Sie sind auf Seite 1von 914

FROM REALISM TO RAPPROCHEMENT:

THE AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL INTERPRETATION

OF COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY

Glenn C. Shipley
Loyola University of Chicago
PhD Dissertation
1983
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

In writing this dissertation I have received support and


encouragement from many people. Fr. Edward Maziarz, my Director,
has been unflagging in his enthusiasm for the project and in his
belief in my ability to bring it to a successful conclusion. Dr.
James Blachowicz and Dr. Peter Maxwell have done me the great
honor of reading every word of it with critical intelligence and
many suggestions for improving both its style and content. And
if it were not for the patience, confidence and support of Dr.
Francis Catania, I would never have completed my doctoral
studies. I am also grateful to my typist, Jane Strom, whose
skillful and tactful work has made concluding the final stages
of this project immeasurably easier.

I owe a greater debt than words can express to my wife,


who has suffered the fate of a "dissertation widow" with love
and good humor; to my children, who accepted their father's
frequent disappearances to work on his "dissertation book;" and
to my mother, who knows what it means to go it alone to finish a
lifetime project, and who taught me all those things which I
rely upon without thinking, so that I can now be free to rely
upon my thinking.

ii
LIFE

The author, Glenn C. Shipley, is the son of Herman


Shipley and Frances (Brachle) Shipley. He was born November 15,
1938, in Villa Park, Illinois. He is married to Marilyn
(Sheridan) Shipley, and is the father of Gregory, William, and
Mark Shipley.

He graduated from St. Alphonsus Grammar School in 1952,


and from St. Michael High School in 1956, both of Chicago,
Illinois. In September of 1956 he was enrolled at Loyola
University of Chicago under a Loyola University Competitive
Scholarship. In 1962, as a member of the United States Air
Force, he attended the Armed Forces Language Institute at the
University of Indiana in Bloomington. In 1965 he returned to
Loyola, from which he received, in February of 1967, the degree
of Bachelor of Science with a major in philosophy.

He began graduate study in philosophy at Loyola


University under a Graduate Assistantship in February of 1967,
and in March of 1967 was awarded a three year National Defense
Graduate Fellowship (NDEA Title IV). In June of 1971 he received
the degree of Master of Arts. He was awarded an Arthur J.
Schmitt Dissertation Fellowship for the academic year 1972-1973.
TABLE OF CONTENTS

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ii

LIFE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . iii

LIST OF TABLES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. viii

LIST OF IN-TEXT REFERENCES . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. ix

Chapter

PART I

I. INTRODUCTION: COLLINGWOOD AND HIS INTERPRETERS

1. Collingwood: His Life, His Writings, and His Era. . . 1


2. T. M. Knox and the "Radical Conversion Hypothesis". . 9
3. Collingwood's Interpreters: An Overview . . . . . . . 22
4. On Interpreting Collingwood . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42

II. THE AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL INTERPRETATION OF COLLINGWOOD'S


PHILOSOPHY

1. The Autobiography as Literary Evidence . . . . . . . 53


2. The Autobiography as Historical Interpretation . . . 60
3. The Autobiographical Interpretation: Four Themes . . 64
4. The Critique of Realism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67
5. The Logic of Question and Answer . . . . . . . . . . 79
6. History and Philosophy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89
7. Rapprochement Philosophy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98

iv
PART II

III. REALISM AND IDEALISM

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 106
2. Realism and Idealism in Religion and Philosophy . . 109
3. Idealism, the Absolute, and the Metaphysic
of Knowledge . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124
4. Absolute Idealism and the Forms of Experience. . . . 128
5. Speculum Mentis and the Emergence of
Explicit Anti-Realism . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139
6. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148

IV. QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS, LOGIC AND DIALECTIC

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 154
2. Abstract and Concrete Universals . . . . . . . . . . 158
3. Science and Supposal . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 167
4. Conclusion: Three Logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181

V. HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191
2. The Identity of History and Philosophy . . . . . . 194
3. The Concrete Universal as Absolute Object . . . . 198
4. The Ideality of History a Scale of Forms . . . . .. 206
5. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233

VI. RAPPROCHEMENT, RELIGION, AND ABSOLUTE KNOWLEDGE

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243
2. Religion, Philosophy, and Incomplete Rapprochement . 247
3. Speculum Mentis: Rapprochement and Developing Series 265
4. Speculum Mentis: Retrogressive Identity . . . . . . 272
5. Speculum Mentis: Progressive Identity . . . . . . . 286
6. Disputed Questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 293

v
PART III

VII. ANTI-REALISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 320
2. Empirical Thinking and the Essay on
Philosophical Method . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 328
3. Sensation, Imagination, and Empirical Thought . . . 335
4. Attention, Freedom and Corrupt Consciousness . . . . 355
5. Idealism and the Limitations of Phenomenology . . . 366
6. The New Leviathan: Attention as a Linguistic Act . . 390
7. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 415

VIII. LOGIC, LANGUAGE, AND MENTAL ACTS

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 423
2. Questions, Answers, and Presuppositions . . . . . 427
3. Dialectical Logic and Philosophical Methodology . 458
4. Language and Logic in The Principles of Art . . . 518
5. Language and Mind: The New Leviathan. . . . . . . . 538
6. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 592

IX. THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 607
2. Anti-Realism and History
a) The Definition of History . . . . . . . . . . . 617
(b) The Outside and Inside of Historical Events . . 625
(c) Individuality, Universality, and the
Subject Matter of History . . . . . . . . . 636
(d) Historical Re-enactment . . . . . . . . . . . . 645
(e) The A-Priori Imagination . . . . . . . . . . . 655
(f) Re-enactment: Beyond Realism and Idealism . . . 667

vi
3. Evidence, Inference, and Necessity
(a) Historical Evidence . . . . . . . . . . . . . 694
(b) Historical Inference . . . . . . . . . . . . 704
(c) Historical Necessity . . . . . . . . . . . . 712
4. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 719

X. METAPHYSICS AND RAPPROCHEMENT

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 721
2. The Autobiographical Themes in the Essay on
Metaphysics . 736
3. Obstacles to Understanding Collingwood's
Reformed Metaphysics . . . . . . . . . . . . . 752
4. The Unity of the Autobiographical Themes . . . . . 767
5. The Rehabilitation of Reformed Metaphysics . . . . 795
(a) From Anti-Metaphysics to Reformed Metaphysics .797
(b) Metaphysics as an Historical Science . . . . 805
(c) The Absoluteness of Presupposing . . . . . . 815
(d) Ontology and Reformed Metaphysics . . . . . . 825

BIBLIOGRAPHY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 836
LIST OF TABLES

1. The Interpretations of Collingwood's Philosophy . . . . 41

2. The Critique of Realism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77

3. Question and Answer Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84

4. The Principles of History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91

5. Rapprochement Philosophy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103

6. The Meanings of History . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 240

7. The Knower-Known Relationship in Perception . . . . . . 388

8. The Philosophy of Mind . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 419

9. Question-and-Answer logic in The Essay on Metaphysics . 430

10. Philosophical Method . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 463

11. Language and Expression in The Principles of Art . . . 520

12. Language, Logic, and Mental Acts in The New Leviathan . 540

13. The Presuppositions of the Analysis of Mental Functions 557

14. Metaphysics and Anti-Metaphysics . . . . . . . . . . . 747

viii
LIST OF IN-TEXT REFERENCES

In this dissertation references to Collingwood's pub-


lished philosophical works are made in the fashion that has
become accepted by Collingwood's interpreters. The references
are made in-text, by abbreviation of the title of the work
followed by the page or pages on which the reference is found.
These abbreviations are as follows:

A An Autobiography. London: Oxford University Press, 1939.

EM An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford. The Clarendon Press, )97~.

EPA Essays in the Philosophy of Art. Edited by Alan Donagan.


Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1964.

EPH Essays in the Philosophy of History. Edited by William


Debbins. New York: University of Texas Press, 1965.

EPM An Essay on Philosohical Method. London: Oxford University


Press, 1933.

FR Faith and Reason: Essays in the Philosophy of Religion.


Lionel Rubinoff, editor. Chicago Quadrangle Books, 1968.

IH The Idea of History. T. M. Knox, editor. London: Oxford


University Press, 1946.

IN The Idea of Nature. T. M. Knox, editor. London: Oxford


University Press, 1945.

NL The New Leviathan. London: The Clarendon Press, 1942.

PA The Principles of Art. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1938.

RP Religion and Philosophy. London: Macmillian and Company,


1916.

SM Speculum Mentis. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1924.

ix
In addition the following standard works on Collingwood are also
given in-text references:

CEPC Krausz, Michael, editor. Critical Essays in the Philosophy


of R. G. Collingwood. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.

CRM Rubinoff, Lionel. Collingwood and the Reform of


Metaphysics. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970.

FYC Johnston, William M. The Formative Years of R. G.


Collingwood. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1967.

LPC Donagan, Alan. The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood.


Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1962.

MHD Mink, Louis O. Mind, History, and Dialectic: The Philosophy


of R. G. Collingwood. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1969.
FROM REALISM TO RAPPROCHEMENT: THE
AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL
INTERPRETATION OF COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY

Glenn C. Shipley
Loyola University of Chicago

During his lifetime at Oxford, the English philosopher,


R. G. Collingwood (1889-1943), published a number of books both
in history and in philosophy, including An Autobiography (1939),
in which he offered a self-interpretation of his intellectual
development. This dissertation is an attempt to measure the
degree to which the Autobiography can successfully serve as an
interpretation of the whole of Collingwood's published
philosophy.

In Part I the problem of interpreting Collingwood's


philosophy is surveyed, and it is shown that the main problems
to which Collingwood's interpreters address themselves are those
which Collingwood also discusses in the Autobiography. These
problems cluster around four major themes: the realism-idealism
controversy, question-and-answer (Q-A) logic, the philosophy of
history, and philosophical rapprochement.

In Part II the early writings (1916-1932) are examined


on each of these issues. After exhibiting an early tolerance of
realism, Collingwood's anti-realism surfaced in Speculum Mentis,
along with a commitment to absolute idealism. While there is no
evidence of a systematic Q-A logic in his early writings, the
epistemic functions of questioning and asserting are clearly
present and indicate an incomplete resolution of problems on
logic and methodology. Similarly the philosophy of history and
the notion of rapprochement identity show a steady development,
but leave serious ambiguities unresolved.

In Part III the later writings (1933-1946) are surveyed


on each of these same issues, and it is shown that Collingwood's
anti-realism not only remained constant, but hardened--which led
to certain difficulties in his analysis of perception. Q-A
logic, rather than being an alternative to formal logic,
actually functions as an interpretative methodology, while the
dialectical logic of the Essay on Philosophical Method becomes
the criteriology of rapprochement completion in all his later
works. In the final chapter of Part III the unity of the
autobiographical themes is reconstructed and used to overcome
the obstacles to a reformed metaphysics as an historical science.
FROM REALISM TO RAPPROCHEMENT: THE AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL
INTERPRETATION OF COLLINGWOOD’S PHILOSOPHY

Copyright, 1983: Glenn Shipley, PhD


PART I

THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING


COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY
Chapter I

INTRODUCTION: COLLINGWOOD AND HIS INTERPRETERS

1. Collingwood: His Life, His Writings, and His Era.

Robin George Collingwood (1889-1943) was the youngest of

four children and the only son of W. G. Collingwood (FYC, 6).

His parents were artists, amateur archeologists, and friends of

John Ruskin. The elder Collingwood was first Ruskin's student,

later his personal secretary and confidant. and after Ruskin's

death in 1900 he became his biographer. The young Robin grew up

in an atmosphere heavily influenced by the Ruskinean ideal of

the universal man (FYC, 1, 17-36, 143-46).1 Like Ruskin himself

and also the young J. S. Mill, Collingwood was educated at home

until he was thirteen (partially due to the poverty of his

parents); and also like Mill, he was started on classical

languages at an early age--Latin at four and Greek at six (A,

1). He was able to read the English proofs for his father's

books by the age of five (FYC, 7), and by the time he started at

____________________
1 An appreciation of the degree to which Collingwood
valued Ruskin's thought can be gained by a reading of
Collingwood's own assessment of it in his early essay, "Ruskin's
Philosophy," delivered as an address at the Ruskin Centenary
Conference, 1919, but published in 1922 and reprinted in EPA, 1-
41.
2

Rugby at thirteen he could read and speak German and French

almost as easily as English (A, 6). At Rugby he taught himself

enough Italian to read Dante in his spare time (A, 7). As a

child he also accompanied his parents on archeological

expeditions: he claims to have attended his first "dig" as a

three-week old infant --in the toolbag of his parents (A, 80).

From Rugby Collingwood won a scholarship to University

College, Oxford, which he attended from 1908 until he graduated

in 1912 with "Firsts" in both Classical Moderation and Literae

Humaniores. He was hired as a tutor at Pembroke College while

still wearing his scholar's robes from final examinations.2 By

1913 he was given an independent hand at excavations on Roman

ruins in England, and was already being regarded by Haverfield

(his Oxford mentor in the subject) as his successor. After the

outbreak of war in 1914 he entered the British Admiralty

Intelligence where he remained until the end of the war in 1918.

During this time he wrote the manuscript for Religion and

Philosophy, which was published in 1916.3 In 1918 he married

Ethel Graham, moved his quarters to a country house, and began

an extremely active academic life as lecturer and tutor in both

philosophy and Roman and British History. In 1934 he was

relieved of some of this burden of tutoring and teaching when he

was appointed to

__________________
2 R. B. McCallum, "Robin George Collingwood,"
Proceedings of the British Academy, XXIX (1944), p. 463.

3 Ibid., p. 464.
3

the chair of Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy.

From 1918 to 1934 he published four books--Roman Britain (1923,

revised edition in 1934), Speculum Mentis (1924), The Archeology

of Roman Britain (1930), and An Essay on Philosophical Method

(1933)--and numerous short articles and monographs.4

The last-mentioned book was produced during a leave of

absence from his teaching responsibilities in 1932, due to a

prolonged illness (A, 117-18)--the beginning of the ill-health

against which the remainder of his life was to be an heroic

struggle (FYC, 12). Between 1935 and 1941, when he resigned his

professorship, Collingwood managed to find time to do the

writing on archeology, history and philosophy that form the bulk

of his later published writings--Roman Britain and the English

Settlements (1936, with J. N. L. Myres), The Principles of Art

(1938), An Autobiography (1939), and An Essay on Metaphysics

(1940).5

Most of the material posthumously published as The Idea

of Nature (1945) and The Idea of History (1946) was also written

during this period, in the form of lectures (IN, v; IN, v-vi).

The New Leviathan (1942), the final work published during his

lifetime, was written under extreme

________________
4 T. M. Knox, "Notes on Collingwood's Philosophical
Work, with a Bibliography," Proceedings of the British Academy,
XXIX (1944), pp. 469-75.
4

stress, Collingwood’s state of health rapidly deteriorating, and

England being torn by war; its final chapters, he notes, were

written during the bombardment of London (NL, v; LPC, 316). In

1939 Collingwood felt well enough to sign on as First Mate on a

sailing yacht, the Fleur de Lys, for a trip from the coast of

France to Greece and the Greek islands--the other members of the

crew being mostly Oxford students. His account of that journey--

the First Mate's Log--was published in 1940 by Oxford University

Press in a limited edition. In 1942 his marriage with Ethel

Graham was dissolved at his wife's request (they had two

children, a son and a daughter), and he married Kathleen Frances

Edwardes, who bore him a daughter (EPH, x-xi). But his health

never fully regained its vigor, and he was forced to retire to

Coniston, to the house he inherited from his father, where he

died in 1943 of pneumonia.6

The years through which Collingwood lived and worked at

Oxford were among the most violent and revolutionary that Europe

has seen, and certainly the most profoundly threatening that

England has endured. His work spans the first half of the

twentieth century, bracketed at one end by the First World War

and the Russian Revolution, and at the other by World War II and

the Fascist holocaust. At Oxford the intellectual climate was no

less subject to violent upheavals. When Collingwood began there

in

_______________
6 McCallum, p. 468; cf. IN, xxi.
5

1908, the 19th century British idealist movement begun by T. H.

Green, with F. H. Bradley and B. Bosanquet its most respected

spokesmen, had just about spent itself, and a realist reaction

headed by Cook Wilson was already in full swing (A, 15-21). By

the time he retired his professorship in 1941 realism had given

way to logical positivism (A, 52). H. J. Paton writes that at

Oxford, in the period between the wars, "Collingwood and I were

the only representatives of our generation--a slender bridge

between predecessors at least ten years older and successors at

least ten years younger."7

In his Autobiography Collingwood corroborates this

remark when he writes that in the area of archeology he was the

only remaining Oxford resident trained by Haverfield as a

Romano-British specialist, and therefore felt an obligation to

keep alive that branch of studies which was left vacant when

Haverfield died in 1919, because most of his students had died

during World War I (A, 120).

In such highly troubled waters Collingwood felt himself

to be the vessel not only of Oxford Romano-British archeology

but also of philosophy. In philosophy the burden was even

greater, and in carrying it (alone, he felt) Collingwood was

buffeted by all the prevailing winds of

__________________
7 H. J. Paton, "Fifty Years of Philosophy," in
Contemporary British Philosophy, Third Series, ed. by:H. D.
Lewis (New York, 1956/1961), p. 345.
6

his era. Consequently even though his early works (Religion and

Philosophy, Speculum Mentis, and even the Essay on Philosophical

Method) have led to his rejection by contemporaries as a latter

day idealist, the body of his later writings continues to arouse

the interest of people of very different philosophical

persuasions--perhaps because many of the sources of these

persuasions were also influential on Collingwood himself.

Thus in the last of his books published during his

lifetime, The New Leviathan, one finds evidence relating him to

most of the major contemporary schools of thought. For example:

(1) pragmatism: "Reason is always essentially practical; because

to be reasonable means to be interested in questions beginning

with 'why'; and this happens because people crave for

reassurance against the fallibility of their knowledge" (NL,

14.31); (2) phenomenology and existentialism: "Man as mind is

whatever he is conscious of being" (NL, 1.84; emphasis his); (3)

linguistic analysis: "Language is not a device whereby knowledge

already existing in one man's mind is communicated to another's,

but an activity prior to knowledge itself, without which

knowledge could never come into existence" (NL, 6.41); and (4)

even Marxism: "Is there nowhere such a thing as 'purely

theoretical thinking'? There is; but it is not real thinking,

and it does not lead to real knowledge . . . . Real thinking . .

. always starts from practice and returns to practice; for it is

based on 'interest' in the thing thought about" (NL, 18.13).


7

Perhaps because such diverse inclinations are reflected

in his philosophy, he has been claimed for, and damned by, most

of these same schools of thought--and this is reflected in the

diversity of interpretations concerning his philosophy in the

growing body of secondary literature about him. Here one finds

him claimed not only by representatives of the traditions just

mentioned, but also (incredibly enough) logical positivism,

radical empiricism, idealism, cultural anthropology, and systems

theory. His roots have been located in Ruskinean moralism,

German Hegelianism, English and/or Italian idealism, and Cook

Wilsonean realism. Affinities have been found between his

philosophy and that of Ryle, Strawson, Wittgenstein, Dewey,

Husserl, Kierkegaard, Barth, and Sartre. And his best work has

been said to be in history, the philosophy of history,

esthetics, the philosophy of mind, metaphysics, ethics,

epistemology, and the history of ideas.

In spite of all these affinities, and in spite of the

remarkable breadth of his interests in this age of

specialization, he fits neatly into none of the contemporary

schools of thought, and succeeded in developing no appreciable

following of his own (cf. MHD, vii-viii, and FYC, vii, 137-46).

This is at least partially a matter of choice on Collingwood's

part: he sought no following, refused to engage in public

debate, and preferred taking his case in writing directly to the

public
8

(A, 56, n. 1, and A, 118). It is also partly due to the

circumstances

of his life: with positivism and analytic philosophy coming into

prominence in his own university, and Fascism and Communism

vying for dominance in the political arena around him,

Collingwood's attempts to steer an independent course led to his

estrangement from nearly all of his contemporaries. Even those

close to him felt a little irritated at him for being "rather

too quick in claiming all knowledge as his portion"8 and often

those who disagreed with him to his face were told, as it were,

to "bathe in Jordan."9 And finally, his isolation is very much

the result of the diversity and incompleteness of his output,

which makes it difficult to find a single insight that unifies

all of his multi-faceted output, or even to find a capstone to

complete the arch.

But whatever the reason for the difficulty in achieving

a clear focus in the surviving portrait of Collingwood's

thought, a portion of the blame for this difficulty must be

shared by the first interpretative authority to reflect on the

whole of Collingwood's output, and to this problem we must now

turn.

_________________
8 Paton, p. 345.

9 McCallum, p. 466.
9

2. T. M. Knox and the "Radical Conversion Hypothesis."

Before Collingwood died in 1943 he named T. M. Knox, a

friend and former student, as his literary executor.9a

Collingwood's will authorized his executor to publish only as

much of his unpublished writings as met high standards--thus

leaving to Knox's judgment what the public should see of the

unfinished works (IH, v). This material included Collingwood's

lecture notes on the philosophy of history, the philosophy of

nature, and ethics, and essays on philosophical theology and

cosmology with which he closed lectures on ethics and on the

philosophy of nature respectively (IN, v; IH, v-vi; CRM, 397).

In addition to this material there was an incomplete sketch of

The Principles of History which Collingwood hoped to be his

magnum opus, but which is now forever lost--and a large number

of other unspecified materials, not available for public

inspection.l0

9a According to David Boucher, Knox was chosen to edit


several works only after Collingwood’s death – see “The
Principles of History and the Cosmology Conclusion to the Idea
of Nature,” Collingwood Studies Vol 2, 1995, pp 142-46.

10 In 1969 I wrote to the Delegates of the Clarendon


Press, Oxford, for information about the status of these
manuscripts. They forwarded my letter to Collingwood's widow
(his second wife), who replied to me as follows: "Dear Mr.
Shipley, The Clarendon Press, Oxford, has passed your letter on
to me. There are a considerable number of unpublished papers of
R. G. Collingwood in my possession. Within the next year or so I
hope to deposit these in the Bodleian Library, Oxford. A number
of manuscripts will be reserved for some years. The incomplete,
unpublished Principles of History is lost. Yours Sincerely, Kate
Collingwood." In May of 1972 I received word from the Bodleian
Library that they still had not received any of the manuscripts
promised to them by Mrs. Collingwood, and stating that they had
been unable to contact her by mail. In June of 1979 I received
word from the Bodleian Library that they had recently received
the manuscripts from Mrs. Collingwood, and that
10

Under the titles of The Idea of Nature and The Idea of History

Knox published only the nearly completed lectures on cosmology

and history. He appended a part of The Principles of History

(actually only a portion of the first third of what Collingwood

had planned to write (IH, vi) and several completed essays

(delivered originally as lectures)as "epilegomena" in The Idea

of History, but omitted doing the same for The Idea of Nature on

the grounds that Collingwood seems to have become dissatisfied

with it: for the sketch of his own cosmology which had closed

his original lectures, Collingwood had substituted a shorter

concluding passage when he set about revising these lectures for

publication sometime after 1939 (IN, v.).ll

___________________
they filled the equivalent of five boxes measuring 14 x 11 x 4
inches "and are packed tight." A partial listing of their
contents included translations, letters, lectures, and notes on
everything from idealism and realism to the epistemology of
logic and English folklore. Most of the material is open to
inspection by scholars but, according to the terms set by Mrs.
Collingwood, is not to be photocopied.

1l There is something odd about Knox's editorial


judgment in this matter. Knox argues (as we shall see in a
moment) that Collingwood's best work was done between 1928 and
1936, and that after his radical conversion to historicism
between 1936 and 1938 his judgments were unsound and not to be
trusted in matters philosophical. On these grounds Knox
published the lectures on the philosophy of history and the
philosophy of nature, and included the terminal essays on
history that form the "epilegomena" to The Idea of History. But
on these grounds the essay on cosmology which closed
Collingwood's lectures on the philosophy of nature in 1934 and
1937 is a product of his mature, middle period. But instead of
publishing it as an "epilegomenon" to The Idea of Nature Knox
accepts Collingwood's later, possible judgment (which is
supposedly unsound) to omit this terminal essay. Instead Knox
published the short concluding piece which argues that
11

When Knox published The Idea of History in 1946 he added

an "Editor's Preface" in which he not only explained significant

editorial details about the manuscripts, but also proposed an

interpretation of the whole of Collingwood's philosophy, on the

basis of which he evaluated the posthumously published works,

and placed them in their setting within the context (as he saw

it) of Collingwood's entire published output. Therefore the

significance of the totality of Collingwood's published works to

date has rested upon Knox's judgment in both constitutive and

retrospective senses: constitutive because two important works,

including their present form, were directly due to his editorial

labors; and retrospective insofar as his account of

Collingwood's development is both (a) the only evidence that the

public has for the "high standards" that Knox used in deciding

which works should be suppressed and which deserved publication,

and (b) the only justification of these standards, based on the

interpretation of the group of writings that Collingwood did

publish in his own lifetime, that Knox offered for extending

that total output.

Knox's interpretation of Collingwood's development can

be outlined as follows:

________________
science "depends on historical thought for its existence" (IH,
177). But this is inconsistent with the editorial policy of The
Idea of History.
12

(1) Dividing Collingwood's writings into three groups,

Knox finds in the "juvenilia" (Religion and Philosophy (1916)

and Speculum Mentis (1924) evidence of skepticism and

dogmatism:12 religious skepticism insofar as religion is

described (in Speculum Mentis) as an erroneous mistaking of

imagining for thinking, and philosophical dogmatism insofar as

only philosophy is asserted as providing the full truth for

which religious assertion is only the symbol (IH, xiv-xv). Knox

says that the shift from the earlier work (in which religion,

theology and philosophy are identified) to the position in

Speculum Mentis marks the ascendancy of a dogmatic strain in

Collingwood's thought which "affected its content and . . . was

linked with a change in his attitude to religion, always one of

his strongest interests" (IH, xv).

(2) By 1932, during the "middle period" (as in

Collingwood's masterpiece, the Essay on Philosophical Method of

1933) the mature and

____________________
12 Knox does not specify what he means by dogmatism and
skepticism. But it seems that for Knox (1) one may understand by
"dogmatism" the imposition of an external source or standard of
truth on the internal doctrines of a body of knowledge; and (2)
"skepticism" to mean the failure or refusal to provide a
criterion for truth or falsity within a body of knowledge. That
is why historicism is a skepticism for Knox: history cannot
provide a criterion of truth or falsity for philosophy.
Therefore any criterion of truth which proceeds from, or is
grounded in, presuppositions which are themselves unquestioned
and/or unquestionable, is dogmatic; and any body of knowledge
resting on presuppositions which cannot themselves be judged to
be true or false is skeptical. Cf. IH, xvii.
13

undamaged mind of Collingwood embraced metaphysics as a separate

and distinct study of the one, the true, and the good (IH, xi).

This would have allowed for a truth-criterion (hence escaping

skepticism) not itself based on the unquestioning acceptance of

religious doctrine (hence not dogmatic). Knox thinks this much

is indicated in Collingwood's essay, "Faith and Reason," which

in assigning independent functions to each faculty escaped the

ascription of a monopoly of truth to any discipline (dogmatism)

as well as the denial of a truth universal and valid for all

thought (skepticism) (IH, xvi).

(3) But in the 1940 Essay on Metaphysics (and the

remainder of his later philosophy, his third period) Collingwood

lapsed back into the latent skepticism and dogmatism of his

youth by denying the independent status of metaphysics (which is

reduced to history). His "reform of metaphysics" is based upon

reducing the metaphysician's task to the historical work of

discovering the "absolute presuppositions" of science in a given

era. Since these absolute presuppositions were characterized by

Collingwood as (a) themselves neither true nor false, and (b)

religious in nature, they indicate a radical change in

Collingwood's mature position. This time Collingwood proposed a

philosophical skepticism and a religious dogmatism. Absolute

presuppositions are dogmatic as unquestionable and religious

(that is, held by an act of "unquestioning acceptance" or


14

"natural piety"--i.e. faith); and they indicate a kind of

skepticism insofar as they rest on no higher criterion of truth

and are themselves neither true or false (IH, xv-xvi).

Knox groups The Idea of History and The Idea of Nature

in the second, mature period, and The Principles of Art

overlapping the second and the third. He claims to have

documentary evidence that in Collingwood's second period he

still held that metaphysics as an autonomous branch of knowledge

was possible, and that in the third period not only is

metaphysics declared to be an historical science, but

"philosophy as a separate discipline is liquidated by being

converted into history" (IH, x; cf. xi-xii).

Unfortunately the work from which these quotations are

taken is The Principles of History which was never completed,

never published, and is now lost and so incapable of being

publicly examined; so there is at present no documentary

evidence to verify these statements. Even assuming that Knox is

a reliable authority, it is impossible to evaluate these

fragments without the full textual context--to see in what ways

Collingwood meant them to be taken, or qualified them, or

posited them as provisional assertions to be later corrected and

modified, etc. In future chapters we shall find direct evidence

in Collingwood's writings that he


15

often employed a dialectical strategy of positing a remark as a

starting point, then modifying the remark, and finally

contradicting it altogether--all in the span of one essay.

Unless we are to remain "scissors and paste" historians, and

therefore show that we have not learned even the first lesson

that Collingwood wished to teach us, we cannot take Knox's

fragments from Collingwood's "nachlass" manuscripts uncritically.

We are therefore left with Knox's arguments, based on

available evidence, concerning Collingwood's radical change of

mind--which Knox says occurred somewhere between 1936 and 1938

(IH, xi). The failure to acknowledge this change of mind is one

of the reasons Knox rejects Collingwood's Autobiography as a

reliable account of his development--the other being that in the

Autobiography Collingwood seems to wish his readers to believe

that he had worked out his theory of absolute presuppositions

and the purely historical character of metaphysics prior to 1932

and the Essay on Philosophical Method. Regarding the latter

point (1) Collingwood made no such claim in the Autobiography--

he says only that "these ideas . . . became clear to me soon

afterward," i.e. after returning to Oxford in 1918, and he says

nothing about any reduction of philosophy to history (Knox even

hedges by calling the claim about the dating of the discovery of

absolute presuppositions an "inference" that Collingwood wished

his readers to make from the text); and (2) even if


16

the claim were made, it is arguable that it has its roots in

doctrines already present not only in his early period, but in

the works of his mature middle period as well.

Supposing that one were to have unimpeachable evidence

that there was a radical change of mind as Knox says there was:

what reasons does Knox assign for it? In his "Editor's Preface"

he gives no less than three: (1) Collingwood's mind changed:

beginning in 1932, "tiny blood-vessels began to burst in the

brain, with the result that the small parts of the brain

affected were put out of action" (IH, xxi); (2) he changed his

mind himself: he came to think, like Croce, that "philosophy as

a separate discipline is liquidated by being converted into

history" because "the skeptical and dogmatic trends, present in

Collingwood's earlier thought, triumphed over the temporary

defeat they had sustained between 1932 and 1936" (IH, xi)); and

(3) Collingwood was an inconsistent, even ficklel3 thinker:

"Collingwood believed in the coincidentia oppositorum, as many

passages in his writings testify. I am suggesting that his own

later philosophy provides a striking illustration of this

phenomenon" (IH, xvii). "He brought a powerful mind to bear on

whatever happened to be engrossing his energies . . . and he

seems to have been inclined

________________
13 Knox does not use the term, "fickle." The term is
mine; the accusation is Knox's.
17

to draw the conclusion that philosophy was simply identical with

whatever he happened to be studying most intensively at the

time" (IH, xv)).

None of these reasons are acceptable. (1) The ad hominem

"brain pathology" explanation, while certainly verified by

documentary evidence, is not detailed enough to make any

accurate assessment of what portions of Collingwood's brain (to

say nothing of his mind or judgment) were affected. The evidence

in fact seems to point to brain damage in the motor areas:

writing to Croce in January of 1939, Collingwood says that "just

a year ago . . . I was partly paralyzed by a stroke which

deprived me of the power of speech . . . . I am making good

recovery: I can use my hand and foot moderately well, and can

speak now well enough for the purposes of my profession" (LPC,

316). Even if we were to assume that Knox's acquaintance with

Collingwood was so intimate that he could detect hemorrhagic

capillaries in Collingwood's brain as early as 1933, why should

we accept such an account as philosophically relevant? Why

indeed, when Collingwood was healthy enough to write the "second

book in his series," The Principles of Art (the first being the

1933 Essay on Philosophical Method) prior to his first

debilitating stroke in 1938, and healthy enough after his stroke

to act as First Mate on a sailing schooner which voyaged for

some months in 1939 in the Mediterranean--and to write a lively

account of
18

the experience? And why again when he was clear-headed enough to

write not only the Essay on Metaphysics, which so scandalizes

Knox, but also The New Leviathan, a work which many critics felt

would alone earn him a respected place in philosophical

literature? John Passmore's two-sentence estimate of the

situation is worth quoting:

It is sometimes suggested by Idealist admirers of


Collingwood that the brain disease from which he began to
suffer in 1933 is reflected in his ultimate heterodoxies.
When one contemplates the speculative freedom of these later
works, one can only wish that his contemporaries could have
been similarly afflicted.14

(2) Asserting that Collingwood's youthful skepticism and

dogmatism overwhelmed his better judgment is less a change of

mind than a relapse; interestingly enough, Knox suggests that

both Collingwood's earlier and later philosophy represent lapses

into a youthful realism, while it is only his middle period

which steered clear of the "shoals of skepticism and the billows

of dogmatism" (IH, xviii, xiv). But the clear evidence of the

Autobiography is that as of 1939 Collingwood interpreted the

whole of his philosophy as a response to the threat of

"realism." It is incredible to think, therefore, that his

literary executor could seriously entertain the hypothesis that

in the end he merely surrendered to its doctrines. Since

Collingwood was an historian of unimpeachable ability, who knew

well how to use evidence, and was fully aware that autobiography

________________
14 John Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London,
1957), p. 306 n. 1; quoted by Rubinoff, CRM, 376 n. 17.
19

is history in which the subject happens to be oneself, if no

radical change of mind is recorded in the Autobiography it is

unlikely to be because of a lapse of memory, but rather because

Collingwood meant to deceive his readers. For what reason? Knox

fails to provide us with any.

(3) Knox's accusations of deliberate inconsistency and

vacillation by preoccupation also cannot go without challenge.

While it is easy to find passages which discuss the coincidentia

oppositorum (e.g. SM, 197-98, 249), there are others which

confine it to the scientific level of thought, where it is

contrasted with the synthesis of opposites (e.g. SM, 310). If by

a "coincidence of opposites" Knox means the simultaneous

affirmation of a pair of contradictory statements, then if

Collingwood asserted this he did indeed, as Knox charges, turn

traitor to his profession as philosopher. But the burden of

proof for this is on Knox: charges of "dogmatism and skepticism"

do not constitute sufficient evidence for the simultaneous

acceptance of a pair of contradictory statements. But if by

"opposites" Knox does not mean contradictories but contraries,

then what sense does the charge make that his later philosophy

is a prime instance of it? For it is just as true that

Collingwood accepted a coincidence of opposites as contraries in

his mature middle period--e.g. in the Essay on Philosophical

Method, where the


20

"overlap of classes" is described in terms of relations of

opposition and relations of distinction (EPM, 74-75).

Furthermore the charge of inconsistency by

preoccupational vacillation (what I have called "fickleness") is

self-refuting. Knox prefaced this remark with the observation

that it was the power of Collingwood's mind that caused him to

become so engrossed in his subject matter that he simply

identified philosophy with whatever he happened to be working on

at the time. But the charge does not bespeak a powerful mind but

a weak one--drifting this way and that according to what

"happens" to occupy it. This suggests an erratic and drifting

route for Collingwood's rudderless vessel. Opposed to this

charge (perhaps the most insulting that Knox levels at him) we

have Collingwood's autobiographical account of the logic of his

philosophical program, which leaves little room for topics to

merely "happen" to occupy his interest. He writes there that he

planned a series of books, beginning with the Essay on

Philosophical Method and continuing with The Principles of Art,

and that he planned (as of 1939) to devote all his remaining

time and energy to completing the series (A, 117-19). The

interpreter faced with a choice between Knox's version and

Collingwood's own account of the development of his thought

might prefer Knox's, but then he must supply convincing reasons

for rejecting Collingwood's. But Collingwood's version promises

to be systematic, and
21

Knox's to be haphazard and disjointed. Therefore an interpreter

cannot be blamed for choosing Collingwood's on these grounds

alone.

But when stripped of its pathophysiological banalities

and uncritical appeal to unexaminable evidence, there is a

positive service that Knox's Preface performs. Knox shows that

one of the crucial problems in Collingwood's mature philosophy,

one that may lie deeper that the more apparent problem of the

relationship of philosophy to history, is the issue of the

functions and autonomy of metaphysics and religion; Knox's

"scepticism-dogmatism" argument rests precisely on the relative

priority or independence of reason and faith. We shall see in

the next section how Collingwood's views on religion and

metaphysics set his interpreters at odds with each other. We

have Knox to thank for calling attention to this dimension of

the problem.

Since Knox's Preface, three principal interpreters of

Collingwood's mature philosophy have grappled with its central

paradox. Of these three, one--Alan Donagan--accepts as decisive

Knox's conclusion that Collingwood's thought suffered a drastic

reversal sometime between 1936 and 1938 (LPC, 1). But Donagan

rejects Knox's "brain-damage" reason for this reversal, and

argues rather that philosophically acceptable reasons must be

found for it (which he claims to provide) (LPC, 12-18). Of the

other two, Louis 0. Mink comes close to acknowledging a radical


22

change of mind, insofar as he accepts a greatly reduced version

of the reversal and locates it much earlier--between 1916 and

1924, when Collingwood discovered "dialectic," first applied in

Speculum Mentis (MHD, 20). Lionel Rubinoff, on the other hand,

roundly attacks what he aptly calls "The Radical Conversion

Hypothesis" initially woven by Knox and later embroidered by

Donagan (CRM, 21). Rubinoff dismisses Knox's reference to

Collingwood's illness as being "of no philosophical relevance"

(CRM, 18), and appears to be the only major interpreter to take

the Autobiography seriously.

In the next section we shall take up the interpretations

offered by these and several other notable commentators on

Collingwood's philosophy, and in the final section of this

chapter we shall try to sketch how the interpretation that will

be offered in succeeding chapters differs from theirs.

3. Collingwood's Interpreters: An Overview.

In 1972 there appeared a collection of fourteen essays

(all previously unpublished) entitled Critical Essays on the

Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, edited by Michael Krausz and

published by Oxford University Press. Aside from its con-tents

(which represent fairly well the current state of the question

concerning his philosophy), the mere appearance of this book

could not help but both please and displease the late Waynflete

Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy.


23

On the one hand it defies his express wishes on the

matter. Towards the end of his life Collingwood's ill health

forced him to recognize the possibility that he might not be

able to finish all the projects that he had set for himself. He

therefore wrote his Autobiography "to put on record some brief

account of the work I have not yet been able to publish, in case

I am not able to publish it in full" (A, 118). In it he wrote

this request not to be the subject of scholarly inquiry:

I am nearly fifty, and cannot in any case hope for more


than a few years in which I can do my best work. I take
this opportunity, therefore, of saying that I will not
be drawn into discussion of what I write . . . . Some
readers may wish to convince me that it is all
nonsense . . . . Some may wish to show me that on this
or that detail I am wrong. Perhaps I am; if they are in
a position to prove it, let them write not about me but
about the subject . . . . And if there are any who think
my work good, let them show their approval of it by
attention to their own. So, perhaps, I may escape
otherwise than by death the last humiliation of an aged
scholar, when his juniors conspire to print a volume of
essays and offer it to him as a sign that they now
consider him senile. (A, 118-19).

The appearance of this volume of essays indicates that it was

only by death that Collingwood escaped that "last humiliation."

But on the other hand the book is scarcely a humiliation

to the memory of the late Collingwood. On the contrary it

illustrates to a surprising degree the extent to which

Collingwood's thought is still very much alive--a liveliness

that could not have but pleased the philosopher-historian who

argued so eloquently for the notion of history as a process


24

of re-thinking past acts of thought still living in the present

(IH, 218). The contributors to this volume realized that they

were defying his wishes, but as students of his philosophy they

found his works, as one of them so succinctly put it, "too

incisive to dismiss and too unclear to adopt" (Mink, in MHD,

vii) and therefore demanding interpretation to an unusual degree.

To a reader familiar with Collingwood primarily as the

author of The Idea of History, and who accepts the ac-count of

Collingwood's development as given by T. M. Knox in the Preface,

this collection of critical essays would come as something of a

surprise. He would be startled at the wide range of topics on

which Collingwood wrote systematic treatises of some brilliance

and originality: besides philosophy of history, the topics

discussed in essays in this volume include esthetics, philosophy

of mind, philosophical method, philosophy of religion,

metaphysics, philosophy of nature, ethics, social and political

philosophy, and even philosophy of education. He would also be

surprised to find no less than half of the essays dealing with

Collingwood's views on metaphysics: as we have just seen, Knox

had found these views dogmatic, sceptical, and in general

scandalously inferior to Collingwood's best efforts in

philosophy and history (IH, xv-xvii). He would also be startled

at the evidence presented by some of the authors for

Collingwood's
25

anticipation of issues the importance of which have only

recently begun to be appreciated: a case in point being Stephen

Toulmin's essay comparing Collingwood to Thomas Kuhn, whose

essay, The Structure of Scientific Revolution, is still being

seriously debated by philosophers and historians of science

(CEPC, 201-21). The central thesis of the latter was discussed

by Collingwood some twenty years earlier in An Essay on

Metaphysics (cf. EM, 48, 74-76).

But it is disconcerting to encounter the evidence, cited

by many of the contributors to this volume, supporting Knox's

argument for the ultimate inconsistency of Collingwood's

philosophy. What is disconcerting about it is that it still

appears to be impossible for the reader to assume any consistent

or even comfortable posture toward this prickly and ill-

assimilated man. As represented by his three principal

interpreters (Donagan, Rubinoff, and Mink) he remains something

of a puzzling figure. Did his attempts to work out a

reconciliation between philosophy and history fail insofar as at

various times he subordinated the one to the other--especially

in his final, allegedly historicist phase? Are Collingwood's

earlier "idealist" reflections on the nature of philosophical

thinking truly "repudiated" by his final analytic philosophy of

mind? Was his revolutionary logic of presupposition, question

and answer really at variance with contemporary logic? Or is

there some
26

comprehensive framework detectable in Collingwood's writings--a

context which he sketched out in his youth and into which all

his later, more detailed writings fit as parts of a systematic

whole?

A case in point is Collingwood's views on religion--the

subject of his earliest publications and by most accounts one of

Collingwood's deepest and most enduring interests. We have seen

that in Knox's view the place of faith and religion is of prime

importance in evaluating Collingwood's alleged dogmatism and

scepticism. In the lead essay of Krausz's collection, however,

Collingwood's views on the religious doctrine of the fall and

redemption of man are singled out by Alan Donagan as "less

blasphemous than laughable" when used to interpret what "any

ordinary Christian believes that Christian redemption is

redemption from" (CEPC, 19). The passage Donagan cites is from

Speculum Mentis, and in it Collingwood is using the fall as a

metaphor symbolizing man's lapse into forbidden knowledge (the

error of abstraction--the separation of subject and object), and

redemption as God's acceptance of this burden of human error as

His own--presumably in the person of Jesus (SM, 302-03). For the

view of the "ordinary Christian" Donagan chooses to compare this

passage to one from John Bunyan's Grace Abounding and The

Pilgrim's Progress, which speaks of the burden of human

suffering that is the lot of every man. Donagan's objection is

that no attempt at a literal paraphrase of religious metaphor

can absorb the truth of passages like the latter


27

without remainder; but this is what Collingwood thought

philosophy could do for religious truth (CEPC, 18).

Now it is the measure of the difference between Donagan

and Lionel Rubinoff that the same passage that Donagan holds up

for ridicule is later cited by Rubinoff as "one of the most

important passages in all of his writings" (CEPC, 101).

Rubinoff's reading of Collingwood is almost a literal rendering

of passages such as this one from The Idea of History:

The task of religious thought and religious practice


(for in religion the theoretical and practical
activities are fused into one) is to find the relation
between these two supposed conceptions of myself as
finite and God as infinite . . . . (I)n religion the
life of reflection is concentrated in its intensest
form, and . . . the special problems of theoretical and
practical life all take their special forms by
segregation out of the body of the religious
consciousness, and retain their vitality only so far as
they preserve their connection with it and with each
other in it (IH, 314-15).

Rubinoff argues that Collingwood's use of the religious metaphor

of the fall and redemption are apt precisely because

Collingwood's entire philosophy is a sustained attempt at

reconciliation of all the divergent tendencies within man--

subject vs. object, thought vs. action, faith vs. reason,

history vs. philosophy, etc.--and the first level on which that

reconciliation takes place is that of religion, with

Christianity as its highest manifestation (CEPC, 106).


28

The two articles by Donagan and Rubinoff therefore take

radically opposing views on the same issue, and their divergent

interpretations extend to the whole of Collingwood's philosophy.

Donagan argues that the collapse of Collingwood's program for an

idealistic metaphysics of the Absolute (in his early philosophy

as expressed in Speculum Mentis and An Essay on Philosophical

Method) left him with a crippled historicist substitute and no

viable philosophy of religion (CEPC, 18). Rubinoff holds that

for Collingwood not only is absolute idealism the only

philosophy adequate to the Christian solution to the twin

problems of alienation and irrationalism that plague the modern

world, but religion itself (at least as Christianity) is a

necessary condition of the possibility of all other forms of

experience--presumably (using the scheme of Speculum Mentis)

art, science, history, and philosophy (CEPC, 86-88).

The reader's suspicion that Donagan and Rubinoff have

their own, divergent meanings for the expression, "absolute

idealism," is partly confirmed by the fact that Donagan

formulates the position in terms of an anti-realist or anti-

abstraction principle (viz. that all abstractions are partial

truths and to that extent erroneous) which is explicit in

Collingwood's early writings, while for Rubinoff the term refers

to the "unified life of the mind," the divisions of which mark

the various subject-object alienations within contemporary

consciousness. If these
29

positions appear as obverse and reverse of the same coin, the

way to distinguish heads from tails would be that Rubinoff

accepts, and Donagan denies, that something describable as "the

absolute standpoint" is possible.

In his book, The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood,

Donagan forcefully (if not always persuasively) argues that the

reason that Collingwood abandoned the idealistic position of his

youth is that he came to realize, from his analysis of mental

functions in The Principles of Art (1938) that all thinking is

conceptual and hence abstract.15 But this position renders

anything like "absolute knowledge" (an absolute identity between

subject and object) impossible, and therefore represents a

"repudiation" of his earlier idealism, in which abstraction (the

cardinal doctrine of realism--on Donagan's reading of

Collingwood) is regarded as the root of all error, and itself a

falsification (LPC, 14, 47-50, 285-89; cf. CEPC, 18). The

philosophy of mind that survives self-destruction by

contradiction forms Collingwood's "later philosophy" which

parallels conclusions of Ludwig Wittgenstein and anticipates

Gilbert Ryle's concept of mind (cf. LPC, 37, 42-43).

____________________
15 The references that Donagan cites at LPC, 14 and 47-
54 to support this assertion--namely, PA, 254 and NL, 7.22, 7.3-
7.31, and 7.38--do not make the claim that "all thinking is
conceptual and hence abstract." See below, pp. 562-76.
30

Donagan reconstructs this philosophy of mind around four

principles: (1) the Principle of Intentionality ("if a man is

conscious he must be conscious of something"); (2) the Principle

of Order ("if a man is conscious of one of his own acts of

consciousness, then it is not by that act itself, but by another

act of consciousness which may be said to be of a higher

order");16 (3) the Law of Primitive Survivals ("when a function

of consciousness (B) is brought into existence having a lower-

order function (A) as its object, unless the lower-order

function (A) continues to exist in its primitive state, the

higher-order function (B) cannot exist at all"); and (4) the Law

of Contingency ("the earlier terms in a series of mental

functions do not determine the later") (LPC, 27-29). In the

resulting hierarchy of levels of consciousness, Donagan argues,

there is no upper limit (LPC, 29,91-92); therefore there is no

such thing as 'absolute knowledge" as an upper limit to

knowledge (cf. LPC, 258).

Lionel Rubinoff, on the other hand, argues persuasively

(if not always forcefully) in his own book, Collingwood and the

___________________
16 None of Donagan's references to Collingwood's texts
for evidence for the "principle of order" support Donagan's
formulation and subsequent employment of this principle: at LPC,
28 and more directly at LPC, 105 and 168, Donagan cites NL,
4.31, 5.91 and 5.92 as evidence that Collingwood's philosophy of
mind "was fundamentally anti-Cartesian; . . . he repudiated
Descartes' doctrine that acts of consciousness are, as it were,
self-illuminating" (LPC, 25). In Donagan's view, Collingwood
came to hold that no act of consciousness can have itself as an
object (LPC, 108, 167-68). For Collingwood's views on self-
consciousness and Cartesianism, see NL, 1.84-1.85, 5.34-5.39;
IH, 141, 291-94, 297, 306; PA, 206, 222-23, 247-52.
31

Reform of Metaphysics, that such a position could never satisfy

Collingwood, whose whole philosophy is an extended argument for

rapprochement--including the rapprochement of subject and object

in absolute knowledge. There was no radical conversion" in

Collingwood's development, Rubinoff argues, because Collingwood

remained true to the idealistic program laid out in Speculum

Mentis (CRM, 23). Taking his clue from the description in

Speculum Mentis of the three ways that the "prize of truth" can

be awarded (to one, to two or more, or to none of the competing

forms of experience), Rubinoff constructs a framework of "three

ontological levels of experience" on which all of Collingwood's

writings can be located.

At the first level, consciousness assumes an absolute


distinction between subject and object, and views the whole
of reality as an expression of whatever experience it is
presently identified with. . . . At the second level, the
distinction between subject and object remains but each
experience now regards itself as only one among a variety
of equally valid standpoints. At the third level the
subject-object distinction has been finally overcome and
some recognition is given to the fact that the forms of
experience, rather than being coordinate species of a
genus, are on the contrary a scale of overlapping forms. On
the basis of these distinctions the implicit rationale of
Collingwood's published works may now be reconstructed.
According to this reconstruction each work may be seen as
exemplifying one or another type of philosophy operating on
one or more of the three levels of experience (CRM, 29-30).

Rubinoff's strategy in answering the charges of Knox and

Donagan, therefore, is to locate the source of one of a pair of

conflicting
32

assertions on one level of this ontological schema, and the

other on a different level. Thus when Collingwood asserts in The

New Leviathan that there is no upper limit to the levels of

consciousness he is speaking at the "second level" in which new

forms of experience are always possible because they are

regarded merely as coordinate species of a genus. But when

Collingwood asserts in Speculum Mentis that absolute knowledge

forms the upper limit of forms of experience, he is speaking

from the "third level" at which subject and object are

identified, the "absolute standpoint" (cf. CRM, 69-73, 369-72).

Where Collingwood's project seems to falter, Rubinoff calls up a

reserve battery of idealistic arguments, from Hegel to Husserl,

and from Bradley to Bosanquet and Blanshard.17 And the summit of

Collingwood's idealistic efforts is a description of mind as

"pure act''l8—which stands in stark contrast to Donagan's static

hierarchy of levels of abstract concepts, related by the logic

of the Principia Mathematica.

___________________
17 The most noteworthy use of idealistic arguments in
Rubinoff's book are the sections dealing with the logic of the
"concrete universal" (interestingly enough in the chapter on
"Philosophy as Absolute Knowledge") and with the theory of mind
as pure act. CRM, 150-83, 315-22.

18 Rubinoff uses in this portion of his argument


Collingwood's translation of G. de Ruggiero's Modern Philosophy.
CRM, 315-22.
33

To the extent that he, too, finds a temporarily

schizophrenic Collingwood unacceptable, Louis O. Mink sides with

Rubinoff--but not by calling up the arguments of Hegelian

idealism. In his perceptive and refreshingly tactful book, Mind,

History, and Dialectic: The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood,

Mink asserts with Rubinoff, and against Donagan, that

Collingwood is a dialectical philosopher rather than an

analytical one. But he holds, in direct opposition to Rubinoff,

that Collingwood "retained dialectic and abandoned the absolute"

(MHD, 78). And like Donagan, Mink finds Collingwood's religious

philosophy the least interesting of all his thought. Mink goes

so far as to say that Collingwood had no sympathy for the

philosophy of religion, and that Religion and Philosophy was

Collingwood's only non-dialectical book (MHD, 16, 20, 260 n. 7).

But Mink is no subscriber to Donagan's thesis that Collingwood's

later philosophy of mind represents a complete break with his

earlier philosophical program as exemplified in Speculum Mentis

and made explicit in the Essay on Philosophical Method (MHD, ix,

16, 20).

Mink employs his considerable interpretative skills in

bringing out the "recessive" themes in Collingwood's philosophy.

In doing so he tries to display the "figure in the carpet" (a

tripartite dialectic of experience, of concepts, and of mind)

that makes it possible to soften many of the apparent

absurdities and contradictions in Collingwood's phil-


34

osophy (MHD, 80; cf. MHD, 52, 118, 237). In his essay for the

Krausz collection, for example, he takes up Collingwood's famous

description of history as the "rethinking of past acts of

thought" and shows that each term of the expression requires

qualifications in the light of Collingwood's "dialectic of

process." In Mink's reconstruction "history" in this expression

must be taken as a philosophical rather than an empirical

concept, and is thus subject to the characterization of

philosophical concepts that Collingwood gave in his Essay

on_Philosophical Method. As a philosophical concept it has a

dialectical structure, which means that the elements designated

by the term "history" are related in a developing series or a

"scale of forms" (CEPC, 157-72).

Mink describes such a dialectical system as having four

properties: it is (1) connective (the terms in the series are

related generically to a single essence or general description),

(2) cumulative (members of the series are preserved and modified

in successive forms), (3) asymmetrical (no member is the mere

duplicate of another, but rather differs both in degree and in

kind from the others), and (4) non-deterministic (in the series

a prior term is necessary but not a sufficient condition for the

generation of its successor). Mink argues that since

intellectual history (e.g. the history of science, art, or

religion) deals with a subject which involves acts that are

purposively
35

connected, cumulative in effect, non-cyclic and non-

deterministic in their growth, it is clear that it answers to a

dialectical system. All history (in the philosophical sense) is

therefore the re-thinking (i.e. the dialectical analysis) of

past acts of thought (CEPC, 172-76).

But while these efforts by sympathetic admirers of

Collingwood's philosophy may go a long way towards giving the

reader an understanding of the intricacies and articulations of

Collingwood's philosophy, their solutions to its central paradox

would fail to satisfy many of the other contributors to the

Krauts volume--and especially as that paradox is stated in the

Essay on Metaphysics. Thus W. H. Walsh points out that when

Collingwood wrote in that work that "absolute presuppositions"

(the true object of the metaphysician's search rather than the

"pure being" of the ontologists, which Collingwood rejects as an

empty concept) are neither true nor false, he qualified himself

as a "metaphysical neutralist"--Walsh's term for a philosopher

who limits himself to description only, refusing to apply

criteria which would allow one to make a judgment on the truth

or falsity, reality or unreality, etc. of the object described.

As merely descriptive and factually encountered factors

operative in the thought of those who are engaged in any piece

of scientific thinking, such presuppositions may escape the

positivistic condemnation of metaphysical assertions as neither

factually verifiable nor analytically tautologies, but they are


36

also rendered immune to any sort of justification--they can

merely be reported. Metaphysics is thus an historical science,

as Collingwood's central thesis of the Essay on Metaphysics

maintains; but how then account for the refutability, adequacy,

or success of one set of "consupponible" presuppositions to

another (CEPC, 134-53; especially, 142-46, 149)?

Similarly, Stephen Toulmin argues that although

Collingwood was one of the few pioneer thinkers to come to grips

with the central and still unanswered metaphysical question

about conceptual changes in the history of science (or

scientific revolutions, as Kuhn was later to call them), his

"relativism" (roughly the equivalent to Walsh's "neutralism")

prevented him from giving a rational account of why they occur.

Instead Collingwood resorted to a quasi-causal, psychologistic

explanation in terms of unconscious mental "strains" occurring

in a constellation or set of presuppositions (Kuhn's "crisis in

normal science") which are "taken up" or resolved when a new

conceptual framework replaces an old one (in Kuhn's terms, when

a new "paradigm science" appears, completing a conceptual

revolution). Toulmin's dissatisfaction with both Kuhn and

Collingwood adds fuel to Walsh's charge: if two sets of

presuppositions differ, must there not be some mutual

presuppositions with respect to which, or by reference to which,

they are in agreement (CEPC, 201-21, especially 209-13)?


37

Finally, Nathan Rotenstreich adds his eloquent voice to

this dissenting chorus with a deft discussion of Collingwood's

proposed reform of metaphysics vis-a-vis the tradition he

proposed to reform--Aristotle, Spinoza, Kant, and Hegel.

Rotenstreich shows that as often as not when Collingwood used

historical examples of a metaphysician (in Collingwood's

reformed sense) who pointed out the presuppositions of science

in one period or another, he (Collingwood) ignored the

evaluative activities of these same philosophers, who were not

concerned with reportage only, but with justification and

critique as well. What remains of Collingwood's truncated

version of metaphysical history is what Rotenstreich calls a

"cultural anthropology of metaphysics," which "does not

distinguish between the intention and the intentionality of a

metaphysical system which attempts to be categorical" (CEPC,

179-221; esp. 179-80, 197-99).

From this seeming dead end two escapes are possible:

expansion and revision. Both are represented by essays in the

Krausz volume. The first is taken by Errol Harris. Like

Rubinoff, Harris is a sympathetic student of Collingwood and of

the great idealists of this and the last centuries, and he

supplements Collingwood's thought by evoking a frankly

idealistic context for it. But unlike Rubinoff, Harris does not

hesitate to criticize some of Collingwood's positions as

untenable.19 In his essay for the


38

Krausz volume, Harris renews his argument with Gilbert Ryle over

Collingwood's defense of the Ontological argument, first carried

out in the pages of Mind in 1935 and 1936, just after

Collingwood's Essay on Philosophical Method was published.20

Ryle had argued that Collingwood's use of Anselm's argument made

the common idealistic mistake of thinking that concrete matters

of fact (concerning the existence of anything whatever) could be

established by the use of a priori arguments that can only

establish their conclusions hypothetically. Harris' response is

to defend the idealist's use of such arguments by showing the

legitimacy of "categorical universal" judgments, "the concrete

universal" of Bosanquet and Bradley, and the Absolute of Hegel

(CEPC, 113-33).

Michael Krausz, on the other hand, takes the alternative

route. Collingwood had said in the Essay on Metaphysics (1) that

all questions

_________________
19 Cf. Errol E. Harris, "Collingwood on Eternal
Problems," Philosophical Quarterly, I, no. 3 (April, 1951), pp.
228-41. Reprinted in his Nature, Mind and Modern Science
(London, 1954), pp. 3-42.

20 G. Ryle, "Mr. Collingwood and the Ontological


Argument," Mind, XLIV (April, 1935), pp. 137-51; E. E. Harris,
"Mr. Ryle and the Ontological Argument," Mind, XLV (October,
1937), pp. 474-80; G. Ryle, "Back to the Ontological Argument,"
Mind, XLVI (January, 1937), pp. 53-57. These essays are printed
in John H. Hick and Arthur C. McGill, eds., The Many-Faced
Argument (New York, 1967), pp. 246-74.
39

have presuppositions from which they logically arise; (2) that

to be true or false a proposition has to be an answer to a

question; and (3) that absolute pre-suppositions are neither

true nor false because they are not answers to questions, but

stand relative to all questions, in a body of inquiry, as their

presuppositions. Krausz argues that Collingwood's formulation of

the relation of absolute presuppositions may be interpreted to

mean either that it cannot be the answer to a question in any

given systematic inquiry, or in any systematic inquiry whatever.

In the second case it is impossible to explain how what is taken

as an absolute presupposition at one time can become a relative

presupposition (i.e. one that is itself an answer to a question,

and therefore verifiably true or false) at another. Krausz's

strategy is to argue in favor of the first interpretation, which

involves altering Collingwood's theory of meaning to conform

with more contemporarily acceptable accounts, notably that of P.

F. Strawson, which allow for senses of truth and falsity not

specified by Collingwood (CEPC, 222-40).

It is unnecessary to delve any further into Krausz's

collection of critical essays,21 since we have at this point a

fairly synoptic

_______________
21 There are included in this volume illuminating
articles by W. van Leyden, Peter Jones, and Richard Wollheim on
Collingwood's esthetics and philosophy of mind; by Leon J.
Goldstein on the constitution of the historical past (which
deserves special marks for its care in comparing Collingwood's
actual historical praxis, in his writings on Roman Britain,
40

overview of the range of alternatives available to the reader

interested in finding out the extent of Collingwood's

coherence--or incoherence--as a philosopher. Many of these ideas

and issues will arise again in chapters to come, but before

stating our own reasons for rejecting the approaches of the

principal interpreters of Collingwood some sort of summary of

conclusions is in order. Table I sets forth observations which

seem to follow from our brief survey of Collingwood's

interpreters.

We shall see in Chapter II that the list of issues

which we have found to be the central core of concern to

Collingwood's interpreters turns out, interestingly enough, to

be the very set of issues that Collingwood himself presents in

his Autobiography. And yet not one of the contributors to this

volume of essays seriously considered the Autobiography as an

interpretation valid for the whole of his philosophy. This is

all the more the pity, because it seems that Collingwood is

worthy of at least that degree of attention that he lavished on

the unfortunate

_________________
with the theory of historical imagination in The Idea of
History--perhaps the first time an author has approached
Collingwood's work on the philosophy of history on his own
terms); by Sherman M. Stanage on "Collingwood's Phenomenology of
Education: Person and the Self-Recognition of the Mind" (based
on a few scant remarks by Collingwood on the speaker-hearer
situation and the learning of language, in The Principles of
Art); and by A. J. M. Milne on Collingwood's ethics and
political theory (which might serve as an antidote to Walsh's
re-marks in an earlier essay about Collingwood's lack of
appreciation for the social sciences.)
41
TABLE 1

THE INTERPRETATIONS OF COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY


_______________________________________________________________

1. The major issues with which Collingwood's interpreters are


concerned are:

a. his attitudes towards, and arguments about, realism and


idealism;

b. his formulation of the logic of questions, answers, and


presuppositions, and in general his position on
philosophical methodology;

c. his remarks about the nature of history and the


relationship of history to philosophy, and especially of
history to metaphysics; and

d. the way or ways in which he worked out a reconciliation


of all the disparate forms of knowledge (religion, art,
science, history, philosophy) within an overall
philosophy of mind.

2. The major alternatives which interpreters have presented for


dealing with the central paradoxes of Collingwood's
philosophy are as follows:

a. since Collingwood's philosophy is not coherent as it


stands, it is necessary to divide his published works into
two or more groups, based on the contradictory premises on
which they are based, and then argue the relative merits
of one group over the other or others;

b. since Collingwood's philosophy is not coherent as it


stands, it is necessary to propose a revision of a portion
of it in order to render the remainder coherent;

c. since Collingwood's philosophy is coherent as it stands,


its apparent inconsistency can be resolved by assimilating
it to a larger and more complete schema--e.g. historical
idealism;

d. since Collingwood's philosophy is coherent as it stands,


its apparent inconsistency can be resolved by showing the
essential core of truth or coherence that unifies its
diverse aspects.
______________________________________________________________
42

Albert Memorial during his military service in World War I. For

in so much of what he writes he seems, like the lines he quotes

from Wordsworth's "Leech-Gatherer" to describe this monument,

Like one whom I had met with in a dream; Or like a man from
some far region sent, To give me human strength, by apt
admonishment (A, 29).

It would be apt, therefore, to admonish oneself as an

interpreter of Collingwood to ask what relationship there is

between what he did and what he had tried to do--the very

question he wished to put to Scott, the architect of the Albert

Memorial--and to start by taking seriously what he said he had

tried to do, before rejecting or revising what he did.

4. On Interpreting Collingwood.

The very issue that is at the center of controversy

concerning Collingwood's philosophy recoils upon the method an

interpreter chooses to employ in dealing with that philosophy.

For (1) if history and philosophy are not identical, then in

dealing with Collingwood's philosophy in an historical manner,

the question of its truth or falsity cannot arise: the historian

would merely point to the "facts" of the matter, record any

lapses in coherence, and let the matter stand. And in dealing

with it in a philosophical manner, all the works of Collingwood

suddenly assume equal standing, and it becomes impossible to see

how later positions develop out of earlier ones, or how one work

has priority over another. One is there-


43

fore stuck again with apparent contradictions in his fundamental

assertions. But (2) if history and philosophy are identical,

then one cannot deal with Collingwood's philosophy in a non-

evaluative manner: understanding what he said at various points

in his career would therefore be only a prelude to measuring its

implicit promise against its explicit performance, and

evaluating the outcome. But this alternative necessitates the

evaluation of some texts as central and others as peripheral,

and therefore choosing the "facts" to which one is to attend.

But if in getting caught up in interpretative

controversies we were to sidestep the issue of truth in

Collingwood's philosophy, we would be showing that we had not

learned the main lessons he wished to teach us about history: to

think historically is not to merely record facts and refrain

from judgment. History is essentially a judgmental affair,

because it involves selective attention to a chosen set of

facts. This is supremely the case when it comes to the history

of philosophy, where the "facts" to which the historian

selectively attends are meanings and meaning-complexes. One must

therefore take a philosopher for what he said (because this

constitutes all the evidence we have for what he was thinking)

but only as a symbol for for what he meant. Conflicts in

evidence (e.g. contradiction in the texts) may make it difficult

or
44

impossible to get beyond the symbol to the meaning, but this

then is the point at which the borders between history and

philosophy become precarious. But since so much of Collingwood's

thought resides here, we must not fear to explore these disputed

territories.

To think philosophically about the past, according to

Collingwood, is also to take it as intentional--that is, as

something already deliberated upon and thought about with us in

mind as the intended heirs to a mental estate. The question one

ought to ask with respect to Collingwood's philosophy should

then be not what chronological series of literary events

occurred in his lifetime, but rather what order or sequence of

thoughts he intended for his readers to follow if they are to

understand his thinking. Now it is in his Autobiography that

Collingwood publicly specified for his philosophical heirs what

sort of program he wished them to inherit, and in it he tried to

make clear how they should proceed to lay claim to this

inheritance. We therefore respectfully decline to accept the

limited inheritance offered to us by Mr. T. M. Knox, and declare

our intentions to carry our suit to a higher court. In doing so

we propose to accept his Autobiography as Collingwood's only

public, legal will.

In arguing our case we shall seriously attempt to live

up to the highest standards of historical scholarship--these

standards being those governing the philosophical interpretation


45

of another philosopher's literary remains. Most of the canons

for such an endeavor are usually given in negative terms. Two of

them were cited by Collingwood himself in the Autobiography: (1)

never accept criticism of any author before satisfying yourself

of its relevance; and (2) reconstruct the problem, or never

think you understand any statement made by a philosopher until

you have decided, with the utmost possible accuracy, what the

question is to which he means it for an answer (A, 74). To these

we add the five interpreter's fallacies stated by Richard

Robinson22 (which we shall number consecutively to the two

Collingwood canons just cited). One should avoid committing any

or all of the following atrocities to a philosophical text: (3)

mosaic interpretation (the habit of laying any amount of weight

on an isolated text or single sentence, without determining

whether it is a passing remark or a settled part of your

author's thinking); (4) misinterpretation by abstraction

(assuming that because an author mentions X and X appears to the

interpreter to be a case of Y. that the author also meant,

asserted, or was aware of Y); (6) the fallacy of insinuating the

________________
22 Richard Robinson, Plato's Earlier Dialectic (Oxford,
1953), pp. 1-5. It is interesting that Robinson seems to
envision the task of an interpreter in terms which sound like a
direct quotation from Collingwood: "The purpose of an
interpreter . . . is to make himself and others rethink the very
thoughts that were thought by someone long ago. Interpretation
is not just any sort of commentary, including the revelation of
the historical causes and consequences of a given thought. It is
the re-creation of that thought" (Ibid., pp. 5-6).
46

future (assuming that the author held doctrines that did not

become explicit until later); and (7) going beyond a thinker's

last word (ascribing to him not merely all the steps he took in

a certain direction but the next step too).23

There may be more rules than this, but these are the

most helpful ones this author has ever encountered, and suffice

for the task at hand. They serve to eliminate every

interpretation of Collingwood that has yet been offered. For (1)

would it not be an error to accept Knox's criticism of

Collingwood's radical conversion to historicism as a lapse into

dogmatism and scepticism due to a cerebrovascular accident,

without satisfying ourselves first that it is relevant? And (2)

would it not be a mistake to reconstruct Collingwood's mature

philosophy of mind, as Donagan does, without understanding what

the question was to which it was meant for an answer? And was

this question not "How can a thinking person understand his own

mind without resorting to the errors of realism?" And (3) is it

not a mosaic interpretation when Rubinoff takes the metaphorical

remark in Speculum Mentis about the three ways the "prize of

truth" may be awarded, and then erects on this frail motif the

"three ontological levels of consciousness" on which are mapped

all of Collingwood's

_______________
23 We also declare ourselves bound by the full set of
grammatical and logical rules necessary for any discourse to
make sense and be coherent. These we omit stating because they
are assumed in any piece of rational inquiry.
47

writings, from books to essays to letters and even translations?

24 And (4) is it not a case of misinterpretation by abstraction

when Mink rules out Collingwood's views on religion and its

philosophy (in the book by that name) on the grounds that they

are not dialectical? For how does Mink know that because

Collingwood argues that philosophy is at least dialectical that

he would accept the further statement that that is all it is?

Does he not say it is also analytical, and is that not what he

is engaged in doing in Religion and Philosophy? And (5) is it

not a case of misinterpretation by inference to assert, as once

again Donagan does, that because in Speculum Mentis Collingwood

connected the doctrine of realism to the mental function of

abstraction, and argued that all abstraction is falsification,

and then later in The Principles of Art argues (if he in fact

did so) that all concepts are abstract, that he therefore

"repudiated" his earlier rejection of realism? And (6) is it not

an insinuation of the future to argue, as Donagan does, that

Collingwood's philosophy of mind is a specimen of linguistic

analysis of the sort carried out in Ryle's Concept of Mind, and

then to assert (on the deception of this analogy with Ryle) that

it is fundamentally anti-Cartesian? But on the other hand (if we

may be permitted

_________________
24 I do not wish to imply that Rubinoff is the only
interpreter to commit this error: Donagan and Mink are equally
guilty of mosaic interpretation--Donagan's four principles of
the philosophy of mind and Mink's tripartite dialectic of
experience, concepts, and mind are also examples of it.
48

to invent a new version of (6), is it not an insinuation of the

past to justify Collingwood's philosophy of mind, as Rubinoff

does, by appeal to the idealism of Hegel? And (7) is it not

going beyond an author's last word to argue, as Rubinoff does,

that because Collingwood took several steps in the direction of

a descriptive phenomenology of consciousness in Speculum Mentis,

that he therefore would take the next step too, and endorse a

"transcendental phenomenology" of mind (CRM, 54, 152-53, 311-15)?

And yet historical scholarship, like history itself, is

a developmental process, as Collingwood says, in which

successive terms sum up and go beyond previous terms without

being necessitated by them. Our own interpretation of

Collingwood is itself subject to this description. Therefore in

what follows we shall see how Collingwood's philosophy, in

senses yet to be specified, displays most of the characteristics

that his interpreters have attributed to it--perhaps even some

that they did not:

(1) As Knox points out, Collingwood's most apparent

problem is his "historicism"--his tendency to identify

philosophy with history; and beyond this is a deeper, less

apparent problem of establishing a workable relationship between

metaphysics (which Collingwood recognized to be at the center of

philosophy) and religious faith. And as Knox (and later such

authors as Walsh, Toulmin, and Rotenstreich) argue, his final

49
position as stated in the Essay on Metaphysics does display

aspects both sceptical and dogmatic. But unlike Knox, we find no

need to posit a radical reversal in his philosophy, and by

viewing the paradoxical statements of the Essay on Metaphysics

in the light of the overall philosophical orientation provided

in his Autobiography, and the development of his thought in his

published writings, this dogmatism and scepticism are

transformed into something more akin to conviction and necessary

self-criticism--philosophical virtues rather than vices. For

there is no need to take the Essay on Metaphysics as a work all

by itself, abstracted from his other writings. When restored to

its rightful context, its central paradox is illuminated and

refined, and the limits of its applicability are re-established;

metaphysics may be more than an historical science, but

Collingwood's point is that it is at least that.

(2) And as Donagan argues, Collingwood's unique

achievement in his later writings is a philosophy of mind that

is carried out by arguments which stress the importance of

expressive, linguistic structures in the life of thought. But

unlike Donagan we find no grounds for arguing that his final

philosophy of mind "repudiates" his earlier anti-realistic

stance, or even that it was "anti-Cartesian" or anti-intuitional

in denying the thesis that self-consciousness is possible at

all. The linguistic basis for his conclusions was present even

in his
50

early writings, and he never varied in his assault on what he

took to be the main tenet of realistic philosophy. For

Collingwood, refuting this central tenet does not mean

maintaining that "all abstraction is falsification," as Donagan

thinks, but rather it involves showing that the proposition

"knowing makes no difference to the object known" is false.

(3) And as Mink argues, the central "figure in the

carpet" of Collingwood's philosophy is recognizable in the

methodology first explicitly spelled out in the Essay on

Philosophical Method--a work that is, as Knox first said it was,

a philosophical classic. We also will agree that the philosophy

of mind that Collingwood worked out in his later writings

exhibits the structure of a scale of forms, a structure first

exhibited in Speculum Mentis, which Mink calls Collingwood's

first dialectical book. However we find no need to argue, as

Mink does, that Collingwood "discovered" dialectic after writing

Religion and Philosophy, nor that Collingwood had no sympathy or

interest in the philosophy of religion. On the contrary we will

find that Collingwood's philosophy is profoundly religious, and

although he discontinued talking about "absolute knowledge" in

his later writings, he modified his view of a philosophical

absolute rather than dropping it altogether (as his discussion

of the ontological argument in both the Essay on Philosophical

Method
51

and the Essay on Metaphysics shows). And although some of the

functions of a philosophical absolute were taken over by

"absolute presuppositions," it is clear that Collingwood took as

one of the absolute presuppositions of contemporary science the

doctrine of Christianity that God exists.

(4) And as Rubinoff argues, Collingwood's philosophy as

a whole cannot be understood apart from his overall orientation

towards a rapprochement of the alienating forces typical of the

contemporary human situation. The paradigm for this rapprochement

was indeed the relation of philosophy and history, which the

position Collingwood called "realism" was committed to ignoring.

And the means that Collingwood used to re-establish continuity

between forms of knowledge was by arguments which are, in some

sense of the term, "idealistic," relying as they do on premises

that are incompatible with the realistic thesis that "knowing

makes no difference to the object known." However there is no

need to call in Hegel's aufheben--or even Bradley's experiential

Absolute--to save Collingwood's rapprochement project. If

because of irreconcilable contradictions on fundamental issues

Collingwood's philosophy cannot be approached on its own terms,

it must be declared to be to that extent inconsistent and in

need of revision, rather than declared to be incomplete and in

need of assimilation to, or absorption by, the philosophy of

Hegel. If we are in debt to Rubinoff for exposing the


52

fallacy of the "radical conversion hypothesis," we also declare

ourselves free of his own fallacy, the "radical consistency

hypothesis." The plain fact is that Collingwood did change his

mind on several issues, and stated publicly that he had done

so--but not on the fundamental issues discussed in the

Autobiography, as we shall see.

In short, the thesis of our interpretation is that it

is possible to make sense of Collingwood on his own terms, if we

are careful to avoid making the errors of our interpretative

predecessors. Perhaps by so doing we shall avoid the wrath of

the shade of Collingwood, who warned us of a haunting should we

fail to take heed to the requirements of philosophical

interpretation:

The reader . . . must approach his philosophical author


precisely as if he were a poet, in the sense that he must
seek in his work the expression of an individual experience,
something which the writer has actually lived through, and
something which the reader must live through in his turn by
entering into the writer's mind with his own. To this basic
and ultimate task of following or understanding his author,
coming to see what he means by sharing his experience, the
task of criticizing his doctrine, or determining how far it
is true and how far false, is altogether secondary. A good
reader, like a good listener, must be quiet in order to be
attentive; able to refrain from obtruding his own thoughts,
the better to apprehend those of the writer; not passive,
but using his activity to follow where he is led, not to
find a path of his own. A writer who does not deserve this
silent, uninterrupting attention does not deserve to be read
at all (EPM, 215).
CHAPTER II

THE AUTOBIOGRAPHICAL INTERPRETATION


OF COLLINGWOOD'S PHILOSOPHY

1. The Autobiography as Literary Evidence.

In an essay written just two years prior to the

publication of his own Autobiography, Collingwood wrote the

following account of the requirements for adequate

autobiographical composition:

If anyone of us were setting out to compose such an account


((viz. an autobiography - "a strictly historical account of
my own past")), he would be confronted with two kinds of
tasks . . . . The first task is that of recollecting: he
must search his memory for a vision of past experiences,
and use various means of stimulating it, for example by
reading letters and books that he once wrote, revisiting
places associated in his mind with certain events, and so
forth. When this is done, he has before his mind a
spectacle of the relevant parts of his own past life; he
sees a young man undergoing such and such experiences, and
knows that this young man was himself. But now begins the
second task. He must not merely know that this young man
was himself, he must try to rediscover that young man's
thoughts. And here recollection is a treacherous
guide . . . because thought is not wholly entangled in the
flow of experience, so that we constantly reinterpret our
past thoughts and assimilate them to those we are thinking
now. There is only one way in which this tendency is to be
checked. If I want to be sure that twenty years ago a
certain thought was really in my mind, I must have evidence
of it. That evidence must be a book or letter or the like
that I then wrote . . . . Only by having some such evidence
before me, and interpreting it fairly and squarely, can I
prove to myself that I did think thus. Having done so, I
rediscover my past self, and re-enact these thoughts as my

53
54

thoughts; judging now better than I could then, it is to be


hoped, their merits and defects. (IH, 295-96, emphasis
mine.)

It would be hard to believe that a trained archeologist

and historian, having just written such a clear account of the

criteria for autobiography, an account which expresses such a

hard-headed view of what counts as evidence for such a literary

project, could have forgotten about them completely when it came

time two years later to write his own autobiography. Yet such is

the charge of more than one of Collingwood's interpreters--

including the man Collingwood named as his literary executor

(cf. IH, x-xi).

Since the charge has been made it must be confronted in

the same spirit of historical objectivity to which Collingwood

himself subscribed. In the second part of his task, Collingwood

wrote, "there is nothing which the autobiographer does . . .

that the historian could not do for another" (IH, 296). If the

autobiographer, in short, performs his task with the same rigor

that is expected of historians, he functions as an historian of

a subject matter which merely happens to be the events of his

own life. If in fact Collingwood was in good faith with this

principle when he wrote his Autobiography (and he at least

claimed that he was--see A, 107 and "Preface"), his own

interpretation of his intellectual development (and this is the

main concern of the Autobiography) stands as one among other


55

such interpretations, each of which must be judged in accordance

with the same criteria: each must be an interpretation of

Collingwood's thought, based on the evidence provided by

Collingwood's published writings, critically evaluated.

One serious objection to taking the Autobiography in

this way is that at the time Collingwood wrote it (1938) two of

his major works (An Essay on Metaphysics and The New Leviathan)

and several articles had not yet been written. Consequently a

good part of his interpretation of what his philosophy actually

achieves remains speculation about what he intended it to

achieve, and not what, on the basis of documentary evidence, it

already had achieved. It is because his work remained incomplete

at the time of the writing of his Autobiography that several of

his interpreters have felt justified in rejecting the latter and

arguing that his later works break entirely with the positions

he had maintained prior to his writing of the Autobiography.

But while it is certainly quite appropriate to raise the

question of the de facto adherence of these later works to the

philosophical doctrines of Collingwood's earlier writings, or of

the adherence of both of these to the interpretation offered in

the Autobiography, it is capriciously arbitrary at best, and

maliciously prejudicial at worst, to exclude the latter as a

possible interpretation valid for the whole of Collingwood's

philosophy, including the later works. That the


56

Autobiography should not be allowed a privileged position among

the interpretations offered of Collingwood's philosophy is a

defensible corollary of the principle cited by Collingwood above

(viz. that correct autobiography is an application of correct

historiography); but that it should be given no consideration is

just as clearly ruled out by the same principle.

A second objection is that in addition to proposing an

interpretation or an account of the development of his thought,

Collingwood's Autobiography also cites evidence to support this

interpretation, and since some of this evidence is not publicly

available, the interpretation based on this evidence is also

open to question.

Now the evidence in the Autobiography is of three sorts:

(1) direct statements by Collingwood of positions he holds, at

least at the time of the writing of the Autobiography; (2)

references to published works that he had completed some years

before, some with and some without qualifying remarks to

indicate the extent to which he still agreed or disagreed with

what he had written; and (3) references to unpublished

manuscripts. Certainly there is no difficulty with taking

statements from the first group as evidence that as of 1938

Collingwood held the positions that he says he does. And just as

certainly, statements from the second can be checked for their

accuracy by consulting the published works


57

to which they refer. Where such reference is factually mistaken,

one can only register the lapse and credit Collingwood only as

holding to the position he is discussing (if he gives textual

indication of it) as his own as of 1938. The third group

requires special comment.

In the Autobiography Collingwood refers to four pieces

of documentary evidence that he gives every indication of having

consulted during his composition of the text, but which are not

accessible to other historians. Two of these documents--an

unpublished book called Truth and Contradiction which he wrote

in 1917, and a book-length essay written in 1920 and jokingly

entitled Libellus de Generatione (as if written by one of the

Italian idealists)--were destroyed by Collingwood after he wrote

the Autobiography (A, 42, 99, and 99 n.l). The other two may

still exist: one is a paper he wrote around 1918 and read to his

colleagues at Oxford, but apparently never published (A, 44);

the other is a 1928 paper which he calls his "Die manuscript"

(because it was written at a country-house at Le Martouret near

Die in France), and which he may have published under a more

descriptive title (A, 107). Of these four documents the first

two were seen by at least one other person apiece--the first by

"a publisher" to whom it was sent (and by whom it was refused)

(A, 42); and the second by Guido de Ruggiero, "for whom I typed

a copy, thinking that it might amuse him as an historian of

philosophy" (A, 99). Whether the latter


58

copy still exists is, to my knowledge, unknown; but in any event

no one has questioned the fact that the original 1917 and 1920

manuscripts did exist until Collingwood destroyed them. The 1918

Oxford paper may be among those unpublished papers still in the

possession of Mrs. Kathleen F. Collingwood. If in fact he did

publish the "Die manuscript" under a different title, it is

still identifiable only in terms of the content he assigns to

it, and is hence not unimpeachable evidence.

Since the remainder of the pieces of literary evidence

that Collingwood cites in the Autobiography refers to books and

articles still publicly available, such evidence is not in

question, and one can still test his interpretation by comparing

it with the relevant texts. The case is not so clear with

respect to the four items mentioned above, and hence they must

be treated as evidence of nothing more than what Collingwood's

views were at the time of his writing of the Autobiography. The

doctrines that Collingwood claims to have espoused in these

documents, insofar as he mentions what these doctrines are, and

insofar as he does not directly re-pudiate the position stated,

must be treated just like the other direct and contentful

statements he makes in the Autobiography--that is, they must be

taken as stating doctrines that he does not assign only to one


59

period or to one document, but puts forward as positions that he

currently held.1

____________________
1 Since the issue is crucial for the interpretation of
Collingwood's philosophy as contained in Autobiography, and
since the issue is made so sensitive by later writers on
Collingwood's philosophy, at the risk of tedium I propose the
following propositional version of what I take to be the limits
of autobiographical interpretation:

Supposing in manuscript M1 at time T1 an interpreter finds


author A1 making these statements:

S1: "I hold P1''

S2: "In M2 at T2 I held P2"

S3: "I still hold P2"

Then an interpreter is justified in making at least the


following assertions:

Il: Ml is evidence that A1 held S1, S2, and S3 at T1.

I2: M1 is evidence that A1 held P1 and P2 at T1.

He is clearly not justified if he were to say:

I3: M1 is evidence that A1 held P2 at T2.

He is not justified because I3 is not constructable on the basis


of S1- S3 of M1. It is valid on the evidence of M2 only if M2 at
T2 contains the assertion, "I hold P2." In short, S2 is itself
an interpretation requiring M2 for its justifying evidence. The
situation is not changed if the interpreter is the author
himself, and the manuscripts are his own writings.
60

2. The Autobiography as Historical Interpretation.

Prior to the Autobiography Collingwood had published

only four philosophical works: Religion and Philosophy (1916),

Speculum Mentis (1924), An Essay on Philosophical Method (1933),

and The Principles of Art (1938). The latter two were intended

as part of a projected series of philosophical works, about

which we will have more to say presently. Concerning the former

two Collingwood has several remarks in the Autobiography.

Religion and Philosophy had been written "some years earlier"

than 1916 "to tidy up and put behind me a number of thoughts

arising out of my juvenile studies in theology" (A, 43). The

main effect of these studies, at least for the development of

his later thought, was his recognition of the falsity of the

claim that empirical psychology had "already exploded the

pretensions and inherited the possessions of the old pseudo-

sciences of logic, ethics, political theory, and so forth," and

was hence the science of human affairs the world was seeking (A,

92).

If this claim never for a moment deceived me, that is a


benefit I owed to my early studies in theology. Like every
one else who studied that subject in those days, I read
William James' Varieties of Religious Experience and a lot
of other books in which religion was treated from a
psychological point of view . . . . I was profoundly
shocked by the Varieties . . . because the whole thing was
a fraud. The book professed to throw light on a certain
subject, and threw no light on it whatever. And that
because of the method used. It was not because the book was
a bad example of psychology, but because it was a good
example of psychology, that it left its subject completely
unilluminated. And in Religion and Philosophy I attacked,
not William
61

James, but any and every psychological treatment of


religion, in a passage of which the crucial words are "the
mind, regarded in this way, ceases to be mind at all." (A,
93).2

According to the above account, then, Collingwood's first

published philosophical work attacked the psychologistic

reductions of religion and mind to neuropathology and physiology

respectively, defending them as on the contrary functions of

consciousness, reason, and will (cf. A, 94-95).

His second philosophical work attempted to establish a

position independently of idealism, but repudiating realism -- a

position which belonged to no recognizable or ready-made class.

I became used to it . . . when ((for example)) one of the


"realists" (not an Oxford man), reviewing the first book in
which I tried to indicate my position, dismissed it in a
few lines as "the usual idealistic nonsense." The book was
Speculum Mentis, published in 1924. It was a bad book in
many ways. The position laid down in it was incompletely
thought out and unskillfully expressed . . . . But any one
who had been intelligent enough to see what I was trying to
say would have realized . . . that it was neither "usual"
nor "idealistic." (A, 56-57).

In a footnote to this passage Collingwood adds that, having just

reread Speculum Mentis for the first time since it was

published, he found it better than he had remembered.

______________________
2 The exact words are: "The mind, regarded in this
external way, really ceases to be a mind at all. To study a
man's consciousness without studying the thing of which he is
conscious is not knowledge of anything, but barren and trifling
abstraction." (RP, 42; FR, 77).
62

It is a record, not so very obscure in expression, of a good


deal of genuine thinking. If much of it now fails to satisfy
me, that is because I have gone on thinking since I wrote
it, and therefore much of it needs to be supplemented and
qualified. There is not a great deal that needs to be
retracted. (A, 56, n. 1).

Surprisingly enough, this is as much as Collingwood has

to say in his Autobiography about his first two published

philosophical books. For the remaining evidence that his ideas

developed as he said they did in the period from 1912 to 1932

Collingwood refers the reader to the short articles he published

in philosophical periodicals, "where they were rendered useless

by the fixed determination of the persons who read such

periodicals not to think about history" (A, 116, n. 1). Two

volumes of these essays have appeared since Collingwood's death

(EPA in 1964 and EPH in 1965). His first two books and these

essays (several of which are included by Knox in the concluding

portions of The Idea of History are the only sources presently

available for critically reconstructing the development of

Collingwood's philosophy during the period prior to the

appearance of the Autobiography.

What sort of conclusion then can one draw from a careful

reading of the Autobiography concerning Collingwood's

development as a philosopher? Every indication in the

Autobiography leads the reader to conclude that if there was any

"development" of his ideas, during which time a possible change

of mind may have occurred, it was in the period


63

from 1912 to 1932 (A, 23, 28, 116-17), and that after 1932 he

was engaged in preparing his conclusions for publication.

The ideas very briefly summarized in this chapter ((viz. ch.


X--"History as the Self-Knowledge of Mind")) and the two
preceding it were being worked out for nearly twenty years
after I became a teacher of philosophy ((in 1912)). They
were repeatedly written down, corrected, and rewritten . . .
. None of these writings has ever been intended for
publication, although much of their substance has been
repeatedly given in lecture form; but I am publishing this
short summary because the main problems are now ((i.e. in
1938)) solved, and publishing them in full is only a
question of time and health. (A, 116-17).

Both of these conditions, however, were to prove problematic:

By about 1930 my health was beginning to suffer from long-


continued overwork . . . . By this time I had in my head a
great deal which I believed the public would value; and the
only way of giving it to the public was by writing books.
On this, therefore, I decided to spend my leisure; and
planned a series, to begin with an Essay on Philosophical
Method. This I wrote during a long illness in 1932. It is
my best book in matter; in style, I may call it my only
book, for it is the only one I ever had the time to finish
as well as I knew how, instead of leaving it in a more or
less rough state. After settling accounts with my
archeological studies . . . I wrote in 1937 the second book
of my series, The Principles of Art. Before it had gone
through the press I was overtaken by the more serious
illness which gave me both the leisure and the motive to
write this autobiography; whose purpose is to put on re-
cord some brief account of the work I have not yet been
able to publish, in case I am not able to publish it in
full. Henceforth I shall spend all my available time in
going on with the series. (A, 117-18).

This passage is crucial for any attempt to reconcile

Collingwood's later philosophy to the interpretation of it

offered in the Autobiography. It will be the purpose of the

later chapters of this dissertation to


64

examine the extent to which this program--his "series"--was

carried out. Right now I merely wish to make two observations.

First, Collingwood leaves no doubt that he considers the Essay

on Philosophical Method as the key to understanding his mature

philosophy. Even the Autobiography itself, the purpose of which

is clearly stated in the text just quoted, is regarded as an

interim report of work in progress. No other work is singled out

for such high marks, and consequently any account of his mature

philosophy which ignores it must do so in defiance of

Collingwood's own clearly stated intentions.

Secondly, Collingwood gives no indication in the

Autobiography of any radical change of mind either before or

after he had begun his "series." He therefore clearly intends

his readers to approach the body of his later writings (i.e.

after 1932) as the fulfillment of a single-minded project, and

the earlier writings as a development leading up to it. An

interpretation of Collingwood's philosophy would be consistent

with the plan of the Autobiography only if it follows this

pattern.

3. The Autobiographical Interpretation: Four Themes.

My life's work hitherto, as seen from my fiftieth year,"

wrote Collingwood approximately five years before his death,

"has been in the main an attempt to bring about a rapprochement

between philosophy and history" (A, 77). The entire problem

concerning Collingwood's mature


65

philosophy is contained in this sentence, and especially in the

meaning of the term, rapprochement. According to Knox and

Donagan the reconciliation which Collingwood outlines in the

Autobiography, and continues in the Essay on Metaphysics,

amounts to nothing short of radical historicism: philosophy as a

separate discipline is liquidated by being absorbed into history

(IH, x). According to Mink and Rubinoff no such reduction occurs

in Collingwood's philosophy, since the rapprochement is

dialectical in nature, and in a dialectical relation the relata

are not separate or mutually exclusive, but rather "overlap" (a

technical term the meaning of which will be examined in Chapter

9).

In the Autobiography neither of these positions is

directly supported. There is no mention of any serious change of

mind, or of any radical reduction of philosophy to history; and

there is no discussion of dialectic or dialectical relations.

After two introductory chapters ("Bent of a Twig" and "Spring

Frost") recounting his early educational experiences at home and

at Rugby (1902-08), there follows two chapters ("Minute

Philosophers" and "Inclination of a Sapling") on Collingwood's

encounters with the Oxford Realists, first as a loyal, but

somewhat sceptical student initiate, and later as a rebelliously

independent tutor. Chapter V ("Question and Answer") encompasses

the years (1915-18) of his work in the Admiralty Intelligence


66

Division during World War I, during which time his daily

communings with the grotesque Albert Memorial led to the

development of his "question and answer logic"3 which was to be

the foundation of all his later philosophical and historical

work. Chapter VI ("The Decay of Realism") records his return to

Oxford in 1918 as a complete opponent of Oxford realism. The

next five chapters ("The History of Philosophy," "The Need for a

Philosophy of History," "The Foundations of the Future,"

"History as the Self-Knowledge of Mind," and "Roman Britain")

deal with the gradual development of his views on historical and

philosophical thinking, listing the principles which became part

of his mature philosophy of history, and giving some indication

of the progress of his work on the archeology of Roman Britain.

A final chapter ("Theory and Practice") records his political

views, especially concerning fascism and socialism, and his

assessment of the rapidly degenerating situation in pre-World

War II Europe.

Even from this brief topical survey one can see that

four themes dominate the Autobiography's interpretation of

Collingwood's philosophy. (1) Out of a total of twelve chapters,

no less than three (III, IV, and VI) deal with Collingwood's

reaction to Oxford realism, and the theme recurs throughout

Collingwood's discussion of his own positive

____________________________

3 Hereafter "Question and Answer" will be referred to by


the abbreviation, Q-A: e.g., "question and answer logic" appears
as "Q-A logic."
67

contributions to philosophy and history. In fact, as we shall

see, the Autobiography exhibits a rather surprising consistency

when seen from the point of view of this rejection of realist

doctrines. (2) Five chapters (VII through XI) are devoted, as

one might expect, to Collingwood's overthrow, based on his

rapprochement between philosophy and history, of the skeptical

conclusions of the Oxford realists. (3) The key to this

reconciliation is discussed in a crucial chapter (V) on his

"revolutionary" Q-A logic. (4) Finally, the theme of

rapprochement is extended, in the final chapter, but also in

remarks scattered throughout the other chapters, to other,

philosophically opposing doctrines: theory and practice, freedom

and obligation, etc. These four themes--the critique of realism,

Q-A logic, philosophy and history, and rapprochement

philosophy--are central concepts in the autobiographical

interpretation.

4. The Critique of Realism.

Collingwood writes that his tutors at Oxford were

members of the "realist" school of philosophers, a school whose

primary function was the destructive criticism of idealism, and

which converged towards the "zero line of complete scepticism"

(A, 18-19).

When I began to read philosophy there in 1910, Oxford was


still obsessed by what I will call the school of ((T. H.))
Green . . . . The philosophical tendencies common to this
school were described by its contemporary opponents as
Hegelianism. This title was
68

repudiated by the school itself, and rightly . . . . This


movement never in any sense dominated philosophical thought
and teaching at Oxford . . . . When I say that Green's
school at this time obsessed Oxford philosophy, what I mean
is that the work of that school presented itself to most
Oxford philosophers as something which had to be destroyed,
and in destroying which they would be discharging their
first duty to their subject. The question what positive
views they themselves held was of secondary importance (A,
15, 16, 19).

At the time of his graduation Collingwood felt that he

was "logically bound to remain a 'realist"' until he had

satisfied himself "either that the positive doctrines of the

school were false, or that its critical methods were unsound"

(A, 23). In connection with the relation between methods and

doctrine there appeared to be three alternatives, between which,

he says, he did not decide until after he had begun to teach

philosophy at Oxford: (a) there was no connection between them

(i.e., both were false); (b) the positive teachings were

mistaken but the critical methods sound; or (c) the positive

doctrines were correct but the critical methods were invalid.

The fourth alternative--viz. that both the positive doctrines

and the critical methods were valid--was apparently ruled out by

Collingwood on the basis of the negativity of the latter: their

positive teachings were incapable of resisting attack by their

own critical methods (A, 23).

Collingwood's description of this method is given in


acid terms:
69

(T)he 'realists'' chief, and in the last resort, it seemed


to me, only method was to analyze the position criticized
into various propositions, and detect contradictions between
these . . . (f)ollowing as they did the rules of
propositional logic . . . . (A, 42).

On any given issue a realist would "fish the problem P out of

the hyperuranian lucky-bag, hold it up, and say 'what did So-

and-so think about this?'" and only after this would they ask,

"Is he right?" (A, 68-9). In short, they separated the

historical question, "What did X think about P?" from the

philosophical question, "Was X right in thinking A about P?" (A,

27, 59). The presupposition of this procedure was that there

were a set of "eternal problems" in philosophy, to which

philosophers gave various answers at various times (A, 60, 69).

