determination- the will is free because it can
determine itself to a particular choice! because it can choose to pursue a
particular interest. Third! there is the moment of remaining abstract in
determination- the will is free because even when it has determined itself
to a particular choice it can again abstract from it. This last moment
means that even though every determination or choice that the will ma&es
belongs to it! the will is never defined by any particular choice that it
ma&esH an important part of this freedom is the reali#ation that the will
has an identity that persists through an ongoing temporal process of
determining itself to! and abstracting itself from! particular choices and
interests. Thus freedom of the will! understood here as freedom of choice!
is essentially freedom as possibility- the will is free because it is possible
for it to pursue! or not to pursue! any of its chosen interests. Hegel also
describes these three moments of the choosing will in terms of
universality! particularity! and individuality.// The first moment is the
moment of universality! because in it the will is understood as a persistent
entity that remains the same as it distinguishes itself from a variety of the
freedom of willing- hegels philosophy of right 11 particular contents by
abstracting from them./0 The second moment is that of particularity! in
which the will renounces its empty universality by identifying itself with a
particular content. The third moment is that of individuality! which Hegel
understands as the unity of universality and particularity. The will is an
individual precisely because it is both particular and universal! both
capable of identifying with a particular content ?which is essential to
individuality because it distinguishes this will from other willsA and aware
that it has a universal identity that is independent of any particular
content with which it happens to identify ?without which it would be
permanently defined as the particular content it happened to have! and
would fail to achieve an individuality independent of itA./1 n the
conception of the will as the faculty of choice! the universal and particular
moments are immediately identified with each other to yield the wills
individuality. That is! the universality of the individual choosing will is
defined as the sum of its particular contents! and each of those particular
contents is defined as belonging to the individual in virtue of its being
included in the universal sum. 'onse$uently! it is impossible for the
contents of the universal and individual moments of the choosing will to
diverge. *uch divergence could occur if the individual will attempted to
determine the particular contents that should belong to the universal! on
the basis of some nontrivial criteria! and then compared those contents to
the particular contents it actually had chosen to place within it. 4ut in the
choosing will! the only criterion for determining that a particular content
should belong to the universal is that it actually does! that it actually has
been chosen for inclusion. This trivial criterion produces the immediate
and undivorceable identity of universality! particularity! and individuality
that defines the choosing will./2 The immediacy of the connection
between the universal will and its particular contents! which defines and
ma&es possible freedom of choice! also e,plains one of the two significant
limitations of this form of the will- the choosing will is formal! in one of the
two senses in which Hegel uses the term. This sense of FformalityG
signifies that there is no particular content intrinsic to the will! which
follows from the fact that the universal will is merely immediately
connected to the particulars it subsumesH rather than specifying which
particulars necessarily belong to it! the universal will must simply accept
particular contents that come to it e,ternally. n other words! even though
the will is free to pursue its chosen interests! it is not responsible for what
those interests are. +t this level! its interests are merely Fthe drives!
desires! and inclinations by which the will finds itself naturally
determined.G/D Thus freedom of choice consists in the wills ability to
resolve itself to satisfy a particular drive in a particular way! but does not
entail that it satisfy one drive rather than another. +s a result! the FfreeG
choices of the will are actually determined by the relative strengths of
natural inclinations! over which the will has no 12 part i- hegels
philosophy control. .reedom re$uires that the content of the choice! as
well as the formal ability to choose! be a product of the will. +s long as the
wills content is e,ternal to its form! the will is dependent on something
other than itself! not fully independent! and not fully free. The second
limitation of freedom of choice! which Hegel also calls formality! is its
dependence upon the ob9ects from which it is given to choose. n other
words! the will that e,ercises freedom of choice has no control over
whether or not the e,ternal ob9ects necessary to satisfy its particular
drives are available to it. The choosing will is thus formal in the second
sense that it is merely sub9ective./C These two limitations ma&e the
faculty of choice an inade$uate and self;contradictory conception of the
will! which is supposed to be unlimited and free. The will must therefore
be reconceived in a way that overcomes its dual formality or dual
e,ternality! its limitation by given! e,ternal content and by given ?or not
givenA e,ternal ob9ects. The wills freedom depends upon internali#ing!