The answers given by different philosophers were to a presumably

identical set of questions--where "the sameness was the sameness

of a 'universal', and the difference the difference between two

instances of that universal" (A, 62). Since truth and falsity

were regarded as properties of propositions (A, 34), the

"answers" could be compared to one another to see if they were

contradictory or not (A, 40-42).

As for the positive content, Collingwood writes that

this consisted of a single assertion, dogmatically maintained:

"except for ((the)) one nonsensical phrase ((that)) knowledge

making no difference to what is known, 'realism' had no positive

doctrines of its own at all but had stolen all that it had from

the school of thought which it was


70

primarily concerned to discredit" (A, 44-45). The dogma was

propagated in a number of ways, all of which embody the central

assertion in one way or another. In its metaphysical form it is

the doc-trine that "the known is independent of, and unaffected

by, the knowing of it" (A, 45). In epistemology the "Oxford

'realists' talked as if knowing were a simple 'intuiting' or a

simple 'apprehending' of some 'reality'" (A, 25).

What all these "realists" were saying, I thought, was that


the condition of a knowing mind is not indeed a passive
condition, for it is actively engaged in knowing; but a
"simple" condition, one in which there are no complexities
or diversities, nothing except just the knowing. They
granted that a man who wanted to know something might have
to work, in ways that might be very complicated, in order
to "put himself in a position" from which it could be
"apprehended"; but once the position had been attained
there was nothing for him to do but "apprehend" it, or
perhaps fail to "apprehend" it. (A, 25-26).

As Collingwood paraphrased the way one member of the

movement stated it, knowing is "the simple 'compresence' of two

things, one of which ((is)) a mind" (A, 25). In ethics "the

great principle of realism, that nothing is affected by being

known" becomes the principle that "(m)oral philosophy is only

the theory of moral action: It can't therefore make any

difference to the practice of moral action" (A, 48). In

political theory the realists denied "the conception of 'common

good', the fun-damental idea of all social life," by "insisting

that all 'goods' were private" (A, 49).


71

In Collingwood's estimation the net result of all this

was nothing short of disastrous--for philosophy, for

civilization, and for the realist movement itself. In a gradual

and piecemeal fashion, a process of self-stultification occurred

within the ranks of the Oxford realists.

In this process, by which anything that could be recognized


as a philosophical doctrine was stuck up and shot to pieces
by the "realist" criticism, the "realists" little by little
destroyed everything in the way of positive doctrine that
they had ever possessed. (A, 49).

But although "the fox was tailless, and knew it," he did not

count it a misfortune: the realists

were glad to have eradicated from the philosophical schools


that confusion of philosophy with pulpit oratory which was
involved in the bad old theory that moral philosophy is
taught with a view to making the pupils better men. They
were proud to have excogitated a philosophy so pure from the
sordid taint of utility that they could lay their hands on
their hearts and say it was no use at all; a philosophy so
scientific that no one whose life was not a life of pure
research could appreciate it, and so abstruse that only a
whole-time student, and a very clever man at that, could
understand it. They were quite resigned to the contempt of
fools and amateurs. If anybody differed from them on these
points, it could only be because his intellect was weak or
his motives bad. (A, 51).

Collingwood writes that at the time of the outbreak of

World War I he had not satisfactorily decided which of his three

alternatives concerning Oxford realism was correct (A, 27-28).

As far as he had advanced was to work out the first of his two

rules for sound scholarship which he tried to instill in his

students.
72

I . . . taught my pupils, more by example than by precept,


that they must never accept any criticism of anybody's
philosophy which they might hear or read without satisfying
themselves by first-hand study that this was the philosophy
he actually expounded; that they must always defer any
criticism of their own until they were absolutely sure they
understood the text they were criticizing; and that if the
postponement was sine die it did not greatly matter. (A,
27).

"This did not as yet involve any attack" writes Collingwood,

"upon the realists' critical methods" (A, 27). Using this rule

himself he came to realize that with respect to what the realist

movement primarily was--viz. an attack on "the school of

Green"--they misspent their shot. The position they assaulted

was not Hegelianism, nor was it even idealism in the proper

sense (A, 15-16, 19).

But when Collingwood returned to Oxford after the war he

was already convinced that both the critical methods and the

positive doctrines of the realists were in error (his first

alternative) (A, 42, 44), and his "logic of question and

answer," worked out during his wartime reflections on the A1bert

Memorial, had led to a second pedagogic maxim: "reconstruct the

problem" or "never think you understand any statement made by a

philosopher until you have decided, with the utmost possible

accuracy, what the question is to which he means it for an

answer" (A, 74).

In an (unpublished) paper read at Oxford in 1918,

Collingwood writes, he assailed the cardinal principle of the

realists:
73

I read a paper to my colleagues, trying to convince them


that ((the realists')) central positive doctrine, "knowing
makes no difference to what is known", was meaningless. I
argued that anyone who claimed . . . to be sure of this, was
in effect claiming to know what he was simultaneously
defining as unknown. For if you know that no difference is
made to a thing by the presence or absence of a certain
condition c, you know what θ is like with c, and also what
θ is like without c, and-on comparing the two find no
difference. This involves knowing what θ is like without c;
in the present case, knowing what you defined as the
unknown. (A, 44).

In addition to this "refutation of realism" Collingwood proposed

an alternative theory of knowledge based on the centrality of

the questioning, rather than the merely asserting, activity:

The questioning activity, as I called it, was not an


activity of achieving compresence with, or apprehension of,
something; it was not preliminary to the act of knowing; it
was one-half (the other half being answering the question)
of an act which in its totality was knowing. (A, 26).

We will presently consider the "logic of question and answer" in

more detail, but here it is worth noting that Collingwood

proposed his "revolutionary" logic as an alternative to

propositional logic:

For a logic of propositions I wanted to substitute what I


called a logic of question and answer. It seemed to me that
truth, if that meant the kind of thing which I was
accustomed to pursue in my ordinary work as a philosopher or
historian--truth in the sense in which a philosophical
theory or an historical narrative is called true, which
seemed to me the proper sense of the word--was something
that belonged not to any single proposition, nor even, as
the coherence-theorists maintained, to a complex of
propositions taken together; but to a complex consisting of
questions and answers. (A, 36-37).
74

As this passage makes clear, Collingwood's alternative logic was

intended as an instrument for the discovery of philosophical and

historical truths--a task for which he felt propositional logic

ill-suited.

As a corollary to his Q-A logic, Collingwood denied the

realist's assumption that there are "eternal problems" in

philosophy. This occurred in two phases (A, 68). In the first,

Collingwood discovered through his historical research and in

his teaching experience that there is in fact no set of

permanent, eternal questions in philosophy (A, 60-68):

I found (and it required a good deal of hard detailed work


in the history of thought) that most of the conceptions
around which revolve the controversies of modern philosophy,
conceptions designated by words like "state", "ought",
"matter", "cause", had appeared on the horizon of human
thought at ascertainable times in the past . . . and that
the philosophical controversies of other ages had revolved
around other conceptions, not indeed unrelated to ours, but
not . . . indistinguishable from them. (A, 68).

Secondly he attacked the problem in principle. There can

be no absolute distinction between historical and philosophical

questions both because the distinction presupposes the

permanence of philosophical problems (which was false on

historical grounds), and because in any case of a philosophical

question one and the same passage is used as historical evidence

that it was a problem and as philosophical evidence of what that

problem was (A, 69-70).


75

Having disposed of the central positive doctrine of the

Oxford realists, as well as their epistemology and logic,

Collingwood went on to reject their moral and political

theories. He writes that since 1919 he lectured almost every

year on moral philosophy, and although his reconciliation-

philosophy was still incomplete, the rudiments were present even

then of a solution to the realist separation or distinction

between "facts" and "theories" (A, 148-49).

My first efforts in this direction were attempts to obey


what I felt as my call to resist the moral corruption
propagated by the "realist" dogma that moral philosophy does
no more than study in a purely theoretical spirit a subject
matter which it leaves wholly unaffected by that
investigation. The opposite of this dogma seemed to me not
only a truth, but a truth which, for the sake of his
integrity and efficacy as a moral agent in the widest sense
of that term, ought to be familiar to every human being:
namely, that in his capacity as a moral, political, or
economic agent he lives not in a world of "hard facts" to
which "thoughts" make no difference, but in a world of
"thoughts"; that if you change the moral, political, and
economic "theories" generally accepted by the society in
which he lives, you change the character of his world; and
that if you change his own "theories" you change his
relation to that world; so that in either case you change
the way in which he acts . . . . There were, I held, no
merely moral actions, and no merely political actions, and
no merely economic actions. Every action was moral,
political and economic. (A, 147, 149).

Collingwood regarded this as only a "theoretical" rapprochement,

and the conclusion of the Autobiography describes Collingwood's

bitter and painful discovery that a "practical" rapprochement

was also necessary. But this meant a unification of what he

calls the "three R. G. C.'s"--the "gloves-on" university

professor; the family man of practical affairs; and the


76

"man of action", a "gloves-off" philosopher for whom "the

difference between thinker and man of action disappeared," and

who used to "stand up and cheer, in a sleepy voice," whenever he

began reading Marx (even though, he says, he was "never at all

convinced either by Marx's metaphysics or by his economics") (A,

150-53). The closing lines of the final chapter give the reader

a sense of just what a threat Collingwood regarded the

"realists" to be, not only to philosophy but to civilization as

well. Recalling his remarks about the realists' reduction of

ethics to pure theory, Collingwood links them with the recent

rise in England of what he regarded as a fascist movement:

I am not writing an account of recent political events in


England: I am writing a description of the way in which
those events impinged upon myself and broke up my pose of a
detached professional thinker. I know now that the minute
philosophers of my youth ((viz. the realists)) for all their
profession of a purely scientific detachment from practical
affairs, were the propagandists of a coming Fascism. I know
that Fascism means the end of clear thinking and the triumph
of irrationalism. I know that all my life I have been
engaged unawares in a political struggle, fighting against
these things in the dark. Henceforth I shall fight in the
daylight. (A, 167).

The results of our survey of Collingwood's critique of Oxford

realism can be summarized as follows:


77

TABLE 2

THE CRITIQUE OF REALISM

1. Any doctrine which asserts as its basic principle that the


known is independent of, and unaffected by, the knowing of
it, is realism (A, 44-45).

2. Realism's ultimate method is destructive criticism; that is:

a. the analysis of a position into various propositions; and

b. the use of the rules of propositional logic to detect


contradictions between these propositions (A, 42).

3. The consequences of realism are:

a. the separation of the historical question of fact from the


philosophical question of truth, and the metaphysical
assumption that the latter are eternal (A, 59);

b. an epistemology which defines knowledge as the simple


apprehension of an object (A, 25-26);

c. a metaphysics which deals with a body of eternal truths


concerning the world's general nature (A, 65-67), and
which denies the reality of becoming (A, 99);

d. an ethics which regards itself as merely moral theory, and


hence makes no difference to the practice of moral action
(A, 47-48, 147);

e. a political theory which denies the conception of a


"common good" and insists that all "goods" are private (A,
49).

4. The basic principle of realism cannot withstand destructive


criticism: it involves the meaningless assertion (on
propositional grounds) that one can know what is
simultaneously defined as the unknown. Realism hence cannot
live up to its own claims, and fails as a philosophy (A, 23,
44).
78

5. The method of realism is false as a philosophical method,


because

a. there is not, and cannot be, a one-one correspondence


between indicative sentences in a language and logical
propositions (A, 35); and

b. meaning, contradiction and agreement, truth and falsity do


not belong to propositions by themselves, but to
propositions as answers to questions (A, 33).

6. The consequences of realism, as well as being disastrous for


civilization, are philosophically erroneous:

a. philosophical and historical questions are inseparable,


and there are no eternal questions and concepts (A, 68-69);

b. knowledge is a complex process consisting of questions and


answers, and questioning activity being one half (the
other half being answering the question) of an act which
in its totality is knowing (A, 26);

c. questions concerning the world's general nature are based


on beliefs or presuppositions made by the phys cists of an
era, these presuppositions being subject to change but not
to the distinction between truth and falsity (A, 66);

d. knowledge of the situation in which one is called upon to


act affects the action of the agent in that situation (A,
147-48);

e. actions (which are moral, political and economic at the


same time) based on false knowledge of the situation in
which one is called upon to act, do not serve the good of
the nation as a whole but the good of a class, section, or
only oneself (A, 147-49, 155).
79

5. The Logic of Question and Answer.

Collingwood states that the first steps that he took in

his youthful revolt against the doctrine of realism were

methodological: in place of the "propositional logic" accepted

not only by realists but by idealists as well (A, 52),

Collingwood formulated a "logic of question and answer",

philosophically more appropriate and historically more sound (A,

26, 28, 30). He went so far as to write it up in book-length

form ("during my spare time in 1917"), and offered it, under the

title Truth and Contradiction, to a publisher, but was refused

on the grounds that "the times were hopelessly bad for a book of

that kind" (A, 42). The book was never published, and

Collingwood later destroyed the only draft of it (A, 99, n.l).

The roots of Collingwood's "revolutionary" logic, as

stated in the Autobiography, are complex, and the rules of this

logic shade off imperceptably into his views on history and

metaphysics. With respect to the former, three areas of his

experience seem to have contributed to the formulation of his

views. The first was his field experience in archeology--

initially under the tutelage of his father, then, after 1913,

directing his own excavations (A, 23-24, 30). This experience.

he writes, impressed upon him the importance of the "questioning

activity" in knowledge: in archeological field work "one found

out nothing at all except in answer to a question; and not a

vague question either, but


80

a definite one" (A, 24). In addition to teaching him that the

questioning activity was not preliminary, but rather integral to

the activity of knowing, it also taught him that the

intuitionistic epistemology (knowledge reduced to direct

acquaintance with an object) and propositional logic (truth as a

property of indicative assertions) espoused by the realists were

inadequate (A, 26-27, 30-31).

The second was his pre-war experience as a teacher at

Oxford. This yielded the first of his two pedagogical rules for

philosophical interpretation: "never accept criticism of any

author before satisfying yourself of its relevance"--that is,

one should satisfy oneself by first-hand study that this was the

philosophy the author actually expounded (A, 27, 74). But (as we

have already seen) while this "did not as yet involve any attack

upon the 'realists'' critical methods", when coupled with his

archeological experience it converged as a "flank attack on

'realism' as a philosophy which erred through neglecting

history" (A, 28).

The third source and by far the most important,

according to the Autobiography, was Collingwood's daily

communings with the Albert Memorial:

A year or two after the outbreak of ((the first world))


war, I was living in London and working with a section of
the Admiralty Intelligence Division in the rooms of the
Royal Geographical Society. Every day I walked across
Kensington Gardens and past
81

the Albert Memorial. The Albert Memorial began by degrees to


obsess me . . . . Everything about it was visibly misshapen,
corrupt, crawling, verminous; for a time I could not bear to
look at it, and passed with averted eyes; recovering from
this weakness, I forced myself to look, to face day by day
the question: a thing so obviously, so incontrovertibly, so
indefensibly bad, why had Scott done it? . . . . What
relation was there, I began to ask myself, between what he
had done and what he had tried to do? (A, 29).

His reflections on the unfortunate Albert Memorial led

Collingwood to formulate the second of his two pedagogical

rules: "reconstruct the problem", or "never think you understand

any statement made by a philosopher until you have decided, with

the utmost possible accuracy, what the question is to which he

means it for an answer" (A, 74). This was a direct

generalization arising from the analysis of his aesthetic

experience of the Albert Memorial: Collingwood forced himself to

reconstruct the problem that Scott had set for himself in

designing such an artistic monstrosity:

Had he tried to produce a beautiful thing; a thing, I meant,


which we should have thought beautiful? If so, he had of
course failed. But had he perhaps been trying to produce
something different? If so, he might possibly have
succeeded. If I found the monument merely loathsome, was
that perhaps my fault? Was I looking in it for qualities it
did not possess, and either ignoring or despising those it
did? (A, 29-30).

In addition to affording Collingwood yet another occasion for

examining the role of questioning in knowledge, his reflections

on the Albert Memorial provided him with a clue for solving the

problem about
82

"eternal questions" in philosophy, and especially in metaphysics

(A, 60). Applying his second pedagogical maxim to political

theory he discovered that "the history of political theory is

not the history of different answers given to one and the same

question, but the history of a problem more or less constantly

changing, whose solution was changing with it" (A, 62). Hence

the realist assumption that different philosophies were

different attempts to answer the same question was a "vulgar

error, consequent on a kind of historical myopia which, deceived

by superficial resemblances, failed to detect profound

differences" (A, 60-61). Just as the ideal nature of the state

exhibits essential differences for philosophers living at

different times and in different societies, so the ideals of

personal conduct are subject to essential changes (A, 61-65).

The question "What is the ideal state?" and "What sort of

behavior is moral?" are not the same questions when asked by

different philosophers, because they have different essential

meanings and different presuppositions. The clearest application

of the principle was to metaphysics, where Collingwood finally

laid to rest "the philosophers convictions about the eternity of

problems or conceptions" (A, 65):

It became clear to me that metaphysics (as its very name


might show, though people still use the word as if it had
been "paraphysics") is no futile attempt at knowing what
lies beyond the limits of experience, but is primarily at
any given time an attempt to discover what the people of
that time believe about the world's general nature; such
beliefs being the presuppositions of all their "physics",
that is, their inquiries into its detail. Secondarily,
83

it is the attempt to discover the corresponding


presuppositions of other peoples and other times, and to
follow the historical process by which one set of
presuppositions has turned into another. (A, 65-66).

Hence after discovering the clue during his reflections on the

Albert Memorial and after generalizing the maxim and applying it

to the fields of political theory, ethics, and finally

metaphysics, Collingwood concluded that "there was no recognized

branch of philosophy to which the principle did not apply that

its problems, as well as the solutions proposed for them, had

their own history" (A, 67). Except in the sense used to

designate collectively a series of problems connected by a

process of historical change, such that their continuity, but

not their differences, are discernible--except in this

inaccurate sense "(t)he conception of 'eternal problems'

disappeared entirely" (A, 67-68, n.l).

Based on the generalizations from these three regions of

his experience, Collingwood formulated his revolutionary Q-A

logic, the rules of which (in the autobiographical version) may

be tabulated as follows:
84

TABLE 3

QUESTION AND ANSWER LOGIC - AUTOBIOGRAPHY

1. A body of knowledge consists not of propositions but of these


together with the questions they are meant to answer (A, 30).

a. "Proposition" denotes an assertive act of thought or


what in those acts of thought is asserted (A, 30).

b. A proposition is always a logical and not merely a


linguistic entity ((i.e. it states what ought to be the
case rather than what merely is the case concerning
assertive acts of thought)) (A, 31).

2. In order to find out what a proposition means the question to


which the proposition was meant as an answer must be known
(A, 31).

3. No two propositions can agree with or be contradictory to one


another unless they are answers to the same question (A, 33).

a. The sameness of two questions is the sameness of an


historical process, and the difference between two
questions is the difference between one thing ((the
first question)) which in the course of that process has
turned into something else ((the second question)) (A,
62).

b. An historical process is a process of becoming such that


if a process P1 turns into a process P2, there remains
in P2 a trace or survival of P1 (A, 98-99).

4. Truth and falsity belong to a complex consisting of questions


and answers such that:

a. each answer and its question must be relevant to a


complex of questions and answers ((i.e., to a systematic
inquiry));
85

b. each question within that complex must "arise"


((Collingwood leaves the meaning of "arise" unresolved
in the Autobiography));

c. each answer must be the "right" answer to its question


(where "right" means "enabling the inquiry to proceed",
and not "true"--the right answer could be false);

d. each answer is to a certain specific question in the


questions and answer complex (A, 37). (cf. A, 31-32--
correlativity of Q & A).

5. Questions not only have answers, they also have


presuppositions which are not subject to the distinction
between what is true and what is false (A, 66).

a. Some presuppositions ((relative presuppositions)) may be


the answer to another question (A, 66).

b. Some presuppositions are "absolute"--that is, are not


answers to any questions at all (A, 67).

6. The question "To what question did So-and-so intend this


proposition for an answer?" is an historical question, and
cannot be settled except by historical methods (A, 38-39).

a. The settlement of an historical question results from


arguing back from the propositional answer to its
question (A, 70).

b. In arguing back from a propositional answer to its


question, one and the same piece of evidence states the
answer and allows the historian to identify the question
(A, 70).
86

Collingwood's informal presentation of this Q-A logic is

interspersed with commentary on it, some of which is worth

mentioning here as a sort of concluding appendix to this section.

It is worth noting, to begin with, that Collingwood's Q-

A logic is formulated in the context of a theory of knowledge,

and a theory of knowledge that looks to history as a paradigm of

knowing rather than to mathematics (A, 36-37). This is the

significance of the first statement in the above table. The

"body of knowledge" or systematic inquiry which he has in mind

is an inquiry in which discoveries are still being made (at

least for the inquirer), and not a closed system with fixed

relationships (cf. A, 75).

Secondly, Q-A logic is at once a theory of meaning, of

logical validity (agreement and contradiction), and of truth:

If the meaning of a proposition is relative to the question


it answers, its truth must be relative to the same thing.
Meaning, agreement and contradiction, truth and falsehood,
none of these belonged to propositions in their own right,
propositions by themselves; they belonged only to
propositions as the answers to questions: each proposition
answering a question strictly correlative to itself. (A, 33;
cf. A, 37).

Another way of putting the matter would be to say that meaning,

validity, and truth are functions of a Q-A complex which, for

Collingwood, is taken as the primary logical unit. Items 2, 3,

and 4 of the above table take up each of these successive

functions.

87
Thirdly, it is over these three functions of the Q-A

complex that Collingwood felt he departed from the doctrines of

propositional logic--the mathematical logic accepted in part by

the idealists, and in total by the realists (A, 33-36, 42). As

in his refutation of the cardinal principle of the realists,

Collingwood was careful to formulate "the central doctrine of

propositional logic" which he was concerned to reject:

that there is, or ought to be, or in a well-constructed and


well-used language would be, a one-one correspondence
between propositions and indicative sentences, every
indicative sentence expressing a proposition, and a
proposition being defined as the unit of thought, or that
which is true or false. (A, 35-36).

This central doctrine would clearly be ruled out of Q-A logic on

the grounds that both meaning and truth are functions of a Q-A

complex, and not of answers or of assertive acts of thought

alone. Yet it is presupposed by all the various well known

theories of truth":

One school of thought holds that a proposition is either


true or false simply in itself, trueness or falseness being
qualities of propositions. Another school holds that to call
it true or false is to assert a relation of "correspondence"
or "non-correspondence" between it and something not a
proposition, some "state of things" or "fact". A third holds
that to call it true or false is to assert a relation
between it and other propositions with which it "coheres" or
fails to "cohere". And, since in those days there were
pragmatists, a fourth school should be mentioned,
holding . . . that to call a proposition true or false is to
assert the utility or inutility of believing it. All these
theories of truth I denied. (A, 36).
88

It is no wonder that, as Collingwood remarks in a later chapter,

"(s)o far as my philosophical ideas were concerned, I was now

cut off not only from the 'realist' school . . . but from every

other school of thought in England, I might almost say in the

world" (A, 53).

Fourthly, it is in connection with his application of Q-

A logic to the supposedly "eternal problems" of metaphysics that

the relationship between Q-A complexes and presuppositions makes

its appearance (A, 66-67). So also the example which Collingwood

uses to illustrate that contradiction or agreement (what we have

called "validity") is a function of the Q-A complex, is the

classical metaphysical problem of "the one and the many":

For example, metaphysicians have been heard to say "the


world is both one and many"; and critics have not been
wanting who were stupid enough to accuse them of
contradicting themselves, on the abstractly logical grounds
that "the world is one" and "the world is many" are mutually
contradictory propositions . . . . There is no contradiction
between saying that something . . . is one, and saying that
it is many. Contradiction would set in only if that
something were said to be both one x and many x's . . . .
Thus, if a given doctrine D is criticized as self-
contradictory because it is divisible into two parts E and
F. where E contradicts F. the criticism is valid only if the
critic has correctly reconstructed the questions to which E
and F were given as answers (A, 40-41).

Fifthly, and finally, the way Collingwood formulates his

Q-A logic presupposes an understanding of "history" as he uses

the term. This is clear from items 3a and 3b of the above table,

which specify
89

"sameness of question" in terms of historical process, and item

6, which makes historical methodology integral to the discovery

of "sameness of meaning" in a Q-A complex.

6. History and Philosophy.

By the time of the outbreak of World War I, but before

his reflections on the Albert Memorial, Collingwood had not

successfully resolved his "threefold question" concerning the

critical methods and positive content of Oxford realism, but his

archeological research and early philosophical teaching

experience aided him in mounting what he calls a "flank attack"

on the same problem:

Working simultaneously along these two lines, I could see


them tending to converge in an attack on "realism" as a
philosophy which erred through neglecting history. If I had
thought it possible to forewarn the "realists" of this
attack, I should have said, "You must pay more attention to
history. Your positive doctrines about knowledge are
incompatible with what happens, according to my own
experience, in historical research; and your critical
methods are misused on doctrines which in historical fact
were never held by those to whom you ascribe them." (A, 28,
emphasis mine).

By 1920, Collingwood writes, he had completely worked

out the idea of a "living past", and was prepared for a frontal

assault on the realists' view of the past as consisting of

corpse-like "events". The realists' neglect of history was a

result of their refusal to admit the reality of becoming. The

overcoming of the error involved in the


90

recognition that historical processes survive in the present,

and this is the key concept in deciding how history can be

reconciled with the "wisdom" sought by philosophers. The past

that the historian studies is part of the situation within which

he is called upon to act (A, 114); and the "events" of the past

are processes of becoming which survive as active features of

the present (A, 98-100).

By 1930, according to the Autobiography, Collingwood

had worked out the principles on the basis of which history as

"a science of human affairs" could be constructed (A, 115).

These principles Collingwood connects with his Q-A logic and

with the maxims drawn from his experience as an archeologist (A,

106-109, 122, 130). Again, for brevity's sake, we shall tabulate

these principles here in slightly altered order from their

appearance in the Autobiography, but with a notation that

facilitates reconstruction of that order:


91
TABLE 4

THE PRINCIPLES OF HISTORY

1. (LG) History is concerned not with events but with processes


(A, 99).

a. Processes are things which do not begin or end ((as


events do)) but turn into one another; if process Pi
turns into P2, Pi goes on in the changed form P2, and
P2 has previously been going on in earlier ((implicit))
form, P. (A, 98).

b. ((In an historical process)) Pi leaves traces (evidence)


of itself in P2, so that an historian living in P2 ((a
situation)) can discover that what is now P2 was once PI
by the interpretation of evidence (A, 98; cf. A, 96).

_________________
NOTE: In Table 4, the following abbreviations are used:
LG = Libellus de Generatione (see page 94, below), mentioned in
Chapter IX of the Autobiography; ARCH-1,-2,-3 = Archeological
principles, mentioned in Chapter XI; HIST -1, -2,-3,-4 =
Historical principles mentioned in Chapter X.

Collingwood clearly indicates that the principles employed in


archeology are applicable to all of history (A, 121, 130, 133).
He also states that the idea of a living past, expressed in
terms of historical processes, became his "first principle of a
philosophy of history"; it is therefore listed as such in the
table. "ARCH-2" follows it, because it amplifies "LG", and is a
natural bridge to "HIST-1". "HIST-1,-2,-3 are listed in that
order in Chapter X of the Autobiography. "HIST-4" is not so
numbered by Collingwood, but he indicates that it forms the
conclusion of a train of thought that "was not complete until
about 1930" (A, 115). Finally, it is worth noting that
Collingwood states in a footnote that the principles we are
calling "HIST-1,-4" were discussed in a paper delivered before
the British Academy after his election to that body in 1934.
They appear almost verbatim in The Idea of History in the
"epilegomenon" called, after the paper, "Human Nature and
History" (IH, 205-231; see especially IN, 215).
92

2. (ARCH-2) There are no mere "events" in history; what is


miscalled an event is really an action, and expresses some
thought (intention, purpose) of its agent; the historian's
purpose is to identify this thought (A, 127-28; cf. A, 130).

3. (HIST-1) All history is the history of thought (A, 110).

a. The thought must be expressed: either in language or in


one of the many other forms of expressive activity (A,
111).

b. The historian must be able to think over again for himself


the very same thought whose expression he is trying to
interpret (A, 111).

4. (HIST-2) Historical knowledge is the re-enactment in the


historian's mind of the thought whose history he is studying
(A, 112).

a. The sameness of the thought is not the sameness of a


universal but the sameness of an historical process (A,
62).

b. The difference between the thought of the agent and the


reenacted thought of the historian is a difference of
context: to the historian it is a past thought living in
the present ("encapsulated", not "free"), while to the
agent it is a present thought (A, 113).

5. (HIST-3) Historical knowledge is the re-enactment of a past


thought encapsulated in a context of present thoughts which,
by contradicting it, confine it to a plane different from
theirs (A, 114).

a. An Encapsulated thought is a thought which, though


perfectly alive ((not a mere "event", which ends and
begins)), forms no part of the Q-A complex which
constitutes the "real" life, the superficial or obvious
present, of the mind in question (A, 113; cf. A, 140-41).
93

b. Present and past planes of thought are distinguished by


observing the way in which ((their respective)) problems
arise (A, 114).

c. Every historical problem ultimately arises out of "real"


life--i.e., out of practical problems (A, 114).

6. (HIST-4) The science of human affairs (i.e. moral and


political wisdom) is history (A, 99, 115).

a. Knowledge achieved by historical inquiry is not knowledge


of his (the historian's) situation as opposed to knowledge
of himself, it is knowledge of his situation which is at
the same time knowledge of himself (A, 114).

b. There must be a kind of action which is not deter-mined


according to rule, and where the process is directly from
knowledge of the situation to an action appropriate to
that situation without passing through the stage of
formulating a rule appropriate to the situation (A, 103).

b. History offers insight into the situation in which one is


called upon to act, rather than ready-made rules for
acting in all situations of a given kind (A, 100-102; cf.
A, 114).

7. (ARCH-1) Success in historical studies depends upon clear


application of Q-A logic to historical problems (A, 121-122,
124).

8. (ARCH-3) No historical problem should be studied without


studying its second-order history, that is, the history of
historical thought about it (A, 132).
94

Again, several comments about these principles are in

order. The first is that what is stated by Collingwood to be the

"first principle" of a philosophy of history, as of 1920, is

expressed by him in two ways, which are not transparently

identical in meaning. The first is "that the past which an

historian studies is not a dead past, but a past which in some

sense is still living in the present"; the second is in the form

in which it appears above. The idea of a living past is

described later in terms of the principle of Encapsulation (5.

of Table 4), so that its later reiteration eliminates the need

to argue for an identity of meaning in these two expressions, as

well as the necessity to speculate why Collingwood took them to

mean the same thing.

Secondly, Collingwood writes that this first principle

of history initially appeared in an essay of short book-length

(Libellus de Generatione) which "was primarily a study of the

nature and implications of process or becoming."

Secondarily, it was an attack on "realism", showing how the


non possumus of "realists" towards a theory of history
arose from their refusal to admit the reality of becoming,
and from their analysis of the true proposition ''P1
becomes P2" into the complex of propositions ''P1 is P1",
"P1 is not P2" "P1 ends where P2 begins", "P2 is P2", and
"P2 is not Pi'', all of them either tautologous or false.
(A, 11).

Hence Collingwood's first principle of history was formulated,

according to the Autobiography, in direct opposition to what he

took to be a realist's position.


95

Thirdly, Q-A logic appears as an integral part of his

listing of historical principles: it appears in his principles

of re-enactment (4), of Encapsulation (5), and of successful

historiography (7).

Fourthly, Collingwood states that in connection with the

principle of re-enactment (4), the question of what the

difference is between the thought of an historical agent and the

re-enacted thought in the historian's mind, was the most

difficult of all the questions he encountered in his study of

historical method (A, 112). The answer that he gives to this

question in the Autobiography and the example which accompanies

it are given in terms of his Q-A logic. According to the

principle of Encapsulation (see 5 in Table 4), present thoughts

and past, Encapsulated thought are distinguished by the way in

which questions arise in each. For Admiral Nelson at the naval

battle at Trafalgar the question, "Shall I take off my

decorations?" and its answer, "In honour I won them, in honour I

will die with them," occur in a primary Q-A series that involve

the battle and his participation in it on the decks of the

Victory. But this question does not arise in a primary Q-A

series involving the Encapsulated thought (the historian does

not contemplate removing his own decorations in fear of losing

his life).

But a question arising in ((the historian's)) primary


series may act as a switch into another dimension. I plunge
beneath the surface of my mind, and there live a life in
which I not merely
96

think about Nelson but am Nelson, and thus in thinking


about Nelson think about myself. But this secondary life is
prevented from over-flowing into my primary life by being
what I call incapsulated, that is, existing in a context of
primary or surface knowledge which keeps it in its place
and prevents it from thus overflowing. Such knowledge, I
mean, as that Trafalgar happened ninety years ago: I am a
little boy in a jersey: this is my father's study carpet,
not the Atlantic, and that the study fender, not the coast
of Spain. (A, 113-14).

That primary or surface knowledge, some examples of which

Collingwood uses from his juvenile re-enactments of the naval

engagement at Trafalgar, serve to "contradict" the imaginative

experience in which one takes on the role of being Nelson (and

in the process forgets oneself or loses oneself in the imagined

object). It is this "contradiction" which confines Encapsulated

thought to a plane different from the context of present

thoughts.

Finally, history as the science of human affairs

(6)corrects the false claim that psychology, a natural science

of mind, is the source of wisdom, especially in matters moral

and political (A, 92, 94, 116, 126).

The nineteenth century, likewise in search of a science of


human affairs, tried to realize it in the shape of a
"psychology" in which the mental was reduced to the
psychical, the distinction between truth and falsehood
thrown overboard, and the very idea of a science negated,
psychology itself being involved in the resulting
bankruptcy. But the revolution in historical method . . .
swept away these sham sciences and . . . brought into
existence a genuine, actual, visibly and rapidly progressing
form of knowledge which now for the first time was putting
man in a position to obey the oracular precept "know
thyself" . . . . (A, 116).
97

But if a "science of human nature" cannot be achieved except by

historical methods, part of the reason is that actions--

historical processes--are not always performed in accordance

with rules. Collingwood points out two occasions in which agents

necessarily act without knowledge of any rule appropriate to the

situation: (1) when a situation requires one to act and yet does

not recognizably belong to any rule-governed types; and, (2)

when the situation is recognized as of a rule-governed type, but

the required act "involves a certain misfit between yourself and

your situation"--presumably because the agent requires more of

himself than action according to type or to rule (A, 103-104).

Of these two cases in which it is necessary to act other-


wise than according to rule, the first arises out of the
agent's inexperience and ignorance of life . . . . The
second arises only for people of experience and
intelligence, and even then occurs only when they take a
situation very seriously; so seriously as to reject not only
the claims of . . . desire, and . . . self-interest, but
((also)) . . . right conduct, or action according to the
recognized rules (A, 105).

Such rule-free occasions call for improvised actions appropriate

to the recognized realities of the situation; and the function

of historical thinking was to provide "insight" into such

situations, the reality of which included the incapsulated past

as part of itself (A, 106, 101)


98

7. Rapprochement Philosophy.

We have already seen that Collingwood regarded his

philosophy as "in the main an attempt to bring about a

rapprochement between philosophy and history"; that he rejected

realism as a "philosophy which erred through neglecting

history"; that philosophy and history shared a common

methodology by employing Q-A logic; and that historical

questions are not separate from philosophical questions because

"all history is the history of thought". The final step in the

autobiographical account is therefore to elucidate the meaning

of Collingwood's "rapprochement" philosophy.

One aspect of this rapprochement occurred to Collingwood

in the course of his philosophical teaching at Oxford: if

philosophers were to deal with the history of their own subject

they ought to do so in a manner that met the contemporary

standards of historical thinking (A, 77)--some of which

Collingwood states in the Autobiography, and which we have

summarized in Table 4.

But, in addition to making philosophy more historically

respectable, it was necessary to make history more

philosophical: this Collingwood did in his own historical work.

As an example of it he cites the chapter on "Art" which he wrote

for the first volume of the Oxford History of England--a chapter

in which he showed how a revival


99

of Celtic art forms was possible after two centuries, during

which time only Romanized art was produced. In solving the

problem Collingwood made use of a modified form of his principle

of incapsulation:

Incapsulation is not an "occult entity". It was my name for


such facts as this--familiar enough to everybody--that a
man who changes his habits, thoughts,etc., retains in the
second phase some residue of the first. (A, 141).

The principle also operates in habits transmitted from one

generation to the next, and without the need of positing any

occult entities "like racial temperament or an inheritance of

acquired psychical characteristics" (A, 142):

(T)he transmission by educational means of any moral ideal


which involves the outlawry of an institution or custom, and
the repression of a desire for it, entails the simultaneous
transmission of that desire itself. The children of each
generation are taught to want what they are taught they must
not have. (A, 143).

This was the means by which a suppressed art-form was preserved

over two centuries of time in Romanized Britain:

(T)he less successful the Britons were in Romanizing


art, . . . the more they were likely to cherish the memory
of their own fashions and ensure that these fashions were
never wholly lost to sight by the rising generation. (A,
144).

Collingwood calls on this example as an illustration of the use

of his rapprochement philosophy:

I found it possible to assert a connection between two


facts, both of them notorious, which had not previously been
thought of as
100

connected. One was the Celtic revival; the other was the
badness of Romanizing British art . . . . (T)he idea which
I expressed in the chapter on "Art" in the Oxford History
of England . . . I would gladly leave as the sole memorial
of my Romano-British studies, and the best example I can
give to posterity of how to solve a much-debated problem in
history, not by discovering fresh evidence, but by
reconsidering questions of principle. It may thus serve to
illustrate what I have called the rapprochement between
philosophy and history, as seen from the point of view of
history (A, 144-145).

In addition to a reconciliation from the historical

direction, there is presumably a reconciliation from the point

of view of philosophy:

This meant, in the first instance, a special branch of


philosophical inquiry devoted to the special problems raised
by historical thinking. Epistemological problems, such as
one might group together under the question "how is
historical knowledge possible?" Metaphysical problems,
concerned with the nature of the historian's subject-matter:
the elucidation of terms like event, process, progress,
civilization, and so forth. (A, 77).

We have already observed how Collingwood resolved the first

question (viz. that one can know the past if it is not a "dead"

past, but is rather "living", incapsulated in the present, and

known by critical evaluation of evidence). In the second group,

Collingwood deals only with the terms "event" and "process"--the

subject matter of the first two principles in Table 3; the

remainder are left unelucidated in the Autobiography.

"But this demand for a new branch of philosophy," adds

Collingwood, "soon developed into the demand for a new kind of


101

philosophy" (A, 77), a "Copernican revolution" (A, 79, n.l) in

which historical knowledge is shown to be an element in all

thinking (A, 86-88, 67-68). Collingwood cites the example of a

scientist who, in framing a theory, makes use of historical

experiments as to what experiments had been tried and with what

results, and insists that this historical knowledge is an

essential element in all scientific thinking (A, 87).

Metaphysics itself is an historical science, insofar as "the

question what presuppositions underlie the 'physics' or natural

science of a certain people at a certain time" is a purely

historical question, and the origins of these beliefs about the

world's general nature have come into existence by certain

changes out of other such beliefs (A, 66-67).

Finally, a similar analysis occurred in connection with

moral philosophy, which also involved an historical element:

If knowledge as to the facts of one's situation is called


historical knowledge, historical knowledge is necessary to
action . . . . Immediately after the War, therefore, I began
to reconsider in detail all the familiar topics and problems
of moral philosophy . . . . In the first place, I subjected
these topics and problems to what I called an historical
treatment, insisting that every one of them had its history
and was unintelligible without some knowledge of that
history. Secondly, I attempted to treat them in another way,
which I called analytic. My notion was that one and the same
action, which as action pure and simple was a "moral"
action, was also a "political" action relative to a rule,
and at the same time an "economic" action as means to an
end. (A, 149).
102

The reconciliation between theory and practice, like that

between history and philosophy, proceeded from two sides. From

the theoretical side thought and action were shown to be

mutually dependent, "thought depending upon what the thinker

learned by experience in action, action depending upon how he

thought of himself and the world" (A, 150). We have already seen

how the need for a practical rapprochement impressed itself on

the "three R. G. C.'s".

Unfortunately this is as much as Collingwood has to say

on the subject of rapprochement philosophy in the Autobiography,

and the reader is directed to complete the task of working out

the details for himself (A, 149). Unlike the discussion of Q-A

logic and the principles of history, there are no explicit rules

for rapprochement. However, from the above discussion several

generalizations about rapprochement philosophy are possible:


103

TABLE 5

RAPPROCHEMENT PHILOSOPHY

1. The subject matter of rapprochement philosophy are viewpoints


presumed to be distinct and opposite (e.g. philosophy and
history, theory and practice, etc.). Such an accepted state
of unreconciled opposition between viewpoints is
characteristic of the "realist" philosophy (A, 148)

2. A reconciliation of opposing viewpoints proceeds from each


viewpoint towards its presumed opposite (e.g. from philosophy
toward history, and from history toward philosophy) (A, 77,
144-45).

3. What must be shown for minimal reconciliation is that there


is a relation of mutual dependence of each view-point on its
presumed opposite (A, 150).

4. A relationship of mutual dependence between opposing


viewpoints is established by subjecting them to both:

a. an historical treatment, in which they are shown to


satisfy the conditions (or principles) of historical
inquiry (to be related as two phases of a process, capable
of re-enactment, etc.); and

b. an analytic treatment, in which they are shown to satisfy


the conditions (or principles) of Q-A logic (they must be
answers to the same question, be part of a Q-A complex,
etc.). (A, 148; cf. A, 31, 42).
104

It is questionable, given Collingwood's remarks about

rule-free situations and improvisation, whether he would agree

that any such semi-formalization of the methodology of

reconciliation is possible. Improvisation apparently extends

even to the level of methodology:

Obscure provinces, like Roman Britain, always rather appeal


to me. Their obscurity is a challenge; you have to invent
new methods for studying them, and then you will probably
find that the cause of their obscurity is some defect in the
methods hitherto used. When these defects have been removed,
it will be possible to revise the generally accepted
opinions about other, more familiar, subjects, and to
correct the errors with which those opinions are perhaps
infected. In this sense, knowledge advances by proceeding to
"from the known to the unknown", but from the "unknown" to
the "known". (A, 86).

Collingwood extends this remark to include "obscure subjects"

including (at that time in England) historical methodology, the

systematic study of which he hoped would reveal epistemological

truths "concealed from the 'realists' by their obviously

conventional and second-hand ideas about the methods of natural

science" (A, 86).

It is also possible that Collingwood's failure in the

Autobiography to specify the sorts of conditions under which

questions are said to "arise" is related to his reversal of the

Aristotelian maxim about the direction in which the mind works

in coming to know a subject (for Aristotle it proceeded from the

known to the unknown). If obscurity is a stimulus for the

invention of new methods which, in turn, reveal errors


105

in previous treatments of the subject, then it is hardly

possible to predict in advance the questions that will arise: it

presumes prior knowledge of the errors that have been made.

But on these issues Collingwood is enigmatically silent.


PART II

THE EARLY WRITINGS (1916-1932)


CHAPTER III

REALISM AND IDEALISM

1. Introduction.

In the Autobiography Collingwood described his weaning

from the brand of realism that he had been taught at Oxford, the

turning point occurring during his reflections on the Albert

Memorial sometime around 1917. At one end of this development is

the teaching of Cook Wilson and the other Oxford realists, and

at the other is the publication of Speculum Mentis in 1924,

which the Autobiography acknowledges was perceived by at least

one reviewer as the "usual idealistic nonsense." In between

these two points there is the publication of his first book,

Religion and Philosophy, in 1916, but actually "written some

years earlier, in order to tidy up and put behind me a number of

thoughts arising out of my juvenile studies in theology (A, 43).

Prior to the appearance of Speculum Mentis Collingwood published

a lecture entitled "Can the New Idealism Dispense with

Mysticism?" and several other articles dealing with the

distinction between science and history and Croce's philosophy.

From these points we should be able to sketch in the curvature

of his thought and compare it to that described in the

Autobiography.

106
107

Along the way we should be able to reconstruct what

Collingwood's understanding was of the realism-idealism issue,

before it hardened into the form it takes in his later writ-

ings--viz. the anti-realism of the Autobiography. This is a

crucial topic, since the starting point for virtually every one

of Collingwood's publications is a critique of the realistic

position of the subject under investigation. Furthermore his

interpreters, as we saw in Chapter I, have used this issue to

discredit the accuracy of the autobiographical account. Indeed

it is difficult to understand how Collingwood could deny that in

the years following the war he thought and wrote as an advocate

of a school of thought widely recognized under the title

"idealism"--as the 1924 article on the "New Idealism"

illustrates. Yet in the Autobiography Collingwood writes that

Speculum Mentis was neither "usual" nor "idealistic" (A, 57). We

shall have to decide on the basis of his use of the term whether

this is a sheer piece of effrontery or if it would be like Hegel

denying that he was an idealist --where the term means

"subjective idealism" of the sort he attributed to the Kantian

philosophy.

The idealism-realism issue is also a strategic boundary

in the interpretation of Collingwood, since (as we also saw in

Chapter I) Rubinoff uses Speculum Mentis as a basic program for

interpreting the entire remainder of Collingwood's philosophy,

and views Collingwood as an


108

unregenerated idealist of an Hegelian pedigree, whereas Donagan

reconstructs what he regards as the steps by which Collingwood

worked his way free from his youthful idealism and forged a

philosophy of mind on linguistic and analytic principles. And

where Rubinoff has to explain why such terms as "absolute

knowledge" and "dialectic" tend to disappear in the later

writings, Donagan has to account for Collingwood's continued and

uncompromising anti-realism in these same works. And finally,

where Rubinoff has to account for the reversal from the

condemnation of abstraction in Speculum Mentis to the apparent

endorsement of it for all higher thought in The New Leviathan,

Donagan, who uses this as an index of Collingwood's conversion

from idealism, must account for the striking difference between

the descriptions of this process of abstraction in the same two

works-a point that we will examine more carefully in later

chapters.

In all of this discussion we must therefore try to be as

clear as the texts will allow us to be on the senses of the

terms "idealism" and "realism" as Collingwood formulates them.

This will necessitate trying to be clear about certain other

related terms, since what we are trying to do is to flesh out

the bones of the abstract formula for realism from the

Autobiography, "Knowing makes no difference to what is known."

What does Collingwood mean by each of the terms, "object,"

"knowing," and "makes a difference"? As we shall see in this and

subsequent chapters, the sense of


109

the formula shifts with the meaning of the terms: where

"knowing" means "perception" the difference knowing makes to the

object of perception is not completely equivalent to the

situation in which "knowing" means "history" and the object is

the thought of an historical agent. And when Collingwood rejects

realism with his autobiographical anti-realistic argument, one

must pay careful attention to the situation in which it is

applied in order not to discard the baby with the bath water.

When he rejects the abstractions of realism in Speculum Mentis,

for example, we must ask if there is any acceptable sense of

"abstraction" that is salvagable from the condemnation as

distinct from the realism that it is aimed at overcoming. And

similarly when we find the project of "absolute knowledge"

collapsing for lack of any concrete subject matter at the end of

Speculum Mentis, we have to ask if from the wreckage we can find

any principles on which a more solid structure of thought can be

erected. (Some of this work will occupy us in the next three

chapters.)

2. Realism and Idealism in Religion and Philosophy.

If we were to begin where a beginning should really be

made, we would probably never achieve the limited goals we have

set for ourselves. A proper assessment of Collingwood's

background would require sketching out not only the realistic

doctrines of Cook Wilson and the Oxford realists but also of the

shadowy figure of Bradley, whose thought was


110

still very much alive—even if only as the target of realistic

critics.1 From this point one could trace the issues backwards

or forwards: backward into the roots of Collingwood’s idealism

in Bradley, Green, Hegel, Kant, and Berkeley, and the sources of

the realism he opposed in Mill, Hume, and Locke; and forward

into the fruits of idealism contemporaneous to Collingwood in

the Italian idealists, Croce, Gentile, and de Ruggiero, and the

development of realism with Alexander, Moore, Ayer and Russell.

All of this would make fascinating reading and would be a

welcome study and an invaluable background work for the

understanding of Collingwood’s philosophy. Having said that we

shall say little more about these matters, except by way of

occasional footnotes suggesting interesting parallels or

contrasts. Our task is to understand Collingwood’s philosophy

as interpreted by the Autobiography, and limitations in both

space and our own background necessitate leaving these matters

for another time.

The place for us to start is with Collingwood’s early

publication, Religion and Philosophy, which we anticipate will

give evidence of Collingwood’s early tolerance of realism. As

expected, this work exhibits an ambivalent attitude toward

realism. On the one hand Collingwood writes that what he is

saying “contains little if anything which

____________________
1 C.J. Warnock, English Philosophy Since 1900 (Oxford,
1964), pp 1-12. Cf. John Passmore, A Hundred Years of Philosophy
(Baltimore, 1957/1968), pp 48-71, 240-57.
111

contradicts the principles of either Realism or Idealism in

their more satisfactory forms,"2 and adds that "There is an

idealism with which I feel little sympathy, and there is a

so-called realism which seems to be only distinguishable from

that idealism by its attempt to evade its own conclusions" (RP,

101, n. 1; FR, n. 1).3 On the other hand (and even this passage

shows a leaning in this direction), in the same work Collingwood

admits that in at least one controversy the position he is de-

fending "would claim the title of idealism" (RP, 94-95). The

only way for us to understand where Collingwood stands in this

early work is therefore to look a little more closely at the

positions he is analyzing and the arguments he puts forward to

confirm or reject them.

Religion and Philosophy is laid out in three parts. Part

I examines the general nature of religion, and attempts to

examine the

____________________
2 In this same footnote he cites with apparent approval
the work of Joachim on The Nature of Truth on the one hand and
Prichard's Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Carritt's Theory of
Beauty on the other as representing the "more satisfactory forms
of the theories he hopes not to be contradicting. In the
Autobiography Collingwood identified Carritt as his realist
tutor, and H. A. Prichard as following Cook Wilson, and H. H.
Joachim as a close personal friend of Bradley and later of
Collingwood (A, 18, 20-22).

3 In-text citations from Religion and Philosophy are


followed by citations from the publication, Faith and Reason,
ed. by L. Rubinoff, because the former is out of print, and
portions of it appear in the latter work. Where no second
citation follows the reference to RP, it does not also appear in
FR.
112

distinction of religion from ritual, conduct, and feeling, and

to identify it as "creed," i.e. its intellectual element.

Furthermore it examines the distinction between religion and

conduct (thought and action), history, science, and philosophy.

To anticipate later conclusions, we might add that it is in this

part that Collingwood not only engages in wholesale

identification of apparently distinct subject-matters (religion

as creed is identified with history, philosophy, and even, by

implication, science; thought and action are identified; etc.),

but also sets up many of the problems against which he would

later struggle in Speculum Mentis. Part II takes up the

metaphysical issues of proving the existence of God, the dualism

of matter and mind, personal identity, and evil--these issues

all approached in a manner which first analyzes a claim, then

its counter-claim, and then attempts to state on which side the

truth appears to reside. Part III is more properly theological

in tone, dealing in successive chapters with the self-expression

of God in Man, in the person of the Christ; God's redemption of

Man; and the problem of Miracles.

As can be seen from this glance at the table of con-

tents, there is a good deal of interesting material in this very

early work, and we must resist the temptation to deal with all

of it (some of it will appear in later chapters--the issue of

the "identities" will appear, for example, in


113

Chapter VI on rapprochement). What we seek to clarify at this

point is how Collingwood stood on the issues of idealism and

realism, and this requires us to limit ourselves primarily to

the material presented in Part II, "Religion and Metaphysics."

In particular we want to find out the way in which Collingwood

understood the independent status of objects of knowledge.

As in most of his subsequent writings, Collingwood

prefaces his positive treatment of the subject with a critique

of false views of the subject matter. In Part I Collingwood

singles out psychology as characteristic of the way the phe-

nomenon of mind in general, and religious thinking in particu-

lar, is improperly approached. When composing the Autobiography

Collingwood recalled this passage with evident approval (A, 93),

and in re-reading it he may have prepared himself for writing

the anti-psychological chapters in the Essay on Metaphysics,

which it strikingly anticipates. Psychology, Collingwood writes,

is distinguished from the philosophical sciences of logic and

ethics (which also study the mind) not by its subject-matter but

by its method.

The method peculiar to psychology may perhaps be described


as follows. The psychology of knowing differs from logic or
the philosophical theory of knowledge in that it treats a
judgement--the act of knowing something--as an event in the
mind, a historical fact. It does not go on to determine the
relation of this mental event to the "something" known, the
reality beyond the act which the mind, in that act,
apprehends. Such a further investigation would be
metaphysical in character and is therefore avoided by psy-
chology. Now this formula can be universalized, and thus
gives us the definition of the
114

psychological method. Take the mental activity as a


self-contained fact; refuse, so far as that is possible, to
treat of its metaphysical aspect, its relation with real
things other than itself; and you have psychology. Thus in
scientific thought as studied by logic we have a judgement
in which the mind knows reality: psychology, treating the
judgement as a mere event, omits its reference to reality,
that is to say, does not raise the question whether it is
true. (RP, 40; FR, 75-76).

In a footnote Collingwood adds that the same omission or ab-

straction is made by formal logic, which he takes to be a psy-

chological rather than a philosophical science (RP, 40, n. 2;

FR, 76, n. 2).

Here we have in germ a strategy which comes to fruition

in Collingwood's later philosophy of history as a re-

interpretation of the act-object distinction, i.e. the dis-

tinction between an act of consciousness and the object of such

an act, where the former is regarded by realists as an event in

the subjective or psychological life of a conscious agent (cf.

IN, 282-301). Our present interest is in the "metaphysical"

aspect of the "reality beyond the act" which the mind

apprehends. Throughout this chapter and those which follow,

where Collingwood's anti-realism is being evaluated we will use

this independent reality of the object as an index to measure

the degree of his anti-realism, bearing in mind that in each

case we must try to assess the meaning of the terms involved. It

is, after all, the object's independence from the act of

knowledge which is at the center not only of Collingwood's


115

autobiographical realist formula, but also of the historical

issue as Collingwood inherited it.4

The passage about psychology which we have just quoted

is taken from a chapter on religion and history, in which

Collingwood is trying to demonstrate that religious creed is not

devoid of reference to historical factuality. The attack on

psychology is carried out because the psychology of religion,

while pretending to deal with the phenomenon of religious

consciousness, fails to do so precisely because it ignores this

factual reference: a mind regarded in an external way, i.e.

without reference to its object, "really ceases to be a mind at

all," and the knowledge gained by studying it in this way "is

not knowledge of anything, but barren and trifling abstraction"

(RP, 42; FR, 77). In a later passage he comments that empirical

psychology treats mind exactly as if it were matter (RP,

__________________
4 Cf. Bertrand Russell, "Logical Atomism," in Contemporary
British Philosophy, ed. J. H. Muirhead (London, 1924), I, p.
360: "For some years I was a disciple of Mr. Bradley, but about
1898 I changed my views, largely as a result of arguments with
G. E. Moore. I could no longer believe that knowing makes any
difference to what is known." A more technical version of the
formula was given by Russell some years earlier in "Meinong's
Theory of Complexes and Assumptions," Mind, n.s. XIII (1904), p.
204: "every presentation and every belief must have an object
other than itself, and, except in certain cases where mental
existents happen to be concerned, extra-mental; . . . and . . .
the object of a thought, even when this object does not exist,
has a Being which is in no way dependent upon its being an
object of thought." R. M. Chisholm in his "Editor's
Introduction" to Realism and the Background of Phenomenology
(New York, 1960), p. 3, n. 1, quotes Russell as saying that he
had been led to accept these theses by Mr. G. E. Moore, and that
"Except Frege, I know of no writer on the theory of knowledge
who comes as near to this position as Meinong."
116

76). But when it comes to describing the nature of history in

contrast to this Collingwood endorses what appears to be a

blatantly realistic definition:

History must be regarded not as a mechanical process, nor


yet as a gradual accumulation of truths, but simply as ob-
jectivity; as the real fact of which we are conscious.
History is that which actually exists; fact, as something
independent of my own or your knowledge of it. In this
sense there would be no philosophy without it; for no form
of consciousness can exist without an object. (RP, 49; FR,
83).

At this point in his development Collingwood had not yet come to

a full realization of what he would later call the ideality of

history, and as the subsequent discussion illustrates, history

is not yet confined to deeds of men. In Chapter V we shall see

how this primitive idea of history became refined in the essays

written between 1920 and 1930.

But what of this concept of a fact as "something inde-

pendent of my own or your knowledge of it"? Where we might be

tempted to soften its realistic impact by qualifying it as dis-

tinct from an object (the factuality of anything is its given-

ness, its aspect of independence, which says nothing about the

facticity of objects, or about their independent existence or

reality), it is better to let it serve as a statement forming

the limit of Collingwood's early attitude toward realism. We

shall never again encounter him affirming anything like it--

unless it is as a premise which he was setting out to demolish.

The problem of the reality of objects makes its appearance in a

later chapter in the discussion of what


117

he calls the "plain man's metaphysic:"

Popular metaphysic distinguishes two categories of reality,


mind and matter. Mind is a reality whose qualities are
thought, will, and so forth; it is not extended over space
or divisible into parts. Matter, on the other hand, occupies
space, and is homogeneously subdivisible into smaller parts;
it has no consciousness of itself as mind does . . . . Mind
is active . . . matter is passive . . . . We have thus three
hypotheses before us. Either the world is entirely material,
or it is entirely spiritual, or it is a compound of the
two . . . . (M)aterialism will admit the existence of
thought, but will try to explain it as a kind of mechanism;
the opposite theory (which for the sake of convenience I
shall call idealism) will admit the existence of mechanism,
but will try to describe it in such a way that its operation
is seen to be a form of spiritual activity. (RP, 72-73).

In a footnote Collingwood adds that the sense of the term

"idealism" which is opposed to materialism "must be carefully

distinguished from Idealism as a theory of knowledge. The

former, concerned with the antithesis between mind and matter,

has no connexion whatever with the latter, which concerns the

quite different antithesis of subject and object, and is opposed

not to Materialism but to Realism" (RP, 73, n. 1).

Here a preliminary distinction has been drawn between

metaphysical and epistemological idealism, and although one

might question whether they truly have "no connexion whatever"

with one another,5 such an equivocation on the term might allow

Collingwood to deny being an idealist (in the

__________________
5 We shall try to avoid being drawn into a protracted
historical discussion of what the various meanings of the term
"idealism" have been--since the title encompasses everything
from Platonic archetypalism to Husserlian essentialism, and
along the way from one end of this spectrum to the other, cuts
across both Kantian and Hegelian territory. Nevertheless to say
that the metaphysical and epistemological
118

metaphysical sense) without being committed thereby to a denial

that he was an idealist in the epistemological sense. More

importantly, Collingwood does not view the realism-idealism con-

troversy in a metaphysical sense--as it might be viewed by

someone who takes realism to be a statement about independent

existence of objects, in which case it is saying something about

reality rather than something about our knowledge of it. For

Collingwood realism is not a metaphysical issue but an

epistemological one, i.e. one which says something not about

reality but about our knowledge of it.

After some argumentation criticizing rigid adherence to

the materialistic hypothesis (partly based on the impossibility

of importing mind-characteristics into a purely mechanistic

description of the world, and partly based on the failure of

mechanists to defend the principle of causality), Collingwood

pays the mechanistic devil his due. Materialism satisfies the

scientist's demand for uniformity, regularity, and

generality--all of which are satisfied by a materialistic

philosophy (RP, 91). But that is not all.

Another merit of materialism is its insistence on fact, on


reality as something beyond the power of the individual

__________________
forms of idealism have nothing whatsoever to do with one another
ignores the fact that Berkeley's idealism arises from a critique
of the concept of matter from a practitioner of epistemological
empiricism.
119

mind to create or alter. Matter is supremely objective. And


when it is said that mind is the only reality, the
suggestion at once arises that the world is less solid, less
satisfying, less "real" than we believed . . . . Materialism
. . . is right as against those theories which make the
world an illusion or a dream of my own individual mind; but
while it is right to insist on objectivity, it goes too far
in describing the objective world not only as something
different from, and incapable of being created or destroyed
by, my own mind, but as something different and aloof from
mind in general. (RP, 92-93).

We shall find Collingwood making this point in various forms

repeatedly throughout his philosophical writings, but usually

not in defense of materialism. Whatever mind may make of the

world, it is not simply the creation of one's own imagination

--a view that Collingwood called "subjective idealism" (RP,

120)6 and one which he tended to associate with solipsism.

____________________
6 This is the title Hegel applied to the Kantian cri-
tical philosophy. Hegel faulted Kant for stopping short with the
analysis of experience at that point at which objects of
experience are shown to be mere appearances (phenomena), whereas
the view that Hegel advocates is absolute idealism, which holds
that objects of experience are not only mere phenomena for us
but in their own nature, since their existence is founded not in
themselves but in the universal divine Idea. Cf. The Logic of
Hegel, tr. from The Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences
by William Wallace (Oxford, 1873), pp. 93-94. Kant himself
refuted a form of idealism which he called "material
idealism"--the theory which declares the existence of objects in
space outside us to be merely doubtful and indemonstrable (the
problematic idealism of Descartes) or to be false and impossible
(the dogmatic idealism of Berkeley)--Immanuel Kant's Critique of
Pure Reason, tr. by N. Kemp Smith (New York, 1961), B 274, p.
244. Collingwood's use of the term is closer to Kant's "material
idealism" than to Hegel's "subjective idealism."
120

The outcome of the discussion of the matter vs. Mind

controversy is that "we cannot conceive matter without ascribing

to it some qualities of mind, nor mind without ascribing to it

some qualities of matter" (RP, 93-94)--in short, the "mixed"

hypothesis. But even here there is a definite tilt towards

idealism.

To ask whether mind is a form of matter or matter a form of


mind is largely a question of words. The important thing is
that we should be able to bring the two into relation at
all; that we should hold such a conception of matter as does
not prevent us from admitting truth, morality, and life as a
whole to be real facts, and that we should hold such a
conception of mind as does not reduce the world to an
illusion and experience to a dream. The first of these
errors is that of crude materialism, and the second that of
an equally crude idealism. The view for which we are
contending would claim the title of idealism rather than
materialism, but only because the current conception of mind
seems a more adequate description of the world than the
current conception of matter. We are laying stress on the
fact that the world is the place of freedom and
consciousness, not of blind determinism; and at present this
can best be conveyed by saying that mind is the one reality.
(RP, 94-95).

A similar fate awaits the immanence-transcendence question in a

later chapter. God must be regarded as both immanent and

transcendent: immanent because all human knowledge and goodness

are the very indwelling of his

_______________________
7 Collingwood closes the chapter with the suggestion
that he does not wish to exclude a "higher materialism" which
would "regard matter as nothing else than mind itself in its
concrete existence, and mind as the life and operation of mat-
ter"--but this must wait for physics to develop to the point
where it can adopt a principle which would regard all matter as
in its degree a form of life (RP, 95).
121

spirit in the mind of man; and transcendent because God has

attained these things whether or not man attains them, his being

not depending upon the success of human endeavor (RP, 119). But

when he asks if God exists only as a "spirit in our hearts" or

if he is also a real person "with a life of his own, whether we

know him or not," he confesses that this is not an easy phil-

osophical problem to solve.

The difficulty of answering this question is bound up with a


well-known philosophical puzzle, the puzzle of how to prove
the existence of anything except as present to the mind. If
it is true that things cease to exist when we are not
thinking of them, . . . then it follows by the same argument
that God is immanent only, and exists nowhere but in the
mind of men. But we cannot really believe that these things
are so . . . . The arguments for pure immanence are at
bottom identical with the philosophical creed of subjective
idealism, and with that creed they stand or fall. (RP,
119-20; FR, 188-89).

If God is not entirely an immanent idea, what objective

status does the concept have? Can the existence of God be

proven? Collingwood argues that the traditional proofs for the

existence of God are not so much impossible as premature: what

is required is to first define what one means by "God," which

involves finding some definite content to the concept-the task

of theology. "No one can prove that God exists, if no definite

significance is attached to the words" (RP, 64).8

______________________
8 Collingwood does not deny that the existence of God
can be proven--he merely postpones it until after an adequate
concept of God has been developed. But after he spends the
remainder of Religion and Philosophy expending considerable
effort to develop just such a concept, he does not conclude his
study with any such proof. Nor does one appear in
122

The only course open to the sceptic who doubts the existence of

God is to discover what he actually thinks, and then to find out

if that idea was justified or not (RP, 69).

This is an extension of a principle which Collingwood

lays down as fundamental to all thought, and which is an early

statement of the principle of intentionality, the modification

of which we will be watching closely in succeeding chapters. In

its earliest formulation it is expressed as follows:

The mind is specifically that which knows the


object . . . . The mind seems to be not so much that which
thinks as the thinking itself; it is not an active thing so
much as an activity. Its esse is cogitare. . . . All con-
sciousness is the consciousness of something definite, the
thought of this thing or of that thing; there is no thought
in general but only particular thoughts about particular
things. The esse of mind is not cogitare simply, but de hac
re cogitare. (RP, 100; FR, 172).

When two minds think the same thought it is never exactly the

same in terms of emphasis or applications peculiar to the

individual; but that does not mean that such a difference

destroys the identity of the truth, or its ability to be the same

truth thought by two different minds (RP, 106; FR, 177).

___________________
any of his writings. What one finds instead is a favorable
discussion of the ontological argument in the Essay on
Philosophical Method (EPM, 124-26), and a very idiomatic use of
the argument in the Essay on Metaphysics (EM, 185-90), which
declares that the statement-God exists" is not a verifiably true
or false proposition, but an absolute presupposition, and
therefore that the ontological proof is only a way for
Christians like St. Anselm to say what in fact they believe. If
Religion and Philosophy is Collingwood's theology, his
philosophy of religion remains unpublished. (Cf. RP, 16; FR,
53-54).
123
In Chapter VI we shall take up the issue of Collingwood's use of

the term "identity" as he uses it in Religion and Philosophy and

Speculum Mentis.9

On the strength of the passages we have been examining

we can say that in this early publication Collingwood already

shows a leaning toward an epistemological form of idealism, but

at the same time he rejects both a "metaphysical" or subjective

idealism which would assert that objects of knowledge are simple

creations or imaginings of subjective consciousness. With

respect to realism he displays a certain tolerance--as in the

notion of "fact" as something independent of any knowledge of

it, and in the distinction between an act of consciousness and

its object (although he says nothing about the esse of the

object to correspond to the esse of

____________________
9 Our purpose in this chapter is to examine Collingwood's
early views on realism and idealism, and it is only secondary to
this that we have become involved in the issues of the
philosophy of religion. But we do not mean to leave the reader
dangling on the issues we have just raised--some of which we
will meet again repeatedly in different chapters. The conception
of God that Collingwood develops in Religion and Philosophy is
basically that of the Christian God--centering on the
Incarnation as the means by which the creator God overcomes his
transcendence. The unity of man and God occurs through a
"concrete union . . . attained in and by the identification of
the self in all its aspects with the perfect mind of God" (RP,
150; FR, 254). This is achieved in the person of the Christ, who
"has absolute experience of the nature of God and lives in
absolute free obedience to his will" (RP, 166; FR, 267). Insofar
as any man achieves a similar concrete identity of will with the
mind of God he achieves union with God (RP, 160, 167; FR, 262,
268). Whether such a person as the Christ actually existed is an
historical issue that Collingwood declines to consider (RP, 151;
FR, 254).
124

consciousness). Similarly he shows a tolerance for the positive

aspects of materialism as a philosophy which, with proper

modifications, is able to satisfy the scientific demand for

uniformity and generality. We have not yet found any form of the

anti-realism argument as outlined in the Autobiography, nor any

linkage of realism and abstraction. The situation, in short, is

pretty much what we would expect it to be on the grounds of the

autobiographical interpretation.

3. Idealism, the Absolute, and the Metaphysic of Knowledge.

In a short piece published after a symposium in 1923

(the year before Speculum Mentis), Collingwood responded to a

paper by Evelyn Underhill on the "new idealism"--by which she

meant the philosophy of Croce and Gentile (FYC, 85). Under hill

charged the Italian idealists with failing to provide room for

mysticism in their account of the forms of experience, and

Collingwood (who had just finished translating Guido de

Ruggiero's Modern Philosophy 1O) undertook a defense of Gentile's

___________________
10 Collingwood translated three of Croce's works and two
books by Croce's disciple, Guido de Ruggiero--see Johnston, FYC,
66. Johnston's book also has a sketchy chapter on Collingwood's
relation to Croce and the Italian idealists, whose influence on
Collingwood Johnston aptly summarizes under the rubric
formulated by Collingwood himself, that "to borrow is to
interpret" (FYC, 89). "Collingwood asks us to focus not on what
was borrowed, but on what led the borrower to select what he did
. . . . It was the multiplicity of his interests and his command
of many fields of learning which made Collingwood 'capable of
borrowing' from Croce, Gentile, and Vico. It was his almost
unique intellectual versatility which 'laid (Collingwood) open
to their influence'" (FYC, 88-89).
125

religious philosophy against her attack. The interest for us of

this brief and tactful article is in the distinctions that

Collingwood draws concerning idealism, which if they do not

directly reflect his commitment to the school of thought he is

discussing, at least indicates to us his understanding of it.

Collingwood corrects Miss Underhill's misconception that

the new idealism "dispenses with mysticism" in the sense that it

ignores an intuitive or immediate consciousness of the supreme

reality as one, eternal, and spiritual. On the contrary, both

Croce and Gentile identify mysticism with religion (FR, 270).11

Gentile in particular does not deny the existence of an absolute

object of thought such as that which mystics

contemplate--something that is one, eternal, and unchanging; nor

is Gentile's philosophy exhausted by calling it a philosophy of

change like that of Bergson for whom absolute reality is an

absolute flux (FR, 273). This misconception is taken over from

Bosanquet, whose view Collingwood corrects as follows:

_____________________
1l Collingwood recognizes that Croce did not represent
religion as one of the "necessary forms of the spirit" in his
systematic philosophy (FR, 270), but adds that it provides the
hint of a new attitude towards religion that "in Gentile blos-
soms into a complete new attitude to religion" (FR, 271-72).
Johnston adds that Croce "accords religion scant place," and
that in this "he differs significantly from Collingwood, who all
his life regarded religion as a necessary, even indispensable
component of culture" (FYC, 70).
126

reality, for Gentile, is history. Now history is not, as


Miss Underhill assumes, a synonym for change. Change
is . . . a realistic concept, history an idealistic. That
which changes is a mere object, which need not know that it
is changing, and indeed which no one need know to be
changing. The philosophy of change is a "metaphysics of
being," that is, a philosophy which tries to describe the
world as a thing in itself without raising the question how
it comes to be known. And there can be little doubt that the
philosophy of change makes the world unknowable. That which
has a history, on the other hand, is a mind, for matter may
change but it cannot be said to have a history . . . . Hence
Gentile's philosophy is a "metaphysic of knowledge," that is
to say, a philosophy which never loses sight of the question
"how do we come to know what we know?" (FR, 274).

In the light of what we shall find Collingwood saying in

Speculum Mentis in this and the next three chapters, it can

hardly be doubted that Collingwood would describe his own

philosophy as a "metaphysic of knowledge." But is that

idealism? By 1923 it is clear that Collingwood had recognized

the essential ideality of history, and had already moved away

from a conception of history as simply "factuality." In Chapter

V we shall observe the staging of this development; at this

point we are interested in the way in which Collingwood

describes idealism. In the essay under consideration Collingwood

finds in Gentile an expression of the common ground of all

idealism (FR, 277), the double aspect of mind as both active and

passive, expressed by Gentile as the identity of act and fact:

(C)hange in a mind must be change for that mind, a change


of which That mind is conscious; and to be conscious of it,
the mind must somehow be raised above it. How is this ap-
parent contradiction to be realized? How is the mind to be
at once in change and out of change?
127

Only if the mind originates change in itself. For then, as


the source and ground of change, it will not be subject to
change; while on the other hand, as undergoing change
through its own free act, it will exhibit change. This
double aspect of the mind as active and passive is the very
heart of Gentile's philosophy. It is his favorite
distinction of act and fact. (FR, 275).

But if the identity of act and fact is the equivalent of Croce's

principle of immanence, what room is there for a principle of

transcendence? Gentile assigns the name of religion or mysticism

to the losing of the mind in its object--the transcendent

element of all human life. The synthesis of the immanent element

of life (which Gentile calls art) with the transcendent is

philosophy, which seeks the absolute, defined (citing Hegel for

support) as "that which has reconciled its own opposite to

itself, and therefore no longer stands in opposition to it" (FR,

276). Collingwood therefore states that in pursuing the

absolute, Gentile's philosophy "is as convinced of the necessity

of transcendence as Miss Underhill herself . . . . That

reconciliation of the opposing principles of immanence and

transcendence which both regard as possible, necessary, and

indeed actual, she calls mysticism, and ((Gentile)) calls it

philosophy" (FR, 276-77). It is, he adds, in basic agreement

with Hegel's Absolute Spirit and the post-Kantian tradition in

philosophy (FR, 277). For this tradition, mysticism is a thing

which cannot be dispensed with -- not as something intuitional

or wholly immediate, but as something assimilated by the labor

of the life of the mind (FR, 278-79).


128

The necessity of mystical experience lies in the principle


that we discover new truths neither by the inference of the
logic-books nor by the intuition of Aristotle, but by an act
of mind which reaches out beyond the given, grasps the new
thought as it were in the dark, and only after that
consolidates its new conquest by building up to it a bridge
of reasoned proof. (FR, 281).

In this discussion of Gentile we find Collingwood de-

fending a form of absolute idealism, and defending it against

attack not from the point of view of someone who finds it

problematic in the sense of failing to show how the object is

unaffected by the knowing of it (epistemological realism), but

from the point of view of someone who charges it with failing to

provide sufficient grounds for mystical religious experience. In

the next section we shall find Collingwood widening this

discussion to include all forms of experience, and deepening his

commitment to absolute idealism at the same time that he begins

to lay the foundation for moving beyond it.

4. Absolute Idealism and the Forms of Experience.

In 1916, when Religion and Philosophy was published, we

found Collingwood stating that the argument he was advocating

did not conflict with either realism or idealism in their more

satisfactory forms. By 1924 not only had his point of view

shifted in the direction of absolute idealism, but his earlier

tolerance had completely vanished. In Speculum Mentis

Collingwood was prepared to take a stronger stand against re-

alism and all its ramifications, and it was this work that

earned him the


129

reputation of being an "idealist." It is a label that he

explicitly rejected, but in much the same sense that he had

rejected it in Religion and Philosophy:

Idealism . . . is the doctrine that the world is made, so to


speak, of mind; and is regarded as the opposite of ma-
terialism or the doctrine that the world is made of matter.
Both of these theories begin by abstracting the object of
knowledge from the subject, and both go on by inquiring into
the nature of the object in this abstraction, regarded as a
thing in itself. Both agree in committing the fundamental
error of separating the metaphysical inquiry as to what the
world is in itself from the psychological inquiry as to how
we come to know it. Idealism in this sense leaves
unreconciled the opposition between subject and object, and
therefore sets the object outside the subject; . . . it
tries to bridge the gap by ascribing to the object some kind
of consubstantiality with the subject, turning it into
another mind, a society of minds (spiritual pluralism) or an
infinite mind (theism). With anything which deserves the
name of idealism in this sense we have nothing to do except
reject it. (SM, 266-67).

What is being rejected is the "metaphysical idealism" that he

had contrasted with materialism in Religion and Philosophy.

But what of the "epistemological idealism" that is

contrasted with realism over the issue of whether knowledge

makes a difference to the object known? Speculum Mentis widens

our horizon beyond the object of religious knowledge; it is an

analysis of successive "forms of experience," each of which

competes with all the others for the "prize of truth" --that is,

the successful fulfillment of its claim to be true knowledge

(SM, 42). Each form of experience is a conscious attitude with

respect to the known, an activity which has both cognitive and


130

practical aspects (SM, 39, 42, 44). In short, each is knowledge

claiming to be wisdom.

Five such forms of experience are examined--art, reli-

gion, science, history, and philosophy--although the list is not

exhaustive of all possible forms (SM, 41, 57, 280). As concrete

activities engaging the whole self, each form of experience

regards the others as illegitimate contenders for the prize of

truth, "rival ways of conceiving the whole"--the "whole" being

that conception of reality which will allow the mind to live the

unified life that it sees and needs in order to be totally

satisfied (SM, 36-37, 47-48). Consequently the forms of

experience cannot be regarded as mere species of a genus, each

taking a portion of the prize: "each denies the others; and

because they are not species they have not that indifference

with respect to one another which characterizes abstract logical

classifications" (SM, 55). Each iS to be examined on its own

merits or in accordance with its own claims, in order to

discover whether its claim is consistent with its actual

performance.

Our map ((of knowledge)) . . . is to be a statement of the


essential nature or structure of each successive form of
experience, based on actual knowledge of that form from
within, and concentrated upon the search for inconsisten-
cies, rifts which when we come to put a strain on the fabric
will widen and deepen and ultimately destroy it. (SM, 45).

When such inconsistencies appear it is the task of a higher order

form of
131

experience to repair the damage by constructing "from without" a

self-conscious justification of the primary, inconsistent form

(SM, 250, 252-55).

Since we will be engaging in an explicit discussion of

the form of experience called science in Chapter IV, of history

in Chapter V, and of the overall argument of Speculum Mentis in

Chapter VI, rather than attempting a detailed analysis of the

contents at this point we shall first present Collingwood's own

summary of the five forms of experience in the Outlines of a

Philosophy of Art which appeared the following year (reprinted

in EPA, 45-154), and then focus on those sections of Speculum

Mentis which particularly reveal Collingwood's views on idealism

and realism.

After stating at some length a general theory of art,

Collingwood locates art within the context of the life of the

spirit, which he characterizes as follows:

The life of the spirit is an indivisible whole within which


are necessary and permanent distinctions: permanent in the
sense that the spirit in its own activity perpetually
affirms them, and necessary in the sense that the attempt
not to affirm them would merely result in affirming them
over again. Fundamentally, the spirit is awareness or
consciousness, which implies a prima facie distinction
between the conscious spirit and the world of which it is
conscious; but since this awareness is itself an act, a
self-modification on the part of the spirit, the passivity
of pure awareness rests upon the creativity of action, and
the life of the spirit is a whole within which
consciousness and action, awareness of the world and modi-
fication of the world are correlative elements. The unity
of these two elements is feeling, where that of which we
are aware is our own states, and
132

these states are identical with the feeling of them: they


are at once states of consciousness and objects of
consciousness.(EPA, 137-38).

Coming upon this passage after reading Collingwood's defense of

"the new idealism" it is hardly possible to ignore Collingwood's

commitment to an idealism at least similar to that of the

Italian philosophers, Croce and Gentile. For certainly the view

expressed here represents the unity of "act and fact" or the

duality of spirit or consciousness as both active and passive--a

view that Collingwood had called the common ground of all

idealism. Furthermore it appears that this distinction is at

least post-Kantian, and probably Hegelian: the con-

sciousness-object distinction is described as occurring within

spirit ("a self-modification on the part of spirit") rather than

forming the limit of spirit beyond which lies an unintelligible

thing-in-itself.

Furthermore Collingwood imbues this structure with an

internal dynamism which propels it through the stages of the

"forms of experience":

Hence a rhythm in which awareness and activity concentrate


themselves into the unity of feeling, and feeling again
articulates itself into awareness and activity, is funda-
mental in all aspects of spiritual life. But life is not a
mere rotation of three psychological categories in a
rhythmical monotony. This triple rhythm is present in all
life, but it is never twice alike; its whole character is
altered by the specific difference of the experience in
which it is embodied. These differences emerge in the course
of a process which on its theoretical side may be called the
spirit's attempt to know itself, on its practical side the
spirit's attempt to create itself. To know itself means also
knowing its world, and to create itself means creating its
world; its world in the former case means the world
133

of which it is aware, in the latter case the world in which


it can live. (EPA, 138).

It is clear that when Collingwood refers to "objects" or "the

world" he means primarily objects of consciousness--what he had

called, in Religion and Philosophy, de hac re cogitare. It

refers to the objective correlate of acts of consciousness, and

when the term "object" is used henceforth without further

qualification this is the sense we shall have in mind. If we

mean to refer to a "thing" we shall call it a "physical object"

or an object having extra-mental reference.

The first stage in the life of spirit is the life of art

or the pure act of imagination--i.e. "the act of consciousness

which presents to itself an object of whose relation to other

objects it takes no cognizance" (EPA, 139). It is important to

bear in mind that by imagination Collingwood does not mean a

faculty which creates objects which appear to be presented in

perception; in an earlier section of this essay Collingwood

makes this point more clearly than he ever did in his subsequent

writings:

In art there are always a subject and an object, a con-


templator and something contemplated. But the subject's
activity, the object's nature, and the character of the
relation between them have certain peculiarities which
distinguish the case of art from other cases. What the
subject does is to imagine: the object is an imaginary
object, and the relation between them is that the individual
or empirical act of imagining creates the object. In
knowledge, on the other hand, the object is real; and the
relation between them is that the empirical act of knowing
presupposes the object and does not create it.
134

This may be said without prejudice to the idealistic view


that there is an absolute or transcendent sense in which
knowing creates its object; for no idealist is so innocent
as to confuse knowledge with imagination and to suppose
that what we generally call knowing is simply imagining.
(EPA, 52).

The caveat against the "idealist" here is clearly against the

"subjective idealist." Furthermore by "the empirical act of

knowing" Collingwood clearly means perception. We shall find

that throughout Collingwood's writings he never intimates that

in perception consciousness creates an object ex nihilo: and

this is the abhorrent sense of "idealist" that he rejected

throughout his published works.

If the essence of artistic consciousness or aesthetic

experience is its monadism, i.e. its contemplation of an object

without relating it to other objects, its practical aspect

appears in play--the immersing of ourselves in an activity

without any question as to the relation of this activity and

anything else. "Just as art does not explain itself by stating

reasons, so play does not explain itself by stating reasons; and

immediacy means the absence of reasons" (EPA, 139-40). But

neither simple imagination nor simple play can remain in this

immediacy as a complete and self-contained form of consciousness:

It is only within a consciousness which distinguishes truth


from falsehood that we can find in actual existence that
consciousness which does not distinguish them . . . . The
question "what am I?" can therefore no longer be answered in
terms of imagination; I am not
135

merely an imaginer but a thinker. The question "what is my


world?" must be answered by saying that it is a world not
merely of fancies but of realities. But if I who think am
also the I who imagine, it would seem natural to superimpose
the act of thinking on the act of imagining in such a way
that the real is merely one division of the imaginary. The
only world whose existence we have learned to recognize is
the world of our own imaginations; and when the distinction
between reality and unreality forces itself upon us . . . we
impose this distinction upon the world of imaginations, and
regard certain imaginations as true and others as false. To
do this is to break with the life of art; for . . . now we
are asserting one imaginary object as real, and denying
another as unreal; and to do this is to embark upon the life
of religion. (EPA, 140-41).

I have quoted this passage at some length because it is

our first contact with a transition between forms of con-

sciousness, and is expressed without much of the complicating

circumlocutions of Speculum Mentis. In fact it is exemplary in

its simplicity, and gives us a clear sense of how Collingwood

envisioned distinctions occurring within the unified life of the

spirit: when a distinction like that between reality and

unreality "forces" itself upon us, it is imposed on the unity of

the form of consciousness which thereafter regards its objects

under this oppositional distinction. In religion this takes the

form of mythological or metaphorical expression, insofar as

religion "says one thing and means another" by using imagery to

convey a truth. Nevertheless religion marks an advance in the

life of spirit:

(I)n religion that indifference to the distinction between


real and unreal, which is the essence of art, is abolished.
Religion is essentially a quest after truth and explicitly
conscious of itself as such a quest. But the truth which it
can and does discover is a truth
136

which is always hidden from view in a reliquary of


symbolism: we see the imagery, but we do not see the truth;
we are only conscious that the truth is there, and its
presence converts the beauty of the imagery into holiness.
But inasmuch as this holiness is a property of a mere
symbol, religion always contains an element of idolatry and
superstition. (EPA, 141).12

Religion, like art, cannot survive the disruptive force

of the tension between metaphorical and literal language. When

it attempts to overcome its own superstitious tendencies it is

forced to distinguish thought from its own imagery, and in the

process "the symbol loses its holiness and becomes merely sig-

nificant" (EPA, 142). With the distinction between metaphorical

and literal expression the life of explicit or self conscious

thought is reached. While art forgets the presence of thought

and concentrates on the pure imagery of language, and where

religious thought was immediately identified with the language

expressing it, scientific consciousness separates thought from

language and intellect from imagination.

Here thought is regarded as an activity self-contained and


self-sufficient, and its object as a self-contained and
self-sufficient intelligible world, reached through, but
lying behind, the sensible world. The aim of science is to
apprehend this purely intelligible world as a thing in
itself, an object which is what it is independently of all
thinking . . . . The world of thought is the universal, the
timeless and spaceless, the absolutely necessary, whereas
the world of sense is the contingent, the changing

__________________
12 Remarks like this make it difficult to assess Col-
lingwood's true estimate of religion, which here seems to have
slipped somewhat under the high position he accords it in
Religion and Philosophy. In Chapter VI we shall review
Collingwood's remarks about religious consciousness and try to
judge the extent to which his view of religion is reductive.
137

and moving appearance which somehow indicates or symbolizes


it. (EPA, 142).

The distinction is the separation of reality from appearance,

the necessary from the contingent, which ultimately poses prob-

lems for scientific consciousness. Science cannot bridge the gap

between the abstract universal and the particular, the necessary

and the contingent, reality and appearance.l3

The overcoming of this opposition is the achievement of the


form of experience known as history. Appearance and reality,
imagination and thought, have been merely distinguished and
not related: they must somehow be brought together again and
shown to be equally necessary, each to the other. This need
is satisfied by the historical consciousness, whose object
is the individual; no longer an abstract universal divorced
from its own equally abstract particulars, but a universal
that particularizes itself, a particular constituted by its
own universality. For history, the truth is no longer an
abstract necessity which nowhere actually exists; it is
concrete and actual, it is real in every sense of the word,
while the truth of science is a reality which is in one
sense utterly unreal, and ideal never realized, a law which
has no instances. (EPA, 143).

___________________
13 Collingwood's view of science in these early writings
is primarily based on the classical Greek notions of science,
perhaps modified by Renaissance advances, but hardly based on
first-hand knowledge of work in the physical and biological
sciences of his day. It is therefore somewhat understandable why
this form of experience is least articulated and not altogether
satisfactory. Having stated the requirement for other forms of
experience that the philosopher of it must be one who not only
observes the experience of others but has engaged in the
activity for himself (EPA, 153), Collingwood was in a weak
position to describe the nature of scientific experience.
Nevertheless we shall try always to evaluate what he says about
it as a reflection of his own understanding of it rather than
what natural science is in itself or in the contemporary
understanding of it. What he does understand by it is sometimes
quite remarkable, as we shall see in Chapter IV.
138

But history too has its fatal flaw. The historian presumes a

world of fact which is already there for him to discover, and

for which the historian is a mere spectator. The fact is a thing

in itself, "a thing whose existence and nature are supposed to

be wholly independent of the thinker" (EPA, 143). This

constitutes the separation of subject and object--a relic of the

abstractness of science remaining in history.14

This abstractness is only overcome in philosophy. The object


of philosophy is nothing short of reality, a reality which
includes both the fact of which the historian is aware and
his awareness of that fact. The philosopher . . . is not,
like the historian, outside his own picture; he sees himself
as part of the historical process which he studies, and
therefore part of his problem is to understand how that
historical process has thrown up in its development an
organ--namely himself--which is at once a part of it and the
spectator of it. With this clue in his hand . . . he is able
to reinterpret that process itself, and to see in every
phase of it a nisus towards self-consciousness. And in
realizing that history is the emergence of the spirit's
consciousness of itself he is actually achieving that
consciousness . . . . His knowledge is therefore explicitly
action; he is creating himself by knowing himself, and so
creating for himself an intelligible world, the world of the
spirit in general. (EPA, 143-44).

Since we are treading on the margins of territories that we

prefer to leave for later chapters, we shall leave off this

discussion of the forms of experience with the conception of

philosophy just given. In Chapter VI

_______________
14 As Collingwood's idea of history developed he struggled
against this very criticism, and his development of the concept
of "re-enactment" is an attempt to overcome the difficulty
completely. The extent to which this constitutes an adequate
rapprochement between history and philosophy will be evaluated
in Chapter IX.
139

we shall be in a better position to evaluate Collingwood's

project for a philosophy of "absolute knowledge."

But we have several particular ideas from Speculum

Mentis to attend to, and to these we must now turn.

5. Speculum Mentis and the Emergence of Explicit Anti-Realism.

In the last section when we discussed the way in which

the five forms of experience competed, as rival ways of con-

ceiving the whole, for the prize of truth, we noted that when a

particular form of experience exhibits inconsistencies it be-

comes the task of a higher form of experience to resolve the

disparity. That form of experience is philosophy, whose main

task is to attain self-consciousness and therefore to overcome

all the contradictions that arise due to the subject-object

dichotomy. In Speculum Mentis this process gives rise to the

construction of what Collingwood calls "dogmatic philosophy"--

i.e. a form of consciousness which is conscious of itself, but

imposes on itself the limits of a particular form of experi-

ence--art, religion, etc.--which it undertakes to justify as the

only true form of experience. But these are errors that the mind

makes about itself, and since the esse of mind is de hac

re_cogitare, it follows that when the mind takes itself as its

object, an error about that object is an error that it makes

about itself--an error that is immediately reflected in the

mind's activities under the


140

erroneous conception of itself: "the mind, having formed a false

conception of itself, tries to live up to that conception. But

the falseness of the conception just means that it cannot be

'lived up to"' (SM, 250).

Art, religion, science, and history are thus philosophical


errors, and owe their characteristics, and the char-
acteristics attributed by them to their ostensible objects,
to the initial error on which each is based . . . . Each
grasps "one aspect of the truth," as we say, forgetting
that truth is a whole whose aspects cannot be thus
separated: each is true, even while it is false . . . .
Error is always present in truth, but negatively present,
that is to say, it is present as that which is
denied. . . .This interdependence of truth and error, error
containing truth positively and truth containing error
negatively, is not only a fact easily verified in empirical
observation . . . but is a corollary of the fact that all
knowledge is self-knowledge, and every error an error about
the knowing mind. Hence an abstraction which separates
subject and object also separates truth and error (good and
evil, and so on), and . . . is a logical consequence of
realism, for if there were a world of real objects
completely other than the mind, absolute errors could no
doubt be made concerning them. (SM, 250-52).

Here for the first time we encounter Collingwood at-

tributing to realism all the errors that the mind makes about

itself. But if we are to become aware of the genesis of this

generalization, we must return to the conception of "fact" with

which we began our investigation of realism in the section on

Religion and Philosophy. Where in that earlier work Collingwood

appeared to be content with leaving uncriticized the concept of

historical "fact" as "something independent of my own or your

knowledge of it," this immunity is no longer respected. The

philosopher knows what


141

the historian does not know, "that his own knowledge of facts is

organic to the facts themselves, that his mind is these facts

knowing themselves and these facts are his mind knowing itself"

(SM, 295; cf. SM, 287). Modern realism arises from the discovery

of the concept of fact, which soon develops into the "historical

form of dogmatism" (SM, 281):

Historical dogmatism is the assertion of fact as ultimately


real, and fact means not only the facts of "history" but the
facts of perception. Such a dogmatism may take a
considerable number of forms ((several of which Collingwood
lists: monism and pluralism, intuitionism and intel-
lectualism, materialism and spiritualism, etc.)) . . . .
That which unites all these divergent views is their common
assertion of the positivity of the object, that is, their
denial that the object is conditioned or affected by
becoming known to any thinking mind or to what, with a
question-begging epithet, is sometimes called finite mind:
its finiteness being just this indifference to it on the
part of its object. Such a realistic account of the object,
as positive fact indifferent to its being known, is at first
sight compatible with any theory as to what the ultimate
nature of this object may be; and so we get all manner of
realisms . . . all equally capable of being held in
combination with the fundamental thesis of realism, which is
distinguished from them as "theory of knowledge" from
"metaphysics." (SM, 282-83).

Here we find a clear statement of what the Autobiography called

the central doctrine of realism. This formulation never changed

substantially in Collingwood's writings.15

______________________
15 Cf. EPA, 182-83 (1925); EPH, 99-100 (1933); EPM,
161-62, 169-70 (1933); IH, v, 142 (1936). The term "realism"
does not appear in some of the later writings because the move-
ment ceased to maintain its positions under that title. But
Collingwood's arguments were directed against the same positions
as they were now maintained under the titles of positivism and
empiricism: cf. PA, 130-31, 149-51 (1938); EM, 34-35, 37-38,
337-38 (1940); NL, 5.2, 5.31-5.32, 5.39 (1942).
142

Just as in the Autobiography it is presented primarily as a

negative thesis: the negative formula that knowledge can make no

difference to its object. But the realist is caught in a

positive antithesis to which he is equally committed--a

coincidentia oppositorum which could not help but embarrass a

subscriber to formal logic. If reality consists of a collection

of objects independent of the mind which knows them, then a

pluralistic realism is affirmed--a universe in which objects and

minds both occur. But on the other hand the historian presumes

that all facts fall into place in a single all-embracing system

of fact, and this system is the absolute, the ultimate

reality--a monistic realism which conflicts with its latent

pluralism precisely over the status of the thinker. Collingwood

phrases the dilemma as follows:

For either the thinker himself falls inside the absolute


whole or he does not. If he does then differences in his
thought about it make a difference to it, and the more
concretely real--that is, organized and interconnected in
all its parts--it is, the more fundamental these differences
will be and the more completely the positivity of fact is
lost. If he does not, then the monistic doctrine is
surrendered and we return to pluralism. (SM, 283-84).

While this is an issue that appears to arise only from within

the perspective of the form of experience called philosophy,

Collingwood emphasizes that it is a problem that arises from

within the historical standpoint itself. The fundamental

principle of history, the concreteness of the object, makes it

impossible for it to define its object in such a


143

way that it leaves out the subject, i.e. the historian, and

"compels us to recognize an object to which the subject is

organic, in the sense that the subject's consciousness of it

makes a real difference to it as a whole and to all its parts,"

so that "(b)eing known, whether truly known or erroneously

known, must make a difference to the object" (SM, 244).

Just as the formulation of the central doctrine of

realism corresponds to the statement of it in the Autobiography,

so one also finds in Speculum Mentis a rejection of the

principle in an argument employing the same strategy. However

the argument introduces a complication in the form of the

principle of abstraction, an issue to which we shall return

after having a look at the argument.

(A)ny object considered in abstraction from a mind which


knows it is neither material nor mental, but an illusion, a
false abstraction. Thus we do not say that the objective
world in itself is mental. If we are asked what it is apart
from a mind that knows it, we shall answer that it is not
"apart from" such a mind; it is "with" it in the sense of
being known by it. If we are asked what it would be apart
from such a mind, we shall answer that the very question
implies the suggestio falsi that we can describe that which
by definition is unknown. (SM, 267-68; cf. SM, 241).

Notice that the nerve of this argument is the absurdity that

results from suggesting that we can describe (and hence know)

what has been defined as something that is unknown, i.e. the

world as it is "apart from" the mind which knows it. This is

slightly different wording from the Autobiography,


144

but essentially the same argument as the one that he claims to

have given at Oxford in a paper which refuted the central

negative tenet of realism (A, 44). It is also noteworthy that

although the phrase "in abstraction from" is employed in

connection with this refutation of realism, its use in the

argument is confined to the meaning, "apart from," as is

indicated by the fact that Collingwood replaces the phrase with

this expression without any change in the resulting sense of the

argument.

But since Alan Donagan has made the issue of abstraction

central to his interpretation of Collingwood's development (see

Chapter I), we should take careful note of this meaning of the

term in Speculum Mentis, so that when we encounter it again in

its altered meaning in Chapter VIII we shall have some basis for

comparison. Furthermore it plays such a prominent role in

Speculum Mentis and its connection with realism is so strong

that it would be hard to ignore it. Collingwood himself ties the

concepts of realism and abstraction together:

Such was . . . and to some extent still is, the belief of


eminent realists, who sum up their own position in the
negative formula that knowledge can make no difference to
its object. On the other hand, it is not possible to assert
so much as this without asserting more, namely the principle
of abstract thought; for what is explicitly asserted is the
complete separateness of subject and object, their
independence of one another: and this implies that there are
facts in existence which are thus completely independent. It
is therefore correct to maintain that realism commits its
author to the principle of pluralism; and pluralism only
means the scientific abstraction of the universal from its
particulars. This path, therefore, leads from historical
dogmatism back to scientific dogmatism. (SM, 283).
145

It is this double implication that causes the basic inconsis-

tency within realism itself, and is responsible for the dual

role that realism is assigned in Speculum Mentis. On the one

hand realism is identified with the particular form of dogmatism

which he calls "historical"--history being taken as "the

assertion of concrete fact," and realism as the assertion of

this fact as ultimately real (SM, 281-87, 201-11). On the other

hand realism is identified with all forms of dogmatism, insofar

as realism is the willful resistance to any doubt that subject

and object are in all cases separate from one another, such an

act of will being the essence of the dogmatic attitude (SM,

259). Realism thus appears to be identified with both the

principle of abstraction (where abstraction means separation of

subject and object), and the principle of concrete factuality.

Collingwood himself recognizes this dual role, and charges the

realists themselves with it:

In spite of the simplicity of these difficulties, they have


not as yet been fairly faced by a single realist with whose
work the present writer is acquainted . . . . The fact is
that modern realism is essentially inconsistent. It is a
halt, or rather a confused running to and fro, between two
principles, the abstract concept and the concrete fact (SM,
284-85).

Speculum Mentis thus emerges as a philosophical work

which not only rejects realism but does so in large part on the

grounds of its principle of abstraction. It is the latter

principle which is responsible for all the errors that con-

sciousness makes about itself. "There is not


146

only one dogmatism; there are as many types of dogmatism as

there are types of abstraction" (SM, 268).16 "Every error is a

lapse from concreteness into abstraction, and all abstraction is

dogmatism" (SM, 288). "(T)he abstraction which separates subject

and object also separates truth and error (good and evil, and so

on) . . . . Such a melodramatic view of life is a logical

consequence of realism (SM, 252; cf. SM3259). "Abstract know-

ledge is the same as error . . . . But all error contains an

element of truth and the error appears as the externality of the

object, its otherness with respect to the mind" (SM, 313).

Furthermore realism and abstractionism are also held

responsible for most of the pernicious consequences of realism

that Collingwood listed in the Autobiography: an ethics which

separates knowledge from conduct (SM, 169-72); an epistemology

which defines knowledge in terms of intuition (SM, 188-94; cf.

SM, 255, 262, 283, and 293); a metaphysics which deals with

hypostatized or abstract universals concerning "nature or the

objective world" (SM, 271-81, especially 273 and 277; cf. SM,

158-63); and political theory which, in the guise of utili-

tarianism, pits the subjective will of the individual (as

desire) against the objective

________________________
16 How many types is that? Clearly more than Collingwood
enumerates in Speculum Mentis, since the abstraction that he
embraced in later years is not one of those considered among the
abstractive processes of the four sub-philosophical forms of
experience. See Chapter VIII, below. We leave it to the reader
to judge if that form of abstraction also qualifies as a
dogmatism.
147

will of society (as law), so that "in such a society one regards

every one else as a means to his own ends"--a society in which,

in other words, all goods are regarded as private (SM, 169-76,

221-31).

Nor is this anti-realism peculiar to Speculum Mentis

alone; many of these themes appear in different guises in ar-

ticles which he published during this period, and some of them

are brought out even more forcefully in later publications. It

is also instructive to pay attention to the synonyms that

Collingwood uses for realism. Thus what is called the "plain

man's metaphysic" in Religion and Philosophy, and "realism" in

Speculum Mentis, is called "the plain man's realism" defined as

"to think of the object as a 'thing in itself,' a thing existing

in and by itself" in a paper of 1928 on "The Limits of

Historical Knowledge" (EPH, 99). In a 1921 paper on "Croce's

Philosophy of History," Collingwood criticizes Croce for his

"vacillation between naturalism, for which some statements are

just true and other just false, and idealism, for which truth

and falsehood are inextricably united in every judgement" (EPH,

12)--the former representing the Croce who is "the realist,

dualist, empiricist, or naturalist, who delights in formal

distinctions and habitually works in dualistic or transcendent

terms"(EPH, 8). In passages such as these it is clear that

Collingwood tends to use interchangeably terms like realism,

naturalism, dualism, and empiricism.


148

This synonymous use of terms is further exemplified in a

1923 paper on "Sensation and Thought" in which Collingwood

attacked what he called "the empiricist fallacy" of divorcing

sensuous appearance from objective reality, or assuming "that a

distinction could be made between what a thing looks like and

what it is"l7--a distinction which is taken as "the infallible

mark of dogmatism (and consequently of realism) in all its

varieties" in Speculum Mentis (SM, 255; cf. SM, 77). Here we

have empiricism and naturalism described in terms identical with

the epistemological doctrine of realism. In a 1925 paper on

"Economics as a Philosophical Science" Collingwood reinforces

this identification of realism and empiricism by defining

"empirical thought" as "that which conceives its object as

substance or thing," as opposed to philosophical thought, which

conceives its object as activity.18 The distinction is virtually

repeated in "Political Action," a paper delivered before the

Aristotelian Society in 1928.19

6. Conclusion.

To say that "realism" as described in Speculum Mentis is

a protean monstrosity would hardly be an exaggeration, and one

cannot help but

____________________
17 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, XXIV (1923-
1924), p. 66.

18 International Journal of Ethics, XXXVI (1925), p. 162.

19 Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, XXIX (1928-


1929), p. 155.
149

wonder why any person of sound mind and civilized demeanor would

ever willingly describe himself as a realist. Are we dealing

with something which has any historically evidenced counterpart,

or is Collingwood presenting us with caricature as a foil for

his protagonist, absolute idealism? While we can certainly say

that at this point that the autobiographical interpretation on

the issue of realism is well supported by the evidence we have

been examining,20 we are left with a number of troubling

problems which we shall have to monitor closely in the chapters

which follow.

_________________
20 Two themes from his discussion of realism in the
Autobiography have not been discussed at this point: the non--
eternity of philosophical problems and the falsity of realistic
logic with its claim to one-one correspondence of propositions
with indicative sentences. We shall be examining Collingwood's
views on logic in the next chapter. Concerning the eternity of
problems, the closest one comes to a statement of his position
at this time is in a 1927 paper on "The Theory of Historical
Cycles" (EPH, 76-89), which argues that in one sense it is true
to say the the problem of politics is always the same, but in an
equally important sense it is always different. The abstract
goal of providing for the needs and betterment of a society
remains the same, but in each case this involves solving
different concrete problems (EPH, 85-87). The reader of the
quotations of the last few pages would not have much difficulty
in constructing an argument to overcome this difficulty: the
problems that philosophers are concerned with are eternal--the
same questions from generation to generation--only insofar as
they are initially taken as abstracted from the historical
situations in which they arise. The refusal to see these
questions and their historical context as related is a willful
dogmatism, and a species of the more fundamental error of
separating subject (the philosopher) and object (the problems he
considers). From an abstract point of view, then, there are
eternal questions and concepts--and such is the point of view of
the realist; from a concrete point of view, there are not--and
such is the viewpoint of the philosopher as historian.
150

The first of these is the issue we just raised. If there

are distinctions which Collingwood is willing to make within the

ranks of those who have been called idealists, so that when

Collingwood denies that Speculum Mentis is idealistic he can

remain in good faith with his readers by assuming that they

understand him to mean that he was not a subjective idealist,

are there no such equivalent distinctions to be found among the

ranks of the realists? While Collingwood tells his readers that

there are as many forms of error as there are forms of realism,

he fails to tell the reader what those forms might be. We shall

find in succeeding chapters that this issue remains unresolved,

and that the "realists" remain not only a shadowy group of

figures warming themselves by the bare fire of their negative

thesis, but also that the position being rejected becomes

progressively more indistinct as his polemic against it

increases in its fury.

What is clear from this polemic is that in discussing

realism Collingwood himself always employs an abstract sense of

"knowing" and "object" because he was dealing with the problem

from what he considered to be the realist's own perspective,

i.e. one which takes the perception of a physical, extra-mental

object as paradigmatic for all forms of knowing.21 This means

that by "realism" Collingwood had in mind

_____________________
21 Passmore writes that "British philosophy, preoccupied
with the theory of perception, tends to classify philosophical
theories by their attitude to the perception of material things:
'realism,' for it, is the view that material things exist even
when they are not being perceived,
151

the epistemological viewpoint which looks to empiricism as its

natural point of departure. That there might be non-empiricist

realists Collingwood never appears to have considered as is

clear from the fact that even in his criticism of a realist he

admired--Samuel Alexander--his main objection is to the fact

that he adopts an acquaintance theory of knowledge (EM, 17678).

His strategy is therefore to attack any sensation-bound theory

of knowledge which neglects the active role of thought in

perception, and to do so by emphasizing the contextual and

interpretative aspects of the perceptual process. In Chapter VII

we shall find Collingwood arguing against a different op-

ponent--G. E. Moore--and adopting a similar strategy, but one

which argues that the expression "sense datum" is intrinsically

absurd. But in both earlier and later writings, his point of

departure is the abstract statement of the realists that

"knowing makes no difference to the object known," where

"knowing" means perception, and "object known" means object of

perception.

Secondly, what about the connection between realism and

abstraction? Obviously an empiricist epistemology must account

for the existence of universal concepts and many do so by

providing a theory

_________________________
and 'idealism' is, most commonly, the view that they exist only
as objects of perception." Op. cit., p. 49, note.
152

which describes universals as arising by a process of

abstraction from particular sensible instances. In Speculum

Mentis Collingwood does not enter into a criticism of any such

abstractive process, nor is it the basis for attack on

"abstraction" as the root error of realism and all forms of

dogmatism. Speculum Mentis, adopting the stance of absolute

idealism, assumes that absolute truth resides only in the whole,

and "abstraction" is whatever divides this whole into atomic

parts. Just as Collingwood did not seem to consider the

possibility of a non-empiricist realism, in Speculum Mentis he

did not appear to consider a non-abstractive realism. But we

found him in at least one passage arguing against realism in a

way which does not entail any commitment to the principle of

abstraction (SM, 267-68), at least not in all senses of the

term. In Chapter VIII we shall find Collingwood proposing a

peculiar description of abstraction that does not involve

"separating" what is abstracted from its abstracting context,

and at that point we shall have to assess whether such a process

can be maintained within an anti-realistic framework. The

statements "all abstraction is falsification" and "abstraction

is necessary for all true judgements" may not be contradictory

when the appropriate interpreting qualifiers are added--"simple

abstraction" in the first assertion being semantically

discernible from concrete or "real abstraction" in the second.

But more of this in Chapter VIII.


153

Thirdly, we wish to point to a hidden presupposition in

these early discussions of realism and idealism, but one which

Collingwood stated early on in his career, and never abandoned.

In Religion and Philosophy Collingwood had already decided that

there was no such thing as a fixed human nature. This appears to

be a corollary of his principle that the esse of mind is de hac

re cogitare. "The question to be asked about mind," writes

Collingwood in 1916, "is not what it is, but what it does; a

question which the logic of things and qualities does not deal"

(RP, 165; FR, 266)--and herein lies an enormous part of the

program for the remainder of his philosophy. Not only does it

entail placing Collingwood on a collision course with empirical

psychology, which until the end of his life he criticized for

treating mind as if it were a thing, and acts of thought as if

they were events not significantly different from those of the

physical world; but it required him to formulate a logic

alternative to that of "things and qualities" in order to have

an instrument for dealing with what mind does without doing

violence to it in the process. In the next chapter we shall look

at Collingwood's early attempts to satisfy this requirement. We

can anticipate that, just as he found in the philosophy of

absolute idealism a kindred spirit for his anti-realistic

leanings, so he would also find in their logic an alternative to

the formal logic he presumed to be the tool of the realist

philosophers.
CHAPTER IV

QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS, LOGIC AND DIALECTIC

1. Introduction.

In the Autobiography Collingwood states that his Q-A

logic was not explicitly formulated until he was obliged to

confront the Albert Memorial on a daily basis during World War

I; but by 1917 it was, since he states that it was at that time

that he wrote a book called Truth and Contradiction, which was

refused by a publisher. After writing the Autobiography

Collingwood deliberately destroyed it (A, 29-30, 42, 99 n. 1).

In Chapter I we noted that Knox found it incredible that

Collingwood could have worked out his theory of absolute

presuppositions (which the Autobiography describes as part of

Q-A logic) prior to writing the Essay on Philosophical Method in

1932 (IH, x-xi). Since the Autobiography is not clear on what

exactly is included in the version of Q-A logic presented in

Truth and Contradiction, we have questioned Knox's judgment on

this issue. In this chapter we must try to find whatever

evidence we can in the writings prior to 1932 of the role of

questions and their presuppositions in the logical functions of

mental acts, and on the basis of this evidence to decide if

Collingwood's autobiographical interpretation can be

154
155

upheld on this point, or if he was deliberately trying to de-

ceive his readers (as one might suspect from his destruction of

the manuscript of Truth and Contradiction, which could be

interpreted as an attempt to cover his own tracks).

At this level of inquiry our task is plain: we are to

take up the early publications, including books, essays, and

published lectures, and examine them for statements concerning

questions, answers, and presuppositions. Unfortunately this task

is already complicated by the overlay of issues from the

previous chapter--especially the problems which arise due to his

early commitment to absolute idealism. For while Collingwood

disclaimed originality in rejecting propositional logic and the

propositional, correspondence, coherence, and pragmatic theories

of truth (A, 36), he appears to claim credit for recognizing

that truth is a property of the Q-A complex and not of

propositions as such (A, 38). Furthermore he clearly wants his

readers to believe that the alternative to formal logic was his

own Q-A logic, and that Q-A logic allowed him to answer his 1914

question about whether the realists' methods were sound: the

answer was that they were not, because "the 'realists'' chief

and only method was to analyse the position criticized into

various propositions, and detect contradictions between these,"

following as they did the rules of propositional logic (A, 42).


156

But if Collingwood could have been so historically

careless as to have forgotten, as other students of Oxford

realism have not, that it was Cook Wilson himself who was highly

critical of propositional logic, and who insisted that what the

actual subject or predicate of a statement was depended on what

question the statement is answering, 1 could he also have been

mistaken about other details concerning his "discovery" of Q-A

logic? What is particularly puzzling is Collingwood's failure in

the Autobiography to mention anything at all about dialectical

logic, and it is this oversight--or was it deliberate

neglect?--that is brought into focus by the issues raised in the

previous chapter. While it is true that in Religion and

Philosophy Collingwood employs a method of argument that relies

more on what he claimed in the Autobiography to be that of the

realists (i.e. analysis into contradictory propositions),

Speculum Mentis is beyond any reasonable shadow of a doubt built

upon the dialectical

___________________
1 "A point of particular importance . . . is Cook -
Wilson's criticism of the subject-predicate logic. First of all,
he sharply distinguishes between the Grammatical subject and the
logical subject, which the traditional logic is content . . . to
identify . . . . Everything depends upon what question ((a))
statement is answering . . . . (S)tress and context are ignored
by the traditional logic; thus there arises what Cook Wilson
regards as the absurd presumption that the noun which is
nominative to the principal verb in a statement is bound to
indicate the logical subject" (John Passmore, A Hundred Years of
Philosophy (Baltimore, 1957/1968), p. 244). Passmore also notes
that Cook Wilson criticized Bradley's dialectical method for
asking "unreal" questions, i.e. questions which cannot
intelligibly arise (op. cit., p. 246).
157

logic familiar to post-Kantian idealist philosophers. If

Collingwood was an anti-realist primarily because he became an

absolute idealist, then it is understandable that he would also

be opposed to a logic of atomic propositions, each externally

related to an equally atomic and distinct state of affairs in

the physical world, and that he would offer in its place a

dialectical logic of developmental processes more in keeping

with the active role of thought in reconciling oppositions. But

this is not the genesis of his thought as he outlined it in the

Autobiography, where the turn away from realism is described

without any mention of absolute idealism or dialectical logic.

In fact it is astonishing to find that there is no mention of

any of the Italian idealists in the Autobiography other than one

brief reference to Guido de Ruggiero as the recipient of a copy

of his manuscript, Libellus de Generatione, which outlined the

logic of historical process (A, 99). His description of this

process is also the closest that Collingwood comes in the

Autobiography to discussing dialectical logic (the term is not

used). In fact in reading the Autobiography one is inclined to

believe that while Collingwood read widely in his youth, in his

maturity he was philosophically influenced only by indigenous

British philosophers.

We already know this not to be the case. But if we are

to understand the Autobiography as an act of self-inter-

pretation, our concern


158

is less with such oversights as these--whatever their reason

might be 2 --than with the extent to which the account he gives

can make sense of his published writings, and it is to these

that we now turn without further prologue.

2. Abstract and Concrete Universals.

As one might expect, there is no mention of the ques-

tioning activity in Religion and Philosophy, nor of the Q-A

complex as the unity of knowledge. But there are scattered

remarks about logic, the universal, abstraction, and scientific

thinking which provide us a few clues about the way in which he

conceived these subjects prior to his turn to absolute idealism.

In the first chapter Collingwood tries to analyze what would be

meant by a philosophy of religion, and in the process outlines

what a "philosophy of" anything means:

The philosophy of any subject means careful reflexion upon


that subject; thus we have the philosophy of art, of
conduct, of science

_______________________
2 One such reason could very well be the political and
military polarizations which were occurring at this time in
Europe. In May of 1936 Italian forces entered the Abyssinian
capital of Addis Ababa, and in July of 1936 the Spanish Civil
War began. The Preface to Collingwood's Autobiography is dated 2
October 1938. In May of 1939 Germany and Italy signed the "Pact
of Steel." From June through August of 1939, Collingwood sailed
to Greece and Italy as First Mate of the schooner yacht, Fleur
de Lys. In The First Mate's Log he writes with outrage and
contempt of an incident with an Italian fascist harbor patrol in
Messina (FML, 170-74), and at the end of his account of the
voyage he describes the discovery by the crew, mostly from
Oxford, of the German-Russian alliance and the Nazi invasion of
Poland. In such circumstances it is understandable why
Collingwood might not wish to make an issue of expressing his
indebtedness to German and Italian idealism.
159

and so on. To do a thing, and to understand what one is


doing and how one does it, seem to be different
things; . . . to conduct an argument is science, to reflect
upon it is logic . . . . But the theory of knowledge or
logic does not consider differences of the object, but only
processes of the subject; and therefore there is no
distinction between the philosophy of religion (as theory of
religious knowledge) and the theory of knowledge in general.
If there is a general philosophy of knowing, it includes
religious knowledge as well as all other kinds; no separate
philosophy is required. (RP, 15; FR, 53).

As Collingwood's thought developed, nearly every statement in

this passage is modified to the point of contradiction, with the

exception of the definition of logic as a "theory of knowedge."3

By the time he came to write Speculum Mentis he had already

abandoned the idea of a "general philosophy of knowing"--as if

knowledge were a genus and cases of it were particular species;

and in the same work he denies that a theory of knowledge does

not consider differences of the object, but only "processes of

the subject." In fact even in Religion and Philosophy

Collingwood could

________________
3 In his chapter on Cook Wilson and Oxford philosophy,
Passmore writes: "Cook Wilson's main theme is logic, but logic
conceived in the Oxford manner, as a philosophical investigation
into thought rather than as the construction of a calculus. The
Boole-Schroder logic, indeed, Cook Wilson condemned as 'merely
trivial,' in comparison with 'the serious business of logic
proper '--inquiry into 'the forms of thought"' (op. cit., p.
240). It must be recalled that Collingwood learned his logic
from Cook Wilson, and never seems to have accepted any other
view than that the true task of logic is to understand the
"forms of thought"--cf. Chapter VIII, below. As Donagan rightly
notes, Collingwood completely failed to appreciate the
revolution in logic occurring during his lifetime.
160

not consistently maintain that logic considers only processes of

the subject, since in this work we have already found him

attacking psychology for treating a judgment (the act of knowing

something) as an event in the mind without going on to determine

the relation of this mental event to the reality beyond the act

which is being apprehended (RP, 40; FR, 75-76).

A more promising and enduring starting point is with his

remarks about the universal-particular distinction. In analyzing

the relationship of philosophy and history (as part of his

efforts to relate religion and history), Collingwood examines

the attempt to distinguish history and philosophy on the grounds

that they deal respectively with the particular and the

universal:

History, it is sometimes said, is knowledge of the par-


ticular, philosophy knowledge of the universal. But the
particular is no mere particular; it is a particular of this
or that universal; and the universal never can exist at all
except in the form of this or that particular. "The
universal" and "the particular" considered as separate
concrete things are fictions; and to equate the distinction
of philosophy and history with such a fictitious distinction
is to admit at once that it is untenable. (RP, 49-50; FR,
83).

Later Collingwood settles in much the same way the suggestion

that the Incarnation can be interpreted by means of the same

distinction--God as the universal and man as the particular. To

regard the universal as if it were something separate and

concrete is the result of a logic gone awry.


161

(T)he universal itself, which as a matter of fact exists


only in various particulars, is sometimes falsely conceived
as if it were itself another particular; and thus arises the
notion of an archetype or ideal specimen of a class to which
every less perfect member is an approximation. These ((are))
two tendencies of false logic, the tendency to elevate one
particular into the standard and only real instance of a
universal, and the tendency to hypostasize the universal
into a perfect and ideal particular . . . . (RP, 163).

What Collingwood suggests as an alternative to the

separate universal of false logic is what he calls a concrete

identity in Religion and Philosophy and the concrete universal

in Speculum Mentis. We shall deal with the latter in the next

section, but it will be helpful to have a provisional idea of

what he means by these terms. Evidently a universal refers to a

unity of some sort, and especially a unity which is capable of

being shared by two minds thinking about the same thing--such is

the minimal sense of "universal" at least since the time of

Socrates and Plato. When Collingwood asks how it is possible for

two minds to think the same thought, he begins by assuming the

factual existence of communication and knowledge (RP, 98, 109;

FR, 170, 180) and, like Kant, asks how this is possible. Since

all consciousness is the consciousness of something definite, it

follows that if one is thinking of anything at all it must be a

thought of something concrete; Collingwood goes so far as to say

that "One simply cannot make general statements without any

thought of their instances" (RP, 46; FR, 81). Two minds share

the same thought when that thought is a concrete identity, i.e.

one which has the characteristics of


162

a whole in each of whose parts the whole is entirely present

(RP, 88-89; cf. RP, 108, 112; FR, 179, 182). Collingwood

contrasts this concrete unity (manifested in personal identity)

with the abstract unity--i.e. what a thing is in itself as

opposed to what it is in relation to its context or the whole of

which it is a part; he argues that the character or self of a

thing, what it is, cannot be distinguished from its relations,

which consist in a quality of the thing itself (RP, 110-12; FR,

181-82).

Without going further into this discussion (we shall

take it up again in more detail in Chapter VI on rapprochement

identity), we can see already a drift in the direction of

idealism of the sort we discussed in Chapter III. It is also

transparent that Collingwood is making use of distinctions that

were known to anyone familiar with the logic of Bradley.4 The

contrast is between the abstract and concrete universals, and

while it is somewhat vague and imbedded in discussion of other

topics in Religion and Philosophy, it is explicit and prominent

in Speculum Mentis. But so is, we must add, the role of

questioning in knowledge.

In Religion and Philosophy Collingwood seems anxious to

take seriously the realists' principle "that the mind is one

thing and the

_____________________
4 F.H. Bradley, The Principles of Logic (Oxford, 1883),
vol. I, p. 188; cf. Bosanquet, The Principles of Individuality
and Value (London, 1927), pp. 35-39.
163

object another," although he immediately adds that "we cannot

rest content with the statement" (RP, 99; FR, 172). The theory

of knowledge contained in this early work seems to be an attempt

at a compromise between correspondence and coherence theories of

truth with the hope expressed that it would offend neither

realists nor idealists. On the one hand mental acts (judgments)

are defined and determined by their reference to objects (RP,

99-102; FR, 17173); on the other hand the "object" toward which

mental acts are directed turns out to be an

identity-in-difference (a concrete universal) whose "inner

structure" is entirely constituted by the necessary relations it

has as part of a whole (RP, 108-14; FR, 179-84).

But by 1924 Collingwood was less willing to grant any

ground to the realist at all. In Speculum Mentis knowledge in

its irreducible and simplest state is an activity of questioning

and answering, and the attempt to identify knowledge as anything

less than this is sharply dismissed:

A crude empiricism imagines that knowledge is composed


wholly of assertion: that to know and to assert are iden-
tical . . . . Knowledge as a past fact, as something dead
and done with--knowledge by the time it gets into encyclo-
pedias and textbooks--does consist of assertion . . . . But
those who look upon it as an affair of discovery and
exploration have never fallen into that error. People who
are acquainted with knowledge at first hand have always
known that assertions are only answers to questions. (SM,
77).
164

Here we have a declaration that sounds like it could be a direct

quote from the Autobiography. But as we have already seen, there

is a great deal else in Speculum Mentis that does not. One

noteworthy difference is that there seems to be a strong

inclination to accept coherence rather than P-Q-A complexes as a

touchstone of truth: Collingwood makes it clear from the start

that the various claimants to the title of truth--his five

"forms of experience"--are to be tested on their ultimate

self-consistency, that is, the coherence they exhibit in

attempting to live up to their own claims (SM, 4445). The

"self-consistency" that Collingwood has in mind, however, is not

merely freedom from propositional contradiction:

Now the characteristic mark by which a form of experience is


shown to be satisfactory is simply that it is possible . . .
. Any scheme ((i.e. form of experience)) which is in itself
contradictory or nonsensical cannot redeem ((its)) promises,
because it cannot be put into execution; but if there is any
scheme of life which is inherently consistent and therefore,
ideally speaking, practicable, we may safely assume that
this is the scheme to adopt. Self-consistency, then, is our
test.5 (SM, 44; cf. SM, 250).

Collingwood immediately adds that any criterion of truth resting

on a presumed correspondence either with human nature or with

the facts

__________________________
5 Cf. F. H. Bradley, Appearance and Reality (Oxford,
1893), p. 120: "Is there an absolute criterion? . . . Ultimate
reality is such that it does not contradict itself; here is an
absolute criterion. And it is proved absolute by the fact that,
either in endeavoring to deny it, or even in attempting to doubt
it, we tacitly assume its validity."
165

about the world is a mistake, because both of these are

inherently doubtful: what human nature is and what the facts

about the world are, are both open to legitimate questioning

(SM, 45). So it is apparent that if the usual form of

"coherence" is not exactly what Collingwood has in mind as a

criterion of truth, "correspondence" of consciousness and object

is no longer acceptable. Nor did he appear to entertain it

seriously again for the remainder of his published career.

Speculum Mentis also in part corrects, in part develops

his earlier views on logic. As in Religion and Philosophy, what

Collingwood is seeking is a philosophical logic, by which he

apparently meant something like Kant's transcendental logic,

i.e. a logic which does not regard mental acts considered in

abstraction from their reference to objects. It must therefore

be not the formal logic of the "abstract universal" (the unity,

identity, or sameness of a concept which is indifferent to the

variation or inter-relation of its own instances), but the

dialectical logic of the "concrete universal" (an

identity-in-difference, or a unity to which difference is

essential) (SM, 162-63). Collingwood's strategy in both of these

early works is to argue that the very attitude of consciousness

that regards all concepts or universals as abstract also

prevents the latter from being identified in any meaningful way

with their objects or instances--in a word, from referring. In

Religion and
166

Philosophy Collingwood limited himself to the case of religious

consciousness, and calls such an abstract attitude with respect

to religious objects "psychology" (RP, 40; FR, 75-76) (although

he does also speak of "abstract history"--this being the "mere

verbal description of events without any attempt at

understanding them," and abstract philosophy as "the dry

criticism of formal rules of thinking without any attempt at

grasping their application"-RP, 51; FR, 85). In Speculum Mentis

such an attitude towards objects of knowledge is taken to be

characteristic of science as such (SM, 158-63). In both cases

the reification of the abstract universal, that is, making it an

object of thought "separate" from its instantiations, is taken

as characteristic of the "realistic" point of view (SM, 189,

252, 282-85). But in Speculum Mentis objects of knowledge are

not described as "real things" or "facts" independent of

anyone's knowing of them, but rather are taken as the objective

correlates of acts of knowledge (SM, 11, 159, 287, 293-95, 310).

And as a consequence the tendency to regard logic merely as a

psychological science (a tendency opposed by such diverse

thinkers as Bradley and Frege) is overcome to some extent, and

logic is allowed to have its own innings--that is, to present

its case as a justification of science as an autonomous

discipline.

But since it is in Speculum Mentis that both Q-A logic

and formal logic (as the justification of science) make their

appearance, it is
167

necessary here to assess their relationship in order to see if

Collingwood's view in the Autobiography, which presents the

former as an alternative to the latter, is reflected in his

second major work. As we shall see, the linking concept between

the two is bound up with the activity of "supposal" or

hypothesis formation, which remains somewhat ambiguous--as one

might expect, since at this stage his reconciliation philosophy

was still incompletely worked out.

3. Science and Supposal.

The form of experience which regards its objects only as

particulars of a universal, as members of a class, or as

instances of a law, Collingwood calls "science" (SM, 158-63).

Whether the abstract concept makes its appearance as a Platonic

form, a medieval universal, or a Renaissance law of nature, the

characteristic viewpoint of scientific consciousness is that it

distinguishes between universals and particulars, and assumes

that the former can be abstracted by thought --i.e., separated

or isolated and studied apart from its instances (SM, 159-60,

180). Such an attitude is variously described by Collingwood as

the abstractness of the scientific concept (SM, 162), the

principle of the transcendence of the universal to the

particular (SM, 179), or the relation of difference without

identity (SM, 243). In any event it asserts the reality of the

abstract concept as indifferent to its exemplifications or to

the mutual
168

relations its instances have other than as members of a class

(SM, 162-63). Furthermore the abstract universal of science is

contrasted with the concrete universal of history:

Classification is the key-note of the scientific spirit;


but classification is nothing but the abstractness of the
scientific concept. For a class as such is a collection of
individuals without any mutual cohesion or organization
except their common membership of the class. They have no
reference to each other, but only to the universal; and
each one refers to the universal in precisely the same way
as every other. As soon as they refer to the universal in
different ways, or, what is the same thing, as soon as they
develop a system of mutual relations between themselves,
they cease to be a mere class and become an organized and
articulated system; and the universal ceases to be an
abstract universal (class-concept) and becomes a concrete
universal, or one to which the differences between its
particulars are relevant. (SM, 162-63).

The point at which science cannot maintain its object as an

abstract universal, and is forced to assert the reality of the

concrete universal is, therefore, the point at which science

ceases to survive as an autonomous form of experience and be-

comes dependent on another form of consciousness, viz. history

(SM, 180, 186-87; cf. 193).

That point occurs when scientific consciousness attempts

to deal with "facts," or to refer to objects and events given in

sensuous appearance. In its most elementary and primitive form

science is constructed in accordance with an a priori or

deductive ideal: it is the attempt to work out the implications

of the concept of a class as such, known independently of all

experience (SM, 164). Since the relations


169

of an indeterminate plurality of abstract units (the members of

a class) to a determining unity (the class itself) is precisely

what constitutes the numerical series, mathematics is the one

and only a priori science. Mathematics "is simply the theory of

order, where order means classificatory order, structure in its

most abstract possible form" (SM, 165). Pure mathematics deals

with classes (e.g. numerical sets) whose members are themselves

classes (numbers) (SM, 169). But if it claims to be objectively

true, mathematics turns out to be an illusion: it is "the truth

about nothing," since it is "the description of the structure of

a null class"(SM, 185).6

The attempt to import some sensuous content into these

empty class-concepts gives rise to the second phase of science:

science on the empirical or inductive model--an ordered

knowledge of "facts" (SM, 177; cf. 168). But the inductive

method (observation and experiment) does not supersede a priori

deduction; on the contrary, induction itself presumes a

principle variously described as the uniformity of nature, the

law of universal causation, etc. which induction is unable to

establish by its own methods, and which rests on the principle

of uniformity itself (SM,

______________________
6 This seems to be a variant of Russell's paradox--the
class of all classes both is and is not a member of itself. For
Collingwood's further use of this paradox, see SM 169, 189, and
192. Collingwood does not, however, seem to apply it to
mathematics itself, but only to mathematics insofar as it claims
to be objectively true.
170

178-79). If it is not to presume the very principle that it

seeks to prove, empirical science is forced to alter its

conception of its own object, and this leads to the third phase

of science: science as supposal.7

Science asserts, not the actual truth, but what would be


true if something ((else)) were true which is laid down as
an hypothesis. It asserts, never that S is P. but that if
there were an S it would be P. Its procedure therefore
consists, first, in making an assumption, secondly in de-
ducing consequences of that assumption. Throughout this
process it never makes an assertion, in the sense of a
categorical judgement, at all. Its judgements are hypo-
thetical from the beginning to end. (SM, 183).8

Such a process is utterly gratuitous: without a basis in pre-

vious assertions, Collingwood insists, no hypothesis can be

framed at all, much less relevant or illuminating hypotheses

(SM, 79). Supposal without a framework of assertion is arbitrary

and meaningless; but supposal within a framework of assertion is

something more than merely hypothetical. Its

____________________
7 Collingwood, true to a long standing tradition in
British philosophy, does not provide his reader with anything
but scant clues about the historical representatives of these
movements. The third phase has taken place "almost within living
memory" in the latter part of the 19th century, and is
represented by the "critical movement" and "scientific prag-
matism" (SM, 180-82). There is no hint in Speculum Mentis that
any movement in science follows this one.

8 Collingwood casts the hypothetical assertion in


subject-predicate form but it is clear that it applies equally
to propositional functions: the procedure of "making assump-
tions" and then "deducing the consequences of these assumptions"
is appropriate for propositions, since what is assumed is a
proposition, not merely the subject of an assertion.
171

object is not only something possible (viz. the alternatives en-

visaged in the hypothesis) but something actual, and this is

beyond the reach of mere supposal (SM, 187-88, 191, 199). Unless

science is to remain a tissue of hypotheses, and fact is

therefore permanently to elude the grasp of science, it must

have a categorical basis in actual assertions. (SM, 185).

On this objective ambiguity founders the autonomy of

science. If the objects of science are pure concepts (mathe-

maticals, universals), they are true of nothing actual at all;

but if science intends its laws to apply to real objects it

cannot deal with the latter by means of purely abstract con-

cepts; and finally, if science says that its object is neither a

null class nor something strictly speaking actual, but only

something possible, it renders its conclusions arbitrary. The

issue cannot be settled from within scientific consciousness

alone, and the attempt to settle it from without gives rise to

"scientific philosophy"--that form of dogmatism which, in the

guise of formal logic and metaphysics, presents itself as a

justification of the scientific attitude (SM, 271).

Since the deduction of consequences from hypothetical

assertions is governed by the rules of formal logic, the latter

is taken (by the critical and pragmatic defenders of the third,

and presumably still current phase of science) as the

justification of the methodology of science. But mathematical or

formal logic constructs its deductions in a


172

categorical fashion: its statements are demonstrably true of

every possible object--true, that is, categorically. Insofar as

formal logic is the categorical basis for the (hypothetical)

mathematical formulation of scientific assertions, mathematical

truths themselves are taken as "true without qualification of

the entire world, actual and possible" (SM, 184-85). Unfor-

tunately this conflicts with the conclusion that mathematics had

reached about itself as the "theory of order"--viz. that it is

the description of the structure of a null class, the truth

about nothing. Formal logic of itself is not able, therefore, to

extricate third-phase science from its difficulties: laws that

are categorically true of every possible object are true of

everything in general, but of nothing in particular. Formal

logic may be able to distinguish valid from invalid inferences,

but without metaphysics as its necessary correlate, such a

vindication of the principles on which scientific thinking is

founded may only be true for thought alone, and not for thought

that is directed to an object (SM, 272-73).

(W)e must demonstrate that what we have hitherto called


logic or the theory of ((scientific)) thought is really
metaphysics or the theory of reality, and that what we have
called the laws of thought are the laws of being. But this
is precisely what we cannot do. Metaphysics is impossible
((on scientific grounds)); for its task is to vindicate the
objective validity of the ways in which we think, and if
there are any flaws in our methods of thought, these will
affect our metaphysical theory of reality and introduce into
it the very mistakes which by its help we had hoped to
eradicate. Hence the theory of being as distinct from
thinking (metaphysics) will only be the theory of thinking
as
173

distinct from being (logic) expressed in different


terminology, but subject to the same fatal weakness, namely
that just as logic can never analyze real thinking--thinking
that, going on in the logician's mind, always lies behind
((i.e. beyond)) his analysis--so metaphysics can never
analyze real being, being as it is in itself untainted by
thought. (SM, 273-74).

In short, scientific consciousness is left permanently and ir-

reparably without justification because its principle of ab-

straction renders its objects (individuals, particular matters

of fact) utterly beyond the reach of its principles (laws, ne-

cessary principles of order) (SM, 185-86, 277).

What science is left with as a justification of its own

viewpoint is a psychology of abstract consciousness which fails

for the very reasons that Collingwood had advanced in Religion

and Philosophy--viz. since it fails to take into account the

truth or falsity of the thought it examines ab extra, as an

event, it cannot justify itself as anything more than another

mental event alongside the first (rather than an explanation of

the thought it claims to be observing) (SM, 274-77). Psychology

(or, more properly, psychologism) marks the point at which

scientific consciousness fails to achieve wisdom or

self-conscious self-justification, just as history marks the

point at which science fails to achieve concrete knowledge of

fact--the difference being that history provides the

justification of the scientific attitude that psychology cannot

(SM, 186, 193). But of this we shall have more to say in the

immediately following chapter.


174

It is important to realize (both for an understanding of

the argument in Speculum Mentis and for an assessment of the

relationship of Q-A and formal logic) that when a form of

experience is show to fail in its claim to be the whole truth

about its object, it is exposed as an error, but it is not

thereby utterly discredited and completely rejected. Since it is

an error that consciousness makes about itself, that error is

overcome only when it is criticized and shown to rely on

something other than itself for its validity (SM, 244-45, 255,

288-91, 296-97). Consequently when scientific consciousness

"collapses" it does not collapse into nothing, but leaves behind

"solid assets" in the form of a pure science of mathematics and

an empirical-hypothetical science of nature, with mathematical

logic and metaphysics as their partial justification, and the

psychology of concrete mind as their absolute justification (SM,

271-72, 277-78, 280, 317; cf. "ST", 73-75). One of the "solid

assets" for Collingwood's philosophy is the status of questions

and answers in this context.

And since the purpose of this excursion through one

portion of Collingwood's "phenomenology of error"9 was to assess

the relationship

_____________________
9 Cf. SM, 289; Collingwood rejects this title as a de-
scription of what he is doing, but in at least one sense of the
term "phenomenology" --as a description of how states of
consciousness appear or manifest themselves--it is still a
correct description of what he is doing in Speculum Mentis.
Collingwood rejects the term because he claims not only to be
merely describing, but also stating the truth about the forms
of experience he is describing.
175

between Q-A logic and formal logic, it is time to make good our

previous assertion that the connecting link is an ambiguous

notion of hypothesis or supposal. The entertainment of an

hypothesis is, according to Speculum Mentis, equivalent to the

asking of a question:

Science is explicitly supposal. But supposal itself . . . is


identical with questioning, which is the cutting edge of the
mind, an activity not self-contained or independent, but
implying behind it a body of information or
assertion . . . . But it is the facts that are true; the
scientific simplification of them into instances of laws,
abstract particulars of abstract concepts, is not true but
arbitrary, useful no doubt, but useful precisely because it
is not asserted as true but merely entertained in the form
of a question. (SM, 186).

But the entertainment of an hypothesis in the form of a question

turns out to be a complex mental function, since hypothesis

formation is identified not only with questioning but also with

"intuition":

The paradox of science may be expressed by calling it in-


tuitive thought. Intuition is the questioning, immediate
side of experience: thought is the asserting, explanatory
side. Science is explicit to itself as thought, but it turns
out on inquiry to be identical with the questioning
activity; that is, it realizes the contradiction of a type
of thought which is not thought precisely because it is
thought's opposite, intuition. (SM, 188).

Collingwood is quick to add that the division of experience into

intuition and thought is an abstract fiction, and represents

only a distinction between two sides of the indivisible whole of

experience--"an immediate, intuitive, or questioning side" and a

"mediating, reflective, logical or


176

assertive side," the former being called sensation and the

latter, thought (SM, 95, 188; cf. "ST", 57-58). But the willful

enforcement of this distinction by scientific consciousness is

another manifestation of its self-contradictory or paradoxical

nature:

It is this falling-back upon intuition that constitutes the


irrationality, the arbitrariness of all science. The
assumptions made by science cannot be justified under
criticism; their only justification is the frankly irra-
tional fiat of the scientist's will. The concept is for him
an abstraction, that is to say hypostasized into a thing,
reified; hence it cannot be explained by thought, it can
only be intuited, and this intuitive attitude towards a
concept is what is meant by assumption in science. (SM,
189).

It is at this point that the ambiguity of hypothesis or

assumption becomes apparent--a ghost that not only remains

unexercised in the body of science, but which survives to haunt

Collingwood's Q-A logic. If assertion is the minimum activity

claiming truth or falsity (SM, 59-60), then (with respect to

assertion) hypothesizing, questioning, and intuition have one

and the function: each is a suspension of the activity of

asserting (SM, 78-79, 186, 188-89). But there are important

differences which such an identification overlooks, and which

are crucial not only for formal logic but for a Q-A logic which

seeks to replace it.

(1) Questions are not merely non-assertions, they are

proto-assertions -- non-assertions about to become assertions.


177

It may be true that "supposal and questioning are at bottom the

same thing" (insofar as asking a question, like framing an

hypothesis, means contemplating the non-existent in the form of

several alternatives, only one of which may be existent), but

"true questioning is a suspension ((of assertion)) which looks

forward to a renewal of this asserting activity, in the shape of

an answer" (SM, 78-79). "Hypothesis" as Collingwood uses the

term in Speculum Mentis vacillates between these two

senses--i.e. proto-assertion and non-assertion-and it is not

until the Essay on Metaphysics that the distinction is clearly

made between questions, assertions, suppositions, and

presuppositions (EM, 21-33).

(2) In Speculum Mentis meaningful questions do have a

bi-directionality, looking both forward to an answer and back-

ward to other assertions (SM, 79), but there is no clear re-

cognition that the assertions which ground questions may be

non-factual but yet meaningful--i.e. function as what he was

later to call "presuppositions." Instead Collingwood leaves the

reader to decide whether the categorical assertions, which are

logically prior to hypotheticals (SM, 183: cf. "ST", 64), are

necessarily or only factually true. Thus, for example, within

two pages he speaks about the mind "categorically asserting a

concrete fact"
178

(when it sets about framing hypotheses),l0 and about

mathematical logic being "categorically true of every possible

object" (SM, 184-85). These are the factual and the

inferentially necessary senses, respectively, of the term. It is

not until the Essay on Philosophical Method that Collingwood

would try again to say what he means by a "categorical

assertion" (EPM, 117-36).

(3) Underlying both of these ambiguities is a basic

equivocation on the use of the phrase, "mental activity," which

leaves mental dispositions (conscious attitudes involved in

raising questions, framing hypotheses, asserting a proposition,

etc.) undistinguished from logical functions (formal properties

of interrogative sentences, hypothetical assertions, categorical

propositions, etc.)ll This leads to certain

_______________________
10 Cf. EPH, 45-46 (1924): "(S)cientific thinking is an
abstract thinking, historical thinking a concrete thinking. In
other words, because the object of science is not a fact but an
abstract type or form, the judgement of science is always
hypothetical: 'if A, then B,' where it is not asserted that A
exists in the world of fact . . . . Whereas the object of
history is the fact in all its actuality, and therefore the
historical judgement is categorical . . . . The ideal of his-
tory, then, is to be a single categorical judgement, articulated
into an infinity of coherent categorical judgements, asserting
the reality and expounding the nature of an infinite individual
world of fact articulated into an infinity of individual facts.

11 The closest Collingwood comes in Speculum Mentis to


recognizing the difference is at SM, 79, where he speaks about
the "empty form of questioning," questions which ask nothing,
mere "marks of interrogation." But he is not here explicitly
distinguishing between mental dispositions and logical func-
tions, but rather two sorts of mental activities, one with and
one without a background of factual assertion.
179

puzzling and unresolved contradictions which mask rather than

illustrate Collingwood's thought in Speculum Mentis, and provide

obstacles to the success of his Q-A logic. (a) On the one hand

questioning is identified with explanation and intellection. The

characteristic mark of the former processes is their "immediacy"

(i.e. their spontaneous actuality, their positivity, or in

general their lack of dependence on something other than

themselves) (SM, 95, 188). Questions are thus immediate, and

answers mediate. (b) On the other hand questions are identified

with the logical function of assertion cast in the hypothetical

mode, while answers are identified with the corresponding

categorical function (SM, 183, 186). In this sense questions are

mediate (their truth depends on something further being

asserted), and answers are immediate (they actually assert

something positive--something true or false). It is not until

Collingwood wrote the chapter on language in the Principles of

Art that logical and psychological functions are distinguished

(PA, 225-69).

Collingwood does not seem to be alarmed at these con-

clusions in Speculum Mentis, since he presumes that such argu-

ments demonstrate that questions and answers are not independent

abstractions, but are both mental activities, and therefore have

the characteristic marks of all


180

mental activity--viz. mediacy and immediacy (cf. SM, 80).12 But

when Collingwood calls the distinction between question and

answer an "ideal distinction," and adds that "the process of

knowledge is . . . not so much an alternation of question and

answer as a perpetual restatement of the question, which is

identical with a perpetual revision of the answer," the

_____________________
l2 Cf. SM, 188-89, where parallel arguments concerning
mental and logical functions are put forward to illustrate the
irrationality of the abstract distinctions made by science: (a)
"Intuition and thought are not two separate activities which are
somehow united in the body of human experience. Experience is an
individual whole in which two sides can always be distinguished:
an immediate, intuitive or questioning side, which is
hypostatized in abstract psychology into the faculty of
sensation, and a mediating, reflective, logical side, which is
called thought. Thought is the one, sensation the many. What
characterizes the intuitive or sensuous side of experience is
just its manyness or perpetual difference from itself, flux,
novelty, or creation. What characterizes the logical or re-
flective side is its self-identity, permanence, unity. Now we
have already seen that science consists in the separation of
these two distinct elements, and the attribution of reality to
thought while denying it to sensation. But division as such is
the characteristic of sensation as opposed to thought: thought
unifies what sensation divides. Therefore any given thing which
is made the field of an unreconciled division is thereby placed
under the head of sensation, for the characteristic unity of
thought has been denied to it. If experience as a whole is now
divided into two separate parts, thought and sense, it becomes
by this very definition wholly sensuous, and each part of it is
a sensuous, not an intelligible, object." (SM, 188-89). (b)
"This argument is more familiar. though more superficial, when
stated in terms of logic. The universal has its very life and
being in its particulars, of whose multiplicity it is the unity.
If now it is disentangled from those particulars and set apart
by itself, it becomes not their universal but another particular
object, thus losing precisely its intelligibility (universality)
and becoming an object of mere intuition, a thing that we no
longer think but only imagine. It is this falling-back upon
intuition that constitutes the irrationality, the arbitrariness
of all science." (SM, 189).
181

ensuing “identity" which "contains all diversity within itself"

(SM, 80) appears dangerously similar to that absolute night in

which all cows are black. The result, in short, is as

unfortunate for his Q-A logic as it is for formal logic: if

truth and falsity are functions of the Q-A complex and there is

no adequate way to distinguish within that complex what counts

for a question and what counts for an answer, then it seems

there may be no adequate criteria for distinguishing between

truth and falsehood either. It is not until the early chapters

of the Essay on Metaphysics that he attempted to disentangle Q-A

complexes and truth criteria (EM, 21-48).

4. Conclusion: Three Logics.

From the evidence that we have just examined it does not

appear that there is any systematic "question-and-answer logic"

as such mentioned in any of Collingwood's writings through 1924,

and a glance at the articles from this date until 1932 does not

yield any significant indication that would change this

judgement. Thus we find Collingwood writing in "The Nature and

Aims of a Philosophy of History" (1925) that the way in which a

problem arises for an historian must convey some hint of the

direction in which evidence for its solution is to be sought,

and that in doing so he argues to and from this evidence, so

that there is in the last analysis no distinction between his

sources and his conclusions (EPH, 5253). While this gives the

observant reader of the Autobiography


182

some confirmation of the use of Collingwood's Q-A principle that

in arguing back from a propositional answer (the conclusion) to

its question the same piece of evidence states the answer and

allows the historian to identify the question, it does not

explicitly suggest that this was a conscious application of a

systematic Q-A logic. And again Collingwood writes in "The

Philosophy of History" (1930) that

a question must be asked with some reasonable expectation


of being able to answer it, and to answer it by ((genuine))
thinking; otherwise it leads nowhere, it is at best idle
"wondering" . . . . We express this by saying that a ques-
tion does or does not "arise." To say that a question
arises is to say that it has a logical connexion with our
previous thoughts, that we have a reason for asking it and
are not moved by mere capricious curiosity. (EPH, 137).

We see at work another of the principles of Q-A logic cited in

the Autobiography, but without any explicit mention of presup-

positions and their logical efficacy in causing such questions

to arise. In fact the omission of any explicit discussion of

presuppositions or presupposing in these early writings renders

suspicious the autobiographical suggestion that he had

formulated Q-A logic as such (including the theory of presup-

position) in the years between 1916 and 1918 when he returned to

Oxford. And once again we must add that this suggestion is

rendered even more suspicious by his failure to mention anything

about dialectical logic and his early absolute idealism.

But perhaps we are allowing ourselves to be misled by

Collingwood's use of that vague and sometimes all-inclusive


183

word, "logic," as well as by his tendency in the Autobiography

to offer Q-A logic as an actual replacement or substitute for

formal logic. In Chapter VIII we shall take a hard look at this

claim and try to settle the issue of whether and to what extent

Collingwood's Q-A logic is "logic" in this sense at all. For now

we can only make several tentative statements based on the

evidence provided in the writings we have been examining. We

note, first of all, that we have three labels to attend to, if

not three logics: formal logic (F-logic), dialectical logic

(D-logic), and Q-A logic. Collingwood's conception of logic

tends to view it in epistemological terms, but he does allow

that logic in general is concerned with the justification of

some form of knowledge. If it is to be a truly philosophical

logic, it must justify not only the conclusions reached by a

body of knowledge, but the way in which it reaches these

conclusions. The way in which conclusions are reached is by a

systematic question-and-answer process, the success or failure

of which is not measured by any external criteria, although in

empirical science, at least, the conclusions arrived at can be

shown to be free of contradiction by formal logic. But a body of

knowledge must not only be free from contradiction; it must also

be able to demonstrate that in its process of development the

methods that it employs for the discovery and verification of

these assertions do not conflict with the ideals which this

knowledge sets for itself. This is the role of dialectical

logic. It would therefore


184

appear that Q-A, F-, and D-logics are ordered in a developing

series such that Q-A and F-logics are opposed and complementary

phases by which knowledge comes to be (Q-A logic), and retains

itself in being by resisting criticism (F-logic), but are both

preliminary to the dialectical measurement of explicit

performance against implicit promise (D-logic). We hasten to add

that this suggestion of the relationship between the three

logics that appear in Collingwood's writings was never made

explicit by him, and is our own reconstruction of their apparent

relationship at this point in our investigation.

Before passing on to the next step of our survey of the

early works, we must make some final comments about D-logic. At

least one of Collingwood's interpreters, whose views this author

greatly respects, has stated that Religion and Philosophy is

Collingwood's only non-dialectical book, and that his moment of

kairos came between his first and second books, because Speculum

Mentis is a dialectical essay where its predecessor is not

(Mink, MHD, 20, 242). To this we can only comment that if

Collingwood discovered dialectic, it could not have come as much

of a surprise. For on his own principles philosophy does not

bring us to know things of which we are simply ignorant, but

brings us to know in a different way things which we already

knew in some way (EPM, 161) Dialectic could therefore only be

something of which he was already aware, so that when it became

explicit it was only a refinement of a reflection on an


185

experience with which he was already familiar. We therefore

cannot accept any interpretation of Collingwood which presumes

that there was any such "event" in the intellectual development

of his philosophy, and especially when no such event is

acknowledged in the Autobiography.

But the evidence of Collingwood's writings forces us to

admit that not only does the explicit use of dialectical

concepts, judgments, and inferences show an order of develop-

ment, but also the use of the term dialectic has a peek-a-boo

career in Collingwood's published writings. So far as this

development is concerned, Religion and Philosophy presents us

with the spectacle of an analytic of concepts and principles,

but does display a propensity for expressing first one side of

an issue and then the opposing viewpoint, and only does so in

order to resolve the issue by showing how the two opposing

viewpoints can be reconciled. Furthermore the discussion of

"concrete identity" (which evolves quite naturally into that of

the concrete universal of Speculum Mentis) is prominent in

Religion and Philosophy, and is opposed to the abstract univer-

sal of "false logic." In Speculum Mentis the concrete universal

emerges as an "identity-in-difference" whose characteristics are

those of a scale of forms, but one which lacks the unity of both

differences of kind and differences of degree that Collingwood

later specified for such a scale


186

in the Essay on_Philosophical Method (SM, 208; EPM, 54-57).

Therefore from Religion And Philosophy to Speculum Mentis to the

Essay on Philosophical Method there is a continuous development

of the idea of defining something not by subsumption under a

universal and abstract class, but by showing how its meaning in-

cludes others which are related by opposition and distinction,

embodying differences of both degree and kind, and where the

variable is identified with the generic essence.

But on the other hand the term dialectic appears and

disappears in Collingwood's writings, sometimes in a most

confusing manner. While the term is not mentioned in Religion

and Philosophy, it is over-used in Speculum Mentis, mentioned

with modesty in the Essay on Philosophical Method (e.g. EPM, 12,

210), disappears altogether in the Autobiography and the Essay

on Metaphysics but re-appears in more classical costume

______________________
13 The reader must be patient with the use of such jargon
at this stage of our investigation--the terms will be explained
in future chapters. But it is well to bear in mind that (1)
where Religion and Philosophy argues that where two terms are
"not different" they are therefore identical, and (2) Speculum
Mentis argues that two terms in a dialectical series are related
to one another in kind only, and not in degree, (3) it is only
after the Essay on Philosophical Method that terms in a scale of
forms are declared to differ both in degree and in kind from one
another. Therefore if Religion and Philosophy is a
non-dialectical book, so is Speculum Mentis--i.e. on the
standards of dialectic set in the Essay on Philosophical Method.

14 There is only one reference to dialectic in the Essay


on Metaphysics, and that is in connection with Hegel's use of
it, which is not treated in a flattering manner (EM, 318).
187

in The New Leviathan.15 Nor can one simply relate the sudden

prominent usage of the term in Speculum Mentis either with his

recognition of its systematic implications (since such a

description is present in Religion and Philosophy in the

analysis of "concrete identity") or with the properly

philosophical use of the implicit-explicit distinction (since

this is not a distinction reserved for philosophical dialectic:

at SM, 93 it is applied to psycho-analysis in the Freudian

sense--the interpretation of dreams is not the bringing into

consciousness of that which was unconscious, but the bringing

into explicitness that which was implicit).

A more promising direction for uncovering Collingwood's

mature understanding of the term is in the posthumous publica-

tion, The Idea of History. In a chapter on Hegel in Part I,

Collingwood takes up Croce's criticism of Hegel's philosophy of

history which appeared to Croce

____________________
15 At NL, 24.63-24.68 Collingwood writes of dialectical
thinking, defined as "the readiness to give up something which
at a certain time you settled on as true." As an example Col-
lingwood cites Plato's discovery that the way to find one's way
about in a Heraclitean world is to think dialectically--a
Heraclitean world being one in which change from X to not-X or
vice versa is constantly occurring. At NL, 27.82 Collingwood
writes of the dialectical spirit as the spirit of agreement and
compromise in the ensuing discussion--see NL, 24.61, 27.9). And
at NL, 24.57-24.61 Collingwood writes of dialectical discussion,
where one's aim is to show that both disagreeing parties in an
argument are correct. NL, 24.57 contrasts dialectical and
eristic discussion, and declares that all logic is concerned
with discussions. In all these usages Collingwood seems to have
in mind a sense of the term derived from classical Greece, i.e.
the sense which emphasizes the manner of conducting a debate
involving disagreeing parties.
188

to be a "gigantic blunder produced by confusing two quite

different things: namely opposition and distinction." Then he

continues:

Concepts, Croce says, are related by opposition: good and


bad, true and false, freedom and necessity, and so forth;
and the theory of their relation, he admits, has been well
expounded by Hegel in his theory of dialectic, which de-
scribes the way in which any concept stands in a necessary
relation to its own opposite, generating it at first and
then negating it, so that the way in which the concept lives
is by creating and overcoming oppositions. But the
individual things which are the instances of concepts are
never related to each other by way of opposition, only by
way of distinction: consequently the relations between them
are not dialectical, and in history, which is the history of
individual actions and persons and civilizations, there is
consequently no dialectic . . . . (IH, 118-19).

It is interesting to note, before turning to Collingwood's

comments on this Crocean criticism, that in The New Leviathan

Collingwood remarks that logic applies to propositions only

because it applies in the first instance to concepts (NL, 7.33,

7.39, 11.35). Following this line of thought one might conclude

that D-logic applies primarily to concepts, and F-logic to

propositions. But extrapolating this analogy is not very

promising, since Q-A logic is not obviously inferential, where

F-logic is, and so is D-logic. Nonetheless there is some point

in the observation that the center of gravity, so to speak, of

D-logic is concepts, which emphasizes the semantic unity of

terms, and has as its central concern the meaning of terms,

whereas F-logic takes as its minimal unit the proposition that

can be the bearer not only of meaning but of truth or falsity.


189

However in the passage that we are presently considering

Collingwood is pursuing a different line of thought:

Plausible though Croce's view is, it does not really get to


the heart of the problem. It implies that in talking of
history we should never use words like opposition or
antagonism, and synthesis or reconciliation: . . . we ought
only to say that they are different: we ought not to speak
of an opposition, but only a difference, between Whigs and
Tories, or Catholics and Protestants. Now it is true that
we do not need to use terms like opposition (let me call
them dialectical terms), when we are talking only of the
outward events of history; but when we are talking only of
the inward thoughts which underlie these events it seems to
me that we cannot avoid them. (IH, 119).

To pursue his argument from the Idea of History any further

would get us into the subject of the next chapter, where we

shall have a chance to observe how his concept of history de-

veloped in the early writings. For now we wish to call attention

to the usage of opposition as a "dialectical" term, and

synthesis as a term of reconciliation.

As we proceed with our investigation of Collingwood's

logical views it will be well to bear in mind that "dialectic"

may represent a number of different meanings in his writings, so

that we might recognize, for example, that as the methodical

program we have called D-logic it stands in a relation with

F-logic and Q-A logic so as to appear to form a scale of forms,

from another point of view any such scale can itself be defined

as "dialectical." And again, while the analysis of a concept

into opposing principles may be called a dialectical

relationship and the


190

synthesis of this opposition may be called a rapprochement (so

that analysis, dialectic, and reconciliation may be interpreted

as three phases of complete philosophical thought), from a more

inclusive sense of the term (e.g. the one so frequently used in

Speculum Mentis) all rapprochement is dialectical. It may well

be that Collingwood omitted explicit reference to dialectic and

dialectical logic in the Autobiography because the term is

capable of such a multitude of meanings that it was virtually

useless for painting the kinds of sharp contrasts that he wanted

to elicit for the purpose of highlighting what he regarded as

central to his philosophical development.

But while we may charge Collingwood's Autobiography with

an error of omission, and even with being somewhat misleading in

that it suggests to the reader that his early Q-A logic already

made explicit the role of presuppositions, it is at least

accurate to the extent that the early writings do show evidence

of a stress on the role of questioning in the process of

knowledge. We can also say that nothing we have found would give

any indication that had he had such a complete Q-A logic he

would have done anything but embrace it wholeheartedly at this

point in his development, since its spirit is present from

Speculum Mentis onwards, and many of its principles are

explicitly stated in the early writings.


CHAPTER V

HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY

1. Introduction.

There can be little doubt that Collingwood felt that his

greatest contribution to philosophy would be his reconciliation

of philosophy and history. The Autobiography describes in some

detail how the two activities between which he divided the

majority of his time, his actual work in Roman-British history

and his philosophical lecturing and writing, gradually

converged, and how this synthesis not only was in large measure

responsible for breaking with the epistemology of his realist

tutors at Oxford, but also was the foundation for the

development of his rapprochement philosophy. If we are to

understand how and why he recognized this relationship to be

axial not only for his development but for interpreting his

entire philosophical outlook, we must take a careful look at how

this philosophy of history took shape in his early writings. And

since the Autobiography specifies that this development can be

found in his essays of the twenties (A, 107, 116-17), it is this

group of articles that we must spend most of our time on in this

chapter.

191
192

But what is it that needs reconciling? If "the phil-

osophy of" something merely means, as Religion and Philosophy

asserts, the careful reflection upon that subject (RP, 15; FR,

53), what is problematic about a philosophy of history? In the

Autobiography the opposition is approached from the direction of

the realism-idealism controversy: realists assumed the existence

of permanent philosophical problems which could be analyzed

independently of their historical setting, so that the

historical question of what someone thought about one of these

"eternal problems" was distinct from the philosophical question

of whether or not he was right (A, 59-68). In addition to this

mistake, the realists assumed that all knowledge was a simple

apprehending or intuiting of some unaffected reality, which

failed to recognize the essential role of interpretation of

evidence in the case of historical knowledge (A, 25-26, 39-40).

But from the other side, in the practice of his historical

studies Collingwood found that those historians he most

respected knew and cared little about philosophy (A, 83), so

that the need for a reconciliation from this direction was

simply the absence of any serious philosophical reflection on

the subject-matter of history. Not only did realist philosophers

neglect history as a form of knowledge not assimilable to their

sense-bound epistemology, but historians neglected philosophy

and therefore failed to pay sufficient attention to the

foundations of their own science (A, 85-90).


193

When we turn to the early writings we find out that it

was not merely neglect that is involved in the distantiating of

philosophy and history, but a basic difference in orientation of

each that must be overcome. As we shall see in the next two

sections, Collingwood's earliest attempts at the philosophy of

history tend to assume that philosophy is the realm of the

universal and history the realm of the particular, and the

resolution of the conflict that arises when it is assumed that

truth resides either with the universal or the particular is by

rooting both in a "concrete identity" or "concrete

universal"--an individual which is both universal and particular

at once. While the idea of an individual historical event as

something which is both universal in meaning and concrete in

objective reference is an idea which as a long and continuous

development in Collingwood's philosophy of history, the focus of

it shifted gradually away from the object of history and towards

the thinking role of the historian, and it is this development

that Collingwood is anxious to indicate in his Autobiography.

It is also quite a natural course of thought from the

point of absolute idealism, as we saw in Chapter III; for if the

common ground of all idealism is the role of the mind as both

active and passive (FR, 275, 277), then to view the historian as

a merely passive receptacle for the transmission of fact as

"something independent of my own or your knowledge


194

of it" is on a collision course with the philosophical view of

knowledge as active, and ultimately with the philosophical de-

mand for self-knowledge. Just as Gentile distinguished between

the realistic concept of change in material objects and the

idealistic concept of the history of mind, and argued that

reality is history (FR, 274), so Collingwood would distinguish

between physical events and re-enacted historical acts, and

argue that mind is what it does, and what it does is to make

history. The path to self-knowledge then is through history, for

it is history which narrates what it is that man has done.

But the reconciliation of philosophy and history devel-

ops as Collingwood's concept of rapprochement became more com-

plete.

2. The Identity of History and Philosophy.

In the earliest form that Collingwood's reconciliation

between history and philosophy takes, the two are simply equat-

ed: philosophy and history are the same thing. In Religion and

Philosophy the identity between philosophy (like that between

religion and philosophy, and between religion and morality) is

established in two ways: first by criticizing the views which

hold them to be separate, and then by showing that they are

mutually dependent on one another. In the case of history its

abstract separation from philosophy has been held by those who

maintain either that historical facts are independent of the

philosophical constructions
195

or interpretations that are placed on them (historical

positivism), or by arguing that the past as such is unknowable

because it depends on inferences based on fallible data

(historical scepticism). Neither of these anti-historical

arguments can withstand criticism. Historical positivism fails

because the distinction between historical interpretation and

historical fact cannot be maintained: historical interpretation

is just historical fact further specified. If one "construction"

that is put on fact differs from another, it is not merely two

"ideas" superimposed on one fact: one was an historical fact and

the other a historical error (RP, 46; FR, 80). Similarly,

anti-historical scepticism fails because it is not just

historical data used in inference that is fallible; the same can

be said of all data. "If inference as such is to be distrusted,

the evidence that leads us to distrust it is discredited with

the rest" as another misreporting of a well-attested fact. (RP,

44; FR, 79).

But not only do arguments for positivism and scepticism

fail to dislodge historical thought, but we cannot do without

either philosophical or historical thought, since they co-imply

one another:

In the first place, it appears that history cannot exist


without philosophy. There is no such thing as an entirely
non-philosophical history. History cannot proceed without
philosophical presuppositions of a highly complex character.
It deals with evidence, and therefore makes epistemological
assumptions as the value of evidence; it
196

describes the actions of historical characters in terms


whose meaning is fixed by ethical thought; it has con-
tinually to determine what events are possible and what are
not possible, and this can only be done in virtue of some
general metaphysical conclusions. (RP, 46-47; FR, 81).

We shall see in Chapter VII that at least one of these "meta-

physical conclusions" (actually a presupposition) mentioned here

is taken by Collingwood from Bradley's The Presuppositions of

Critical History, which Collingwood would later acutely

criticize (IH, 238-39). It is interesting to note that this is

the first reference to "presuppositions" which we have

encountered in Collingwood's writings, and it occurs in the

context of an argument that identifies philosophy and history.

The argument continues by showing the philosophy needs or

presupposes history:

It is equally certain that philosophy is impossible without


history; for any theory must be a theory of facts, and if
there were no facts there would be no occasion for theory .
. . . History must be regarded not as a mechanical process,
nor yet as a gradual accumulation of truths, but simply as
objectivity; as the real fact of which we are conscious.
History is that which actually exists; fact, as something
independent of my own or your knowledge of it. In this
sense there would be no philosophy without it; for no form
of consciousness can exist without an object. (RP, 47-49;
FR, 81-83).

Collingwood draws the conclusion that the relation of history to

philosophy is that neither can exist without the other, or as he

says, "each presupposes the other" (RP, 49; FR, 83).


197

Each is knowledge; and if they are different, they must be


the knowledge of different objects. How can we distinguish
these objects? History, it is sometimes said, is knowledge
of the particular, philosophy knowledge of the universal.
But the particular is no mere particular; it is a
particular of this or that universal; and the universal
never can exist at all except in the form of this or that
particular. . . . History, like philosophy, is the
knowledge of the one real world; it is historical, that is,
subject to the limitation of time . . . . It is
philosophical, that is, all embracing, universal, for the
same reason; because historical fact is the only thing that
exists and includes the whole universe. History a parte
objecti--the reality which historical research seeks to
know--is nothing else than the totality of existence; and
this is also the object of philosophy. History a parte
subjecti--the activity of the historian--is investigation
of all that has happened and is happening; and this is
philosophy too . . . . (T)he philosophical presuppositions
of history are not something different from the history
itself; they are philosophical truths which the historian
finds historically exemplified. History and philosophy are
therefore the same things. (RP, 49-51; FR, 83-85).

As can be seen from this argument, Collingwood had not at this

point penetrated very deeply into the nature of historical

thought. As he refined the concept he would narrow the object of

history from "the knowledge of the one real world" or "the

totality of existence" to res gestae--deeds of men, done in the

past. And even in Speculum Mentis he showed dissatisfaction with

such wholesale identities as he proposed in Religion and

Philosophy. Since it is not a settled part of his mature

outlook, we shall not engage in criticism of the argument here

(although we shall do so in examining the concept of

rapprochement identity in Chapter VI). But while one may quarrel

with the argument here, the spirit of reconciliation is

certainly present here, its only flaw being that the


198

resulting rapprochement between history and philosophy is less a

marriage than a fusion. While he continued to use the strategy

of "co-implication and therefore identity" in arguing for the

reconciliation of any two forms of consciousness, he became more

careful (a) to specify the differences between them as well, (b)

to distinguish what any form of consciousness is implicitly from

what it is explicitly,] and (c) to locate them not as

co-ordinate species of the genus, "knowledge," but rather as

successors on a scale of forms.

3. The Concrete Universal -_Absolute Object.

This is evident in Speculum Mentis, where philosophy and

history are described as having aims insofar as they both

essentially assert concrete reality and deny simple abstraction.

Therefore "the identification of philosophy with history is far

less violent and misleading than its identification with

science, religion, or art." But it is immediately added that

"all such identifications are barren abstractions. since to

"assert the identity without the difference or the difference

without the identity is to turn one's back on reality and amuse

oneself with paradoxes" (SM, 246). The differentiating feature

of philosophy as opposed to history, as presented in Speculum

Mentis,

_______________________
1 Cf. SM, 108, n. 1, where Collingwood acknowledges that
in Religion and Philosophy he had overlooked the distinction
between implicit and explicit--roughly, the distinction between
its "promise" or what it indirectly implies (implicit) and its
"performance" or what a form of consciousness directly asserts
(explicit).
199

is that in philosophy subject and object are identified, whereas

for historical thinking concrete fact is always assumed to be

something independent of the knowing activity of the historian

(SM, 241-43, 249). That is why Collingwood calls modern realism,

in which the object is presumed to be unaffected by the knowing

of it, the historical form of dogmatism.

Now these appear to be paradoxical assertions if taken

in conjunction with what Collingwood says about the reconcili-

ation of philosophy and history in the Autobiography. (a) If it

is philosophy, and not history, that is the form of con-

sciousness in which subject and object are identified, then how

can history be the "self-knowledge of mind" that Collingwood

intended it to be? And (b) if the form of dogmatism peculiar to

the historian is realism, then how can realism be "a philosophy

which erred through neglecting history"? We already know part of

the answer to the second question from Chapter III: what makes

history dogmatic is its unquestioning acceptance of the concept

of fact as something independent of anyone's knowledge of it,

which is the fundamental concept underlying realism. Since there

are as many forms of realism as there are of dogmatism,

historical realism follows scientific, religious, and artistic

realism. What makes historical realism an error is its

assumption that this is the whole story, and what is neglected

is the higher concept of


200

history in which fact and the knowledge of fact are reconciled

in self-consciousness--i.e. the philosophical concept of

history. But this leads us back to the first question, and

ultimately to the development of the concept of history in

Collingwood's early writings. The first stage in this

development we have just reviewed in Religion and Philosophy.

The second is in Speculum Mentis, which we will consider in this

section. The third is in the essays on history that appear in

the decade of the twenties, which we will examine in the

immediately following section.

The recognition that the form of experience known as

history is an improvement on abstract science is an achievement

of the Renaissance, and is solidified in the experimental method

of Renaissance scientists. "Experiment means the recognition of

fact, and experimental science means the assertion of fact, even

if only mutilated fact, as the true presupposition of scientific

thought" (SM, 201-202).2 The first to recognize this explicitly,

says Collingwood, was Descartes:

_____________________
2 The reader would be correct to assume that by the
"assertion of fact" at this point Collingwood means something
more than the utterance of a statement that something or other
is a fact or is the case. In Speculum Mentis to assert a fact
means to assert it as true, which is more than merely observing
it. To be asserted as scientifically true it must be capable of
withstanding Baconian cross-examination, which means subjecting
a fact to the sort of treatment an hypothesis gets in the
laboratory. Cf. SM, 53.
201

All science, said Descartes, rests upon the one indubitable


certainty that I think and that therefore I exist. Now the
thought and existence of which Descartes spoke were not
abstractions--anything thinking anything, or anything
somehow getting itself thought about . . . . Descartes meant
what he said; and what he said was that the concrete
historical fact, the fact of my actual present awareness,
was the root of science. He was only going one step beyond
Bacon, for whom the root of science was natural fact:
Descartes, more profoundly, saw that before natural fact can
be of any use to the scientist he must observe it, and that
the fact of his observing it is the fact that really
matters. Science presupposes history and can never go behind
history: that is the discovery of which Descartes' formula
is the deepest and most fruitful expression. (SM, 202).

If it is surprising to find Descartes' cogito translated as "the

fact of my actual present awareness," and given credit for

expressing the discovery that "science presupposes history,"3 it

is nonetheless revealing of Collingwood's early view of the

matter: the recognition of the historical element of science is

the first stage of both a revolution in science (the development

of the experimental method) and the beginning of a revised

awareness of history (SM, 202-203). It also brings into focus an

early association of history as a form of knowledge and

perception as a level of mental activity. The early annalists or

historical compilers were not aware of their reliance on

perception, but as the concept

_____________________
3 As we shall see, this is not the last of Collingwood's
creative interpretations of Descartes and the history of
philosophy: cf. EPM, 10-25, 124-26, 155-60; EM, 185-90. In The
Idea of History Descartes is treated as an historical sceptic,
and Vico's anti-Cartesianism is hailed as the real beginning of
scientific historiography (IH, 59-70).
202

of history developed the role of perception, as opposed to sen-

sation, became more explicit.

Sensation is the false or abstract account of perception. In


perception we are immediately aware of our object, which is
a concrete and therefore historical fact: perception and
history are thus identical. But the immediacy of perception
does not exclude mediation, it is not abstract immediacy
(sensation) but implicitly contains an element of mediation
(thought) . . . . Perception is explicitly immediate, but it
always contains within itself mediation (thought,
"interpretation of sense-data," "inference from the
immediately given," or whatever one likes to call it) and is
therefore never abstract immediacy . . . . History is thus,
as a specific form of experience, identical with perception.
(SM, 204-205).

Just as perception requires an element of memory insofar

as an object of perception is grasped not all at once or

immediately but serially, or as a "synthesis" or reconstruction,

so also the annalist or writer or memoirs is someone whose

reminiscences rely on memory--one's own or that of a

"source"--for its narrative sequence. But such a reliance on

memory must, to retain even the rudiments of reliability,

distinguish between memory and pure imaginative fantasy, and

this requires the exercise of a selective criterion (SM,

213-14). The earliest forms of historiography were dominated by

various mixtures of the true criterion of history with ideals

drawn from other forms of experience, so that in historians like

Herodotus and Thucydides factual coherence was mixed with

aesthetic or dramatic effect (SM, 214-16). It is only in the

eighteenth century that the concept of fact becomes explicit and

such errors were overcome to reach "historians' history" (SM,

216).
203

But it is at this point that fact is elevated to the

level of the absolute:

There is thus no feature of experience, no attitude of mind


towards its object, which is alien to history. Art rests on
the ignoring of reality: religion, on the ignoring of
thought: science, on the ignoring of fact; but with the
recognition of fact everything is recognized that is in any
sense real. The fact, as historically determined, is the
absolute object. The mark of the absolute object is
individuality, for individuality is concreteness. The object
as individual is the whole of what exists, and this is
concretely articulated into parts each of which is again
individual, and so to infinity . . . . The object, as a
system of fact so organized, is objective throughout, for
every part is a true microcosm, and is truly infinite. (SM,
218-19).

It is to this extent that history achieves what art, religion,

and science could not. For where esthetic consciousness ex-

presses itself in a monadic work of art, but while each such

work is its own cosmos, it is only so by ignoring not only other

works of art but the everyday world in which the artist lives

and works (SM, 84, 219). Religious consciousness locates its

individuality in God, "the monad of monads, a cosmos whose

structure is that of the absolute object"--but whose individu-

ality stands over against that of the world "whose very nature

is to be outside him," and therefore leaves the absolute in-

dividuality of God unattained (SM, 219). Scientific conscious-

ness replaces the concept of God with the concept of law, but

with the consequence that "(w)hat is individual and organized as

a system of individuals is not the world but only the concept"

which keeps law separated from true individuals to the


204

extent that any such individual is only a particular instance of

the law. The failure of each of these forms of experience is

redeemed by the success of history, which reaches the idea of an

object "beyond which there is nothing and within which every

part truly represents the whole."

This absolute whole is the concrete universal; for concrete


universality is individuality, the individual being simply
the unity of the universal and the particular. The absolute
individual is universal in that it is what it is throughout,
and every part of it is as individual as itself. On the
other hand it is no mere abstraction, the abstract quality
of individualness, but an individual which includes all
others . . . . The principle of its structure is not
classification, the abstract concept, but the concrete
concept, which is relevance, or implication. . . . (T)he
concrete universal is the daily bread of every historian,
and the logic of history is the logic of the concrete
universal. (SM, 221).

It is doubtful whether every historian would recognize

that his "daily bread" consisted of "the concrete universal" in

the sense of being the "system of systems, the world of

worlds"--including the later Collingwood himself, as we shall

see in Chapter IX: while the historian brings to his study an a

priori concept of the past, as well as presuppositions about the

coherence of the past, he feels himself under no obligation to

consider the whole of it as an absolute object consisting of an

infinity of facts (IH, 240-45, 303). In fact it is under the

burden of such a goal that history collapses by the "inner

dialectic" of its own version of the monism-pluralism dilemma.

If history exists, its object is


205

an unknowable infinite whole; and if its parts are atoms, then

history disappears and science takes its place, with its own

unresolved problems of universality and particularity (SM, 234).

In either case, the absolute object remains unachieved.

Thus history is the crown and the reductio ad absurdam of


all knowledge considered as knowledge of an objective
reality independent of the knowing mind. Here for the first
time we place before ourselves an object which satisfies
the mind; an object individual, concrete, infinite, no
arbitrary abstraction or unreal fiction, but reality itself
in its completeness . . . . The progressive alienation of
the mind from its object is in history complete. The world
is triumphantly unified as object, only to find itself
separated from the mind by a gulf which no thought can
traverse. (SM, 238).

We shall resume this discussion in the next chapter,

where we shall be concerned with the rapprochement identity of

absolute knowledge as it is presented in Speculum Mentis, but at

this point we must make several observations about the concept

of history herein presented. The reader has no doubt wondered

why it is necessary for history to postulate itself as an

absolute object at all, for if it were not for this the final

"reductio ad absurdam" would not occur at all. It appears that

the chapter on history is only a stage along the way to

establishing the demands of absolute knowledge--i.e. the demand

for an object that will fully satisfy the mind. What mind? The

mind of an absolute idealist, one concludes-for there is only

token effort to take into account the actual praxis of

historians in Speculum Mentis, other than the occasional remarks

about Herodotus and Thucydides, Mommsen and Gibbon. What we are

confronted
206

with instead is what amounts to a very abstract view of the

subject matter, one which tends to assimilate historical

thinking to perception and memory, and the historical object to

the world of fact--all of it. Little consciousness is exhibited

of the uniqueness of human acts in the range of facts, of the

need for cross-examination of facts by the historian's critical

intelligence, or the legitimate role of the historian's

presuppositions in this process.

We are therefore a long way from the view of history

presented in the Autobiography--but this itself is consistent

with the autobiographical interpretation, since Collingwood

states that in these years the rapprochement between history and

philosophy was incomplete, and was subject to a long and

painstaking development. The evidence for this development is

contained in the essays written between 1920 and 1930, and to

these we must now turn.

4. The Ideality of History as a Scale of Forms.

There is no clearer index to Collingwood's views on the

philosophy of history than that which can be obtained by careful

attention to these essays from the decade of the twenties. In

them one finds a gradual shift away from a definition of history

solely in terms of the realism-idealism controversy and toward a

clear recognition of the multi-layered


207

senses of the term. Between these two ends of the scale we shall

find not only most of the "principles of history" mentioned in

the Autobiography making their appearance, but we shall also see

parallel discussions of both the static logic of historical

assertions (for example concerning "categorical judgements" and

"the concrete universal") and the dynamics of history in terms

of processes and dialectical development.

A. In "Croce's Philosophy of History" (1921) and "Can

the New Idealism Dispense with Mysticism?" (1923) Collingwood

writes, as we have already seen, as a sympathetic critic of

Italian and German idealism, and in the process of his discus-

sion of this philosophy he formulates (and explicitly approves)

the notions of a "living past," history as dealing with thought,

and the basic process of "re-thinking" past thoughts (EPH, 6-10;

FR, 274-75).

History goes on in the mind of the historian: he thinks it,


he enacts it within himself: he identifies himself with the
history he is studying and actually lives it as he thinks
it, whence Croce's paradox that "all history is contemporary
history." . . . History is thought, annals the corpse of
thought. But has thought a corpse? and if so, what is it
like? . . . Croce's general "philosophy of the spirit"
supplies him with a ready-made answer. Nothing exists but
the spirit; but the spirit has two sides or parts, thought
and will . . . . Thought is the synthesis of subject and
object, and its characteristic is truth; will is the
creation of an object by the subject, and its characteristic
is utility . . . . Annals are not thought but willed; they
are constructed--"drawn up"--by the historian for his own
ends. (EPH, 6-7).
208

In this 1921 essay Collingwood goes on to criticize Croce for

mixing idealism with naturalism (which, we recall, is a synonym

for realism), and he calls on Croce to purge his philosophy of

its naturalistic elements in order to "reach the point of

absolute idealism" which the essay appears to assume to be a

step forward (EPH, 22). While Collingwood is critical of Croce

for reducing philosophy to the methodological moment of history,

and for absorbing philosophy into history (EPH, 20-21), the idea

of a living history of thought remains untouched. It comes

fairly close to the "first principle" of history as Collingwood

formulated it in the Autobiography (A, 110).

In the 1923 essay Collingwood presents in even stronger

terms the contrast between the idealistic and the naturalistic

view of history. We already quoted the passage in which

Collingwood contrasts Croce and Gentile on the issue of the

"metaphysic of being" which presents a philosophy of the real-

istic concept of change, and a "metaphysic of knowledge" which

presents a philosophy of idealistic concept of history (FR,

274). Although Collingwood does not explicitly state the extent

to which he would subscribe to either Croce's position or

Gentile's, these passages do show an awareness of a distinction

between process in general and historical processes. When taken

in conjunction with his charges against Croce, it is not

unreasonable to infer that Collingwood leaned toward a view on

the ideality of history not significantly


209

different (at this point) from that of Gentile. By 1923,

Collingwood appeared to have accepted the basic ideality of

history, i.e. that thought is essential to it. Later Collingwood

will drop the idealism-realism emphasis, while retaining the

distinction between natural change and historical processes.

B. In "Are History and Science Different Kinds of

Knowledge?" (1922) and "The Nature and Aims of a Philosophy of

History" (1924), Collingwood examines the epistemological claims

of history vis-a-vis other forms of knowledge. These two essays

represent a position intermediate between that of Religion and

Philosophy (in which various forms of knowledge are identified

insofar as they are directed toward the same intentional object)

and that of Speculum Mentis (in which forms of knowledge are

distinguished on the basis of the manner in which they grasp

their intentional objects--as successive approximations to the

truth).

In the 1922 essay Collingwood denies that there are any

epistemological grounds for a distinction between history and

science: "when both are regarded as actual inquiries the

difference of method and logic wholly disappears" (EPH, 33). It

is not the case that the scientist deals with the universal and

the historian with the particular exclusively, nor that it is

the function of the scientist to generalize and of the historian

to particularize; both deal with the world of individual fact,

and both activities involve the interpreta-


210

tion of individual facts in terms of general concepts (EPH,


26-27).

Interpretation is not the employment of a previously con-


structed tool (concept) upon a separately-given material
(fact): neither the concept nor the fact is "possessed"
(thought and observed respectively) except in the presence
of the other. To possess or think a concept is to interpret
a fact in terms of it: to possess or observe a fact is to
interpret it in terms of a concept. Science is this
interpretation . . . . The object which the scientist
cognizes is not "a universal," but always a particular fact,
a fact which but for the existence of his generalizing
activity would be blank meaningless sense data. His activity
as a scientist may be described alternatively as the
understanding of sense-data by concepts, or the realizing of
concepts in sensation, "intuiting" his thoughts or "thinking
out" his intuitions . . . . (T)here is no such thing as
knowledge either of the particular or of the universal, but
only of the individual: and . . . the sense-datum (pure
particular) and concept (pure universal) are false
abstractions when taken separately ((and)) yet, as elements
in the one concrete object of knowledge, the individual
interpreted fact, are capable of being analytically
distinguished. (EPH, 28-29).

In the 1924 essay Collingwood seems to reverse his

earlier position: he declares that "history and science are not

identical a parte subjecti)" because "scientific thinking is an

abstract thinking, historical thinking a concrete thinking"

(EPH, 45). We recall from Religion and Philosophy that by "a

parte subjecti" Collingwood understands precisely the activity

of the knower qua historian, scientist, etc.--in contrast to "a

parte objecti)" which refers to the reality or object studied by

a given form of knowledge (RP, 51; FR, 84-85).

In short, Collingwood seems to be saying here that,

contrary to his earlier judgment, there is an epistemological

ground for
211

distinguishing science from history--the distinction being that

between abstract and concrete thinking respectively.

The apparent contradiction is reconciled somewhat when

one pays careful attention to the shift of levels between the

two essays--the first dealing with the praxis of the two kinds

of inquiry (" . . . regarded as actual inquiries . . . "), the

second with the ideals of the two forms of knowledge. The dis-

tinction is important for an understanding of Collingwood's

emerging philosophy of history, and the point of view which he

adopts in Speculum Mentis. Both science and history, he wishes

to tell us, deal with individual facts, and both make use of

generalizations and the application of generalizations (par-

ticularization) to concrete cases. But each proposes a different

ideal for itself.

Ideally, historical thought is the apprehension of a world


of fact. Actually, it is the presentation by thought to
itself of a world of half-ascertained fact: a world in which
truth and error are at any given moment inextricably
confused together. Thus the actual object of actual his-
torical thinking is an object which is not "given" but
perpetually in process of being given . . . . The philosophy
of history, therefore, is a study of historical thinking:
not only psychological analysis of its actual procedure, but
the analysis of the ideal which it sets before itself.
Historical thought is one among a number of attitudes taken
up by the mind towards the objective world; it is an
attitude which assumes that there exists a world of
facts--not general laws, but individual facts--independent
of the being known, and that it is possible, if not wholly
to discover these facts, at any rate to discover them in
part and approximately. The philosophy of history must be a
critical discussion of this attitude. (EPH, 44).
212

But this distinction (based on mental dispositions, be

it noted) still does not extract Collingwood from his dif-

ficulties, since (a) to distinguish between what a form of ex-

perience or thought is ideally from what it is in practice, or

actually, is, on Collingwood's own grounds, to commit the error

of realism (SM, 313; cf. RP, 8, 29-33; FR, 47, 66-68); and more

seriously, (b) the historian does not always deal with the same

set of "facts" as does the scientist--a point which Collingwood

had already acknowledged in his 1923 essay on the New Idealism,

wherein he recognized that the facts with which the historian is

concerned are consciously performed processes in contrast to the

events of nature: "that which has a history . . . is a mind, for

matter may change but it cannot be said to have a history" (FR,

274). To be subject matter for science an event must merely be

capable of being thought. With events that are already thoughts

the scientist has no direct concern, since the facts which he is

proposing to explain are not artifacts but rather natural events.

Collingwood makes no note of these objective distinc-

tions in his 1924 essay since he is limiting himself to a dis-

cussion of the differences in ideals between history and other

forms of knowledge. Consequently he stresses the manner in which

the historian, as opposed to the scientist, seeks to express his

judgments about the "facts" he is investigating. Although both

hypothetical and categorical forms are used in


213

science and history, the scientist seeks to express his judg-

ments primarily in the hypothetical mode, in which the antece-

dent is the ground of the consequent ("if equals be added to

equals, the sums are equal"), whereas the historian aims at

categorical judgments. "The ideal of history, then, is to be a

single categorical judgment, articulated into an infinity of

coherent categorical judgments, asserting the reality and ex-

pounding the nature of an infinite individual world of fact

articulated into an infinity of individual facts" (EPH, 46). The

historian assumes the objective independence of these facts from

the knowing mind, so that "these actual happenings are always

the object of his thought, and never his thought itself"--this

being the realistic bias of the historian (EPH, 46-47).

As in Speculum Mentis, which was published in the same

year as the essay under consideration, Collingwood is unclear

about what he understands by "categorical judgement," and his

example does not clarify his usage. Collingwood uses as an

example of a categorical judgment used by scientists the state-

ment: "all whales are mammals"--which he then criticizes as not

truly categorical since it "does not imply an enumeration of all

actual whales but rather tells us that whatever we can identify

as a whale, if and when we do so identify anything, we can

further identify as a mammal." The implication seems to be that

(a) categorical judgments do imply an actual enumeration of all

the entities
214

involved--that is, some sort of quantification; and (b) that

categorical judgments as used by scientists refer to their

objects only hypothetically, and hence fail to be truly

categorical. In the 1924 essays the doctrine of categorical

judgments is vague, and requires further clarification.

But Collingwood does further specify what sort of

"single categorical judgement" the historian's ideal would be,

and what the limitations of such an intentional object would be.

The infinite whole of fact which it is the historian's


business to determine is . . . a world whose centre is the
historian's "immediate" perception, and whose radius is
measured by the depth to which he can see into the signi-
ficance of that perception . . . . The world of every his-
torian is limited by the limits of his knowledge . . . .
Each historian sees history from his own centre, at an angle
of his own: . . . so the various "perspectives" of
historians are arranged in a "space of perspectives;" each
historian is a monad which mirrors the universe from a point
of view that is irrevocably not any other's point of
view . . . . But a monad has no windows, and the historian
as such cannot do the work of co-ordinating the infinity of
possible perspectives. He can only travel from one per-
spective to another . . . . But in reflecting, that is
philosophizing, about his own thought he recognizes that he
is a monad, and to realize that one is in the "egocentric
predicament" is to transcend it. When thought returns upon
itself and faces the question of its own relation to its
object, by criticizing the point of view from which it has
regarded that object it transcends this point of view. (EPH,
53-55)4

___________________
4 Although Collingwood twice uses the expression, "space
of perspectives" in this essay, it never again occurs in his
writings. The term strikes the reader familiar with Husserl and
Lonergan as similar to the notion of "horizon."
215

It is here that we have the rudiments of an answer to

the first of our two paradoxical questions at the beginning of

Section 3. Although the historian's ideal is to articulate a

single categorical judgment, in practice he is always partially

separated from the object of his thought, so that his thought

and its relation to its object is at best one of similarity and

not one of total identity. As an historian, then, "he is always

the spectator of a life in which he does not participate: he

sees the world of fact as it were across a gulf which, as an

historian, he cannot bridge" (EPH, 47). But as a philosopher the

historian can also reflect on the fact that he himself "is part

of the world of fact, and that his own historical thought is a

product of the historical process which he is studying" (EPH,

47). In other words the historian qua historian is limited by

his "realist" assumption about the independence of the facts he

is observing, but the historian qua philosopher is capable of

transcending (by sympathetic interpretation and by critical

reflection) this separation of subject and object. History is

therefore the "self-knowledge of mind" when it becomes

self-consciously or critically reflective about itself, or when

it becomes philosophy. (Cf. EPH, 85-86).

Furthermore the way in which history becomes critically

reflective is by attending to the way in which historical

problems arise within the historian's own experience (EPH, 51-

53). Before something can become an


216

historical issue "the problem must arise within historical

thought; it must, that is to say, arise somehow out of the

attempt to perceive more adequately the world that exists here

and now for our perception" (EPH, 53).

Hence although Collingwood does not use the terms "en-

capsulation" and "re-enactment" in this essay, the concepts and

their relationships are the same as those which he expresses in

the historical principle which we have called "HIST-3" (number 5

of Table 4) in our summary of the Autobiography. The experience

in question, says Collingwood,

is . . . subject to the distinction between truth and


falsehood: hence we have not only to read, but to criticize.
The recognition of this truth is what differentiates history
in the higher sense of the word from the mere absorption and
repetition of stories . . . . This critical work is
sufficiently difficult to require somewhat elaborate
training, which involves the incidental construction
of . . . historical methods. As the word method suggests,
these sciences consist of empirical generalizations or rules
of procedure, instructing the student how to proceed in
typical cases . . . . Their business is to solve the problem
"how can the historian check his sources"? to which the
general answer is, "the historian who knows his business can
always invent methods of checking any source." (EPH, 51-52).

The only element lacking in this account, as compared to that of

the Autobiography, is the fully developed notion of the "real

life" or "practical problems" which constitute the "superficial

or obvious present" of the historian: these elements are added

in his 1930 essay, "The Philosophy of History," which we will

consider presently.
217

But we must observe in passing that in the above passage

Collingwood is beginning to relate several concepts which are of

very high importance for his later philosophy: (1) he is

beginning to acknowledge explicitly that there are levels of

meaning to the concept of history; (2) he recognizes that in the

higher sense of the term, truth and falsehood are distinguished

by means of critical thinking; (3) that this critical thinking

gives rise to historical methods; and (4) that these methods

consist of rules of procedure on how to proceed in typical

cases. Furthermore (5) it is noteworthy that in this 1924 essay

(as well as in Speculum Mentis, published the same year) he

first recognizes that "the various forms of thought (art,

science, history, philosophy) are not species of a genus," but

rather form what he was later to call a "scale of overlapping

forms" such that "art and science are contained in history, not

excluded from it: yet contained in a form transmuted by their

subordination to the historical end," while history "is not

contained in this manner in art or science" (EPH, 48).

Similarly, the philosopher must in a sense be an historian


and the historian in a sense a philosopher; but the phil-
osopher is suppressed in the historian, and the historian is
preserved but subordinated in the philosopher; history is
included in philosophy while philosophy is excluded from
history. (EPH, 49)

Here we catch a partial glimpse of an answer to the

second of our two paradoxical questions at the beginning of the

previous section of
218

this chapter: the realist is a philosopher who attempts to

ignore the history of his own subject matter, which, on

Collingwood's view, is a self-stultifying process. Not only is

realism the root of all forms of formalistic and abstract

dogmatism (which would mean, in terms of the account given in

Speculum Mentis, that it erred as much through neglecting

history as it did through neglecting art, religion, and

science--that is, it neglected them as concrete but partial

modes of thought), but it is a philosophy which neglects the

historical appreciation of concrete fact, which is its own

basis. The full flowering and ultimate consequence of the

realistic attitude towards the objects of knowledge is history;

but to deny that subject and object can ever be reconciled to

one another (which is the same thing as to affirm that objects

of knowledge are unaffected by the knowing of them) is to

prevent the historical viewpoint from ever reaching its highest

point of development--viz. a self-consciously critical process,

the self-knowledge of mind.

C. But the complete answer to our two questions is

possible only by an explication of two further lines of thought:

(1) the idea of history as a developmental process, and (2) the

nature of historical evidence. The latter is developed in two

essays published in 1928 and 1930, which we shall consider

shortly; the former is worked out in three essays in which

Collingwood deals with the cyclic view of history and its

companion notion
219

(in the 19th century at least) the idea of historical progress.

In "Oswald Spengler and the Theory of Historical Cycles"

(1927) Collingwood criticizes Spengler for writing history as

though he were describing a natural phenomenon, which reduces it

to so many episodes in the natural lifecycle of an atomic

"culture," which is elevated to the status of a thing with

definite characteristics. Collingwood's objection to Spengler is

similar in strategy both to his previous criticism of Croce and

to his later criticism of Toynbee: an historian cannot treat his

subject matter as if it were a natural entity with physical

properties subject to natural laws, because it commits the

positivistic error of regarding as given what in fact is

constructed by the active process of interpretation on the part

of the historian.

These are not superficial flaws . . . . They are sacrifices


of truth to method; they are symptoms of a logical fallacy
which underlies the whole book and has actually been
erected into a principle. The fallacy lies in the attempt
to characterize a culture by means of a single idea or
tendency or feature, to deduce everything from this one
central idea without recognizing that a single idea,
asserted in this way, calls up its own opposite in order to
have something to assert itself against, and henceforth
proceeds, not by merely repeating itself, but by playing a
game of statement and counter-statement with this
opposite . . . . (W)here ((Spengler)) fails is in thinking
out what he means by "characteristic." He thinks that the
characteristic is a fundamental something whose logical
consequences flow smoothly and unopposedly into all its
manifestations; whereas it is really the dominant partner
in a pair of opposites, asserting itself only so far as it
can keep its opposite in check and therefore always colored
by the hidden presence and under ground activity of this
opposite. (EPH, 63, 65).
220

Now while Collingwood does not explicitly use the

expressions "event" and "process" in this passage, it is clear

that his critique of Spengler is based on the historical

principle we have called "LG" in our summary of the

Autobiography. Any single idea, tendency, or feature of a

culture in history "calls up its own opposite" with which it

plays a game of statement and counter-statement--becomes, in the

terminology of the Autobiography, a process the components of

which are not static characteristics that do not change, but

rather "turn into one another":

(W)hile recognizing that a given culture has a certain


self-consistent character, a fundamental idea which is
working itself out into a complete social life, we must
assert that this idea or character is not static but dy-
namic; it is not a single unchanged thing . . . but a pro-
cess of spiritual development, an idea which grows out of
other ideas, in an environment of other ideas, which asserts
itself against these other ideas through a process of
give-and-take in which it modifies them and is modified by
them in turn. (EPH, 73).