ma&ing a part of itself! anything upon which it is dependent./5 n abstract
right! therefore! the will is conceived as being committed to willing its own
freedomH it &nows that it must have its own freedom for its content or
ob9ect if it is to overcome its formality./6 t also &nows that the first step
in willing its own freedom and overcoming its formality is the overcoming
of its sub9ectivity! its dependence on a world of natural ob9ects that it
e,periences as e,ternal and limiting. The will of abstract right thus see&s
its freedom by trying to claim some aspect of the e,ternal world as its
own. The first stage of its effort is the ownership of property! in which the
will identifies itself not only with its ability to choose! but also with an
ob9ect of its choice! with a small piece of the natural world./@ This location
of its freedom in an e,ternal ob9ect! which overcomes the mere
sub9ectivity of the choosing will! is the primary feature that characteri#es
the will in abstract right.0> That is! in all stages of abstract right! the
individual will identifies its freedom with something e,ternal to itself. The
development from stage to stage within abstract right represents the
progressive reconception of the will as it tries to overcome the limitations
that arise from its initial identification of its freedom with a particular piece
of property. This development toward freedom in abstract right! as we will
see! leads to a reconception of the relationship among the universal!
particular! and individual moments of the will. *pecifically! the universal
and individual moments! which are immediately identified in the choosing
will! become separated and mutually e,ternal in abstract right. 8orality! as
we will also see! ultimately arises because although the will of abstract
right overcomes the sub9ectivity of freedom as choice! its logical structure
prevents it from ever overcoming its formality. The separation of universal
and individual means that in none of its stages is the will of abstract right
able to develop a the freedom of willing- hegels philosophy of right 1D
content intrinsic to itself H abstract right is never able to overcome the
e,ternality of the individual wills particular content from its universal
form. The first stage of abstract right! freedom as the right to own
property! clearly remains formal in this sense of being without intrinsic
content. Property does represent a development beyond choice in that it
ob9ectifies the will by subordinating a concrete thing in the world to the
purposes of the willing sub9ect. 4ut property remains an inade$uate
e,istence for freedom! because the choice to own this piece of property is
still not a product of the will. t is essential to the free will that it own
property! but it is not essential that it own any particular piece of property!
so the preference for one piece of property o
er another cannot come from the will itself! and therefore no piece of
property that the will happens to identify with can be a truly sufficient
ob9ectification of its freedom. That is! although the wills identification with
a piece of property internali#es an ob9ect that was e,ternal to the will! the
decision to ma&e this particular identification remains e,ternal. *till
plagued with e,ternal dependence! the property;owning will remains
unfree. This is why the third moment of property is alienation ?)ntO
usserungA- a 9ust as in the third moment of freedom as choice the will has
to be able to abstract itself from any determination it ma&es! in the third
moment of freedom as the right to own property it has to be able to
abstract itself from any property it owns. Thus! Fit is not only possible for
me to dispose of an item of property as an e,ternal thing B am also
compelled by the concept to dispose of it as property in order that my will!
as e,istent! may become ob9ective to me.G0/ This is not to say that must
renounce all of my property! but rather that must renounce some of it if
am to become conscious of the persistent identity of my will. .reedom
re$uires that be able to! and sometimes do! alienate my propertyH failing
to do so! would become permanently identified with a decision that did
not stem from my will! and could not conceive of myself as free.00 The
re$uirement that be able to alienate my property leads to the
re$uirement that my e,istence and rights as a free being be recogni#ed by
another being! and that reciprocally recogni#e this being as freely
e,isting and bearing whatever rights freedom re$uires. This is because in
order to alienate property! to give up my ownership! must implicitly
recogni#e that the ob9ect is now available to be claimed as property by
any other free being who so desiresH to alienate my property involves the
recognition of the property rights of others! even if there are no others
around to claim ownership immediately. Li&ewise! for another free being
to ma&e an ownership claim on an ob9ect that once owned re$uires her
to recogni#e me as the &ind of being who could have both legitimate
ownership of the ob9ect and the right to renounce that ownershipH to claim
alienated property involves the recognition of 1C part i- hegels philosophy
the property rights of others 9ust as much as the alienation of property
does. The result is a further ob9ectification of my freedom. 8y freedom is
no longer ob9ectified solely in the ob9ects that own! but is now also
ob9ectified in another free being- FThis relation of will to will is the true
distinctive ground in which freedom has its e,istence.G01 n one sense!