In "The Theory of Historical Cycles" (1927) and "A Philosophy of

Progress" (1929) Collingwood continues to develop the concept of

history as a living thought-process rather than a dead set of

events--first by showing that the cyclical view of history is a

function of the limitations of the historian's own knowledge,

and secondly by locating the theory of historical cycles within

the context of range of possible viewpoints that the historian

can take toward his subject matter.


221

In the 1927 essay Collingwood stresses the need for a

unifying principle in history in contrast to its pluralizing

tendencies, which culminate in taking its data as so many atomic

events. In addition to being held together subjectively by the

historian's own thinking, it is held together objectively by a

continuity of problems the successive resolutions to which form

the fabric of history. So far as the historian can see history

as a whole, he sees it "as a continuous development in which

every phase consists of the solution of human problems set by

the preceding phase" (EPH, 87).

But that is only an ideal for the historian; that is what he


knows history would look like if he could see it as a whole,
which he can never do. In point of fact, he can only see it
in bits; he can only be acquainted with certain
periods . . . . At any given moment, therefore, the
historian can only present an interim report on the progress
of historical studies, and there will be gaps in it. These
gaps will appear as breaches in continuity, periods in which
the historian loses track of the development . . . . In this
condition, we see history split up into disconnected
episodes, each episode forming a relatively intelligible
whole, separated from its neighbors by dark ages. That is
the point of view from which we see history in cycles. . . .
The cyclical view of history is thus a function of the
limitations of historical knowledge. (EPH, 87-89).

In "A Philosophy of Progress" (1929) Collingwood sets

out to answer the question he had posed in his 1927 essay on

historical cycles: do the moral categories of good and bad have

a place in the evaluation of the course of history (EPH, 77)?

His answer, in brief, is that "whether


222

you think the course of events is an upward or a downward course

depends not on it but on you" (EPH, 109)--that is, on the

presuppositions of the historian. Three views are possible: the

Greco-Roman view in which history is a process of increasing

decadence from a presumed golden age; the 18th and 19th century

European view of history as giving evidence of progressive

improvement of human conditions and man's ability to solve his

perennial problems; and the more recent theory of historical

cycles, in which there is an alternation between periods of

decadence and of progress (EPH, 104-105). Since the third is

nothing more than a combination of the first two, the real

question is one which gets at the basis on which one measures

progress or decadence, and Collingwood suggests that in the end

the question is not so much factual or theoretical as much as it

is practical. The historian who works to preserve and improve

what he finds of value in the world and who therefore continues

to find the world as it is a better place on the whole than it

was, will view history as on the whole a progressive development

leading to the present. One who resigns himself to inactivity

finds it on the whole a worse place than it was in a previous

age; he feels that a past age is not again achievable, and

therefore writes as a pessimistic historian who views history as

decadence. And finally, one who finds that some things at the

present time are degenerate and require improvement (e.g. a

present form of government) while others are already notably

better (e.g. architecture and


223

engineering) will find both elements of progress and decadence

in history, and opt for some version of a theory of historical

cycles. But in any case the question is decided by the

limitations in the present practical life of the historian:

The question whether, on the whole, history shows a progress


can be answered, as we now see, by asking another question.
Have you the courage of your convictions? If you have, if
you regard the things which you are doing as things worth
doing, then the course of history which has led to the doing
of them is justified by its results, and its movement is a
movement forward. (EPH, 120).

Here we not only have an illustration of Collingwood's

use of "HIST-4" to solve an historical problem, we also have the

second phase of the answer to the first of our two paradoxical

questions. The process of history is taken by the historian as

consisting of events that occur independently of his knowing

them, but upon critical examination the nature or meaning of

these events is determined by the historian's judgment. This

judgment is limited by the limitations of the historian's own

mind. But these limitations are not merely theoretical, they are

also practical: at the level at which the historian is both

agent and patient, or at the level in which subject and object

are identified, the historical processes are additionally

determined by the historian (e.g. whether or not they shall be

progressive, retrogressive, or cyclical).

D. If such a conclusion as this seems to destroy the

last shred of historical objectivity, the balance is restored in

two further essays,


224

"The Limits of Historical Knowledge" (1928) and "The Philosophy

of History" (1930), which complete the sketch of Collingwood's

development of the concept of history prior to 1932, and before

he had written the series of lectures which were later to be

published as The Idea of History.

The 1928 essay argues that although the historian is

limited by the quantity and quality of the evidence he has at

his disposal, this does not mean that the historical sceptic is

correct in his claim that history is "the doubtful story of

successive events." On the contrary, historical scepticism is

only the negative aspect of a full definition of history which,

when confronted by conflicting evidence, cannot stop short at

the critical confrontation of one statement by its contradic-

tory, but must proceed to the dialectical task of showing why

one statement must be revised on the basis of another--why, in

short, criticism is a phase in the complete process of histor-

ical thinking, which must present its arguments on the basis of

all relevant evidence (EPH, 96). What the historian is seeking

is not "what really happened," since this has about the same

status as the Kantian unknowable "thing in itself." The past

referred to by historical thinking is not, that is, what is

demanded by that permanent tendency in all thought which is

"sometimes called the plain man's realism--to think of the

object as a 'thing in itself,' a


225

thing out of all relation to the knowledge of it, a thing

existing in itself and by itself" (EPH, 99). Such thinking leads

to the notion of a specious past--a "limbo where events which

have finished happening still go on," where the past is

something still existing in a ν ο η τ ο s τ ο π ο s of its own; a


world where Galileo's weight is still falling, where the smoke

of Nero's Rome still fills the intelligible air, and where

interglacial man is still laboriously learning to chip flints"

(EPH, 101). On the contrary, what the historian seeks is a

present filled with those symbols of the past which Collingwood

calls "evidence."

An event that has finished happening is just nothing at


all. It has no existence of any kind whatever. The past is
simply non-existent . . . . What the historian wants is a
real present . . . . He wants to reconstruct in his mind
the process by which his world--the world in those of its
aspects which at this particular moment impress themselves
on him--has come to be what it is. This process is not now
going on . . . . He is trying to know the past . . . as it
appears from its traces in the present . . . . (A)ll
historical thought is the historical interpretation of the
present. By leading to the present, it has left its traces
upon the present; and by doing that, it has supplied the
historian with evidence concerning itself, a starting point
for his investigations. (EPH, 101-102).

The process of historical criticism, therefore, is a process of

confronting one piece of evidence with another, related piece,

from the point of view of establishing how the historian's own

present came to be what it is (EPH, 98-99).

Thus far Collingwood has only determined that the his-

torian's knowledge of the past is limited by evidence, and that

this evidence must be something that constitutes part of the


226

historian's own present. In "The Philosophy of History" (1930)

he not only refines the notion of evidence, but also adds a

second set of limitations to historical thought, connects

historical inquiry with Q-A logic, again attacks the realists'

conception of a specious past, and outlines several of the

remaining "principles of history" with which we are already

familiar from the Autobiography--all this within the very

compact space of the four concluding pages of the essay.

First, with respect to evidence and the limits of his-

torical knowledge:

History is knowledge of the past, and the past consists of


events that have finished happening. The past does not exist
and cannot be perceived; our knowledge of it is not derived
from observation and cannot be verified by experi-
ment . . . . We come to know the past, not immediately, but
by interpreting evidence. This evidence (or data) is
something that exists in the present and is perceived by the
historian . . . . But data are not enough. They must be
interpreted. This requires principles, and the body of
principles constitutes historical method or technique. Some
of these principles are scientific in character, that is,
they concern particular groups of evidence . . . . Some are
philosophical, that is, they apply universally to all
evidence whatever, and compose the logic of historical
method. It is to this that we must refer such problems as,
the nature and limits of negative evidence, the possibility
of analogical argument, and so forth. Data, on the one hand,
and principles of interpretation on the other, are the two
elements of all historical thought. (EPH, 13637).

This is one of those passages where the reader is confronted

with a direct contradiction. Did not Collingwood, after all,

state in the Autobiography that history is not concerned with

past events (which begin and end) but


227

with processes (which do not)? Was this not the "first

principle" of history ("LG")? Here the interpreter must tread

with extreme caution, but in the process he will make a

discovery of the first importance in understanding how to treat

the many direct contradictions one finds in Collingwood's

writings. Making use of his "dialectical principle," Collingwood

often begins an expository section of his writing by making a

statement that he thinks corresponds to the ordinary beliefs of

his reading audience, and then in successive sentences and

paragraphs, leads him beyond this point to the position he

wishes to establish.5 In this case Collingwood is starting from

the point of view of the "plain man's realism"--that history is

knowledge of an object, the past, which exists independently of

his knowing it-and leads him to a modified notion of history as

knowledge of a significant present. This is manifestly his

intention, and it is made clear by filling in the first ellipsis

in the above quote, and adding the concluding paragraph of the

essay:

___________________
5 Cf. CRC, 9 May 1935, Collingwood to Ryle, p. 15: "(I)n
the work of any competent philosopher I find that the part
played by systematic fallacies is partial only; repeatedly, when
real difficulties arise, his insight into the subject, sharpened
by the sense of the difficulty, leads him to reject the fallacy
even at the cost of inconsistency and to adopt a better
procedure than that which he had followed . . . . Now this being
so, a philosopher named as the victim of a fallacy might . . .
say to me: 'You pillory me unfairly; on page X, it is true, I do
fall into your fallacy; but on page Y I correct it; you ought to
take my work as a whole, and interpret X in the light of Y; if
you did so you would see that the error was only a temporary
slip at worst; and, at best, you might wonder whether it was not
merely the exploration of a provisional point of view.'"
228

A "realistic" theory, according to which knowledge is the


"apprehension of a really existing object," is ruled out as
absolutely inapplicable to history. . . . (T)he historian
does not select, because no past facts are "there" before
him, to select from, until he has put them there by sheer
historical thinking. . . . Finally, since the past in itself
is nothing, the knowledge of the past in itself is not, and
cannot be, the historian's goal. His goal, as the goal of a
thinking being, is knowledge of the present . . . . But, as
historian, he is concerned with one special aspect of the
present--how it came to be what it is. (EPH, 136-39).

We shall have occasion in the sequel to examine many

other instances where Collingwood seems to take back with one

hand what he had given with the other, but in the meantime we

should note that a successful gloss on these passages would be

something like the following: "Although from the point of view

of the plain man's realism history is taken to mean knowledge of

the past, where the past consists of events that have finished

happening, since the past does not exist (as the realistic

theory might lead one to suspect) one must revise the notion of

the past to mean that aspect of the present which gives

indication (evidence) of how it has come to be what it is--and

this is the past the historian is concerned with." Such a

reading does not violate Collingwood's "first principle of

history," and in fact makes sense of the complete passage

--especially its final paragraph. But be it noted, it still does

not get Collingwood out of the woods, because the reader is

still puzzled by what it would mean for historical objectivity

for the historian to "put" facts before himself "by sheer

historical thinking." For a clarification of what this means


229

we must next pay note to the role of Q-A logic in historical


thinking:

The beginning of historical research is therefore not the


collection or contemplation of crude facts as yet unin-
terpreted, but the asking of a question which sets one off
looking for facts which may help one to answer it . . . .
And the question must be asked with some reasonable ex-
pectation of being able to answer it, and to answer it by
genuinely historical thinking . . . . We express this by
saying that a question does or does not "arise." To say that
a question arises, is to say that it has a logical connexion
with our previous thoughts, that we have a reason for asking
it and pre not moved by mere capricious curiosity. (EPH,
137)6

Now although there is no mention in this passage of Q-A logic as

such, it is clear (e.g. from the discussion of a question's

"arising" by logical connection with the historian's own pre-

vious thoughts) that he has Q-A logic in mind, just as he had

described it in the Autobiography--short, that is, of an ex-

plicit discussion of the relation of questions and presupposi-

tions.7 Hence this passage confirms that as of 1930 Colling-

_________________
6 Cf. CRC, loc. cit., p. 17: "Thus it seems to me that
the individual 'proposition' assented to on any given occasion
is assented to only in a context, never by itself; and this
context is not a fortuitous context but a necessary one; I mean,
'It is not yet noon and the sun is shining' won't do as a
substitute for 'It is not yet noon and it is half-past eleven.'
The context is not (may I say?) a merely psychological context,
consisting of anything else that we may happen to be thinking at
the time; it is a logical context, consisting of other things
which if we didn't think we couldn't think what ex hypothesi we
are thinking."

7 This distinction would not be in the province of the


working historian anyway; and not even, according to the Essay
on Metaphysics, the task of the metaphysician. It is the task 6f
the logician. See EM, 54.
230

wood was making use of the principle of history which we have

labeled "ARCH-1," and two of the corollaries of "HIST-3" in our

summary of the Autobiography.8

Finally one finds an explicit statement of "ARCH-3" in the

1930 essay:

All history must be the history of something particular, and


the most we can ever do is to express the present state of
knowledge concerning this particular subject. As no history
can be universal, so no history can be final . . . . All
history is thus an interim report on the progress made in
the study of its subject matter down to the present; and
hence all history is at the same time the history of history
. . . . (EPH, 138).

Here again we have Collingwood apparently contradicting

himself, and then revising his previous statement. In the first

part of the paper he states that second-order reflection on

history, viz. the philosophy of history, must show how history

"is somehow a universal and necessary characteristic of things,

not merely a particular and contingent characteristic of a

certain group of things" (EPH, 122).

"The philosophy of something" is a legitimate phrase only


when the "something" in question is no mere fragment of the
world, but is an aspect of the world as a whole--a universal
and necessary characteristic of things. . . . If there is to
be a philosophy of history, history must be . . . a
universal and necessary human interest, the interest in a
universal and necessary aspect of the world. (EPH, 122-23).

______________________
8 It also, incidentally, states what Collingwood means by a
question "arising"--i.e., that the question has a "logical
connection with our previous thoughts, that we have a reason for
asking it . . . ." (SM, 137).
231

If history is concerned with a "universal and necessary aspect

of the world," then how is it that "all history must be the

history of something particular"? And how can all history be at

the same time the history of history without infinite regress?

The answer, insofar as one is possible on Collingwood's grounds,

is the same for both problems: "history" is an equivocal term,

with layers of meaning which it is the work of the philosopher

to distinguish--but to distinguish in a manner which cannot but

violate the expectations of someone committed to the logic of

the abstract universal. If one considers history in terms of its

limitations (both by its given evidence and by the historian's

own principles of interpretation) history always deals with

something particular; but if one regards history as that aspect

of the present which explains how that present came into being,

history deals with a universal and necessary aspect of the

world. This sort of distinction is only possible from the

philosophical point of view--the historian is not explicitly

aware of it. But Collingwood views these levels of meaning of

the concept of history not as several static definitions

separate from one another but as themselves part of a

developmental process in which the idea of history is

progressively realized.

In the intermediate part of the 1930 paper (clearly a

prototype of his later lectures on The Idea of History--cf. EPH,

xxxiii) Collingwood
232

shows how the step which elevates history to the rank of a

philosophical science was taken:

The essence of this development is the doctrine of the


individual judgement. Ordinary logic distinguishes the
individual judgement "This S is P." from the universal
judgement "All S is P." Now, says Croce, "This S is P" is
history, "All S is P" is science. But whenever we say "All S
is P" we have before our minds a "this S." . . . . "All S is
P" means "This S. in its character as S. is P." When the
element of individuality is taken away we have, not a
universal judgement "All S is P." but nothing at all. This
conception can be expressed by saying that all knowledge is
historical knowledge (individual judgement) and that science
is history with its individual reference neglected. (EPH,
135-36).

We shall have occasion in the sequel to return to this

theme in connection with some of Collingwood's later remarks

about historical and scientific judgments, about the concrete

universal, and about the structure of philosophical concepts.

But for now it is sufficient to notice that the formal opposi-

tion between universal and particular judgments is taken (by

Croce and, on approval, by Collingwood) to be overcome by the

individual judgment of history, which is not merely a particu-

larized universal judgment, but a judgment distinguishable from

a particular judgment as the base-line of its intelligibility

(when individuality is taken away we do not have a universal

judgment but "nothing at all").9 But such distinctions as these

are made by the philosophy of history which, as Collingwood was

so often to point out, is not something different or separate

from history itself, but is history with its presuppositions

made explicit (cf. EPH, 125).

___________________
9 This view is later criticized by Collingwood (IH, 303).
233

5. Conclusion.

In our survey of Collingwood's essays in the philosophy

of history between 1920 and 1930 we managed to find direct or

indirect evidence which substantiates his claims in the

Autobiography concerning the development of his ideas on the

relation of philosophy and history--with one notable oversight.

One principle that is totally missing in these essays is the one

we have called "HIST-4"--history as the science of human

affairs. It is the absence of this principle that mars his

discussion of the object of history, so that it seems that the

object of history is the whole of changing reality, and hence

"science is history with its individual reference neglected."

Now it so happens that not only is this principle the

central issue of his 1936 British Academy lecture, "Human Nature

and Human History" (IH, 205-31; cf. A, 116-17, n. 1), but the

principles of history which we have called "HIST-1, -2, -3, and

-4" appear almost verbatim in this essay. Even assuming that

Collingwood read the substance of his 1936 lecture back into his

earlier essays on the philosophy of history, and that therefore

the development of his ideas on the relationship of philosophy

and history was not as complete as he said it was as of 1930,

the real question that arises in understanding Collingwood's

early reconciliation between history and philosophy concerns the

manner in which
234

he finally distinguishes them within some sort of unity. For

what kind of unity would that be? History, science, art,

etc.--his "forms of experience" in Speculum Mentis--are not, he

insists, species of a common genus, "knowledge," as the realists

had asserted. That meant that each of the forms of experience

has an epistemology proper to it. At the same time Collingwood

feels obliged to show that all forms of experience are mani-

festations of a single process, mental activity, and are

therefore variations on a single theme.

We have already had occasion to notice that Collingwood

was not entirely successful in his several attempts to

distinguish history from other forms of knowledge solely on the

grounds of the manner in which they express their judgments. In

his 1922 essay on science and history he admitted that both of

these forms of experience make use of particular and universal

judgments and therefore cannot be separated on the basis of the

sorts of judgments they use. But in his 1930 paper he asserts

that the judgment peculiar to history is individual judgment

("This S is P") which he distinguishes both from the particular

judgment ("Some S is P") and from the universal judgment ("All S

is P"). But since judgments of science are merely the judgments

of history with their individuality suppressed, it follows (as

Croce had said) that "all knowledge is historical knowledge" and

that "science is history with its individual reference

neglected" (EPH, 136).


235

But then it would seem that science is a species of history, or

that both of these are (as Speculum Mentis seems to leave one

believing) unsuccessful forms of philosophy. In any event we

have the sort of genus-species situation within knowledge that

Collingwood had hoped to overcome. On the other hand the attempt

to distinguish different sorts of knowledge on the grounds of

their subject matter is equally unsuccessful. If history deals

with a "universal and necessary aspect of things"--i.e. their

"becoming"--then it is clear that it is indistinguishable from

the science of nature, since everything in nature is also

subject to a process of becoming (EPH, 12224). Starting from

either direction then, one arrives at the conclusion that the

forms of knowledge are indistinguishable from one another.

"Everything," Collingwood writes in 1930, "has a past;

everything has somehow come to be what it is; and therefore the

historical aspect of things is a universal and necessary aspect

of them" (EPH, 124). On this account there would not only be a

history of Greece and Rome, but of the San Andreas Fault and the

moon.

Perhaps Collingwood assumed that the reader would recall

what he had written in his 1923 essay on the New Idealism, where

he says that "that which has a history . . . . is a mind, for

matter may change, but it cannot be said to have a history" (FR,

274), and would supply this reservation as the distinguishing

feature of history. But he does not


236

tackle the issue explicitly in his published writings until his

British Academy lecture of 1936, where it is assaulted head on

and solved in the manner described in the Autobiography.

The thesis which I shall maintain ((writes Collingwood in


"Human Nature and Human History")) is that the science of
human nature was a false attempt--falsified by the analogy
of natural science--to understand the mind itself, and
that, whereas the right way of investigating nature is by
the methods called scientific, the right way of investi-
gating mind is by the methods of history . . . . Since the
time of Heraclitus and Plato, it has been a commonplace
that the entire world of nature is a world of "process" or
"becoming." But this is not what is meant by the histor-
icity of things; for change and history are not the
same . . . . (H)uman history shows change not only in the
individual cases in which . . . ideals are realized or par-
tially realized, but in the ideals themselves . . . . The
processes of nature can therefore be properly described as
sequences of mere events, but those of history cannot. They
are not processes of mere events but processes of actions,
which have an inner side, consisting of processes of
thoughts; and what the historian is looking for is these
processes of thought. All history is the history of
thought. (IH, 209-11, 215--emphasis mine).

Collingwood's solution to the problem then is to distinguish

between two classes of intentional objects—mere events and

"actions" of historical agents, the latter having deliberate

thought as part of its essential structure. Natural science

deals with the former, history with the latter.

But Collingwood is also saying something further in

this essay, and that is that the processes with which historical

inquiry deals are developments of a self-making mind (IH, 226).

What exactly "mind" is, and what part "thought" plays in the

life of men with minds, is something that Collingwood works out

in some detail in The Principles of Art and


237

The New Leviathan. But the notion of mind as a self-making

activity is explicitly present in Speculum Mentis, and goes as

far back as Religion and Philosophy.

In the latter Collingwood wrote, it will be recalled,

that "there is no such thing as human nature in the sense of a

definite body of characteristics common to every man," and that

therefore "the question to be asked about mind is not what it

is, but what it does; a question with which the logic of things

and qualities does not deal" (RP, 164-65; FR, 266). In Speculum

Mentis the doctrine of mind as a self-making activity is put

forward as the final realization of all knowledge:

Knowledge polarizes itself into abstract or erroneous and


concrete or true. Abstract knowledge is the same as error,
because, separating what is thought to be from what is, it
erects that which it thinks into a false object over against
itself, an external world . . . . But in concrete knowledge
the mind sees itself face to face, and knows even as it is
known. Here the object is the subject . . . in the sense
that the object finds its very life in being known by the
subject, the subject in knowing the object . . . . In an
immediate and direct way, the mind can never know itself: it
can only know itself through the mediation of an external
world, know that what it sees in the external world is its
own reflection. Hence the construction of external
worlds--works of art, religions, sciences, structures of
historical fact, codes of law, systems of philosophy, and so
forth ad infinitum-is the only way by which the mind can
possibly come to that self-knowledge which is its end. (SM,
313-15).

In Collingwood's view the process of creation of these "external

worlds"--of art, religion, science, history (as historiography),

and philosophy--is the very process of history, and the

historian in the very


238

best sense must be the one who can recreate all these processes

over again by "re-thinking" them in his own historical

imagination. In the process of doing so, and in confronting the

"evidence" of these worlds in a critical fashion, he not only

discovers the past to which he is heir but re-creates that past,

and in the process builds the structure of his own consciousness:

Man has been defined as an animal capable of profiting by


the experience of others. . . . The body of human thought or
mental activity is a corporate possession, and almost all
the operations which our minds perform are operations which
we learned to perform from others who have performed them
already. Since mind is what it does, and human nature, if it
is a name for anything real, is only a name for human
activities, this acquisition of ability to perform
determinate operations is the acquisition of a determinate
human nature. Thus the historical process is a process in
which man creates for himself this or that kind of human
nature by re-creating in his own thought the past to which
he is heir. (IH, 226).

That such a view, so eloquently expressed and so close to the

standpoint of European existentialism, would bring Collingwood

to loggerheads with behavioral psychologists requires no special

demonstration; we shall see in a future chapter how this aspect

of Collingwood's philosophy developed into the anti-positivistic

polemic in the Essay on Metaphysics. His antipathy to behavioral

psychology is neither something entirely new in his philosophy

nor is it inconsistent with its central tenets. We have already

seen that as early as Religion and Philosophy Collingwood


239

assaulted "psychology" as the pseudo-science of mind, since it

treats of mental activities as mere events (RP, 42; FR, 77). And

we have had occasion to notice that Collingwood's fundamental

view of human mentality makes deliberate activity (in a manner

yet to be explained) its central and irreducible aspect. But the

issue of immediate interest here is the support that one finds

throughout Collingwood's philosophy, and not merely in the

period following the appearance of the Autobiography, for the

reconciliation of history and philosophy through the concept of

mind as a self-making activity. Although "HIST-4" does not

appear explicitly prior to the 1934 British Academy Lecture, it

is a principle latent but operative in his early philosophical

writings, and takes no great feat of interpretive skill to

discern in his discussions concerning history.

It remains to pull all of these strands together into

some sort of summary of our survey of Collingwood's earlier

reconciliation of philosophy and history. What we have seen

emerging from Collingwood's essays on the philosophy of history

is a discussion which not only confirms most, if not all, of

what he had said about his discovery of the "principles of

history" as he described them in the Autobiography, but in ad-

dition a fuller discussion of several of these topics which

parallels and complements the autobiographical sketch. The main

ideas of this complimentary account can be summarized in tabular

form as follows:
240

TABLE 6

THE MEANINGS OF HISTORY

1. (EPH-1) "History" is an ambiguous term, the meanings of


which display a progressive and orderly development with
both a temporal and logical structure, the highest point of
which relates the diversity of these meanings in the unity
of a philosophical concept. (EPH, 39-40, 124-25).

2. (EPH-2) History understood as the ideal of the historian is


the knowledge of a unified and meaningful whole of acts of
historical agents, expressed in a single categorical
judgment. (EPH, 46).

a. The objective aspect of this ideal is the drama of


history as a single developmental process, which con
sists of the successive resolution of problems relat-
ing to human self-consciousness (in the form of art,
religion, science, etc.).

b. The subjective aspect of this ideal is the continuity


of this drama provided by the historian's own con-
sciousness, i.e. his expectation that the object of
history will be an organized and coherent whole. Min-
imally this is the view that history has a plot. (EPH,
37, 111, 137-38).

3. (EPH-3) History understood as the practice of the historian


consists of the two fundamental elements: historical data,
or evidence, and principles of interpretation. Each of these
limits the ideal anticipations of the historian. (EPH, 137).

a. Objectively, historical thinking is limited by the


evidence which provides the data for historical analy-
sis. Such data (i.e., traces of the past existing in the
present) requires critical analysis before serving as
evidence of (for or against) any historical thinking at
all. -TEPH, 136).

b. Subjectively, historical thinking is limited by the


historian's own "point of view"--the principles of
241

interpretation he brings to the data he is analyzing.


Such principles include the nature and limits of
negative evidence, the possibility of analogical ar-
gument, views of history as cyclic or linearly pro-
gressive, etc. (EPH, 89, 137).

4. (EPH-4) At the level at which theory and practice (and


subject and object) are identified, the historian is also an
historical agent, not only observing history but making it.
This is the philosophical concept of history, in which
subject and object are identified--where, in the case of
history, the historian is both agent and patient. (EPH, 46,
49, 120).

5. (EPH-5) The philosophical concept of history is concerned


with a fully articulated answer to the question, "How has
the world (of human affairs) as it now exists come to be
what it is"? The answer to this question is conceived as the
first stage of an activity to either keep it that way or to
initiate an alteration of it. (EPH, 89, 92, 102, 109, 120;
cf. EPA, 144).
242

One must pay careful attention therefore to which level

of significance the particular use of the term "history" refers

in any given passage in Collingwood's writings. To accuse

Collingwood of "radical historicism" in his later years (as

critics do who read the Essay on Metaphysics without seeing it

in the context of his other writings on history) may be either

utterly true or totally false, depending on what one understands

by "history" and "historicism." As a philosophical concept,

history is identified with philosophy, and therefore the

reduction of philosophy to history is the identification of

philosophy with itself--a harmless tautology. On the other hand

as an empirical concept (the collection of events which

Collingwood calls raw data, or the uninterpreted evidence, of

history), history is not only not identical with philosophy, but

can hardly be said to be identical with itself.

Nevertheless in our examination of Collingwood's later

philosophy of history we shall have to attend to the manner in

which he tries to retain a criteria of historical objectivity

while yet rejecting the realistic historian's emphasis on

extra-mental "facts." But meanwhile we must turn now to what

Collingwood understood by his "identities" in conjunction with

the issue of what he expected of a "rapprochement" philosophy,

and therefore what method he used to achieve this end.


CHAPTER VI

RAPPROCHEMENT, RELIGION, AND ABSOLUTE KNOWLEDGE

1. Introduction.

Just as in his discussions of Q-A logic and the

philosophy of history, Collingwood made his approach in the

Autobiography to the discussion of a need for a new branch of

philosophy, devoted to the work of reconciliation, from a

critique of realism.

It was during World War I and his daily reflections on

the Albert Memorial that he discovered the "vulgar error" of the

realists--their false belief that problems of philosophy were

eternal, and that different philosophies were different attempts

to answer the same questions (A, 60). The first instance he

cites of his own clear recognition of the truth about eternal

problems came in political theory, where it became obvious to

him that the political theories of Plato and Hobbes are not two

theories of the same thing--the "nature of the state"--because

there were genuine differences between the ideal states (and not

just the empirical ones) being discussed in each case, ideals

that are ignored in treating them as if each intended the same

thing (A, 61). There is a relation between them, but the

relation is not the sameness of an abstract

243
244

universal, but the sameness of an historical process; and the

difference between one thing which in the course of that process

has turned into something else (A, 62). Collingwood went on, he

says, to apply this "clue" to the problems of ethics and

metaphysics, and in the case of the latter it bore fruit in his

ultimate discovery that metaphysics is an historical science (A,

63-65). And finally, he found that his discovery could be

generalized to the whole field of philosophy: "By degrees I

found that there was no recognized branch of philosophy to which

it did not apply" (A, 67).

Later in the Autobiography (in Chapter XII, "Theory and

Practice") Collingwood picks up the discussion of rapprochement

again and spells out the nature of his reconciliation in ethics.

In addition to his reconciliation of history and philosophy (as

instanced in his reflections on the political notion of the

state) he was also working on a rapprochement between theory and

practice in order to counteract the "moral corruption propagated

by the 'realist' dogma that moral philosophy does no more than

study in a purely theoretical spirit a subject matter which it

leaves wholly unaffected by that investigation" (A, 147). In so

doing he subjected the familiar topics and problems of moral

philosophy first to an historical treatment (to show,

presumably, how the problem developed as an historical process

wherein the differences were truly integral to it and changed

the nature of the problem as it developed), and secondly to an

analytic treatment (which, by critical argumentation,


245

both differentiated the problem into its correlative parts, and

then showed them to be aspects of one and the same identical

entity). Naturally enough in a chapter on theory and practice,

the example Collingwood used was one of action--first

distinguished as moral, political, and economic, and then

unified insofar as every action is moral, political, and

economic--not separated into three classes, but seen as three

characteristics, distinguished and yet united in any actual act

(A, 148-49).

We have recalled these passages here to remind the

reader not only of the anti-realist context of Collingwood's

remarks about rapprochement, but also to recall the two phases

(historical and analytic) of his earlier reconciliational

philosophy. We have said enough in the previous section about

the historical phase of his rapprochement methodology to give

the reader a sense both of how he felt it should be carried out

and what its intrinsic and unresolved problems were. In this

section, therefore, we shall concentrate on Collingwood's

"analytic" phase. In doing so we must pay heed to one further

proviso:

These were the lines on which I treated the subject in my


lectures of 1919. I continued to lecture upon it yearly
during the whole remainder of my life at Pembroke College,
with constant revision. The scheme I have just described
obviously represents a stage in my thought at which the
rapprochement between history and philosophy was very in-
complete . . . . The rapprochement between theory and prac-
tice was equally incomplete. I no longer thought of them as
mutually
246

independent; I saw that the relation between them was one of


intimate and mutual dependence, thought depending upon what
the thinker learned by experience in action, action
depending upon how he thought of himself and the world . . .
. But this was only a theoretical rapprochement of theory
and practice, not a practical one. (A, 149 50).

If we are to approach this topic in Collingwood's early writ-

ings, therefore, in the spirit of the Autobiography, we must not

only take into account the sense of the term "analytical" as

used by Collingwood, but also the fact that he regarded this

"analytic" to be incomplete. How it was completed (and the sense

in which his early analytic was incomplete) Collingwood leaves

to the reader to work out for himself (A, 149).1

The evidence from Collingwood's writings is insufficient

to establish what the actual topic was to which he first applied

his rapprochement method; although he lectured on ethics and

political philosophy since 1919, his first publications

specifically on these subjects were not until six years later

(cf. "EPS," 1925), and by then both Religion and Philosophy and

Speculum Mentis had appeared. While it is true that he treated

the subjects in ethics and political science in these later

publications much as he says he did in the Autobiography, for

our

_____________________
1 The only further clue the reader has from the
Autobiography is Collingwood's unreserved praise for his Essay
on Philosophical Method, which he recommends as his "best book
in matter; in style, I may call it my only book" (A, 117-18).
The reader must conclude that as of 1933 rapprochement metho-
dology was fairly complete.
247

purposes the earliest instance, in his published writings, of

rapprochement is in the area of religious philosophy. Not only

is religion as a "unified life of all the faculties" the first

published topic on which Collingwood exercised his early

reconciliational technique, but it provides us with an index as

to how that technique was modified between 1916 and 1924, when

Collingwood once again dealt with the subject in Speculum Mentis.

2. Religion, Philosophy, and the Incomplete Rapprochement.

At the time of his writing of Religion and Philosophy

(published in 1916, but written some time earlier--see RP, v)

the analytic phase seems to be only recourse Collingwood re-

sorted to in his treatment of philosophical problems, the his-

torical phase being only implicit in what he was saying, not in

what he actually did.2 We have already seen an example of this

analytic phase in Collingwood's treatment of the identity of

philosophy and history. Consequently we expect him to begin with

a pair of concepts presumed to be isolated or "separated" from

one another. In

__________________
2 Actually Speculum Mentis, for all its discussion of
history and its relation to philosophy, does not actually dis-
play in its compositional format any more concern for the his-
torical development of its subject matter than does Religion and
Philosophy, except that the former has that same vague reference
to historical development of forms of experience as does Hegel's
Phenomenology of Mind. But cf. SM, 50-55 (an "ages of man"
analogy), and 21-38.
248

this case the reconciliata (the term we shall henceforth use for

viewpoints to be held together in the relationship of

rapprochement) are religion and philosophy. But from the first

words of the book we are aware that the orientation of the

discussion to follow is primarily philosophical:

This book is the result of an attempt to treat the Christian


creed not as a dogma but as a critical solution of a
philosophical problem. Christianity, in other words, is
approached as a philosophy, and its various doctrines are
regarded as varying aspects of a single idea which, ac-
cording to the language in which it is expressed, may be
called a metaphysics, an ethic, or theology. (RP, xiii).

Collingwood also specifies the sense in which he understands the

terms "religion" and "philosophy," at least for the purposes of

discussion in this book:

Just as every man has some working theory of the world which
is his philosophy, some system of ideals which rule his
conduct, so every one has to some degree that unified life
of all the faculties which is a religion . . . . We apply
the term religion to certain types of consciousness, and not
to others, because we see in the one type certain
characteristics which in the others we consider to be ab-
sent. Further investigation shows that the characteristic
marks of religion, the marks in virtue of which we applied
the term, are really present in the others also, though in a
form which at first evaded recognition. (RP, xvii-xviii).

Collingwood did not follow up these clues about the

presence of
249

one form of consciousness in other forms until Speculum Mentis,3

and while it is interesting to note that the germ of his later

doctrine of a "scale of forms" is present in this early

discussion of the nature of religion, in Religion and Philosophy

the strategy he follows is based not on the construction of a

phenomenology of forms of experience, but rather on the analytic

method of his earlier (and still incomplete) rapprochement.

Therefore he begins with what already amount to theories of

religion, but theories which treat of religion as if it had no

direct relationship to philosophy. Furthermore it is to be noted

that Collingwood does not start out with a definition or

description of religion that omits its philosophical aspect

(e.g. "primitive religions") and then try to derive philosophy

from this description. He starts out rather with

"anti-intellectual" theories of religion--religion viewed as

(mere) ritual, as conduct, or as feeling--that is, theories that

deny that religion has an intellectual element and therefore

deny that it is

______________________
3 In addition to examining the relations of religion to
philosophy, history, and conduct (morality), Collingwood
recognized a "fourth question" concerning the relation of re-
ligion to art, but declined to deal with the issue in Religion
and Philosophy, promising to discuss the nature of metaphor,
prose, and the philosophy of language (all being in the province
of art) in a future volume (RP, xvi). In Speculum Mentis he
recalls this promise, and indicates to his readers the extent to
which he felt the earlier work to be deficient (SM, 108, n. 1).
250

identical with philosophy. Each of these theories is then

subjected to a critique, and in the process of denying the

premise (that religion is mere ritual, mere conduct, or mere

feeling, each without an intellectual element) he affirms the

consequence that creed is not nonessential to religion.

(a) The claim of religion to be mere ritual is based on

anthropology's examination of religions of lower culture, which

purport to show that ritual is prior to creed. But Collingwood

argues that aside from the issue of what relation there is

between primitive and modern religions (which may be one of

analogy only), the theory still lacks an account of how ritual

practices arise in the first place. The necessary nature of

ritual implies a grounding in fears, and the ritual act is

performed because the primitive people assume the universe to be

governed by certain powers, and that their acts will somehow

please or influence these powers in ways beneficial to the

tribe. But such a judgment about the nature of the powers that

govern the universe is a primitive theory, and the belief that

acts will influence that power is creed. (RP, 6-7; FR, 45-46).

(b) Similarly the view that holds that doctrine has

little or no bearing on conduct, and therefore holds that re-

ligion is primarily a system of rules guiding conduct, ignores

the fact that action relies on knowledge of the situation which

calls for application of the rule. There


251

is no such thing as conduct divorced from knowledge or knowledge

divorced from conduct. Furthermore the conduct that is being

recommended presumes a judgment that certain sorts of conduct

are good and others bad, which is a judgment based on creed: it

is the presumption of the truth of the moral creed that results

in the good act. (RP, 7-9; FR, 46-49).

(c) Finally, religion as pure feeling trades on the

ambiguities of the word "feeling," which in some cases (as when

it refers to very indefinite and indistinct states of mind)

seems to rule out any truly intellectual element, but in others

(as when it implies absolute and positive conviction coupled

with an inability to offer proof or explanation of the

conviction) it does not rule out knowledge per se but actually

means the same thing as knowledge, albeit unreasoned. But in the

first case one could hardly call such feeling religious, because

it does not hold to any truth at all, being too indistinct and

indefinite (not all indefinite states of mind are therefore

religious, nor are religious states of mind indefinite). And if

feeling just means emotion, it must at least admit to a kind of

emotion that is appetition for the desired thing--in this case,

God--and consequently presumes some knowledge of God as

desirable. In any event religious feeling requires some

intellectual element. (RP, 11; FR, 49).


252

It can be seen from these arguments that if there is any

"reduction" of religion that is to occur, at least Collingwood

will not be content to let this be the humiliating reduction of

religion to a lesser form of experience. Whether he allows for a

kind of exalting reduction by assimilating it to a "higher"

realm remains to be seen. But these passages (and especially

when taken with the perceptive analysis of Christian beliefs

concerning the fall and redemption of man, in the concluding

chapters of the book) show a refined sense of awareness of the

subject matter of religion, and an unwillingness to have it

sullied by inappropriate and reductive comparisons.

Now at this point the reader would expect (if the "an-

alytic" follows the pattern of the discussion of the relation of

philosophy and history) a criticism of the view that philosophy

has no religious element, the implication being that if it is

not the case that philosophy does not have a religious element,

then philosophy must have an essential religious dimension just

as religion must have an element of philosophy. In other words,

insofar as philosophy is essential to religion and religion to

philosophy, religion and philosophy mutually imply one another

and are hence identical (that is, nonseparate). But what one

finds instead in Religion and Philosophy is an identification of

the two by their object, coupled with a denial that there is any

such thing as a separate "philosophy of religion"--separate,

that it, from theology


253

or creed.

(T)he theory of knowledge or logic does not consider dif-


ferences of the object, but only processes of the subject;
and therefore there is no distinction between the philosophy
of religion (as theory of religious knowledge) and the
theory of knowledge in general. If there is a general
philosophy of knowing, it includes religious knowledge as
well as all other kinds; no separate philosophy is
required . . . . If the philosophy of religion is
indistinguishable from philosophy as a whole, what is the
relation of philosophy as a whole to religion or theology?
Philosophy is the theory of existence; not of existence in
the abstract, but of existence in the concrete; the theory
of all that exists; the theory of the universe . . . . Now
if philosophy is the theory of the universe, what is
religion? We have said that it was the theory of God and of
God's relations to the world and man. But the latter is
surely nothing more or less than a theory of the
universe . . . . Religion and philosophy alike are views of
the whole universe . . . . If religion and philosophy are
views of the same thing--the ultimate nature of the
universe--then the true religion and the true philosophy
must coincide . . . (RP, 15-18; FR, 53-55).

We have already seen that Collingwood identified history and

philosophy in much the same way--as both dealing with "knowledge

of the one, real world." This occurs, in fact, in a chapter in

which the relation between history and religion is being

discussed, and the implication towards which the reader seems to

be compelled is that since religion and philosophy are

identical, and since history and philosophy are identical,

religion is identical with history. The conclusion of the

chapter even suggests that science is also not anti-religious,

and therefore, by implication, identical with religion, phil-

osophy, and history.


254

It goes without saying that such a Mulligan stew of

subjects is more than a reader can be expected to digest. To

simply identify religion and philosophy seems not only to lead

to the confused state wherein what can be said as proper to each

is now predicable of the other (as if one could resolve an

honest dispute about some aspect of reality by engaging in

prayer or sacrifice, or that one might celebrate ritual syllo-

gism on a Sabbath morning and thereby appease a reasoning god),

but renders suspect the autonomy of all other forms of thought

as well. If two kinds of knowledge are identified by reference

to their object, and if there is no distinction in the processes

of the subject whereby a "philosophy of" something and a theory

of knowledge in general may be distinguished, then there seems

to be no remaining way of distinguishing between two ways of

knowing the same thing, and consequently between science,

religion, history, and philosophy. But then on what grounds can

one even distinguish between subjective processes of knowledge

and objective correlates of these processes?

These consequences of his position are not altogether

evaded by Collingwood, as we see in a later chapter of Religion

and Philosophy where he argues as follows:

My imagination of a table is certainly a different thing


from the table itself, and to identify the two would be to
mistake fancy for fact; but my knowledge of the table, my
thought of it in that sense, is simply the table as known to
me, as much of the table's nature as
255

I have discovered. In this sense, my "thought about" the


table-what I think the table to be--only differs from the
table itself if and in so far as I am ignorant of the
table's real nature. My thought of the table is certainly
not something "like" the table; it is the table as I know
it. Similarly, your thought of the table is what you know of
the table, the table as known to you; and if we both have
real knowledge of the table, it seems to follow that our
thoughts are the same, not merely similar; and further, if
the mind is its thoughts, we seem to have, for this moment
at least, actually one mind; we share between us that unity
of consciousness which was said to be the mark of the
individual. (RP, 100-01; FR, 172-73).4

Even with the proviso that in life "real knowledge" or the

knowledge of the real nature of something (even artifacts,

judging from the example) is seldom if ever perfect, so that "in

a sense, no two people ever do, or ever could, think or will

exactly the same thing" (RP, 106; FR, 177), such an assertion

puts an intolerable strain on the notion of identity. For even

if my knowledge of the table were "real knowledge," it would

seem strange to assert that my concept of the table is subject

of predication in the same sense that the table is--and

therefore capable of supporting

_________________________
4 In a footnote to this passage Collingwood denied that
his argument placed him in an idealistic stance: "I believe that
the argument I have tried to express contains little if anything
which contradicts the principles of either realism or idealism
in their more satisfactory forms." (RP, 101; FR, 173). It is
interesting to note that in his later philosophy when he puts
forward his theory of historical re-enactment, which makes a
similar claim to the identity of mind as in the present
paragraph, he also juxtaposes it against both realists and
idealists--see IN, 282-302.
256

articles placed on it, capable of physical destruction with

sufficient mechanical force, etc. And to assert that we never

have "real knowledge" of anything seems to grant so much ground

to scepticism that the argument in point seems futile.

Since Collingwood's rapprochement program is precisely

one of showing that two forms of thought are not "separate" but

rather are "the same"--whether that sameness be the sameness of

an historical process or the sameness of question to which they

are the responses--it is clear that at the root of

reconciliation philosophy is a notion of identity that on the

face of it (from our above example) is under disruptive

pressures which threaten to split it assunder. For (a) if "the

same" means merely "not different," then when two forms of

thought are said to be "the same" they are being said to be "not

different," and in their indifference they are not only no

longer two forms of thought (and so the comparison is fatuous),

but they are also indistinguishable from nothing at all;5 but

(b) if "the same" means "similar in some, but not all

characteristics" then when two forms of thought are said to be

"the same" they are being

________________________
5 The situation is aggravated rather than ameliorated in
the case of the forms of knowledge, since Collingwood specifies
their objects, in each case, to be the "whole universe" or "all
of existence," which leaves no room a parte objecti for a
distinction between them. And since the forms of knowledge have
been identified with each other and with philosophy, a
distinction a parte subjecti) is also impossible.
257

said to be "similar and dissimilar" in specifiable ways--which

is precisely what Collingwood seems to be denying.

But lest we be charged with a case of unfair pillory, we

hasten to add that Collingwood shows even in Religion and

Philosophy that he is aware of the difficulty, and goes so far

as to try to meet it head on. In the same chapter from which the

table example is drawn (a chapter, incidentally, which deals

with inter-subjective identity as the grounds of possibility for

religious unity of God, man, and universe) Collingwood

distinguishes between an abstract and a concrete unity, and says

that "the unity whose possibility we are concerned to prove is

the fully concrete identification, by their own free activity,

of two or more personalities" not as a universal condition but

as an ideal (RP, 106-07; FR, 178).

A person is undoubtedly himself, and can never help being


himself, whatever he does; but this merely abstract unity,
this bare minimum of self-identity, is much less than what
we usually call his character or personality. That is rather
constituted by the definite and concrete system of his
various activities or habits . . . . The same distinction
applies to the unity of a society. In one sense, any kind of
relation between two people produced a kind of social union
and identification; in another sense, only the right kind of
relation unifies them, and a different relation would
destroy the unity. In the first case, their union is what I
call the purely abstract unity; in the latter, it is the
concrete unity that has to be maintained by positive and
harmonious activity. (RP, 107-08; FR, 178-79).

Aside from the question of what the "right kind of relation"

might be, or by what criteria one decides rightness and non

rightness of relations,
258

there is still the puzzling and as yet unresolved question as to

what the distinction between abstract and concrete unity refers

to. Collingwood's answer seems to rely on a modification of the

relation of whole and part:

But is unity the same as identity? There seems at first


sight to be a very decided difference between saying that
two things are part of the same whole, and saying that they
are the same thing; the parts of one thing seem to be
themselves quite separate and self-existent things, possibly
depending on each other, but each being what it is itself,
and not the others; while the whole is simply their sum. We
have already expressed doubts as to the strict truth of this
conception . . . . (I)f a whole was to be knowable, it must
be of such a kind that the parts are not simply added in
series to one another, but interconnected in such a way that
we can somehow say that each part is the whole. In that case
each part would also be in a sense the others . . . . Each
part has its own nature, its own individuality, which is in
the strictest sense unique; and apart from the contribution
made by each several element the whole would not exist.
Change one part, and the whole becomes a different whole.
Not only does the whole change, but the apparently unchanged
parts change too. (RP, 108-10; FR, 179-80).

Collingwood uses the instance of any whole consisting of three

parts, x, y, z--whether that whole be a machine with three

working parts, a society of three members, a stanza of three

lines, or a syllogism containing three propositions. In such a

system the definition of the part x can only take the form of a

definition of the whole xyz, since the "thing" itself is "only a

relation, an interchange, a balance between the elements which

at first we mistook for its parts" (RP, 112-13; FR, 182-83).


259

The attempt to evade this analysis of relations and

relate by pointing to the difference between what a thing is in

itself and what it is in relation to its context or the whole of

which it is a part is also, Collingwood says, unsuccessful,

since "the character or self of a thing, what it is, cannot be

distinguished from its relations" (RP, 112; FR, 182) Even though

its "internal relations" seem not to change when a change of

context or of its "external relations" occurs, it is impossible

to deprive a thing of every context (as one would presumably be

forced to do to prove that what it is in itself is not affected

by its context), so that one can do no more than to replace one

context with another.6 Whether the "context" be spatial or

temporal does not greatly affect the argument, since "the

history of a thing in the past and its capabilities for the

future are as real as its present situation" (RP, 111; FR, 182).

But even this analysis of the relationship of parts to

whole, although presumed to be correct and even essential for

his argument, is regarded by Collingwood as a variety of

abstract unity. It is merely the lowest possible sort of whole,

the necessary, abstract unity

____________________
6 Collingwood seems unaware that his argument at this
point begs the question: to "change a context" does not ordin-
arily mean to deprive a thing of all contexts, so to assert the
impossibility of the latter does not affect the argument that
there is a difference between what a thing is in itself and what
it is in relation to its context.
260

of its elements. It is not yet the "contingent unity of

co-operation" between consenting minds that is required for a

community of persons. Since Collingwood wishes to show that all

personalities are components of a whole (the universe) and

therefore "necessarily identified with each other and the whole,

that is, with the universe considered as homogeneous with them,

an absolute mind, God" (RP, 114; FR, 184), this minimum,

abstract unity, although essential, falls short of the mark; it

leaves us with an abstract God.

(T)he error lies in mistaking this fundamental assumption


for the final conclusion; in assuming that this elementary,
abstract unity is the only one which concerns us . . . . To
call this formless and empty abstraction "the Absolute" is
merely to abuse language; and to suppose that this is all
philosophy has to offer in place of the concrete God of
religion is completely to misunderstand the nature and aim
of philosophy . . . . The Absolute . . . is not a label for
the bare residuum, blank existence, which is left when all
discrepancies have been ignored and all irregularities
planed away . . . . A real philosophy builds its Absolute
(for every philosophy has an Absolute) out of the
differences of the world as it finds them, dealing indi-
vidually with all contradictions and preserving every detail
that can lend character to the whole . . . . The formless
and empty Absolute of this abstract metaphysic perished long
ago in the fire of Hegel's sarcasm . . . ((as)) the
pseudo-Absolute, the "night in which all cows are black" . .
. . (RP, 114-16; FR, 184-86).

We shall return in a moment to what Collingwood understands by

"the Absolute," but for now we wish to show that in contrast to

the abstract Absolute Collingwood proposes a "concrete identity

of activity":
261

A mind is self-identical in this sense if it thinks and


wills the same things constantly; it is identical with
another, if it thinks and wills the same things as that
other . . . . Now these two cases are typical first of the
self-identity of God, and secondly of his identity with the
human mind . . . . Further, this divine mind will become one
with all other minds so far as they share its thought and
volition; so far, that is, as they know any truth or will
any good. And this unity between the two is not the merely
abstract identity of co-existence, but the concrete identity
of co-operation. (RP, 116-19; FR, 186-88).

In Religion and Philosophy, however, Collingwood at-

tempts little more than to show how such a unity is possible;

since he has not built his Absolute "out of the differences of

the world" as he found them, but rather built them out of ab-

stract concepts by dialectical analysis, his philosophy of re-

ligion at this stage remains an unfulfilled promise. Furthermore

the reader is left unsatisfied how there can be "other minds" at

all, or how one distinguishes between the mind of God and the

minds of men when they are thinking and willing the same thing.

We have covered a lot of ground since initiating our

discussion about Collingwood's rapprochement philosophy, and it

may be helpful here to pause and survey the territory. (1) We

have seen that Collingwood claimed in the Autobiography that

prior to 1932 he had only partially worked out his rapprochement

philosophy, to the point where he saw that the relation between

reconciliata was one of "intimate and mutual dependence." (2) As

the first published example of this


262

partial reconciliation we took up the analysis of religion and

philosophy in the book of that name, his first publication. (3)

In contrast to the reconciliation of philosophy and history

which we examined in the previous section (and found to involve

an argument that showed history and philosophy to mutually

implicate one another, and therefore to be "identical"), the

reconciliation of religion and philosophy took a more complex

and circuitous route. (4) The strategy of the latter argument

turned out to rely on the epistemological assumption that forms

of knowledge, and even minds, which intend the same object are

identical--thereby identifying religion and philosophy as forms

of knowledge about "all of existence" or "the universe," and

incidentally identifying all other forms of knowledge as well.

(5) Collingwood recognized that this was a kind of abstract

identity, and attempted to correct this abstract notion of

identity with a discussion of "concrete identity"--which turns

out to mean a contingent unity of the activity of co-operation

between minds. (6) Such an identity is the only true Absolute

sought by philosophy and religion alike; therefore they are

reconciled by sharing a common ideal object.

On route from reconciliation to Absolute we discovered a

number of subsidiary issues, which we shall find of importance

in considering Collingwood's further development of the notion

of rapprochement. (1) In Religion and Philosophy, at least,

Collingwood displayed both a remarkable


263

sensitivity for the issues confronting persons who attempt to

reflectively understand their religious consciousness, and an

equal obteuseness about the "division of knowledge" into

provinces, to the point where the forms of knowledge--science,

history, art-appear as species of the genus, "knowledge"

(although he never explicitly says this). (2) But in trying to

sort out the confusion that results from identifying forms of

knowledge with each other, we discovered that for Collingwood

there are levels of meaning for the concept of identity, just as

there were levels of meaning to the concept of history. So when

two reconciliata are said to be "identical" or "the same" one

must carefully attend to which sense of "identity" is being

used. We have observed at least three uses of the term so far:

(a) a bare, abstract identity in which terms are related only as

members of a class or genus; (b) a (dialectical) identity of

whole and part, in which relations and relate are so intimately

connected that any change in a part necessarily implies a change

in the relations and in the whole, and vice versa; and (c) a

concrete identity of mental activity, in which persons may co-

operate in thinking truth or in doing good. The first two in-

volve relations of necessity, the third a relation of contin-

gency. The first two are also abstract, the third is fully

concrete. (d) While the self-identity of the Absolute mind, or

of God, is not specified as a fourth kind of identity, it is at

least put forward as the limiting case


264

of the concept of identity--the self-identity of truth, in all

its diversity, with itself (RP, 117-20; FR, 186-190). (3) For

each sense of the term identity there corresponds a sense of the

term "separate"--so that there will be (a) separate members of a

class (abstract separation--entities treated as mere instances

of a class), (b) separate elements of an organic whole

(dialectical separation), and (c) personal separateness

(concrete separation--if the unity of cooperation breaks down,

for example). We would have to presume that a separateness or

disunity in the self-identity of the Absolute mind or God would

be impossible; the disunity would occur between God and man, and

would fall into the category of concrete separation.7 (4)

Finally the reader is left to his own devices to decide what

would constitute an instance of the first sense of the term,

"identity," as well as its corresponding sense of separation,

insofar as Collingwood's examples from the second meaning (what

we have called dialectical identity and separation) --namely a

three-part machine, society, poem, or syllogism (he even refers

later to the stones forming the arch of a house)--seem to leave

little room for an example of something that is not an "organic

whole."

______________________
7 This issue is taken up by Collingwood in the conclud-
ing chapters of Religion and Philosophy in the discussions on
evil, the self-expression- God in man (in the person of the
Christ), and God's redemption of man (RP, 122-93; FR, 192-211,
251-69). These are interesting and occasionally profound
chapters and utterly repudiate the thesis that Collingwood had
neither interest nor insight into the nature of religious
consciousness.
265

3. Speculum Mentis: Rapprochement and Developing Series.

Some of these themes and the issues they raise appear

again in Speculum Mentis, and others in essays published between

1916 and 1926. In a footnote in Speculum Mentis Collingwood

proposes that his chapter on religion be taken as a correction

of the views he put forward in Religion and Philosophy, and says

his "mea culpas" for the oversights of that earlier work:8

With much of what that book contains I am still in agree-


ment; but there are certain principles which I then over-
looked or denied, in the light of which many of its faults
can be corrected. The chief of these principles is the
distinction between implicit and explicit. I contended
throughout that religion, theology, and philosophy were
identical, and this I should not so much withdraw as qual-
ify by pointing out that the "empirical" (i.e. real but
unexplained) difference between them is that theology makes
explicit what in religion as such is always implicit, and
so with philosophy and theology. This error led me into a
too intellectualistic or abstract attitude towards re-
ligion, of which many critics rightly accused me; for in-
stance . . . I failed to discover any real ground for the
distinction not only between man and God, but between man
and man . . . . (SM, 108, no. 1; emphasis mine).

The way in which Collingwood revised the conception of his forms

of knowledge and their relations is based on a more careful

analysis of the language of art, religion, science, and history,

as well as on a

____________________
8 The fact that Collingwood here and elsewhere expli-
citly acknowledges changes in his position on topics discussed
in previous writings should alert the reader to beware of any
claims by overzealous interpreters to find a radical consistency
in all of his writings. It should also, however, be a warning to
all who claim a "radical conversion" where no such change of
heart is acknowledged explicitly by Collingwood. For another
explicit acknowledgement, see PA, 288, n. 1).
266

careful delineation of what the claims of any one form are

(explicitly) as distinct from what the limitations of these

claims are (implicitly) when seen from a "higher" viewpoint.9 He

withdraws his previous assertion that epistemology (in the guise

of logic) "is a masterscience having jurisdiction over the whole

field of knowledge"--which he now regards as "pure

intellectualism" (SM, 49); and he condemns all identifications

of philosophy with religion, science, art, or history as "barren

____________________
9 The "implicit-explicit" distinction, although singled
out by Collingwood as very important and the essential differ-
ence between the argument in Speculum Mentis and that of
Religion and Philosophy, is difficult to define in terms general
enough to be acceptable to all levels of the scale of forms of
knowledge as they are presented in the later work. Collingwood's
characterization of the distinction tends to be in terms of
mental dispositions. "In any given experience," he writes,
"there are certain principles, distinctions, and so forth of
which the person whose experience it is cannot but be aware:
these I call explicit features of the experience in question . .
. . On the other hand, an observer studying a certain form of
experience often finds it impossible to give an account of it
without stating certain principles and distinctions which are
not actually recognized by the persons whose experience he is
studying . . . ((for example)) theology makes explicit certain
principles which are implicitly, but never explicitly, present
in religious consciousness; and in general what we call
philosophy reveals explicitly the principles which are implicit
in what we call everyday experience" (SM, 85, n. 1). However in
the course of the argument it becomes clear that what may be
implicitly assumed in one form of experience (e.g. religion) may
become explicit either in the next form (e.g. science) which
appears as its successor in the developing series, or by the
"dogmatic philosophy" of that form itself--the philosophy which
is engendered by a form of knowledge when it attempts to justify
itself as a total outlook on reality. Roughly, then, the
"implicit-explicit" distinction is the distinction between
something presumed and something asserted by the expression of a
form of experience.
267

abstractions" (SM, 246; cf. FR, 91). Having served his time on

the Procrustean couch of logic, Collingwood is bent upon

correcting his previous mistakes, and rises now to the occasion

by roundly condemning the view that the five forms of experience

are species of a genus, which may be substituted for one another

or taken up in any order. They now form a series, and in this

series there is an element of denial and distinction:

(O)ur forms of experience are not mere species of a genus,


because each denies the others; and because they are not
species they have not that indifference with regard one
another which characterizes abstract logical classifica-
tions. They must form an order of some kind . . . . But
what is even more important than the actual order is the
suggestion of serial arrangement as such. For a series of
terms implies that each term is as it were built upon or
derived from its predecessor and therefore does not start in
vacuo, is not wholly fresh embodiment of the universal, but
is essentially a modification of the term before. Hence
even if we only recognized three terms, and made a series
by alternating them, abcabcabc . . ., there would be no
repetition, for the second a would be not the mere first a
again, but a modified by having been developed through b
out of c; the third a would be a modified by the same
process in the second degree; and so on. (SM, 55; cf. SM,
206-07).

We now see a glimmering of an answer not only to the

question of what the way was in which Collingwood modified his

original rapprochement philosophy, but also the way in which the

"sameness of question" turns out to be not the sameness of a

universal but the sameness of an historical process. The

modification consists in the addition of a notion of what Col-

lingwood would later call a "scale of forms" to the analytic


268

phase of his di-phasic (now tri-phasic) method of reconcili-

ation. We shall see in a moment the radical way in which this

modifies the notion of identity; but just on the analogy of his

three-term system, it is clear from the comparison of this

system with that offered in Religion and Philosophy that there

is a shift of emphasis here from the mere assertion that the

change of relations in a three-term system implies a change in

the relate (in a system of dialectical identity) to the

specification of how that change affects the relationship. The

terms are related not merely "internally" (Collingwood avoids

the "internal-external" metaphor in Speculum Mentis) but in an

ascending series, in an order of development, such that when a

term changes it is changed through the agency or mediation of

another term in the series into something further which

incorporates the others (its predecessors) into itself. But this

is the way that Collingwood had defined historical change in his

1927 and 1929 essays on the philosophy of history: history is a

process of spiritual development, a dynamic rather than static

concept, in which ideas grow out of other ideas and modify these

previous ideas while being modified by them (EPH, 73). The

manner of identification of the forms of knowledge and the

sameness of historical problems converge on the concept of a

developmental series.

Collingwood is quick to reassure the reader that al-

though the forms of experience and the stages of history display

a developmental
269

structure, the life of mind is "not the rotation of a machine

through a cycle of fixed phases," and consequently one should

not expect to have his nose held to a "dialectical grindstone"

(SM, 56). It will be recalled from Religion and Philosophy that

the "identity of cooperation" (which we now recognize as the

identity of historical processes) was regarded as a contingent

identity, and not a necessary one. Consequently it is not

surprising that at the very beginning of a work which is to

spell out the stages of development of a mind through successive

forms of experience, stages which parallel the development of

consciousness in mankind as a whole (cf. SM, 50-54), Collingwood

should feel bound to deny that the relation between phases is

one of compulsion or necessity--and this importation of

contingency is a measure of Collingwood's distance from Hegel.

On the other hand (as will be recalled from our previous

discussion of Speculum Mentis)--the test of each of these forms

of experience (each of which claims not only to give the truth

but "to give the absolute or ultimate truth concerning the

nature of the universe, to reveal the secret of existence, and

to tell us what the world really and fundamentally is" (SM, 41))

is to be its inherent self-consistency. The "prize of truth" for

which they all strive is to be gained by the form of knowledge

which is self-consistent, or which proves its claim by

"demonstrating the necessary inconsistency of the other forms"

(SM, 45).
270

But then it would seem that the grindstone of dialectical

necessity that Collingwood seems anxious to keep away from the

noses of his readers is kept whirling a few inches away (perhaps

to sharpen an analytical blade). How does a form of knowledge,

which retains its claim to truth by demonstrating both its

inherent self-consistency and the inherent and essential

inconsistency of rival forms of knowledge--how does it do so

without displaying itself as the necessarily true form of

knowledge and the necessary successor to its predecessors? For

if the other forms are inherently inconsistent, then it is clear

that they cannot of themselves achieve ultimate truth, and

therefore of necessity fail.

By now the reader should expect that the solution to the

problem will more likely be to revise the notion of necessity

than to withdraw one or the other of the pair of contradictory

claims.l° But to get an idea of how Collingwood actually viewed

the manner in which such a series of terms are related we must

(once again begging the reader's indulgence) take another look

at the argument of Speculum Mentis. In so doing we shall

deliberately take a different route from the one Collingwood

laid out for his readers. Instead of beginning with artistic

experience and proceeding

_____________________
1O This is Rubinoff's strategy: see CRM, 61, 176-83.
These passages are also the most flagrantly Hegelian in his
whole book.
271

through theothers until we reach philosophy, we shall begin

where we left off in our discussion of Q-A logic, i.e., with

science, and work first backwards to religion and then art, and

then forward to history and philosophy.

Our reason for this strategy is primarily to test this

new requirement for rapprochement: for if (a) the forms of

knowledge constitute a series wherein each term is a modifica-

tion of the one before, then in an analysis of a successorform

one should find traces of its predecessor--traces that will,

when analyzed show how the successor-form is "built upon or

derived from" its predecessor. Thus in the analysis of science

which constituted much of our discussion of Q-A logic, we should

be able to detect a religious element, and in the latter an

artistic element. And if (b) there is no dialectical necessity

involved in the series then when we progress from science to

history the latter will resolve the inconsistencies of the

former without being the necessary outcome of it, or necessarily

implied by it. In short, when viewed retrogressively there will

be necessary relations exhibited between terms in the series;

when viewed progressively these relations will appear to be

contingent.

One more final note before beginning our survey. From

our discussion of the analysis of science in Speculum Mentis we

notice that scientific consciousness is characterized in terms

of (1) the sort of


272

ideal object it intends to grasp, (2) the faculty of mind by

which it habitually operates, (3) its characteristic mode of

expression, and (4) its fatal weakness, or inner contradiction,

that renders it to be an unstable mode of knowledge. Besides

these four, Collingwood further characterizes it (5) by the

consequences it has for human action, insofar as it generates,

when taken as a guide for conduct, a particular form of ethics.

While important for Collingwood's rapprochement between theory

and practice, and therefore another partial confirmation of his

contention in the Autobiography that he sought to carry his pro-

gram of reconciliation even into the realm of ethics and con-

duct, we propose to ignore this fifth aspect here in order not

to further tangle the knotted threads of our argument.

4. Speculum Mentis: Retrogressive Identity.

Science, as described in Speculum Mentis, is the con-

scious attitude of regarding its object always as an instance of

a universal law (SM, 158-63). It operates by a faculty of

understanding, which distinguishes between universals and par-

ticulars, and assumes that universals can be separated or iso-

lated (abstracted) by thought and studied apart from its in-

stances (SM, 166-67). Instances of such universal laws are not

regarded as having mutual relations among themselves other than

those specified by the law (SM, 162, 166-167). But scientific

laws are not merely statements of what would be the case if

certain uniform conditions obtain (the hypothetical deductive

aspect of science),
273

science also seeks to assert its laws as holding in the real

world, and therefore referring to individuals or to the world of

facts perceived by observers (the categorical-inductive aspect

of science) (SM, 177, 183). In epigrammatic form, science is the

form of consciousness which intends an object which can be

expressed in universal, referentially true assertions.

Now it is not difficult to see that this sort of con-

sciousness presupposes and depends for its existence on sub-

ordinate acts of consciousness. Scientific consciousness pre-

supposes a distinction between universals (concepts, laws) and

the particulars (perceptions, instances) to which they apply--a

distinction, Collingwood insists, which is essential and

irreducible for scientific thinking, given the sort of object

(ideal) it intends.ll But a distinction between a universal and

something particular is a distinction between something merely

entertained as a meaning (in imagination) and something to which

this meaning refers as a real instance (in perception); it is

not only an assertion, but an assertion with a referent, i.e., a

real object (EPH, 135-36; cf. SM,

______________________
1l Collingwood states that "mathematics, mechanism, and
materialism are the three marks of all science," but he reduces
all three of these essential characteristics of science to the
"assertion of the abstract concept"--they are all "products of
the classificatory frame of mind" (SM, 167). For Collingwood's
later view of what the characteristic marks of modern science
are, see IN, 13-27.
274

238-39). It is, as we said, both hypothetical (a possible

meaning) and categorical (referential). As hypothetical sci-

entific consciousness is the exercise of making supposals, of

entertaining questions and formulating hypotheses--all of which

imply the consideration of an object without reference to its

truth or falsity, or to its existence or non-existence. This is

the defining characteristic of imaginary objects, and

Collingwood's claim is that imagined objects are what the forms

of consciousness known as religion and art intend. For art the

entertainment and expression of imagined objects is necessary

and sufficient to it as a mental activity; for religious

consciousness there is the additional requirement that its

objects be taken as truly existing--it is not indifferent to the

existence of its object as is artistic consciousness (cf. EPA,

137-41).

Therefore it is clear that (1) if scientific conscious-

ness requires that its object be expressed in scientific asser-

tions, and (2) if scientific assertions essentially imply a

distinction between universals and particulars, and (3) if this

distinction demands expression in hypothetical assertions which

(4) are not only entertained as possible meanings but also (5)

are taken as categorically true, or as truly referring to

particulars, and finally (6) if the latter two activities (that

is, (4) and (5)) are characteristics essential to artistic and

religious consciousness respectively, then (7) we have

demonstrated that scientific


275

consciousness essentially and necessarily contains elements (or

structures) that are characteristically religious and artistic.

If this is an acceptable summary of the argument in the first

three portions of Collingwood's "dialectic of experience" it

seems to be saying too much and too little at the same time. Is

it not asking too much to expect us to believethat before a law

of nature is taken to be scientific it must first be grasped

artistically and then religiously--first painted by an artist

and then worshipped by a priest?l2

________________________
12 Collingwood does point to an explicit inheritance of
religion and art in science, but he presents it in the form of a
mental disposition--a "bias toward abstraction." He writes:
"This bias is allowed unconsciously to control its development .
. . . Because the abstractness of science is a perpetuation of
the abstractness of religion, science most naturally arises out
of a religion which has not overcome this abstractness, that is
to say, out of a non-Christian religion. Hence European science
has its roots in the religion of pagan antiquity . . . . Science
in the modern world is science Christianized, science fed by a
religious consciousness in which the primary abstractness of
religion has been cancelled by the notions of incarnation and
atonement. This gives the distinction between the a priori
science of the Greeks and the empirical science of the modern or
Christian world. But religion, even in the form of Christianity,
never really transcends its abstractness . . . . The aim of
science is to avoid this fault; Greek science aims at avoiding
the specific fault of Greek religion, modern science at avoiding
that of Christianity, namely, its liability to misinterpretation
in a sense which makes God an arbitrary tyrant, whose very gifts
are an insult to a free man. The history of European science
begins with the breakdown of a religious view of the world in
the mind of ancient Greece, and the concepts of Greek science
appear as a kind of depersonalized gods" (SM, 160-61). It
appears that Collingwood would have agreed with Cornford against
Burnet: "Principium sapientiae (quae scientiae) timor dei."
276

This is something of the impression one gets by a forward

reading of Speculum Mentis. But in reversing directions we see

that it obviously is not what he has in mind. Collingwood is not

speaking generically--he is not saying that one and the same

object of consciousness is first taken as an art-object and then

as a religious object and finally as a science-object. He is

making what appears to be a logical point--that forms of

consciousness and their characteristic modes of expression are

bound to one another in a logically necessary fashion, such that

in thinking scientifically one cannot help but also think (in an

implicit way) religiously and artistically (but not necessarily

vice-versa).

But then is this not saying too little? Our previous

objection concerning the reduction of the forms of consciousness

to one another as species of a genus seems to apply here as

well. Surely in scientific consciousness there is an element of

creed, if one takes creed as the form ofexpression of a

consciousness which assumes its object to be real and asserts

itself in statements about that object that are assumed to be

true and distinct from other statements about it which are

false. But to take the object of religious consciousness to be

creed in this sense is to reduce religion to its mode of

expression, and this would be an error as grievous as merely

taking it as an event in the brain, insofar as both ignore what

is properly and peculiarly being asserted by


277

religious statements. Religion is not particularly concerned

with objects sliding down inclined planes or the displacements

of fluids by solid objects of a given weight; and science is not

particularly concerned with the effect that natural laws will

have on the moral behavior of those who believe in them. Fur-

thermore religion expresses itself not only in credal asser-

tions, but in exclamations, questions, petitions, demands,

apologies, etc. By focusing on the mode of expression, and on

only one mode at that, Collingwood seems to be ignoring what it

is that is being expressed by that mode, and this is the sort of

formalism Collingwood had criticized psychology for employing.

And nothing is added by relating a mode of expression to a

faculty of consciousness, since the same objection can be raised

about the mode of consciousness which takes its object a certain

way, but does not specify what is peculiar to the object it is

so taking.

These objections would be more biting if it were not for

the fact that Collingwood spends an entire chapter of Speculum

Mentis trying to say what religion is, not only generically (as

a form of consciousness sharing characteristics with other

forms) but specifically. Religion is a form of consciousness

which intends an object which is a unified whole (like the

object of art), which is ultimately real (like the object of

science and unlike the object of art), and which is taken as

sacred or holy--that is,


278

deserving of adoration (unlike both science and art):

God, we are told by theologians, is the ultimate reality,


conceived as spirit; spirit omnipotent, omniscient, cre-
ative, transcending all sense of immediacy, yet immanent in
his church. But this language, well enough in theology, is
very far from natural to religion . . . . From the simple
and unsophisticated point of view of the religious
consciousness, it is not the spirituality nor the immanence
of God that is important, nor even his power or goodness,
but his holiness, the necessity of falling down before him
in adoration. This sense of the holiness of God is the
explicit differentia of the religious experience. (SM,
118-19).

As in Religion and Philosophy, Collingwood is anxious not to

characterize religion in a reductive fashion, so he is at pains

not to be content, as some writers on religion had been, to

describe "the holy" as a feeling of uncanniness for the divine.

If it is a feeling, writes Collingwood, and one which is a uni-

versal characteristic of religion, "it must be bound up with its

essential nature, and capable of being deduced from it"(SM, 119).

Holiness is to religion what beauty is to art. It is the


specific form in which truth appears to that type of con-
sciousness. As religion, therefore, is a dialectical de-
velopment of art, so holiness is a dialectical development
of beauty. Now religion is art asserting its object. The
object of art is the beautiful, and therefore the holy is
the beautiful asserted as real. . . . Further, holiness,
like beauty, polarizes itself into the positively holy
(God) and the negatively holy, that which we are forbidden
to find holy or worship, the devil and all his works. But
specifically, holiness is asserted as real, and therefore
God is regarded as not our own invention, not a fancy work
of art, but a reality, indeed the only and ultimate real-
ity. Hence that rapture and admiration which we enjoy in
the contemplation of a work of art is in the case of God
fused with the conviction that we here come face to face
with something other than ourselves and our imaginings,
something infinitely real, the ground
279

and source of our own being. It is this fusion which


constitutes the sense of holiness, and forms the basis and
motive of worship. Neither the real nor the beautiful is as
such the proper object of adoration: it is only the
aesthetic attitude towards ultimate reality, or conversely
the elevation of beauty into a metaphysical principle, that
constitutes worship. (SM, 119-20).

once again it is necessary to enter a caveat here against the

possible misinterpretation of Collingwood's intent. In analyzing

religion as a form of consciousness which intends an object that

is defined by holiness, and then by defining holiness in terms

of the object of artistic consciousness (the holy as the

"beautiful asserted as real"), Collingwood is not simply saying

that religion elevates an art object, asserts its reality, and

then falls down in worship of it. That he does not mean this is

clear from his comments about idolatry:

(T)he enemy of religion is idolatry, or the attempt to


worship an object which, however exquisite to the artist's
eye, cannot claim to be the ultimate reality. The sin of the
idolater is to worship his own works of art known to be
such. This is not true religion, because true religion
worships the real God, no mere figment of the
imagination . . . . (I)n religion the mind becomes aware
that it is in danger of illusion. God and religion are
correlative; and to doubt the reality of God is to deny the
validity and legitimacy of religion. There are no religions
without a god or gods: what have passed by that name have
been either philosophies, or religions whose gods have
escaped the eye of the observer, or a kind of mechanical
contrivance put on the market by a deluded or fraudulent
inventor. (SM, 119-20).
280

In defining religious consciousness as the artistic

object asserted as real, therefore, Collingwood is attempting to

characterize what is actually a unified whole by means of terms

drawn both (a) from a lower form of consciousness (art), which

forms one of religion's distinguishable (but not truly separate)

elements, and (b) from within that form of consciousness itself

(the assertion of God as ultimate reality). But the lower term,

in this case the artistic object, "the beautiful," is

transformed into something different--into "the holy" or

something deserving of worship. If "the beautiful" is taken

generically, then "the holy" is a specification of that genus in

such a way that the generic essence is modified by the specific

difference of religious consciousness to the extent that it

becomes identified with it: the genus, in short, is identified

with the variable--the beautiful is asserted as real.

Now we have just seen that a very similar state of af-

fairs appears to be the result of Collingwood's analysis of

scientific consciousness. The genus provided by religious

consciousness (creed: the assertion of the imagined object as

real) is modified by what is specific to scientific conscious-

ness (the principle of abstraction) to become not an object of

faith and worship but an object of scientific inquiry--the

conception of reality as particular instantiations of universal

laws. And we see again


281

from this analysis that the object of religion (God as ultimate

reality) is not taken over by scientific consciousness without

modification: laws of nature are not merely the worshipped God

reduced to the status of universals. The object of scientific

consciousness takes the generic essence of religious

consciousness as already abstract it takes up only the notion of

an imaginary object asserted as real and leaves aside the sacred

or holy aspect of the object of religious consciousness. It

becomes, in terms Collingwood does not employ, wholly profane

science.

We see therefore a very important exemplification of

what Collingwood's modification of the notion of identity was in

Speculum Mentis. The relationship between forms of knowledge is

as good an illustration as one can expect to find of what

Collingwood meant by a "developing series" in which each term is

a modification of the one before. It is also the basis upon

which he will construct his analysis of a "scale of forms" in

the Essay on Philosophical Method: "In a philosophical scale of

forms the variable is identical with the generic essence itself"

(EPM, 60). We do not have to proceed much further in our

retrogressive survey before discovering another anticipation of

a doctrine in the Essay on Philosophical Method: in a scale of

forms there is no zero end of the scale, the minimum realization

of the generic essence lying not at zero but at unity (EPM, 81).

In this case the minimum specification of


282

the genus, "object of knowledge," is the object of artistic

consciousness.

It is no accident that art occupies the primary position

in Collingwood's survey of the forms of experience because to be

an object of consciousness at all is to be entertained as an

object in imagination, without which even perception is

impossible (SM, 204-05; EPA, 57).

The first stage in this process ((viz. the life of spirit or


awareness or consciousness)) is the life of art, which is
the pure act of imagination. This is not only empirically
the first stage observable in children and primitive
peoples, it is necessarily the first stage. Awareness in
itself . . . is an act of consciousness which presents to
itself an object of whose relation to other objects it takes
no cognizance . . . . (I)n religion that indifference to the
distinction between real and unreal, which is the essence of
art, is abolished. Religion is essentially a quest after
truth and explicitly conscious of itself as such a quest.
(EPA, 141).

Once again it is necessary to enter a word of caution to

avoid a misunderstanding. Collingwood is not saying that art

first asserts, then withdraws the aspect of truth or falsehood,

or the reference to reality. Art is not asserting at all: its

"apparent assertions are not real assertions but the very

suspension of assertion"--and the non-assertive, nonlogical

attitude towards an object of consciousness, the indifference to

its reality or unreality, is imagination (SM, 60). That is why

art is prior to the other forms of consciousness, and even the

discussion of its essential nature as the activity of

imagination is not taking place


283

from within artistic consciousness itself, but is thought's way

of describing its most primitive function.

To imagine is to refrain from making a distinction which we


make whenever we think: the distinction between reality and
unreality, truth and falsehood. Therefore imagining is not a
kind of thinking, nor is thinking a kind of imagining, for
each negates the specific nature of the other . . . . Hence
the relation between imagination and thought is that thought
presupposes imagination, but imagination does not presuppose
thought . . . . As thinking presupposes imagining, all those
activities whose theoretical aspect takes the form of
thought presuppose art; and art is the basis of science,
history, "common sense," and so forth. Art is the primary
and fundamental activity of the mind . . . . It is not a
primitive form of religion or science of philosophy, it is
something more primitive than these, something that
underlies them and makes them possible. (EPA, 54-55).

But although artistic consciousness is the suspension of

assertion (and it will be recalled from Chapter V that the

suspension of assertion is one of the ways Collingwood defines a

question and an hypothesis), it is not simply the "blooming,

buzzing confusion" that William James ascribed to the world of

pure sensation. Artistic consciousness has at least the co-

herence necessary to hold its object together as a single en-

tity, and in so doing it makes a rudimentary distinction between

beauty and ugliness. It is this minimal activity that permits us

to call it consciousness or mental activity at all. Insofar as

imagination is a constructive activity (which ultimately issues

in the creation of works of art) it is a representative of

mental consciousness striving to see its world as a whole, the

whole in this case being the imagined object, the work of art

(SM, 63-65).
284

And even though art proclaims its refusal to be bound either by

any necessary relation to the world of reality, or by the

restrictive, rule-governed world of thought, it nonetheless

utilizes, at least implicitly the minimum realization of thought

in its application of the principle of beauty:

Now this process of imagining a whole, or creating a work of


art is . . . no mere rudderless drifting of images across
the mind; it is a process of unification in which the mind
strives to see its world as a whole, the "world" being just
the work of art which for the time being absorbs the whole
gaze of the mind . . . (T)he whole comes into imaginary
existence only in the critical process of experimenting with
its parts . . . . The law of this process, its guiding
principle, is beauty . . . . Now art as such has nothing to
do with principles or laws . . . . ((But)) beauty is not a
concept. It is the guise under which concepts in general
appear to the aesthetic consciousness. Beauty means
structure, organization, seen from the aesthetic point of
view, that is, imagined and not conceived. (SM, 65-66).13

The work of aesthetic consciousness, then, is the creation of

coherence in its minimal form. "When one imagines," writes

Collingwood, "one must imagine something; it must be a definite

and not a self-contradictory imagination, and hence the

necessary unity of the work of art" (SM, 70).

_____________________
13 Although the general sense of what Collingwood is
saying about beauty and art is clear, it is difficult to un-
derstand how beauty can be the "law of this process" of uni-
fication, "its guiding principle--and still not be a concept.
Perhaps Collingwood is trying to present it after the fashion of
Kant's a priori forms of intuition, space and time, which were
also not concepts. Collingwood's later esthetic drops the notion
of beauty altogether, while retaining the theory of imagination:
see PA, 37-41, 137, and 149.
285

We see in the experience of art what Collingwood takes

to be the minimum sense of unity--the identity of a coherent,

imagined object in terms of structure or organization, its

ability (from the point of view of consciousness) to be held

before the gaze of consciousness as an object to it. To para-

phrase Collingwood, to be one is minimally to be a coherent

object of imagination, without consideration of truth or fal-

sity, reality or unreality. But concern only for internal co-

herence is what is ultimately responsible for what Collingwood

calls the "monadism of art:"

Every aesthetic act is an individual internally organized by


the harmonious fitting-together of subordinate aesthetic
acts . . . . Works of art always ignore one another and
begin each from the beginning: they are windowless monads;
and this is because they are acts of imagination, from which
it necessarily follows that they are careless of mutual
consistency and interested only in their internal
coherence . . . . The work of art is a monad, and monadology
is the philosophy of art. (SM, 71-72).

Since art as imagination is necessarily the fundamental

form of consciousness, it is clear that we have reached the end

of the line in our retrogressive survey of the forms of

consciousness (at least those starting with science and its

subordinate forms) necessarily presupposes its predecessors;

each of the subordinate forms, that is, is a necessary, but not

a sufficient condition for its superordinate form, without which

it could not be what it is. And although Collingwood is not

altogether rigorous in exhibiting this dependence at all the

levels of description we found him giving of the forms of

consciousness(i.e. as intentional
286

structures, as objects of consciousness, as modes of expression,

and as faculties of mind),14 the main outlines of the

rapprochement identity, when approached retrogressively, are

clear--and its ideal limit is the minimal form of unity as the

coherent object of imagination.

5. Speculum Mentis: Progressive Identity.

When Collingwood begins the chapter on science in

Speculum Mentis he summarizes the failure of both art and re-

ligion to fulfill the promise that they hold out as being com-

plete and independent forms of consciousness. In so doing he

takes up not what they are in themselves

____________________
14 While it is relatively easy to find passages in
Speculum Mentis and elsewhere that illustrate the retrogres-
sively necessary relationship of forms of consciousness, the
basis for this relationship is given in terms of intentional
structures (the way that consciousness intends its objects),
faculties (imagination, understanding, faith, reason), and ty-
pical modes of expression (hypothesis, assertion, etc.), but not
always in terms of their objects. When religious consciousness
transforms "the beautiful" into "the holy" the transition
between objects, while highly abstract, is fairly explicit. But
when science takes up its object one might expect that "the
holy" would now become "the true" or "the abstract universal" or
some such entity. But Collingwood does not carry forward the
analogy, perhaps because "the truth" is what is intended by all
forms of thought as such, from science on up; or perhaps, again,
because thought self-conscious of itself as such is best dealt
with in its expressive mode in linguistic forms. But from the
point of view of Speculum Mentis, Collingwood clearly felt that
the different descriptive terms we have distinguished were just
different ways of characterizing the same entities--art,
science, religion, etc.
287

(forms of consciousness or intentional structures), nor what

they intend as ideal objects, nor as faculties of mind, but the

way they manifest themselves--art as imaginative expression, and

religion as credal assertion. It is in this form that they most

clearly show their failure to achieve fully satisfying results.

Art and religion, to the superficial observer, are forms not


of thought but of language. Art . . . is simply language
itself, language in its pure form apart from any meaning . .
. . Art is not pure language, but thought failing to
recognize that it is thought, mistaking itself for
imagination. Religion is . . . a dialectical development of
art, art realizing that it is not bare imagination but
assertion, and then proceeding to misinterpret its own as-
sertions and to suppose itself to be asserting the image or
word when it is really asserting the meaning of the word. In
a special sense both art and religion are thus linguistic
functions, forms of expression rather than forms of thought.
(SM, 154).

But if art and religion are both "phases in the history of a

mind, preceding its attainment of complete mastery over the

means of expression," science represents thought's completion of

this development in the recognition that language is the servant

of thought rather than either the whole of thought (as art

assumes) or thought's master (as religion assumes) (SM, 155).

Scientific consciousness explicitly distinguishes between

metaphorical and literal meaning, and hence between thought and

language (SM, 157). It does so by the assertion of the abstract

concept, as we have already seen, and the historical locus of

this event was in the world of post-Homeric Greece, where

scientific
288

concepts appeared first in the guise of depersonalized gods (SM,

158, 160-61). Whereas (a) art fails completely to recognize the

claim of thought on its conscious activity, being totally

absorbed in the technique of expression, and (b) religion only

minimally recognizes the claim of thought but misinterprets it

by identifying thought with its own expression, language with

reality, (c) science represents thought fully conscious of

itself as thought, thought expressed rather than concealed (SM,

154-55).

From the point of view of the modes of expression of the

forms of consciousness, then, each is an incomplete fulfillment

of what thought is trying to achieve: each only partially

conceives of an object which will fully satisfy its (the mind's)

requirements. But when taken as ultimate and independent

statements about what consciousness is, and what the

relationship of consciousness is to its object, they are not

only incomplete they are errors--mistakes that consciousness

makes about itself and about its object. When made explicit by

the labors of thought, these errors appear not as inadequacies

of modes of expression but as actual contradictions within that

mode. Thus art appears to non-assertively assert, religion to

not mean what it says it means, and science appears to

non-referentially refer (SM, 242-43; cf. SM, 311).


289

Now if one were of a formalistic cast of mind, which

Collingwood clearly was not, one might easily demonstrate that

from contradictory statements everything follows of necessity

(because anything, including further contradictory statements,

can be derived from any rule which allows contradictories to

stand as simultaneously true). Therefore when any form of

knowledge is shown to rest on a presupposition (when what it

implicitly presumes is made explicit) that is inherently false,

or self-contradictory, it would automatically rule out the

possibility that any other form of self-consistent knowledge

could proceed from it--and certainly not of necessity. Therefore

from the collapse of one form of knowledge by self-contradiction

no other form of knowledge can follow of necessity, and the

progressive dialectical process, as we anticipated, would show

no necessity: the relation of succession is not one of necessity

but of contingency.

But this is not Collingwood's route. We saw in a pre-

vious chapter (Chapter IV) that Collingwood's commitment to an

anti-realist position concerning the relation of knower and

known necessitated the conclusion that any such error that

consciousness makes about its object recoils on itself, altering

the nature of conscious activity itself (SM, 241). When a form

of consciousness is shown to express itself in an inconsistent

manner, like the rift in the sail of a schooner, it need not

abandon ship,
290

because it has a greater resiliency than strict logic might

allow. It can repair its own damages by transforming itself into

something that at first sight it was not--spontaneous and

reflective thought. Therefore imaginative consciousness (art)

can recognize that it is not utterly free of the imposition of

thought, since it presumes a guiding principle of selectivity

(the idea of relevance) in the construction of a coherent work

of art (SM, 97). The consciousness of this controlling element

in artistic creation is the birthplace of art criticism, and of

esthetic philosophy (SM, 98-100). The distinction that is

introduced is one of form and content, of the manner in which

meaning in art is expressed as opposed to what is being

expressed by that form (SM, 96). This distinction is the

beginning of scientific consciousness,15 and recognizing the

danger that artistic consciousness may at this point cease to be

itself and become science, esthetic philosophy--thought

conscious of itself as art--resists the absorption of its

primary form (artistic experience) by attacking science, perhaps

in the form of an intuitionism that is read back into science as

its (science's) essential nature (SM, 262). Esthetic philosophy

"reduces all philosophical problems to terms of imagination or

intuition," which describe the world as one of pure change, a

monadic world in which every event is new in the sense of

irrelevant to what went before (ibid.).

_______________________
15 Notice that Collingwood here at least implicitly ac-
knowledges that it is possible to pass directly from art to
science--but only through the intermediary of some sort of ex-
plicit thought process, such as art criticism.
291

The same dogmatic service of thought can be performed

for the other forms of experience, and it is this polymorphous

perversity (Collingwood of course does not use this phrase, apt

as he may have found it) that prevents the phases of the

dialectical series of forms of knowledge from becoming neces-

sarily successive. Once a form of consciousness has at its

disposal a battery of modes of expression (questions, asser-

tions, supposals, etc.) provided by the capacities of thought,

it can respond to the threat of destruction of itself by its own

inner dialectic (self contradiction) either by becoming

explicitly what it was only implicitly (rational thought, for

example, instead of pure imagination; assertion instead of mere

questioning) or by transforming itself into another form

altogether (transforming the object of art into the object of

religion, for example). Art can defend itself by becoming

art-criticism or esthetic philosophy or it can allow itself to

be absorbed by religion, science, or history as one of its

essential constituents. Religion can develop a dogmatic defense

as theology, science can develop a dogmatic defense as

metaphysics and logic, and history (peculiarly enough, as we

noted earlier) can develop a dogmatic philosophy in the form of


292

realism; or each could be transformed in its successor (SM,

260-87).16

We have at this point shown, therefore, how Collingwood,

true to his epistemological assumptions,has maintained the

contingency of the forward motion of his process of re-

conciliation between the forms of knowledge. Progressive

rapprochement identity (according to the position proclaimed in

Speculum Mentis, at least) consists in the unifying activity of

a form of consciousness, deliberately attempting to preserve its

integrity by overcoming errors which become manifest when its

implicit assumptions are explicitly expressed. Since it can

overcome error in a variety of ways, and with differing degrees

of success, the possible modes of succession of thought forms

are not fixed, and contingency in the progressive direction is

preserved. The ideal limit to the process of overcoming

expressed errors is total self-consistency, or absolute

knowledge. Such a knowledge would not only grasp its intentional

object in a non-misleading way, but would also account for the

errors that it has made in achieving this totally adequate

knowledge. Therefore it cannot intend an object that is utterly

one, a bare blank identity (the abstract Absolute), but a

unity-in-diversity, one for which differences are essential, a

"concrete universal." But a concrete universal as an

__________________
16 Although strictly speaking, tertium non datur, I see
no reason why Collingwood would object to the suggestion that a
form of experience could simply remain what it is, ignoring the
contradiction within itself.
293

absolute object would have to be an infinite whole of fact, and

a whole in which subject and object are not conceived as

separate, but identified. Ideal maximal progressive rapprochement

identity, therefore, is one of complete identity of subject and

object.17

Since there is a whole battery of problems that arise in

connection with Collingwood's concluding chapters of Speculum

Mentis, especially concerning this progressive rapprochement

identity in the form of "absolute knowledge," we propose to deal

with these problems as a series of disputed questions with which

we will close this chapter.

6. Disputed Questions.

(1) Why do forms of consciousness succeed one another?

Collingwood's descriptive phenomenology does not set out to

answer this question, but it certainly does "arise"--even on his

own sense of that term. If there is no necessity (meaning

logical compulsion) in the forward direction in a scale of forms

of knowledge, then it would seem not merely contingent that they

succeed one another but utterly accidental, even gratuitous or

miraculous. Is the reader to assume a "nisus" or innate striving

toward greater adequacy of thought? Does thought have

_______________________
17 Sources for the statements in this paragraph (the
argument is nowhere, of course, stated as such by Collingwood)
include: SM, 238-41, 288-97. More detailed, explicit references
will be given in section 6, question 2.
294

an inborn natural tendency to supersede or overreach or

transcend itself and thus create different forms of itself? Is

the logical requirement of self-consistency a motive force at

all levels of consciousness?

In his "Outlines of a Philosophy of Art" (published one

year after Speculum Mentis) Collingwood actually does posit a

"nisus towards self-consciousness" at all levels of con-

sciousness (EPA, 144), but in Speculum Mentis he does not give a

consistent answer to this question. On the one hand, in the

introductory and less precise passages of the book, Collingwood

seems to lean towards the "nisus" thesis, if we may so call it,

insofar as he assumes that the disease of modern man is

self-alienation, the separation of the forms of experience one

from another, and the cure for this disease to be their "reunion

in a complete and undivided life" (SM, 36). But on the other

hand, Collingwood denies that there is anything like a fixed

"human nature" (SM, 296)--a denial he defended throughout his

lifetime, and against which he threw all the weight of his

reflections on the nature of history as a "self-making ac-

tivity." But if there is no such thing as a fixed human nature,

not even in the minimal sense of the term, then it is hard to

account for any tendency for consciousness to become altered at

all. In fact it seems utterly groundless to assert that

consciousness would seek to grasp a fully satisfactory object

unless there are fundamental and irreducible


295

characteristics of consciousness as an activity, and what could

this be but a minimally essential human nature?

Collingwood does not acknowledge the problem at all in

Speculum Mentis, the assumptions upon which it builds its argu-

ment being (1) that knowledge and consciousness exist (but in a

divided state), and (2) that these mental activities claim fully

satisfactory ideal objects (cf. SM, 39). It is not until he

attempted a more complete analysis of mental activity in The

Principles of Art and The New Leviathan that the

emotive-expressive aspects of mental activity was fully inte-

grated into his philosophy of mind.

(2) Even assuming that, for whatever reason, the forms

of consciousness do succeed one another in a scale of developing

forms, and in much the way Collingwood describes them, is there

any end-point to the series? We have seen in our retrogressive

survey of the forms of consciousness that there is a terminal

point at the "lower" end inasmuch as the consideration by

consciousness of a whole object, its mere entertainment by

imagination, is the minimal sense in which intentionality can

grasp its object at all. But we have also seen that the

imaginary object is intended without consideration of its

reality or unreality (i.e. without reference), and that this is

the root sense of abstraction, insofar as the act which grasps

an imaginary object does so by ignoring (Collingwood will later

say by "suppressing") its relations to any and all


296

other objects. And abstraction, as the negative side of in-

tentionality, is also the act by which consciousness cuts itself

loose from its object, or sets the object apart as "separate"

from itself. But this is the primitive act of separation of

subject and object, the root error of realism.

From this analysis it is not surprising that the repair

to the torn fabric of consciousness will be the reunification of

subject and object by an act that is the very opposite of

abstraction--viz. reconciliation. This in fact is Collingwood's

strategy in Speculum Mentis: the termination of the scale of

forms is philosophy (which succeeds history), and whereas

history achieves concrete knowledge (and therefore rectifies

implicitly the abstractness of science), philosophy achieves

absolute knowledge (and therefore overcomes the last vestige of

abstraction in the form of history's separation of subject and

object--the historian contemplating a world of facts, and not

fully aware that he is more than merely an observer of those

facts) (SM, 238-39; cf. SM, 242-43, 311, and EPA, 143-44).

We shall see in a moment what the subject matter of this

absolute knowledge is, and how it leads to further difficulties

unresolved in Speculum Mentis. For now it is sufficient to

notice that the argument that


297

Collingwood provides for us as a justification for the

transition from history to philosophy does not appear to leave

us with any alternative, and thus threatens the contingency of

the forward dialectic. He not only argues (a) that if the

distinction or separation between subject and object is invalid,

then the last veil hung between the mind and its object falls,

revealing (not Salome but) the mind itself in mirror

reflection--the "speculum mentis" of his title; but also (b)

that on either of two mutually exclusive alternatives, the

result (the identity of subject and object) follows:

If subject and object are opposite, then they can only


exist in synthesis: well and good. But if they are distinct
concrete facts, they both fall within the world of fact,
and of this world it remains true that everything in it
determines the whole and everything else, it follows that
subject and object are just as inseparable on this
hypothesis as on the other. For the concept of the world of
fact as the concrete universal has destroyed any dis-
tinction between a logic of opposition and a logic of dif-
ference.18 The fundamental principle of history itself,
namely, the concreteness of the object, thus makes it im-
possible for the object to ignore the subject, and compels
us to recognize an object to which the subject is organic,
in the sense that the subject's consciousness of it makes a
real difference to it as a whole and to all its parts . . .
. Being known, whether truly known or erroneously known,
must make a difference to the object: to deny this . . . is
to turn one's back on concrete thought and revert to the
fallacies of abstraction. (SM, 244; emphasis mine).

With this passage it appears that the veil is not so much


dropped as torn

___________________
18 Collingwood here anticipates another doctrine of the
Essay on Philosophical Method: "the kind of opposition which is
found among philosophical terms is at once opposition and
distinction" (EPM, 75).
298

down, revealing not only the mirror of the mind but

Collingwood's own presuppositions, and it becomes clear that the

position he is advocating is naked epistemological idealism

(albeit of an unusual variety). The suspicion (if one still

needs convincing) is further confirmed in a later passage in a

section dealing with the historical form of dogmatism, in which

Collingwood praises German idealism for killing "scientific

realism--the popular philosophy of today-as dead as a door nail"

(SM, 287).

But the admission also threatens Collingwood's entire

philosophical enterprise in Speculum Mentis. For if the forward

movement of the dialectic of experience is not propelled by

necessity, then the final transition, even more so than all the

intermediate ones, seems hypothetical at best and arbitrary at

worst. But the above passage, as the underlined words show,

seems to contradict the thesis that the dialectical progression

is not one of logical necessity.l9 The reader is shot as from

_________________________
19 Cf. SM, 292-93: "Not that such creation of an ex-
ternal world is capricious. The mind cannot simply think what-
ever it pleases, or even imagine whatever it pleases. It is
bound by the laws of its own nature to this extent, that even
though it can deform its nature by misconceiving it, it can
never deform it out of recognition, because misconceiving is
after all a kind of conceiving. Its scientific concepts, its
religious imagery, its aesthetic imaginings must grow out of the
soil of fact, and that fact is just its own nature as that
stands for the time being. This necessity of all its actions,
ignored in the life of imagination, is though ignored not done
away. It is transformed, by being ignored, from a rational ne-
cessity to the blind necessity of instinct . . . . The discovery
of necessity . . . is the achievement of the religious con-
sciousness; but this necessity is there from the first."
299

an historical cannon into the realm of idealistic philosophy.

We shall see in the next question that Collingwood's

attempts to escape from the consequences of his own argument by

denying that his position commits him to a metaphysical form of

idealism are not convincing enough, as they stand, to exonerate

his "absolute knowledge" from self-contradiction, and

consequently from the necessity of positing even a further form

of consciousness to repair the damage.

(3) Does philosophy have an object? The reader of

Speculum Mentis is well aware that Collingwood wants philosophy

to be a form of knowledge that (a) is self-consistent, (b) is

self-consciously reflective, and (c) achieves the object of

self-knowledge in a manner that escapes, or overcomes, the

errors of subordinate states of consciousness (SM, 45-46,

247-49). We have just seen that Collingwood hopes to fulfill

these conditions in the guise of absolute knowledge. By as-

serting that the differentia of absolute knowledge is the

identity of subject and object (SM, 249), Collingwood argues

that he has found a kind of knowledge that fulfills all the

requisite conditions. (a) If it is identical with its object,

there is no "externality of the object," and therefore no place

for necessary inconsistency to conceal itself. And (b) so also

it is not knowledge of an object that is other than itself, but

is rather that
300

object knowing itself. But (c) the problem of inconsistency

arises once again the instant one attempts to see how such a

knowledge achieves its object in a manner that escapes error.20

The reason for this is that the instant one attempts to

import any content into the abstract formula "the identity of

subject and object" the air becomes murky with the gaseous

remains of previous errors. The object of philosophy, he says,

is not that of art, religion, science or history because each of

these forms of knowledge intend an object that is assumed in

some sense to be independent of the subject (SM, 30609). Yet

what the philosophical form of consciousness reflects on is

nothing other than the succession of worlds created by art,

religion, etc.

In an immediate and direct way the mind can never know


itself: it can only know itself through the mediation of an
external world, know that what it sees in the external world
is its own reflection. Hence the construction of external
worlds . . . is the only way by which the mind can possibly
come to that self-knowledge which is its end. (SM, 315).

Absolute knowledge, therefore, consists in nothing more than a

survey of the succession of errors by subordinate states,

recognized as such by

____________________
20 In fairness to Collingwood it should be pointed out
that he says that absolute knowledge is not secure from error,
but rather it is called absolute because "in it there is no
element of necessary and insurmountable error" (SM, 295).
301

a form of consciousness that takes its object to be nothing

other than itself. But each of these subordinate forms of

consciousness when recognized as illusory (erroneous portrayals

of an object separate from the mind which contemplates it) are

absorbed into philosophy: there is no "map of knowledge" because

"there are no autonomous and mutually exclusive forms of

experience" (SM, 306). Philosophy is therefore the consciousness

of something which is also the consciousness of nothing.

The same conclusion follows if one proceeds in another

direction--from a description of absolute mind. Here Colling-

wood's rejection of all possible content is even more sweeping.

He says that whether the life of the spirit be described by a

group of categories, a group of laws, a group of presupposi-

tions, a world of objects, or a series of stages, it is an

erroneous description of absolute knowledge because the de-

scriptive terms are "versions of a single error: the error of

abstraction, of failing to realize that subject and object,

condition and conditioned, ground and consequence, particular

and universal can only be distinctions which fall within one and

the same whole, and that this whole can only be the infinite

fact which is the absolute mind" (SM, 310). But the recognition

of this "infinite fact" is an act which "abolishes the notion of

an external world other than the mind" (SM, 310). But then it

would seem that the infinite world of fact is abolished with the
302

external world, the baby discarded with the bath water, and

absolute knowledge is left with nothing to contemplate.

Collingwood's attempts to evade the contradictory as-

pects of the concept only tend to add to one's puzzlement. For

example he says that the abolition of an external world other

than mind does not imply the abolition of the distinction

between suject and object:

These distinctions are only abolished by the coincidentia


oppositorum which is the suicide of abstract thought, and
conserved by the synthesis of opposites which is the life
of concrete thought . . . . But in abolishing the notion of
an external world other than the mind we do not assert any
of the silly nonsense usually described by unintelligent
critics as idealism. We do not assert that the trees and
hills and people of our world are "unreal" or "mere ideas
in my mind," still less that matter is nothing but a swarm
of mind-particles. The very essence of trees and hills and
people is that they should be not myself but my objects in
perception: they are not subjective but objective, not
states of myself but facts that I know. None the less, my
knowing them is organic to them . . . . They and I alike
are members of one whole, a whole which the destruction of
one part would in a sense destroy throughout . . . . (SM,
310-11).

But then what is this "whole" in which "subject and object are

identified" and which nevertheless is one for which externality

is an illusion; which is an "infinite world of fact" and yet not

"one stupendous whole" (SM, 299)? How does a synthesis of

opposites differ from a coincidence of opposites, unless the

identity that is that synthesis is identifiable, describable,

recognizable? If absolute knowledge is self-knowledge, and if


303

in it subject and object are identified, and if self-knowledge

is only possible through the intermediation of subordinate

forms, then how is it possible for objects of consciousness not

to be "mere ideas in my mind"? Is it any wonder then that in the

"progressive reduction of art, religion, science and history to

philosophy" not only is it the case that "each one of these

lives disappears; but philosophy itself disappears as completely

as any" (SM, 293), leaving not so much as the smile of the

Cheshire cat?

Now one might grant that what Collingwood is dealing

with in these enigmatic passages is a mystery surpassing un-

derstanding, the mystery of self-consciousness and its existence

in a world that appears external to the mind which nonetheless

knows it. One might grant that in grappling with such a mystery

one cannot help but lapse into forms of speech that are

contradictory, the sort of language familiar to mystics and

spiritualists. One might be so lenient with him, were it not for

the fact that Collingwood himself is claiming consistency for

what he is saying, that he uses logical criteria for deciding if

the claims of consciousness can live up to their expressed

performance, and that what he has led the reader of Speculum

Mentis to expect is a coherent account of what it means to be a

fully adequate form of knowledge.


304

Therefore we cannot rest content with accepting this

state of affairs as a fitting conclusion to his search for

rapprochement. We have the right to demand that if a "higher"

form of consciousness is itself inconsistent on logical grounds,

if it cannot live up in its performance to what it had promised,

we must either (a) declare it to be an exception to the rule of

consistency, or (b) posit an even higher state of reflective

consciousness to further repair the damages. But it is easy to

see that so long as a state of consciousness is distinct from

its object, alternative (b) leads to an infinite regress, and

therefore the goal of Speculum Mentis (and progressive

rapprochement) will be forever frustrated, because

self-knowledge will never be possible: it involves a

contradiction in terms. And the first solution (a) acknowledges

that the criteria of consistency (a supposedly higher form of

consciousness--absolute knowledge) be affirmed as itself

inconsistent. But then why not absolve any of the lower forms

from an equivalent necessity to be self-consistent? Why not stop

the series with history, for example? What need is there for

philosophy?

As we shall see in a future chapter, Collingwood's so-

lution was to opt for alternative (a), which is what we might

expect for someone who felt himself to be committed to the So-

cratic view of philosophy as self-knowledge. But in taking this

route Collingwood provided philosophy


305

with one of those rare occurrences--a bonafide metaphysical

paradigm. If the criteria of consistency is itself inconsistent

it may be so either by (1) asserting something to be both true

and false at the same time and in the same manner, or (2) by

asserting something that is neither true nor false. In the Essay

on Metaphysics Collingwood took the latter option, and spelled

out the consequences of this doctrine as a theory of "absolute

presuppositions" which are the basis for truth and falsity

without being themselves true or false (EM, 21-33).

(4) If absolute knowledge collapses for want of a co-

herent object, how are the various forms of consciousness de-

scribed in Speculum Mentis reconciled to one another? Or does

Collingwood's early rapprochement philosophy end in complete

disaster? Is retrogressive identity the only acceptable basis

for rapprochement?

We have had occasion in previous chapters, and this

chapter is an extension of these reflections, to remark on the

peculiar usage that Collingwood has for terms that appear as key

words in all of the contradictory texts cited above-"other

than . . . , separate from . . . , identical with . . . , the

same as . . . ," etc. These terms, and the understanding of them

in context, count greatly toward contributing to the sense or

nonsense of what Collingwood is trying to say in these highly

elliptical and abstract passages. It is also


306

crucial for an understanding of rapprochement philosophy, since

the entire effort of reconciliation is to show that the

reconciliate are not "other than" or "separate from" each other,

but are rather "identical" or "the same as" each other as parts

of a "concrete whole."

Now we recall from section 2 of this chapter that in

Religion and Philosophy four sorts of identity can be dis-

tinguished--abstract, dialectical, concrete, and absolute. The

first two were bound, we noted, by relations of necessity, the

latter two by relations of contingency. We also noted that each

had a corresponding sense of "separate." If we come fresh from

this discussion to the present problem in Speculum Mentis, we

notice several interesting shifts in meaning, and as usual with

Collingwood, a small investment of careful attention to these

shifts yields dividends for the interpretative speculator.

If we return, for example, to the transition from his-

tory to philosophy we notice that the object of history is taken

to be the "concrete universal" and that this "infinite whole of

fact" is taken to be an object that ostensibly satisfies the

mind:

There is thus no feature of experience, no attitude of mind


towards its object, which is alien to history. Art rests on
the ignoring of reality: religion, on the ignoring of
thought: science, on the ignoring of fact; but with the
recognition of fact everything is
307

recognized that is in any sense real. The fact, as


historically determined, is the absolute object. The mark of
the absolute object is individuality, for individuality is
concreteness. The object as individual is the whole of what
exists, and this is concretely articulated into parts each
of which is again individual, and so to infinity . . . . The
object as a system of fact so organized, is objective
throughout, for every part is a true microcosm, and is truly
infinite . . . . This absolute whole is the concrete
universal . . . . It is the system of systems, the world of
worlds . . . The principle of its structure is not
classification, the abstract concept, but the concrete
concept, which is relevance, or implication . . . and the
logic of history is the logic of the concrete universal.
(SM, 218-21).

Aside from the fact that it is hard to see why an absolute mind

knowing such an object would not be "one stupendous whole" (SM,

299) if its object is a "system of systems" and a "world of

worlds," we notice an additional peculiarity in this passage.

The description of the concrete universal corresponds fairly

closely to the description of both dialectical and concrete

identities as we discovered them in Religion and Philosophy. (1)

The relations and relate are connected not as abstract

particulars subsumed under an equally abstract genus, but as

parts of a whole such that the parts reflect the whole and the

whole reflects the parts--therefore a dialectical identity. But

(2) they are also described as concrete in the sense of

individual--and thus (like the identity of cooperation between

minds in Religion and Philosophy, wherein the two minds share

that unity between them which is taken to be the mark of the

individual, and therefore become one mind) a concrete identity.

If Collingwood is truly pressing these two sorts of identity

into doing
308

service in the single notion of the concrete universal, then it

is not surprising that we should find in it relations of both

necessity and contingency, since dialectical identity involved

relations of necessity, and concrete identity involved relations

of contingency. In the concept of the concrete universal, then,

we have an attempt to express the overlapping of two senses of

identity; it is therefore an instance of what Collingwood will

later call the "overlap of classes" in his Essay on

Philosophical Method (EPM, 26-53). Which brings us to our next

question.

(5) Is there any way that absolute identity as the ideal

for progressive reconciliation can be made intelligible?

Unfortunately the suggestion from the last paragraph, i.e. that

the concrete universal as an overlap-concept might be expanded

to become the absolute object, runs headlong into the

subject-object contradictions we have been at pains to concile.

On the one hand the concrete universal turns out to be the

absolute object, thus accounting for the fact that the identity

of history and philosophy, while a "barren abstraction" like all

such identifications, is less misleading than the others (SM,

246). On the other hand the object of history fails to be the

object of philosophy, because the historical consciousness fails

to be fully aware of the identity of subject and object. History

as a separate form of
309

consciousness fails to apprehend the concrete universal (an in-

finite whole of fact) because of a remnant of the original sin

of the mind--the abstract separation of subject and object (SM,

237-38); the historian simply cannot grasp an "infinite given

whole of fact," and therefore in confronting the the panorama of

history and the virtual infinite of historical evidence the

historian must select his materials, arrange them into periods,

etc.--all acts of abstraction.21

It is at this point that Collingwood introduces his

hypothetical identity of subject and object by an act of ab-

solute consciousness: "If therefore the infinite given whole of

fact is the nature of the knowing mind as such, our problem is

solved, and the possibility of knowledge is vindicated" (SM,

241). Once again we are brought to the brink of complete

disaster for Collingwood's voyaging vessel of consciousness: the

fabric of his mainsail is, as we have seen, ripped from top to

bottom by inner contradiction.

In Religion and Philosophy, at least, he left an escape

route open in the form of the Absolute Mind as God, with whom

men may contingently be

____________________
21 Collingwood's description of historical abstractness
is almost Heideggerian: "History, which seems to be essentially
remembrance, is only possible through forgetfulness, a
forgetfulness which in destroying what it takes away makes it
impossible for us ever to understand what is left" (SM, 236).
310

united through identity of purpose with Jesus Christ. In

Speculum Mentis this door also seems to be shut, both by his

explicit assertion that the absolute mind is the mind of

individuals and not that of some "world spirit" which he rejects

as a "myth" (SM, 298-99), and his affirmation that the absolute

mind is the mind of each of us (SM, 298).22

Fortunately, there is more than one way to reach ab-

solute knowledge, and while we have been preoccupied with a

discussion of consciousness and its objects, we have lost sight

temporarily of another approach to the subject—one which

Collingwood himself, in his haste to

_____________________
22 Once again, in fairness to Collingwood it must be
said that in this passage he says that "the mind of which we are
speaking . . . must at least be the mind of each of us . . . ."
(SM, 298), thus leaving the way open for the insertion of a
higher mind which does not share the inherent failing of human
nature. But in a passage where the life of absolute mind is
described by means of the religious metaphor of the fall and
redemption of man, he seems to reject this possibility. The
metaphor likens the fall of man to the loss of absolute
knowledge through an act which forever separates subject and
object, and redemption to the regaining of this knowledge
through an act of divine transcendence--the incarnation. In his
fallen state man fails to achieve self-knowledge: "not knowing
himself as he ought to be, he cannot know himself as he actually
is. His error is implicit just because it is complete" (SM,
269). However Collingwood criticizes the metaphor as having one
flaw: the "transcendence of God." He has also asserted that "no
one can worship the absolute" (SM, 151), and furthermore that
the point of entry of God into a philosophical system marks
unerringly the point at which it breaks down (SM, 269). Finally,
the reader might also recall that Collingwood maintains that
there is no fixed human nature, so that the imagery of the fall
is further flawed insofar as it is inapplicable to man.
311

reach the absolute standpoint, may have overlooked. We noted

above (section 4) that in the beginning of the chapter on

science Collingwood called art and religion "forms not of

thought but of language (SM, 154). We have also seen him carry

out his analysis of the explication of implicit errors of

successive forms of consciousness in terms of their linguistic

forms--expression (art), assertion (religion), etc. Even his

discussion of knowledge as question and answer tends to focus on

the language of conditionals, hypotheticals, assertions, and

implications. In this discussion Collingwood drops an intriguing

hint which is later picked up in his discussion of the nature of

philosophical thinking. Discussing symbol and meaning in his

chapter on religion, Collingwood writes:

To distinguish a symbol from its meaning is to put oneself


in the way of explaining or translating the symbol. Now it
is a matter of common observation that religion never
explains itself . . . . To ask for explanations is the mark
of extreme sophistication; in other words, it is the mark of
the life of explicit thought . . . . Art is untranslatable,
religion cannot translate itself. Art cannot be translated
because it has no meaning except the wholly implicit meaning
submerged, in the form of beauty, in the flood of imagery.
Religion cannot translate itself not because it has no
meaning . . . but because, although it has a meaning and
knows it has a meaning, it thinks it has expressed this
meaning already. And so it has, but only metaphorically; and
this metaphorical self-expression, this fusion of symbol and
meaning, requires translation . . . . For literal language
is only language recognizedly metaphorical . . . .(SM,
128-30).

We have seen that in his apology in Speculum Mentis for

the sins of Religion and Philosophy, Collingwood pointed to the

failure to
312

recognize the distinction between symbol and meaning in religion

as his major oversight in that earlier work (SM, 108, n. 1). And

we also noted that when he originally published Religion and

Philosophy he deliberately declined to deal with the issue of

religious language (RP, xvi). And we have seen that in Speculum

Mentis the distinction appears as the singular way that the

error implicit in religion is made explicit--religion "asserts

the reality of what is only a symbol and thereby treats a symbol

as though it were a concept" (SM, 153). The same might be shown

for all the other forms of consciousness: each manifests its la-

tent error in the form of inadequate or self-contradictory

expressions. Not only religion requires translation, it seems,

but all the forms of consciousness: when science, for example,

achieves explicit thought, it does so by means of its ability to

express meaning in several ways, by means of overlapping

metaphors in the form of alternative hypotheses and equivalent

mathematical expressions, thus overcoming the fixed formulas of

religious dogma (cf. SM, 155-57).

In the chapter on philosophy this line of thought is

picked up again, and provides us with a possible key to un-

scramble many of the paradoxes of absolute thought:

We have hitherto allowed ourselves to say that in art,


religion, and so forth the substance of truth was present,
but was concealed in an inadequate form: that, for instance,
religion actually solved the
313

riddle of life but presented its solution in a mythological


form. This implies that the task of philosophy, regarded as
the philosophy of religion, is the simple translation of
this solution of the riddle of life out of the language of
mythology into that of philosophy . . . . Translation itself
is based on the fact that the meaning takes new colour and
shines with a new light when we express it in different
words. To set the meaning as an abstract self-identity over
against the language makes translation pointless: to swamp
it in a mere immediate union with the language itself makes
translation impossible . . . . (T)hought in its concrete
form is not indifferent to its own choice of language. It
realizes that an unsuitable linguistic form affects its own
inmost being, and that what we have called merely formal
error is in reality material and essential error. Our
distinction between formal error and material error was, in
fact, only an abstract way of stating the very important
fact that no error is wholly erroneous, but is always
capable of a dialectical development into truth by simply
bringing to light what is already implicit in it: what the
thinker, as we paradoxically say, "really means," but "does
not know that he means." This process of translation into
progressively adequate language is simply the dialectical
self-criticism of thought. (SM, 252-53).

I have quoted this passage at length because it is so

important, so capable of being overlooked,23 and so pregnant

with possibilities. For (1) if philosophy is the process of

making explicit what is implicit in other modes of thought, and

(2) if the implicit errors of these modes of consciousness are

only made explicit when expressed or translated into language,

and (3) if the dialectical development of error into truth is a

___________________
23 Collingwood himself seems to have overlooked its
significance, both in the conclusion of Speculum Mentis, where
the suggestion is not followed up, and later in The Principles
of Art, where the significance of language for thought and the
role of philosophy as translation appear as discoveries, rather
than as a development of a line of thought already initiated ten
years earlier. Cf. PA, Chapter XI, pp. 225-69.
314

process of translation into progressively more adequate language

(the dialectical self-criticism of thought), then it is clear

that (4) absolute knowledge in the form of philosophy is the

translation, by dialectical self-criticism, of expressions of

subordinate forms of consciousness, into increasingly more

adequate language. One is tempted to say (as Collingwood does

not) that the object of philosophy is expressed in absolute

language--i.e. language purged not of all error but only of its

element of necessary and insurmountable error.

What such a language would be like is a matter for

speculation, although Collingwood's later writings provide us

with a few clues. It would have a peculiar grammar and the Essay

on Philosophical Method and the methodological chapters of the

Essay on Metaphysics are attempts to provide us with an informal

account of what that grammar is like. It will deal with problems

of the sort provided by art, by science, and by history, and The

Principles of Art, The Idea of Nature, and The Idea of History

are examples of what it would sound like when these problems are

translated by philosophical consciousness into a more adequate

language. And it would attempt to formulate an idea of what an

object would be like that would totally satisfy the mind, and

these reflections are presented in the Essay on

Metaphysics--Collingwood's last word on the religious

foundations of contemporary thought.


315

But aside from what an absolute language would be like,

it is clear that the conception outlined in the quotation above

has the potentiality for clarifying some, if not all, of the

difficulties we found with the notion of absolute knowledge. (1)

If the differentia of philosophy is taken to be the

identification of subject and object, the difficulties with this

conception arise when it is described in terms of consciousness

and its object--the stumbling block always being

self-consciousness. But if absolute knowledge or philosophy is

described not in terms of consciousness but of language, then

this particular difficulty disappears: language is quite capable

of being self-referential, of discussing and describing itself,

and of introducing modifications to overcome errors in the

expression of its more primary forms (e.g. "natural languages").

Not only are subject and object identified insofar as both are

embraced within the same whole--a world of language in which

pronouns, reflexive forms, and self-referential assertions are

all possible; but the subject is also both a receiver of meaning

and a creator of meaning in this world. Therefore a change in

one part (e.g. the creation of a new meaning--a poetic metaphor,

a new scientific hypothesis) necessitates a change in the whole

(the interconnected world of meaning) and in all the other parts

(related meanings). Since the subject here is a user of lang-

uage, he is identified with


316

objects not immediately (he does not actually "become" the

object) but through the mediation of subordinate expressive

acts--through the unreflective use of the language of art,

religion, science, and history. He becomes one with his object

not actually but virtually, symbolically, by an identity of

meaning.

(2) As a world of language the "concrete universal" (as

expressed judgment) could understandably be a "world of worlds"

and a "system of systems." As an expressive form characteristic

of philosophy it contains elements both hypothetical (calling

forth alternative possible meanings) and categorical (in its

referential determination of a given meaning); and in

philosophical discourse the concrete universal can be engaged in

questioning (like art), answering or asserting (like religion),

abstracting (like science) or referring (like history). And it

can claim adequacy at all these tasks without being "one

stupendous whole," since not all entities are linguistic.24 And

even though not all entities are linguistic, there would still

be no externality, no element of necessary and insurmountable

error, insofar as there are no non-linguistic entities

____________________
24 The terms "linguistic" and "linguistic expression"
must be taken as having the widest possible extension--including
not only the utterances of natural languages, but all sorts of
artificial languages as well (including mathematics and logic)
and even works of art (music, painting, dance, etc.). Cf. PA,
252-69.
317

that are not capable of being described, referred to, or

translated into linguistic entities. Therefore none are in

principle "external to" or "separated from" a subject.

Linguistic expression makes the whole world of objects, real and

possible, actual and fictitious, true and false, accessible to

the user of language, the subject.

(3) Philosophy as translational activity preserves the

contingency (and hence the freedom) of the progressive movement

of rapprochement insofar as there is no necessity to translate

something erroneously expressed unless one is committed to the

creation of, or preservation of, a higher mode of expression.

Philosophy as translation aims at consistency, but not strictly

speaking a formal consistency, but rather a consistency of

coherent meanings--meanings which cannot help but overlap in

specifiable ways, rather than abstract meanings which are

mutually exclusive. And even though it aims at consistency,

there is no fixed set of rules which prescribe a one-to-one

translation of one set of terms into another. Translation must

have a certain flexibility, aiming as it does at the

transmission of meaning rather than at mimetic correspondence.

Translation of meaning is impressionistic rather than

photographic: its rules are not necessarily the rules of strict

formal correspondence, but vary from loose metaphor to verbatim

literal and grammatical transformational analysis. One cannot

even say that the same ideal


318

is always adhered to, for in poetic translation a strict,

word-by-word translation would be undesirable, even ridiculous.

But philosophy, if nothing else, interprets itself as a guardian

of meaning rather than a keeper of rules. As such the forward

motion of philosophy is towards progressively more adequate

meaning, and the means to achieving this is, if not the opposite

of necessary inference, at least independent of it. Its

resources are the resources of freedom rather than those of

necessity.

(4) The ultimate identity that would serve as a maximal

ideal for a progressive rapprochement would therefore be an

identity of meaning, where through an identification of meaning

and meant, subject and object (knower and known) are identified.

The world of experience thus reconciled is an absolute built out

of the differences of the world as it finds them, but not by a

principle of abstraction (which leaves something always unsaid)

but by the progressive consolidation of a world of expressed

meanings, of articulated facts, bound together in such a way

that the whole (itself a meaning) could not be what it is

without its parts (which themselves are, or have, meanings) and

vice versa.

But we have been allowing ourselves the license of an

unrestricted flight of Collingwoodean fancy. How much of it

Collingwood might have


319

agreed with, we can only surmise. But there is little doubt that

his rapprochement philosophy is capable of the sort of

flexibility that would include modifications along the lines we

have suggested here; for indeed, for two or more reconciliata to

reach rapprochement means for them to have, and to be shown to

have, not the same objects unaffected by the knowing of them,

but the same meaning.


PART III

THE LATER WRITINGS (1933-1942)


CHAPTER VII

ANTI-REALISM AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF


MIND

Introduction.

In Chapter I we noticed that one of the major issues of

concern to Collingwood's interpreters is his position on the

realism-idealism controversy. Knox argues that he vacillated

from a youthful realism to a mature idealism and then back to a

dogmatic and sceptical realism in his later writings. Donagan

maintains that the youthful idealism propounded in Speculum

Mentis, with its anti-realistic, anti-abstraction principle, was

superceded by a more mature philosophy of mind in which

abstraction is recognized as being essential for thought; the

resulting philosophy of mind, though flawed, is compatible with

realism and contemporary analytical philosophy. Rubinoff denies

that Collingwood was ever anything but an idealist. And Mink

argues that Collingwood's philosophy escapes both idealism and

realism.

In Chapter II we found that Collingwood's

self-interpretation in the Autobiography also stresses the

realism-idealism controversy, but it stresses mainly his

opposition to errors of realism, and only incidentally denies

that his early work (Speculum Mentis) was, as one of his

reviewers

320
321

called it, "the usual idealistic nonsense." On this inter-

pretation we know only that Collingwood was opposed to the

central tenet of realism, as well as to its many pernicious

consequences, but not what Collingwood's commitment was to

idealism. We also saw in this chapter that Collingwood framed

the central tenet of realism in terms of the knower-known re-

lationship, and not in terms of the dependency of matter on mind

or even in terms of an abstraction principle. On the basis of

the autobiographical interpretation, then, we concluded that an

affirmation of the legitimacy of abstraction does not

necessarily constitute an espousal of the doctrine of

realism--not, that is, without evidence that Collingwood himself

drew the inference that the central tenet of realism necessarily

implies the principle of abstraction.

However in Chapter III we saw that the evidence of

Speculum Mentis does seem to point to this inference, since

throughout that early work Collingwood does attack realism by

means of a critique of the principle of abstraction. Realism's

basic error, according to Speculum Mentis, is the assumption

that truth is the result of abstraction, or is contained in the

abstract concept, and the correction of this error, which is the

work of philosophy, is the realization that all abstraction is

falsification, because "to abstract is to consider separately

things that are inseparable" (SM, 160). But both in Chapter III

and in Chapter VI we were


322

at pains to show that there is an ambiguity in the meaning of

terms like "separate" and "identical" which render the formu-

lation of the principle of abstraction, as it is expressed in

Speculum Mentis, equally ambiguous. The ambiguity infects the

discussion of realism itself, which on the one hand is respon-

sible for all the root errors that consciousness makes about

itself, and on the other hand is the particular form of dog-

matism associated with historicism. These ambiguities remain

unresolved in Speculum Mentis, which is not surprising from the

point of view of the Autobiography, since his rapprochement

philosophy was at this point still incomplete (cf. A, 107, 116).

But even though Speculum Mentis presumes that an attack on the

principle of abstraction is an attack on realism, there is

evidence that in the same book the principal doctrine of realism

as described in the Autobiography is itself attacked in an

argument employing the same strategy as the later work, and the

argument does not depend on premises tied to a principle of

abstraction. Collingwood argued that to ask what an object world

is or would be apart from a mind which knows it, presupposes the

false suggestion that we can describe that which by definition

is also unknown (SM, 267-68). This argument does not depend on

any formulation of a "principle of abstraction" as essential to

realism (cf. CEPC, 9-12).


323

What we require at this point, if the autobiographical

interpretation is to be upheld, is evidence that in his later

philosophy Collingwood did not, as some of his critics have

charged, surrender to the realism that he had rejected in his

early writings. If we can show that throughout his later

writings Collingwood continued to deny the principal doctrine of

realism, we shall take it that on this issue, at least, the

autobiographical interpretation is vindicated. Since this is the

main concern of this chapter, we shall attempt to adhere as

closely as we can to the fundamental formula of realism as

Collingwood understood it: that "knowing makes no difference to

the object known." We shall not attempt to follow up on all the

evidence that is available to show that he also sought to

overcome all the mistaken consequences that follow from this

premise--notably those concerning moral philosophy2--although we

may

______________________
1 As we pointed out in Chapter III, the autobiographical
formula for realism is phrased in extremely abstract terms, with
no differentiation made between various senses or cases of
"knowing" and "object," and no exact designation of what sort of
"difference" is made (or not made). Throughout this chapter we
shall assume that Collingwood is talking about an epistemological
doctrine, i.e. one which primarily says something about knowing
rather than something about reality.

2 In the bibliography of the Krausz collection of


Critical Essays on the Philosophy of Collingwood there is a note
that the lectures on ethics, currently being edited by Mrs. K.
Collingwood in collaboration with Mr. J. Rusk, are going to be
deposited in the Bodleian Library. Until they are made
available, Collingwood's views on ethics will probably remain
only partially revealed in the remarks in The New Leviathan.
324

make occasional note of these consequences in passing. We shall

also not be concerned with a detailed discussion of the

principle of abstraction, except as it bears directly on the

discussion of the central tenet of realism in the passage under

discussion--our reason being that the connection of these two

principles is not a direct part of the autobiographical

interpretation.

But does the denial of the principal doctrine of realism

necessarily imply the affirmation of an idealist thesis?

Certainly to deny the proposition that "knowing does not make a

difference to the object known" logically implies the af-

firmation that "knowing makes a difference to the object known,"

but is that all that it implies, and is this idealism? In an

intriguing article, John F. Post suggests that Collingwood's

anti-realism argument in the Autobiography not only shows that

the central tenet of realism is false, but is just as effective

against the idealist position that knowing does make a

difference to the object known, since either premise implies the

meaningless assertion that one can know what is simultaneously

declared to be unknown.3 Taking our cue from

_____________________
Since Collingwood's ethics is not what has caused widespread
interest in his philosophy, or even widespread controversy about
it, there is little problem with leaving it out of consideration
here. We do this knowing full well that for Collingwood, even in
the Autobiography, theory and practice cannot be fully separated
from one another.

3 John F. Post, "Does Knowing Make a Difference to What


Is Known?" Philosophical Quarterly, XV, no. 60 (July, 1965), pp.
220-28.
325

this article, we would like to propose a modification of Post's

argument and use it as an abstract framework for our investi-

gation of the realism-idealism controversy in Collingwood's

later philosophy.

In order to be as clear as possible (but only as clear

as necessary) about what is being affirmed by this negation, we

propose the following schema:

A. (1) Knowing makes a difference to the object known.

(2) (1) is false (realism).

(3) (2) is false, because the denial of (1) is absurd


(anti-realism).

But does A (3) then imply that A (1) is true? And is this

idealism? In order to see if this is so, let us propose a more

complicated version of schema A:

B. (1) Knowing makes a difference to the object known.

(2) The object known makes a difference to knowing.

(3) (1) is false and (2) is true (radical realism).

(4) (1) is true and (2) is false (radical idealism).

(5) Both (1) and (2) are false (radical scepticism).

(6) (3), (4), and (5) are false because (1) and (2) are both

true.

Whether or not there are any historically manifested

representatives for the positions we are calling "radical

realism," "radical idealism," and "radical scepticism," we wish

to know how
326

Collingwood stands with respect to these fundamental options. If

we can show that in his later philosophy Collingwood held to A

(3) we will have shown that on this issue the autobiographical

interpretation is vindicated. But we wish to know further if

Collingwood held to B (4), B (5), or B (6). We do know that

Collingwood claimed that he could never plead guilty to a charge

of scepticism (EPM, 223), and that in some sense of the word

idealism (but we do not know yet if, in the later philosophy, it

is in the radical sense as we are using that term), he claimed

not to be an idealist (A, 56-57).4 But can we really defend B

(6)? Does Collingwood really hold that B (1) and B (2) are not

related as disjuncts but as conjuncts?

Our strategy will be simply to take up the later writ-

ings, beginning with the Essay on Philosophical Method, con-

tinuing with The Principles of Art, and concluding with The New

Leviathan, with

___________________
4 In Chapter III we noted that in his early philosophy
Collingwood rejected "subjective" and "metaphysical" idealism,
and although he appeared to approve of an epistemological
idealism, held that "Absolute Knowledge" was humanly possible,
and ruled out a kind of objective idealism that relied on a
Divine Mind as a locus for absolute knowledge, we found these
passages in Speculum Mentis to be plagued with difficulties. In
the present chapter where "idealism" is used without quali-
fication, the epistemological, non-subjective variety is meant.
But we must remain alert to the possibility that what he says
about "idealism" may not be applicable to other forms of
idealism, particularly objective idealism of an Hegelian
pedigree.
327

side-excursions to the Essay on Metaphysics, The Idea of Nature,

and The Idea of History. We shall try to find out what

Collingwood means by the terms "object," "knowledge," and the

relation of "making a difference." Of necessity this involves

setting out in some detail Collingwood's later philosophy of

mind. But in this chapter we will only be concerned with so much

of it as relates to the question of the principal doctrine of

realism--and consequently the discussion will center on the

issue of the perception of the "real world" and the modification

of the object of perception by thought. In the next chapter we

will take up the "higher" functions of mind--conceptual,

propositional, interrogative, and implicative thinking--and

later we will be concerned with the historical imagination and

the ultimate meaning of "difference" and "identity" for a

rapprochement metaphysics. We refer the reader to other

expositions of the levels of practical consciousness in

Collingwood's later philosophy of mind: since these are

peripheral to our main concern, we shall have little to say

about them in this chapter. (See, e.g., Mink, MHD, 82-92, 117

figure 2).

It will help the reader to bear in mind that in this

chapter we shall try to give Collingwood every opportunity to

make clear what is the status of objects of perception, and

whether there is any possibility for the object to make a dif-

ference to the perceptual knowledge of it. We


328

shall therefore ask the reader's forbearance while we examine

some "circumstantial evidence" to confirm our suspicion that

Collingwood was trying to escape from the idealism-realism

dilemma.

Finally, it may be helpful if for orientation the reader

refer occasionally to Tables 7 and 8. While these summaries do

not correspond exactly to the sequence of topics in the chapter,

they will give the reader an overview of the essential features

of Collingwood's philosophy of mind presupposed in the

discussion of this theory of perception.

2. Empirical Thinking and the Essay on Philosophical Method.

Critics of Collingwood have dismissed the view of

philosophy expounded in the Essay on Philosophical Method

primarily because they saw it as a specimen of idealistic argu-

ment (cf. LPC, 259-60). The grounds for this assertion are

primarily (a) the view of predication presented in the essay--

viz. that all philosophical statements are both categorical and

universal; and (b) the use to which this analysis of predication

is put--viz. the defense of the Anselmian ontological argument.5

We will refrain from a full discussion of both of these issues:

the former will be examined in the next chapter, insofar as it

is best discussed in

_____________________
5 G. Ryle, "Mr. Collingwood and the Ontological Argu-
ment," Mind XLIV, 174 (April, 1935), pp. 137-51; reprinted in
Hick and McGill, eds., op. cit. pp. 246-60.
329

connection with Q-A logic and the nature of hypothetical and

categorical judgments; and the latter issue will arise again in

the chapter on metaphysics and rapprochement (Chapter X), since

the ontological argument seems to be the ultimate test of

whether there is an upper limiting case of unity in the scale of

forms of knowledge.

The question at this point is whether or not the Essay

on_Philosophical Method contains any statements which would

substantiate, modify, or disprove the central anti-realistic

thesis of the Autobiography. But it appears that in this work

Collingwood intends to dodge all responsibility for dealing with

such issues. Although the purpose of the essay is to describe

the nature of philosophy, Collingwood announces at the outset

that he will not expand the essay to include the place of

philosophy among the other forms of thought, the place of

thought among the other activities of the mind, and the relation

of mind to the world (EPM, 7-8). For reasons of both expediency

and specificity, he declines to deal with the broader issues

raised by the essay: "though no doubt the thoughts here

expressed have implications in metaphysics, logic, and the

theory of knowledge, these implications will not be discussed"

(EPM, 8).

On the other hand, Collingwood confessed at the end of

the essay that his original contract with the reader (EPM, 45)

to treat the proposed


330

characteristics of philosophical concepts, judgments, and

arguments as only hypothetically or provisionally affirmed has

been violated throughout the book by appeal to

"experience"--that is, philosophical experience, instances in

which the concepts, judgments, and arguments are displayed as

having these characteristics (EPM, 223-24). Therefore the

interpreter is put in the difficult position of taking the

substantive remarks of the essay as in one sense true for

philosophy (as Collingwood sees it) without qualification, and

in another sense taking such remarks as only provisionally true.

Until the actual standpoint of the essay is spelled out (and it

will be to the best of our ability in the next chapter – see

below, pp 461, 592 ff), we can only look for indirect evidence

to add probability to our contention that the essay does not

represent a departure from the central theses of the

Autobiography.

When we turn to the Essay on Philosophical Method for

evidence to determine whether or not Collingwood held to B (3),

B (4), B (5), or B (6), i.e. whether the negative proposition

which denies the realist's principal doctrine logically entails

the positive proposition that knowing does make a difference to

the object known, the closest we come to such evidence is in a

passage in which Collingwood is discussing the problem of the

starting point in philosophy. Philosophy can justify its own

starting point, he says, "only if the arguments of philosophy,

instead of having an irreversible direction from principles to


conclusion, have a reversible
331

one, the principles establishing the conclusions and the

conclusions reciprocally establishing the principles" (EPM,

160). The escape from the charge of vicious circularity is

premised, Collingwood says, on the realization that philosophy,

unlike empirical and exact science, does not proceed from the

unknown to the known: it relies on the "Socratic principle that

philosophical reasoning leads to no conclusion which we did not

in some sense know already" (EPM, 161).

Every school of philosophical thought has accepted this


principle, recognizing that philosophy does not, like exact
or empirical science, bring us to know things of which we
already knew in some way; . . . for if the species of a
philosophical genus overlap, the distinction between the
known and the unknown, which in a non-philosophical sub-
ject-matter involves a difference between two mutually ex-
clusive classes of truths, in a philosophical subjectmatter
implies that we may both know and not know the same thing;
a paradox which disappears in the light of a notion of a
scale of forms of knowledge, where coming to know means
coming to know in a different and better way. (EPM, 161).

Here we see that Collingwood is employing the two most

central doctrines of the essay--the overlap of classes and the

scale of forms (the technical meanings of which will be explored

in the next chapter) to justify the philosophical sense in which

knowing makes a difference to the object known. For if

philosophical knowledge proceeded in the manner of empirical

knowledge, then it would simply be the case that the object made

a difference to the subject, or to the knowing of it, without

any
332

reciprocal co-effect of knowing on the known. But Collingwood is

here asserting that "every school of philosophy" accepts the

principle that in philosophy it is necessary to anticipate its

conclusions "by an experience that possesses them in substance

before its reasoning begins," so that "in philosophy the

conclusions can be checked by comparing them with these

anticipations" (EPM, 163). The object of philosophical

knowledge, therefore, is not something passively given: its

initial datum is always being modified in the light of its

conclusions (cf. EPM, 94-97).

Collingwood spells out for his readers the ways in which

this initial datum of philosophy differs from that of empirical

science. It is different (1) in its relation to the process of

reasoning (premises and conclusions are irreversibly related in

inductive reasoning, whereas in philosophy the arguments are

reversible); (2) in its own constitution (it consists not of

empirical facts but of universal propositions which form the

material or substance out of which the final system is

constructed); and (3) in the way in which it comes to be

possessed (it is apprehended not by perception but by

thought--the experience of a thinker) (EPM,166-69). (These

principles will be more carefully examined in Chapter VIII). But

the differences do not end there, and Collingwood spells out a

further difference as (4) the principles that in philosophy

knowing makes a difference to what is known:


333

In empirical science we begin by perceiving that the facts


are so, and go on by forming a theory as to why they are
so; but in adding this new theory to the old facts we do
not come to know the facts in a different way, we only come
to have something new in our minds . . . alongside the old
knowledge. The process is a special kind of accumulation.
But in philosophy the knowledge . . . why things are so
makes a difference to the knowledge that they are
so . . . . Our knowledge is not simply accumulating, it is
developing; it is improving as well as increasing; it is
widening and strengthening itself at once. There is
consequently a parallel difference in the result of the
process, the conclusion which the argument estab-
lishes . . . . (I)n philosophy, the theory that emerges
from consideration of the facts is no mere hypothesis, it
is the facts themselves more thoroughly understood. (EPM,
169-70; emphasis mine).

The incautious reader may leap to the conclusion that

because Collingwood is contrasting empirical and philosophical

thinking that it is only in philosophy that the proviso holds

that knowing makes a difference to the object known, and that in

empirical thinking perception of the facts leaves them un-

altered, the process being a "kind of accumulation" rather than

a kind of modification. But such a conclusion ignores Colling-

wood's precautionary remark at the beginning of the essay. He

says there that when he talks about "empirical" or "non-philo-

sophical" concepts he is referring not to the concepts as they

are actually used in science or mathematics, but to concepts

which are mistakenly thought to be philosophical: "what I am

discussing, when I distinguish philosophical method from that of

exact science, is not mathematics itself but a certain method,

often mistakenly used in philosophy, which is believed to be

that of mathematics" (EPM, 9).


334

Collingwood's point is that he is not primarily concerned with


making statements about empirical or exact sciences, but about
philosophy; and therefore it is not essential to this point that
what he asserts as true for the empirical or exact sciences be
true or not as they are actually employed in those fields, but
only that what he is asserting as true for philosophy and
philosophical concepts--empirical and exact science as
alternative methods and concepts for philosophy.6

But then does the provision that knowing makes a dif-


ference to the object known apply to the whole of the relation
between knowledge and its object, or just to that relationship
wherein the "object" is taken as the initial datum of philoso-
phy, and "knowing" is understood as that special relationship to
an object that is mediated by the sort of thinking called
philosophy? To answer this question we clearly must broaden our
discussion from its self-imposed limitations in the Essay on
Philosophical Method. This broader framework is provided by the
philosophy of mind he declined to deal with in the essay on
method.

_________________
6 It would be a misinterpretation to take the remarks in
the Essay on Philosophical Method as evidence that at this time
Collingwood held to the strict autonomy of separate modes of
thought--science, history, philosophy, etc.--or that he held to
the existence of a metaphysics of the one, the true, and the
good. The essay leaves such issues unresolved.
335

3. Sensation, Imagination, and Empirical Thought.

Since Collingwood declared in the Autobiography that The

Principles of Art was the second book in his mature series, one

would hope for some direct link between its contents and those

of the Essay _ Philosophical Method--the first book of the

series of those he planned to write as of 1932. A promising case

of a direct relation of subject matters might be the

characterization of "empirical thinking" that appears in both

(cf. PA, 221 and EPM, 164-70), were it not for the fact that the

essay on method so severely limits the applicability of that

characterization. The linkage between the two works is

there--but it is indirect: it appears in the form of their

styles of argumentation, the overlapping of concepts employed in

the theory of art, the scale of forms of experience and of

knowledge that appear in the central chapters of the later work,

and in the overall relation of conclusions to starting point,

etc. specified in the Essay on Philosophical Method and

exemplified in The Principles of Art.

Even if we had already examined these methodological

criteria, it is not of direct concern to us in this chapter to

spell out this indirect relationship. Nor would it be to our

purpose to examine in detail Collingwood's philosophy of art.'

In keeping with our principle of limited


336

objectives, we shall be looking only for evidence for or against

Collingwood's judgment on the central tenet of realism.8

_________________
7 The Principles of Art is divided into three major
sections. Book I deals with the distinction between art and
pseudo-art, the latter being primarily art-craft and the re-
flection on art based on it, this being the "technical theory of
art." In this group of arts falsely so-called are all forms of
what Collingwood calls representation art, amusement art, and
magical art, all of which presume a distinction between means
and end that is alien to true art. Book I ends with two chapters
which treat of art in the correct sense of the term--as
expression and as imagination. For the purpose of clarifying the
meaning of the terms "expression" and "imagination," Book II
begins afresh with an examination of the general
characterizations of experience as a whole, based on the
structure of experience as exhibited by reflection on mental
functions familiar to anyone who thinks. Book II includes
chapters on thinking and feeling, on sensation and imagination,
on imagination and consciousness, and on language. Book III
outlines a theory of art based on the distinctions and conclu-
sions of Books I and II. The critical chapters in Book III are
those which discuss art as language and art as truth.

8 Although our concern is not directly with the theory


of art, it is noteworthy to observe at this point that the
structure of argument in The Principles of Art makes little
sense apart from its anti-realistic orientation. The "technical
theory of art," against which the whole of Book I is a
continuous argument, is based on the realist's separation of end
(the work of art) from means (the artist's activity), and some
of Collingwood's most acrimonious comments in this section are
reserved for the "realistic aestheticians" (who, like Sam
Alexander, maintain that "beauty" is a subjective feeling
aroused by direct acquaintance or perception of the art-work
(PA, 149). These are exceeded only by his contempt for the
psychologizing art-critics (who, like I. A. Richards, attempt to
account for this subjective feeling on the basis of the
stimulus-response model--PA, 29-36; cf. PA, 262-64), and for the
positivistic anthropologists (who, like Freud, Edward Tylor,
James Frazer, and Levy-Bruhl, wind up talking like "one of
Moliere's prize idiots" when they attempt to derive art from
magical beliefs, while utterly misconceiving the nature of myth
and magic in the first place--PA, 58-64).
The theory of art as expression and as imagination which
Collingwood works out is also fully anti-realistic inasmuch as
instead of the art-object
337

Interestingly enough it is in the section on empirical thinking

in The Principles of Art that we find the clearest indication in

that work of the stance that Collingwood is taking on the

central tenet of realism. In developing a theory of imagination

Collingwood discusses the intermediate position of imagination

in the region of experience between sensation and intellect, and

points out that "sensation must be regarded as a flux of

activity in which . . . as soon as the act is over, the sensum

has

________________________________
it makes the function of imagination and its expression in
language primary and even exclusively essential to true art.
Collingwood goes so far in this direction that he asserts that
"a work of art may be completely created when it has been
created as a thing whose only place is in the artist's mind (PA,
130)--or, as he later puts it, in his head (PA, 151). In Book II
the anti-realistic orientation (one might even call it a bias)
is apparent in his final analysis of art as language or as the
imaginative expression of emotion---mental functions which exist
even at the level of the logical and symbolic levels of thought
as the "emotions of intellect" (PA, 252-69). Further indications
of the anti-realism of Book II will be analyzed in the text of
this section of our chapter, and in Chapter VIII. Finally, in
Book III, while saying little directly against realism (as one
might expect, since anti-realism is his starting point and not
his ultimate conclusion), Collingwood counters the realistic
esthetician's subject-object dichotomy in art by discussing the
truth in art as something not in the art work only or in the
subject only, but as a knowing of oneself which is also a making
of oneself (PA, 291-92), and by discussing the active role of
the artist's audience in the work of art itself (PA, 300-24).
Even in so short a summary as this, it is apparent that to
excise the anti-realistic orientation of the book is to make
nonsense of its argument. That other estheticians have
recognized this is indicated by the fact that they point to his
"art-only-in-the-head" overstatement as representative of
Collingwood's supposed over-intellectualization of the subject
of esthetics as a whole: see e.g. S. Langer, Feeling and Form,
Charles Scribner's Sons (New York, 1953), p. 382. If this is
overstatement, we would like to suggest that it is due to his
anti-realistic bias.
338

vanished, never to return. Its esse is sentiri" (PA, 198). At

this point he paraphrases the sort of criticism that someone

like G. E. Moore (he cites him by name) would raise to such an

overstatement, and gives his own response to it:

"Naturally," it may be said, "we cannot see a colour with-


out seeing it. But what could be more absurd than to argue
that, because we have stopped seeing it, the colour has
ceased to exist? For all we know, colours may perfectly
well go on existing when we are not looking at them." The
objection is an excellent example of "metaphysics" in the
sense in which that word has at various times become a term
of merited abuse . . . . The fairy-tale about the existence
of unsensed sense, no doubt, is believed by the people who
indulge in it to be a piece of philosophical
thinking. . . . But even if the belief in question were
true, propositions of this kind would still be nonsense
unless it were true not merely that a sensum exists apart
from our sensation of it, but that in this state of
apartness it is open to our inspection; we have it before
our mind in such a way that we can appreciate its
qualities, compare them with those of other sense, and so
forth. The question is not one of metaphysics, whether
colours exist or not, when we do not see them; it is a
question of epistemology, whether we can "have them before
our mind" in the above sense otherwise than by seeing them;
and if so, how. If we cannot, propositions of the kind in
question are all nonsensical . . . . (PA, 198-99; emphasis
mine. Cf. PA, 170; NL, 5.31-5.39).

The argument in this passage is an application of the refutation

of the central doctrine of realism as found in the

Autobiography. Its thrust is to demonstrate the absurdity of the

epistemological proposition that "knowing makes no difference to

the object known" by showing that this entails knowing what is

simultaneously declared to be unknown--in this case sensing

something that is unsensed.


339

What Collingwood is maintaining in this passage is that either

(1) what Moore and empiricists in general have been comparing is

a sensum and something else like a sensum, but different from

it--in fact an imaginatum9--or (2) they have been talking

complete nonsense--the nonsense of being the assertion of the

existence of unsensed sensa.l0

_____________________
9 Collingwood does not use the term "imaginatum" or even
"phantasm," but on the analogy of his deliberate usage of the
term "sensation" for the act of sensation and "sensum" for what
is sensed in that act (PA, 173) we feel it to be justified.
Collingwood's determination to "speak with the vulgar and think
with the learned" causes a certain inarticulation and headache
for his interpreters, as we shall see when we come to the
altered terminology of The New Leviathan. Cf. PA, 174, and below.

1O This is the argument in support of the thesis that


the esse of sense is sentiri that Donagan claims he failed to
find in Chapter VIII of The Principles of Art (LPC, 32-34, and
32 n. 1): in Chapter VIII it appears on P.170. These pages are
predictably the most confusing in all of Donagan's book. (a)
Donagan first asserts that he could find no such argument, and
then himself cites the argument quoted above (evidently feeling
that it is a bad argument, and a bad argument is no argument at
all). (b) Then Donagan proceeds to argue that "what
((Collingwood)) took for an 'obvious truth' is a howler . . . .
(I)t is not at all obvious that being sensed may not be merely
an episode in the history of a sensum, even though it is its
very essence as a sensum. Collingwood seems to have confounded
the obvious truth that only while it is sensed does a sensum
exist as a sensum with the pleasantry that when it is not being
sensed it cannot exist as anything whatever" (LPC, 33). But
since Collingwood's whole point is the "obvious truth" that
Donagan grants, and not the different proposition that an
unsensed object cannot exist as anything whatever when it is
unsensed, it appears that the howl is on Donagan: he affirms
what he proposes to refute. (c) Then in addition to this
supposed refutation of what is not and yet is an argument,
Donagan proposes what he calls "some positive evidence" for
maintaining that the esse of a sensum is not sentiri." This he
finds in the following argument: "The strongest argument for
asserting that most of our sense are physical objects,
340

This would seem to let the empiricists off the hook by

allowing them to opt for (1), but to choose this option is, for

a radical empiricist, to surrender his empiricism, since the

radical empiricist is one who maintains that all knowledge

arises from sensation, where knowledge is not considered to be

coeval with sensation as originator, but rather subsequent upon

it--both temporally and logically.ll What Collingwood is

proposing instead is a modified empiricism in which thought as

the deliberate achievement of a thinker is present even at the

level of sensation. Since radical empiricists assume that

knowledge arises from the active impression of "sense data" on

passive organs of sensation, it is clear that Collingwood's

position would not be taken by them as a supporting modifica-

tion.12

____________________________
and so can exist unsensed, is that every natural language in
which men speak of what they see, hear, taste, and smell is a
physical object language" (LPC, 34). But as Donagan himself
notes (but fails to apply to his own "evidence") on such grounds
as this one could justify belief in fairy-tales, for every
natural language is as much a fairy-tale language as it is a
physical object language. Donagan's "evidence" (or is it an
argument?) is not as mute as the rock that Dr. Johnson kicked to
refute Berkeley, but it is just as ineffective.

1l Cf. Errol E. Harris, Nature, Mind, and Modern Science


(New York, 1954), p. 119.

12 Mink writes: "Collingwood is an empiricist, but one


who belongs to no identifiable school . . . . As an empiricist,
Collingwood is a radical empiricist, but he is also a radical
idealist, for whom the originative powers of thought are coeval
with the most rudimentary forms of experience" (MHD, 111). Mink
rightly recognizes that Collingwood escapes the classification
of both realism and idealism, that "the traditional opposition
of 'empiricism' and 'idealism' is not a fruitful subject for
investigation or debate, and that all of the interesting
341

Nevertheless this is Collingwood's program in Book II of

The Principles of Art, and the strategy of argument in this

section makes little sense unless it is viewed as an extended

argument which both (1) rejects the empiricist epistemology on

which realistic esthetics is based, and (2) attempts to save

whatever meaning survives this critique. The argument we have

just cited, for example, appears just after a rather extensive

survey of the British empiricists on the relation of sensation

to imagination, during which his main concern was not with a

mere refutation that there is a valid basis for the distinction

between real and imaginary sense, but with extracting whatever

sense he can from the philosophical tradition on the subject. In

order to understand the modification of empiricism that

Collingwood is proposing we must examine this distinction more

closely.

________________________
problems cluster around what it means to be radical" (ibid.).
Unfortunately Mink does not address himself to this question,
and therefore his paradoxical assertions shed no light on how it
is possible for a position to be both empirical and idealist
when both are asserted in their radical forms--that is, as
positions which exclude their opposites. An index of his
confusion on this issue can be found in his use of the term
"genetic" as it applies to the scale of forms of consciousness:
Mink asserts at one point that Collingwood avoids the "genetic
fallacy" of the pragmatists and the non-genetic fallacy of the
empiricists (MHD, 111), but later he says that for Collingwood
feeling and rationality are linked genetically (MHD, 262).
342

In Chapter VIII Collingwood sets up "the problem of

imagination" against the background of the contrast between

feeling and thought, the "problem" being that imaginary sense

seem to be neither feelings nor thoughts. The difference between

these two "features of our experience" is carried out on the

basis of several contrasting characteristics. (1) In terms of

the acts of feeling and thinking, feeling is simple and thought

bipolarly complex: thinking carries with it the sense of success

or failure, truth or falsity, or in general a reference to

self-imposed standards or criteria by which it judges whether

what it has tried to do has been done well or ill. Feeling may

have oppositions and distinctions within itself, but the sense

of its having been done altogether "deliberately" or of its

having succeeded or failed is absent from it (PA, 157). (2) In

terms of what is felt or thought, feelings are private, and

thought is public: what one feels is not open to inspection in

the same way as is what one thinks (PA, 157-58). (3) Thoughts

can corroborate or contradict each other, but feelings cannot

(PA, 158), and the main reason for this is that (4) feelings are

in perpetual flux in which nothing remains the same (what we

take for permanence or recurrence is only a greater or lesser

degree of resemblance between different feelings), whereas in

thinking we are concerned with something that lasts, that

genuinely recurs as a factor in experience (although it is not

necessary
343

to assert the eternity of all objects of thought as such (PA,

159).13 Finally, (5) feeling has the character of a foundation

upon which thinking is erected as a superstructure--which is why

feeling appears to arise in us independently of thought, in a

part of our experience which functions independently of all

thinking and seems unaffected by it, a level Collingwood calls

"psychical" (PA, 163-64).14

Within feeling Collingwood distinguishes two "kinds" of

experience, sensation and emotion--not as a distinction between

two species of a common genus, but as two aspects of one and the

same experience (like "a terrifying red") which can be

distinguished

________________________
13 In the subsequent analysis not all of the disting-
uishing criteria are given equal weight by Collingwood, but (4)
is taken as essential to feeling--i.e., that it is impermanent,
or in constant flux, while thought is something that recurs and
lasts. In section 4 of this chapter we will see how crucial this
distinction is for the characterization of attention--the major
function of imagination. On the contrast between sensation (or
feeling) and thought in his early writings, see SM, 188-89.

14 “I hold that the proper business of psychology is to


investigate this level of experience," i.e. the psychical level,
the level of experience at which we merely feel sensations
together with their peculiar emotional charges, "and not the
level which is characterized by thought" (PA, 164). Collingwood
refers the reader to a note on p. 171 in which he states that "a
science of feeling must be 'empirical' (i.e. devoted to
ascertaining and classifying 'facts' or things susceptible of
observation), but a science of thought must be 'normative', or
(as I prefer to call it) 'criteriological', i.e. concerned not
only with the 'facts' of thought but also with the 'criteria' or
standards which thought imposes on itself" (PA, 171, note; cf.
IN, 230-31).
344

by thought, but always occur together in experience.15 They are

combined according to a definite structural pattern describable

by saying that sensation takes precedence over emotion. The

priority is not temporal, causal, or logical (as grounds and

consequent), but as analyzably distinct: emotion exists as a

kind of charge on a sensation, a charge which can be stripped

off the sensum--a process Collingwood calls "sterilizing" the

sensum by ignoring its emotional charge (PA, 162). This is

accomplished, as he later explains, by an act of attention (cf.

PA, 162-63, 203-11).

Thinking is also distinguised in two ways. In its

primary form thought is exclusively concerned with feeling as

its sole and universal subject matter. First-order thinking is

the process by which we become aware, by an act of attention, of

certain feelings and go on to think of these feelings as

standing in certain relations to other feelings, remembered as

past or imagined as possible (PA, 164-65). All empirical thought

is of this sort: making empirical statements we express our

thoughts about the relations between sensa, actual or possible --

__________________
15 The same distinction between a sensum and its emo-
tional charge, within the experience of feeling, is made in The
New Leviathan, but (1) Collingwood adds a "diffuse consciousness
of feeling" between first-order thought and the purely psychical
level, and (2) distinguishes feeling as an "apanage" of mind
rather than a constituent (only forms of consciousness are
constituents of mind) (NL, 4.1-4.31). Collingwood does not
define "apanage," but it refers to the ordinary English usage:
"Man as mind is consciousness . . . ; he has feelings . . . . "
(NL, 4.2).
345

relations of attention to, selection of, comparison with, etc.

the sense under consideration (PA, 165-66).

Thus our experience of the world in space and time, the


"world of nature" or "external" world, which means not the
world external to ourselves (for we ourselves are part of
it, in so far as "we" are our bodies; and if "we" are our
minds, there is no sense in speaking of anything as
external to them) but the world of things external to one
another, the world of things scattered in space and time,
is an experience partly sensuous (strictly sensuous-
emotional) and partly intellectual: sense being concerned
with the colours we see, and the sounds we hear, and so
forth; and thought with the relations between these things.
(PA, 166) 16

But thought also has a secondary function, and second-order

thought is thought about thought, thought concerned with the

relations between one act of thinking and another, or between

the contents of such acts (PA, 166-67). Collingwood does not

further characterize second-order thought at this point, other

than to contrast it with first-order thought as reason to un-

derstanding, or philosophy to science, and to insist that the

term "experience" be used to cover not only feeling, but first

and second-order thought as well (PA, 167).

The stage is now set for Collingwood's discussion of

the problem of imagination. If sense are in a state of constant

flux, it does not

_______________
16 To take this passage as a piece of subjective idealism
would be a mistake, since Collingwood's intention is not to
dissolve the "external" world of nature, but to avoid an
"inside-outside" dichotomy with no room for bodily overlap.
346

seem possible (given the characterization of thought and feeling

that he had just given) that they could be the object of thought

of any kind, because relations between sense cannot be fixed if

the sense are constantly being both "given" and "taken away."

The difficulty is epitomized in the empiricist formula, "sense

data," where the term "data" implies that the sense are not only

given but retained, which conflicts essentially with the term

"sense" which refers to something which neither persists nor

recurs (PA, 169). The term "sense datum" is therefore either

absurd or refers to something like a sensum but different from

it, and hence the act which grasps it is not properly termed

sensation (PA, 170-71).

In order to see what the distinction actually means,

Collingwood engages in an examination of the historical phase of

the problem from Descartes to Kant, centering his discussion on

the common-sense distinction between "real" and-"imaginary"

sense as two classes of a common genus. He distinguishes threel7

phases of the problem: (1) the identification

____________________
17 Although there is no particular dialectical magic to
the number three for Collingwood, it is interesting to note that
the three phases to his historical discussion of this problem
correspond to the three ways that the classes "real" and
"imaginary" as species of the genus "sense" can be related: (1)
the classes can be simply identified (17th century ration-
alists); or (2) abstractly distinguished (English empiricists);
or (3) arranged on a scale of overlapping classes (Kant). For
evidence that this is not an accidental arrangement, see PA,
187, n. 1.
347

of sensation with imagination by the 17th century rationalists;

(2) the defense of the common-sense distinction by the English

empiricists; and (3) the Kantian solution to the problem (PA,

187).

(1) In the 17th century, Descartes, Hobbes, and Spinoza

found that by direct inspection, real and imaginary sensa could

not be distinguished. At bottom both were identical: both

exhibit a kind of confused disorder, and it is only by reasoning

that the two can be distinguished (PA, 175-76). But although

Collingwood ultimately agrees with the conclusions (a) that

there is no direct or internal test by which the two classes of

sense can be distinguished, and (b) that it is only on the basis

of some kind of thought that the distinction can be made (PA,

194), he is not content to merely identify them. He therefore

goes on to examine the defense of the commonsense distinction by

the English empiricists.18

__________________
18 CF. NL, 4.83-4.89: "For Plato, sensations and emo-
tions cannot be knowledge because they lack the precision which
knowledge must have. For Leibniz, feeling in general is confusa
cognitio. I do not accept either view in its entirety. Plato
thought that knowledge cannot even rest on a foundation of
feeling, because feeling is too vague; knowledge must be the
work of pure thought operating all by itself. But what a
foundation needs is strength, and strength is what feeling has.
Leibniz thought feeling was confused knowledge, and to clear up
the confusion is to purge it of what makes it feeling and leave
it knowledge. But feeling is not knowledge at all; it is
feeling; and if you could purge it of what makes it feeling
there would be no residue. Yet each was right in saying that
feeling is confused or indistinct. That is why one should not
try to define it or any kind or element of it; but only to give
examples and say: 'This is the sort of thing to which the word
refers."'
348

(2) The common-sense distinction was reinstated by the

English empiricists, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, but each failed

to adequately justify it. As if recognizing some inadequacy to

the distinction, each put forward a pair of criteria for

discriminating real from imaginary sense. Locke's "real ideas"

are distinguished from "fantastical" ones insofar as (a) the

latter are related as ectype to the archetypal "real

ideas"--these being the "original" or "real being" of the

objects; and (b) by an "introspective" criteria whereby

imaginary sense are the result of a voluntary activity, whereas

real sense are not--the two cases being distinguished by simple

introspection as to how the ideas arise in us (PA, 17677).19

Similarly Berkeley distinguished "ideas of sense" from

________________________
19 Cf. Donagan: "In his philosophy of mind Collingwood
was fundamentally anti-Cartesian; for he . . . repudiated Des-
cartes' doctrine that acts of consciousness are, as it were,
self-illuminating. You cannot know your own mind by turning an
inner eye on its operations, because introspection can do no
more than to bring to mind something of which you have already
become aware" (LPC, 25). "All that introspection could do would
be to reproduce your visual field in a second 'inner' visual
field; and there is no reason to suppose that having a second
visual field or a second auditory field would make you conscious
of your first one" (LPC, 41). It is clear that Donagan has a
different meaning in mind for "introspection" than does
Collingwood. Collingwood attributes the introspection theory to
the empiricists--Locke, Berkeley, and Hume-and means it to refer
to the distinction between real and imaginary sense on the basis
of the degree of control the subject has over such experiences,
the former being relatively involuntary (PA, 177-79). However
there is a secondary sense of the term "introspection" as used
by Collingwood, this being closer to the sense that Donagan has
in mind. At PA, 205 Collingwood writes that introspection as the
method of putting questions to consciousness cannot tell us
anything about the psychical or purely
349

"ideas of imagination" in two ways: (a) by a restatement of

Locke's introspection theory (the "strength and liveliness"

criteria which, Collingwood argues, only makes sense as meaning

that, e.g. "a real sound is heard whether we will or no, whereas

an imaginary one can be summoned up, banished, or replaced by

another at will" (PA, 178-79)); and (b) the "relation theory"

which suggests that ideas of sense are subject to the laws of

nature, but ideas of imagination are not (PA, 179-82). Finally,

Hume dropped Berkeley's relational theory and (a) reinstated the

introspection theory: "impressions" (real sense) are

distinguished from "ideas" (imaginary sense) by the "degree of

force and liveliness with which they strike the mind"--which

Collingwood once again takes to mean

_____________________
sentient level of experience; the correct method for such
knowledge is to be found in a well-grounded behavioral
psychology. But although Collingwood is rejecting introspection
here as a method for inquiring about the purely psychical level,
he is not rejecting it as a method for understanding the
functions of consciousness. Indeed, so far from being
"anti-Cartesian" in this sense, Collingwood's mature philosophy
of mind is nothing but introspective: it consists entirely of
"soundings" at various levels of consciousness (NL, 9.35-9.4),
made by putting questions to (conscious reflection on) lower
levels (cf. PA, 205-06), which might just call on Donagan's
"Principle of Order" as a blessing on the project. It is
therefore hard to see what sense it makes to assert that the
introspective method was rejected by Collingwood, or how in
rejecting it Collingwood was being fundamentally anti-Cartesian.
To be anti-Cartesian Collingwood would have to maintain that
conscious acts cannot be objects to other conscious acts, which
is certainly not what Collingwood maintained. And if being
anti-introspectively anti-Cartesian means rejecting that there
is an "inner eye" that is something other than a conscious act,
then it is probable that Descartes himself was not a Cartesian,
for certainly his introspective acts were acts of consciousness.
350

the inability of our minds to set purpose to, control, excite,

suppress, or modify our sensory experience (PA, 182-83). (b) But

Hume also recognized (but yet minimized) the difficulties in-

volved in cases like dreams, hallucinations, and violent emo-

tional upheavals, in which the criterion does not apply, since

in such cases sense are not subject to voluntary control, but

are nonetheless certainly imaginary. In such cases he therefore

falls back on the relational theory to account for the

distinction (PA, 183-85).

Collingwood argues that none of the empiricists' cri-

teria is successful. In Locke's representative theory the

substitution of the relation of ectype to archetype for the

relation of imaginary sense to real sense is inconsistent with

his causal theory, which describes real sense as caused by ob-

jects (PA, 177)--it assumes the untenable identification of

resemblance and causation which Hume so vigorously refuted. If

real sense cannot be accounted for in this way, their dis-

tinction from imaginary sense collapses. The introspection

theory similarly fails on the grounds that the exceptional cases

of hallucinations, dreams, etc. proves not the rule that real

sense, but not imaginary sense, are involuntary, but rather that

will has little to do with the distinction: imaginary sense are

often less subject to control than are real sensa (PA, 179).

Finally, the relational theory fails because although imaginary

sense may not obey all the laws of nature, they


351

obey some, and are furthermore subject to "psychological laws"

which cannot be thoroughly disentangled from laws of nature.

Furthermore the relational criterion is circular: we can only

know what the laws of nature are by experience, or by studying

real sensa--but to distinguish real sense by appeal to these

laws presumes the distinction to be established (PA, 182).

Finally, (3) Kant corrects the relational theory by

showing that first-order laws of nature imply second-order

"principles of the understanding," and argues effectively that

while a sensum may be "wild" in the sense of not belonging to a

"family" of known natural laws of the first order, it cannot be

wild in the sense of failing to belong to laws of the second

order.

It is a principle of the understanding that every event


must have a cause. No event that comes under our notice can
escape this principle. The furthest length to which it can
go towards wildness in that direction is a failure on our
part to discover what, in particular, its cause is. Thus
Kant's discovery of second-order laws involves the
discovery that there are no wild sensa. At the same time it
enables him to explain what we mean when we say that wild
sensa exist. We are saying that certain sensa, though . . .
we know they must admit of interpretation, have not yet
been actually interpreted . . . . Instead of trying to
conceive real sensa and imaginary sensa as two co-ordinate
species of the same genus, . . . he conceived the
difference between them as a difference of degree. For him,
a real sensum can only mean one which has undergone
interpretation by the understanding, which alone has the
power to confer the title real; an imaginary sensum will
then mean one which has not yet undergone that process.
(PA, 186-87; emphasis mine).
352

It is noteworthy that Collingwood takes the Kantian position as

the concluding phase of the controversy (PA, 187), and does not

subject it to any criticism as he had the previous positions. If

the reader is left in any doubt that Collingwood wishes to

accept this solution to the problem as final, his footnote to

this passage affixes his final seal of approval: he cites the

Essay on Philosophical Method to the effect that what is

involved in Kant's doctrine is an instance of the rule for

philosophical concepts wherein differences of degree always

imply difference in kind (PA, 187, n. 1).20

___________________
20 That Collingwood's philosophy of mind would accept as
final a viewpoint that is ultimately Kantian would not be
accepted by Lionel Rubinoff, who would argue that a further step
is required to raise it to the "absolute standpoint" at which
subject and object are identified. But there is nothing in The
Principles of Art to indicate that Collingwood accepted anything
but the Kantian viewpoint as final on the question of real and
imaginary sense, and that he looked with anything but favor upon
Kant's limitation of thought to the bounds of possible
experience. The Hegelian absolute standpoint is nowhere in
evidence in this work, except insofar as that standpoint is
implicit in the Kantian philosophy. It is therefore going beyond
Collingwood's last word to assign The Principles of Art to the
"third ontological level" at which subject and object are
identified, as Rubinoff does (CRM, 373). On the other hand to
classify Collingwood as a Kantian would be equally misleading,
even if it would be not as misleading as assimilating him to
Hegelianism. (While statistical frequency of citations of
authors does not count for much in philosophical works, it is
interesting to note that Hegel has only one reference in
Collingwood's index to The Principles of Art, and this an
unfavorable one, while Kant has 14, mostly favorable).
Collingwood never accepted any categorial schema of logical
relations as final, even though he approved of the Kantian for-
mulation of them: see NL, 5.66-5.67, 7.34. Nor is there any hint
of a "deduction of the categories" in Collingwood, either in the
Kantian or the Hegelian sense of the term "deduction." And
finally, Collingwood never elevated art into one of the modes of
absolute experience, as Hegel does: cf. IH, 121, 311
353

The Kantian solution also makes it possible to solve a

long-standing problem in the traditional controversy--the

problem of illusory sense, with its two variants, the terms

"appearance" and "image" as used in false theories of percep-

tion. It would seem like a development of the common-sense

theory that illusions are imaginary sense mistaken for real

ones. But to assign illusion to the class of imaginary sense is

misleading, because there is no special quality that sense can

have in virtue of which they are illusory. If there were it

could never be detected, since mistakes of the same general kind

are made about real sense, especially in unfamiliar cir-

cumstances (e.g. the child or savage looking at a mirror for the

first time and thinking the image to be behind the plane of the

mirror, so attempting to reach at it through or behind the

glass). It is not a special quality of imaginary sense, it is a

mistaken interpretation.

We were wrong, therefore, to define illusory sensa as im-


aginary sensa which we mistake for real ones. Illusory
sensa can be defined without referring to the distinction
between imaginary and real. Any sensum is illusory in so
far as we make an error about it. This error does not
consist in mistaking it for a different sensum . . . . All
that there can ever be in a sensum is directly present to
us in the act of sensation. We may be mistaken in believing
that another person in our circumstances would have a
similar one; but we cannot, in seeing a red patch, mistake
it for a blue one. The mistakes we make about our sensa are
mistakes about their relations with other sense, possible
or expected. (PA, 189).

__________________
14 Cf. also Rubinoff, CRM, 210-11. For Rubinoff's interpre-
tation of Collingwood on perception, see CRM, 107-12.
354

Similarly the term "appearance" is not a quality of a sensum

(such as the quality that the short man has who is further away

than this closer tall man, the two being "really" the same

height). On the contrary the term refers to the interpretation

placed on the two sensa, first of all as resembling one another

(as men) and secondly the judgment that the further or future

experience of these sense will or will not continue to show the

same kind of resemblance (when standing next to one another they

will have the same height) (PA, 190-91).

And finally, the term "image" is used to describe the

kind of relation that exists between, for example, a photograph

and the scene photographed, both of which are directly

inspectable and comparable by us in distinct acts of perception.

But if perception itself is explained on this analogy, it

presumes that we can compare our sensa (the images) with their

originals (the real objects), a condition of the analogy which

cannot be fulfilled (PA, 191-92).

Collingwood's concluding summary of the discussion of

the common sense distinction between real and imaginary sensa is

worth quoting:

Sensa cannot be divided, by any test whatever, into real


and imaginary; sensations cannot be divided into real sen-
sations and imaginations. That experience which we call
sensation is of one kind only, and is not amenable to the
distinction between real and unreal, true and false,
viridical and illusory. That which is true
355

or false is thought; and our sensa are called real and


illusory insofar as we think truly or falsely about them.
To think about them is to interpret them, which means
stating the relations in which they stand to other sensa,
actual or possible. A real sensum means a sensum correctly
interpreted; an illusory sensum, one falsely interpreted.
And an imaginary sensum means one which has not been
interpreted at all: either because we have tried to
interpret it and failed, or because we have not tried . . .
. They are sense in respect of which the interpretative
work of thought has been done well, or done ill, or left
undone. (PA, 194).

4. Attention, Freedom and Corrupt Consciousness.

How does this discussion of sensation and imagination

stand with respect to Collingwood's refutation of the principal

doctrine of realism? We stated above that this denial entails

the affirmation that knowing makes a difference to the object

known. We begin to see the way in which this affirmation is made

in Collingwood's philosophy of mind. For first-order thinking,

"knowing" is an act of interpretation, and the "difference" it

makes to the object is the difference between a sensum

uninterpreted, a sensum interpreted, a sensum interpreted

incorrectly, and a sensum interpreted correctly. The "object"

for first order thinking is sensory experience ("feeling" in

Collingwood's terminology), the object insofar as it is felt.

The term "real" in this context is applied or withheld as a

judgment about sensa, and has a double sense: a rainbow, for

example, is "really there" in the sense that I see it--but then

so is the imaginary beast in the dark corner of the room, and

the snakes of delirium tremens. But in another sense the rainbow

is really there as the rain and


356

the sunshine (which I do not see), or the things in terms of

which I interpret my sensa (PA, 192-93).

And this is Collingwood's ultimate reply to the real-

ists' assertion of an object which is unaffected by the knowing

of it. Collingwood's answer, as stated in his reply to Moore, is

that it must be an entity that is imaginary--i.e. the assertion

of a sensum as already interpreted, or the mere assertion of the

possibility of repeating the interpretation of a sensum as "the

same" as a prior one, or as "unchanged" between episodes of

feeling. "And it is imagination, not sensation," Collingwood

writes, "to which appeal is made when empiricists appeal to

'experience"' (PA, 203). But what the radical empiricist wishes

to assert by an object unaffected by the knowing of it is an

object that is an uninterpreted sensum, and about this it would

be ridiculous to say that it would be just the same as it is if

it were not known at all.

But how does one know, on Collingwood's grounds, when a

sensum is correctly interpreted? If he cannot answer this, the

realists' withers remain unwrung. What the realist wishes to

know is how sense-experience, if it is a pure flux of unrelated

and fleeting sense, can give us knowledge of an "external

world.21 Merely denying that there is such a

____________________
21 This is the epistemological question of perception:
see E. Harris, Hypothesis and Perception (London, 1970), p. 237.
357

thing as an external world (as Collingwood seems to be implying

in the passage at PA, 166) does not solve the problem. It merely

shifts the locus of the question from epistemology to meta-

physics: for what then are the colors, sounds, etc. that con-

stitute the objects of acts of sensation? We have seen that

Berkeley's suggestion that they are mere ideas is rejected by

Collingwood as is the suggestion that it is a metaphysical

problem rather than an epistemological one (PA, 199). Colling-

wood does not mean to imply that there is no such thing as a

world of objects, or that "a world of objects external to the

knower and existing independently of him" is an utterly non-

sensical expression. What he is denying is that "external to"

and "independent of" are properties of sensa; they are actually

interpretations of imaginata (i.e. what a sensum would be like

as it exists in an unperceived state).

The real issue as Collingwood sees it is an epistemo-

logical one, and centers on the supposed passivity of sensation.

The thesis to be examined is that, in some way not clearly


defined, imagination contrasts with sensation as something
active with something passive, something we do with some-
thing we undergo, something under our control with some-
thing we cannot help, a making with a receiving . . . .
((But)) it is not a distinction between activity and pas-
sivity as such. Sensation is an activity. Even if we do it
only because we are stimulated to it by forces outside our
control, it is still something we do . . . . Nor is it a
distinction among passivities (things that happen to us, as
distinct from things we do, according as they are done to
us by external bodies impinging on our own, or by changes
arising within our own organism . . . .
358

For sensation, as well as imagination, is on its bodily


side a change arising within our own organism, and due to
the energies of that organism itself . . . . Nor is it a
distinction among activities (things we do) between those
we do of our own choice and those we cannot help doing. It
is in fact easier to stop seeing this paper, by shutting
one's eyes, than to stop imagining the frightful accident
which one saw yesterday. (PA, 196-97; emphasis mine).

The conclusion seems to be that if there is any distinction at

all between imagination and sensation the basis for this dis-

tinction must fall altogether outside the category of activity--

passivity (cf. NL, 5.4-5.49). This category may be at home in

the mechanical realm of matter, where forces are exerted by

pushing and pulling; but in the realm of thought it is not

adequate. Thought is free as matter is not: to be a thought is

to have an essential freedom to succeed or fail--to be "bipolar"

as Collingwood says.

The empiricists' problem of "sense data" is therefore

poorly conceived, because the assumption of sensa as "given"

(from the Latin, datum) is false as a presupposition (PA, 196,

200). The empiricists (including Hume) failed to appreciate

adequately the intermediating function of imagination in the

sensation-intellection relation. The freedom of imagination

falls between the freedom of sensation (which is the freedom of

a spontaneous, living, sentient organism) and that of in-

tellection (which is the freedom of choice between alternatives

consciously conceived) (PA, 197). The freedom of imagination

consists in the alternatives of recognizing a feeling as

belonging to oneself or
359

in refusing to so recognize it (PA, 224). This refusal or the

process of "disowning" feelings is what Collingwood calls

"corrupt consciousness" (PA, 217-19).

But to understand the intermediation of imagination, its

freedom, and the corruption of consciousness it is necessary to

identify and characterize the function of imagination which

transforms sensa into imaginata. This function is "attention"

(alternatively called "awareness" or simply "consciousness"--PA,

206).

Thought . . . detects "relations between sensa" . . . But


in order that we may detect resemblances or any other
relations between things, we must first identify each of
them: distinguish each as a thing by itself and appreciate
its qualities as those qualities we find it to possess,
even though as yet (not having determined their relations
to qualities found elsewhere) we are not in a position to
name them . . . . This act of appreciating something, just
as it stands, before I can begin to classify it is what we
call attending to it. (PA, 203).

Collingwood is careful to distinguish attention from both in-

tellection and sensation. As distinct from intellection, at-

tention selects and divides, but it does not abstract: abstrac-

tion is a higher function involved in the formation of concepts

("redness" as opposed to "this red patch"), whereas attention

"appreciates" a sensible quality "as it presents itself to us, a

concrete individual" (PA, 204). Nonetheless attention is

"thought in its
360

absolutely fundamental and original shape" (PA, 216).22 At the

merely psychical level, the distinction between conscious and

unconscious does not exist. But the instant there is added the

activity of attention, "the block of feeling present to the mind

is split in two" the conscious part being that part of feeling

attended to, the unconscious part being the ignored remainder of

the field, the negative counterpart of attention, or its

penumbra (PA, 204-05).23

____________________
22 Since attention is both (a) thought in its minimal
sense, and (b) not abstract, Donagan's contention that Colling-
wood's later philosophy of mind (which starts with The
Principles of Art) is founded on the recognition that "all forms
of thinking-from the highest to the lowest, are conceptual,
and . . . all concepts are abstract" (LPC, 14) is obviously
false. Since an essentially similar characterization of the
function of attention is made in The New Leviathan (see NL,
4.18, 4.24, 4.5-4.6, 7.2-7.39) it is doubtful whether Donagan's
contention holds even for The New Leviathan alone (in section 6
of this chapter we shall see that The New Leviathan poses
special problems for any consistent interpretation of
Collingwood's philosophy of mind). In The Principles of Art, at
least, it is clear that "thinking" is a term whose extension is
broader than Donagan is willing to allow: it includes
imagination, which is not abstract, but concrete. In a later
passage Collingwood contrasts analytic and abstract thought with
imagination, and writes: "These ((i.e. analytic and abstract
thought)) are not the only kinds of thought . . . . They are
given merely as examples of what ((intellect)) does which im-
agination, never analytic and never abstract, cannot do" (PA,
254; cf. PA, 287). As we shall shortly see, attention is a
function of imagination.

23 Collingwood recognized that there is a proper func-


tion for psychology in the study of "unconscious feeling" at the
psychical level, but insisted that it still rested on a more
general philosophical principle--this principle being that
consciousness has a double object including not only sensation
but the object of sensation (PA, 206). Collingwood's attacks on
psychology all have this intent behind them as an unspoken
premise: empirical psychology cannot absorb the labor of
philosophical psychology because it depends for its existence
361

On the other side attention is distinguished from feeling in

having the bipolarity that is proper to thought:

Attention . . . has a double object where sentience has a


single. What we hear, for example, is a sound. What we
attend to is two things at once: a sound, and our act of
hearing it. The act of sensation is not present to itself,
but it is present, together with its own sensum, to the act
of attention. This is, in fact, the special significance of
the con- in the word consciousness; it indicates the
togetherness of the two things, sensation and sensum, both
of which are present to the conscious mind . . . . Thus the
difference between seeing and looking, or hearing and
listening, is that a person who is said to be looking is
described as aware of his own seeing as well as of the
thing he sees. (PA, 206).

We see here a clearer statement of what Collingwood meant in

Religion and Philosophy when he said that the esse of mind is

not cogitare simply, but de hac re cogitare (RP, 100; FR, 172).

What is essential to the act is not only sensation or its ob-

ject, but both taken together. Collingwood's use of the term

"consciousness" in connection with higher processes of thought

indicates that the same is true for all the successive levels of

thought (cf. IH, 291, 306).24

__________________
on the philosophical analysis of consciousness. But Col-
lingwood's insistence on this point should not blind the reader
to the complimentary affirmation that philosophical psychology
cannot absorb empirical psychology, because the psychical level
(at which consciousness and unconscious are not distinguished)
merges with the physiological and is not directly analyzable by
the phenomenological analysis of consciousness.

24 Because sensation proper (as distinct from percep-


tion, which is sensation attended to) is "not present to itself"
and has a single object rather than a double, it cannot properly
be called "consciousness" in the technical sense of the term as
defined at PA, 206. Sensation proper exists
362

Because attention is thought, and because thought is

bipolar, it is possible for attention to make mistakes--and this

is the sense in which it is free in the minimal sense of that

term as applicable to thought. A conscious being is not free to

decide what feelings he shall have, but he is free to decide

what feelings he shall place in the focus of his consciousness.

This is not a mere response to stimulus (which is the level of

freedom of a sentient organism), but it is also not yet the

freedom of choice of alternative plans of action. It is

intermediate between the two (PA, 207-08). The attention to

feeling modifies it by "domesticating" it, allowing the one who

attends (the rudimentary self) to dominate the feeling and to

perpetuate it indefinitely (PA, 20609). But it does so only at a

certain risk--the risk inherent in the freedom it possesses. The

risk is the danger of becoming a corrupt consciousness:

As thought ((attention)) must have that bipolarity which


belongs to thought as such. It is an activity which may be
well or ill done;

____________________
at the psychical level of pure feeling, at which the distinction
between conscious and unconscious does not yet exist. The
objects of sensation are merely feelings present to conscious-
ness; by attending to them, consciousness perpetuates them and
thus prepares them for further acts of interpretation. However
as we shall see in section 6, in The New Leviathan Collingwood
introduces a "diffuse consciousness of feeling" at a level below
that of attention proper, and assigns "selective attention" to
the second level of thought--thought about thought--as one of
its practical functions. It is clear that "consciousness" is not
being used there in its technical sense.
363

what it thinks may be true or false. But this seems


paradoxical; for since it is not concerned with the
relations between things, and hence does not think in terms
of concepts or generalizations, it cannot err, as intellect
can, by referring things to the wrong concepts . . . . But
the statement "This is how I feel" does imply bipolarity.
It has an opposite: "This is not how I feel;" and to assert
it is to deny this opposite . . . . ((Consciousness)) lives
by rejecting error. A true consciousness is the confession
to ourselves of our feelings; a false consciousness would
be disowning them, i.e. thinking about one of them "That
feeling is not mine" . . . . I call this the "corruption"
of consciousness, because consciousness permits itself to
be bribed or corrupted in the discharge of its
functions . . . . (PA, 216-17).

The corruption of consciousness (also called bad-faith, insin-

cerity, self-deception, or in psychological terms, repression,

projection, dissociation, and fantasy-building) belongs to

neither of the commonly recognized species of untruths—errors or

lies; these belong to higher levels of thought (PA, 218-19; cf.

PA, 115, 283). But it is an example of untruth in its minimal

sense, and hence of evil; not exactly a crime or vice (because

not fully a choice) and not exactly a disease (because not

suffered passively), corrupt consciousness is "a kind of sheer

or undifferentiated evil, evil in itself, as yet

undifferentiated into evil suffered or misfortune and evil done

or wickedness" (PA, 219-20).25

______________________
25 It is not difficult to see why Collingwood regarded
realists as arch-propagandists of a coming fascism (A, 167).
Fascism is a celebration of irrationalism and is hence the re-
sult of a kind of corruption of consciousness: it disowns ra-
tionality and its attendant emotions. Realism, by dissociating
theory and practice, and denying that knowledge has any effect
on its object, and furthermore by treating moral subjects in a
364

We have seen the sense in which Collingwood regards the

act of attention as intermediate between sensation and

intellection, the extent of its freedom, and its rule in the

corruption of consciousness. It remains to determine the way in

which attention is to be regarded as a function of imagination.

The act of attention, Collingwood has been insisting, is the act

which converts "impressions" (feelings) into "ideas"

(imaginata). In so doing it modifies the feelings attended to:

feeling is no longer something in complete flux, it is dominated

and perpetuated by the act of attention. The modified feeling is

no longer a "bare feeling" it is a feeling of which we have

become conscious (PA, 209, 213). To say that a feeling is

attended to is to say that it is an uninterpreted sensum that is

ready for interpretation, so that "regarded as names for a

certain kind or level of experience, the words consciousness

((or attention)) and imagination are synonymous" (PA, 215). But

within a single experience they can be distinguished. Attention

is the act which converts a bare sensum into one ready for

interpretation, and imagination is the result of that

conversion. "Imagination is thus the new form which feeling

_____________________
purely theoretical way, opens a path for disowning rationality
by denying its applicability--and hence its expression in moral
acts. Whatever moves passions is whatever causes acts, and
rationality (ex hypothesi) does not move passions. This paves
the way for a political movement that plays directly on passions
without regard for reason. Cf. EM, 133-42; NL, 35.43-35.44.
365

takes when transformed by the activity of consciousness" (PA,


215).26

But once again we must raise the empiricist's question:

if an imaginatum is a sensum that is ready for interpretation,

is that readiness something that is found in the sensum or

something given to it by an act of consciousness? It is clear

that Collingwood is straining to make consciousness, or thought

in its minimum sense, speak with an active voice; but it is not

clear whether there is any contribution to this conversation

from the side of the sensa, or from a world of nature beyond

them. It is also clear that Collingwood is maintaining his

assertion that imagination is indifferent to the reality or

unreality of its objects (PA, 136) --an assertion that dates

back to Speculum Mentis (SM, 60, 112). But if feeling is

ambiguous with respect to the category of activity-passivity

_____________________
26 The term, "imagination," like the terms "thought" and
"consciousness," has a very broad extension in Collingwood's
philosophy. Although in The Principles of Art his discussion
tends to confine it to a level of thought between sensation and
intellection, it is capable of operating at higher order levels
of thought as well. In The Idea of History he speaks of an "a
priori" imagination (and we may recall that "a priori" is a term
he uses to distinguish thought from feeling). This a priori
imagination (a) does the entire work of historical
reconstruction, (b) operates in artistic creation, and (c)
functions in perception by "supplementing and consolidating the
data of perception in the way so well analyzed by Kant, by
presenting to us objects of possible perception which are not
actually perceived" (IH, 241-42). If a priori imagination
operates even at the level of historical reconstruction, it
clearly escapes confinement to a strictly intermediate level in
the scale of forms of knowledge. It is simply, in Kantian terms,
the faculty of re-presentation.
366

(and in The New Leviathan Collingwood explicitly extends this

ambiguity to all the other Kantian categories), and if

imagination is indifferent to the distinction between real and

unreal, the reader is left wondering how any interpretation can

be lifted off the face of an utterly indeterminate flux of

sensa. And if it cannot, the obvious question is how knowledge

of an "external world" (i.e. the world extrinsic to our organs

of sense)--in Collingwood's terms, the "not-self," is possible

at all.

5. Idealism and the Limitations of Phenomenology.

In The Principles of Art (and to a lesser extent even in

The New Leviathan) Collingwood seems to deliberately choose

language that refuses to take sides in the realism-idealism

controversy. As Louis O. Mink points out, there are some lethal

booby-traps left for anyone who tries to decide the issue from

Collingwood's texts (MHD, 112). A case in point is the following

passage, in which Collingwood is trying to reconcile the

characterization of imaginata (a) as uninterpreted sensa, and

(b) as feeling dominated and perpetuated by consciousness:

Now it has already been argued . . . that the work of de-


termining relations between things must depend on something
prior to it, namely having these things held before the
mind in such a way that we can compare them with one
another, and so become able to see how they resemble one
another, and so forth. We must know what each is in itself
before we can decide how they are related. To know what a
given thing is in itself is not, of course, the same as
367

knowing what kind of a thing it is . . . . Our knowledge of


what it is in itself, if we try to express that in words,
will be stated in some such phrase as "this is what I see,"
or, since to call my act one of seeing is already to
distinguish, "this is how I feel." . . . And we become able
to say this, not through bare sensation, but through
consciousness of sensation. What makes us able to say it is
that we have, by the work of attention, at once selected
and perpetuated some element which we find in the field of
sensation, and some corresponding element in the sensory
act. (PA, 212-13).

Collingwood apparently finds no difficulty in asserting of one

and the same sensum that it has elements which are at once se-

lected, perpetuated, and found, and that corresponding elements

exist in the sensory act. A few pages later a similar land mine

is planted for explorers at a higher level: "The work of

intellect," Collingwood writes, "is to apprehend or construct

relations" (PA, 216, 255-56). Which is it? The reader will not

get any direct satisfaction from Collingwood in answer to this

question.27 The reason for such deliberate ambiguity may be

either that Collingwood

____________________
27 Cf. Mink, MHD, 112-13: "Collingwood does not
want to decide whether thought 'apprehends' or 'constructs,'
'finds' or 'puts.' In his view, it does both. As the activity of
converting implicit differences into explicit distinctions, it
seems to itself, at any level, to be apprehending. But as an
object of consciousness to a higher level, it seems to be con-
structing. Experience, one might say, is the realist, reflection
on experience the idealist. Neither is false; what is false is
the presumption that there is irreducible logical in-
compatibility between the theories expressive of each. In the
dialectic of theories, realism states the viewpoint of any level
of consciousness from its own standpoint, idealism viewpoint of
any level of consciousness in its reflection on a lower level.
The theory of levels accounts for each by assigning to each a
function which cannot be usurped by the other." Cf. Rubinoff,
CRM, 29, 59, 116, 136 ff.
368

wished to leave the question open, or else that Collingwood held

to the simultaneous truths that (even at the level of

perception) knowing and the known interact, each making a

difference to the other.

There would be no way to decide between these two al-

ternatives were it not for a few pieces of circumstantial

evidence. We have already seen how Collingwood argues directly

against the realists' thesis that knowing (in this case, con-

sciousness) makes no difference to the object known (the sen-

sum): it is carried out directly in his attack on Moore (in the

doctrine of the unsensed sensum) as well as indirectly in his

discussion of the modification of feeling by attention. We have

also seen how Collingwood's attempt to save whatever sense he

could from the empiricists' tradition concerning "sense data"

led to his characterization of imagination (in the form of

selective attention) as intermediary between sensation and

intellection, and his dismissal of "sense data" as interpreted

imaginata masquerading as bare sensa. We have furthermore argued

that the entire discussion about empiricism would be a

non-sequitur and a diversionary aside if it were not that he

hoped to save something from the tradition. What he saved was

not, certainly, the ambiguous phrase, "sense data." Nor was it

the disjunctive proposition that either knowing affects the

known or the object affects the knower (but not both):


369

this disjunction is eliminated with the argument that

activity-passivity is a category inapplicable to bare,

uninterpreted sensation. What is saved is the role of thought as

active down to the level of sensation, where it is present as

the act of attention which alters feeling by perpetuating and

dominating it. But what is it that is dominated and perpetuated?

Here we must enter our circumstantial evidence.

A.--In the theory of art propounded in The Principles of

Art (see notes 7 and 8 above) Collingwood directly attacks the

realistic estheticians for distinguishing too sharply between

what is "found" in a work of art and what is "brought" to it by

an observer. The position of the realistic estheticians, who

maintain that "beauty" is something subjective that is "imputed"

to the art-object, is an attempt to rehabilitate an ancient

technical theory of art based on the false analogy between art

and craft. Collingwood describes what he takes to be their

position as follows:

(T)he technical theory depends on distinguishing what we


find in the work of art, its actual sensuous qualities, as
put there by the artist, from something else which we do
not strictly find in it, but rather import into it from our
own stores of experience and powers of imagination. The
first is conceived as objective, really belonging to the
work of art: the second as subjective, belonging not to it
but to activities which go on in us when we contemplate it.
The peculiar value of this contemplation, then, is
conceived as lying not in the first thing but in the
second. Any one having the use of his senses could see all
the colours and shapes that a picture contains . . . but
((to enjoy an esthetic experience)) he must use his
imagination, and so proceed from the first part of the
370

experience, which is given in sensation, to the second


part, which is imaginatively reconstructed. This seems to
be the position of the "realistic" philosophers who
maintain that what they call "beauty" is subjective.
148-49).