this is an advance! for shifting the ob9ectification of my freedom from the
ob9ects that own to other free property owners represents a small but
important step on the path to finding my freedom in an ob9ect or content
that is truly mine. This is because other free beings are less alien to me
than unfree ob9ects are. +t the same time! however! this deepened
ob9ectification also amounts to an increased interdependence. .or the first
time! my freedom is dependent upon the freedom of another! and her
freedom is dependent on mine. This is true not 9ust in the sense in which
it is true in the liberal conception of freedom B where the freedom of each
depends on others not interfering with it B but in the more significant
sense that without other free beings cannot be free at all. n the liberal
conception can be a free individual! and in fact it will be easiest for me to
be free! if no other people even e,ist to encroach upon my freedomH
choice is something that can e,ercise all by myself. Hegels
demonstration of the limitations inherent in understanding freedom as
choice! and his further development of the concept of freedom as
re$uiring the ability to alienate property! show that without other free
beings who recogni#e my freedom myself cannot be free. He thus shows
that! parado,ically! increased freedom re$uires increased
interdependence.02 'ontract! the structure that arises out of this mutual
recognition of free property owners! is the second main stage of abstract
right. n contractual relationships Fthe contracting parties recogni#e each
other as persons and owners of property!G and they underta&e to e,ercise
their rights by e,changing property with each other.0D +t this stage! the
freedom of a person resides not only in the property she chooses to own!
but also in the contracts she enters into! and in her respect for and
performance of the obligations contained in those contracts. 'ontracts
unite the will not only with the ob9ects being e,changed! but also with the
will of the other party. Whereas in owning property raise a particular
ob9ect to the universal! by e,ternali#ing my will in it and ma&ing it one
means among many of serving my ends! in contractual relationships also
raise my particular will to the universal. This is done by positing a
common will that the two contracting! particular wills share. )ach will
remains distinct! yet also enters into community with the other! by means
of this universal will.0C n this way! contract furthers freedom- it dissolves
not only the e,ternality between myself and particular ob9ects! but also
the e,ternality between my particular will and other particular wills.05 the
freedom of willing- hegels philosophy of right 15 4ut this
reconceptuali#ation of the will that ta&es place in contract also gives rise
to the limiting structure that can ultimately be overcome only by moving
into morality. The interdependence involved in freedom as contract
effectively doubles the conception of the will. )ach individual will is now
understood to be composed of two distinct parts- a particular will of its
own! and a universal will that it shares with the other wills involved in the
contract. +s Hegel puts it! Fin any relationship of immediate persons to
one another! their wills are not only identical in themselves and! in a
contract! posited by them as common! but also particular.G06 The great
significance of this development is that for the first time the particular and
universal moments of the individual will are divided. n fact! the universal
moment is now understood not to reside within the individual will itself!
but to be a creation that it shares with one or more other wills! which
e,ists only in the contracts negotiated between them. Thus the universal
moment! upon which the freedom of the individual will depends! is now
itself e,ternal to the individual will and its particular contents. This means
it is now possible for an individuals pursuit of her chosen interests ?the
particular contents of her willA to diverge from the re$uirements of her
freedom ?the particular contents of the universal willAH whereas the
particular contents of the choosing will are immediately identified with its
universality ?because its universality is simply defined as the sum of its
particular contentsA! their identification is now uncertain or contingent.
This can be seen more clearly with the help of a simple e,ample. enter
into any contractual relationship for two reasons- to satisfy my particular
interest in some property or another ? prefer your piece of land in .lorida!
for instance! to the one have in +las&aA! and to satisfy my universal
interest! shared by all free beings! in ob9ectifying my freedom by
participating in and respecting contractual arrangements. f all goes well!
one and the same relationship will satisfy both of my interests- the
contract will enable me to get the particular property want! and to
ob9ectify my freedom with another free being. 4ut all may not go well- Fit
is purely contingent whether . . . particular wills are in conformity with the
will which has being in itself! and which has its e,istence solely through
the former.G0@ n some cases! my universal interest will be satisfied ?a
valid contract is e,ecuted and respectedA! while my particular one is not ?
am disappointed with the e,change have madeA. n other cases! my
particular interest will be satisfied ? get what wantA! while my universal
one is not ? may violate the mutual respect of rights that contracts
re$uire B for e,ample! by defrauding my counterpartA. n this latter case
satisfy my chosen interest! yet violate the re$uirements of my own
freedom in the processH in defrauding someone elevate my particular
interest over my universal one! which prevents me from being a free
individual-Ff the particular will for itself is different from the universal! its
attitude and volition are characteri#ed by arbitrariness and 16 part i-
hegels philosophy contingency! and it enters into opposition to that which
is right in itself H this is wrong.G1> f this occurs! if the particular will does
not conform to the universal! right is merely a *chein ?a semblance of
what it should be! having an e,istence inappropriate to its essenceA! and
it! as well as freedom! must be restored by repairing the wrong have
committed.1/ t is important to emphasi#e that in failing to respect
freedom as contract wrong not only the victim of the fraud or crime! but
also myself. violate the victims rights as a free property owner and party
to a contract! but in doing so also violate the sphere of contractual rights
in general. *ince respect for these rights is essential to my own freedom!
wrong myselfH as a free will that fails to respect freedom! fail to respect
or to be ade$uate to my own essence. This is why it is my freedom that
must be restored! and not only that of the victim. There is no guarantee!
however! that will recogni#e the harm that have done or! even if do
recogni#e the harm! that will ta&e steps to repair it. +fter all! to commit
a crime is to place my particular interests ahead of the universal! and
there is no reason to thin& that will alter my priorities if left to my own
devices. The only solution is that society must punish me if commit a
crime. This punishment is for the sa&e of both 9ustice and freedom. t
serves the former by restoring right! and the latter by restoring my
respect for right! which is essential to my freedom. +s Hegel puts it! Fthe
in9ury which is infiicted on the criminal is not only 9ust in itself . . . it is
also a right for the criminal himself.G10 Punishment! for Hegel! protects us
from destroying our own freedom by pursuing our particular interests
without respect for rightH punishment is a means by which society protects
a person from herself for the sa&e of her own freedom. t does so by
turning her will from the particular ?her own contingent drives and needsA
to the universal ?the re$uirements that stem from her own nature as a
free beingA. However! punishment can only restore respect for right! and
thereby protect freedom! if it is 9ust. :n9ust punishment again gives
precedence to a particular interest over the universal! and is therefore
only another wrong! which restores neither right nor respect for right. 4ut
at this stage there is no guarantee that punishment will be 9ust B for the
will that e,acts punishment has the same basic features as the will that
committed the wrong! and is therefore e$ually capable of placing its
particular and sub9ective interests ahead of the universal. To ensure that
9ustice is done! the punishing will must be a will which! as a particular
and sub9ective will! also wills the universal as such.G11 4ut this can only
happen if the will is reconceived in such a way that the universal will
resides within the individual! if the ob9ect in which the freedom of the will
resides is again ?as it was in the case of freedom as choiceA ta&en to be
the individual will itself. Without this reconception! the freedom of willing-
hegels philosophy of right 1@ the universal confronts the individual will as
something e,ternal! to which the conformity of its particular contents is
therefore contingent.12 n this reconception! however! the relationship of
particular and universal cannot merely revert to what it was in the
choosing will without also reinstating the limitations inherent in choice.
This must be avoided! while simultaneously overcoming the limitations
produced by the separation of universal and particular in abstract right.
The latter re$uires reuniting the particular and universal moments of the
will within the individual! and the former re$uires that their identification
no longer be immediate and abstractH the internali#ed universal will must
not identify with whatever particular contents it happens to find! but
instead must determine out of itself the particular contents necessary to
the free individual. We can now recapitulate the development of the will in
abstract right. n abstract right! the will tries to give itself internal content
and ob9ective e,istence! which it lac&s when conceived as the faculty of
choice. t achieves ob9ectivity in property! thus internali#ing one of the
e,ternal factors upon which the choosing will is dependent! but remains
formal. The formality of the will! the fact that no particular property is
necessary to it! gives rise to its need to be able to alienate its property!