Such distinctions as used by realistic estheticians like Samual

Alexander do not do justice to what Collingwood thinks the true

situation to be:

The distinction between what we find and what we bring is


altogether too naive . . . . If ((an artist)) paints his
picture in such a way that we, when we look at it using our
imagination, find ourselves enjoying an imaginary ex-
perience of total activity like that which he enjoyed when
painting it, there is not much sense in saying that we
bring this experience with us to the picture and do not
find it there . . . . No doubt there is a sense in which we
bring it with us. Our finding of it is not something that
merely happens to us, it is something we do . . . . The
imaginary experience . . . is the kind of experience we are
capable of having. Thus the two parts of the experience are
not contrasted in the way in which we fancied them to be.
There is no justification for saying that the sensuous part
of it is something we find and the imaginary part something
we bring . . . . We bring our powers of vision with us, and
find what they reveal. Similarly, we bring our imaginative
powers with us, and find what they reveal: namely an
imaginary experience of total activity which we find in the
picture because the painter has put it there. (PA, 149-51).

Now if this is true for a work of art, it must be true in some

sense for perception in general, and also for scientific ob-

servation, inasmuch as the same sensation and imagination are at

work--even if one does not assume that the experience of nature

is like an imaginary experience of total activity which is "put"

there by an artist. What Collingwood is saying is that sensation

itself is an active process of an agent, and this


371

is what he means when he says that it "makes" its sensa. He does

not mean that the objects extrinsic to our sensory organs are

"created" ex nihilo by our minds. But he is also saying that our

powers of vision find what they reveal--and the revelation

involved is the process whereby somehow (and this is not ever

specified by Collingwood) information is passed from objects

within our field of experience as a presentation of

uninterpreted sensum. It is the difference between "seeing" and

"looking" or between "hearing" and" listening" that Collingwood

is referring to when he adds the act of attention to this field

of felt experience, and not the difference between a nothing and

a something. Or to put it another way, the difference that

knowing (as perception) makes is not the difference between

there being something where there was formerly nothing at all;

it is rather the difference between something present but

indefinite (an uninterpreted sensum) and something present and

now more definite (a sensum ready for interpretation--present

and sustained). But Collingwood is not denying the presence of

something--on this The Principles of Art is clear:

Theoretically, the artist is a person who comes to know


himself, to know his own emotion . . . . But this knowing
of himself is a making of himself . . . . Moreover, his
knowing of this . . . world is also the making of the new
world which he is coming to know. The world he has come to
know is a world consisting of language; a world where
everything has the property of expressing
372

emotion. In so far as this world is thus expressive or


significant, it is he that has made it so. He has not, of
course, made it "out of nothing." He is not God, but a
finite mind still at a very elementary stage in the
development of its powers. He has made it "out of” what is
presented-to him in the stil1 more elementary stage of
purely psychical experience: colors, sounds, and so forth.
(PA, 291-92; emphasis mine).

B.--As if in confirmation of this conclusion that some-

thing must be presented to consciousness that is not created ex

nihilo by that consciousness, Collingwood at one point even

adopts the metaphorical terminology of matter and form to de-

scribe the levels of mental functions:

(I)n the relation between any one level of experience and


the next above it . . . the higher level differs from the
lower in having a new principle of organization; this does
not supersede the old, it is superimposed on it. The lower
type of experience is perpetuated in the higher type in a
way in which a pre-existing matter is perpetuated when a
new form is imposed on it . . . . In this metaphorical
sense of the words, any new and higher level of experience
can be described in either of two ways. Formally, it is
something quite new and unique, capable of being described
only in terms of itself. Materially, it is only a peculiar
combination of elements already existing at the lower
level, and susceptible of description in terms of these
lower elements. Consciousness . . . is formally
unique . . . . Materially, it is only a certain new
arrangement of psychical experiences. (PA, 233).

Would Collingwood accept this metaphor as applicable at

the level of sensation? Is it not possible that there is a

similar relationship existing at the interface between sensation

and the world of objects extrinsic to the organs of sensation,

such that sensation can be regarded as formally "something quite

new and unique, capable of being described


373

only in terms of itself," but materially it is "only a certain

new arrangement" of material entities--cells composed of organic

and inorganic molecules, functioning together as an organ in

response to physical stimuli from the environment? (Cf. NL,

9.5-9.56).

From the point of view restricted by the self-imposed

limitations of a science of mind, we must answer (as Collingwood

does in The New Leviathan) that we do not know (see NL,

5.2-5.4). But before involving ourselves in a discussion of the

presuppositions of a phenomenology of consciousness, we must

enter further pieces of evidence from The Principles of Art in

which Collingwood lets himself escape for a moment from the

confines of these presuppositions.

C.--Where Collingwood is arguing that the distinction

between real and imaginary sense is not a distinction between

activity and passivity, nor among passivities, nor among ac-

tivities, in the passages deleted from our above quotation

Collingwood argues as follows:

Response to stimulus is in some sense passive, in so far as


it cannot arise without a stimulus; but it is also active,
in so far as it is a response. If I am a kind of factory
for converting wave-lengths into colours, air disturbances
into sounds, and so forth, as the materialists
believe . . . there is work done in that conversion; the
machinery is active, even if it is controlled by no manager
or foreman . . . . For sensation, as well as imagination,
is on its bodily side a change arising within our own
organism, and due to the energies of that organism itself.
The afferent nerves through whose activity we feel a
pressure on a finger-tip are not
374

solid rods conveying that pressure itself to the brain;


they are functioning in their own way as a special kind of
living tissue; if they ceased to function in that way, no
amount of pressure on the finger could give rise to
sensation. (PA, 196-97).

Now if Collingwood meant to come up with a radical idealist

explanation for sensation, and one which hence eliminated the

need for asserting that objects make a difference to the knowing

of them, it is difficult to see why he would be considering such

physiological mechanisms at all. No doubt, he is arguing that

thought (as attention) dominates the "feeling" provided within

the psychic level of experience, and that even at the psychical

level the organs of senses are not utterly passive. But he is

not denying that the physiological mechanisms provide something

for thought to dominate, or that the organs of sensation are

"stimulated" by forms of physical energy.

D.--Several pages later when Collingwood is discussing

the way in which feeling modified by attention (and notice that

the modification is only stated to be in terms of time and

use--attention perpetuates and dominates feeling-and not in

terms of content: it does not modify a red into a blue, or blue

into loud, or sweet into hard; cf. PA, 189) he talks about the

psychological phenomenon of color fading, which is compensated

by the act of attention: 28

_________________
28 In The New Leviathan Collingwood uses this identical
example, but gives it precisely the opposite interpretation:
"colours themselves as
375

In the flux of sensation, one pattern of the total sensory


field is being replaced by another. Attention now focuses
itself on one
element in that field: for example this scarlet patch. As I
look, the red is actually fading; it is being obscured by
the superimposition of its own after-image, which dulls the
scarlet moment by moment. But by attending to the scarlet
and neglecting everything else I create a kind of
compensation for this fading ((By this)) progressive
refocusing of attention . . . we do not lift any sensa, as
such, out of their native flux; but we obtain a new kind of
experience by moving as it were with the flux, so that the
self, and the object are (so to speak) at rest relatively
to each other for an appreciable time. What we have done is
. . . liberated ourselves for a moment from the flux of
sensation and kept something before us long enough to get a
fair sight of it. (PA, 210).

Collingwood's hesitation to accept fully these metaphors ("as it

were. . . so to speak") should not blind the reader to the

affirmation of the point at issue. It is a temporal modification

of feeling that is being made, and by engaging in acts of

attention "something" is kept before us, and for long enough

time a "fair sight of it" may be gotten--not by lifting off any

sense (attention is not abstraction) but by running with it (so

to speak) so that it appears stable compared to its moving

background.

_______________________
we actually see them are vague; and so with sounds, smells,
emotions, etc. We never see anything exactly any colour. However
carefully we look at a colour it remains ambiguous. Indeed,
looking at it carefully creates a new ambiguity; for the eye
becomes fatigued and a complimentary after-image interposes
itself between the eye and the colour at which one is looking,
so that the mere looking at a colour dims it" (NL, 5.71). If
"looking carefully" means "attending to" the colour, it seems
that this process adds to the fading of it rather than
compensating for it.
376

E.--When Collingwood raises the question about how long

a period of time a sensum has to be perpetuated by attention in

order to be retained, he replies that (from the perspective of

The Principles of Art) no definite answer can be given (PA,

210). But The Idea of Nature provides us with the start of an

answer, and at the same time suggests a reason for the use of

terms which express qualified confidence in the physiological

descriptions in the previously cited passages. In discussing the

contemporary view of nature, Collingwood argues that when the

impact of evolutionary science began to be thought out it had

already, in the 19th century methodology of history, a model for

dealing with a world of constant change:

History had by now established itself as a science, that


is, a progressive inquiry in which conclusions are solidly
and demonstratively established. It had thus been proved by
experiment that scientific knowledge was possible con-
cerning objects that were constantly changing . . . . The
historical conception of scientifically knowable change or
process was applied, under the name of evolution, to the
natural world (IH, 13).

One of the consequences of the evolutionary view of nature is

that, as Whitehead put it, "there is no nature at an instant,"

and therefore the study of natural forms of motion requires a

notion of "minimum space" and "minimum time." In the latter case

this issues in the principle that "different orders of

substances take different orders of time-lapse to exist" (IN,

22; cf. EM, 266-67). But this principle does not warrant

adoption of an idealistic stance.


377

The principle . . . opens no door to subjective idealism.


One might express it by saying that how the world of nature
appears to us depends on how long we take to observe it . .
. . This, though true, would be misleading . . . . How the
natural world appears to us does certainly depend on how
long we take to observe it; but that is because when we
observe it for a certain length of time we observe the
processes which require that length of time in order to
occur. (IN, 23). 29

But just as we noticed Chapter VI that historical knowledge is

limited in one direction by the "facts" at the historian's dis-

posal, so observation in science is limited in physical situ-

ations in an exactly analogous fashion:

Our experimental knowledge of the natural world is based on


our acquaintance with those natural processes which we can
observe experimentally. This acquaintance is limited
downwards in space and time by our inability to observe any
process that occupies less than a certain amount of space
or a certain lapse of time, and upwards by the impos-
sibility of observing any process that occupies more space
or more time than the range of human vision or the time
covered by human records . . . These limits, upper and
lower, of our observations in space and time have been
greatly enlarged by the apparatus of the modern scientist,
but they still exist, and are ultimately imposed on us by
our constitution as animals of a definite size and living
at a definite rate . . . . The natural world which human
scientists can study by observation and experiment is an
anthropocentric world; it consists only of those natural
processes whose time-phase and space-range are within the
limits of our observation. (IN, 24).

___________________________
29 Cf. IN, 84: "Nature stays put, and is the same
whether we understand it or not;" and IH, 133: "In
science, . . . the facts are empirical facts, perceived as they
occur. In history . . . fact . . . is not immediately given. It
is arrived at inferentially by a process of interpreting data."
378

In these passages Collingwood is not writing as if the

"natural world" external to our sense organs can have no effect

on our knowing of it. In fact it is a presupposition of natural

science that there is such a world and that it can make itself

known to us (cf. IN, 175; EM, 222-23). The statement that the

natural world observed by science is an anthropocentric world

only echoes the Kantian restriction of scientific knowledge to

the bounds of experience possible for a human being of limited

capacities; it does not deny that there is something there to be

known.

F.--Confirmation that we are on the right track comes,

indirectly, from the Essay on Metaphysics. In a passage in which

Collingwood is discussing the extent to which Aristotle's

metaphysics is compatible with contemporary scientific

presuppositions, Collingwood singles out as a rejected presup-

position the belief that the existence of nature is an observed

fact:

Aristotle thought . . . that by merely using our senses we


learn that a natural world exists. He did not realize that
the use of our senses can never inform us that what we
perceive by using them is a world of things that happen of
themselves and are not subject to control by our own art or
any one else's ((but is rather)) the first and fundamental
presupposition, on which alone any science of nature can
arise . . . . For when we speak of the existence of natural
things we mean (as Aristotle very truly says) the existence
of things that move of themselves or events that happen of
themselves. The idea of movement or happening . . . is
contained in the idea of a natural world. The idea of
motion, therefore (for if the world of nature is a world of
bodies all the events in nature are motions), cannot be an
idea which we obtain, as the Greeks thought we obtained it,
through the use of our senses. It is an idea which we bring
with us in
379

the shape of an absolute presupposition to the work of


interpreting what we get by using our senses. The
proposition that there is motion in nature is a
metaphysical proposition. (EM, 215, 217).

Collingwood is not saying that we do not get something by the

use of our senses, but only that through sensation we do not get

the concept of motion or of an existent world of nature; what we

get are uninterpreted sensa. And he is not saying that a world

of nature and of natural objects does not exist, but only that

assertion of its existence is not justifiable as a simple

product of sensual experience, but rather through the correct

interpretation of sensa. And finally, Collingwood is not ruling

out the possibility that the "data" presented to us in sensation

can be given and retained, but that "real, empirical knowledge"

of the natural world (or of any world of fact, including the

historical world of evidence) absolutely presupposes the

existence of a world of nature.

G.--These passages also shed light on our problem in-

sofar as they provide us with a clue to understanding why, in

The Principles of Art, Collingwood hedges in his assent to the

legitimacy of the physical basis for psychical sense. The reason

is not that he refuses to take sides on the realism-idealism

debate, but rather because he is bound by his own

presuppositions concerning the proper limits to the methods of

mental science. In The New Leviathan this rule is stated in

negative fashion
380

as the Fallacy of Swapping Horses:

I have mentioned two approaches to the problem of self--


knowledge: the natural sciences and the sciences of man . .
. . Each is valid. Each is a search for truth, and neither
goes unrewarded. Each, therefore, has its own problems and
must solve them by its own methods . . . . Of these two
different forms of science, the one that has started a hare
must catch it. The reason is plain. You can only solve a
problem which you recognize to be a problem. The same
methods, therefore, which led to the asking of a question
must lead to the answering of it . . . . No amount of
admiration for some other horse must betray you into the
Fallacy of Swapping Horses. If the wretched horse called
Mental Science has stuck you in midstream you can flog him,
or you can coax him, or you can get out and lead him; or
you can drown, as better men than you have drowned before.
But you must not swap him even for the infinitely superior
horse called Natural Science. (NL, 2.6-2.73).

As we shall see in section six of this chapter, Collingwood's

efforts to stay strictly within the bounds of this rule in The

New Leviathan lead him into difficulties concerning his char-

acterization of feeling. In The Principles of Art, however, he

occasionally strays across the border, as in the above passages

where he appeals to physiological descriptions. But in one very

important passage he gives us a glimpse of how natural science

(in the form of behaviorism) and mental science are related. The

passage is cryptic, shimmering with interpretative possibilities

and ambiguities, and therefore we must quote it at length:

At the merely psychical level, the distinction between


conscious and unconscious does not exist . . . . The mind
here exists only in the shape of sentience . . . . When the
light of consciousness falls on such occupations, they
change their character; what
381

was sentience becomes imagination. Hence we cannot study


psychical experience, or even assure ourselves that it
exists, by inquiring of our own consciousness; that can
only tell us . . . of the things to which it
attends . . . . Those which are utterly outside its ken
must be studied by other methods. But what are these
methods to be? Behaviorism has dealt with the problem, and
gone some way towards a correct solution, by dismissing
"introspection," that is, inquiry made of consciousness, as
futile, and identifying the psychical with the
physiological. The method thus devised is perfectly sound,
but for one flaw. Unless we had independent knowledge both
that there is such a thing as psychical experience and what
kind of thing it is, the problem which the behaviorist
solves by his method could never arise. This independent
knowledge is derived neither from observing bodily
"behavior" nor from questioning consciousness, but from
analyzing consciousness, and thus discovering its relation
to a more elementary kind of experience which it
presupposes. The principle of this analysis depends on the
fact that attention (or as we may now indifferently call
it, consciousness or awareness) has a double object where
sentience has a single . . . . ((A)) person who is said to
be looking is described as aware of his own seeing as well
as of the thing he sees. (PA, 205-06).

Let us at the risk of some repetition try to be clear about what

this important passage is asserting. (1) Psychical experience

(the level of pure sensation) cannot be studied or shown to

exist by inquiring of (putting questions to) consciousness, (2)

the reason being that consciousness alters sensation.

(3)Therefore "introspection" (not in the sense used in his

discussion of empiricism, but as the putting of questions to

consciousness) is ruled out as a method for studying psychical

experience (but not as a method for studying

consciousness)--some other method is required. (4) Behaviorism

(a natural science) has devised a method perfectly sound for

this purpose--a method which (a) rejects "introspection," and

(b) identifies the psychical


382

with the physiological (and therefore subject to the

investigative methods of the physical sciences). (5) The only

flaw with behaviorism as a method is that it fails to recognize

that unless it presupposes (a) that psychical experience exists,

and (b) it is a certain kind of thing (namely a physiological

phenomenon but present to conscious beings), it would have

nothing to investigate. (6) This knowledge is established

independently of both "introspection" and behavioral study; it

is established by the analysis of consciousness. (7) The

principle of this analysis is that consciousness has a double

object, whereas sentience has a single.

But what then is this "analysis of consciousness"?

Judging by the "principle" of its analysis, it is nothing other

than phenomenology: the principle cited is merely a restatement

of the principle of intentionality. But then phenomenological

analysis must not only be able to tell us that psychical

experience exists (because sentience has an object?) but also

what kind of a thing it is (something present to us as a

concrete sensum, to be attended to).30 This passage is

____________________
30 This does not solve all the interpretative difficul-
ties in the passage under consideration. It is not clear, for
example, how the analysis of consciousness can discover the re-
lationship of consciousness to a more elementary kind of ex-
perience (the psychical level) without altering it in the pro-
cess, because analysis must itself be a kind of consciousness.
383

therefore isomorphic with all those other remarks about psy-

chology scattered through his writings, from his rejection of

the psychologistic reduction of religion in Religion and

Philosophy to his assault on psychologism as a metaphysical

pseudo-science in the Essay on Metaphysics (cf. EM, 112-42). In

them he is arguing not that psychology (in this case,

behaviorism) does not have a legitimate field of investigation,

but that it presupposes philosophical psychology (in this case,

phenomenological analysis).31

But once the "flaw" in behaviorism is made good by ac-

ceptance of the presuppositions established by phenomenological

analysis, its methods are sound for examining the psychical

level of a natural phenomenon, a level at which "introspection"

is futile. And in The Idea of Nature Collingwood is not bound by

the limitations of the inquiry into consciousness by the methods

of introspection. The Principles of Art occupies an intermediary

position--but Collingwood's sense of the limitations presupposed

in a given piece of thinking prevents him from giving a complete

account of perception, and from giving full assent to the

____________________
31 By calling Collingwood's "analysis of consciousness"
phenomenological we do not mean to imply a conscious identifi-
cation of Collingwood with the continental phenomenological
movement begun by Husserl. If there is any such connection
between Collingwood and the phenomenologists, it is nowhere
explicit in his writings. Furthermore Collingwood would not
accept phenomenological analysis as purely descriptive; he in-
sisted always that it was "normative" or "criteriological." Cf.
EM, 109; PA, 171, note.
384

physiological aspects of perception--the level at which objects

external to our sense organs initiate changes in those organs.

H.--We find an actual instance of an "analysis of con-

sciousness" in one of the epilegomena to The Idea of History

--"History as the Re-Enactment of Past Experience." The analysis

is dialectical: it takes the form of a number of objections

raised by hypothetical realists and idealists to the assertion

that historical knowledge is possible only on the condition that

the historian can re-enact in his own mind past acts of thought.

We shall take up this argument in Chapter IX, so we shall not at

this point enter into the details of this dialectical analysis.

It suffices to say that in this epilegomenon we have an actual

case in which Collingwood argues against both the realist's view

that acts of thought and their objects are independent of one

another (and therefore that although two acts of thought may

have the same object, they are not the same thoughts because

thoughts are bound to subjects and the subjects are different

persons) and the idealist's view that objects are ultimately

dependent on thought (and therefore that in being thought an

object becomes subjective).32 On either view, he argues, history

is not possible (IH, 289-90).

___________________
32 Once again it is worth noting that part of this com-
plex argument is aimed at particular idealistic views of history
(Croce and Oakeshott), so the use of the term "idealism" here
should not be
385

Collingwood's answer to these objectors is ultimately that

thought is neither purely subjective nor purely objective, but

always both (IH, 292). But in answering the idealist objector

Collingwood goes one step further--a step that requires stating

what we have just seen him call the principle of the analysis of

consciousness:

Why did ((the idealist objector)) think that the act of


thought, by becoming subjective, ceased to be
objective? . . . It is because he understood by
subjectivity not the act of thinking, but simply
consciousness as a flow of immediate states. Subjectivity
for him means not the subjectivity of thought but only
the subjectivity of feeling or immediate experience. Even
immediate experience has an object, for in every feeling
there is something felt and in every sensation there is
something sensed: but in seeing a colour what we see is
the colour, not our act of seeing the colour . . . . The
subjectivity of immediate experience is thus a pure or
mere subjectivity; it is never objective to itself: the
experiencing never experiences itself as experiencing.
If, then, there were an experience from which all thought
were excluded . . . the active or subjective element in
that experience could never be an object to itself, and
if all experience were of the same kind it could never be
an object at all. (IH, 294-95).

In this essay the term "experience" refers to the immediacy of

something to consciousness, a term consistent with his usage

throughout his writings. It also provides him with a means for

distinguishing three senses of the term "awareness" which we

know to be a synonym for

___________________________
understood to be applicable to all forms of it--in particular
objective (Hegelian) idealism. It is possible that an objective
idealist would not feel the argument here cited as damaging. We
shall have more to say on this interesting variant of the
autobiographical anti-realist argument at IH, 288, in Chapter IX.
386

"attention" and for "consciousness." It means (1) the immediate

experience of feeling, (2)self-consciousness, and (3)

perception. Collingwood says the term should be confined to its

second sense: "I am aware of my act not only as an experience

but as my experience, and an experience of a determinate kind"

(IH, 291).

But then if awareness is self-consciousness how can

thought be anything but subjective? How can thought be an object

to itself? In answering this Collingwood expands the term

"awareness" even further:

((The objector)) will perhaps say that one act of thought


may be an object to another act, but not to itself. But
this . . . needs modification, for any object is properly
the object not of an act but of an agent, the mind that
performs the act. True, a mind is nothing except its own
activities; but it is all these activities together, not
any one separately. The question is, then whether a per-
son who performs an act of knowing can also know that he
is performing or has performed that act. Admittedly he
can, or no one would know that there were such acts, and
so no one could have called them subjective; but to call
them merely subjective, and not objective too, is to deny
that admission while yet continuing to assume its truth.
The act of thinking . . . has to be studied as it
actually exists, that is to say, as an act . . . . This
study . . . is self-knowledge . . ; it is the object of a
self-knowledge which differs from mere consciousness in
being selfconsciousness or awareness, and differs from
being mere self-consciousness in being self-knowledge;
the critical study of one's own thought, not the mere
awareness of that thought as one's own. (IH, 292).33

__________________
33 Cf. Donagan's "Principle of Order," which is one of
the four major presuppositions which Donagan claims hold for
Collingwood's mature philosophy of mind: "If a man is conscious
of one of his own acts of consciousness, then it is not by that
act itself, but by another act of consciousness which may be
said to be of a higher order" (LPC,28). Any
387

So now it appears that the schema is complete; in addition to

(1) the immediate experience of sensation, (2) mere conscious-

ness, and (3) self-consciousness, we have also (4) critical

self-consciousness or self-knowledge, the critical study of

one's own thought. For an analysis of consciousness to be com-

plete it must be carried through to this final stage, which we

have often seen Collingwood call philosophy. In a later chapter

we shall see that the critical study of one's own thought is the

study of the presuppositions of that thought, or metaphysics,

and that the methodology of metaphysics necessitates the

methodology of history. But for now we wish to point out that in

an actual specimen of the analysis of consciousness Collingwood

has in fact appealed to the principle of intentionality in the

sense that all consciousness (even consciousness of sensation or

perception) implies the presence of an object.

Now if we pull these various strands of circumstantial

evidence together into a final summary concerning the relation

of knower to known, what emerges from the evidence of The

Principles of Art, when taken in conjunction with the evidence

from remarks in The Idea of Nature and The Idea of History, is

this:

___________________
interpretation which accepts an overly-strict adherence to this
principle must ultimately come to grips with the passage just
cited, which states that this principle "needs modification" and
defends the thesis that at least one act of consciousness can be
self-illuminating, namely self-knowledge.
388

TABLE 7

THE KNOWER-KNOWN RELATIONSHIP IN PERCEPTION

1. The knower-known relationship as it occurs in the act of


perception is not adequately described by simple assignment
of activity or passivity to either knowing or its object.
(PA, 196-97)

a. Knowing does not create its object ex nihilo (i.e.,


knowing is not totally active with respect to an object);
(PA, 291-92)

b. nor does the object create knowledge of itself ex nihilo


in the knower (knowing is not totally passive in the act
of perception). (PA, 196-97)

c. Although knowing is active (in the form of sentience)


even at the level of sensation, for there to be an object
of sensation something must be present to it (and
therefore active in this minimal sense)--i.e. it must
present itself to the knower's field of sentience. (PA,
210)

2. In perception the object affects knowledge by being present


to sensation; its being an object for sensation is the same
as its being present to sensation. Its esse is sentiri. (PA,
189, 8-24; PA, 198; cf. PA, 206)

3. At the level of sensation, knowing affects the object by


perpetuating it and domesticating it by an act of attention.
This act makes the sensum one's own (an item of our own
experience) and maintains its presence in experience for
sufficient time to allow further acts of thought concerning
it to occur (discrimination, comparison, abstraction,
measurement, etc.). (PA, 212-13)

___________________
NOTE: In this table, "object" is to be taken as "object of
sensation"--i.e., whatever is sensed, or present to sensation.
"Knowing" is, unless qualified, to mean "empirical
knowledge"--i.e., knowledge by perception, and has the same
broad extension as "thought"--including first order attention.
389

4. These further acts of thought are interpretations of a


sensum.

5. Limitations on observation come (a) from the side of the


object (how long a process takes to occur, how large or
small it must be in order to exist) as well as (b) from the
side of the subject (the limits of duration of attention,
spatial discriminatory capacities, etc.). These are (a) the
presupposition concerning minimum space and time in nature,
and (b) the limits of possible experience in subjects,
respectively. (IN, 23-24)

6. The assertion of the existence of a world of nature external


to our organs of sensation and capable of presenting
information to us by acts of these organs, is not a matter
of direct perception, but the result of an interpretation of
sense. This assertion is a presupposition of natural
science. (EM, 213, 217)

7. Natural science overlaps the study of mind at the psychical


level, the physiological aspects of which are studied by
behaviorism, using the methods of natural science, and not
using the methods of conscious inquiry or introspection.
(NL, 2.6-2.73; PA, 205-06)

8. That there is such a level of experience, and that it


consists of concrete sense present to sensation as something
to be attended to (i.e. as uninterpreted sense) is
presupposed by behavioral psychology, but is demonstrated by
the analysis of consciousness, on the basis of the principle
of intentionality. (PA, 205-06)
390

6. The New Leviathan: Attention as a Linguistic Act.

Unfortunately we are not yet finished with our

survey of Collingwood's writings on the issue of realism. We

come at last to his final work, The New Leviathan--the last work

published during his lifetime, and his final word on the subject

of the philosophy of mind.34 As with The Principles of Art, we

are looking for evidence concerning Collingwood's evaluation of

the principle doctrine of realism,35 and

____________________
34 The New Leviathan is an odd book in many ways, when
compared to Collingwood's other works. It is written in a highly
aphoristic and Olympian style, with the pseudo-mathematical
device of numbered paragraphs and sub-numbered sentences. Its
rhetoric is more hectoring and bombastic than usual, with racial
slurs directed at whole nations or peoples--especially the
Germans and Turks (cf. NL, 12.4-12.42, 33.47-33.75, 42.142.74,
44.1-44.9, and 45.1-45.96). Some of these oddities may be
written off as due to the highly emotional circumstances under
which the book was written (he writes that he concluded it
during a Nazi bombardment of London), as well as the trials of
his struggle with his rapidly failing health (cf. NL, v).
Specific oddities in terms of doctrine will be dealt with di-
rectly in our discussion. But an interpreter should be cautious
about the weight he puts on specific and unparalleled statements
that he finds in this work--statements that do not appear
supported elsewhere in Collingwood's other writings. In our own
work we have therefore approached it with caution, and treat it
last rather than first; to reverse this procedure (as Donagan
and Mink do) and deal with The New Leviathan as a foundation for
understanding his mature philosophy of mind is not, in our
opinion, sound strategy (cf. Donagan, LPC, 19).

35 The New Leviathan is subtitled "Man, Society, Civi-


lization, and Barbarism," and these correspond to the four parts
into which the book is divided. Although there are scattered
remarks about perception, thinking, and science throughout the
latter three parts, our main concern will be only with the first
part, in which the philosophy of mind is expounded that serves
as a foundation for parts II-IV. That the argument of The New
391

especially as that evaluation affects his analysis of

perception.As it happens there is no direct argument in The New

Leviathan that has the form of the autobiographical refutation

of realism. But there is a discussion of the issue of empiricism

that parallels (but definitely does not duplicate) that given in

The Principles of Art. As in the earlier work, this discussion

arises in the context of the distinction between feeling and

thought (NL, 1.61, 4.13-4.19). Within feeling Collingwood

distinguishes a sensuous element and an emotional charge (NL,

4.1). But unlike the earlier work he calls thought a

"constituent" of mind and feeling an "apanage": feeling belongs

to mind not the way a man belongs to a family or a plank to a

boat (as a constituent or an element) but in the way in which an

estate belongs to a family or a mooring to a boat-

___________________
Leviathan as a whole is fundamentally anti-realistic hinges on
the denial that theory and practice can be separated (or that
theoretical reason can be separated from practical reason)--a
denial made at the very beginning (NL, 1.66) and reinforced
throughout parts I-IV in various forms (cf. NL, 7.22,
14.3-14.31, 18.13, 19.25, 20.21, 27.55, 36.25-36.7,
41.32-41.33). Since The New Leviathan is primarily an ethical
treatise (or perhaps more properly a treatise on social and
political philosophy) the stress on the pernicious consequences
of realistic philosophy (cf. A, 47-48, 147) is quite
understandable. But throughout the work there are other direct
assaults on what Collingwood had recognized to be realistic
doctrines: e.g. the rejection of the reduction of the term
"society" to the abstract notion of class (NL, 19.37, 19.7); a
defense of the notion of a common good and a rejection of the
view that all "goods" are private (NL, 20.1220.22, 21.27-21.65,
36.25-36.55); and the description of the body politic as a
dialectical entity (NL, 24.52-24.75, 29.129.75, 39.1-39.15).
392

i.e. as something it has but not as something it is (NL, 4.13-

4.19). With this distinction in mind, Collingwood addresses the

question of radical empiricism:

There is a saying, nihil est in intellectu nisi quod prius


fuerit in sensu. If this were true, the precision or de-
finiteness which is characteristic of thought would already
be characteristic of feeling. Many people try to persuade
themselves that it is; but they are mistaken. They regard
feeling as a constituent of knowledge; but it is only an
apanage of knowledge: an indispensable apanage, but an
apanage and no more. Are there objects of feeling or not? I
do not know. Nobody knows. Some have said there are, some
have said there are not. As the question is unanswerable on
positive grounds I answer it on methodological
grounds . . . . Entia non sunt multiplicanda (runs Occam's
Razor) praeter necessitatem. Following this rule I answer
the question: "Are there objects of feeling or not" by what
I call a methodological negative. Feeling must on any view
have modes . . . . The question is whether a theory of
feeling needs objects as well as modes. The Lockian theory
does; the Cartesian does not. By Occam's Razor the
Cartesian theory is preferable. (NL, 5.19-5.2, 5.39).

Is Collingwood taking a different tack here than he did

in The Principles of Art? It would certainly seem so, since on

the strength of the above quotation a reader could certainly say

that the "matter-form" analogy accepted in the earlier work is

certainly not applicable to something that is an "apanage" and

not a "constituent." If feeling is "an apanage and no more" (and

we do not ask how it can be an "indispensable apanage" and still

not be a constituent) it cannot stand with respect to higher

levels of experience as something capable of being perpetuated

as a "certain new arrangement of psychical experiences" or as a


393

"peculiar combination of elements" preserved by an act of

consciousness (PA, 233).

But before analyzing his argument to justify this "me-

thodological negative," we must notice that Collingwood is

putting a question to consciousness, finding that it is

unanswerable on "positive" grounds, and therefore answering it

on methodological grounds. We recognize this to be a case of the

"inquiry into consciousness" that Collingwood had said cannot

tell us what sort of thing the psychical level is or even whe-

ther it exists. A non-positive answer is therefore not sur-

prising on the grounds of the positive evidence offered by

consciousness alone. It is also not surprising that methodology

enters into the discussion, since Collingwood had asserted that

what the method of inquiry into consciousness could not

establish could be settled by the methods of behavioral psy-

chology as corrected by the "analysis of consciousness" using

the principle of intentionality. What is surprising is that the

"methodological answer" to the question turns out to be

negative: there are no objects of feeling. The "methodological"

criteria therefore cannot refer to the methods of behavioral

psychology (there is no experimental evidence cited), nor is

there any "analysis of consciousness" here based on the

principle that consciousness has a double object while sensation

has a single. In fact it appears that the criterion being used

does not allow sensation to have even a single object: it has

only modes. The criterion appealed to must therefore be the


principles involved in
394

an "inquiry into consciousness" which (as expected) cannot

answer such questions.

But why then is the question answered in the negative?

Should it not be simply left open (as it is at NL, 5.2, where he

says that he does not know and nobody else does either)? Should

it not merely be stated that feeling is ambiguous with respect

to this category as it is with the other Kantian categories (NL,

5.66)? In order to get a handle on why Collingwood reaches such

a conclusion, let us look at the argument offered between the

question and the answer, deleted from the above-quoted passage.

The passages are long and difficult, and are best dealt with by

paraphrase. The argument proceeds as follows:

(1) Locke asserted that there are proper objects

(colours, sounds, etc.) of acts of feeling (seeing, hearing,

etc.); the general name for these objects is "sense data" (NL,

5.21-5.23). Since data are first-order objects to sensation, and

hence second-order objects to simple consciousness (con-

sciousness in its most primitive form).36 The immediate

_____________________
36 There is a lack of terminological uniformity between
The Principles of Art and The New Leviathan which adds to the
difficulty of comparing the views of mind presented in each – a
confusion complicated by the alternation between the purely
relative use of terms (like "first-order" and "second-order"
objects, where the same object may be a first-order or immediate
object to one level of consciousness and a second-order or
mediated object to a second level reflecting on the first) and
the use of similar terms to refer to concrete levels of
395

or first-order object of simple consciousness is the activity of

sensation itself (NL, 5.24). (2) Berkeley asked, "What is the

status of objects of sense-perception?" and answered, "Their esse

is percipi," meaning that the being of colour is its being seen,

the being of sound its being heard, etc.--the sounds, colours,

etc. being apanages of mind or products of the activities of

seeing, hearing, etc. (NL, 5.27-5.29). (3) G. E. Moore and

others (obviously contemporary empiricists) beginning with the

same assumption (i.e. that sense-data are objects of sensation)

reach the opposite conclusion, i.e. that any object is precisely

what it would be if we were not aware of it (NL, 5.31;

Collingwood quotes from "The Refutation of Idealism"). (4) The

Cartesian answer is that there are modes of feeling (blue, hard,

loud, etc.) but no objects. This does not mean that Descartes

denied that there were such things as blue colors, loud sounds,

etc., but that "Descartes denied the blue colour to be the

object of a transitive verb to see, as a dog may be the object

of a transitive verb to kick. It means that for Descartes the

grammar of the sentence 'I see a blue colour' is not like the

grammar of 'I kick a bad dog' but like the grammar of 'I feel a

transient melancholy' or 'I go a fast walk.' The colour, the

melancholy, the walk, are not objects of an action, they are

modes of an action; their names have an adverbial function in

the sentences in

_____________________
mind (like "first-order" and "second-order" consciousness).
Where there is apparent lack of synonymy we shall indicate the
fact. In this case Collingwood's use of "simple consciousness"
is synonymous with first-order attention from The Principles of
Art.
396

which they occur" (NL, 5.34-5.35). On the Cartesian theory

feeling as sensuous or emotional has modes, but neither

sensations nor emotions have objects: therefore "in neither case

is there anything of which it is other than idiotic to ask

whether its esse is percipi or not" (NL, 5.37). (5) If the

Cartesian theory is accepted, then the question which (a)

Berkeley answered one way ("sensa are mind-dependent") and Moore

and others answered in the opposite way ("sensa are not

mind-dependent") is a nonsense question; it is "a question to

which no possible answer is right because it arises logically

from an assumption that is not made" (NL, 5.36).37 (6) By

Occam's Razor, the infinity of entities required by the theory

that says that feeling has objects as well as modes is ruled out

as unnecessary. All one needs for an account of feeling is

modes. Therefore

_________________

37 The argument here is confusing, but the following


schema seems likely:

Question: Are sensa mind-dependent?


Answer (1): Sensa are mind-dependent (Berkeley).
Answer (2): Sensa are not mind-dependent (Moore).
Presupposition: Mind-dependency is something that sensa can
have or be.

The implication seems to be that this presupposition (if that is


indeed the presupposition that Collingwood has in mind) is not
being made on the Cartesian theory because to be mind-dependent
something must be a constituent of mind or of consciousness, and
feelings are not constituents of mind but apanages (and apanages
are not constituents). Another way of saying this is that
feelings cannot have 2nd-order objects because they are not
conscious acts; therefore whether apanages have 2nd-order
objects (objects as well as modes) is a nonsense question.
397

the Cartesian theory is preferable on methodological grounds.

(NL, 5.39). (7) But either view (i.e. that there are both modes

and objects of feelings or that there are only modes) fits the

facts, and neither is inherently nonsensical (NL, 5.38).

We seem to be on familiar territory--this review par-

allels that given in The Principles of Art on the question of

real and imaginary sense. But there are several important dif-

ferences in the two accounts. (a) Although Collingwood winds up

stating, as we have already noticed, that feeling is "ambiguous"

with respect to the Kantian categories (and hence have the

status of uninterpreted sense) he concludes here with a Cartesian

rather than a Kantian answer to the question, "Are there objects

of feelings?" (b) In opting for this answer Collingwood

introduces an essentially linguistic argument (i.e. that the

terms referring to sense function as adverbs rather than as

nouns) that is absent in the previous account.38 (c) The

Cartesian answer, which he accepts, renders it

_____________________
38 The linguistic argument, while interesting, is both
(a) non-essential to the main argument, and (b) unreliable. (a)
To demonstrate its inessentiality it is only necessary to read
the above summary of the argument without it--it still makes
perfect sense. The use of Occam's Razor does not require the
adverbial function of sense-object terms; it hinges on the
non-necessity of positing two sets of entities, sense-modes and
sense-objects, when all one needs are modes. (b) But this
highlights the unreliability of the argument, since what
Descartes (and Collingwood) seem to be proposing is to
substitute the term "mode" for the term "object." Now it is true
that sense-modes sometimes function adverbially (e.g. "He felt
the train moving, but visually nothing changed"), but then the
distinction refers to the manner in which things are felt--by
touch, sight, taste, etc.--rather than what is felt by these
modes. For if terms like blue, sweet, loud, etc. function
adverbially in a sentence, then it
398

"idiotic" to assert that there is anything of which it is true

to assert that its esse is percipi (which runs counter to his

previous assertion that the ease of a sensum is sentiri). (d)

And yet he states that neither the assertion that sensa are

mind-dependent (Berkeley) nor the assertion that they are not

(Moore) is inherently nonsensical, and that both fit the facts.

This contradicts his earlier argument that Moore's

position (or the position of any empiricist who argues that

there are entities describable as "sense data" which are objects

of the act of sensation) implies that something absurdly

describable as "unsensed

_________________________
should be proper to say that "He tasted sweetly" or "He looked
bluely" or "He heard loudly"--all of which are semantically
peculiar. The more acceptable usage is not adverbial but
adjectival: "He tasted a sweet pastry," or "He gazed at a blue
feather," or "He heard a loud siren," etc. On the
Descartes-Collingwood theory it would seem that each "object" of
feeling is only another mode, so that we would have to posit
separate senses for every color, taste, texture, etc.--each
being a "mode" or modification of the general term, "feeling."
But linguistic legislation cannot settle the problem of what it
would mean if sense-data terms were made proper objects of verbs
of sensation: "I see blue," "I hear loud," etc.--which appear to
be truncated or incomplete sentences. Completion of their sense
is made possible by intentional or sense-giving acts of
interpretation. The substitution of the term "mode" for "object"
merely postpones the inevitable question, are such entities
present to us or do we present them to ourselves? But if
Collingwood's linguistic argument is taken not as a piece of
verbal legislation but as an illustration of an epistemological
point he wishes to make, then his denial that there are objects
of feeling may come down to nothing more than the denial of
sense-data as the perception of substances rather than of
processes of nature. It would thus be consistent with The Idea
of Nature, which states that one of the consequences of the
modern view of nature is the resolution of substance into
function (IN, 16-17).
399

sensa” can exist. And finally, (e) there is no mention here, or

in what follows it in The New Leviathan, of anything to do with

imagination or imaginary sense.

Some, but not all, of these discrepancies may be re-

solved by paying careful attention to a subtle shift of levels

between the two works, The New Leviathan being strictly bound by

the negative limitations of "The Fallacy of Swapping Horses,"

and The Principles of Art sitting a little looser in the saddle.

In the later work the inquiry proceeds by putting questions to

consciousness and answering them by taking "soundings"

(consciously reflecting or introspecting) at various levels of

consciousness. Since this is the Cartesian method,39 it is

predictable that the same method will yield similar conclusions:

consciousness does not need to assume that sensation has objects

as well as modes. The methodological negative therefore merely

allows the inquiry to proceed by not inhibiting it with

questions that it cannot (on its presuppositions) answer. Since

one of its main presuppositions is that the only constituents of

mind are acts of consciousness, and that with respect to

______________________
39 Collingwood's starting point in The New Leviathan is
even Cartesian: "Of all the things we know or have been told
about Man, which is the one thing that concerns us at the pres-
ent stage of our inquiry? I answer: The division between body
and Mind" (NL, 1.21). But of course, Collingwood's aim is not to
construct a mathematically secure science, nor to proceed only
by way of clear and distinct ideas. Nevertheless these
concessions to Descartes should alone be enough to render sus-
pect any account of Collingwood's philosophy of mind that begins
with the assertion that it is fundamentally anti-Cartesian
(Donagan, LPC, 25).
400

these essential elements feelings are merely apanages, it is not

a matter for consciousness to decide what the relationship may

be between feelings and what they are directed towards. Whatever

these objects may be, they are not first-order objects for

consciousness. Therefore when Collingwood rejects the assertion

that sensation has objects he may be doing nothing more than

what he does in The Principles of_Art when he criticizes the

notion of "sense data": he may be rejecting the absurd notion of

"unsensed sensa." In other words, the terms "sense-object,"

"sense datum" and "unsensed sensum" may be synonyms: all may

refer to a sensum as a datum--something really present only as

re-presented, an imaginatum.

But then the reader is stumped for an explanation as to

why Moore's position is not inherently nonsensical, and why the

notion of "sense-object" is not resolved into an imaginatum, as

it is in The Principles of Art; in The New Leviathan the entire

issue of imaginative representation is never mentioned. Can we

assume that this is because he had said all he cared to on the

subject in The Principles of Art (cf. Mink, MHD, 81)? That might

be the case were it not for some remarkable direct discrepancies

between the two works on the issue of feeling, discrepancies not

easily dismissed on the above grounds.


401

These discrepancies become more obvious the instant we

begin to expand the discussion of feeling. In The New Leviathan

Collingwood characterizes feeling and its relation to thought as

follows. (1) It is an apanage of mind rather than a constituent

(NL, 4.19-4.2). (2) It consists of sensuous elements and

emotional charges which interpenetrate all over the field of

feeling (NL, 4.1, 4.4). (3) Feelings are evanescent--they begin

to perish as soon as they begin to exist (NL, 5.5). (4) Feelings

are indefinite (NL, 4.8) but strong (NL, 4.86). (5) The strength

that feeling has is (a) vividness ("compression

strength"--basically, intensity) and (b) tenacity (the quality a

feeling has which makes it "linger in the mind, be slow to

vanish, and be easily revived when the occasion permits") (NL,

5.14-5.17). (6) Within the here-and-now field of feeling (NL,

4.4) there are place-differences, time-differences ("it has

spatial and temporal bulk"), and intensity differences (louder

and softer sounds, brighter and dimmer colors, etc.) (NL, 4.4,

4.43). (7) Within this field there is also a focal region where

precision and intensity are greatest, and a penumbral region

where they decrease in every direction until in some outer zone

precision and intensity recede into dimness and confusion (NL,

4.44).

Thus far the description of feeling is not significantly

different from that given in The Principles of Art. But

Collingwood adds several more statements about feeling in

relation to thought, statements


402

that lead us into unfamiliar territory. (8) Feeling has no

edges--its spatial and temporal penumbra fade away (NL, 4.45).

(9) Feeling is the proper object of simple consciousness and is

immediately given to that consciousness (NL, 4.19, 4.24, 4.71).

Without this simple consciousness and the field of feeling

present to it there could be no higher-order acts of selective

attention (NL, 4.5). (10) Distinctions within the field of

feeling are made by an act of selective attention--a practical

act of second-order consciousness in which one's attention is

turned one way or another, "creating . . . a situation in

which . . . consciousness is concentrated on one object (one

feeling) or another" (NL, 4.5). (11) The act of attention really

makes the edges of anything distinguished within the field of

feeling (NL, 4.52 -4.6)--distinctions such as positional

distinctions (distinctions of place and time), qualitative

distinctions, distinctions between sensations and their

emotional charges, between different sensings (seeing, hearing,

smelling), etc. (NL, 4.61-4.63). (12) Any characteristics that

feelings may have are discoverable by simply reflecting on that

consciousness; to attempt to argue about it is to commit the

Fallacy of Misplaced Argument (the fallacy of arguing about any

object immediately given to consciousness) (NL, 4.71-4.73). (13)

There is no generalizing about feelings ("that is, no framing

universal propositions about them and assuring oneself that

these are
403

true, or (alternatively) omitting to do so because one is too

lazy"), although it is possible to think inductively about

feeling ("to think inductively is to assume, because this x has

(or some x's have) a certain characteristic, that other x's have

or would have the same characteristic") (NL, 5.55-5.56). (14)

Feelings have modes but not objects (NL, 5.2-5.39). (15) Feeling

is ambiguous with respect to activity (something I do) or

passivity (something I undergo) (NL, 5.45.49). (16) Feeling is

ambiguous with regard to the Kantian categories of quantity,

quality, relation, and modality (NL, 5.6-5.66). (17) It is also

ambiguous with regard to the Kantian category of quality,

although this ambiguity has limits (NL, 5.67-5.72). (18)

Feelings cannot be remembered, although propositions about

feelings can be remembered (NL, 5.54). (19) Feelings may be

preconscious until they are reflected upon by an act of

consciousness (NL, 5.9-5.91), or unconscious insofar as they are

repressed (NL, 5.86-5.87). (20) Feeling remains preconscious

until it is named (NL, 6.28). Naming is a linguistic act of

expression, which includes everything from the language of

gesture (e.g. an expressive shiver to the cold) to the language

of speech (saying "it is cold") (NL, 6.1, 6.25). "Language in

its simplest form is the language of consciousness in its

simplest form; the mere 'register' of feelings, as wild and mad

as those feelings themselves; irrational, unorganized,

unplanned, unconscious" (NL, 6.58). (21) A language is an

abstraction from discourse, which is the activity


404

by which a man means anything (NL, 6.11). To discourse is to

mean something by the gesture (expression) you make; a language

is a system of gestures (sounds or the like) as having meanings.

Discourse is the activity of meaning something (a) by something

else (b), where meaning (a) is an act of theoretical

consciousness, and (b) is a practical activity, the production

in oneself or others of sounds, etc. which serve as the vehicle

of that meaning (NL, 6.18-6.19). (22) Finally, selective

attention is an act of practical thinking, at the level of

conceptual thought (NL, 7.2-7.21); it is a doing of something to

oneself (focusing consciousness on part of the field of feeling)

and also a doing of something to the object (circumscribing it,

drawing a line between it and the rest of the field) (NL, 7.3).

Leaving the higher functions of consciousness for later

discussion (we will have more to say about language, logic, and

conceptual and propositional thinking in Chapter VIII), we must

now ask how all this stands with respect to the fundamental

tenet of realism. Once again we meet with Collingwood's

intransigent insistence on the activity of thinking and its role

even at the primary level of perception. And once again we find

Collingwood anxious to reject the view of mind that makes it a

passive partner in the knower-known relationship. In his final

published work, then, it is clear that Collingwood has retained

his opposition to the principal doctrine of realism that the

known is unaffected by
405

the knowing of it. To this extent the autobiographical

interpretation is vindicated.

But what about our further question about whether the

object has any effect on the knower? And is this description of

the functions of consciousness consistent with that given in The

Principles of Art, and how does it compare with the

circumstantial evidence that we educed from that earlier work

and from his other late writings? Although we would like to

defend Collingwood's later philosophy of mind as a brave attempt

to reconcile idealism and realism, we find instead that in The

New Leviathan he appears to be so intent on overcoming the

errors of realism that he leaves little room for interpreting

the knower-known relationship in anything but idealistic terms:

not only does knowing make a difference to the object known even

to the level of perception, but there seems to be no way that

the object can make a difference to the knowing of it.

The crux of the matter is, of course, sensation itself.

If there is no way that sensation can present to us a world of

sensa that is something more than in a state of constant flux,

utterly diversified, and without any "edges" at all, then it is

impossible to see (1) why an exercise of the "circumsribing"

function of attention is not utterly free to make any sort of

arbitrary pattern of fancies out of the chaos of sensa on which

it operates; (2) why there should be any sort of correlation


406

between various modes of sensation with respect to one and the

same object of sensation; and (3) how it is possible to

disambiguate feeling at all by any act of interpretation. We

will take up each of these points separately.

(1) We have seen that Collingwood described the field of

feeling as containing positional and qualitative distinctions,

place-differences and time-differences, intensity differences,

and even focal and penumbral regions. But then we saw him go

even further and assert that there are no edges within the field

of feeling, and that all distinctions within it are made by acts

of selective attention--an act of practical consciousness. He

goes so far as to say that not even so much as a "red patch" is

immediately given to consciousness, because "the red is actually

given in feeling to consciousness as a quality transfusing all

the rest of the same field" (NL, 5.65; emphasis mine). The sensa

given in feeling "interpenetrate" all over the field of feeling

(NL, 5.62), and only the activity of consciousness as selective

attention can "cut up" such a field into distinct feelings

("sensations distinct from emotions, visual sensations distinct

from auditory sensations, red patches distinct from green

patches, and so on ad infinitum") (NL, 5.63). The field of

sensation is utterly ambiguous with regard to all the Kantian

categories, and only one small postscript indicates that this

ambiguity has any limits: with


407

respect to the category of quality Collingwood says that "colour

may be indeterminate, but it falls between points on a

colour-scale. We can always fix these limits as closely as we

need . . . but the ambiguity is only restricted, it can never be

removed" (NL, 5.72).

But how is it possible to "restrict" an ambiguity that

(a) includes the impossibility of distinguishing even so much as

a red patch on a green field, and that (2) excludes sensa from

having any "edges" at all? And how is it possible for there to

be differences (qualitative, quantitative, etc.) within a field

if everything within that field "interpenetrates" and

"transfuses" and "begins to perish as soon as it begins to

exist"? And how can there be such differences present in the

field if it is only consciousness that puts such distinctions

there?

Lacking answers to these questions we must conclude that

something has gone wrong with Collingwood's description of

feeling, and especially of sensation. It is not consistent with

itself within The New Leviathan, and it certainly is not

consistent with his remarks in other works, about scientific

observation and its presuppositions. In order that there be

something "there" for perception to attend to, we must assume

that edges are not only "made" by acts of selective attention,

they are also "found" to be there when something is attended

to--once, twice, or however many times one chooses. And although

within a given field of sensation--vision,


408

for example--there may be ambiguities (colors at the periphery

of my vision begin to interpenetrate, or even within the direct

foreground of my visual field if I let my focus blur), it is

nonetheless equally an item of experience that for a given

position within that field something is not always red, green,

blue, etc. all over at the same time, and to the same

degree--this much at least he admitted in The Principles of Art,

when he argued that "we cannot, in seeing a red patch, mistake

it for a blue one" (PA, 189). It is sometimes predominately one

color or another, or it is mottled, or whatever, but certainly

not always totally indefinite. And if it is true that I become

aware of edges by letting my focus wander back and forth from a

red patch to its surrounding green field and back again, and

thereby re-establishing the distinctness of the red patch from

its background, it is not a matter of utterly creating this edge

ex nihilo in the visual field, it is a matter of re-creating or

re-presenting it for myself in the act of perception. If it were

not then it would be nonsense to assert that observation of

nature yields any information at all. Selective attention would

just as surely create the patterns of nature as a painter

creates a visual scene on his canvas: it is a reverse "tabula

rasa" with the messages written on the blank sheet of sensation

by the perceiver's consciousness rather than by natural objects.


409

(2) So also with the formation of percepts which the

medieval scholastics would subsume under the faculty of "common

sense" (not the body of assumed rules or customs or attitudes

towards the world and others, but rather the result of the

operation of a faculty related to imagination, and which holds

together sense from various organs of sensation--colors and

shapes with sounds, textures, smells, tastes,etc.--to form a

"common sensible"). Collingwood's sensuous field as he describes

it cannot be distinct even with respect to modes, if he is to be

consistent, since "visual sensations distinct from auditory

sensations . . . and so on ad infinitum" (NL, 5.63) are only

distinguished by acts of selective attention. But then it

becomes utterly arbitrary whether I associate this color brown

to which I am attending with this shape which I am holding,

where the shape happens to be a cup I am holding under the table

and color is that of the table between my eyes and the cup. Or

even worse, what is to stop my act of attention from taking this

loud noise for this sweet taste? Collingwood wishes us to

withhold such distinctions until we reach a higher level of

discrimination, but by then it is too late: no amount of

discriminating is going to inform me of an error of this sort

unless some original act actually grants me information on the

basis of which I can correct my error. On Collingwood's grounds

(at least in The New Leviathan) it is impossible, using the

findings of mental
410

science, to ever have any such original act. Sensation as such

is essentially and irretrievably ambiguous.

(3) But the problems that Collingwood gets himself into

in The New Leviathan are not due solely to his assertion that

the field of sensation is ambiguous with respect to one or

another of the Kantian categories (which is true even for his

position in The Principles of Art insofar as uninterpreted sense

are ambiguous until interpreted by application of one or more

categories) but rather they are also due to the fact that he

goes beyond this point and makes statements about the field of

feeling that are actually interpretations of it--generalizations

about feeling that his own principles do not allow him to make.

Thus although he says that no generalizations can be made about

feeling (which is itself a generalization about feeling) he

proceeds to say that within a visual field all colors

interpenetrate, that they have no edges, that within the field

of feeling there are place-differences and time differences,

that they cannot be remembered, etc. What are these but

generalizations about feeling? And how does a reader begin to

reconcile the statement that there can be no generalization

about feeling with the statement that immediately follows it,

that it is possible to "think inductively" about feeling, where

"to think inductively is to assume that because this x has . . .

a certain characteristic, that other x's have or would have the

same characteristic" (NL, 5.55-5.66)? For what else could

inductive thinking,
411

on this description of it, be but generalization?

Now it is true that in The Principles of Art many of

these same generalizations were made about feeling, but they

were merely provisionally assumed as a way of distinguishing

feeling from thought, and in order to establish the intermediate

role of imagination. Once imagination as attention is understood

as the minimum specification of the genus thought, the realm of

feeling is redefined as the psychical level of experience on

which attention operates, and through which attention "finds and

makes" the patterns it requires of the world extrinsic to our

sense organs. The methodology of mental science has not been

violated, because consciousness as attention is used to define

feeling (feeling is what attention is conscious of; sensa are

its second-order objects).

All this is demolished by the overstatements of The New

Leviathan. Does the later work then represent a change of mind

in The Principles of Art? And if Collingwood is saying that the

experience of distinctions as given to us in sensation is not his

experience is he not "disowning" a feeling, and is this not the

"corruption of consciousness" that he sought to warn us against?

We cannot answer these questions on the basis of the existing

evidence. We can only try to discern what Collingwood was trying

to say--what he intended to mean rather than what he merely

said. Now
412

it is clear that Collingwood wishes to say, in The New

Leviathan, not only (1) that feeling prior to reflection upon it

is lacking in the distinctions proper to thought alone, and

hence has only a potentiality for categorial predication, but

also (2) that it has place-distinctions and time-distinctions

and intensity-distinctions (even in the pre-reflective state),

and (3) that it nonetheless belongs to us as a field of

experience --as an apanage of mind, or something we have, rather

than a constituent, or something we are.

This is basically a Kantian view on the structure and

function of mind, since (2) is another way of stating what Kant

called the "forms of sensibility"--space and time: for anything

to be an object of possible experience, according to Kant, it

must be spatially extended and temporally successive. This even

seems to be consistent with the view expressed in The Principles

of Art, where Collingwood speaks of the function of attention as

perpetuating sense by keeping them before us long enough to get

a fair sight of them; and also consistent with the view of The

Idea of Nature where Collingwood talks about minimum-space and

minimum-time as limiting conditions for scientific, experimental

observation.

But it has the same problems that the Kantian forms of

sensibility have. Sensa as placed and timed are not utterly

indeterminate, but are rather determined to be someplace and

sometime, and therefore bearing interpretation, in the minimal

sense, already. If they are conditions


413

for the possibility of objects of sensation, then they must be

conditions not only for the subjective act of a percipient, but

also conditions true for the object as well--in Collingwood's

terms, for the sensum. The sensum has to be the "kind of thing"

that meets the requirements of sensation; it has to be a spa-

tially-extended and temporally-persistent thing if perception of

it is to be possible.

The question ultimately comes down to this: if dis-

tinctions, "edges," are not found but made by acts of practical

consciousness, how is it possible to attend to what is not

there--to something (the field of interpenetrating sense) that

is not some thing (nothing determinate at all)? There seems to

be nothing to attend to. Collingwood would say that there is

something there, only not something definite, and that once

selective attention has done its job, it can find the

distinctions that it put there. But the retort occurs

immediately: put where? To distinguish even left and right sides

of a sensory field involves a distinction, which in turn

presupposes spatial distinctions with respect to one's own body

within the sensory field. Are these "put" there as well?

In Collingwood's case the issue is further complicated

by the addition of intensity-distinctions and even a minimal

qualitative
414

distinction, as well as a focal and penumbral structure to the

here-and-now field of sensation (which must also be a

"there-and-then" if the focal-penumbral analogy is to be carried

out). All of this adds up to a field of feeling that is not

altogether indeterminate. But supposing that we can ignore the

contradiction of a field that is determinately indeterminate, a

here-and-now that is also a there-and-then, etc. we still wish

to know how what remains of indeterminacy if such a field is

disambiguated. On this Collingwood leaves the reader in no

doubt: disambiguation of the field of feeling is the work and

product of thought which, by a practical activity called

language, functions as selective attention.

Unfortunately this activity is also not free of am-

biguity, because "language" is not merely the practical side of

second-order thought, as some passages in The New Leviathan

would lead us to believe (e.g. NL, 4.33). It necessarily and

essentially involves a theoretical aspect--the element not only

of producing sounds or gestures or expressions, but of meaning

something by them, where the meaning is an act of theoretical

consciousness (NL, 6.18-6.19). But this description of language

as discourse must be taken as the narrower sense of the term,

"language," which does not include psychical expressions

(grimaces, blushes, tears, etc.) because the latter do not

include thought at all, and hence not theoretical consciousness

and not meaning. How then does one import meaning into the

psychical level of sensation and the chaotic world of sensa?


415

The disambiguation we are especially interested in is

that of the much discussed red patch. If the edges of such a

patch (and the color itself as distinct from its background) are

made by an act of selective attention which is linguistic in the

sense just stated (i.e. including the non-vocal act of meaning,

where meaning is an act of theoretical consciousness), then for

a portion of the field of feeling to be not only present as a

"this" but as an interpreted presence, "this red," and an

interpreted presence related to other such items in a field of

feeling, a "this red patch in a green field," it must be related

to theoretical consciousness through meaning. But once again the

inevitable question arises, is this found in the sensory field

or is it put there? On Collingwood's earlier account of the

matter it is still possible to say, "both found and

put"--leaving the details to behaviorism shored up by the

analysis of consciousness. But in The New Leviathan the

disambiguation of feeling by the elliciting of meaning appears

to be impossible, since one is forbidden to make any

generalizations about feeling. There seems to be no way to

bridge the gap between meaning as an act of theoretical con-

sciousness, and utterly ambiguous sense.

7. Conclusion.

The only way out of these dilemmas is to return to the

position of The Principles of Art, where such intemperate

assertions are not made, and where there is still a possibility

for a "science of feeling" to establish


416

what a "science of mind" cannot--i.e. the manner in which

objects extrinsic to our sense organs can act on them to yield

information about the natural world. This does not mean that we

must ignore The New Leviathan altogether: in the summary with

which we shall conclude this chapter we attempt to retain from

it those elements of the philosophy of mind which are consistent

and compatible with the groundwork laid out in The Principles of

Art. In the matter of language, for example, the later work

shows a distinct improvement (as we shall see in the next

chapter).

But how does it finally stand with Collingwood's view of

the knower-known relationship insofar as the principal doctrine

of realism is concerned? Our final conclusion must be somewhat

disappointing. It is not a matter of faulting Collingwood for

failing to be idealist enough to recognize that reality somehow

exists "for us" and not merely "for itself;" or for not being

realist enough to recognize that there is a world of objects

unaffected by our knowing of them (or, as some would have it,

that the natural language we use to express our thoughts is of

necessity a physical-object language) It is a matter of faulting

Collingwood for failing to be Collingwood enough, for failing to

recognize that the "Law of Primitive Survivals"40 does not apply

only to higher-order mental functions, but (by the logic of the

overlap of

___________________
40 "(A)nother principle that I have assumed throughout
((is)) the LAW OF PRIMITIVE SURVIVALS. It runs as follows. When
A is modified into B there survives in any example of B, side
by side with the function B
417

classes) operates even at the level of sensation, or that no

matter how far one goes down the "scale of forms" one never

reaches a zero-point in the scale (EPM, 31 95., 81-82). These

general principles alone should have led him to recognize that

something is given in sensation other than a riotous chaos of

interpenetrating and utterly ambiguous sensa; that sensation,

although the activity of a not utterly passive agent, is

nonetheless the working-up and further organization of elements

continuous with the world of nature and of nature's energies,

and not something utterly created by the agent and imposed as a

form on a passive and indeterminate matter.

Why Collingwood failed to describe adequately sensation

could only be settled by appeal to evidence which we do not yet

have. Perhaps from the body of his unpublished manuscripts a

theory of perception may yet emerge that can pull together the

paradoxes that are left unresolved in his published philosophy.

But we must notice that the failure is due to the espousal not

of realism, but of something more akin to the radical idealism

as we propositionally formulated it at the beginning of this

chapter. We therefore cannot rest content with any

interpretation that

_____________________
which is the modified form of A, an element of A in its
primitive or unmodified state" (NL, 9.5-9.51). We recognize this
to be the law of dialectical relationship present in
Collingwood's writings ever since Religion and Philosophy, but
obviously not always followed.
418

asserts that the dogmatism of Collingwood's later philosophy was

a reversion to the realism of his youth. On the contrary, it was

a reversion to, and ultimately the dogmatic assertion of, his

youthful idealism. The application of the "Fallacy of Misplaced

Argument" to rule out controversy concerning sensation is as

much an expression of this dogmatism as is the removal of

absolute presuppositions from the criteria of truth and falsity

in the Essay on Metaphysics. But the case of sensation presents

the interpreter with examples of overstatement that tend to

stress the contribution to knowledge made by the knower, rather

than one that stresses the contribution of the object. Therefore

as we already noted, to this extent the autobiographical

interpretation is vindicated.

Collingwood's position of the relationship of knower and

known was from beginning to end one which is developed in direct

opposition to what he understood to be the fundamental tenet of

realism. He never succeeded in utterly freeing himself from this

preoccupation with the errors of realism, and it was perhaps

this preoccupation that ultimately drove him to overstatement.

It may be unfortunate that overstatements were made at all, but

it is at least consistent with the overall interpretation

offered in the Autobiography.

We end this chapter with a final summary of Colling-

wood's core philosophy of mind.


419
TABLE 8

THE PHILOSOPHY OF MIND

1. The field of human experience consists of two kinds of ex-


perience, feeling and thinking. (PA, 157).

a. Feeling is the here-and-now presence of a field of


successive sense, each with its emotional charge. Re-
lative to thought, feeling is simple, private, evane-
scent, perpetually in flux, and appears to arise in us
independently of our willing it. Feeling exists at the
psychical level, is rooted in our physiological
processes, and is (in some sense) the foundation upon
which the superstructure of thought is erected. The
study of feeling is the proper domain of behavioral
psychology. (PA, 157-64, 205).

b. Thought is the deliberate act (or achievement) of an


agent, and can succeed or fail. Relative to feeling,
thought is bipolarly complex, public, capable of genuine
recurrence and contradiction, and is somehow consequent
on feeling. It exists at the mental level, and is not
subject to empirical investigative methods alone, but is
rather the object of criteriological sciences. All
thought presupposes feeling. (PA, 157-60, 164-66, 221).

c. A science of mind proceeds by means of inquiry into


consciousness, or by putting questions to conscious ness
and answering them with data provided by consciousness
itself. From the point of view of a sci ence of mind,
feeling is an apanage of mind (something it has), but a
constituent of experience (something it is); thought is
the only constituent of mind, but it is also a
constituent of human experience. (PA, 20506; NL, 1.61,
4.14-4.2; IH, 291-94).

2. Feeling has a double character, sensation and emotion, united


in any given experience, but distinguishable by acts of
attention. (PA, 160-62; NL, 4.1).

a. Sensation is the activity of seeing, hearing, tasting,


etc. something; and what is sensed in these acts are
420

sensa: colors, sounds, tastes, etc. Sensation is prior


to emotion as capable of being attended to apart from
emotion, but not temporally, logically, or causally
prior. A sensum can be "sterilized" by ignoring its
emotional charge. (PA, 160-62).

b. Emotion is the "charge" accompanying a sensum. Relative


to sensation, emotion is secondary, or capable of being
"stripped off" a sensum and ignored. It is likely that
emotion is present in all experience, and exists in
modified state up to the level of intellect. (PA,
160-62, 169-70, 221, 294).

c. All thought presupposes feeling; and thought alters


feeling, which becomes by successive development due to
thought, imagination, appetite, passion, desire, etc. by
acts of practical thinking. (PA, 230-34; NL, 7.1-7.24,
9.55, 11.1-11.24).

3. Thought is distinguished as primary and secondary, on the


basis of what is being thought about, or as practical or
theoretical depending on what it affects. (PA, 164-68; NL,
1.63-1.68, 10.51).

a. 1st order thought (or empirical thinking) is concerned


exclusively with feeling, relations between sense, be-
tween sense and sensation, between sensation and emotion,
etc. (PA, 164-66; cf. NL, 4.31).

b. 2nd order thought (or intellect) is concerned with other


acts of thought; it is thought about thought. Its acts
may be abstract, analytical, conceptual, propositional,
rational, etc. (PA, 166-68, 253-54; NL, 6.58-6.59).

c. Practical thought is making up one's mind to (do some-


thing to oneself or to one's environment). Thought is
primarily and always practical, because it always has an
effect on oneself or on one's environment. (NL,
1.65-1.68, 7.22, 9.35, 14.3; PA, 289; IH, 310-12).

d. Theoretical thought is making up one's mind that (such


and such is the case, or is not the case, or would be the
case if . . . , etc.). (NL, 1.64-1.67, 14.3, 14.35; PA,
253, 289; IH, 310-12).
421

4. Attention (or awareness or consciousness) is the absolutely


fundamental act of thought which stabilizes and perpetuates
feeling-acts long enough that they may enter into relations
with other feelings and with thought. Attention is the act
of appreciating something present as a concrete individual,
just as it stands, before analyzing it. (PA, 203-04).

a. 1st order attention is an act of first order thought; it


divides the field of feeling into focal and penumbral
regions, perpetuates and domesticates feelings --i.e.
stabilizing feelings and asserting ourselves as the
owners of these feelings and able to dominate them. It
is therefore the free act of an agent, an act free in a
sense intermediate between the freedom of sensation (the
freedom to respond in several ways to a stimulus) and
the freedom of intellect (the true freedom of choice of
alternative plans or courses of action). (PA, 203-08,
215-22).

b. 2nd order attention is an act of 2nd order thought; it


is the practical act which isolates and identifies a
re-presented imaginatum by naming it, or by performing a
linguistic act of meaningful expression. As a 2nd order
act of thought, attention is abstractive or conceptual.
(NL, 4.3-4.68, 6.2-6.36; IH, 242, 291).

5. Imagination is feeling altered by consciousness--feeling as


selected, perpetuated, and domesticated by attention.
Imagination is another name for consciousness, awareness, or
attention, but it is distinguished as the result of at-
tention or the result of the conversion of a sensum unin-
terpreted into one ready for interpretation or into one
interpreted by an act of 2nd order thought. It is an a priori
function of thought which operates at the level of 1st order
thought as perception, and at higher levels as artistic
interpretation, scientific hypothesis formation, and
historical reconstruction (PA, 209-15; IH, 242, 291).

6. There are therefore three stages logically distinguishabl in


the life of a feeling:

a. Bare feeling is something given in sensation, and if


unattended to, is carried away in the flux of feeling.
Its being is its presence to sensation, and it is re-
lated to thought as an uninterpreted sensum.
422

b. Conscious feeling (or feeling as the object of first--


order attention or of simple consciousness) is feeling
perpetuated and dominated by consciousness or imagina-
tion. Its being is its re-presentation to consciousness,
and it is related to thought as a sensum ready for
interpretation.

c. Related feeling (or feeling as the object of second-


order attention, or of consciousness proper) is feeling
placed in its relation to other feelings, something
constructed or apprehended inferentially by the work of
intellect. Its being is relational, and it is related to
thought as an interpreted sensum. (PA,

d. "Sense datum" refers equivocally to all or any of these


above three, but it is properly speaking only (c),
related feeling. (PA, 169-70).

7. The expression of feeling is a bodily act (a practical act)


having levels which correspond to the stages in the life of
a feeling).

a. Psychical expression is the involuntary muscular and


glandular register of feeling, as wild and disorganized
as these feelings themselves. (PA, 228-34, 266; NL,
6.58).

b. Imaginative expression or language in the broad sense is


the activity of discourse, or of meaning something (a)
by something else (b), where meaning (a) is an act of
theoretical consciousness, and (b) is a practical
activity, the production in oneself or others of a
physical vehicle for that meaning. At its lowest level
language is simple naming; this is the level of
conceptual thought. (NL, 6.2-6.28).

c. Intellectual expression is language at the level of


propositional or analytic thought and all levels beyond
this (e.g. rational thought). It is thought expressed as
questions, propositions, inferences, reasons why, etc.
(NL, 6.1-6.29, 6.57-6.59; PA, 221, 224-54).
CHAPTER VIII

LOGIC, LANGUAGE, AND MENTAL


ACTS

1. Introduction.

In Chapter I we found that one of the major

controversies concerning Collingwood's philosophy, as assessed

by his interpreters, is his contention in the Essay on

Metaphysics that metaphysics is an historical science --i.e.

that the proper occupation of the metaphysician is to detect the

presuppositions being made by the scientists of a certain era.

The presuppositions, insofar as they are absolute (that is, not

themselves answers to questions but standing as presuppositions

to all questions in a systematic inquiry), are neither true nor

false, and in discovering them the metaphysician acts as an

historian. His job is not to pass judgment on the truth or

falsity of these absolute presuppositions, but merely to detect

and report them. Since the entire controversy concerning the

historical character of metaphysics turns on the role of

absolute presuppositions, and since the theory of

presuppositions is part of Collingwood's question-and-answer

(Q-A) logic, we concluded that Q-A logic is itself one of the

major concerns in the interpretation of Collingwood's philosophy.

423
424

In Chapter II we found that according to the

Autobiography, Collingwood's attack on the methods of the

realists entailed, for him, the rejection of propositional logic

(F-logic) as an index for correct thinking, since it posited

truth as a property of propositions. In direct opposition to

this Collingwood proposed an alternative in the form of a Q-A

logic, in which truth is taken as a property of propositions

only as answers to questions. By reflecting on the sort of

thinking he was accustomed to doing in his own historical work,

Collingwood found that if one includes in this thought process

the presuppositions on which questions are formulated and from

which they arise, then the presupposition-question-answer

(P-Q-A) complex is not only the unit of truth and falsity in

systematic inquiry but also the index of meaning and validity.

The Q-A logic that he developed from these reflections was

formulated, he felt, in direct opposition to the false methods

of the realistic philosophers, who ignored the necessity of re-

constructing the concrete question for the propositional answer

they were abstractly criticizing--an extension of their

ignorance of historical matters. He went as far as to write up

his Q-A logic and offer it to a publisher, but it was turned

down, and he subsequently destroyed the only manuscript of it.

In Part II we found that in his early philosophy Col-

lingwood does indeed criticize the formal logic of dogmatic

realism, and in
425

Speculum Mentis he does argue that truth is a function of Q-A

complexes. But we also found that in his earliest publication,

Religion and Philosophy, there is no mention of a Q-A logic as

such, but there is a good deal of discussion about dialectic and

dialectical relations. In Speculum Mentis dialectical relations

are even expanded into a logical schema, so that the truth

embodied in a system of thought which shows development is

described as dialectical in form, and dialectic is contrasted

with formal logic as the logic of the concrete and abstract

universal respectively. Since there was some evidence that led

us to suppose that formal logic was held to be of limited

validity in its function as the justification of the consistency

of scientific conclusions, we suggested that although there is

no mention of the fact in the Autobiography, the early writings

show evidence that when Collingwood discusses "logic" we may be

dealing not with one sort of logic but with at least three: (1)

Q-A logic (discussed in Speculum Mentis, partially described in

the Autobiography, and reappearing in semi-formal attire in the

Essay on Metaphysics); (2) F-logic (the formal logic in the

tradition stemming from Aristotle--described and criticized in

Speculum Mentis, called "propositional logic" in the

Autobiography and ascribed to the realists, and discernible as

the logic employed by "exact and empirical sciences" in the

Essay on Philosophical Method); and (3) D-logic (the dialectical

logic present in germ form even in his earliest work, Religion

and Philosophy;
426

described, examplified, and exalted in Speculum Mentis; but

mysteriously unmentioned in his Autobiography).

Our task in this chapter is minimally to examine the

evidence provided by his later writings to test whether or not

he remained true to his autobiographical assertions concerning

his "revolutionary" logic. Since the most notorious and explicit

formulation of this Q-A logic is in the fourth chapter of the

Essay on_Metaphysics, it is clear that we shall have to examine

this chapter in some detail. But since our examination of his

early writings raises questions about the relationship between

Q-A logic and D-logic, and of both of these to F-logic

(questions not even hinted at in the Autobiography) we shall

have to expand our discussion to include these topics as well.

Since the Essay on Philosophical Method describes the sort of

logical relations he had in his earlier works called

"dialectical," it is clear we shall have to examine the major

doctrines of this important work as our primary source for what

Collingwood understood by what we are calling D-logic. And

finally we find that the only locus of discussion of F-logic and

logical relations in the later writings is in connection with

language and the higher-order functions of mental activity in

The Principles of Art and The New Leviathan. This necessitates

picking up the discussion of Collingwood's philosophy of mind

where we left it in Chapter VII--viz. with the analysis of the

functions of intellect.
427

Our strategy is therefore as straight-forward as it was

in the last chapter. We propose to take up these topics in the

order in which we have just reviewed them. In each case we shall

first present a brief summary of the major theses of the texts

we are considering, in tabular form. This will be followed by a

critical discussion of issues relevant to the topics of this

chapter. In the concluding section we shall attempt to pull the

strands of the discussion together in a final evaluation of what

we can reconstruct of Collingwood's thought on the subject of

logic.

2. Questions, Answers, and Presuppositions.

In Chapter IV, where we discussed the form of experience

that Collingwood called "science" in Speculum Mentis (i.e. the

form of experience that habitually takes its object to be an

instance of an abstract universal), we noticed that Q-A logic

was left in an incomplete state, inasmuch as the relationship of

questions to presuppositions was not made explicit. This

incomplete analysis led to the further difficulty of an

equivocation in the use of the term "hypothesis" as he used it

in his description of scientific thinking. This equivocation in

turn rendered ambiguous his discussion of the

hypothetical-categorical distinction on which he based his

judgment of the superiority of history over science. We shall

have more to say in the next section on the issue of categorical

and hypothetical judgments, but at this point we must make good

our promise
428

from Chapter IV to clear up the ambiguity about questions and

hypotheses.

That ambiguity rested on the description of questions

and hypotheses as "non-assertions," the equivocation being that

questions are not merely non-assertions but proto-assertions or

non-assertions which seek completion in assertion. Sentential or

propositional fragments are also non-assertions, but they are

not therefore either questions or hypotheses. Since we shall in

all likelihood never know what the contents of his early

unpublished work, "Truth and Contradiction," had to say on the

subject of Q-A logic, we are left to the surviving fragments of

that doctrine in his published writings as the only evidence we

have for reconstructing his thought on the matter. On the

evidence of Speculum Mentis we can safely assume that as of 1924

he was not employing the distinctions necessary to disentangle

questions from hypotheses. We can also state that on the

evidence of The Idea of Nature the distinction is being clearly

utilized in his lectures of 1934 (cf. IN, v, 29-30). So on the

evidence of these two works alone it appears that he had worked

out the requisite distinctions sometime between 1924 and 1934.1

_______________________
1 Knox found it incredible that Collingwood had devel-
oped his position on Q-A logic and presuppositions prior to
1932, and on this ground alone he felt justified in rejecting
the autobiographical interpretation (IH, x-xi). But as we have
already observed, there is no
429

But the date on which he actually worked out the ne-

cessary distinctions is not as relevant to our discussion as the

fact that he ultimately did work it out to his own satisfaction,

and that we have an indication of his basic ideas on the subject

from the fourth chapter of the Essay on Metaphysics. Since the

summary is given there in semi-formal outline already, we shall

here merely summarize it in tabular form, interspersing his own

notes and comments between the various definitions and

propositions. (His "notes" were numbered; his comments were not.)

________________________
such direct assertion in the Autobiography, and even if there
were it is hardly grounds for rejecting the autobiographical
interpretation without sufficient evidence to the contrary. We
have already stated that we do not accept Knox's authority in
his claim to have had access to such unambiguous and unqualified
evidence in Collingwood's unpublished manuscripts, since to do
so would be guilty of uncritical historiography.
430

TABLE 9

QUESTION-AND-ANSWER LOGIC IN THE ESSAY ON METAPHYSICS: Q-AM

Proposition 1. Every statement that anybody ever makes is made


in answer to a question. (EM, 23).

Comment 1. Statements and questions may be made to someone


else or to oneself (EM, 24).

Comment 2. In proportion as a person thinks scientifically


he knows that his statements are answers to
questions.

Note 1. A question is logically prior to its own answer.

Comment 3. A question is also temporally prior if thinking


is scientific, but the temporal priority is such
that the question does not cease to be a question
when the answer begins, but continues for the
whole duration.

Comment 4. An answered question does not cease being a


question; it only ceases being an unanswered
question. (EM, 24).

Definition 1. Let that which is stated (i.e. that which can be


true or false) be called a proposition, and let
stating it be called propounding it (EM, 25).

Note 2. The use of the word "proposition" is exclusively


limited to that which is stated, and "pro-
pounding" only for proposition. This is not
ordinary usage, which would allow also that a
supposition or question be propounded as well.

Proposition 2. Every question involves a presupposition.

Comment 5. Any given question directly or immediately in-


volves only one presupposition, that being the
presupposition from which it arises. Indirectly
it may involve more than one. (EM, 25).

Comment 6. The answer to any question presupposes whatever


the question presupposes (EM, 63).
431

Definition 2. To say that a question "does not arise" is the


ordinary English way of saying that it involves a
presupposition which is not in fact being made
(EM, 26).

Comment 7. One can make presuppositions without knowing it,


or without knowing what presupposition one is
making ((cf. comments 2 and 5)).

Definition 3. The fact that something causes a certain question


to arise I call the "logical efficacy" of that
thing (EM, 27).

Definition 4. To assume is to suppose by an act of free choice.

Comment 8. All assumptions are suppositions, but not all


suppositions are assumptions.]

Comment 9. Some suppositions are made without being aware


that they are made, or without being aware that
others might possibly be made. (EM, 27).

Proposition 3. The logical efficacy of a supposition does not


depend upon the truth of what is supposed, or
even on its being thought true, but only on its
being supposed (EM, 28).

Comment 10. In scientific thinking it is possible and often


profitable to argue from suppositions which we
know to be false, believe to be false, or neither
know nor believe to be false or true (EM, 28).

Proposition 4. A presupposition is either relative or absolute


(EM, 29).
_____________________
1 Collingwood does not further define "assumption" and
"supposition," but from his remarks it appears that "supposi-
tions" are presuppositions (and may therefore be either absolute
or relative), and that "assumptions" are presuppositions of
which we are conscious. Since we are not always conscious of our
presuppositions (Definition 4 and Comment 9), it follows that
not all suppositions are assumptions.
432

Definition 5. By a relative presupposition I mean one which


stands relatively to one question as its pre-
supposition, and relatively to another question
as its answer (EM, 29).

Comment 11. To question a presupposition is to demand that it


should be verified; that is, to demand that a
question should be asked to which the affirmative
answer would be that presupposition itself, now
in the form of a proposition. Hence to speak of
verifying a presupposition involves supposing
that it is a relative presupposition (EM, 30).

Definition 6. An absolute presupposition is one which stands,


relatively to all questions to which it is re-
lated, as a presupposition, never as an answer
(EM, 31).

Comment 12. Absolute presuppositions are not verifiable(EM,


32).

Comment 13. The use of absolute presuppositions in science is


their logical efficacy; it does not depend on
their being true or false, but only on their
being supposed.

Proposition 5. Absolute presuppositions are not propositions


(EM, 32).

Comment 14. That is because they are never answers to


questions (EM, 32).

Comment 15. The distinction between truth and falsehood does


not apply to absolute presuppositions at all,
that distinction being peculiar to propositions
(EM, 32).

Comment 16. Any question involving the presupposition that an


absolute presupposition is a proposition is a
nonsense question. This includes such questions
as "Is it true?" or "What evidence is there that
it is true?" (EM, 33).
433

Now even though, incredibly enough, Collingwood does not

here define the terms "question," and "presupposition," and

although the term "hypothesis" does not appear in this outline,

it is nonetheless clear that since an hypothesis is a

supposition consciously made within a given inquiry,2 we may

take it that an hypothesis is what Collingwood is calling an

assumption. With the distinction between questions and

assumptions made explicit, the ambiguity from Speculum Mentis

concerning questions and hypotheses as non-assertions disappears.

But we are also confronted with a new problem insofar as

there are several noteworthy differences between the two

versions of Q-A logic, i.e. that offered by the Autobiography

and by the Essay on Metaphysics (which we shall hereafter refer

to as Q-AA and Q-AM respectively). (1) We notice that Q-AA

stressed the fact that Q-A logic differed from propositional

logic inasmuch as it took the Q-A complex as the unit of

meaning, truth, and validity, rather than recognizing these to

be properties of propositions as such (see above, Table 3 nos.

2, 3, and 4). In Table 9 we notice there is no mention of

meaning or validity, and truth or falsity is taken as the

defining characteristic of propositions as such (Def. 1).

_________________________
2 We assume that from the point of view of scientific
inquiry the notion of an unconscious hypothesis would not be
acceptable, since one could never know when the conditions for a
satisfactory demonstration of it were fulfilled. Cf. Table 9 ,
Comment 2.
434

(2) The strict Q-A correlativity of Q-AA is here universalized

and stated in terms of persons (Proposition 1). (3) In

connection with the function of presuppositions in "raising"

questions, which is never defined in Q-AA, Collingwood here

introduces the notion of "logical efficacy," or the property of

"something" (e.g. suppositions) which "causes" questions to

arise (Definition 3, Proposition 3).

At first these differences seem innocuous enough. The

first falls back on the ancient tradition dating back to Plato,

that the minimal unit of truth or falsity is the proposition or

declarative sentence. The second states the Q-AA requirement of

correlativity in terms of persons engaged in acts of questioning

and answering. And the third specifies the priority relationship

of presuppositions to questions and answers. The omission of the

requirement that meaning and validity hold only for Q-A

complexes and not for propositions by themselves might also be

written off as a mere oversight of Q-AM. But honesty requires us

to admit that there are actually major problems involved in

these differences between Q-AA and Q-AM, problems noticed (and

sometimes exploited) by many of Collingwood's interpreters. For

if truth or falsity is proper to propositions as such, how are

we to understand the related truth-value of questions and

presuppositions, not to mention the Q-AA assertion that truth

and falsity do not belong to propositions as such? And if Q-A

correlativity is defined

435
in terms of persons, how can Q-A logic escape the charge of psy-

chologism, which is offensive to logicians precisely because it

is necessarily rooted in the subjective processes of con-

sciousness? And how can one decide which presupposition "causes"

a question to arise within such subjective states of

consciousness?

Since these difficulties all turn in one way or another

on the Q-AA assertion of the priority of the Q-A complex over

the proposition as the unit of meaning, truth, and validity, a

priority inadvertently called into question by Q-AM, we shall

examine each of these logical functions in turn. If the Q-AA

claim cannot be upheld, we shall have to ask whether Q-AM is

sufficient correction of his earlier view to sustain the Q-AA

claim for Q-A logic as an alternative to traditional F-logic.

(1) Let us examine first the claim of the Autobiography

for a Q-A meaning-priority over the meaning of a proposition as

such. In Q-AA Collingwood insisted that (a) in order to find out

what a proposition means the question to which the proposition

is an answer must be known; and also (b) since each answer is to

a certain specific question in the systematic inquiry, it is

possible using the same piece of evidence (presumably the

textual assertion) to argue back from a propositional answer to

its question (see Table 3, nos. 4 a-d, 6 a-b). But these two

requirements seem impossible to fulfill, since it is difficult

to see how one can ever know to which question an answer

belongs, and hence which


436

presupposition-question (P-Q) complex is specifically prior to

it, unless one had independent and prior knowledge of the

meaning of the propositional answer (cf. Mink, MHD, 128).

Supposing the assertion is "Eric is going to Elgin"; how is one

to decide whether this assertion belongs to the question, "Where

is Eric going?" or to the question "Is the moon more or less

than 106 kilometers distant from the earth?" Without knowing

that the proposition about Eric has no evident

meaning-correlation with a question concerning the distance

between planetary bodies, the answer appears unassignable to one

question or P-Q complex rather than another.

Collingwood might well reply that the Q-A complex we are

discussing is an absurd example, because it does not meet the

requirements (a) that they belong to the same systematic

inquiry, and (b) that a question must be relevant to that in-

quiry. Therefore a question cannot be fished out of a

"hyperuranean lucky bag" and stuck together with an utterly un-

related question. But absurdity is what we use as an index for

the passage into incoherence, and we wish to know how Col-

lingwood's Q-A logic prevents us from such a lapse. On his

grounds such a lapse appears not only possible but inevitable,

since we do not have any criteria for deciding what constitutes

"sameness of inquiry." But even laying aside this important

omission, if we take the case of a recognizably systematic


437

inquiry (and in so doing tacitly import requirements not

specified by Collingwood), similar objections arise. Supposing

the inquiry is legal, and we are trying to find out what the

question was that is Q-A related, to an assertion-a slip of

paper bearing the words, "Eric is going to Elgin." Is this the

answer to the question, "Where is Eric going?" or "Who is going

to Elgin?" or "Is anyone going to Elgin?" It appears that in

even a fairly simple case with directly related questions and

answers, an answer may retain its meaning while being Q-A

related in several Q-A complexes. In short, it appears that the

meaning of a proposition may be Q-A complex independent.

Obviously one of the other of the two Q-AA requirements

must be abandoned, and since we wish to retain the notion of a

systematic inquiry for Q-AM, but not necessarily the

meaning-requirement, it may be necessary to drop the latter and

declare Q-AM to be an improved revision. If we adopted this

conclusion we evade the viciously circular argument that "we

cannot know what a statement means unless we know what question

it answers, but we cannot decide which question it answers

unless we know what it means" (Mink, MHD, 128). But we do not

yet know if there is some special sense of the highly ambiguous

term, "meaning" which Collingwood may have in mind, and which

may escape such objections as these.


438

(2) But there is a second logical function attributed to

the Q-A complex in the Q-AA version, but not appearing in

Q-AM--i.e. validity. According to the Autobiography, "no two

propositions can agree with or be contradictory to one another

unless they are answers to the same question" (Table 3, 3).

Again, even setting aside the issue of how one establishes which

question corresponds to a given answer, it appears to fail to

meet objections on the grounds of fairly straightforward

examples. In our example from the previous section the

contradictory of "Eric is going to Elgin" would be, on

propositional grounds alone, "Eric is not going to Elgin," and

it is capable of being constructed without any reference to a

common question, whatever that might be. What is worse, we can

say that these propositions are contradictory even though they

may be answers to different and even opposing questions: the

first may be an answer to "Is Eric going to Elgin?" and the

latter to "Is Eric not going to Elgin?" They are obviously not

the same question, yet they are contradictory answers (cf.

Krausz, CEPC, 225). Furthermore, as we saw in the example from

the previous section, one and the same answer may be the answer

to several different questions, without losing its identity,

i.e. its agreement with itself. It would appear, therefore, that

validity and such validity relations as agreement or

contradiction are also Q-A context independent.


439

With this line of argument Collingwood would be even

less tolerant then the former. The sense of sameness he is

talking about, he would reply, is not that of an abstract class

or universal, or even of propositions constructed on these

grounds. "Sameness of question" is determined on the basis of

sameness of an historical process, the process of a concrete

inquiry, where the researcher holds before his mind a question

the central meaning of which is continually being modified in

the light of new data or partial answers to it (cf. Table 3, 3

a-b).

Since this reply borders on the relationship of Q-A and

D-logic, we shall have to postpone a more satisfactory

consideration of it until we have had a chance to examine the

latter more closely (which we shall do in the next section). But

we may note here that it still fails to meet the objection. From

the point of view of the F-logic that Q-A logic is supposed to

replace, it is inadequate: F-logic makes the claim that in the

case of certain propositions it is possible to decide on their

validity on structural or syntactic grounds alone, i.e. on the

placement and grouping of their logical constants, irrespective

of its location in a Q-A complex or of the specific meaning of

its terms. The assertion, "Eric is going to Elgin and it is not

the case that Eric is going to Elgin" is invalid on formal

grounds alone, because there is a self-contradiction involved in

the statement. Such a self-contradiction would even render a

question
440

invalid, insofar as questions of the form, "What is the A such

that A and not-A?" can have no valid answer for any possible

substitution for A in the question. And if Collingwood were to

point out that this is what he meant when he said that a ques-

tion is "right" if it enables the inquiry to proceed (Table 3 4

c), we should have to reply that a contradictory answer stops

the inquiry from proceeding not because it is the "wrong" answer

but because it is self-contradictory, which it would be no

matter which Q-A complex it appeared in.

Perhaps we are flogging a dead horse, insofar as there

is no mention of contradiction or validity relations in Q-AM.

But then what sort of logical relations are there between pro-

positions, questions, and presuppositions? We shall take this up

again when we examine the consistency claims for Q-A logic.

However, we have one further logical function of Q-A complexes

to attend to, one which appears in both Q-AA and Q-AM.

(3) Although Collingwood states in Q-AM that the

proposition is that which can be true or false (Table 9, De-

finition 1), he also states that every proposition is an answer

to a question (Table 9, Proposition 1), so that it appears that

he wishes to retain the Q-AA requirement of strict Q-A

correlativity with respect to truth claims (Table 3, 4). While

it is true that Q-AM does not explicitly state that the presence
441

of a question (with or without its presupposition) is a

necessary condition for the truth or falsity of propositional

answer in a P-Q-A complex, this was clearly his intention in

Q-AA, so we wish to examine the sense in which a proposition is

dependent for its truth on the P-Q complex antecedant to it. Now

in both Q-AA and Q-AM Collingwood specifically states that the

presupposition of a Q-A complex need not be true, but only

supposed; and he never suggests that questions by themselves

have any assignable truth value aside from their answers or

presuppositions, so that it is not unreasonable to assume that

questions are neutral with respect to truth or falsity. But then

if both questions and presuppositions need not have any

assignable truth value, from whence comes the truth or falsity

of the answer?

Collingwood would no doubt reply that he never said that

an answer is deducible from a question and its presupposition;

in fact he would say that its not being deducible is essential

to the relationship of presupposition. If there were no need for

inquiry, then there would be no need for presuppositions, since

questions would not "arise" and propositions could simply be

deduced from one another as in a purely formal system.

Collingwood is speaking of the sort of inquiry which is not

closed or complete with respect to propositions and their

relations. He is discussing on-going inquiries in which

discoveries are being made, real questions are arising, answers

are being verified in ways appropriate to


442

the systematic inquiry at hand, and assumptions are being called

for as an aid to deciding alternative answers to questions.

But then the truth value of a propositional answer is

being decided by verificational processes outside the Q-A com-

plex itself, and we are faced with the alternative of adding a

further requirement to the truth claim for the Q-A complex (i.e.

that a Q-A complex is true or false only if the answer is

verifiable or falsifiable), or dropping the claim altogether

(i.e. that the truth or falsity of a proposition is dependent on

its being an element in a Q-A or P-Q-A complex). But in either

case it appears that truth is something that is Q-A complex

independent. In our previous example, if "Eric is going to

Elgin" is true only if Eric is indeed going to Elgin and false

if he is not, this appears to be the case whether or not "Eric

is going to Elgin" belongs to the question, "Where is Eric

going?" or "Who is going to Elgin?" Unless Collingwood has some

special sense in mind for the term "truth," we are forced to

admit that even this requirement fails to hold for even a simple

example.

But perhaps we have disproven too much. There is cer-

tainly some sort of logical connection between a proposition and

its presupposition, and there is also a logical relation between

a question and its presupposition. And we can say that a

proposition that is a valid answer to a question presupposes

whatever the question presupposes, so that


443

there is some sense in which answer, question, and

presupposition form a logical complex. But it appears that in

attempting to sort out the logical relations of the terms of

this complex Collingwood conflated a number of distinct

characteristics of linguistic entities--viz. meaning, truth, and

validity--and then assigned them all to the Q-A complex. But (1)

meaning is a linguistic function that applies minimally to terms

(individual words, or phrases and propositions regarded

precisely as terms, and capable of being used as the subject of

an assertion--e.g. of the form, "A means B"); (2) truth is a

function minimally applicable to propositions (whatever says

something (a predicate) about something else (a subject)); and

(3) validity is a function of complexes of propositions bound

together by logical connectives. On the face of it, it appears

unlikely that anything like a Q-A or P-Q-A complex can satisfy

logically appropriate conditions for being the minimal unit for

all three of these functions.

However it also seems unlikely that an Oxford professor

of philosophy, respected enough to be named to the distinguished

chair of Waynflete Professor of Metaphysics, would be wholly

ignorant of such an elementary logical distinction. We therefore

suspect that something has escaped our notice. Perhaps

Collingwood does have a special usage in mind for each of these

functions (meaning, truth, and validity), so


444

that they may after all escape some of these objections.

Pursuing this lead will take us into a discussion of

Collingwood's views on language and intellectual consciousness,

which will occupy us in section 4 of this chapter, immediately

following our analysis (in section 3) of his Essay on

Philosophical Method, the distinctions of which are required to

make sense of his definitions both of language and of mind (i.e.

definition by means of what he calls a "scale of forms").

But we have one last claim for Q-A logic to attend to

before pursuing this line of inquiry. According to the

Autobiography, Q-A logic is supposed to be an alternative to

propositional F-logic, which he says it replaces. Minimally this

must mean that it can do the same things that F-logic does, and

satisfy the claims that F-logic makes for itself. And there is

much to recommend a direct parallel between Q-A and F-logic. If

we wish to understand what sort of logical relations are

involved in P-Q-A complexes we must begin by assuming that it is

a function more akin to validity than to truth or meaning, since

it involves a relationship between elements that are on a level

with propositions rather than with terms, and it relates these

elements within a complex which resembles a group of

propositions linked by logical connectives. Secondly one can say

that there are certain truth-functional relationships that exist

between the elements of a P-Q-A complex, although it is not

straightforwardly one
445

of entailment:3 questions alone nor questions with their

presuppositions nor presuppositions alone do not entail their

answers, even though a propositional answer alone can be shown

to entail certain presuppositions (e.g. (a) "There is a noon

train to Elgin," (b) "Who is taking the noon train to Elgin?"

and (c) “Erik is taking the noon train to Elgin,” where (a) does

not entail (c), but (c) does entail (a)).4 Similarly within a

P-Q-A complex one can say there are certain logical

relationships that exist between the question and the other

elements: for example that if a propositional answer and one of

its direct presuppositions are known, a valid question can be

reconstructed and interposed between them

__________________
3 What the exact truth-functional relationship is be-
tween a proposition and its presupposition has been a matter of
lively contemporary debate into which we shall not enter here.
But we may note in passing that most of the contending
definitions of presupposing take into account the difference
between presupposition and entailment. For a good discussion of
the subject and an excellent bibliography, see Nuel D. Belnap
and Thomas B. Steel, The Logic of Questions and Answers (New
Haven, 1976).

4 Cf. P. F. Strawson, Introduction to Logical Theory


(London, 1952), pp. 174-75: "If a statement S presupposes a
statement S' in the sense that the truth of S' is a precondition
of the truth-or-falsity of S. then of course there will be a
kind of logical absurdity in conjoining S with the denial of
S' . . . . But we must distinguish this kind of logical ab-
surdity from straight-forward self-contradiction. It is self-
contradictory to conjoin S with the denial of S' if S' is a
necessary condition of the truth, simply, of S. It is a dif-
ferent kind of logical absurdity to conjoin S with the denial of
S' if S' is a necessary condition of the truth or falsity of S.
The relation between S and S' in the first case is that S
entails S'. We need a different name for the relation between S
and S' in the second case; let us say, as above, that S
presupposes S'." Notice that Strawson's definition holds
directly between statements or propositions, and does not in-
volve questions at all. Cf. note 5, below.
446

(in our above example, (b) is constructable directly from (c)

and (a)--assuming that we know that (c) is an answer to a

question, and that (a) is a common presupposition to both the

question and its answer); that from a propositional answer and

an appropriate question one or more presuppositions can be

constructed; that from a question and its presupposition(s) the

range of alternative possible answers is limited; etc.5 And

finally, one can say that the terms used in any given P-Q-A

complex cannot be used with shifting meanings without destroying

the sense (and consequently the logical relations) of the P-Q-A

complex itself (in our above example question (b) and answer (a)

are compatible with presupposition (a') "There are no passengers

on the noon train to Elgin," only if "taking the train" in (b)

means "driving the train," and Eric is an engineer; otherwise a

P-Q-A complex consisting of (a')-(b)-(c) would involve a

self-contradiction, and therefore would be nonsensical).

__________________________
5 Cf. P. T. Geach, Logic Matters (Berkeley, 1972), p.
82: "I say that P presupposes Q when, if Q is not true of an
object x, the question does not arise whether or not we ought to
predicate P of x, and thus neither P nor its negation is true of
x . . . . This relation of presupposition is quite different
from entailment . . . ." Cf. also Belnap and Steel, p. 113: "A
question, q, presupposes a statement, A, if and only if the
truth of A is a logically necessary condition for there being
some true answer to q. Evidently it is a consequence of this
definition that A is a presupposition of q, if and only if every
direct answer to q logically implies A." Both of these
definitions introduce the notion of a question directly into the
definition of presupposition. in contrast to Strawson (above,
note 4).
447

Thus it is not difficult to show that there are

specifiable logical relations involved in Q-A logic with its

distinctive P-Q-A complexes; and we can also say with some con-

fidence that meaning, truth, and validity do have a bearing on

these P-Q-A complexes, inasmuch as they require an identity of

meaning of their terms, have truth-functional relationships

between the elements of the complex, and validity or entailment

relationships between propositional answers and their

presuppositions. But this seems to reverse what Collingwood was

trying to say about Q-A logic (at least in Q-AA): instead of Q-A

complexes determining the meaning, truth, and validity of

propositions, it appears that all three are established

independently of those complexes, and have a logical priority

over them. Without some sort of deductive inference structure

how could one decide whether a question legitimately arises from

a given presupposition, and consequently what counts for a real

answer in a P-Q-A complex? And without some means of

establishing the semantic identity of the terms, we have no way,

within Q-A logic, to determine the limited range of answers

and/or presuppositions allowable for a given question. It

appears, therefore, that far from being an alternative to

F-logic, Q-A logic presupposes it.

But the final blow to the thesis that Q-A and F-logic

are alternative logics is that Q-A logic fails to meet the

claims of
448

consistency, completeness, and formality that F-logic not only

claims but demonstrates for itself--at least for the sort of

axiomatic F-logic with which Collingwood was familiar.6 Now in

some respects Q-A logic as Collingwood discusses it has the

appearance of a formal system: it states some criteria for what

counts as an element within that system (questions, answers,

presuppositions--although as we noted, questions and

presuppositions are never defined), as well as how they are to

be introduced or eliminated (assumptions are made by acts of

free choice, questions arise in accordance with the logical

efficacy of a presupposition, questions are eliminated if their

presuppositions are not made, or if they are raised with respect

to absolute presuppositions, etc.). But this appearance of

system breaks down when it is examined more closely for its

consistency, completeness and formality.

(1) Concerning consistency we have perhaps already said

more than enough. In summary we may note that if it is possible

in some cases (i.e. complex propositions bound by logical

connectives) to decide on the truth or falsity of a proposition

on formal grounds alone, without knowing anything about the

question which it answers, or without requiring that

___________________________
6 Cf. I. M. Bochenski, The Methods of Contemporary
Thought (New York, 1968), PP. 70-72. On Collingwood’s notion of
F-logic and its sources, see EPM, 148n, 153; Krausz, CEPC, 3n.
449

the variables within a proposition be specified semantically,7

then it seems not only that the Q-AA contention that meaning,

truth, and validity are properties not of propositions alone but

of Q-A (or perhaps P-Q-A) complexes is false, but so also is the

Q-AM assertion that some presuppositions (viz. absolute

presuppositions) cannot be true or false because they are not

(or cannot be) answers to questions. On formal grounds alone we

may argue that any assertion is false if it contains a formal

contradiction.

In the sequel we may find that Collingwood might have

meant that the question of formal coherence belongs to a dif-

ferent systematic inquiry (i.e. part of a Q-A system where the

questions raised are precisely about the coherence of state-

ments). But we may still observe that formal questions cannot

ever be irrelevant in any systematic inquiry to which Q-A logic

is applicable: insofar as an inquiry is systematic (or claims to

be so) its coherence is presumed.

(2) Concerning completeness, we must ask, first of all,

what is the full set of expressions of which questions, answers,

and presuppositions are members? Collingwood says that they are

the elements of a systematic inquiry, but that is hardly enough:

a systematic inquiry may also involve digging in the earth or

flying to the moon, but these activities are not part of a P-Q-A

complex. The elements of such a complex

_________________
7 Bochenski, p. 33; cf. IH, 253.
450

obviously belong to a set of expressions in a language of some

sort, a set at once broader than that of F-logic (because

F-logic is ordinarily confined to the set of all propositions

that can be true or false, whereas Q-A logic includes questions

and presuppositions, which are not propositions nor

proposition-fragments and yet have logical functions), and

narrower than it (because Q-A logic is only concerned with those

P-Q-A complexes that are part of a systematic inquiry, and not

the set of all possible propositions, whether they are part of

such an inquiry or not). Furthermore it can only include the set

of all meaningful expressions in a systematic inquiry, since

presuppositions and questions, while truth-value neutral, are

nonetheless bearers of meaning at the level of complexity of a

statement (to be a presupposition, for example, a statement need

not be true or false, but it must be intelligible--i.e. a

well-formed grammatical sentence).

It is not just a matter of having a group name for these

elements of Q-A logic, it is a matter of deciding (or having

grounds for deciding) what counts for a well-constructed formula

(a meaningful expression) in it and ruling out all expressions

that are not. It is clear that Collingwood has some such

criteria in mind, because he indicates that not just any

combination of terms with a question mark at the end could count

as a question (cf. Table 3, 4 a), nor can any arbitrary grouping

of words
451

count as a supposition or proposition just because it ends with

a period. Candidates for membership in Q-A logic are evidently

grammatically sound and formally coherent questions and

assertions in a language of some sort, presumably the language

accepted and employed by the inquiry in progress. But this means

that Q-A logic relies on extrinsic factors for what counts for a

candidate for membership in the Q-A system, and we must presume

such grammatical and formal criteria as essential to it. If

Collingwood presupposes all these rules in the construction of

his Q-A logic, how can we concur with his suggestion in the

Autobiography that Q-A logic was intended as an alternative to

F-logic, or that in logic he was a revolutionary?

If there is anything revolutionary in his Q-A logic it

is not that it supplants grammar and formal logic, but rather

that, if anything, it extends them or adds something to them in

their application within organized inquiry or

knowledge-acquisition, something essential that was ignored in

the reduction of knowledge to a set of propositions which merely

conform to the rules of grammar and logic. (In section 4 of this

chapter we shall take this matter up again in connection with

Collingwood's discussion of language and logic in The Principles

of Art.)

(3) Finally, concerning formality, it is clear from the

very
452

first proposition of Q-AM that Q-A logic is not staying within

the bounds of a formal system: Proposition 1 appears to be

stating a matter of psychological rather than purely logical

fact. If proposition 1 had read: "From every statement a

question can be constructed," it might have generated some

interesting formal problems--e.g. what the interrogative

function entails for propositions cast into this mode; how they

might function in relation to declarative propositions of

various sorts; etc. But instead Collingwood says that "every

statement that anybody ever makes is made in answer to a

question," where personal agency is brought into what might

otherwise be a purely logical analysis of the relationship

between questions and answers. Since the thrust of 20th century

logic is precisely in the opposite, non-psychologistic

direction, it is clear that this way of stating the relationship

of question and answer would not be regarded by formal logicians

as acceptable.9

______________________
8 I. M. Bochenski, Contemporary European Philosophy
(Berkeley, 1969), p. 253.

9 Even sympathetic critics have taken offence at this


approach: see J. F. Post, "A Defense of Collingwood's Theory of
Presuppositions," Inquiry, VIII (1965), pp. 332-54: "The reader
is first struck by the psychologism of what purports to be a
purely logical investigation . . . . The psychologism runs
throughout" (p. 333). Post sets out to eliminate the formal
absurdities from Collingwood's theory of presuppositions, as
does Krausz in his article for the book of critical essays on
Collingwood which he edited: see CEPC, 222-40. The
reconstructions by both Post and Krausz are admirable, but fail
to take into account what Collingwood had in mind
453

But aside from this there is still a question of whether

Proposition 1 (and notice that it is called a proposition rather

than a definition) is factually true. Is it reasonable to assume

that every statement that is ever made by anyone is made in

answer to a question? What about commands, warnings, and

exclamations; petitions filed in court; classroom lectures,

declarations of religious faith, sentences read during a

filibuster in Congress, etc. (cf. Mink, MHD, 127-28)? But even

aside from exceptions, we are certainly not aware that this is

always the case. Collingwood's assurance that this priority of

questions is purely logical (Table 9, Note 1) may soften the

claim a bit, but it does not render it any less uncertain. If a

question is logically prior to its answer, how are we to

understand this priority? Collingwood discusses it in terms of

causality, since a question arises as a result of the causal

operation of what he calls the "logical efficacy" of a

supposition (Table 9, Definition 3). Even if we could set aside

our hesitation to accept something like an efficient cause

operating at the logical level of thought, we are still

_____________________
for Q-A logic. He gave no indication that he ever intended it to
be reducible to, or incorporatable into, a formal system of
logic. A formal "erotetic logic" treats questions just as formal
logic treats propositions--as so many finished products. It is
not concerned with the process of asking questions, but only
with the formal properties of questions once they are already
asked. But Collingwood was interested precisely in the process
of ongoing inquiry, where questions are arising; he insisted
that the process was completely reducible neither to
psychological feeling states nor to the rules of formal logic,
and yet had a "logic" or rationality of its own.
454

left wondering about the priority of questions to answers. If it

is a priority in thought we wish to know why it is not merely

carried away in the stream of immediate consciousness, or why it

is not "merely psychological" or subjective (cf. IH, 292). What

is the objective dimension to a question--i.e. that aspect of it

which is not carried away in the stream of subjective

consciousness? Is it not merely subjective and hence merely psy-

chological unless one can also specify this objective component?

This is where the formalist would press him hardest for

an answer, and it is difficult to see how he would reply. Every

time Collingwood uses the term "logical" to describe the

priority of Q-A complexes, or of presuppositions to questions,

or of questions to answers, he is tacitly appealing to criteria

which he simultaneously appears to dismiss—i.e. to the objective

aspect wherein the relationship does not depend on mere

co-location in subjective consciousness. Without such objective

criteria we could hardly know what assumptions were uniquely

efficacious in causing a certain question to arise, since in our

subjective consciousness we are seldom aware of what all the

assumptions are that we are making relevant to a given

situation. But to say that anyone employing Q-A logic is bound

by the relationships he is describing is to say that the rules

of Q-A logic hold independently of subjective thought-contexts,

and are
455

binding directly on the related elements of the P-Q-A complex.

Without such an objective specification Collingwood's Q-A logic

is open to the sort of criticism that one of his sympathetic

critics leveled at him: "Collingwood says that 'every thought we

find ourselves thinking is the answer to a question' ((EM, 36)).

Surely every presupposition, whether it is an AP ((absolute

presupposition)) or not, may be a thought we find ourselves

thinking. Hence every presupposition may be the answer to a

question, and it seems that there can be no AP's. Short of radi-

cal revision of the whole chapter, there is no way out of this

contradiction."l0

* * * * * * * * *

From the foregoing it is clear that on the face of it

there are serious difficulties with Q-A logic either in the Q-AA

or Q-AM versions. The P-Q-A complex does not succeed in standing

up to the autobiographical claim that it is the unit of meaning,

truth, and validity, nor does Q-A logic meet the criteria of

consistency, completeness, and formality required of it if it is

to serve as an alternative to F-logic. Unless we can find

mitigating arguments in the later writings to reconcile some

_____________________
1O Post, "A Defense of Collingwood's Theory of Presup-
positions," p. 336. Post also raises an interesting objection to
the suggestion that there is a class of assertions (absolute
presuppositions) which have no truth value: "A sentence with no
truth value would be implied by every statement, since there
would be no way for the latter to be true and the former to be
false" (ibid.).
456

of the more glaring of these difficulties we shall find it

impossible to uphold the Autobiography on this issue: it fails

to be coherent on its own much less as an interpretation of

anything else.

But perhaps misled by Collingwood's autobiographical

claim that Q-A logic is to be understood as an alternative to

replace F-logic, we have been asking the wrong questions about

Q-A logic, expecting something more of its explicit performance

than its implicit promise is capable of delivering. Rather than

being a substitute for F-logic, suppose Q-A logic is regarded as

complementary to it, perhaps even tacitly presupposing it?

Suppose it addresses not a body of determinate propositions but

rather a somewhat indeterminate situation from which definite

propositions are to be extracted? In such a situation knowledge

would be something yet to be achieved, and the asking of

questions based on presuppositions (which may state the basic

structural framework or relevant features of the situation

within which such knowledge is to be determined) would be one of

the means that bring determinacy to it. Questions would

therefore be one of the signs of the difference which knowing

introduces within the knower-known situation, signifying the

presence of consciousness or awareness at the linguistic plane

of knowledge. And the P-Q complexes would therefore


457

have a heuristic priority not reducible to, but presupposing,

F-logic and its relevant requirements within inquiry.ll

But if we try to interpret Collingwood's Q-A logic in

strictly formal terms we are committed to ruling out any "psy-

chologisms" that may appear in it, which threatens to gut the

theory as Collingwood proposes it: he would not ultimately

warrant the requirement of an F-logic which would call for the

elimination of the personal dimension to inquiry precisely be-

cause that is what he claims all knowledge is for--i.e. self-

knowledge. Therefore it is clear that just as in Speculum Mentis

he had argued against the abstract universal, so too he presents

Q-A logic as the thought of an agent employed in the acquisition

of knowledge. The combined weight of the evidence we have

considered thus far indicates that Collingwood would refuse to

give up this requirement.

But then this involves using terms like "question,"

"answer," and "presupposition" and even "meaning" and "truth,"

in something other than a univocal, F-logical way. They may not

be the merely formal entities they appear to be, but rather they

may include in their meanings a reference to their entertainment

within a personal consciousness. They may be, in short,

epistemological entities rather than merely or purely logical

ones, and as epistemological entities they must be regarded as

displaying

______________________
1l Cf. Donald S. Mackay, "On Supposing and Presuppos-
ing," The Review of Metaphysics (Vol. II, no. 5, 1948), pp. 1-20.
458

the properties of mental activities better expressed by the use

of verb-forms rather than noun forms: questioning, propounding,

answering, presupposing, etc.--the very forms that Collingwood

prefers to use.

In the next section we shall explore the requirements

that Collingwood finds necessary for dealing with the structure

of concepts of this sort--concepts that we have already

witnessed him calling "dialectical."

3. Dialectical Logic and Philosophical Methodology.

The one work in which Collingwood makes the sort of

distinctions required for a logic that can serve as an al-

ternative to traditional F-logic is in the Essay on

Philosophical Method--a work which in his autobiographical self-

estimate he called "my best book in matter; in style, I may call

it my only book, for it is the only one I ever had the time to

finish as well as I know how" (A, 118). In the Essay the subject

matter (philosophical logic or methodology) is distributed in a

manner which corresponds to the traditional (Aristotelian)

division of logic into terms, judgments, and inferences.

Chapters II-IV deal with terms--philosophical concepts or

universals (the overlap of classes, the scale of forms, and

definition and description). These chapters also discuss

classification and division, but not extensionality


459

or the distinction between the denotation and connotation of

terms. Chapters V and VI deal with the quantity and quality of

judgments, but say nothing directly about predication, the

distribution of terms, or the analytic-synthetic distinction.

Chapter VIII deals with deductive and inductive inference, but

not with the modes of valid or invalid deductive inference. And

Chapter IX even discusses the systematic claims of completeness

and consistency, but says nothing about formality (cf. Mink,

MHD, 61-62). It would therefore appear that if we are ever to

find a clue for understanding Collingwood's view of "logic" it

would be in this work.

However we have already had occasion to note that there

are formidable problems in trying to ascertain what the

standpoint of the Essay is, or how the reader is supposed to

take its substantive remarks about non-philosophical methods or

even non-methodological philosophical issues. We may recall from

that discussion that in the Essay he states that (a) the manner

in which non-philosophical concepts, judgments, and forms of

reasoning are characterized is not meant to say anything

explicitly about mathematical or empirical science, but is

rather only meant to contrast methods commonly thought to be

employed by these modes of thought and mistakenly applied to

philosophical subjects (EPM, 9, 151); and (b) he confesses in

the final chapter that his initial agreement with the reader to

treat as an hypothesis the assumption that philosophical


460

concepts have a peculiar logical structure, has been violated

throughout by appeal to philosophical experience (EPM, 222-23).

In the context of our present discussion these two difficulties

put obstacles in our path to understanding Collingwood's views

on logic. The first renders suspect any interpretation of the

Essay which takes as literally true its remarks on subjects

other than philosophy; and the second raises the issue of the

circularity of the argument of the Essay insofar as the defining

characteristics he proposes as applying to philosophy itself are

first advanced hypothetically and then "proven" categorically by

appeal to the experience of philosophers. We might get around

the first obstacle by pointing out that the Essay itself argues

that logic is a part of philosophy, and "what philosophy is" is

the very subject of the book (EPH, 2-3, 7). But this is further

complicated by the fact that Collingwood states that he will not

discuss the implications of the Essay for metaphysics, logic, or

the theory of knowledge (EPM, 7-8)--a promise which is also

violated throughout, e.g. by his discussion of the ontological

argument and the subject matter of metaphysics in the sixth

chapter, by his discussion of philosophy as a branch of

literature in the tenth, as well as his use of examples from

epistemology, logic, and ethics throughout the book.


461

Until we have had a chance to survey the key concepts

and the central argument of the Essay we cannot resolve these

difficulties of the standpoint of the Essay. But from even a

superficial reading of the introductory chapter one can draw

several conclusions about how Collingwood intended the Essay to

be taken. (1) The Essay is concerned with discussing the nature

of philosophy as an activity of thought, exemplified as

philosophical experience and expressed on certain occasions in

characteristic or typical ways (EPM, 2-3, 7); (2) Concerning

this activity certain generalizations are possible which are

capable of serving as ideal principles of method, and to which

we are bound when we are trying to think philosophically (EPM,

3-4). (3) The strategy of discussing is basically Kantian in the

sense that (a) certain "facts" (or experiences) are brought to

our attention, (b) and then described and analyzed by comparing

them with similar examples from non-philosophical (or

pre-philosophical) equivalents, (c) the comparison exhibiting a

peculiar but typical structure to philosophical concepts,

judgments, and forms of reasoning, (d) which is only possible

under certain necessary conditions (EPM, 3-4, 222-23). At the

very least, then, we are entitled to say that Collingwood's

overriding concern in the Essay is to say something that is true

for a certain kind of thought, namely philosophy. This will have

to suffice as a provisional sense of the standpoint of the Essay

until we examine the issue of its argumentative circularity.


462

As usual we will begin with a brief outline of the key

concepts and conclusions of the Essay before proceeding to a

discussion of them and an analysis of the main line of argument

in the Essay.
463
TABLE 10

PHILOSOPHICAL METHOD

1. The overlap of classes: the concepts or universals of


philosophy are exemplified in overlapping classes instead of
mutually exclusive classes. A universal concept is one which
unites a number of different instances in a class-either a
plurality of individual instances in a general concept or a
plurality of specific differentiations into a generic
concept. The overlap of species of a philosophical genus
consists in the inclusion of part of the meaning of one of
the concepts in the meaning of another (i.e. it is a
relation of intension between concepts rather than a
relation of extension between classes). Alternative ways of
stating the overlap are: (a) two or more specifically
differing concepts may be exemplified in the same instances
(i.e. they may be conceptually different but instantially
the same), so that any distinction in philosophy may be a
distinction in concepts without a difference in instances;
and (b) Aristotle's formula for the overlap, i.e. that two
concepts may be the same but their being is not the same
(being an instance of the one is not the same as being an
instance of the other). (EPM, 27, 31, 40, 50, 91). Ignoring
the first rule of philosophical method (i.e. that the
specific classes of a philosophical concept are always
liable to overlap) leads to three related fallacies:

a. The fallacy of false disjunction (ffd) states that when a


generic concept is divided into its species there is a
corresponding division of its instances into mutually
exclusive classes.

b. The fallacy of precarious margins (the positive ap-


plication of the ffd) states that if there is a dis-
tinction between two concepts there must be a difference
between their instances (or, the margins between species
of a philosophical genus can be trusted not to spread to
include all the instances of co-ordinate species).

c. The fallacy of identified coincidents (the negative


application of the ffd) states that where there is no
difference in the extension of two concepts, there is no
distinction between the concepts themselves. (EPM,
48-50).
464

2. The scale of forms: the specification of a philosophical


genus (or concept) is such that its species differ from one
another both in degree and in kind, and are related to one
another both by opposition and by distinction. They therefore
constitute a scale of overlapping forms in which (a) whenever
the variable increases or decreases, certain critical points
on the scale are reached at which one specific form
disappears and is replaced by another; (b) the variable of
each species (its specific difference) is identified with the
generic essence; (c) every species is a realization of the
genus (there is no zero-point to the scale where the generic
essence is altogether absent, but rather it starts with unity
as the minimum realization of the genus); and (d) any point
on the scale sums up (or intentionally includes) the whole
scale from the minimum specification to that point. The scale
of forms explains the overlap of classes (i.e. shows how it
is possible) insofar as successive species of a philosophical
genus intentionally include the positive content (or meshing)
of all the forms preceding it in the scale. (EPM, 56-60, 81,
89, 91). Ignoring the second rule of philosophical method
(i.e. that the specification of a philosophical concept
constitutes a scale of forms) leads to several related
fallacies, all arising from the ffd applied to differences of
degree and kind and relations of opposition and distinction:

a. The fallacy of calculation assumes that because there are


differences of degree in philosophical concepts they are
susceptible of measurement and calculation (i.e. that
they are differences of degree only and not also
differences of kind).

b. The fallacy of indifference assumes that because the


species of a philosophical genus differ in kind, they
exhibit no differences of degree.

c. The fallacy of the false positive assumes that where


terms are related in a philosophical series the relation
is not of opposition but of mere distinction (so that it
makes positive terms out of negative ones).

d. The fallacy of null opposition asserts that the terms


related in a philosophical series are opposites but not
distincts (so that the negation of positive terms have
no actuality). (EPM, 80-81, 85-86).

3. Philosophical definition: the definition of a philosophical


concept is by means of a scale of forms, beginning with a
rudimentary minimum definition (the generic essence)
465

and adding qualitatively new determinations which gradually


alter the original definition and improve it as a statement
of the concept's essence. Philosophical definitions are
descriptive (i.e. they aim at a complete listing of
attributes, but not by mere enumeration but by exhibiting
their connections); (b) are real rather than verbal (i.e.
they seek to state the essence of a concept rather than the
meaning of a word); and (c) are relative rather than
absolute (i.e. they seek to make more precise what was to
some extent definite already, rather than stating a
definition which makes the difference between knowing
something and not knowing it at all). (EPM, 92, 94-98,
100-01). The phases of a philosophical definition are:

a. the minimum specification of a concept--the lower end of


the scale, or the necessary rudimentary expression of
the genus without which it would fail to be a genus at
all;

b. the intermediate specifications--later modifications of


the minimum specification by adding new qualifying
determinations; and

c. the final specification--the phase reached when the


definition explicitly states all that can be found in
the concept and is adequate to the thing defined. (EPM,
100-01).

4. The principles of concrete affirmation and negation:


philosophical judgments are so related that every negation
involves an affirmation, and every affirmation involves a
specific (not indiscriminate) negation. Whenever a phi-
losophical assertion is made it affirms something definite
and also denies something definite. In philosophy the af-
firmative judgment (S is P and not Q) and the negative
judgment (S is not Q but P) are equally definite and specific
answers to the same question (what is S?). (EPM, 10708, 110).
Ignoring these two principles leads to two associated
fallacies:

a. The fallacy of abstract negation assumes that the


rejection of one account of a philosophical matter does
not require giving a better account of it, or that it is
possible in philosophy to negate without affirming.

b. The fallacy of abstract affirmation assumes that in


philosophy it is possible to affirm (i.e. predicate a
concept in a judgment) without denying anything definite.
(EPM, 105-07).
466

5. Philosophical judgments as universal: philosophical


judgments are universal (i.e. of the form, all S is P.), but
rather than excluding this includes the subordinate forms,
the particular judgment (every S-type is P) and the singular
judgment (every individual S is P) as well as the purely
universal judgment (S as such is P). All three types of
structure are to be found in the philosophical judgment; what
is not found is any sufficiency of one to the exclusion of
the rest. (EPM, 111-12, 115).

6. Philosophical judgments as categorical: philosophical


judgments are not merely hypothetical (i.e. of the form, if S
is P it is Q) but also are essentially categorical in
intention (i.e. of the form, S is P). As categorical,
philosophical judgments are never devoid of objective or
ontological reference. ( EPM, 121, 125).

7. Philosophical inference as reversible: the arguments of


philosophy, instead of having an irreversible direction from
principles to conclusion (as in deduction) or from data via
principles to conclusion (as in induction), have a
reversible direction, the principles establishing the
conclusion and the conclusions reciprocally establishing the
principles. Philosophical arguments escape vicious
circularity insofar as the conclusions in philosophy are
already something known, and establishing them by means of
principles means making them known in a different and better
way. Philosophical conclusions are anticipated by an
experience that possesses them in substance before its
reasoning begins, and its conclusions can be checked by
comparing them with these anticipations. In a philosophical
scale of forms, the terms "experience" and "conclusion" are
applicable to any two successive stages (or levels): the
higher level "explains" the lower. (EPM, 160, 163, 172).

8. Philosophy as systematic: it is the ideal of philosophical


discourse to be constructive or systematic--that is, as
final, complete, objective, and unified as it can be.
Although none of these ideals can be met absolutely, in
viewing philosophical science itself as a scale of forms,
its topics can be arranged as a hierarchy of overlapping
concepts, differing in degree and kind, and related as op-
posites and distincts. (EPM, 177, 186-93).

_________________________________________________________
467

No doubt this outline does scant justice to the argu-

mentative structure and detail of example in the Essay, and

perhaps raises more questions than it resolves. We cannot deal

with all of Collingwood's arguments and illustrations without

duplicating in length the Essay itself. But we shall have

occasion to discuss several of the examples in what follows, in

connection with our examination of the structure of his main

argument. But perhaps we can settle several questions with some

comments about each of the key concepts we have just summarized.

(1) The first misconception to be avoided is that

Collingwood's Essay is concerned with describing characteristics

of philosophical concepts, judgments, and inferences that belong

exclusively to philosophy. Although each of these logical units

is contrasted with its non-philosophical equivalent, the

contrast does not make an absolute distinction between the two

sorts of usages. In each case he is careful to point out that

while such characteristics are occasionally but exceptionally

encountered in non-philosophical experience, in their

philosophical employment they are typical, important, and

essential. Thus when he discusses the overlap of classes, for

example, he points out that it occurs even in empirical science:

exceptional or paradoxical border-line cases provide obstacles

in any attempt to carry out a schema of classification based on

an arrangement of species of a genus into


468

mutually exclusive classes which exhaust the membership of the

genus between them. Collingwood points out the instance of the

classification of animals (a problem discussed with insight by

Aristotle), in which amphibians overlap the classes of fish and

reptile, having characteristics of both (i.e. they are

vertebrates with lungs, like reptiles, but capable of underwater

breathing, like fish) (EPM, 30). But where such an overlap is

exceptional in empirical science and ruled out by the a priori

divisions of exact sciences,l2 in philosophy it is typical and

essential. As examples Collingwood points out the predicability

of the transcendental attributes, unity, truth, and goodness,

under all the categories (EPM, 32-33); the overlap of judgment

and inference as two species of the genus thought, in logic

(EPM, 36); the overlap of thought and action as characteristics

studied by logic and ethics respectively (EPM, 43-44); and in

ethics the overlap of good acts across the divisions of goods

____________________
12 Collingwood seemed to think that the difficulties of
border-line cases arises only in empirical science but not exact
sciences, since in the latter (i.e. in mathematics) the
divisions can be carried out a priori by stipulative defini-
tions, and hence the exclusiveness and exhaustiveness of the
species are assured (EPM, 30-31). But insofar as the overlap of
classes is defined by the scale of forms as being a relation of
overlap-by-inclusion, the system of classification of numbers
seems to fit his description of an overlap of species of a
genus, as Donagan points out (CEPC, 5-6).
469

into the species pleasant, expedient and right (EPM, 41).13

It is interesting to note in connection with this dis-

cussion that Collingwood relates the non-philosophical and

philosophical usages of a term with the pre-philosophical and

philosophical phases of a concept--which is reminiscent of Q-AA

logic, in which the sameness of two questions is said to be the

sameness of an historical process (EPM, 33; cf. above, Table 3,

no. 3a). He writes:

There are words which are used in two different ways, a


philosophical and a scientific; but the words are not on
that account equivocal; they undergo a regular and uniform
change in meaning when they pass from one sphere to the
other, and this change leaves something fundamental in
their meaning unaltered, so that it is more appropriate to
speak of two phases of a concept then two senses of a word.
For example, matter is a word used both in physics and
metaphysics . . . . Such cases are common. Mind, for the
scientist, in this case the psychologist, is the name of
one limited class of things outside which lie things of
other kinds; for the spiritualistic philosophy, it is a
name . . . for all reality . . . . Even in concepts that
have no strictly scientific phase, a similar distinction
can often be traced between a philosophical phase and a
non-philosophical. (EPM, 33-35).

_____________________
13 Mink points out that it is possible and relatively
easy to work out a system of mutually exclusive species for this
example from ethics, simply by employing the mutually exclusive
and exhaustive classes, (a) pleasant and expedient and right,
(b) pleasant and expedient, but not right, (c) pleasant, but not
expedient and not right, (d) expedient, but not pleasant and not
right, etc. (MHD, 65). One might extend Mink's suggestion and
defend the claim that by a rigorous use of stipulative
definitions, a system of classification can always be
constructed that employs mutually exclusive and exhaustive
classes. But as Mink notes, most of the difficulties in what
Collingwood says in the chapter on the overlap of classes, many
of which arise from examples which seem to presume an overlap of
extension between classes, are cleared up in the chapter on the
scale of forms (MHD, 66, 70).
470

In a later chapter in which Collingwood is comparing the li-

terary language of philosophy to the technical (i.e. artifi-

cially symbolic) language of science, he points out that the

subject matter of philosophy demands a vocabulary with groups of

words "nearly but not quite synonymous, differentiated by shades

of meaning which for some purposes can be ignored and for others

become important," and single words which have various senses

according to the ways they are used, but without being utterly

equivocal (EPM, 206-07). It is precisely in such a vocabulary as

this, and in cases of overlapping meanings to which such a

vocabulary applies, that philosophy is interested, and which

gives it its typical characteristics.

But we must also notice, before passing on to consider

further parallels between philosophical and non-philosophical

concepts, that here as elsewhere in the Essay Collingwood does

not provide us with clear guidelines for the limits of this

distinction, or with any criteria for deciding when a concept is

rightfully being employed in its scientific phase and when in

its philosophical one. Furthermore, (as even his comment in the

above quotation shows a dim awareness), lumping pre- and

non-philosophical concepts together may overlook important

distinctions which may turn out to be pertinent when the

overlapping meanings of the term in its philosophical employment

are being unpacked. Collingwood may be guilty of falling prey to

the "genetic fallacy"--i.e. assuming that an earlier stage in

the development of a concept is a necessary condition


471

for the understanding of the mature concept--in short, confusing

temporal and logical priority.

(2) Another example of the manifestation of a phil-

osophical characteristic in a non-philosophical context is the

scale of forms. Collingwood points out that the "fusion" of

differences of degree with differences of kind in a scale of

forms is not unique to philosophy, but is also familiar to

"common sense" or ordinary experience, as in social structures

which distinguish between nobility and gentry, or in criminal

codes which distinguish between capital and other degrees of

punishment (EPM, 73). It is also familiar in empirical science,

where the double criteria of degree and kind are operative in

scales of forms in which different forms are modified and

replaced by others: Collingwood cites the example of the states

of matter, e.g. ice, water, and steam, which differ from each

other in both degree (colder and hotter) and kind (solid,

liquid, and gaseous states). Other examples are the periodic

table of elements and the stages of organismic development (e.g.

embroyogenesis) (EPM, 59). He even insists on this as a way of

defining a scale of forms:

The combination of differences in degree with differences


in kind implies that a generic concept is specified in a
somewhat peculiar way. The species into which it is divided
are so related that each not only embodies the generic
essence in a specific manner, but also embodies some
variable attribute in a specific degree. In respect of the
variable, each specific form of the concept differs from
the rest in degree; in respect of the manner in which the
generic essence is specified, each differs from the rest in
kind. In such a system
472

of specifications the two sets of differences are so


connected that whenever the variable, increasing or
decreasing, reaches certain critical points on the scale,
one specific form disappears and is replaced by another. A
breaking strain, a freezing point, a minimum taxable
income, are examples of such critical points on a scale of
degrees where a new specific form suddenly comes into
being. A system of this kind I propose to call a scale of
forms. (EPM, 57).

Just from the examples cited here it is clear that there are

non-philosophical as well as philosophical scales of forms; but

Collingwood remarks that it is just in such cases where

differences of degree and kind exist in combination that phil-

osophical thought is primarily interested (EPM, 56-57).

But in this case he goes one step further, and tries to

distinguish philosophical from non-philosophical scales of

forms. In the latter the variable is something extraneous to the

generic essence (e.g. heat, which accounts for the variation of

water in its transformations of state, does not enter into the

generic essence of water as expressed in the formula, H2O). But

in a philosophical scale of forms the variable is identified

with the generic essence itself (e.g. in Plato's forms of

knowledge the variable is given as definiteness or truth, which

is an essential characteristic of all knowledge as such) (EPM,

59-60).

However, since Collingwood does not specify for his

readers what he means by the terms, "generic essence," "vari-

able," and "specific forms," rather than clarifying the issue

this distinction raises


473

a hornets nest of further difficulties. What does it mean to say

that the variable is identified with the generic essence? It is

not a matter of demanding technical definitions for these terms,

since on Collingwood's grounds this may involve him in an

infinite regress (see Table 10, 3: philosophical definitions are

by means of a scale of forms, so that the concept of a scale of

forms is defined by means of a scale of forms). What we wish to

know is minimally how he is using these terms, even if this can

be stated only in mere verbal equivalences.

From scattered remarks throughout the Essay we may offer

the following as a first approximation to this requirement. (a)

A generic essence is whatever is included in the definition of a

genus, where (b) a definition is anything which fixes limits,

discriminates, distinguishes, makes clearer or more precise, or

removes ambiguities, and (c) a genus is a universal or a

concept--i.e. that which unites a number of different things,

either as (d) a general concept unites a plurality of individual

instances into a class, or (e) a generic concept unites a

plurality of specific differentiations into a universal (EPM,

26-28, 94-95, 98-100). (f) A variable is whatever is being used

as the index of difference in degree, or that in respect of

which each specific form (species) of a concept (genus) differs

from the other specific forms in degree (EPM, 57). (g) A

specific form is any further modification, qualification,


474

distinction or determination of a generic essence, general term,

or concept (EPM, 94-95, 100). (h) Essence and property are two

species of attribute, to which correspond definitions and

theorems as two species of exposition (EPM, 95). (i) An

attribute is anything which serves to qualify, modify,

distinguish or determine a genus.

Armed with these preliminary definitions we may now

return to the distinction between a philosophical and non-

philosophical scale of forms: in the former the variable was

said to be identified with the generic essence, in the latter it

was something extraneous. Paraphrasing this distinction using

our preliminary definitions yields statements something like

these: in the specification of a concept one species differs in

degree from another species in virtue of some attribute which in

the case of a non-philosophical concept is not included in the

essential definition of the genus, whereas in a philosophical

concept it is so included. In short, it turns out to greatly

resemble the analytic-synthetic distinction. Is Collingwood

distinguishing between a philosophical and a non-philosophical

scale of forms on the grounds that judgments stating such a

scale are either analytical (if philosophical) or synthetic (if

non-philosophical)?

(3) Once more we are up against the problem of Col-

lingwood's use of the term "identity," since we do not know what

"identified" means in
475

the expression "the variable is identified with the generic

essence."14 We may suppose that he minimally means that in

philosophical genera defined by a scale of forms there are real

and necessary connections between the variable attribute and the

genus which is being specified in differing degrees (EPM,

100).15 Whether this means that philosophical assertions are

analytic (in the sense of the tradition deriving from

Leibniz--viz. that the predicate is "contained in" the subject)

is not ever directly stated in the Essay itself. But based on

the discussion

_______________________
14 Cf. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by
Norman Kemp Smith (London, 1929), p. 48: "Either the predicate B
belongs to the subject A, as something which is (covertly)
contained in this concept A; or B lies outside the concept A,
although it does indeed stand in connection with it. In the one
case I entitle the judgement analytic, in the other synthetic.
Analytic judgements (affirmative) are therefore those in which
the connection of the predicate with the subject is thought
through identity; those in which this connection is thought
without identity should be entitled synthetic."

15 By way of explanation of what Collingwood means by


the "differentiation" involved in the specification of a generic
concept in a scale of forms, Mink writes: "Two things may be
differentiated as distinct from each other or as opposite to
each other. Opposition ‘is a relation subsisting between a
positive term and its own mere negation or absence’ (EPM, 75);
distinction is, apparently, any relation of difference between
two positive terms which differ in meaning" (MHD, 67). On this
interpretation one might also say that "difference in kind" is
also a relation between two positive and different attributes,
and "difference in degree" is a relation between a positive term
or attribute and its relative negation or absence. Unfortunately
this interpretation is weakened by the qualifying preface to the
remark that Mink quotes, which reads: "In its non-philosophical
phase, opposition is a relation subsisting between a positive
term and its own mere negation or absence" (EPM, 75--emphasis
mine).
476

of philosophical judgments as categorical-universal and the con-

troversy this generated with Gilbert Ryle,16 we may infer that

he does not mean us to understand the scale of forms in a

strictly analytical sense. To these two pieces of evidence we

must now turn.

(a) Collingwood insists that philosophical judgments are

universal, but also that they are not therefore merely

hypothetical l7--they are also essentially categorical, i.e. the

subject of the

___________________________
16 There are three unpublished letters between Colling-
wood and Gilbert Ryle, presently in the Bodleian Library, Ox-
ford. CRC-I is dated 4 May, 1935, and is from Collingwood to
Ryle; CRC-II is from Ryle to Collingwood, dated 21 May 1935; and
CRC-III is from Collingwood to Ryle, dated 6 June 1935. All are
related to the article written by Ryle, entitled "Mr.
Collingwood and the Ontological Argument," Mind, Vol. XLIV, no.
174 (April, 1935), pp. 137-51--basically a discussion of Chapter
VI of the Essay on Philosophical Method. In CRC-I, 14,
Collingwood points out that EPM, 63 (where Collingwood takes up
an objection to the view that opposition and distinction are
fused in a scale of forms, so that the scale of forms explains
the overlap of classes) is directed against a view of Croce. In
The Idea of History Collingwood expands on this point. Croce
criticized-Hegel's philosophy of history for confusing
opposition and distinction, since opposites refer to concepts
and distinction to individuals. But Collingwood argues that both
are applicable to historical events insofar as events have an
inside consisting of thought, and thought is conceptual and
hence oppositional. Opposition is a dialectical term, as is
reconciliation or synthesis (IH, 119).

17 Cf. Bernard Bosanquet, Knowledge and Reality (London,


1892), pp. 1-58. Collingwood, like Bosanquet, took issue with
Bradley s use of the categorical-hypothetical distinction, which
Bosanquet summarized as follows: "The universal judgement, if
bona fide universal, and in sense singular or collective,
cannot, so Mr. Bradley maintains ((in The Principles of Logic)),
be categorical. A categorical judgement
477

assertions being made is no mere ens rationis but something

actually existing (EPM, 125). We shall have more to say about

the categorical aspect of philosophical judgments in a moment,

but we may point out that in stating it he is declaring his

departure from at least the narrower versions of the

analytic-synthetic distinction, since he indicates that the

universal statements of philosophy have objective reference and

are not merely tautologies that indicate only the equivalent use

of words.

(b) This is confirmed in the second and final of his

letters in his correspondence with Ryle concerning his logical

views expressed in the Essay. In it Collingwood states that the

most important difference between them is Ryle's disbelief in

synthetic a priori propositions, a disbelief which he says he

does not share, and is connected with the possibility of

metaphysics (CRC-III, 1, 7). In stating his dissent from Ryle's

insistence that all universal propositions are hypothetical, and

hence that "no

________________________
affirms the existence of its elements, and enunciates some mat-
ters, conveyed by an idea, as true directly of Reality. But a
universal or abstract judgement does not affirm the existence of
its elements, and may be true though none of them exist or are
even possible of Reality'' (p. 5). Bosanquet insists that some
judgements, like "Heat is a mode of motion," and "Gases have a
spectrum consisting of lines," have subjects that "are thought
generally, through abstract characteristics, and are not
individually known," but are nevertheless fact: "They are
universal fact, and to say this is impossible seems to me a flat
denial of the commonest experience" (pp. 14-15). Cf. CRC-I, 13.
478

universal propositions are categorical" is a tautology (CRC-II,

5), Collingwood replies that tautologies are always merely

verbal. On his own view of logic, universal propositions deal

with real propositions and not just verbal ones--that is, they

deal not merely with affirmations and negations about words, but

about things (CRC-II, 5-7).

In his first letter to Ryle, Collingwood located the

problem at a different level:

It seems probable to me that the fundamental point at issue


between us is concerned with the way in which we answer the
question "what is a universal?" . . . . It looks to me as
if, in your logic, this question was answered by saying "a
universal is a class"; i.e. that whenever we make a
statement (assent to a proposition) about "all x" we are
really making n statements about the n instances of x which
exist. The theory of universals is thus, so to speak,
resolved into the theory of classes. It seems to me that
this analysis . . . (following Russell) . . . would
represent a line of thought more or less identical with
logical nominalism. In my own view, this line of thought is
so far from satisfactory that it inverts the necessary
order of analysis and is thus a case of obscurum per
obscurius. I am disposed to think that what makes a number
of things instances of a class is their common possession
of some common nature, and that this common nature (the
so-called "universal") is thus the ratio essendi of the
class as such. Instead of resolving the theory of
universals into the theory of classes, I should therefore
be inclined to the opposite line, of resolving the theory
of classes into the theory of universals. This is of course
akin to logical realism. (CRC-I, 28).

In the conclusion of the letter Collingwood summarizes the

matter in the statement that "the question which most

fundamentally seems to divide us appears to me to be question:

Is a universal simply a class, or is it that


479

which makes a class a class?--where you take the first

alternative and I the second" (CRC-I, 29).

It does not take much imagination to see the connection

between what Collingwood is here calling simply a "universal"

and what he had called a "concrete universal" in Speculum

Mentis--a similarity which is all the more striking for the

absence of that small qualifier, "concrete." It will be recalled

from Chapters V and VII (above, pp. 5-3, 5-16, 7-22, 7-28, 7-36,

7-39 and 7-47) that in Speculum Mentis Collingwood (a)

contrasted the "concrete universal," or one to which the

differences between its particulars are relevant," to the

"abstract universal," which is "indifferent to the variation of

its own particulars" or "to their own exemplification in this

particular or that, and differentiated only in their spe-

cifications" (SM, 162-63). He also (b) contrasted the structure

of a classificatory system based on abstract classes with the

structure of a dialectical series of progressively inclusive

("overlapping") universals (SM, 55, 162-64, 206-07); and (c) he

contrasted the formal logic built on the notion of the abstract

universal, or class-concept, with the dialectical logic which

employs the concrete universal (SM, 49, 195, 279). And finally,

(d) he argued that a dialectical logic which employs the

concrete universal "destroyed any distinction between a logic of

opposition and a logic of difference" (SM, 244).


480

It is clear that the Essay continues and develops this

line of thinking first sketched out in Speculum Mentis: (a) is

another way of stating the distinction between the philosophical

and the non-philosophical concept; (b) is transparently a

description of a "scale of forms;" (c) is the contrast he is

drawing between his own logic and that of Ryle, in his corres-

pondence with Ryle, his own being built on the notion of a

universal concept as described in the Essay; and (d) is the

"fusion" of "relations of opposition and distinction" and

"differences of degree and of kind" as described in the Essay

concerning the scale of forms. The logic described in the Essay

is therefore the dialectical logic discussed in Speculum Mentis.

If this is so there is one interesting corollary on the

Essay's thesis that the "variable is identified with the generic

essence"--about which we may speculate. Does Collingwood have in

mind the fact that the F-logic built on the notion of a class,

the substitution of one or another instance for a "variable"

takes for granted that no difference occurs, as a result of the

substitution, to the formula in which the variable occurs? And

if so, would this situation not be drastically altered where the

substitution-instances are specifications of a philosophical

concept having the structure of a "scale of forms" as he

describes it--i.e. one in which on instance differs from another

not only in degree but also in


481

kind, and has relations with it not only of distinction but of

opposition as well? We should like to think that this is the

case, so that when Collingwood speaks of an abstract universal

as being "indifferent to the variation of its particulars" we

may understand him to mean that when an abstract term is being

used as a simple class concept the relationship it has with its

instances is a relationship of a variable with its replacement

instances. But when a concept is so structured that it has a

layering of overlapping meanings, such a relationship of

sustitutivity or replacement is not possible without doing

violence to its structure of meaning, or without reducing it to

being an abstract class-concept.

Remaining alert to this possibility, but also aware that

it is not explicitly warranted by any texts of the Essay, we

turn to his discussion of judgments--the point of contact

between D-logic and Q-A logic.

(4) As entries 4, 5, and 6 of Table 10 indicate, Col-

lingwood maintained that all philosophical judgments are uni-

versal, categorical, and affirm or deny concretely. Collingwood

nowhere insists that this characterization of the philosophical

judgment is complete, but he does argue that it is minimally

necessary. All three of these requirements pose difficulties for

Q-A logic. The "principle of concrete affirmation and negation,"

for instance, applies to the class of expressions that in Q-A

logic are called propositions,


482

namely that which can be true or false. But what about absolute

presuppositions? Collingwood's formulation of the principle

appears to relate it to the Q-A complex:

The affirmative judgement in philosophy runs thus: S is P


and not Q; the negative thus: S is not Q but P; where P and
Q are equally definite and specific answers to the same
question: what is S? The peculiarity of the philosophical
judgement in respect of quality, then, lies in the peculiar
intimacy of the relation between its affirmative and
negative elements, which is of such a kind that P cannot be
validly affirmed while Q is left indeterminate, nor Q
validly denied while P is left indeterminate. (EPM, 110-11).

But this leads to the curious result that absolute

presuppositions, which are neither true nor false because not

answers to questions, are not philosophical because they do not

affirm or deny; either that or there are some philosophical

propositions (namely absolute presuppositions) which neither

affirm nor deny (or perhaps affirm without denying or deny

without affirming)--which violates the principle of concrete

affirmation and negation.

What we do not know is whether Collingwood would agree

that whatever judgments affirm or deny must be also true or

false, or whether there is a class of judgments which can affirm

or deny, and do so concretely, without being either true or

false. It is clear that from the point of view of Q-A logic, the

latter case is clearly possible. It is also clear that D-logic

makes affirmation and negation essential to judgment as such:

Collingwood writes in the Essay that "Any judgement


483

predicates a concept, and whenever we affirm one specific

concept we deny the other specifications of the same genus"

(EPM, 107). But what of truth or falsity in D-logic?

(5) Truth and falsity in D-logic appear to have some-

thing to do with the universal-categorical aspect of phil-

osophical judgments. We shall take up the universality aspect in

this section and the categorical aspect in the next. According

to the Essay just as philosophical concepts are

characteristically universal, so also are philosophical judg-

ments, but Collingwood seems to assume that his readers will

understand what he means by this. (cf. EPM, 111). From his

example of a universal judgment ("all men are mortal") we may

assume that he means by it a judgment of the form "All S is P."

or one which affirms or denies a predicate concept of a

universal subject. But after having told us that the relation

between concepts in philosophy is an intentional "overlap"

rather than an extensional one, he describes the universal

judgments of philosophy in extensional terms:

The species universal, particular, and singular overlap;


the universal judgement that all men are mortal does not
exclude, it includes the particular judgement that some men
are mortal and the singular judgement that this individual
man Socrates is mortal. These three elements introduce
differentiations into its significance, even considered as
a universal judgement: as a pure universal, it means that
man as such is mortal; as a universal of particulars, it
means that every kind of man is mortal; as a universal of
singulars it means that every individual man is mortal.
These are not so much three kinds of universal judgement as
three elements present in every universal judgement whether
in philosophy or anywhere else. (EPM, 111).
484

In the ensuing discussion Collingwood tries to dis-

tinguish the universality of philosophical judgments from that

of others, but in the process appears to badly conflate what is

here given in extensional terms with (a) what is emphasized in a

judgment, (b) the sequence in which judgments are made, and (c)

the priority of meaning of judgments. Thus he says that (a) the

type of judgment in which the "determining element" is the

singular (in what he calls induction by simple enumeration) is

such that "each individual instance of S is found on examination

to be P and is called a generalization;" but (b) a second type

"begins not from the singular but from the particular" and "goes

on to judge" that since each particular kind of S is P. S as

such is P (which he calls an empirical generalization); and (c)

in the third type the universal element is taken as primary: "we

begin by thinking that S as such is P. and this is seen to

involve the particular, that any specific kind of S is P. and

the singular, that each instance of S is P" (called the

universal judgments of exact science or mathematics) (EPM,

111-12; cf. EPH, 135-36). In these cases the manner in which the

universal judgment is reached, or its sequence in the way it is

advanced, is taken as what determines the type or meaning of

universal judgment it is, and the type of universal judgment

indicates what is being emphasized in that judgment.


485

The compression of these three "types" into one judg-

ment--the universal judgment of philosophy--is evidently not a

source of embarrassment for Collingwood, and the best indication

of this is in his response to Ryle on the matter. In the first

letter of their correspondence he states that in his view logic

is concerned with "real thinking" which "contains within itself

every kind of proposition, simultaneously thought together and

having a logically necessary structure” -- these forming for any

universal judgment its logical context, which consists of

"things which if we didn't think we couldn't think what ex

hypothesi we are thinking" (CRC-I, 16-19).

Further: I believe that this logical context must have a


certain logical structure. I believe, for example, that
there are always in it affirmative and negative elements, .
. . categorical and hypothetical elements . . . ((and))
propositional and inferential elements. I believe that in
any example of real thinking all these elements are pre-
sent; although . . . they are certainly not all ordinarily
(or perhaps ever) expressed in words . . . . When I say
"all," I am making a big assumption: I am assuming that
there is a certain complex of element-types which forms a
whole, and that every example of real thinking contains an
example of every element-type contained in this whole.
(CRC-I, 17-18).

Collingwood confesses that he cannot give a complete account of

the whole of element-types that he is discussing, but he admits

that what he has in mind is (a) "the old-fashioned formal logic"

which holds that any proposition whatever must have a certain

quality, quantity, relation, and modality--any complete whole

consisting of these four element-types with its respective

alternative variants; and (b) he says that this


486

"old-fashioned formal logic" was modified by Kant who disting-

uished three element-types within each of the four character-

istics of a proposition, bringing the number of element-types to

twelve. Without subscribing to this as a final number,

Collingwood indicates his assent to the existence of a "good

many" constant element-types found in any example of real

thinking.

He then concludes this remarkable synopsis of his

beliefs concerning logic with the following sketch:

I think that what . . . I have called kinds of proposi-


tions, may be one of two things. They may be what I am here
calling element-types, and in that case any example of real
thinking will contain within itself an example of every
kind of proposition. Or they may be . . . varieties of
propositions which are not element-types, but are merely
variants or alternative forms of this or that one
element-type. In the former case, every kind of proposition
(or inference for that matter) which the logician studies
must be an element-type of which an instance is present in
the real thinking done by himself as a logician. In the
latter case, of course, this need not happen. Lastly I
believe that the main task of logical theory is to
ascertain, so far as one can, what I have called the
logical structure of real thinking and the element-types
involved in that structure. I expect that you would
entirely deny this, and maintain that when the logician
speaks about kinds of propositions he means not
element-types but alternative varieties. I will not go on
to argue that point; I will only observe that logical
atomism, although I recognize the very important work which
it can do in the analysis of propositions taken singly,
begins by begging the question which I am here declining to
argue, in assuming that when we simultaneously assent to a
number of propositions . . . we are not thinking
simultaneously a complex of thoughts which must be thought
together if it is to be thought at all, i.e. a complex
having a logically necessary structure which is itself an
important subject for logical study, but merely an
assemblage of thoughts each of which presents to the
logician only the problems arising out of itself taken by
itself. (CRC-I, 18-20).
487

This very important letter is the only place, so far as

I know, that we find Collingwood, as he says, "giving myself

away rather completely" on the subject of his view of logic. We

shall therefore be forced to rely on it heavily for an

understanding of what Collingwood is attempting to say in the

Essay.

But in the context of our present discussion we notice

especially that it is not accidental when we find Collingwood

engaged in a compression of several logical functions into one

act, since "real thinking" (which must be what is being

expressed in a philosophical judgment) "contains within itself"

all the "element-types" on which logical judgment is based; and

further that this is a complex of thoughts which "must be

thought together if it is to be thought at all, i.e. a complex

having a logically necessary structure." But we shall have to be

on our guard against accepting any manifestation of "real

thinking" as a Deus ex machina explanatory device to resolve all

logical discrepancies we may encounter. "Real thinking,"

whatever else it may be, has a "logically necessary structure,"

so that wherever this structure fails to appear we may assume

that real thinking has not successfully occurred.18

____________________
18 Collingwood's first letter to Ryle also confirms from
a different direction our earlier provisional characterization
of the Kantian standpoint of the Essay: his own statement to
Ryle that the "element-types" of "real thinking" correspond
roughly to the Kantian schematized categories gives
488

(6) We are still on the trail of what Collingwood's

view in the Essay, and hence in D-logic, of truth and falsity

is, and we come now to the chapter on philosophical judgments as

categorical--perhaps the most controversial chapter in the

entire Essay, primarily because of the use of the ontological

argument and its extension to the domains of logic and ethics.

As we have already noted, it was this chapter that set off the

exchange between Collingwood and Ryle.

Once again under the rubric of "categorical"

Collingwood seems to be compressing into a single notion a

number of functions which are logically distinct,l9 and in

Ryle's criticism of this chapter it is this compressive

indistinctness that causes the greatest distress. Both in his

review article and in his correspondence with Collingwood,

________________________
us grounds for saying that what Collingwood is attempting in the
Essay is a brief survey of some salient features of what Kant
would call "transcendental logic" (although there is not much to
be gained by overemphasizing this point).

19 At various points in Chapter VI of the Essay Col-


lingwood says about categorical philosophical judgments (a) that
the subject of categorical judgments is something actually
existing (EPM, 117); (b) that the subject of such judgments
cannot be conceived except as actual (or its essence implies
existence) (EPM, 131, 133); (c) that the subject of such
judgments actually provides an instance of itself (EPM, 130);
(d) that in such judgments we declare ourselves committed to
believe that (a) ~PM, 127); and (e) that anything describable by
such a judgment is obliged to produce an instance of itself
(EPM, 130).
489

Ryle accuses Collingwood of failing to distinguish between

propositions which assert concrete matters of fact (particular

or existence propositions, which Ryle holds are the same--all

existence propositions being particular propositions and

vice-versa) and universal propositions which assert an abstract

relationship between properties, but do not say anything about

something which exists (CRC-II, 2, 4, 5; cf. MFA, 250-51). And

indeed, Collingwood's formulation of the rule for categorical -

universal judgments in philosophy seems to tee designed to cut

directly across this distinction. In discussing the Anselmian

ontological argument as an instance of the rule Collingwood

writes:

Divesting his argument of all specially religious or the-


ological colouring, one might state it by saying that
thought, when it follows its own bent most completely and
sets itself the task of thinking out the idea of an object
that shall completely satisfy the demands of reason, may
appear to be constructing a mere ens rationis, but in fact
is never devoid of objective or ontological reference . . .
. (I)n effect his argument amounts to this, that in the
special case of metaphysical thinking the distinction
between conceiving something and thinking it to exist is a
distinction without a difference . . . . Reflection on the
history of the Ontological Proof thus offers us a view of
philosophy as a form of thought in which essence and
existence, however clearly distinguished, are conceived as
inseparable. On this view, unlike mathematics or empirical
science, philosophy stands committed to maintaining that
its subject matter is no mere hypothesis, but something
actually existing. (EPM, 124-25, 127).

In his response to Collingwood's Essay Ryle denied that

the ontological argument proves anything because it is formally

fallacious. Hence it does not prove that there is anything about

which it is true
490

to say that its essence implies its existence, because a

statement of essence is a universal proposition and hence

hypothetical. From a hypothetical statement alone or in

conjunction with others no concrete matter of fact or existence

proposition can be inferred. In order to infer the existence of

something, Ryle argues, one needs at least one genuine singular

proposition, i.e. one which either (a) embodies at least one

logically proper name, or (b) has at least one definite

description which in fact describes something. Unless a

universal proposition rests on or contains a logically genuine

singular proposition, it does not successfully refer. (CRC-II,

2, 5).

In his reply to Ryle Collingwood counterattacked by

denying the distinction on which Ryle based his disproof. It is,

he says, fallacious: not all universal propositions are

hypothetical, and it is not only singular and particular pro-

positions that can assert existence:

You seem to me . . . to be arguing on the assumption . .


that any general proposition must belong to either one or
the other of two classes . . . "any-propositions" and
"every-propositions." I wish to maintain that there are
also what I will call "all-propositions." (a)
any-propositions. These are what you call general
hypotheticals, which do not depend for their truth on the
existence . . . of any of the things to which they
apply . . . . (Y)ou accept my account of these and my
description of arithmetical and geometrical propositions as
belonging to this type. (b) every-propositions. These I
think you are assuming . . . as a kind, and the only
possible kind, of general categorical. They apply to every
instance of a certain class, and depend for their truth
upon the existence . . . of these instances
491

. . . (Y)ou believe . . .that the only way in which a


general proposition can be categorical is by being
enumerative. With this logical doctrine is bound up a
metaphysical doctrine to which . . . you also subscribe:
viz. that what exists is an assemblage, or various
assemblages, of "particular matters of fact." . . . But in
fact I am quite consciously, in my essay, attacking these
assumptions. I will admit for the sake of argument that
there are any-propositions and every-propositions; but I
contend that there are also all-propositions or (as some
logicians have called them) "true universals" having a
categorical character, i.e. they are not enumeratives, and
yet they are not indifferent to the existence of the things
to which they apply, but are of such a kind that their
truth depends on that existence. I regard such propositions
as especially characteristic of philosophy. (CRC-I, 24-25).

This is as close as we shall ever come to understanding what the

doctrine on truth is in the Essay, and since this issue (at

least on Collingwood's view of it--cf. CRC-I, 7) crosses over

the boundary of logic and enters that of metaphysics, we must

postpone further discussion of this until Chapter X.

But we must note here that in order to defend his case,

Collingwood must produce at least one acceptable example of what

is to count for a valid categorical universal judgment, or a

synthetic a priori proposition. As we shall see in Chapter X, in

the Essay on Metaphysics Collingwood provides us with several

candidates for such judgments--"God exists" being one of them,

but others are offered in his discussion of the transcendental

analytic section of Kant's first Critique. In the present

instance Collingwood sticks to existential propositions, as in

his reply to Ryle:


492

I believe that such propositions as "God exists," "mind


exists," "matter exists," and their contradictories, do not
assert or deny particular matters of fact; nor do I believe
that they assert or deny anything which can be adequately
described as collections or classes of matters of fact. To
assert or deny propositions of this kind, with reasons
given for the assertion or denial, seems to me the business
of constructive or destructive metaphysics . . . . I do
think that a philosophical proposition may be e.g. about
thought or matter; and . . . if I learnt to use your
language, I could call thought or matter a designated
entity; but I could never allow that it was either a
particular matter of fact or a mere collection of
particular matters of fact. (CRC-I, 4, 6).

But the most peculiar and idiosyncratic instance that

Collingwood gives of the rule that philosophical judgments are

never devoid of objective or ontological reference is not the

Ontological Proof of Anselm, but his discussion of logic. He

paraphrases this view in his letter to Ryle:

Logic not only discusses, it also contains reasoning:


consequently, whenever a logician argues a point in the
theory of inference, he is producing an instance of the
thing under discussion; and, since he cannot discuss with-
out arguing, he cannot discuss any point in the theory of
inference without doing so. Consequently, in so far as it
necessarily contains reasoning, the theory of reasoning
((i.e. logic)) cannot be indifferent to the existence of
its own subject-matter; in other words, the propositions
which constitute the body of that part of logic cannot be
in substance hypothetical. For example, if a logician could
believe that no valid reasoning anywhere existed, he would
merely be disbelieving his own logical theory. (CRC-I,
11-12; cf. EPM, 130).

The logician, to paraphrase a paraphrase, not only mentions

logic he also uses it in the construction of his logical system.

But both this example


493

and the example he gives from ethics20 seem to illustrate a

different point than the one he was making about the Ontological

Proof of Anselm. Concerning logic and ethics he seems to be

saying that such concepts are self-instantiating--logic being

logical and ethics being ethical; and that the denial of such

self-instantiating concepts leads to a different sort of

absurdity--what might be called categorical nonsense (or perhaps

what Austin has called "performative absurdity"--cf. Rubinoff,

CRM, 184). Thus if one were to set out to formally demonstrate

that there is no such thing as logical demonstration, or if one

were to argue that one ought not to say what one should or

should not do, he would be engaging in a categorical (or

performative) absurdity: what he says he is doing is

incompatible with what he is doing. But certainly the

Ontological Proof does not produce or provide an instance of

itself. Although it presumes a commitment to the definition of

God as a being than which none greater can be conceived, if one

were to deny that "a being none greater than which can be

conceived" has ontological reference he would not be doing

_____________________
20 Collingwood argues that ethics cannot be merely de-
scriptive nor merely normative any more than can logic. Ethics
describes not action as opposed to ideas of action, but the
moral consciousness; and this it is forced to describe as al-
ready being in some sense what it ought to be. Conversely "this
in turn will affect the account which it gives of action; for no
theory of moral ideals is conceivable which does not admit that
to some extent moral ideas affect action" (EPM, 132). Ethics, in
short, must be ethical.
494

something incompatible with what he is saying he is doing. The

Ontological Proof does not seem to meet the description he is

offering for categorical judgments as self-instantiating, and at

this point we do not have a clear idea of what Collingwood

understands to be the uniting concept for these two sets of

examples.

A candidate for a common concept might be "having on-

tological reference." But then what sort of "ontological re-

ference" does logic have? If logic has ontological reference in

the sense that it occurs as a thought-process in someone's mind

who is thinking logically, then it is no less true that

mathematics and empirical science have a similar reference. But

the entire point of using the Ontological Proof as an example

seems to indicate that the "ontological reference" that he has

in mind is not merely to "second intentions" or to mental

events: it is not, he says, a mere ens rationis but something

actually existing. We therefore seem to be left with the

suggestion that there are some judgments which necessarily imply

the existence of what they describe. But then this narrows the

field to the one special case being discussed in Anselm's

argument, as Collingwood himself admits: "What it does prove is

that essence involves existence, not always, but in one special

case, the case of God in the metaphysical sense: the Deus sive

nature of Spinoza, the Good of Plato, the Being of Aristotle:

the object of metaphysical thought: (EPM, 127).


495

It is true that Collingwood attempts to extend this "object" to

philosophical thought in general" by adding that

"metaphysics . . . is not unique in its objective reference or

in its logical structure; all philosophical thought is of the

same kind, and . . . partakes of the nature of metaphysics,

which is not a separate philosophical science but a special

study of the existential aspect of that same subject-matter

whose aspect of truth is studied by logic, and its aspect as

goodness by ethics" (EPM, 127). But the extension fails to

convince the reader, for there is no good reason provided for

dropping the limitation of the "essence involves existence"

maxim to that "one special case" being discussed in the

ontological proof.

But here we once again encounter Collingwood's advance

warning that he will not pursue the consequences of his Essay

into the realm of metaphysics (much as we are tempted to admit

that he has already done so), and we must leave the matter in

this unsatisfactory state (as he himself does) until we have an

opportunity to examine his explicit views on metaphysics in

greater detail.21

_______________________
21 The reader is left at this point with the very uneasy
suspicion that Collingwood has stated a very important
philosophical truth, but expressed it very badly, and left it in
a highly ambiguous state. Everyone knows that philosophers have
claimed to be stating truths that have ontological reference,
and further that they have employed arguments to reinforce these
truths. What is in question (at least since the time of Hume) is
whether there is any necessary validity to that claim, and
whether their arguments succeed in demonstrating what their
authors believe they do. Collingwood seems to by saying that the
real
496

(7) If the chapter on categorical thinking is the most

controversial one in the Essay, the chapter on philosophical

inference22 is the most axial: it is the chapter that more than

any other displays what is unique in a philosophical methodology

that ideally unifies the specific topics in philosophy; and it

is the chapter in which Collingwood completes the discussion of

the work of his predecessors on the subject.23 In Collingwood's

view the development of the idea of philosophical

________________________
tradition in philosophy has always been committed to maintaining
this claim to ontological reference, and that to abandon it is
to abandon philosophy. But to adequately argue that the
ontological reference claims of metaphysicians is successful he
would have to rely on something more than the evidence provided
by the ontological argument. What is required is a fully
developed theory of meaning and reference. In the sequel we
shall see that he did make a start on such a theory in his
discussion of language and mental acts.

22 Part of the material of Chapter VIII of the Essay was


presented in our own Chapter VII, Section 2. On Collingwood's
view of inference, cf. IH, 253-56.

23 In the first chapter Collingwood reviewed the stages


of development of the notion of philosophical method, which we
saw falling into four major phases: (a) the Socratic phase, in
which the function of dialectical questioning was vigorously
employed to make implicit thought explicit in definitions; (b)
the Platonic phase, in which dialectical method is expanded to
include arguments which directionally proceed from
quasi-mathematical, hypothetical definitions to non-hypothetical
first principles of thought, primarily by removal of
hypothetical restrictions as the argument proceeds; (c) the
Cartesian phase, in which mathematics is taken as an explicit
model for philosophical method (but continually violated in
actual practice by Descartes and his followers by employing
arguments that are not strictly speaking deductive and do not
employ first principles which are self-evident); and finally,
(4) the Kantian phase, in which philosophy is freed from math-
ematical methodology by recognizing
497

methodology culminates in the demand for a self-justifying kind

of thinking. Justification in a philosophical context requires

argument, argument means inference, and inference suggests

inductive and deductive reasoning. Since Collingwood has all

along been comparing philosophical method with the method of

exact and empirical sciences, it is not surprising that the

culmination of this comparison occurs in a chapter which deals

with inference. If philosophy is to escape scepticism and

dogmatism it must show how its arguments can be self-justifying

without

_____________________
that in philosophy there are no definitions, no axioms, and no
demonstrations of a sort essentially mathematical (EPM, 4-6,
10-25, 155-56). The first chapter ends with a critical
discussion of Kantian methodology, which, Collingwood says,
fails to adequately reconcile the conflicting claims of the
critical method (a) as a propaedeutic to philosophy proper (i.e.
to metaphysics) and (b) as philosophy itself (EPM, 20-24). In
Chapter VII ("Two Sceptical Positions"--a chapter which, like
Chapter X, appears to be an aside but is not) Collingwood
resumes his discussion of critical philosophy which he takes to
be one of two related sceptical positions (the other being
analytic philosophy) which dominate the contemporary
philosophical scene. In essence his reply to the attempt to
reduce philosophy to the function of criticism is that it
assumes positive standards of consistency from which it finds
its subject diverging, and unless it undertakes to defend these
standards it fails to justify itself and assumes a dogmatic
stance with respect to its subject-matter (EPM, 140-41).
Similarly the "analytic view" (of which he finds Moore and
Russell representative) cannot exempt the positive principles it
assumes as true from common sense and/or science from its
analysis without self-contradiction (EPM, 143-46; cf. 138-39,
142 n. 1). The upshot of this discussion of critical and
analytic philosophy is that if philosophy is to avoid both
scepticism (the result of an unbridled exercise of destructive
criticism) and dogmatism (the result of assuming certain
principles to be true without justification), it must present
positive grounds for its own activity; that is, it must be
self-justifying.
498

being circular. We might rightfully expect this to be the most

crucial chapter in the Essay.

Noting that (a) "in its demand for close and cogent

reasoning, philosophy resembles exact science," i.e. "each alike

works on the principle that no conclusions may be asserted for

which valid and sufficient reason cannot be given" (EPM, 154);

but also that (b) it resembles empirical science insofar as "it

is supported throughout its texture by crossreferences to

experience (EPM, 164), Collingwood raises the question whether

and how philosophical inference can be deductive (like exact

science) and/or inductive (like empirical science--EPM, 151; cf.

IN, 254-55). For the purpose of distinguishing philosophical

inference from both deduction and induction, Collingwood

analyzes inference into three components: the data from which

the argument proceeds, the principles according to which

inference takes place, and the conclusions to which the argument

leads (EPM, 151). It is on these three that he compares the

inferences of mathematics, empirical science, and philosophy.

In exact science the data are suppositions, the prin-

ciples are axioms, and the conclusions are inferred in the sense

of being demonstrated or shown to follow with perfect logical

rigor from the data according to the principles. The axioms are

of two sorts: those of logic, which do not belong to the body of

mathematics proper and are properly


499

speaking not suppositions but presuppositions "in the sense that

unless they were true the science could not take a single step

in advance;" and special axioms, which are part of exact sci-

ence, but are "self-evident" or indemonstrable, and known to be

true by a kind of intuition (EPM, 151-52).24 The arguments of

exact science are therefore irreversible--that is, "the

conclusions are logically dependent on the axioms; there is no

reciprocal dependence of the axioms on the conclusions" (EPM,

153).

Empirical science, on the other hand, relies on a sort

of inference known as inductive reasoning, in which individual

facts empirically known by perception, or the historical record

of perceptions in the past, are the data from which conclusions

in the form of universal

____________________
24 As is clear from the example he uses, Collingwood has
Euclidean geometry in mind as a model for exact science. But he
covers himself from attack on the grounds that no contemporary
geometrician would accept "self-evident" as descriptive of
geometrical axioms. Collingwood writes that "the main lines of
this view are not, for our purposes, affected if it is
maintained that the special axioms are not known to be true, but
only assumed . . . ((because)) in that case we shall have to say
that the entire body of the science consists of assumptions, but
that these fall into two classes: primary or fundamental
assumptions, the so-called special axioms, and secondary or
derivative assumptions, the so-called conclusions." In either
case "the logical axioms cannot be merely assumed, for . . . we
cannot think as if the principles of thinking were true, for if
they were not we should not be thinking" (EPM, 153). The
contemporary geometer would have to agree that some sort of
deductive inference-structure is presupposed, and that this is
not a part of the content ("body" as Collingwood puts it) of
geometry itself.
500

speaking to be derived (EPM, 165). The principles of induction

are, like exact science, of two sorts: logical principles pre-

sumed as certain, and assumptions with the degree of certitude

only that they are known not to be untrue, and that it is

expedient to use them--a certitude which increases in pro-

bability as the inductive inquiry proceeds, but never reverts to

deductive certitude (EPM, 165-67). Comparing deductive and

inductive inference, Collingwood concludes:

The logical movement of inductive thought is therefore


irreversible in the same sense as that of exact science.
The principles on which induction rests receive in return
no support from the inductive process itself . . . . The
process of thought in exact science, though irreversible as
regards its principles, may be reversible as regards its
data . . . . In this respect, inductive argument is not
reversible; for its data are what they are because they
enjoy the status of facts vouched for by perception; and
although we can infer the existence of an unobserved fact
from reasons inductively established by the study of
similar facts, we only infer it (where to infer, as always
in the context of inductive thought, means to establish as
probable) and do not perceive it. (EPM, 167).

Philosophical inference differs from both induction and

deduction which as species of the philosophical genus,

inference, overlap. (a) In philosophical inference there is no

division of axioms into those belonging to the science and those

belonging to logic, since logical principles are part of

philosophical thought itself. As a consequence philosophy cannot

neglect its own logical presuppositions (EPM, 154-55). (b) What

appears in philosophy as an axiom or indemonstrable proposition

serving as a starting point is, as philosophical argument

proceeds,
501

justified by what follows it. In this procedure philosophical

inference has the form of what Kant had called a "transcendental

deduction." Thus the Cartesian cogito is neither a self-evident

truth nor an assumption, but rather "in Kantian language the

principle cogito ergo sum is . . . transcendentally deduced,

that is, shown to be the condition on which experience as it

actually exists . . . is alone possible" (EPM, 156). (c) This

means that philosophy is obliged to justify its own starting

point. (EPM, 159). But (d):

This can be done only if the arguments of philosophy, in-


stead of having an irreversible direction from principles
to conclusions, have a reversible one, the principles es-
tablishing the conclusion, and the conclusions reciprocally
establishing the principles. But an argument of this
kind . . . is a vicious circle. The solution of the
dilemma lies . . . in the Socratic principle that
philosophical reasoning leads to no conclusions which we
did not in some sense know already . . . . Establishing a
proposition in philosophy, then, means not transferring it
from the class of things unknown to the class of things
known, but making it known in a different and better way.
(EPM, 160-61).

(e) Philosophical knowing in this way differs from that of exact

science inasmuch as the conclusions are in some sense known

without any proof at all: the arguments of philosophy exhibit as

a reasoned and ordered whole of interconnected knowledge what

was already in substance known before the work of philosophical

inference occurred at all:

If philosophy differs from exact science in this way—


the anticipation . . . of its conclusions by an
experience that
502

possesses them in substance before its reasoning be-


gins--other differences will follow, the chief being that
in philosophy the conclusions can be checked by comparing
them with these anticipations, and that by this checking
the principles at work in the reasoning can be verified. If
this is so the direction of the argument in respect of
principles and conclusions is reversible, each being es-
tablished by appeal to the other; but this is not a vicious
circle because the word "established" here means raised to
a higher grade of knowledge: what was a mere observation is
now not merely observed but understood; what was merely an
abstract principle is verified by appeal to facts. (EPM,
163).

(f) Philosophy differs from empirical science insofar as the

initial data of philosophy does not consist of individual facts

apprehended by perception, but of universal propositions appre-

hended in the experience of thinking; and the conclusions of

philosophical inference are not something new, but are the facts

themselves more thoroughly understood (EPM, 168-69). "(I)n

philosophy the knowledge . . . why things are so makes a

difference to the knowledge that they are so" (EPM, 169). (g)

The "experience" on which "conclusions" are philosophically

based, and by appeal to which they are checked, is only

"non-philosophical" or "pre-philosophical" in a relative sense:

These two phrases ((i.e. experience and conclusions)) are


names for any two successive stages in the scale of forms
of philosophical knowledge. What is called experience may
be any stage in this scale; in itself, as all human ex-
perience must be, permeated through and through by philo-
sophical elements; but relatively crude and irrational as
compared with the next stage above it, in which these phil-
osophical elements are more fully developed . . . . But
what is asked of the higher is not simply that it should
agree with the lower, but rather that it should explain
it . . . . The
503

accomplishment of this task is only the continuation of a


process already begun; it was only by thinking that we
reached the point at which we stand, for the experience
upon which we philosophize is already a rational experience
. . . . But the new and intenser thinking must be thinking
of a new kind; new principles are appearing in it, and
these give a criterion by which the principles involved in
the last step are superseded. (EPM, 172-73).

The ultimate response to the charge of vicious circularity in

philosophical reasoning is therefore that, since all experience

is already somewhat systematic and rational, whenever its sys-

tematic connections are exhibited, the experience is "estab-

lished" in a higher sense of the term. (In the language of The

Principles of Art, one might say that it is not merely a datum

but an interpreted datum.) The "reciprocal" establishment in

philosophical inference is therefore not truly reciprocal or

circular, but more like the coiled meanings in a scale of forms.

(h) But this response seems to get us out of the Charybdis of

vicious circularity only be dashing us against the Scylla of

vacuous philosophical inference: for did Collingwood not just

tell us that the distinguishing mark of philosophical inference

was that it is reversible as deductive and inductive inference

are not? Collingwood's reply is that philosophical inference is

always deductive and inductive, just as it is always critical

and analytical, but always with a difference. As deductive it is

a complete system based on principles and connected throughout

by strictly logical bonds; but as such its principles are open

to criticism on the
504

grounds that they must succeed in explaining our experience. As

inductive it seeks rational universality; but only by finding it

already present in the activity of philosophizing which is

already occurring. As critical it always seeks to refute theory;

but only in order to leave an experience standing which can be

interpreted in the light of the principles implied in the

critical process itself. And as analytical it begins with a

knowledge-datum and seeks to explain what this knowledge means;

but in so doing we come to know that datum in a different way,

and therefore as modified in the knowing of it. (EPM, 173-75).

There is much left unexplained in this account of

philosophical inference. For example we would like to know

precisely how philosophy employs the logical principles which

are a part of it, as stated in (a); and we would like to know

more about what the conditional possibility in a "transcendental

deduction" in (b) consists of, and in what sense necessity is

involved in such a deduction, and if this is the same as

"justification" in (c); and we would like to know how it is

possible to "know already" in (c) an experience which in (f) is

called universal and non-perceptual, and in (g) is called

rational; and most of all we would like to know what it means

for this experience, and indeed all experience, to be permeated

through and through with philosophical elements as stated in (g).


505

What appears to be presupposed in all this is a full--

blown epistemology that is only hinted at rather than explicitly

stated. Some of the outlines of this epistemology will appear in

the next and succeeding section of this chapter when we come to

examine the intellectual functions of mind and the analysis of

language, where we shall find some hints towards the resolution

of several of these problems (e.g. in the notion of a

pre-reflective act of meaning at the first level of

consciousness, and in the view that rationality it-

self--including rational inference--is an extension of con-

sciousness' demand for meaning, in this case what might be

called "rational meaning" at the level of reasoned discourse).

But before coming to this discussion and the implications for

Q-A logic, we have one more "key concept" from the Essay to deal

with.

(8) It is in Chapter IX that Collingwood comes closest

to evaluating the dialectical logic of the Essay in terms of the

criteria of consistency, completeness, and formality which we

discussed in connection with Q-A logic in the preceding section.

In this chapter Collingwood examines the claim of philosophy to

be systematic and constructive rather than piecemeal and

analytic--a claim that has been assaulted since the 19th century

on the grounds that a system of thought claims for itself

finality, completeness, objectivity, and unity, and philosophy

has none of
506

these. Our philosophical knowledge is always open to future

developments, is beyond the terminable survey of any individual,

is the expression of a personal and private point of view, and

effectively solves its problems not by mass generalities, but by

handling each problem individually (EPM, 176-78).

Collingwood's reply in essence is that even if one

concedes each of these points to the critic, the ideal of a

system remains undaunted. (a) While not absolutely final, all

knowledge in order to advance must take account of where it

presently stands, and therefore retains a synoptic or sum-

marizing element. In philosophy this record of progress is

intensified insofar as any new development does not merely add

to permanent and unaltered assets, but requires that previous

conclusions be re-examined in the light of new developments

(EPM, 179-81). And (b) while not absolutely complete, every

philosophy is a borrowing from past philosophies and a colla-

boration with present philosophical thought, so that there is

not and never has been any such thing as a private, personal,

self-contained system of philosophy (EPM, 181-82).25 And (c)

although each philosopher contributes only a part of a total

_______________________
25 This obviously does not answer the objection: some-
thing may be no less incomplete for having taken account of
previous and contemporary discussion of an issue, or even for
having taken into account all such discussion, since all pre-
vious discussion may have missed the essential point. What must
be shown is that all the relevant or pertinent issues are dealt
with satisfactorily.
507

system, and hence his work is not that system but only a portion

of it, in philosophy that contribution includes a theory of the

whole of what philosophy is, and thus anticipates its objective

conclusions (EPM, 182-84). And finally, (d) only an "anarchist

of the mind" would fail to see that even a methodical avoidance

of rigidity is itself a system or method, and although a

philosopher should avoid bondage to any readymade or rigid

formula, a willingness to revise one's principles in the light

of one's conclusions does not necessitate the rejection of all

principles or of all conclusions (EPM, 184-85).

But Collingwood feels that the real answer to all these

objections to systematic philosophy is made possible by

regarding the topics or constituents of philosophy as comprising

a scale of overlapping forms, wherein each topic differs from

the rest not only in kind but also in degree. The universal

subject-matter of philosophy differs intensively and

specifically whether the genus is divided into the species of

logic, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, etc.; or in the

division of the subject into historical phases (ancient,

medieval, modern); or at the contemporaneous level in the

division between what may minimally pass for philosophy, what

retains its coherence in being grouped into one or more schools

of thought, and the final "common spirit" of the present age; or

finally in one's own philosophy, in the division between

unexamined
508

opinions, criticized and defined assertions held with greater

conviction, and a fully articulated and systematic whole of

philosophical judgments (EPM, 19498). In any of these

arrangements of philosophical topics a systematic ideal is

present as a scale of forms, which at each point sums up the

scale to that point, showing how subordinate positions are

opposed to and distinct from that point, and in error by

comparison to a higher point on the scale (EPM, 190). In a scale

of forms of philosophical knowledge any particular position is a

non-final summary, an incomplete termination, a subjective

necessity, and uniformly or methodically flexible (EPM, 191-92).

Each approximates to an ideal of a perfectly philosophical

subject matter treated by a perfectly philosophical method (EPM,

192).

Now although in this discussion of system in Chapter IX

of the Essay there is no clear correspondence with the criteria

for systematicity which we examined under the titles of

consistency, completeness, and formality, in connection with our

comparison of Q-A and F-logics, we can nevertheless see a rough

correspondence between the description of a system which

Collingwood here employs and those used to evaluate formal

axiomatic systems in F-logic. Thus the criterion of consistency

(that within the system propositions containing formal

contradictions are not provable) roughly corresponds to the

claim of unity in a philosophical


509

system; completeness (that all true statements within the system

are derivable from the axioms and rules of method within the

system) correspond roughly (but with considerable overlap) to

Collingwood's terms "finality" and "completeness"; and formality

(that the construction of well-formed statements within a system

is carried out by the strict application of its rules, and not

by the interpretation of specific meanings of the terms within

the statement--i.e. that there be a purely formal way to decide

which statements are well formed within the system) roughly

corresponds to what Collingwood is calling "objectivity."26

But the points of difference are more striking than the

points of superficial similarity. It is obvious from the

discussion of philosophical inference in Chapter VIII of the

Essay that, as Collingwood conceives it, D-logic is not simply a

deductive system, and therefore to apply axiomatic criteria for

evaluating it as a formal, consistent, and complete system would

not be altogether appropriate. A system in which principles are

revisable in the light of conclusions obviously transgresses the

requirements of an axiomatic system of F-logic, in which the

axioms or principles are stated in an object-language and the

rules in a meta-language, in which the rules and principles are

never revisable in

____________________
26 Cf. Bochenski, The Methods of Contemporary Thought,
510

the light of conclusions. For (a) if the meaning of terms within

the system can form scales of overlapping forms, it is difficult

to see how a criterion of strict consistency can be upheld,

since the prerequisite of semantic identity of terms is violated

every times such a term definable by a scale of forms is

introduced. And (b) if the highest term in a dialectical system

is summational or synoptic but not final, it is clear that a

higher term (a statement that first appears as a denial but

implies the positive principles on which the criticism is based)

can always be introduced which is not strictly inferable from

within the system (since its positive principles do not yet lie

within the system)--in short, the system is always incomplete.

And (c) if experience is the touchstone of a revision (or

reversal) of an argument from conclusions to principles, even if

this experience is that of a thinker, it is clear that the ideal

of a purely formal validity cannot be maintained.

This brings us back to the question of circularity,

which is all the more vicious in that it appears to escape ob-

jectivity altogether: for whatever "experience" is appealed to,

it will always be merely someone's property unless what it means

can be communicated in objective form. Collingwood's appeal to

experience in both the discussion of philosophical inference in

Chapter VIII and in his discussion of systematic philosophy in

Chapter IX casts a suspicion of radical subjectivity on the

whole
511

enterprise of the Essay. The issue raised by the entire argument

of the Essay is this: if philosophical arguments are reversible

on the basis of experience (and therefore its principles are

corrigible), how does one know when one has successfully

inferred in a philosophical sense? Collingwood wants to say that

a successful philosophical inference is one which increases our

understanding of experience at the same time it changes it (or

makes a difference to it). But if the criterion of success

appealed to here is the fact of "philosophical experience" or

"the experience of a thinker," then the argument of Chapter VIII

is truly and merely circular: we know that philosophical

inference is successful because we know we draw successful

philosophical inferences. But the appeal to experience is

inadequate as a criterion of success, since not all or just any

philosophical inference will do. Some are better than others,

some contradict others, some (as in Plato's dialogues) are meant

to be understood as logically fallacious.

Another way of stating the problem is that if the cri-

terion of successful philosophical inference is epistemological

(one form of knowledge explaining another), how are we to decide

what is good epistemology? Will any old theory of knowledge do?

What about a realist's epistemology? We have seen that

Collingwood argues that a realist epistemology is unsuccessful,

but he argues that it fails not because it


512

is not epistemology (which it is: it purports to explain what

occurs in knowing--that is, it makes knowing an object of know-

ledge), nor because it does not explain experience (which it

does: it puts forward a theory of how objects are known), but

because it fails to be good epistemology. It contradicts itself

by talking formal nonsense about unsensed sense, knowing what is

simultaneously declared to be unknown, etc. On the "experience"

of realist epistemology alone, on Collingwood's grounds, we

could not say that we have successfully inferred in a

philosophical sense.

But if we take seriously Collingwood's remark that when

we talk about "establishing principles" it is in a different and

higher sense of the term "establish" than when we talk about

"establishing experience," then we may have a way out of this

vicious circularity while retaining a legitimate sense of

philosophical inference--and this is the only hope that the

entire argument of the Essay has. Collingwood's commitment to

the assertion that philosophical concepts are arranged as a

scale of overlapping forms, also commits him to the conclusion

that the principles employed in philosophical argument are

increasing both in generality (taking in more of our experience)

and in intentional reference (stating more of what is in that

experience in terms of significance). This "higher knowledge" is

systematic knowledge as articulated and related in a system of

discourse bound by logical relations and (inasmuch as it is not


513

merely formal) categorically referential. If this "higher

knowledge" is the same thing as what he meant by "real thinking"

in his correspondence with Ryle, then it is possible that the

criterion of success in philosophical inference may be the same

as the criterion of a successful epistemology; it is the

articulation of our own knowledge as a system of discourse,

logically related and categorically referential. In the next

section we shall pursue this lead into Collingwood's philosophy

of mind and his analysis of language, and in so doing catch

sight of logic as an extension of meaning at the rational level.

But before proceeding with this analysis we must make

good a previous promise. We are now in as good a position as we

shall ever be to evaluate the standpoint of the Essay. We noted

in a previous chapter and also at the beginning of this section

that (a) the Essay claims both conditional and unconditional

validity for itself, and (b) that its treatment of pre- and

non-philosophical methods cannot be taken as literally true for

mathematics and empirical science. But within this present

section we have also seen that Collingwood (c) extended

philosophical concepts to include all experience (all human

experience is "permeated through and through by philosophical

elements" (EPM, 172); (d) declared that philosophical thought is

never devoid of ontological reference (EPM, 125); (e) criticized

analytical and critical philosophy for failing


514

to justify themselves by presenting the positive principles from

which their critical and analytical methods proceed (EPM, 145,

148-49); (f) insisted that philosophy is obliged to produce a

theory of itself and to be constructive and systematic (EPM, 1,

198); and finally, (g) stated that what he is doing in the Essay

is to discuss the nature of philosophy by discussing not only

what it is or has been, but also what it is trying to or ought

to be (EPM, 2, 4, 7).

From (e), (I), and (g) it follows that the Essay is

stating a theory of philosophy that is nonetheless itself

philosophy, and is stating what philosophy is and what it ought

to be by presenting its positive principles. From these and (d)

it follows that, ideally speaking, what is true of philosophy

must also be true to some extent for reality (i.e. philosophy

cannot be content with constructing a mere ens rationis or

formal system, but must have ontological reference). And from

these together with (c) it follows that (once more within

unspecified bounds) what is true for philosophy is true to some

extent for all experience.

Now the reason that we must hedge these conclusions with

qualifiers like "to some extent" and "ideally speaking" is that

we cannot simply apply the concepts of the Essay in a wholesale

manner either to experience in general or to reality. Obviously

not all concepts overlap in a scale of forms, nor is everything

in reality arranged in hierarchical fashion.


515

Furthermore if the classificatory ideal of exact and empirical

science is retained as a legitimate way to organize experience

(which is never denied in the Essay), then either one must deny

to it the title of true experience, which is then reserved for

philosophy alone, or else state that there are valid experiences

not subject to the characteristics of philosophical experience.

But if we approach the Essay from the perspective pro-

vided by Speculum Mentis we can say that Collingwood would

choose the first alternative: although it is quite possible to

adopt the scientific point of view on experience, such a

viewpoint cannot be ultimately and finally true (i.e. true un-

conditionally or absolutely), but only true in an abstract way.

If, as Speculum Mentis proposes, all knowledge is truly or-

ganized in a scale of forms, and if the doctrine of the Essay

concerning the relative standing of successive terms in this

scale as "experience" and "conclusion" be taken seriously, then

it follows that the relative position of empirical science and

philosophy are such that empirical science is "experience" to

philosophy's "conclusion." Furthermore if this conclusion is

already present as an experience which "anticipates" its

conclusion before reasoning about it begins, then empirical

science is an experience which anticipates the conclusions that

are first stated explicitly by philosophy. Philosophy "explains"

science only by incorporating its positive content, and

rejecting its negative


516

aspect (i.e. its abstractness). From the point of view of

Speculum Mentis, then, the closest that we can come to saying

what the Essay's evaluation of exact and empirical science is,

is that they are not what philosophy explicitly states itself to

be. Philosophy is self-justifying; exact and empirical sciences

are not. (Cf. Rubinoff, CRM, 26-27).

Unfortunately this gets us into difficulties concerning

our original statement that-the Essay utilizes an essentially

Kantian strategy--i.e. it assumes the fact of certain

experiences and goes on to ask on what necessary and sufficient

conditions such an experience is alone possible. We are left, as

we were in Chapter VII above, confronting something resembling

the "absolute knowledge" of an Hegelian sort rather than

confronting conditional schematized categories without which

experience would not be intelligible. The Essay leaves us in

unresolved puzzlement about this matter, except to the extent

that Collingwood makes it clear that he is not content with

leaving philosophical method where Kant had left it in the

Critique of Pure Reason: philosophy cannot be content with

viewing itself as merely critical--it must go further and state

what the positive grounds are from which criticism proceeds. But

the positive grounds that he provides, as we shall see in a

moment, are not a repetition of his conflicting remarks about

"absolute knowledge" in
517
Speculum Mentis, but a development of the theme of language that

we first discovered in germ in Speculum Mentis.

But where does all this leave us in our discussion of

Q-A logic? In the previous section of this chapter we found that

although Collingwood proposed Q-A logic as an alternative to

F-logic, on examination it turns out either to presuppose it or

to presuppose what F-logic presupposes; meaning, validity, and

truth appear to be establishable independently of Q-A or P-Q-A

complexes, and Q-A logic (either as Q-AA or Q-AM) fails to meet

criteria of consistency, completeness, or formality. In this

section we have been primarily concerned with discussing D-logic

and its relationship to F-logic, from which it differs in a

number of important ways (employing overlapping classes,

reversible inferences, etc.). Q-A logic has hardly entered into

the discussion. In the next section we shall see that rather

than being an oversight on Collingwood's part, it is an

indication that in his view these three logics are related

primarily by locating them in an epistemological context--i.e.

through the intellective, linguistic functions of mind.

As we noted above, the clue to the discovery of the

nature of philosophical thinking in the Essay is the overlap of

classes, and this is described in essentially semantic terms: it

is an overlap of intensional meaning, and meaning is a function

of mind at the linguistic level of


518

consciousness. The final step in our analysis of Collingwood's

views on logic must therefore take us back to the philosophy of

mind in The Principles of Art and The New Leviathan. After

surveying the functions of intellect and reason in these two

works, we shall attempt a final evaluation of the roles of the

three logics we have been discussing.

4. Language and Logic in The Principles of Art.

In our exploration of Collingwood's views on logic we

have noted not only a certain informality to his presentation of

both Q-A and D-logics, but also a tendency to describe these

logics in epistemological terms--concepts, judgments,

suppositions made by acts of choice, Q-A correlativity defined

in terms of persons, etc.--in short, terms which retain a

reference to mental activities as part of their essential

meaning. While any practitioner of contemporary formal logic

would find this to be archaic flaw, we find Collingwood in his

correspondence with Ryle insisting on the propriety of this

epistemological informality, and even suggesting (as in the

passage where he states that he understands the universal to be

that which makes a class a class) that there is somehow a

priority of the epistemological to the formal: that there can be

an F-logic depends on the fact that there are certain

"element-types" of which thought is capable, and it is on the

basis of these that F-logical systems are constructible.


519

Now all this leans heavily on a philosophy of language

and mind for its justification, and we left our examination of

Collingwood's philosophy of mind at exactly the point where we

now wish to resume the discussion. Whatever else Q-A logic,

F-logic, and D-logic may have in common, they are varieties of

discourse, and hence linguistic functions of mind at the level

of intellect. Consequently we must return to The Principles

of_Art (and in the next section to The New Leviathan) to examine

as best we can the functions of mind at the conceptual,

propositional, and rational levels, in order to see if we can

find a clue to unscrambling some of the puzzles we have thus far

encountered in our examination of the three logics with which we

are presently concerned. This will eventually lead us into a

discussion of Collingwood's views on abstraction, which has been

such a sensitive issue for Collingwood's interpreters, and which

we have thus far avoided.

Once more, at the risk of oversimplification, we shall

first present an outline of Collingwood's major conclusions on

language in The Principles of Art.