which gives rise to the need to engage in contractual relations with other
free wills. This deepens the wills ob9ectification! but also separates the
particular will and the universal will! and forces the e,ternali#ation of the
latter from the individual. +s a result! the will is still formal- the drives of
the particular will continue to be given to it e,ternally as natural
inclinations! and there is no guarantee that they will coincide with the
universal will! which is now a re$uirement of its freedom. This! finally! is
the death of the will of abstract right. +s long as the will locates its
freedom in an ob9ect e,ternal to itself! which is what characteri#es
abstract right! there is always the possibility that the content of the will!
its own particular drives! may be at odds with its own freedom! its own
universality. +lthough it is also possible for the wills particular drives to
accord with its freedom! if this is in fact the case it is only accidentally or
contingently so! not owing to any feature of the will itself.1D This ma&es
the will of abstract right an inade$uate conception of the will and results in
the need to reconceive the will in such a way that it determines its own
particular contents out of its newly reinternali#ed universal moment. 1.
The 8oral 'onception of the Will The needed reconception ta&es place in
the transition from abstract right to morality- LThe will of abstract rightM
first posits itself in the opposition between the universal will which has
being in itself and the LparticularM will which has being for itselfH then! by
superseding this opposition B the negation of 2> part i- hegels philosophy
the negation B Lthe moral willM determines itself as will in its e,istence! so
that it is not only a free will in itself! but also for itself! as self;related
negativity . . . The infinite sub9ectivity of freedom! which now has being
for itself! constitutes the principle of the moral point of view.1C This says
that in abstract right! as we have 9ust seen! the individual will ta&es its
freedom ?the universal will that has being in itself A to e,ist independent
of ?that is! in opposition toA itself and its particular contents. This
constitutes a negation! because the individual will is understood not to be
the e,istence of the universal will. Rather! the universal will is thought to
e,ist outside any individual will! in the contracts that bind a number of
property;owning wills together! and in the punishments that enforce
breaches of those contracts. The moral will arises when! for the reasons
we saw earlier! this negation has to be negatedH the individual moral will
understands that it is the e,istence of the universal will! which is therefore
internal to it. The moral wills location of its universal moment within itself
ma&es it not only a free will in;itself ?that is! it not only implicitly is the
e,istence of freedomA! but also a free will for;itself ?that is! it also ta&es
itself to be the e,istence of freedomA. This is e$uivalent to its being self;
related! or an infinite sub9ect! both of which signify that the moral will
&nows itself to be determined only by itself! since it &nows itself to be the
e,istence of the concept that determines it.15 The moral will is not only
self;related! but is a self;related negativity because it understands itself to
be internally divided! to have parts that FnegateG each other in their
mutual differentiation! yet are held together within a single self.
*pecifically! the individual moral will understands itself to contain both its
particular contents and its universal concept! and understands that the
two are not yet identical but must be made so! if the moral will is to
ensure! as the will of abstract right cannot! that it wills its own freedom.
We can now recogni#e that in the transition from abstract right to morality
the will has become particulari#ed! and this recognition allows us to begin
to connect the moral will to the logical concept of 9udgment- the moral will
is the particular moment of the will! 9ust as 9udgment is the particular
moment of sub9ectivity generally. n the moral will! as in 9udgment!
universality! particularity! and individuality are both divided and held
together! &nown to be different and assumed to be implicitly identical.16
ts particulari#ation differentiates the moral will from the choosing will! in
the same way that 9udgment is differentiated from the concept- although
the moral will and the choosing will are similar ?and differentiated from
the will of abstract rightA in locating their universal moment within
themselves! they differ in the sense that the moral will is aware of the the
freedom of willing- hegels philosophy of right 2/ distinction between itself
as individual and universal! and is resolved to overcome this difference! to
ma&e e,plicit the implicit identity of these two moments by demonstrating
that their particular contents are the same. The choosing will! on the other
hand! immediately identifies its universal moment with whatever
particular contents it happens to have. +s we have seen! this ma&es it
formal! because it is determined by ends and purposes not intrinsic to its
universal form! particular ends that are simply given to it as natural
instincts. n order to overcome this formality and become free! the
individual moral will must determine out of its own universal concept the
particular ends and purposes to which it applies itself! transforming its
e,istence from a natural form into a form that it prescribes. 7ust as the
will of abstract right &nows that it must own and use property! the moral
will &nows that it must ta&e genuine ownership of itself or! as Hegel says!
have its personhood as its ob9ect.1@ The fact that the individual wills
particular contents and universal form are still distinct at the outset of
morality ?even though the will now understands its universal moment to
be internal to itself A means that the contingent identification of the two!
which was the undoing of abstract right! has been internali#ed but not yet
overcome.2> Li&e 9udgment! the moral will implicitly assumes the identity
of its universal and individual moments! but without initially providing any
determinate! particular basis for this implicit assumption.2/ +nd this
leaves open the possibility that the particular contents of universal
freedom and the particular contents of the individual moral will may be at
odds. The need to overcome this opposition between the individual will
and its universal concept ma&es morality Fthe point of view of relationship!
obligation! or re$uirement.G20 The course of morality thus presents the
attempt to thin& the moral will in a way that fulfills its obligation by
overcoming the internal opposition that &eeps its particular contents
e,ternal to its universal form- The process within this sphere is such that
the will which at first has being only for itself! and which is immediately
identical only in itself with the will which has being in itself ?i.e.! with the
universal willA is supersededH and leaving behind it this difference in which
it has immersed itself in itself! it is posited for itself as identical with the
will which has being in itself.21 dentification of the process of morality as
the positing of the determinate identity of its universal and individual
moments! which are initially separate and connected only e,ternally!
completes the connection between 9udgment and the moral will! for this is
the same process that is re$uired of 9udgment itself. 7udgment! we saw!
must unite its individual sub9ect with its universal predicate not through
an empty copula! but with a determinate and particular content that
belongs to both sides of the 20 part i- hegels philosophy 9udgment. The
individual moral will! li&ewise! must secure its freedom by ensuring the
conformity of its particular contents to its universal form! which it can do
only if it can determine the particulars that genuinely belong to its
universal side. We can thus conclude that 9udgment and the moral will are
ali&e in both conceptual structure and process. nitially! they are defined
by having a structure that presupposes the mutual e,ternality of their
universal! particular! and individual moments! at the same time that it
assumes and asserts their identity. 4ecause this structure is self;
contradictory! both 9udgment and the moral will are then defined by the
attempt to demonstrate the mutual internality of their moments! by
determining the particular contents inherent in the universal that the
individual must adopt as its own. n the case of the moral will! the
internali#ation of its own moments is necessary to its internali#ation of the
e,ternal dependencies that plague the choosing will and the will of
abstract right- the dependency on e,ternal content and an e,ternal world.
The moral wills internali#ation of its own moments is thus essential to the
spiritual sub9ects process of selfliberation through coming to &now itself
as being without insuperable e,ternality. n the ne,t section we will
consider the finitude of 9udgment! and the re$uirements that must be met
if this finitude is to be overcome. We will then e,amine in detail how this
finitude is connected to the finitude of the moral will! and how the moral
will see&s to overcome it. We will identify three distinct stages of the
moral wills effort! each of which is connected to its own specific logical
structure! and will see that precisely because of their connections to these
logical structures all of the moral wills efforts must fail. n the last of
these efforts! the moral will see&s to use the power of the highest form of
9udgment to overcome the finitude built into its structure of 9udgment. n
understanding the failure of this effort! then! we will understand not only
the ultimate finitude of the moral will! but also that of 9udgment itselfH in
the failure of the moral will we will discover that 9udgment is unable to
internali#e the individual and the universal without losing its form of
9udgment and becoming syllogism. This will show us that a conception of
the truly free will must shed the structure of 9udgment! cease being a
moral will! and adopt the structure of syllogism! becoming an ethical will.