520

TABLE 11

LANGUAGE AND EXPRESSION IN THE PRINCIPLES OF ART

1. Expression is the fundamental practical act of mind in which


emotions are manifested by bodily acts. It is by the same act
that we express an emotion and become conscious of it. When a
man expresses an emotion what is meant is that he finds
himself in a feeling-situation of emotional excitement from
which he attempts to extricate himself by doing something,
where that doing is both a conscious activity and a
linguistic act. Expression in its primitive state is
non-descriptive because it is not a process of
conceptualization or classification: it is completely
individualized and oriented to the felt situation. It is also
primarily addressed by the person to himself, and secondarily
to an audience of persons like himself, and in both cases the
expression is intended to make his audience (including
himself) understand how he feels. (PA, 109-14).

2. Psychical expression (e.g. grimacing, blushing, cringings)


are primitive expressions at the psychical level. It consists
in the doing of involuntary and perhaps even totally
unconscious bodily acts, related in a single experience but
analyzable into the elements of a sensum, its emotional
charge, and the expression of that emotion. There are no
unexpressed emotions, because every kind and shade of emotion
at this level of experience has its expression in some change
of the muscular or circulatory or glandular system of the
organism. (PA, 228-30, 238).

3. Language in its wider sense, or imaginative expression,


consists of bodily actions expressing certain emotions
insofar as we are conscious that controlling them is our way
of expressing these emotions. These emotions are minimally
those which arise only through the consciousness of self
(e.g. hatred, love, anger, shame). Language in its widest
sense is the bodily expression of emotion dominated by
thought in its primitive form as consciousness. Within such
a system there is a synthesis of material elements
consisting of psychical expressions, but organized according
to a formal principle provided by the corresponding mode of
consciousness (i.e. primitive consciousness of self). (PA,
231-35).
521

4. Speech (vocal language or language proper) is a system of


gestures having the peculiarity that each gesture produces a
characteristic sound. Every kind or order of speech is an
offshoot from an original language of total bodily gesture,
that is, a language in which every movement and stationary
poise of every part of the body has the same kind of
significance which movements of the vocal organs possess in
a spoken language. This total bodily gesture is the one and
only real language: it is the motor side of our total
imaginative experience (or total activity of imaginative
consciousness). Speech is a function of self-consciousness:
the discovery of myself as a person is the discovery that I
can speak. But this self discovery is also the experience of
myself as a listener, and the consciousness of our own
existence is also the consciousness of the existence of
other persons as speakers in the community of language.
Understanding the speech of others involves an act of
imaginative, reconstructive consciousness in which mistakes
can occur, both in expressing one's own emotions (the
corruption of consciousness) or in mistaking the speech of
others (misunderstanding or misinterpretation). (PA, 242-51).

5. Intellectualized speech is language specifically suited to


expressing thought and its attendant intellectual emotions.
It differs from imaginative expression in the same way that
the object of imagination differs from that of intellect,
i.e. as something presented as one, indivisible,
self-contained and complete in itself (imagination) and as a
manifold of such objects with determinate relations between
them (analytic thought), or again as a relation between
something determinate and something indeterminate (abstract
thought). Intellectualized language, even when modified by
the grammatical and logical analysis of language, never loses
its emotive expressiveness. In its final form as artificial
symbolism invented for a purely scientific purpose, it has
both expressiveness and meaning, whereas in its imaginative
form it has expressiveness but not meaning. (PA, 252-61,
268-69).
522

As in the previous sections of this chapter, we will

group our comments around these summarized topics.

(1) We notice first that in his discussion, language is

located on a scale of forms, the minimal form of which is what

he calls "expression," and which consists of species that are

themselves concrete (i.e. having their own form or principle of

organization) but are further determined by successive forms

(i.e. are "matter" or "experience" for the "synthesis" of their

elementary parts by a higher mental act) (PA, 23034).

Collingwood even calls attention to this sort of structure when

he insists that "each level must organize itself according to

its own principles before a transition can be made to the next,

for until that has been done, the raw material needed for the

creation of the next is not forthcoming" (PA, 234). Thus the

emotions of consciousness (emotions that presuppose a

consciousness of self) must be formally or linguistically

expressed before a transition can be made to the level of

intellect.

One consequence of defining language by means of a scale

of forms is that successive levels incorporate the positive

content of all that precedes them in the scale--each is a

summary of what went before it. Consequently, true to his

description of such a scale in the Essay, Collingwood insists

that the element of expressiveness is never lost when


523

language develops into the forms expressive of intellectual

functions. Consistent with his Law of Primitive Survivals,

Collingwood therefore insists that there exists something he

wishes to call "emotions of intellect," which intellectualized

language, even in its symbolic form as mathematics or logic,

continues to express: intellectualized language has both ex-

pressiveness and meaning, whereas imaginative language has

expressiveness, but not meaning as distinct from it. Unfor-

tunately, aside from his brief suggestions that this is what is

involved in the excitement of intellectual discovery, and that

it is intellectual emotions that are involved when one values a

thought to the point that he feels it important enough to utter

in a given situation (PA, 164, 267), Collingwood does not

develop this interesting suggestion in The Principles of Art--at

least not beyond the point necessary for the elaboration of his

esthetic theory (it plays an important role in his discussion of

esthetic truth--cf. PA, 282-88).27 As we shall see in the

conclusion to this chapter,

____________________
27 This is not the only frustration for an interpreter
seeking to understand Collingwood's idea of language in The
Principles of Art: the chapter on language is the most exas-
perating chapter in the whole book. While it is the apex of the
entire argument of his esthetics (art is ultimately defined as
imaginative expression or language) and laced with pregnant
suggestions, it never fulfills its promise in a satisfying
analysis of the phenomenon of language. And what is worse is
that it presents examples which are not only misleading but
downright abusive. As an example of the emotive expressiveness
of intellectualized language Collingwood conjures up for his
readers the image of the "fastidious Cambridge mouth" of I. A.
Richards (whose theory of language in art he
524

there is concealed in the vagaries of this discussion an im-

portant clue to the understanding of his Q-A logic and its

relation to F-logic and D-logic--i.e. the heuristic intellective

function of questions as anticipations of answers.

(2) A second consequence of defining language by means

of a scale of forms is that each level presupposes the materials

presented to it by a lower level: psychical expression is

presupposed by language as imaginative expression; the language

of imaginative gesture is presupposed

______________________
clearly opposes); and he compares grammarians to primitive
African butchers who slice steaks from living animals (PA, 259,
264). Worst of all, he relies for many of his major conclusions
on arguments that are utterly contingent, gratuitous, and
unconvincing. The most notable instance of this is his argument
in support of the thesis that all language, even in the
symbolic, intellectualized language of the mathematician, is
emotively expressive. He states baldly that "every mathematician
knows" that a symbolism re-acquires the emotional expressiveness
of language proper. He then goes as far as to say that in
expressing a perfectly definite intellectual emotion a perfectly
definite act of thought is expressed too, so that a visiting
physicist seeing Archimedes racing naked from his bath down the
streets of Syracuse shouting "Eureka!" would, if he had himself
made Archimedes' discovery and knew how to read this expression
of intellectualized emotion, be able to understand the whole
scene, even that it was the discovery of specific gravity that
caused Archimedes' excitement (PA, 267-68). It is no wonder that
intelligent readers like Susanne Langer accuse him of "philo-
sophical malpractice" (Feeling and Form, p. 384), since ar-
guments like these are utterly unconvincing. On such grounds as
these one might prove that the earth is flat and that precise
scientific information may be passed from mind to mind by mental
telepathy. Unfortunately such diversions as these may also
distract the reader from supplying his own convincing examples
and arguments for the serious suggestions and principles he is
advocating.
525

by speech, and speech is presupposed by symbolic language. It is

therefore just a consequence of defining language by a scale of

forms when Collingwood states that one of the presuppositions of

F-logic (which occurs at the level of symbolic expression) is

the "propositional assumption" which presupposes the grammatical

and lexicographical units (words, phrases, sentences)

constructed at the level of speech: propositions or statements

(that which can be true or false) are isolated from a group of

expressions called sentences which are presumed to be already

grammatically well-formed. (Cf. PA, 260).

Unfortunately, for his readers, Collingwood appears so

bent upon emphasizing the artificiality of forcing the living

language of imaginative expression into the categories devised

by the grammatical and logical analysis of language that the

positive point that he is making is submerged under what appears

to be an abusive assault on grammarians and logicians for doing

what he admits to be their proper jobs. But if Collingwood's

description of grammarians as "butchers" is meant to be merely

abusive, why would he bother analyzing this abusiveness any

further? But he does, distinguishing between the grammatical

functions of lexicography (the cataloguing of recurrent units of

speech, called words, and the listing of their respective

meanings as relations of synonymy), accidence (rules governing

word inflection), and syntax (rules governing words as

functional units in sentences) (PA, 256-57)? And further,


526

why would he feel obliged to describe the three stages (actually

three presuppositions) in the grammatical analysis of speech,

viz. (a) the reduction of language as an activity to the product

of this activity, "speech" or "discourse"; (b) the division of

this product into units (words, idioms, phrases, sentences,

etc.); and (c) the devising of a schema of relations between

these units (syntax or the rules of grammar)--these presupposing

respectively the belief in a "metaphysical fiction" of the

finished product of speech-language, the existence of

self-sustaining atomic word-units that comprise this product,

and fictional rules governing their relationships (PA, 254-56)?

May we not safely assume that having taught himself half a dozen

languages and demonstrated his proficiency both as a translator

and as a celebrated user of English, that he was well aware of

the importance of such grammatical analysis and of lexicography

and the science of linguistics in general, but that he felt

constrained to warn his readers against a certain reductionistic

tendency which results from an overtly idolatrous attitude

towards the teachings of such sciences? And are his remarks in

opposition to this attitude not indicative of his continuing

struggle against what he understood to be the realistic

thesis28--in this case, the treatment of

______________________
28 This is clear from a passage in which he first de-
scribes the activity of the grammarian as a cutting up of a
presumed "thing" called language into pieces called words. "Some
readers will object to this
527

language as as a "thing"?

(3) Of more direct concern to this chapter is his

discussion of "the logical analysis of language"--by which he

understands "a certain technique, first systematically

expounded. . . in Aristotle's Organon" and subsequently

developed by a long line of logicians culminating in "the

logical analysts and positivists of the present day" (PA, 259).

The aim of this technique, he says, is to make language into a

perfect vehicle for the expression of thought--that is, to

remove the

_________________
phrase on the ground that I have used a verb of acting when I
ought to have used a verb of thinking; a dangerous habit, they
will remind me, because when you get to the point of saying
'thought constructs the world' when you mean 'some one thinks
how the world is constructed,' you have slipped into idealism
through mere looseness of language; and that, they will add, is
the way idealists are made. There is much that might be said in
answer to this objection; as, that philosophical controversies
are not to be settled by a kind of police-regulation governing
people's choice of words, and that a school of thought . . .
which depends for its existence on enforcing a particular jargon
is a school which I neither respect nor fear. But I prefer to
reply merely that I said cut because I meant cut. The division
of the 'thing' known as language into words is a division not
discovered, but devised, in the process of analyzing it" (PA,
255). In the immediately succeeding passage, Collingwood also
declares his refusal "to be frightened by the bogy of idealism"
when he states that grammatical rules are devised rather than
discovered (PA, 256). We might add that the reason that
Collingwood meant to say "cut" when he could have said "dissect,
and "butcher" when he could have said "anatomist" (for after
all, grammarians do cut up language "at its joints" as Aristotle
would say, rather than hacking them across muscle bundles for
sale as steaks at a market), is that his intention was polemical
as well as analytical. He wished to warn us of what he regarded
as a dangerous tendency. What else would this be but realism?
528

frustrations of expressions due to the inaccuracies and am-

biguities in speech, and to do so by replacing them with logical

forms (either of the subject-predicate form of Aristotelian

logic or the propositional forms of what Collingwood calls the

"modern analytic school" of logic) (PA, 259-60).

Once again Collingwood distracts the reader from his

positive treatment of the subject by his emphasis on the ar-

tificiality of the logician's project, i.e. proposing a modi-

fication of language rather than a theory of it. What a con-

temporary logician would be surprised at is not the accusation

that he is proposing a modification of language (for after all,

most contemporary logicians would agree that what they are doing

is constructing formal systems, which may or may not have a

similarity or applicability to natural languages). On the

contrary he would be surprised by the suggestion that what he

might be mistaken to be doing is the construction of a theory of

any natural language (which is taken to be the province of a

science of linguistics).

But he might further not only be surprised by, but also

take issue with, Collingwood's list of the "assumptions" of the

logical analysis of language. In addition to assuming that the

grammatical transformation of language has been successfully

accomplished, the logician, Collingwood says, makes three

further assumptions:
529

First comes what I shall call the propositional assumption.


This is the assumption that, among the various "sentences"
already distinguished by grammarians, there are some which,
instead of expressing emotions, make statements. It is to
these that the logician confines his attention. Second, the
principle of homolingual translation. This is an assumption
about sentences corresponding to the lexicographer's
assumptions about words (or . . . lexicographical units)
when he "defines the meaning" of a given word by equating
it with that of another, or of a group of words taken
together. According to the principle of homolingual
translation, one sentence may have precisely the same
meaning as another single sentence, or group of sentences
taken together, in the same language, so that one may be
substituted for the other without change of meaning. The
third assumption is that of logical preferability: namely
that, of two sentences or sentence-groups having the same
meaning, one may be preferable, from a logician's point of
view, to the other . . . . The preferred version is
preferred because it is one which the rules of the
logician's technique enable him to manipulate. (PA, 260-61;
cf. A, 3536).

We suspect that a contemporary logician would object to this

description of the assumptions he makes in his logical in-

quiries: (a) he would object to the confinement of his attention

to statements alone, and worse still to statements as sentences

already distinguished by grammarians; (b) he would say that

homolingual translation or substitutability is not dependent on

identity of meaning alone, but on the logical form or structure

of language as well; and (c) he would argue that logical

preferability is not something dependent solely on the

logician's point of view, but rather is presupposed by the

logical employment of sentences in a language and merely

displayed by translation into formal structures. But rather than

presuming to speak for contemporary logicians, we are more


530

interested in what Collingwood has to say about these

assumptions, and in this connection it is noteworthy that he

never denies that they are valid assumptions. He says only that

as proposals for the modification of language, they can never be

carried out in their entirety. Language proper, even as an

artificial symbolism, can never lose its emotive-expressive

aspect. Once mastered, a symbolic language, invented to serve a

technical purpose, reacquires the emotional expressiveness of

language proper (PA, 262, 268).

The principles of homolingual translation and logical

preferability provide us with some supporting evidence for the

suggestion we made in considering the "variable" (which the

Essay on Philosophical Method declared to be extrinsic to the

generic essence in non-philosophical concepts, but identical

with it in philosophical concepts) in terms of the substi-

tution-relations of a logic based on abstract class concepts. As

we noted in our discussion of the Essay, when Speculum Mentis

described the abstract universal of logic as one which is

"indifferent" to the variation of its instances, and when the

Essay described the classes of F-logic as one in which the

variable is not identified with the generic essence, what he

seems to have in mind is the fact that in F-logic replacement

instances of a class (whether this be of terms or propositions)

are indifferent to whatever other properties these instances may

have: their identity is based solely on the criteria for


531

their membership in the class. They are therefore substitutable

one for the other. In Speculum Mentis and in the Essay

Collingwood deliberately contrasted this sort of replacement-

relation with another in which the differences of the instances

of a class are relevant to the class itself. In Speculum Mentis

this was called a "concrete universal," or one in which the

variable element between the instances of the universal is not

ignored, but makes a difference to the generic universal itself;

in the Essay this was expressed by saying that for philosophical

concepts, the variable (presumably what allows one instance of a

concept to differ from another instance of the same concept) is

identified with the generic essence (i.e. is related to the

meaning of the concept in a necessary and essential manner). We

suggested that if such differences between individual instances

of a universal are essential to the identity of the concept as

such, then they must be regarded as part of that concept's

meaning--which brought us to the brink of a discussion of the

analytic-synthetic distinction.

What we wish to point out here is that in an explicit

discussion of the assumptions of what is undoubtedly F-logic,

Collingwood states the replacement-relation of substitutability

of instances for one another in a class as essential to the F-

logical analysis of language.

(4) Another interesting corollary of the definition of

language by means of a scale of forms is that in the

specification of the genus


532

"expression" into the species "symbolic language," the essential

functions of emotive expression and intentional meaning are both

retained in the same act. This has a peculiar outcome: since no

matter how artifactual a symbolic language becomes it retains or

"reacquires" the emotional expressiveness of language proper, in

Collingwood's view it never loses contact with the emotional

life of the speaker.29

As his remarks about interpersonal self-consciousness

and the community of speakers and hearers indicates (PA, 247--

52), he does not believe that such an admission leads to a form

of linguistic solipsism in which a "private language" is

employed which no one can understand but the speaker (since no

one can "read" the emotional life internal to a user of

___________________
29 Computer analysis and programmers reading this today
might be startled by such a conclusion, since machine-
communication languages like COBAL seem to work quite effec-
tively for the tasks which they are designed to perform. What
Collingwood might say about the development of such languages as
these is hard to say, since it would be peculiar to predicate
"emotional expressiveness" to a computer print-out, while one
would also be forced to admit that there is some sort of
communication occurring between man and machine by means of such
languages. Our guess is that Collingwood would not take
computer-language to be language at all, but a sort of book-
keeping aided by mechanical and electronic devices, not any more
expressive of thought than the noises emitted from a
tape-recorder or the typescript emerging from a typewriter. The
computer operator is still engaging in linguistic expression at
the input and interpretation ends of the process of machine
communication: the rest is automatic book-keeping, not thought.
533

a private language). On the contrary Collingwood goes to the op-

posite extreme and declares that at a primitive level total

communication can and does occur--as in the spread of emotion

like a kind of contagion from person to person, e.g. panic in a

crowd.30 Although this occurs directly only at the psychical

level (and this is the level at which even animals can be said

to communicate), at levels above this, in which emotions require

consciousness of self, such communications occur usually only

through "language" in its broadest sense (as totally bodily

gesture--cf. PA, 238, where Collingwood baldly states that there

are no unexpressed emotions).

Collingwood does not spell out in detail how the in-

tentional meanings of a speaker are bound to his expression of

emotion, but it is clear that he wishes to retain both functions

in all levels of linguistic activity. For Collingwood meaning

never loses its aspect of being

___________________
30 In speaking of psychical emotions which are always
expressed as some change in the muscular or circulatory or
glandular system, Collingwood writes that "nothing but lack of
skill ((in observing such changes and correctly interpreting
them)) prevents us from reading like an open book the psychical
emotions of every one with whom we have to do. But observing and
interpreting is an intellectual process; and this is not the
only way in which psychical expression conveys a meaning. There
is a kind of emotional contagion which takes effect without any
intellectual activity; without the presence even of
consciousness" (PA, 230). Collingwood cites, in addition to the
spread of panic through a crowd, the examples of the sympathetic
feeling of pain or joy, and the terror transmitted from prey to
predator.
534

something that a speaker does (where "speech," of course, is

taken in a broad sense to include not only vocal utterance but

any suitable substitute for it--e.g. the sign language of mutes;

it includes anything in which a physical gesture can be tied to

a meaning). Meanings are bound to what have more recently been

called "illocutionary acts," or what a speaker intends to convey

by what he says. They are not something contained in a

dictionary, with fixed relations of synonymy, but are part of a

living process linked to the emotional life of speakers, whose

intentions to convey meanings have a career in which meanings

are born, develop in a context of relations, and may even die.

Meanings, on Collingwood's view, are not something words have,

but something that speakers do with words. (cf. PA, 269).

This is as far as Collingwood takes us on the path to

language. Whether or not a case can be made for a language that

is purely symbolic or has meaning without being expressive, such

a thing would not be regarded as a true language by Collingwood.

(5) One final aspect of Collingwood's discussion of

language needs to be mentioned before going on to relate lang-

uage to the levels of consciousness, and that is the global or

comprehensive aspect of each level of the linguistic scale of

forms. Each has what Collingwood calls its own principle or

organization or form, although he is not always


535

careful to make explicit what that principle is. In the final

analysis it might not be possible to do so, since any one level

may be capable of a virtual infinity of forms with no apparent

unifying communality between them: imaginative expression in

art, for example, encompasses everything from dancing

(Collingwood calls dance the mother of language) to drama to

painting--the list is only arbitrarily broken off, every work of

art being a "monad" and even the everyday acts of human life

being to some extent works of art.

But in attempting to characterize them as essential

structures, Collingwood points continually toward a completed,

global activity--in the case under discussion, the "language of

total bodily gesture," which he calls the only real (imag-

inative) language (PA, 246-47). He correlates this "total bodily

gesture" language with the corresponding mental function of

"total imaginative activity" (AP, 247). There is a similarity

here to what we have seen Collingwood advocating concerning the

organizational unity of the "logical structure of real thinking"

in his correspondence with Ryle: in any example of real thinking

there is contained an example of every kind of proposition as so

many "element-types" (CRC-I, 18). If any level of consciousness

has its own organizational unity, and if this unity must be

complete before a transition to a higher level of consciousness

may occur (cf. PA, 233-34), then the explicit articulation


536

of the "logic" or coherence of any level of consciousness is a

matter of making explicit or expressing what is already a

completed whole, insofar as that unity is viewed from a higher

level.

We may speculate, in terms of our discussion of logic,

that the systematic unity of F-logic (or what we may now call a

symbolic language in which what we say can be distinguished--but

not separated--from what we mean, and artificial symbols can be

devised and stipulated for a particular meaning) is exhibited

only by the assumption of a higher viewpoint (what might be

called today a "meta-language") for which F-logic is an object.

In Speculum Mentis we observed Collingwood making just such an

argument: F-logic is the unifying principle of a form of

experience which he called "scientific thinking," in which the

distinction between what we say and what we mean is first made

manifest (SM, 128-30, 154-57; cf. PA, 269); but if the principle

of organization of such an activity is not already somehow

complete, the transition could not be made to a higher viewpoint

for which the lower is regarded as an object. Philosophy is such

a higher viewpoint, according to Speculum Mentis, and its logic

is dialectical. Can we conclude for Collingwood that D-logic is

a metalanguage for the discussion of objects that have F-logic

as their unifying principle?


537

Perhaps. But once more we must point out where Col-

lingwood leaves the discussion and where we resume it. He never

called D-logic a meta-language, nor did he ever explicitly work

out the relationship between D-logic and F-logic other than to

point out in the Essay the salient ways in which D-logic differs

from F-logic in their respective ideals. We have also tried to

remain alert to the fact that the existence of something which

meets the description Collingwood gives of D-logic depends on

his ability to provide us with concrete, irreducible, and

convincing instances of such a logic. So far the instances of

D-logic that we have encountered are those which stress the

overlapping layers of meaning in certain terms used by

philosophers, the unity of meaning and reference in universal

categorical philosophical judgments, and the reversible

inference structures employed in typical philosophical

arguments. But in the final analysis the issue of whether there

is anything which meets the criteria for D-logic described by

the Essay rests, as we saw in our analysis of the Essay, on

whether or not there can be a kind of knowledge which is

self-justifying.

But in the meantime we have already seen that for Col-

lingwood the issue of logic is always bound to that of language,

and language is a function of a conscious mind. Before

concluding our survey of the topic we therefore must attend to

final discussion of logical mental functions in The New

Leviathan.
538

5. Language and Mind: The New Leviathan.

We are now in as good a position as we shall ever be to

mount a final assault on the heights of Collingwood's philosophy

of mind--i.e. the functions of intellect and reason. We must

remind ourselves once again of the difficulties we encountered

in Chapter VIII in reconciling the conflicting terminology

between The Principles of Art and The New Leviathan.31 Some of

these terminological ambiguities, we noted, can be cleared up by

recognizing wider and narrower senses that Collingwood allows

for terms like "consciousness" and "thought;" and some of them

can be reconciled by paying careful attention to the differing

approaches of the two works, which helps put such unannounced

shifts in the comprehension of its terms in their methodological

contexts.

Although we did not call attention to this fact in the

immediately proceeding section of this present chapter, this

shift in approach between the two works is even apparent in the

discussion of language in each of the two works. The Principles

of Art considers language in terms of the

____________________
31 The principal discrepancy is that in The Principles
of Art consciousness, even in its most primitive-form, is called
thought, and its function as attention is selective without
being abstractive; in The New Leviathan "simple consciousness of
feeling" is not considered to be thought, and selective
attention functions only at the secondary level of consciousness
and is abstractive (cf. PA, 204-06, 215-17; NL, 4.13-4.5).
539

dialectical array of forms of expressiveness from psychical

expression in physiological changes to symbolic language; The

New Leviathan considers language as an abstraction from, or re-

striction of, "discourse" or "the activity by which a man means

anything" (NL, 6.1-6.11). An unwary interpreter might conclude

from a superficial comparison of these two treatments of

language that Collingwood had "changed his mind" or "repudiated"

his earlier treatment of the subject. Our own inclination is to

see the later work in the light of the earlier one, and hence as

an analytic discussion, from a restricted point of view, of a

topic which has a broader context and represents one portion of

a "scale of forms"--in this case, the scale of forms of

expression.

However this does not resolve all the interpretative

difficulties posed by The New Leviathan on the issue of language

and logic. We shall attend to some of the more important of

these problems after our summary of the doctrines of The New

Leviathan on language and the levels of mental functions.


540
TABLE 12

LANGUAGE, LOGIC, AND MENTAL ACTS IN THE NEW LEVIATHAN

1. Discourse is the activity by which a man means anything: it


is the activity of meaning something (a) by something else
(b), where meaning (a) is an act of theoretical con-
sciousness, and (b) is a practical activity, the production
in oneself or others of a flow of sounds or the like which
serve as the vehicle of that meaning. Discourse is
continuous, so that even the rests or pauses of silence,
immobility, or the like which punctuate it are significant
parts of it, not interruptions of it. But selective at-
tention breaks it up into words; vocal words if it is
speech, gesture-words if in gesture, etc. Once discourse is
broken up into units it is the lexicographer's business to
determine the meaning or various meanings which a given word
bears whenever it is used. The phonetic or other vehicle of
discourse is physical in the sense of being a succession of
feelings or sensations with their emotional charges produced
by the activity of speech or the like. (NL, 6.1-6.19).

2. Language is an abstraction from discourse: it is the system


adopted, the means employed, the rules followed in the
activity of discourse. It is a system of sounds or the like
as having meanings, these meanings being what a person using
that word means by making that sound or gesture. Language is
not a device whereby knowledge already existing in one man's
mind is communicated to another's, but an activity prior to
knowledge itself, without which knowledge could never come
into existence. As consciousness develops, language develops
with it. (NL, 6.11, 6.18, 6.41, 6.58).

a. Language in its simplest form is the language of con-


sciousness in its simplest form; the mere register of
feelings, irrational, unplanned, unorganized, uncon-
scious. At this level of consciousness thought is merely
apprehensive, or capable of taking what is "given" to
it. (NL, 6.58, 10.51).

b. When consciousness becomes conceptual thought, language


develops abstract terms. At this level of consciousness
thought is capable of framing abstractions from what is
given. Selective attention breaks up continuous
discourse into words. A word is a lin-
541
guistic habit of the community using it; the habit of
conveying a special meaning by using any member of a
certain class of auditory and visual vehicles, of which
any member is an example of that word. (NL, 6.12, 6.17,
6.58, 10.52, 34.123.

c. When consciousness becomes propositional thought, lang-


uage develops the indicative sentence as the standard
verbal form in which to state the proposition. At this
level of consciousness thought is capable of dis-
criminating truth from error.(NL, 6.59, 10.51).

d. When consciousness becomes reason language becomes de-


monstrative discourse wherein sentences are so linked
together as to state verbally the consequences of one
proposition in relation to another. At this level of
consciousness thought is capable of understanding both
itself and other things.(NL,6.59,10.51).

3. Conceptual thinking or selective attention is an act of


practical consciousness by which a man emerges from the state
of feeling and simple consciousness of feeling. A man makes
himself conscious of his feelings by naming them, either by
the language of gesture (e.g. by an expressive shiver) or by
the language of speech (saying "cold"). To name the feeling
awakens consciousness of the feeling: until it is named, the
feeling is preconscious; when it is named it becomes
conscious. (NL, 6.2-6.28, 7.2-7.23).

a. Selective attention is the act in which a person attends


to some element or group of elements within the a
confused mass of feeling. The act of attending is doing
something to oneself as well as doing something to the
object being attended to; it is focusing one's own
consciousness on a certain part of the field of feeling
and repressing the rest; but it is also circumscribing
it, drawing a line between it and the rest of the field
(NL, 7.23-7.24).

b. The act of classifying is the practical activity of


consciousness involved in "drawing the line" between
objects (sense) in a field of feeling, i.e. the point at
which one decides to stop calling the color seen "red"
and begin calling it "purple" or whatever. On acts like
this classes depend for their existence; all classes
being artifacts, depending on practical activities for
their existence and depending for their publicity as
between various persons on these persons performing
practical activities of similar kinds; for many classes
are private to the persons who made them. A class is a
collection of many things into one, in virtue of their
resemblance. The distinguishing mark of a class is that
it is a whole whose parts, its "members," are mutually
related by way of resemblance.
542

Membership in a given class demands a certain kind and


degree of resemblance. The settlement of what the degree
and kind of resemblance is for membership in a class is
an act of practical consciousness called classifying.
(NL, 19. 22-19.35).

c. Evocative thinking is the act of arousing in oneself by


the work of thought feelings not found as given in
oneself; it is an act which goes with the act of se-
lective attention. Feelings thus aroused, called
evocations, form a context inseparable from any
selection, and are connected with it by logical
relations. Evocations are feelings felt but not given,
produced by the same act of practical consciousness that
produced the selection or abstraction from the given
field of conscious feeling. (NL, 7.32-7.38).

d. A concept (notion) is a selection together with its


context of evocations. Any logical relation may preside
over the birth, from a given selection, of an evocation
forming part of its context. It is not possible to
compile a list of such logical relations, although
contrast and comparison are two such relations. (NL,
7.34-7.36, 7.39).

e. Abstractions are determinate in some ways, indeterminate


in others (as in a triangle, which is determinate in
having three sides, but except for what is implied in
this, it is indeterminate in everything else). Ab-
stractions are only second-order objects made by the
mind out of its immediate or first-order objects. Ab-
straction is a necessary part of thought; an abstraction
is false if the elements abstracted are judged to be
mutually independent entities. (NL, 7.56-7.57, 7.67,
26.18-26.19).

4. Propositional thinking is the set of mental acts that are


involved in asking and answering questions, and disting-
uishing truth from error (and good from evil). Asking a
question implies contemplating alternatives. A question that
offers no alternatives is a bogus question, from the point
of view of knowledge proper. The technique of knowing proper
or scientific method depends on replacing vague or confused
questions, which are unanswerable, with real questions which
have a precise answer. (NL, 4.344.35, 11.12).

a. Let a man have a certain form of consciousness, C1. To


that form of consciousness let x, y, z be immediate
objects. Let him call into being in himself another form
of consciousness, C2, the consciousness of C1. Then to
C2, C1 is a first-order object, and x, y, z are
second-order objects. For the form of consciousness, C2,
the second-order objects x, y, z, are abstractions from
the first-order object C1 made by C2. and the knowledge
of these abstractions is mediated by C1.(NL, 5.26,
11.34).
543

b. The subject of a proposition or what the proposition is


about is never a first-order object. (NL, 11.34).

c. The predicate of a proposition is never a first-order


object, but always a concept (NL, 11.35).

d. Logic applies to propositions because the predicate of a


proposition is a concept, and logic applies to concepts.
Because the predicate of a proposition is a concept, any
proposition may theoretically involve a mistake, though
there are mistakes that people do not make. (NL, 11.35).

5. Rational thinking, or reason as a mental function or form of


consciousness, is thinking one thing x because you think
another thing y, where y is your reason or ground for
thinking x. A piece of rational thinking involves at least
two propositions standing to each other as ground and
consequent. Rational thinking begins when a man accustomed
to propositional thinking starts making a distinction not
made in propositional thinking as such: the distinction
between "the that" and "the why." The distinction is
preconscious until it is reflected upon. (NL, 14.1-14.2).

a. Simple knowledge is the knowledge that arises when a man


reflects upon a piece of propositional thinking and asks
himself whether he has really done it, and answers in
the affirmative. Such a judgment is fallible, i.e.
errors can be made about it. (NL, 14.2114.25).

b. Reflection on the fallibility of such a "that" judgment


prompts one to seek out a second proposition which
offers reassurance of the trustworthiness of the first.
It is the practical act of trying to alleviate the
distress caused me by the untrustworthiness of my
knowledge that gives rise to the distinction between
"the that" and "the why." (NL, 14.25-14.29).

c. Practical reason (making up one's mind to, or forming


what a moralist calls reasons for an intention) comes
into existence when a man forms an intention, reflects
on it, and asks himself whether he really means it. In
this reflection he seeks another intention y to confirm
the original intention x, something from which the x may
follow as a necessary consequence, or stands in relation
to it as ground to consequent. Reason is essentially
practical and hence prior to theoretical reason, because
to be reasonable means to be interested in questions
beginning with "why"; and this happens because people
crave for reassurance against the fallibility of their
knowledge. (NL, 14.31-14.5).
544

d. Theoretical reason (making up one's mind that, or seek-


ing reasons for a proposition) comes into existence when
a man first, by propositional thinking, makes up his
mind that something is so, and then, seeking to confirm
this piece of propositional thinking, looks for a reason
why he should think so. Theoretical reason is based on
the presupposition that a certain kind of propositional
thinking, viz. that about which questions beginning with
"why" can be legitimately asked, is a matter of free
will (i.e. it is not the mere acceptance of something as
given, but is a voluntary decision to think this and not
that). (NL, 14.35-14.37).

e.Questions beginning with "why" cannot be legitimately


asked about first-order objects, but only about objects
of the second and higher orders (i.e. abstractions). If x
is an intention, any ground for it, A, must be another
intention. One intention supporting another both form
part of the same intention, which includes them both and
perhaps other things. Let us call this larger intention
I. Similarly if s is a proposition about whose truth
someone desires reassurance, it follows that t, the
ground of that reassurance, must be a proposition of
whose truth he is satisfied; and s and t are here
abstractions from a first-order proposition P which
includes them both and perhaps other things as well. As
long as I and P are first-order objects they are matters
of immediate conviction or resolution. To demand
confirmation of either would be to place it in a context
of other intentions or other propositions that might
afford grounds for it; that is, to reduce it to the
level of, or to make of it, an abstraction. An intention
is made into an abstraction by surrounding it with a
context of other intentions; a proposition by
surrounding it with a context of other propositions.
(NL, 14.39-14.44).
____________________________________________________________
545

With the advance warning that this section will contain,

of necessity, some rather thorny exegetical discussion, which we

shall try to confine so far as possible to the doctrines

summarized in this table, we shall again group our comments

around these topics.

(1) Coming to The New Leviathan fresh from the dis-

cussion of language in The Principles of Art, one cannot help

but notice some evident similarities which render the apparent

differences in the discussion of consciousness in the later work

less paradoxical. (a) In both works we find a field of feeling

at which a primary consciousness (called "simple consciousness"

in the earlier work and "diffuse consciousness" in the later) is

directed. In this "first state of mental life" consciousness is

merely "apprehensive" (NL, 10.51) or "appreciates" (PA, 203)

what is presented to it in feeling. The expression of this level

of consciousness is loosely called "language" but it is of an

illogical, ejaculatory sort of gesture language and not yet

speech. (b) The second stage of mental life begins with

selective attention, an act of second-order consciousness (i.e.

the consciousness of first-order consciousness) in which

attention is directed towards some sense and away from others in

a field of firstorder, conscious feelings. Second-order

consciousness is expressed in an act (pointing, speaking, making

designating gestures, etc.) which is the same as the act of

consciousness by which he makes himself aware


546

of some designated entity or feeling as that which he is

conscious of, or what he "means" (in the widest sense of the

term "meaning" which includes the most rudimentary act of

reference). This is the level of conceptual thought. (c) At

higher stages of mental life the expression of conscious

functions include what we know as language proper--indicative

and interrogative sentences at the level of propositional

thought, demonstrative discourse for rational consciousness. The

terms "intellect" and "knowledge" generally apply to the second

level of consciousness and the mental functions above it, which

as forms of reflective consciousness presuppose primary

consciousness without which it would have nothing to reflect on

(NL, 9.54).

In all this we seem to be on familiar territory, just as

we are in the discussion of discourse as a continuous system of

bodily movements, only later broken up by "selective attention"

and made into words that are subsequently catalogued by a

lexicographer (NL, 6.1-6.18). Is this not what we have become

acquainted with in The Principles of Art as the "one real

language of total bodily gesture" which is transformed into

speech and then "cut up" by the "butchers" who practice

lexicography and grammar? Even Collingwood's penchant to phrase

all his definitions in terms of conscious acts of human agents

(especially noteworthy in his description of reasoning, where

the terms "inference" and "implica-


547

tion" are conspicuous by their absence) takes us back to the

beginning of the present chapter, where we found his definition

of "logical efficacy" and Q-A correlativity formally ob-

jectionable precisely because they introduce this personal and

epistemological dimension.

But there are also some important differences which

cannot be overlooked, these tending to group themselves around

the three major intellective functions of conceptual, propo-

sitional, and rational thinking. Leaving aside the latter two

for a moment, we notice first that there is no precise analog in

The Principles of Art to correspond to the discussion of

"naming" in The New Leviathan. In fact in the later work

Collingwood appears to be putting forward a radical linguistic

thesis that it is by naming something that we become selectively

aware of it: language is "prior to knowledge itself" and

knowledge could not come into existence without it. How are we

to reconcile this with The Principles of Art, where Collingwood

says that simple or first-order attention is the "act of

appreciating something, just as it stands, before I can begin to

classify it," and that this is done by "identifying" something

as having just the qualities we find it to possess before naming

it (PA, 203)? And what of the passage from the Essay on

Philosophical Method where he writes:

It is only in some dark and half-conscious way that we know


our thoughts before we come to express them. Yet in that
obscure fashion they are already within us; and, rising
into full consciousness as we find the words to utter them,
it is they that determine the words, not vice-versa. (EPM,
200).
548

The astute reader will note that if indeed what he calls

the "diffuse consciousness" of feeling in The New Leviathan is

the same mental function as "simple consciousness" and

first-order attention in The Principles of Art, then there is no

insoluble conflict: first-order attention divides a field of

feeling into focal and penumbral regions, but it does not

abstract (PA, 204). Therefore second-order attention could be

abstractive and denominative, without violating first-order

functions of consciousness. And surely this parallel is

indicated when Collingwood writes that "thought is at first

merely apprehensive, capable of taking what is 'given' to it,

and then merely conceptual, capable of framing abstractions from

what is 'given"' (NL, 10.51). Similar discrepancies in the use

of the term "attention" in The New Leviathan can often be

resolved by adding appropriate qualifiers in passages where the

unqualified term "attention" is used without specifying whether

it is referring to the first-order function of consciousness

(which divides without abstracting) or second-order

consciousness (which is selective and abstractive). Thus when he

writes (in a passage which is directly proceeded by a discussion

of selective attention) that "The act of attending is not merely

a doing something to yourself, focusing your consciousness . . .

it is also a
549

doing something to the object: circumscribing it, drawing a line

between it and the rest of the field" (NL, 7.3; cf. 4.51), he

appears to be locating both division and selective abstraction

in the attentive act of second-order consciousness, but "act of

attending" here may be referring to both levels, just as

"consciousness" may refer to a given level or to that level and

all below it.

(2) Unfortunately sorting out labels for levels of

consciousness and adding qualifiers for functions of conscious-

ness does not settle the issue of how it is possible to "divide"

a field of feeling or to "circumscribe" something within it

without being "selective" about it, or contrariwise how

first-order consciousness if it is not selective, can divide

without abstracting. Granted that Collingwood's stated intention

in The New Leviathan is to take successive "soundings" at

various levels of consciousness (NL, 9.4-9.42), and that he is

therefore not committed to stating why one level gives rise to

the next, or how they come into existence, or even how certain

mental functions are possible at all; nonetheless difficulties

like these pose problems for the reader even in understanding

the descriptive sense of these "soundings." In this case the

problem is one of understanding the functions of division and

abstraction in discourse, and especially as these pertain to the

process of "naming."
550

Particularly confusing is Collingwood's discussion of

naming as a mediating act of consciousness, which view he re-

jects with the following argument:

Until you name it, the feeling is preconscious. When you


name it, it becomes conscious. This does not mean that the
act of naming it becomes conscious; it does not, either as
an act of your own or even merely as the sound of your
voice or the like. It remains preconscious until you
reflect upon it. . . . "If a man becomes conscious of a
feeling only through finding a name for it, is not that a
way of saying that his consciousness of the feeling is not
immediate, as you said (4.22), but mediated through
language?" The consciousness of B is mediate if you can
only be conscious of B as an abstraction from something
else, A, of which you are conscious. Let A be something of
which you are immediately conscious; then A is a first-
order object and B. the abstraction from it, a second-order
object (5.25), and the consciousness of B is mediated
through the consciousness of A . . . . But the feeling is
not an abstraction from the name of the feeling. The man
who names his feeling thereby becomes immediately conscious
of it; he is not conscious of his name for it until he
reflects on the act of naming it, and he proceeds to think
of the name he has uttered in abstraction from that act.
(NL, 6.28-6.39).

It would appear from this passage that either (a) there is ab-

solutely no function to the "diffuse consciousness" of feeling

(since feeling presents itself directly to second-order

consciousness and its function of selective attention by nam-

ing), or (b) naming it (a second-order function) makes us di-

rectly conscious not of the feeling but of the first-order

consciousness of a feeling (that is, a feeling as "apprehended"

by first-order consciousness--or, as The Principles of Art puts

it, a feeling as "appreciated" by being perpetuated and

domesticated by first-order
551

attention). But if (b) is the case, then what are we to make of

the remark that feeling is not an abstraction from the name of

the feeling--and especially when he defines abstraction in this

context as the attainment of a second-order object by means of a

first-order object, where the first-order object is what is

immediately given to consciousness?

Since (b) is the most likely alternative for making

sense of both The New Leviathan and The Principles of Art on the

issue of first and second-order consciousness, we must settle

the problem of the peculiar usage of the term "abstrac-

tion"--which we shall in (although this possibility is not

made explicit in The New Leviathan) that this may not be an

"either-or" situation; i.e. it may be possible that even though

second-order consciousness is consciousness of first-order

consciousness, it may also be directly conscious of the object

of first-order consciousness as well, that object being feeling.

This would be consistent with his remark in The Principles of Art

that "attention (or . . . consciousness or awareness) has a

double object where sentience has a single," that is, "a person

who is said to be looking is described as aware of his own

seeing as well as of the thing he sees," or again "(w)hat we

attend to is two things at once: a sound, and our act of hearing

it" (PA, 206). It is also consistent with his "Law of Primitive

Survivals"
552

(which we will also deal with in a moment) in The New Leviathan,

which states that in any higher form of consciousness there must

survive elements of a previous function in its primitive or

unmodified state (NL, 6.52); in this case we suggest that what

he may be saying is that feeling is still directly present in

first-order consciousness as a "primitive survival," and hence

still an immediate object to second-order consciousness (the

distinction between "apanage" and "constituent" to the contrary

notwithstanding).

Secondly we wish to call attention to the fact that at

the very lowest level of consciousness "meaning" is introduced:

at the "first state of mental life" a man is said to be con-

scious of a confused mass of feeling because he has found a

language of some kind by which he can "mean" it, albeit a very

primitive, illogical, ejaculatory sort of language (NL, 7.24).

Therefore abstractive or selective attention, the "second stage

of mental life," presupposes the presence of some primitive,

pre-reflective "meaning" on which the naming function operates.

But if "meaning" here refers to the level of gesture-language

(which is included in what Collingwood calls "discourse"), i.e.

the "system of bodily movements, not necessarily vocal, whereby

the men who make them mean or signify anything" (NL, 6.1), then

in its primitive function consciousness can mean something

without naming it. Using "discursive" as an adjective for

Collingwood's use of "discourse"


553

in this broad sense, we can say that such pre-reflective "mean-

ing" in first-order consciousness is discursive without being

properly speaking linguistic (cf. NL, 6.11). The conscious cry

of a distressed infant (recognizably distinct from the random

cries of the newborn--cf. PA, 235-37) might be an example of an

expression that means something (the infant is consciously

signaling his distress) without naming it; it is an act that is

discursive (carries meaning) without being linguistic (using

designated words in a spoken language). But such meanings are

individualized expressions, and not generalized descriptions:

the infant's cry of distress is an expression of his present

emotional state, and not in any way a descriptive generalization

about a feeling or feelings not present, or involving relations

with these other feelings (PA, 112; cf. IH, 314, 330).

If we are on the right track, then when Collingwood

writes that a man makes himself conscious of a feeling by naming

it (NL, 6.25), and adds that this is an act of conceptual

thought (NL, 7.23), and adds further that with this act goes an

act of evocative thinking (defined as "the act of arousing in

yourself by the work of thought feelings you do not find as

'given' in yourself"--NL, 7.32), he is not by-passing or

revising the function of first-order consciousness and its

primitive, discursive
554

meaning-act, but rather he is presupposing it.32 The very first

act of consciousness (and it must be remembered that it is only

second-order consciousness that is reflective and hence properly

speaking thought) is an act of designating meaning, and this

assignment of meaning is coextensive (and one might even say co-

intensive) with consciousness itself. If the question were put

to Collingwood, "Can an analysis of mind and consciousness get

beyond or behind language?" we suggest that he would answer,

"Yes, but not by language proper; and if you were to succeed in

getting there, what you would find would be meanings too

primitive to express in words." But as Collingwood pointed out,

reaching this primitive level is an experiment not easily made

(NL, 6.56), so the function of

_____________________
32 The interpretation we are offering of Collingwood's
description of the functions of first- and second-order con-
sciousness differs sharply with that offered by Alan Donagan.
Donagan argues for a reversal between The Principles of Art and
The New Leviathan on the issue of selective attention, and
postulates that between the writing of the earlier and the later
works Collingwood changed his mind: he came to hold that all
thinking is conceptual and all concepts are abstract (LPC, pp.
14, 48-49). We have already argued that this view fails to hold
without qualification for The Principles of Art, and we are now
arguing that it does not hold even for The New Leviathan. We
maintain that Donagan failed to appreciate the function of
first-order consciousness, and relies uncritically on what he
(but not Collingwood) calls "The Principle of Order" (LPC, 28,
52, 93, 105, 167-68). Cf. W. van Leyden in Krausz, CEPC, 27-29.
555

assigning meaning is mostly unreflective and pre-conscious (cf.

IH, 330; Donagan, LPC, 43)33

Obviously this account is very vague, and leaves

much to be said about the fundamental relations of language and

consciousness. We do not know how to characterize this primitive

sort of pre-reflective, discursive meaning-act, or how language

proper with its highly inflective,

_________________
33 Collingwood's remarks in The New Leviathan on first- and
second-order consciousness pose as many problems for an
interpreter as do his remarks on feeling. Our own interpretation
can make sense of many passages, but then others present
problems. For example, Collingwood writes that Hobbes was right
when he said that experience teaches us that it is a vulgar
error to believe that you must first be conscious of a feeling
before you can fit it with a name (NL, 6.56). Unless he means
something idiosyncratic by "naming," this passage (as well as
the discussion surrounding it--NL, 6.42-6.57) appears to support
a radical linguistic thesis like the one Donagan proposes. But
Collingwood provides us with enough clues to overcome his
overstatement. He points out (a) that language is not always
rational (NL, 6.57), and (b) that Hobbes' doctrine is that
"language has become the pre-condition and foundation of
knowledge so far as knowledge is scientific" (NL, 6.47; emphasis
mine). In The Principles of Art, where Collingwood was more
careful in distinguishing symbolic or intellectualized language
from its more primitive variety, he had pointed out this
restriction on Hobbes' discussion of language: "When
Hobbes . . . says that the primary use of speech is for
'acquisition of science,' for which purpose 'the right
definition of names' is the first requisite, clearly, he is
identifying language in general with intellectualized language
or symbolism" (PA, 226). Therefore if one supplies the qualifier
"intellectualized" before "language," in the passage under
discussion from The New Leviathan (NL, 6.56), and "second-order"
before "conscious," the passage can be brought into conformity
to our own interpretation. Cf. IH, 314, 330, where Collingwood
speaks of artistic expression and "unreflective experience."
556

highly differentiated grouping of sounds and meanings can arise

from it, even though he leaves us with the hint that it has

something to do with poesis or "art" (NL, 6.29). We have already

noted that Collingwood's program of "taking soundings" of

consciousness at various depths does not commit him to any

genetic explanation of how one level of consciousness gives rise

to another. In fact in an important chapter he insists that

there can be no laws for the progressive development of mind.

This is stated in the chapter entitled "Retrospect" (Chapter

IX), in which Collingwood sets forth the four principles that he

says he has assumed throughout his discussion of mental func-

tions, one of which (the "Law of Primitive Survivals") we have

already encountered. Before continuing our discussion it would

be best to summarize these principles.


557

TABLE 13

THE PRESUPPOSITIONS OF THE ANALYSIS OF MENTAL FUNCTIONS

1. The Law of Contingency: the earlier terms in a series of


mental functions do not determine the later. The terms in
this case are mental functions called first-order con-
sciousness, second-order consciousness, etc. "Mental func-
tion: means not a single act but a type of activity, and
"series" means an arrangement in which each term is a mo-
dification of the one before it. (NL, 9.3, 9.36, 9.48).
((This law can be restated and clarified in two variant
forms:))

a. The series of mental functions is an irregular series,


i.e. it is not one in which the-development of its terms
is governed by a rule. All mental processes have an
asymptotic or approximative character; they do not have
real initial and terminal points, but always begin with a
first term with a mixture of the second, and end at a
second term qualified by the first. Every case of mental
"being" turns out on examination to be a case of mental
"becoming". (NL, 9.4, 34.58, 34.63).

b. The development of mind is not predictable. The logical


development of a series of mental functions is in-
dependent of its temporal development. In the logical
development of the series of mental functions ABCD (for
first-order consciousness, second-order consciousness,
etc.), the relation between any two successive terms A
and B is such that B renders A necessary or “presupposes”
A as that out of which it develops, while A does not
render B necessary. In a temporal development of such a
series A comes into existence at one time and its
modification B at a subsequent time. But while the
existence of the series ABCD presupposes

___________________________________________________________
NOTE: We take the liberty of assuming that the comments
from Chapter XXXIV cited in (la) are a clarification of the
expression, "irregular series," which cannot consistently mean
"not governed by any rule whatsoever," since at least one rule
is applicable to it, namely that each term is a modification of
the one before.
558

the existence of each of its terms, and each successor


presupposes its predecessor, it is not the case that
given the successor B. A must have come to exist before
it in time, since A and B may have come to exist
together or coexist in the same act. But whether mind
develops from function A to B. or from AB to C, or ABC
to D (a progressive development), or whether it
degenerates from ABCD to ABC, etc. (called regression)
is not predictable; it depends on the practical energy
available to a mind at any given time. (NL, 9.43-9.48).

2. The Law of Primitive Survivals: When ((a mental function)) A


is modified into B there survives in any example of B. side by
side with the function B which is the modified form of A, an
element of A in its primitive or unmodified state. If A be
consciousness and B second-order consciousness or reflection,
then reflection is a modification of consciousness, and unless
there were a primitive survival of mere consciousness there
would be nothing to reflect on, and no reflection would occur.
(NL, 9.5, 9.51, 9.54).1

____________________________________________________________
1 Notice that in this summary of the principles stated in
Collingwood's "Retrospect" there is nothing to correspond with
Donagan's "Principle of Order"; in fact one might argue that
Collingwood's explicit statement that a series of mental
functions can coexist in a single act (NL, 9.48) essentially
conflicts with it. The best evidence that Donagan can cite in
support of his "Principle of Order" is NL, 5.91-5.92, which is
extracted from a discussion of Freud on whether feelings can be
unconscious (NL, 5.8), and is an account of the extent to which
Collingwood agrees with Freud's usage of the terms "conscious"
and "preconscious." Collingwood writes that "no man is conscious
of any given form of consciousness, even though it is operating
in him, until he 'reflects' on it or calls into being in himself
another form of consciousness, C2, the consciousness of C1'
((NL, 1.73)) the form of consciousness with which we started.
Any form of consciousness, practical or theoretical, call it Cx,
exists in what Freud calls a preconscious condition unless and
until it has been reflected upon by the operation of a form
Cx+l'' (NL, 5.915.92), cited by Donagan by references at LPC, 28
and 108). Notice that Collingwood says "form of consciousness."
Now compare this with Donagan's formulation of this subsidiary
principle, which he elevates into one of the four main pre
suppositions underlying
559

___________________________
Collingwood's entire philosophy of mind (LPC), 27): "if a man is
conscious of one of his own acts of consciousness, then it is
not by that act itself, but by another act of consciousness
which may be said to be of a higher order" (LPC, 28). Notice
that Donagan has substituted "act of consciousness" for "form of
consciousness." In our view this is not a legitimate
substitution; what may be true for a relation between forms or
whole orders of consciousness (first-order, second-order, etc.)
may not be true for individual acts of consciousness which may
be at the same level. On Donagan's "Principle of Order" it is
difficult if not impossible to see how there might be a concept
of a concept, or a proposition about a proposition, or inference
about inference; and certainly not without one of them being
reduced to pre-consciousness. But Donagan might have referred to
IH, 292, where Collingwood does say an act of thought may be an
object to another act but not to itself. This might lend support
to his "Principle of Order" were it not that Collingwood
explicitly denies it in the next sentence.
560

It takes no great interpretative powers to recognize that this

description of the relations of the series of mental functions

is a direct application of the "scale of forms" described in the

Essay on_Philosophical Method, and a fairly clear echo of the

description of the dialectical relations between the "forms of

experience" in Speculum Mentis. With this discussion of the

dialectical structure of mind as a scale of forms of mental

functions we find ourselves again confronting the relationship

between F-logic, with its abstract class-concepts, and D-logic

with its overlapping universals.34 From Table 12, 3 a-b, we see

that the abstract class-concept involved in second-order

attention and naming is the sort that is used in

classifying--the practical activity of "drawing the line"

between objects in a field of feeling (or presumably that field

as prepared by first-order consciousness). From Table 13 we see

that the

_______________________
34 It is interesting to note that Collingwood positions
this "retrospective" chapter in the midst of his analysis of the
level of mind he calls "conceptual thinking." Why did he place
it here and not after his chapters on propositional and rational
thinking (i.e. between Part I on Man and Part II on Society)? Is
it not because the "scale of forms" is a discussion of the
relations of concepts in D-logic, and he felt obliged to call
attention to the fact that the series of mental functions (and
notice that first-order consciousness, second-order
consciousness, etc. are concepts or "names" and not judgments,
propositions, or inferences) are dialectically related as a
scale of forms and not merely as abstract class-concepts?
561

level of mental function at which F-logical class-concepts

operate is a whole (i.e. taken as an order or form of

consciousness) related to other levels of mental functioning as

one element in a scale of forms, where each term is a

modification of the one before it, but contains a "primitive

survival" of that previous form.

Since Collingwood indicates that he is not restricting

his discussion to mind only in its capacity as philosophical

thinking, but rather states directly that he is talking about

"the modern European mind" or the mind of a European man (or

that which "has produced in itself the thing called modern

European civilization"),35 we may finally offer a general answer

to a long-standing question concerning the applicability of what

we have been calling the D-logic of the Essay on Philosophical

Method. Insofar as the several orders of functioning of the

human, civilized mind are arranged in a scale of forms, D-logic

is applicable to the relations between these levels. Since

Collingwood asserts in no

______________________
35 Presumably Collingwood would regard other civiliza-
tions (e.g. American and some Far Eastern countries) as exten-
sions of "the modern European mind," since in the later parts of
The New Leviathan he extends the term "civilization" to
include-any manifestation of civil behavior or what he calls
"civility" (NL, 35.63; cf. 34.4-34.51, 34.7-34.79, and 35.22-
35.44)--essentially, the approximation to the ideal of re-
fraining from the use of force in relations with one's fellow
man, and the spirit of agreement to teach and be taught (NL,
35.44, 36.46-36.51). Therefore whatever civilization strives for
such an ideal would be classifiable as possessing what
Collingwood is calling the "modern European mind," which is not
meant to be a primarily geographical epithet.
562

uncertain terms both in The Principles of Art and The New

Leviathan that the series of mental functions are so arranged,

he would not regard this assertion as a tautology (i.e. that

something having the structure of a scale of forms has the

logical relations of a scale of forms). It is what he would call

a universal categorical judgment (in this case, this means that

it is self-instantiating).

What we do not know is what Collingwood would accept as

adequate restrictive conditions for the applicability of D-logic

and F-logic respectively. That there are such restrictions is

evident from the recognition that within a given level of mental

functioning (e.g. propositional thinking) rules which would not

be applicable for the relationship between that global level and

its successor would be applicable for the elements within that

level. Propositional logic and grammatical rules do not employ

the rules of dialectical logic per se, and yet the former are

legitimate and applicable within certain levels of consciousness

(cf. NL, 11.35).

(3) But we are not yet finished with the issue of

"naming," and we must now come to terms with the major dif-

ference between the analysis of mind offered in The New Leviathan

and all his previous writings on the subject. The major focus of

this apparent reversal of opinion is what we may call the

"linguistic-abstraction" thesis, i.e. that at the second


563

level of consciousness and above (everything included by the

term "reflective consciousness") all thought is the result or

product of linguistic activity, and that all linguistic activity

is necessarily abstract.

We have already had to qualify a more radical version of

this thesis (viz. one which extends the linguistic-abstraction

thesis to all consciousness) by pointing out that at the level

of first-order consciousness there is a prereflective,

discursive, meaning-function, so that second order "naming" does

not create meaning ex nihilo, it identifies them by means of

denominating gestures of some sort (speech or the

like)--gestures that call attention (one's own as well as that

of one's audience) to some specifically meant feeling. Compared

to second-order selective attention, first order consciousness

is not a function in which one act is compared or contrasted

with another as a present one compared to one not present, or as

two presented feelings which are compared as what one means as

opposed to what one does not mean by a given expression. And we

have also had occasion to note that Collingwood's account of

language in The Principles of Art leads one to conclude that for

him all meaning is intentional, whereas all symbolic meaning is

both intentional and conventional. But in The New Leviathan we

find him adding that all meaningful language (i.e. speech) is

abstract, and so are also all the expressions of consciousness

which are founded on it.


564

At issue here is what appears to be a major reversal in

Collingwood's final estimate of the nature of thought. In

Speculum Mentis, it may be recalled, Collingwood made ab-

straction to be the ultimate source of all the errors that the

mind makes about itself, and consequently also about its

relation to the world: to abstract is to falsify (SM, 160, 288).

But in The New Leviathan abstraction is seemingly elevated to

the highest rank of thought: conceptual thinking and all thought

above it (viz. propositional and rational thinking) is

abstractive (NL, 7.63). In confronting this pair of claims it

appears that the only two alternatives are either total

scepticism concerning knowledge claims (if all abstraction is

falsification and all intellectual thinking is abstract, then

all intellectual thinking is falsification), or a complete

reversal in Collingwood's mature philosophy (rejection of the

claim that all abstraction is falsification). Since Collingwood

was steadfastly non-sceptical, the latter is the most obvious

alternative (cf. Donagan in Krausz, CEPC, 9-13).

But as we have seen several times over in the course of

our examination of Collingwood's philosophy, the easy and

obvious interpretation is not always the correct one. The

evidence we are confronted with is an apparent contradiction,

not a documented "repudiation"; and an escape from the con-

tradiction may be found, as in other such cases, by a careful

analysis of the meaning of the


565

mediating term--in this case, "abstraction." Our experience thus

far in interpreting Collingwood would support our anticipation

that the term is not being used univocally, and that it has a

layering of overlapping meanings not always specified

explicitly, but discernable from careful comparison of the

opposing uses of the term.

In Speculum Mentis a concept is called abstract if it is

used as a class-unifying term, and if it only defines membership

in the class on the basis of a specifying criterion (the

determining element) but leaves out of consideration all other

qualifying characteristics of the members themselves (the

indeterminate elements)--and this is the sense in which

Collingwood means that something is abstract if it is thought as

"separate" from its members and their individuating differences.

It is the unity of identity of a class "in spite of" (or

indifferent to) the differences of its members. "Physical

object", for example, includes rocks, fish, birds, men, planets,

stars, etc. indifferently, and laws governing the motion of

"physical objects" takes such a disparate and differently

organized group in their most general, generic aspect--as dead

things, pushed and pulled by mechanical forces. But a live bird

dropped from a leaning tower will not behave as a dead rock

dropped from the same height. But for the purpose of the

abstract statement of the law which governs the free fall of

physical objects, the differences between the


566

bird and the rock are ignored: the self-moving capacities

involved in the flight of a bird are not taken into account in

the law.

This is not to say that such a motion cannot be "ex-

plained" in a much more complicated treatment of this situation

(e.g. one which balances the forces exerted by the flying

activities of the bird, generated by biochemical energies

released and used by the mechanical movements of muscles and

bones, etc., against the forces of gravity); but the closer one

gets to an adequate explanation of the differences between the

linear downward acceleration of the rock and the curvilinear

deceleration of the bird, the closer one gets to taking into

account the specific differences between the "dead" rock and the

living bird--and thus approximating to the ideal of a

non-abstract or "concrete" universal, i.e. one in which

differences are essential.

But consider now Collingwood's use of the term "ab-

stract" in The New Leviathan--in this case in reference to

concepts:

The act of attending is not merely a doing something to


yourself, focusing your consciousness on a certain part of
the field and repressing . . . the rest; it is also a doing
something to the object: circumscribing it, drawing a line
between it and the rest of the field . . . . With the
delimiting of the patch or other selection . . goes the act
of evocative thinking: the act of arousing in yourself by
the work of thought feelings you do not find as "given" in
yourself. These I call evocations: they form a context
567

inseparable from any selection and are connected with it by


logical relations, logic being the science which studies
the structure of concepts or, which is the same thing, the
relations between them . . . . As not given but abstracted
from the given, a selection is a product of practical
consciousness; . . . ((it)) is nothing found, it is
something made . . . . A selection together with its
context of evocations is a concept (notion) or a number of
them. (NL, 7.3-7.39).

What sort of "concept" meets the description here given--the

"abstract concept" of Speculum Mentis or something closer to the

"concrete universal"? Is it not the latter that is thought to be

"inseparable" from the context from which it is selected and

bound to it by logical relations? And is it not the abstract

class-concept which is thought of as "separate" or "indifferent"

to its contextual circumstances?

It is possible, if a bit muddle-headed, to decide as an

interpretative comment on this passage that in The New Leviathan

Collingwood had broken with his earlier views on abstraction and

conceptualization, and then foolishly allowed himself to

backslide into "associationism" by defining a concept as "a

selection together with its context of evocations" --which is

associationism insofar as it confuses what is selected with the

concept by which it is selected (Donagan, LPC, 54-55). But this

is no different than assuming that all planetary motion is

circular and then inventing "epicycles" to explain away

retrograde orbits. Not only would the ordinary association

pyschologist not say that


568

a selection is connected with an evoked context by means of

logical relations which preside over the birth of a concept; he

would on the contrary tend to derive all logical relations from

the purely external and coincidental "constant conjunction"

between a selected item and another, and to reduce logical

relations to this constant conjunction.36 Quite the contrary, by

defining “concept" in the way he does, Collingwood is stating as

clearly as he can, without using the term (and hence avoiding

calling attention to its previous use by Bradley, Bosanquet, and

other idealists), that the concept he had in mind was one in

which a universal is bound to a context by logical relations of

necessity, or one to which differences are essential, or in

short the concrete universal.

But even if this were a "lapse" on Collingwood's part,

one would have several other similar regressions to explain in

his discussion of the

_____________________
36 Cf. Howard C. Warren, A History of Association Psy-
chology (New York, 1921), pp. 6-7: "All the writers belonging to
the association school admit the rise of ideas following
sensations, according to the same laws of association that hold
where the antecedent is an idea. Some go further and regard as a
form of association the simultaneous presence of two or more
sensations in consciousness, such as occurs in the act of
perception. Others merely assume a nexus in such experiences
without explicitly classing them as instances of association. On
the other hand, all agree in denying that one sensation can
bring up another sensation by association; it is generally
admitted that the rise of sensations depends on something
outside of consciousness, or at least on something apart from
the individual human experience.”
569

terms "abstract" and "abstraction" in The New Leviathan. In his

discussion of rational thinking, for example, he states that to

place an intention in a context of other intentions that afford

grounds for it (where "grounds" are taken as an intention from

which a consequence follows by necessity) is to make of that

intention an abstraction (NL, 14.32, 14.43). And what holds for

abstraction at the conceptual and rational levels also holds for

the proposition level: "An intention is made into an abstraction

by surrounding it with a context of other intentions; a proposi-

tion by surrounding it with a context of other propositions"

(NL, 14.44).37 Concepts, propositions, and intentions that are

bound by logical relations to contexts of other concepts,

propositions and intentions surely cannot be "abstract" in the

sense that Collingwood had condemned as falsification in

Speculum Mentis.

Unfortunately rejecting one erroneous interpretation of

these passages on abstraction does not mean that we have

successfully resolved all the interpretative difficulties, nor

that we can even be satisfied that we have understood (much less

confirmed) what Collingwood

___________________
37 Cf. IN, 130: "By a real abstraction I mean a real
phase in a real process, in itself, and apart from the subse-
quent phase to which it is leading . . . . Bud and leaf are thus
phases of one process, and the bud in itself is an abstraction
from that process, but an abstraction made by nature, which
everywhere works in this way through successive phases of the
process, doing one thing before it goes on to the next."
570

means by these dark sayings. We suspect that all of this has

something to do with what Collingwood called "real thinking" in

his correspondence with Ryle, as well as the "total imaginative

activity" and "language of total bodily gesture" in The

Principles of Art: all of these are various systematic wholes

presupposed by the elements or "element-types" that go to make

them up. But as with the earlier instances we found of these

systematic wholes, we do not know in anything more than a vague

and abstract way what the relations are between their elements,

how many such elements there are, if they are just variations of

a single form, etc.

In particular we do not know what the limits of de-

terminacy are for abstractions at any given intellectual level.

Collingwood tells us in The New Leviathan that abstractions (by

which we may understand him to mean the result of acts of

selective attention) (a) are determinate in some ways and in-

determinate in others (NL, 7.56, 10.16; cf. PA, 254); (b) are

always indeterminate--i.e. are never wholly determined (NL,

11.54); and (c) are essential for thought beyond the primary

level of consciousness (NL, 7.63).38 Unfortunately he also adds

that

_______________________
38 Cf. Mink, MHD, 108: "Now the characteristics of 'ab-
straction' which Collingwood refers to in different places are
three: selectivity, indeterminacy, and self-determination As a
process, abstraction is the activity of consciousness (also
called 'attention') directed on an object in such a way as to
spot-light some features of the object and neglect others;
571

(d) "abstractions are only second-order objects made by the mind

out of its immediate or first-order objects as naturally and as

unconsciously as bees make honey out of flowers" (NL, 7.67).

What can "naturally and unconsciously" mean here? Collingwood

would probably answer that we cannot know what an abstraction is

until we have made it, and then we can examine the product of

the practical activity which produced it, but only be engaging

in another conscious act (e.g. examining a concept by

formulating propositions about it, and therefore engaging in an

act of third-order consciousness). But isn't "selective

attention" a deliberate act of consciousness, and is it not

selective attention that is the very process by which

abstraction is achieved? How can it then be "unconsciously"

done? And if "classifying" is the practical activity of

consciousness involved

___________________
these features are thus 'abstracted' from the object, and they
can be named and themselves made the objects of other and
repeated acts of consciousness without the repeated presentation
of the object . . . . However because second-order objects have
been selectively abstracted from the totality of activity, they
are indeterminate in all respects except those by which they
have been constituted . . . . Finally, . . . the activity of
consciousness in abstracting is a free activity, determined by
nothing except . . . by itself in abstracting these features
rather than those from its object. . . . . ((But)) it might be
said that the very existence of a verbal language determines the
limits of abstraction: we can attend only to those
distinguishable features of experience for which we have names."
Mink fails to see any paradox in saying that abstraction can be
free and indeterminate and yet determined and limited by names
in language.
572

in "drawing the line" in abstraction, did he not tell us that

all classes are artifacts (NL, 19.22-19.35; see above, Table 12,

3 b)? How then can abstractions be make as "naturally . . . as

bees make honey"?

The difficulty that dogs Collingwood's heels is the same

as the difficulty that plagues any of the usual accounts of

abstraction: as a theory of how we arrive at concepts, it

appears to presuppose what it attempts to explain. Ordinarily

abstraction is described as a process of "leaving out" inci-

dental or extraneous elements in a field of what is being

attended to, until only what is "essential" remains, this being

the abstracted concept.39 Whether this "leaving out" be regarded

as extracting "form" from its original mixture with "matter," or

a process of "separating in knowledge what is inseparable in

fact," the essential act is still a negative or eliminative one

and this raises serious difficulties. What allows the process to

come to a halt at a certain point? Does this not presuppose that

one already has the concept by

____________________
39 Peter Geach, Mental Acts (London, 1957), p. 18: "I
shall use 'abstraction' as a name for the doctrine that a con-
cept is acquired by a process of singling out in attention some
one feature given in direct experience--abstracting it-and
ignoring the other features simultaneously given--abstracting
from them. The abstractionist would wish to maintain that all
acts of judgment are to be accounted for as exercises of
concepts got by abstraction . . . . My own view is that ab-
stractionism is wholly mistaken; that no concept at all is ac-
quired by the supposed process of abstraction."
573

comparison to which the one emerging from this eliminative

process is recognized as comparable and equivalent? And lacking

this prior concept, what is to stop the eliminative process at

anything short of pure nothingness? Do we not. have to

distinguish the selected item from the criterion by which it is

selected (Donagan, LPC, 54-55)? Or to press the juice out of the

matter-form metaphor, if we are "given" something in sensation

or feeling, do we not have to possess something by which we can

accept or apprehend or take hold of the gift?

The closest that Collingwood comes to meeting these

objections is when he engages in what appears to be a frankly

pragmatic maneuver. His basic response to the charge of elim-

inative abstractionism would be to point out that concepts are

not "found" (as naive empiricists might say), they are "made"

(as subjective idealists say), but only by an act. of practical

consciousness prior to theoretical consciousness, and based on

interest or practical concern with the object attended to (as

pragmatists modify idealism) (cf. NL, 7.22, 18.13).40 In taking

a basically pragmatic view of the purposive character of

concepts, Collingwood reaps the benefit

______________________
40 Cf. H. S. Thayer, Meaning and Action: A Critical
History of Pragmatism (New York, 156877 pp. 429-31; and Mink,
MHD, 7-8, 12, 111, 138. Collingwood would probably not be
flattered by the comparison with pragmatism, but in latter years
he appears to be less hostile to this line of thought: cf. IN,
300.
574

of the pragmatic maneuver, which is precisely to eliminate the

need to posit theoretical and fictitious extramental entities

with which the mind is supposed to conform, on intramental

entities with which it is supposed to be innately furnished. But

in contrast to the pragmatists Collingwood appears to be saying

that even though concepts are made for practical purposes, they

nonetheless have logical relations which preside over their

birth within their "context of evocations"; and he nowhere says

that such logical relations are matters of scientific expediency

or economic utility (cf. SM, 182).

This is as far as Collingwood takes us, and we must note

that it may put us down the road a bit from naive empiricism,

but it does not take us the whole way towards a satisfactory

account of abstraction. Saying that concepts are made does not

explain why a concept is well-tailored to the need--or why one

concept "works" while another does not. And we are still not

enlightened as to what these "logical relations" are that

preside over the birth of concepts (although we are told that

"resemblance" is one, and "contrast." and "comparison" are

others (cf. NL, 7.34-7.36), which bodes ill for our defense of

Collingwood against the charge of associationism).

But as we pursue the development of meaning through the

higher levels of consciousness, we shall try to watch for the

way in which a relatively indeterminate meaning is modified by

conceptual,
575

propositional, and rational thinking--or the way in which a

meaning becomes more determinate as it becomes more "abstract,"

just as in The Principles of Art the uninterpreted sensum

becomes reedy for interpretation by being perpetuated and

domesticated by imaginative consciousness, and finally fully

interpreted by acts of intellectual consciousness. We do not

know, on the basis of The Principles of Art and The New

Leviathan, if Collingwood would accept that there could be any

such thing as a concept that is totally determinate, but if

there could be it would not be something abstract, because

something abstract always has an element of indeterminacy (NL,

11.54).

Finally, we shall use the expression "real abstraction"

to refer to Collingwood's description of abstraction in The New

Leviathan, in order to distinguish it from other theories of

abstraction, including the "false abstraction" he condemned in

Speculum Mentis.41 By "real abstraction" we shall understand the

doctrine that abstraction is the process of consciousness by

which a selection is located in its "context of evocations," or

a proposition in a context of other propositions,

_________________________
41 There is an echo of Speculum Mentis in a later chap-
ter of The New Leviathan, where Collingwood writes: "Abstraction
is a necessary part of thought. In thinking of a process of
change you must think of its positive and negative elements in
abstraction from the process. False abstraction is the same
thing complicated by a falsehood, namely, that these two
opposite elements are mutually independent and hostile entities"
(NL, 26.18-26.19).
576

an intention in a context of other grounding intentions, etc.

Having little to go on from Collingwood's cryptic remarks about

this process, we cannot, except by employing inventive energies,

amplify this weak signal concerning abstraction into a more

articulate program for public broadcast. We are particularly

annoyed by the distortion in the original signal insofar as

relating a concept. or selection to other concepts or feelings,

a proposition to other propositions, etc. is not

straightforwardly the same process as subsuming concrete

instances under a universal, or relating a proposition to its

referrent, etc. We still have no adequate criteria for

distinguishing between the referring and meaning functions of

language and consciousness. But. even lacking such criteria for

this distinction we are still forced to recognize a significant

difference between the simple or "false" abstraction rejected in

Speculum Mentis, and the contextual or "real" abstraction

advocated in The New Leviathan.

(4) Collingwood also provides us with very few infor-

mative statements about what he means by "propositional think-

ing" in The New Leviathan. We are told (a) that it is at this

level that truth and error are distinguished; (b) that in

engaging in it we are involved in asking and answering

questions; (c) that asking questions implies contemplating al-

ternatives; (d) that the subject of a proposition is never a


577

first-order object, and (e) neither is the predicate, which is

always a concept. Since Collingwood's primary concern in The New

Leviathan is with the emotional and practical sides of this

level of thinking, it is not too surprising that the theoretical

aspects of this order of consciousness are somewhat neglected.

But for our purposes we cannot ignore it, and therefore we are

obliged to flesh-out this skeleton to the best of our ability.

The way this can be done is to make use of three clues

which he has provided for us: the discussion of the levels of

consciousness as a scale of forms in the "retrospective" chap-

ter; his discussion of "emotions of intellect" in The Principles

of Art; and the placement of both of these in the context of

language as expressive discourse. Making use of these three

clues we may reconstruct what we believe to be a modest version

of what he intended us to understand about this level of

consciousness.

If we begin with the "first stage of mental life" in

which a presented feeling is "apprehended" by a pre-reflective

act of first-order consciousness, the "Law of Primitive Sur-

vivals" allows us to conclude that the primitive act of "mean-

ing" that is involved (what he might have described in The

Principles of Art as a "sensum prepared for interpretation") is

preserved and modified by second-order consciousness


578

by its act of selective (abstractive) attention. In its modified

form, first-order meaning is a designated and named entity (the

first state of reflective consciousness, or what might be called

the first stage in the actual interpretation of a sensum). At

the propositional level meaning is again modified to include the

unity of meaning in an assertion, i.e. the unity of meaning of a

subject and its predicate, where both parts of the assertion are

assumed to be themselves meanings derived from second-order

consciousness. Hence the subject of a proposition or what it is

about is not merely an object as presented to first-order

consciousness, but that object as modified by first- and

second-order consciousness, and now further determined as the

subject of a third-order propositional act.42

__________________________
42 To the great dismay of the reader of The New Le-
viathan, Collingwood is not always as careful as he might be to
indicate exactly what he means when he uses terms like "object"
in "object of consciousness." In the present instance concerning
propositional thought, this leads to considerable unnecessary
confusion. (a) Collingwood first described each level of
reflective consciousness as being conscious of its immediately
lower form, so that first-order consciousness, C1, is the
"object" of second-order consciousness, C2, just as C2 is to C3,
etc. (NL, 1.73, 5.91). Furthermore, (b) he defined "first-order
object" and "second-order object" in purely relative terms, so
that C1 is a "first-order object" to C2, as C2 is to C3; and C1
is a "second-order object" to C3 (NL, 5.26, 5.91); and (c) he
defined the terms "mediation" and "abstraction" (in one of its
senses) in terms of this relative schema, insofar as the
consciousness of a second-order object is mediated by the
consciousness of a first-order object (NL, 6.31-6.34). But then
he muddies the waters when he discusses each successive level of
consciousness. (d) At the level of second-order (conceptual)
consciousness he says that feeling is not an abstraction from
the name of the feeling (NL, 6.35). (e) At the level of
third-order (propositional) consciousness he states that the
subject and the predicate of a proposition are never first-order
objects,
579
_________________________
the predicate (at least) always being a concept. And (f) for
fourth-order (rational) consciousness, first-order objects are
things about which questions beginning "why" must not be asked,
since questions beginning "why" are legitimately asked only
about objects of the second and higher orders, or abstractions
(NL, 14.39). In each of the cases (d) through (f) Collingwood
seems to be saying that the immediately lower level of
consciousness is not the immediate or first-order object to its
successor-which-contradicts (a). Driven by such paradoxical
statements the reader may not be blamed for deciding that
Collingwood is making one of his unannounced shifts of meaning
between his defined, relative sense of the terms "first- and
second-order objects" (b), and what we may call (g) the absolute
sense of these terms, i.e. the sense in which a "first-order
object" would be the object of first-order consciousness, a
"second-order object" for second-order consciousness, etc. But
even if the absolute sense of these terms may make passing sense
of several confusing passages (e.g. the misleading examples
offered at NL, 11.34), we think it would be a mistake. A better
interpretation, in our estimation, would be to recall that in
The Principles of Art Collingwood told us that consciousness has
a double object, both of which are "present" to the conscious
mind (PA, 206). Thus it is possible that a form of
consciousness, say C3 (propositional thinking) may be conscious
both of a lower form C2 (conceptual thinking) and of what he is
calling its "first-order object"--in this case a proposition.
Thus when he writes that the subject of a proposition is never a
first-order object, the reason is that the first-order object of
an act of propositional thought is a whole proposition, and not
its subject. The subject of a proposition is, like the
predicate, a concept, the product of a practical act of
second-order consciousness, and hence a second-order object for
third-order (propositional) consciousness. Finally, it is
important to point out once again that there is a difference
between a "form of consciousness" like propositional thought,
and an "act of consciousness," like the practical act of putting
together a particular sentence. Having said all this, honesty
requires that we admit that we find difficulties on any
interpretation of these difficult passages from The New
Leviathan; e.g. if we invoke the principle of the double object
of consciousness, both of which are present to it, then we are
faced with difficulties in understanding not only what
"abstraction" means (e.g. at NL, 14.214.27) but also our earlier
use of the "double object of consciousness" principle to account
for the radical linguistic claim that naming a feeling makes us
directly conscious of the feeling. If it is possible for a
higher-order consciousness (say C3 to be directly and
immediately conscious not only of
580

On this line of thinking a sentence would be the expression of

the unity of meaning of an act of propositional thought, and

truth and falsity apply minimally to this level of propositional

meaning.

Unfortunately this leaves us without any way to account

for the presence of questions at this level, since questions do

not assert a predicate of a subject, nor are they true or false.

But if questions are interrogative sentences and have something

of a subject-predicate form, should they not belong to the level

of propositional thought? Here we must take up our second clue

from The Principles of Art. Just as we found that there are

broader and narrower senses of the terms "thought" and

"language" for Collingwood, so also we are now obliged to

recognize broader and narrower senses for the terms "truth" and

"falsity," the narrower sense being confined to the level of

propositional thinking and those above it, and the broader sense

extending not only to the level of conceptual thought

(second-order consciousness) but even to the first stage of

mental life, "apprehension" or simple attention. And here we

note that Collingwood not only breaks with the traditional logic

on the subject of truth and falsity, but even from his own

earlier doctrine in Speculum

___________________________
its own object (for C3, propositions), but also of a lower level
of consciousness and its object (C2 and its concepts), then how
can there be a second-order objects (abstractions) at all?
581

Mentis that art as imaginative expression has nothing to do with

truth (or is "indifferent" to the distinction between truth and

falsehood):

This utterance ((of an artist)), so far from being in-


different to the distinction between truth and falsehood,
is necessarily an attempt to state the truth . . . . Now,
if any one thinks . . . that intellect is the only possible
form of thought, he will think that whatever does not
contain arguments cannot be a form of thought, and there-
fore cannot be concerned with truth. Observing that art
does not argue, he will infer that art has nothing to do
with the truth . . . . It is hardly worth while to refute
this argument, by pointing out that truthfulness about
one's emotions is still truthfulness. . . . Art is not in-
different to truth; it is essentially the pursuit of truth.
But the truth it pursues is not a truth of relation, it is
a truth of individual fact. The truths art discovers are
those single and self-contained individualities which from
the intellectual point of view become the "terms" between
which it is the business of intellect to establish or
apprehend relations. Each of these individualities, as art
discovers it, is a perfectly concrete individual, one from
which nothing has yet been abstracted by the work of
intellect. Each is an experience in which the distinction
between what is due to myself and what is due to my world
has not yet been made. (PA, 28788).

In a footnote to this passage Collingwood adds that "I am not so

much criticizing anybody else, as doing penance for youthful

follies of my own," and informs the reader to see his Outline of

a Philosophy of Art and Speculum Mentis.

Now even bearing in mind that in The New Leviathan

Collingwood distinguishes between "linguistic activity in

general" and "literature or poetry or in general art" (NL,

6.29), where the latter is conscious not only of names for

feelings but of the act of naming


582

them, we are still obliged to recognize that there is a

legitimate extension of the term "truth" below the level of

propositional consciousness. If we recall his discussion of

"corrupt consciousness" at this point it is not difficult to see

that "truthfulness" at the first level of consciousness consists

of apprehending feelings as one's own, rather than "disowning"

them, the habit of which is the corruption of consciousness. At

the second level of consciousness, at which "naming" occurs,

truth is conceptual but non-relational; it is concerned with

"the 'terms' between which it is the business of intellect to

establish or apprehend relations. If truth has, as it appears

from The Principles of Art, the structure of a scale of forms,

then we may say that truth, like meaning, appears in the

expression of all higher-order functions of consciousness, so

that there are pre-reflective, conceptual, propositional and

rational truths.

But then what sort of a "truth" does a question have? We

suspect that it is something between the fully propositional and

conceptual levels of truth, but here we are forced to engage in

a bit of reconstructive speculation. Collingwood tells us that

"real" questions are those which offer alternatives, and "bogus"

questions are those which do not; he also tells us that

scientific method depends on replacing unanswerable vague or

confused questions with real questions which can have a precise

answer (NL, 11.12). The "real-bogus" distinction for questions

is something
583

like the "true-false" distinction for propositions, but with

obvious differences which Collingwood does not specify.

"Offering alternatives" is something that propositions may do as

well as questions, but the proposition "X is either Y or Z"

expresses something quite different than the question "Is X Y or

is it Z?" The alternatives offered in a question are not offered

as affirmatively or negatively stated, but rather as

alternatives demanding or requesting or looking forward to some

further linguistic or mental act which chooses between

them--something that will satisfy the question or complete it in

a propositional sense. With a question one is conscious of the

fact. that something is being left unresolved, and a completing

act is being called for.

But just as propositions, like "real" questions, may

offer alternatives,43 so also propositions may be incomplete or

call for resolution: "Eric is going to . . ." is an incomplete

sentence, since the proposition "(x) is going to(y)" contains a

predicate which calls for

_______________________
43 What Collingwood also desperately needs to make sense
of questions, but steadfastly refuses to provide, is some sort
of categorial schema, or categorial designators, to set the
limits of sense and nonsense for alternatives at the
propositional level. "Which of the following two alternatives is
true, A, B. or C?" is a nonsense question, as is "What sort of
train is this, red, yesterday, or singing 'Celeste Aida'?" but.
not for the same reasons. Both appear to be well-formed
interrogative English sentences, but the alternatives offered in
the first case conflict with the conditions presupposed by the
question, and in the latter case conflict with categorial schema
ordinarily presupposed in ordinary English usage.
584

the presence of some value for the second variable (y) in order

to make sense of the whole propositional sentence. But an

incomplete sentence is not a question--it may merely be a

sentence fragment. An incomplete sentence does not express the

speaker's intention to put an interrogative sentence. What is

required is some syntactic and/or semantic function which allows

the incomplete proposition to be a completed interrogative

sentence, so that a hearer (who may be the speaker himself) may

know that completion is not only lacking but known to be

lacking--i.e. that he has expressed his intended meaning in the

form of a question. In a natural language like English such

completing interrogative functions are available either by the

use of "token" pronouns (who, what, how, when, whether, etc.) or

by alternations in word order, as when we put a verb in the

first position in a sentence ("Is x y?" "Does x y?" "Can x y?"

etc.)44

_________________________
44 There may ultimately be no foolproof way of desig-
nating linguistic structures which unequivocally indicate a
questioning intention. "What fools are these mortals?" does not
require an answer, and neither does "How many have fallen in
this battle" when uttered in a circumstance which makes it clear
that no answer is being sought (e.g. in a funeral oration).
Furthermore a questioning intention may be indicated by nothing
more than an alteration in tone of voice, or by stressing
certain words or syllables: "These apples are fifty cents each?"
Of course we have no way of knowing, but it may be
considerations like these that inclined Collingwood to emphasize
questioning as an intentional or conscious act rather than a
linguistic entity in his Q-A logic.
585

Although such considerations as these are essential to

the description of interrogative sentences in a language (which

some may find to be a more fruitful line of inquiry),

Collingwood would probably relegate it to the "grammatical

analysis of language" about which he had such unflattering

things to say in The Principles of Art. That his concern was not

in this direction is indicated by the fact that he says nothing

about such syntactical and semantical requirements in any of his

writings. His interest was in what we might call the heuristic

aspect of questioning as an intellectual function of

consciousness. In this respect his main concern was to show that

questions have not only a logical relation to assertions,

presuppositions, and other questions in a systematic inquiry

(explored by Q-A logic) but that the reason questions can stand

in such logical relations is that they are expressions of a

certain level of consciousness, and therefore "constituents" of

mind, achievements of thinking agents, and part of the emotional

life of persons.

Therefore when he says that "real" questions are those

which offer alternatives, this is not the entire story. A "real"

question is also a "truthful" question which truly expresses the

intellectual emotions of a conscious agent--emotions like

curiousity, wonder, interest, etc.; the emotions of inquiry. A

question therefore stands not as an atomic entity, but in a

multiplicity of relations--logical, epistemological, emotional,


586

and perhaps others. Its "truth" or truthfulness is a complex

function depending on which context it is seen to belong in. Q-A

logic is an exploration of questions in the context of other

questions, presuppositions, and answers as employed in

systematic inquiry. The requirement of offering alternatives

therefore merely states what a question must be to be fully

determinate at the level of propositional thought--i.e. for a

question regarded as an epistemological entity. Other

requirements may appear from the grammatical analysis of

language, and still more from the logical analysis of language,

the latter governed by the rules which preside (to extend

Collingwood's metaphor) over the birth of questions and

propositions by selection from a context of propositional

evocations--P-Q-A complexes bound together in a systematic

inquiry.45 (Cf. NL, 4.3-4.36).

(5) If this reconstruction of Collingwood's intended

analysis of third-order consciousness is correct, there is

nothing to prevent us from extending it to fourth-order con-

sciousness as well. By the "Law of Primitive Survivals" meaning

survives even at the level of rational discourse, but at this

level the meaning-seeking function of consciousness

______________________
45 In Q-AM Collingwood is careful to point out that in
scientific inquiry when a question is answered it does not cease
to be a question, but only an unanswered question (EM, 24; see
above, Table 9, Comment 4). We might add here that an
intellectual emotion expressed in a question does not cease to
be an emotion once the question is answered, but rather ceases
only to be an unsatisfied emotion.
587

is transformed into a unifying act in which one propositional

meaning is related to another as ground to consequent--i.e.

validity in inference. And since questioning survives at this

level also, the questioning function at the level of rational

discourse is the expression of the anticipation of meaning

fulfillment in a validity relationship, i.e. that one

propositional meaning actually will be related to another as

ground and consequent.

Fortunately we do not have to rely quite so heavily on

our own reconstruction at this level, since Collingwood provides

us with a few more informative remarks than he does for

propositional thinking. Even a cursory reading of his discussion

(Table 12, 5) makes clear that Collingwood is not reducing

rational discourse to the F-logical functions of implication: it

is not a "truth-functional" relation that exists between

propositional forms that he is concerned with, but rather the

reason or reasons for thinking that something is the case or

that something should be done--i.e. intentional inference rather

than strictly formal implication. Collingwood unmistakably makes

the point when he insists that "reason is always essentially

practical; because to be reasonable means to be interested in

questions beginning with 'why'; and this happens because people

crave reassurance against the


588

fallibility of their knowledge" (NL, 14.31).46

But how do we know when one proposition or

intention is the ground for another, or that one is a

consequence of the other? Collingwood's answer brings us once

again before his idiosyncratic usage of "abstraction." "One

intention supporting another both form part of the same

intention, which includes them both, and perhaps other things"

(NL, 14.4). The relation of ground to consequent for Collingwood

therefore appears to be the relation of part to whole, and is a

relation

___________________
46 In the passage just proceeding the one cited Collingwood
asserts that "first-order objects are things about which
questions beginning 'why?' must not be asked," since "such
questions are legitimately asked only about objects of the se-
cond and higher orders (abstractions)" (NL, 14.39). Once again
we are up against the application of his "Fallacy of Misplaced
Argument" (NL, 4.73) which forbids us from arguing about any
object immediately given to consciousness. Unless we bear in
mind that the "first-order object" of fourth-order (rational)
consciousness is a complex intention or proposition containing
at least two intentions or propositions, one being the ground
and the other its consequent, the proscription about
why-questions seems paradoxical; since fourth-order con-
sciousness is reflection on third-order (propositional) con-
sciousness, it seems that it would be perfectly legitimate to
ask why-questions concerning first-order objects of this sort
--e.g. "Why should I mow the lawn?" is a question about the
proposition "I should mow the lawn." But a proposition is a
first-order object for third-order consciousness, and a second-
order object for fourth-order consciousness, so the rule holds.
But notice that the "objects of the second and higher orders"
puts "abstraction" in a downward occurring attitude ("higher"
merely indicating the numerical ordinals for orders of conscious
objects--second-order object, third, etc.). For fourth-order
consciousness, therefore, a proposition is an abstraction from
(or second-order object to) its first-order object, which is a
ground-consequent complex proposition, just as for third-order
consciousness a concept is an abstraction from its first-order
object, a (simple) proposition. (Cf. NL, 7.67).
589

of inclusion (cf. NL, 14.41). To demand confirmation of a

larger, inclusive intention or proposition would be, he says,

"to place it in a context of other intentions or other pro-

positions that might afford grounds for it; that is, to reduce

it to the level of an abstraction," or in other words, "to make

it an abstraction" (NL, 14.43). It would be, to extend the

terminology drawn from the level of conceptual thinking, to

place an intention or proposition in a "context of evocations"

of other grounding intentions or propositions within which it is

included and to which it is related as part to whole.

And here once again we touch on not only what Colling-

wood had called, in his correspondence with Ryle, "real think-

ing," in any example of which would be included all the

"element-types" on which logical relations are founded, but also

the pragmatic aspect we have already noticed in his analysis of

the functions of mind (e.g. when concepts are "made" by an act

of practical consciousness). For fourth-order consciousness both

of these features are brought into play in a chapter on

"Theoretical Reason":

In all forms of rational thinking a distinction is made


between the self and the not-self. Such thinking is pri-
marily practical; its first function is to ask and answer
the question: "Why am I doing this?" It has, however, a
secondary function, to ask and answer questions about what
is not myself. These may be called "theoretical" questions;
but they are never purely theoretical . . . . They arise
out of practical problems concerning the self and other
things . . .
590

Consider the place of experiment in natural science. An


experiment means an interference by a natural scientist
with some process of nature. The "experimental method" in
natural science is the method wherein a scientist comes to
understand a natural process by interfering with it . . . .
Is there nowhere such a thing as "purely theoretical
thinking"? There is; but it is not real thinking, and it.
does not lead to real knowing . . . . Real thinking is
always to some extent experimental in its method; it always
starts from practice and returns to practice; for it is
based on "interest" in the thing thought about; that is, on
a practical concern with it . . . . A man will have a
different theoretical attitude towards things other than
himself according as his practical attitude towards them is
different; and his practical attitude towards them will be
different according to differences in his attitude towards
his own actions. (NL, 18.1-18.2).

There are many avenues to explore in this extremely interesting

passage and the chapter from which it is drawn--e.g. the

"experimental" aspect to all rational thought and its aspect of

"interference," which reminds us of his remark from the

Autobiography concerning his interest in "obscure provinces"

because of the challenge to invent new methods for studying them

(A, 86). But we wish to note here that we have a new dimension

to add to the logical aspect of "real thinking" that Collingwood

had divulged in his letter to Ryle: in addition to (a)

containing in any example of itself all the "element-types" on

which logical relations are founded, real thinking (b) is always

to some extent experimental in its method, (c) starts from

practice and returns to practice, and (d) is based on interest

or practical concern with the thing thought about. Furthermore

one can dimly discern that (e) it depends on differences in

"attitude" towards
591

--such differences as are involved in the three different ways

that a modern European answers the question, "Why am I doing

this?"--viz. because it is useful, right, or my duty (NL,

14.65-14.69). Since each of these gives rise to a particular

world view (utilitarian thinking giving rise to teleological

Greek science, regularian thinking to classical modern science

with its laws of nature, and duty to historical consciousness

and its transformation of contemporary science (NL, 18.318.92),

it is not difficult to see that such "attitudes" are what

Collingwood calls "absolute presuppositions" in the Essay on

Metaphysics.

Since this gets us beyond logic and into Collingwood's

views on metaphysics, we must stop at this point, with the

promise that w% shall resume the discussion in Chapter X, where

we shall do our best to clarify these views. But we must. make

one final remark before bringing this section, and chapter, to a

close. We wish to call attention to the fact that. questioning

functions at both the third- and fourth-order levels of

consciousness, and that at the fourth level (as might be

expected, given the Law of Contingency for mental functions) it

becomes a why-question which presupposes both that there is a

level of propositional thinking (and all that this presupposes),

and also that there is a relation of ground to consequent that

can be established for propositions within this level. This is

an important observation for any one's own actions


592

evaluation of Q-A logic, since questioning traverses the dis-

tinction between simple propositions (minimal units of truth and

falsity in the narrower sense) and complex propositions

(propositions related by logical connectives, and minimal units

of truth-functional validity).

6. Conclusion.

We have come a long way since initiating our discussion

of Q-A logic at the beginning of this chapter, and it is now

time to try to pull the strands of our investigation together.

Unfortunately to try to summarize further what is already a

summary would be to virtually repeat the chapter, so instead we

shall limit our remarks to several observations on what we think

are the more important central features of Collingwood's

discussion of logic.

(1) In the introductory section we recalled the work of

previous chapters in which we showed that Q-A logic is re-

cognized not only by Collingwood but also by his principal

interpreters to be one of the major features of his overall

philosophical outlook. This is explicitly stated by Collingwood

in his Autobiography, and in subsequent interpretation of his

thought one of the major controversies concerning his philosophy

concerns the role of absolute presuppositions in metaphysics

--presuppositions being part of the unique P-Q-A complex defined

in Q-A logic.
593

We also recalled that in previous chapters we found that

although in the Autobiography Collingwood presented Q-A logic as

an alternative to F-logic and fails to mention D-logic at all,

his early writings contrast F-logic not with Q-A logic but with

D-logic. In this chapter we proposed to examine the later

writings to see not only if there is evidence supporting Q-A

logic as described in the Autobiography, but also to find

whatever enlightenment we could about the relationship between

these three logics in Collingwood's philosophy.

(2) When we took a close look at Q-A logic as it appears

in the Essay on Metaphysics (Q-AM) we noticed that the P-Q-A

complex remained central to his observations about logic, and

that the elements of this complex retained a logical

relationship to each other that is not merely reducible to a

relationship of mere co-location in subjective consciousness.

However we noticed also that there were several differences

between Q-AA and Q-AM, the most notable being the fact that Q-AA

described the Q-A complex (or