2. The ncomplete .reedom of the 8oral Will Recalling our previous
discussions of finitude and 9udgment! it is easy to see that 9udgment is
finite in the sense that it fails to be what it claims to be! and is therefore a
limited e,pression of! or inade$uate to! its own concept. 7udgments claim!
we have seen! is that its sub9ect and predicate! the freedom of willing-
hegels philosophy of right 21 its individual and universal moments! are
implicitly identical even though they appear to be separate and
independent. This claim is sta&ed in the copula! which asserts that the
individual sub9ect is identical to the universal predicate. 7udgment fails to
ma&e good this claim! we have also seen! because the copulas assertion
of identity is merely immediate. The identity claim can be 9ustified only on
the basis of a demonstration that the particular contents of the individual
sub9ect truly are those of the universal determinacy attributed to it! but
the empty copula is devoid of particularity. n failing to ma&e good its own
claim! 9udgment fails to be what it ought to be! and is therefore finite. The
fact that 9udgment is finite in this sense means that its sub9ect and
predicate are finite in the other sense discussed earlier- the individual
sub9ect and the universal predicate are mutually e,ternal. This is a direct
conse$uence of 9udgments failure to demonstrate their identity in virtue
of shared particulars. *uch particulars! if shown to be contained in both
the sub9ect and the predicate they unite! would provide proof of the
internal identity of the two! proof that the individual truly is the universal.
n the absence of such particulars! however! they are lin&ed only by the
empty copula! which is e,ternal to the sub9ect and predicate! and which
therefore leaves them e,ternal to each other.22 +s a result! the individual
sub9ect! which is supposed to be infinite in virtue of containing within itself
the universal determinacies that define its own nature! e,periences those
determinacies and that nature as independent of itself! and is therefore
finite.2D (vercoming the finitude of 9udgment! and thereby overcoming
the finitude of its sub9ect and predicate! re$uires the development of a
logical form in which the connection between the individual sub9ect and
the universal moment is not immediate! and therefore e,ternal and
contingent! but mediated through particulars belonging to both! and
therefore internal and necessary. (nly in such a form could the individual
find its freedom in being bound to a universal that is truly its own. The
development of the various stages of 9udgment in the Logic chronicles the
attempts of 9udgment to become such a form! to become ade$uate to its
own concept. n Hegels terms! the development of 9udgment amounts to
a process of raising the individual to the universal! or of ma&ing the
universal not only an sich but also fO r sich! by giving the universal u
e,istence in an individual sub9ect that &nows itself to be the e,istence of
the universal.2C This is done by gradually forging a determinate identity
between the sub9ect and predicate of the 9udgment. This determination of
their identity amounts to what Hegel calls a fulfillment of the copula! a
transformation of the implicit and therefore e,ternal identity provided by
the empty is into an e,plicit and therefore internal identity provided by
concrete particulari#ation of the universal.25 The successive stages of
9udgment increasingly appro,imate this final copulation. 22 part i- hegels
philosophy However! as the Logic ultimately shows! the successful
fulfillment of the copula cannot be accomplished by 9udgment! because
that fulfillment amounts to the overcoming of 9udgmentH the fulfilled
copula internali#es the universal and individual so thoroughly that it
destroys one of 9udgments defining features B namely! the essential
difference of its moments. The development of 9udgment thus
demonstrates that in all of its stages 9udgment is a self;contradictory
logical concept- what 9udgment is ?the particulari#ation of its universal!
particular! and individual momentsA is always at odds with what 9udgment
claims to be ?the identification of universality and individuality through
particularityA.26 7udgment thus remains finite! even in its highest forms.
The internali#ation of individuality and universality necessary for infinitude
is found not in 9udgment! but in syllogism! the concept that follows it in
the development of Hegels Logic.2@ +fter considering the connection of
the finitude of 9udgment to that of the moral will! and the moral wills
failed attempts to overcome its finitude! we will conclude this section by
considering the development from 9udgment to syllogism! and the parallel
development from morality to ethical life. The first sense in which the
moral will is finite is a direct result of its having the structure of 9udgment!
and therefore correlates directly to the first sense in which 9udgment itself
is finite- the moral will asserts the identity of its individual and universal
moments but! at least initially! provides no proof of its assertion! and thus
fails to be what it claims to be. The individual moral will! that is! insists
that it can ensure its conformity to its universal concept! but leaves the
universal indeterminate and thus leaves its conformity to it contingent.
The conse$uence of the moral will being finite in this sense is! 9ust as it is
in 9udgment! the finitude of its moments- as long as the particular
contents of its universal moment remain undetermined! the individual
moral will and its universal concept are mutually e,ternal. n other words!
the FinfiniteG moral sub9ect is not truly infinite! because the concept that
determines it is not truly internal to it. The moral will is also finite in the
second sense that it e,periences the natural world of ob9ects as an
e,ternal limitation. This limitation B which we have seen to arise because
the will is spirit in the form of 9udgment! ta&en to be separate from and
independent of nature B was transcended by the will in abstract right! but
only at the cost of e,ternali#ing its universal moment! and with it its own
content. The moral will reinternali#es its universal moment in the ?as yet
unreali#edA hope of internali#ing its content! but at the cost of again
finding itself alienated from the natural world. Whereas the individual will
of abstract right located its freedom in ob9ects B such as property and
contracts B which therefore came to be internal to it! the individual moral
will the freedom of willing- hegels philosophy of right 2D locates its
freedom in itself! and as a result e,periences all mere things as e,ternal.
These two senses in which the moral will is finite drive the developments
that ta&e place in moralityH as long as the moral will is finite! it contradicts
the concept of the will as that which is free or infinite. Two basic
reconceptions are necessary! corresponding to the two types of finitude
that must be overcome. .irst! the individual moral will must determine the
particular ends re$uired by the universal concept of freedom and adopt
those ends as its ownH failing this! it will remain formal or without intrinsic
content! dependent upon something e,ternal to itself to provide it with
ends! and it will fail to be free. *econd! the moral will must produce in the
ob9ective world the ends it determines to be intrinsic to freedomH failing
this! it will remain Fthe point of view of the difference! finitude! and
appearance of the will.GD> That is! it will be merely sub9ective ?formal in
Hegels second senseA! confronted by an alien realm that does not
conform to its freedom! and will again fail to be free.D/ n addition to
these basic re$uirements! there are two additional strictures imposed on
the individual moral will! which derive from the developments leading to
morality in the Philosophy of Right. .irst! it must recogni#e the ends that it
determines to be re$uired by freedom as also being in accordance with its
own sub9ectivityH if freedom is to be truly internal to the individual will!
the re$uirements of freedom cannot be e,perienced by that will as alien to
itself ?as they were in abstract right! leading to the necessary possibility of
committing wrong by violating those re$uirementsA. *econd! these ends
must also accord with what Hegel calls universal sub9ectivityH as we saw
for the first time in our consideration of contractual relations! in order to
respect its own freedom an individual will must respect the freedom of all
other free sub9ects! who at this stage also insist on determining and
actuali#ing for themselves the contents of freedom.D0 Hegel sums up
these tas&s by saying that the moral will must determine and produce
content that is simultaneously sub9ective ?recogni#ed as its ownA and
ob9ective in three distinct senses ?e,isting in the world! in accordance with
the concept of freedom! and in accordance with universal sub9ectivityA. He
also tells us that the moral wills ultimate failure will lie in its inability to
produce content that satisfies all of these criteria.D1 The re$uirement that
the content of the moral will e,ist in the world means that its freedom
cannot be conceived merely as potentiality! spontaneity! or possibilityH
rather! the moral will must give its freedom e,istence in action! since it is
action that translates internal ends or purposes into the e,ternal world.D2
The moral will must therefore identify itself with its actions! much as in
abstract right the will had to identify itself with its property. 4ut an action
is the proper e,pression of freedom only if it 2C part i- hegels philosophy
meets the criteria described earlier! and so the moral will identifies itself
only with actions that meet those criteria.DD .irst! the moral will identifies
with an action only if it recogni#es it as sub9ective! or its own. 8ost
basically! the will must recogni#e the action as something it did on
purpose! a $uality that Hegel calls being formally its own. He discusses
this demand in Purpose and Responsibility! the first main section of
morality. n addition! the will must recogni#e the content of the action as
its own! which occurs only if the action is described in accordance with the
intention under which the will claims to have performed it. Hegel discusses
this in moralitys second main section! ntention and Welfare. 4ut even if
the moral will finds satisfaction in an action performed on purpose and
under an intentional description that it recogni#es as its own! it is still
finite! still not completely free. The moral will here is limited in much the
same way that the choosing will was- it is able to determine itself to
satisfy particular ends with particular means! but the particular ends it
happens to have are still given to it- Fthe as yet abstract and formal
freedom of sub9ectivity has a more determinate content only in its natural
sub9ective e,istence B its needs! inclinations! passions! opinions! fancies!
etc.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen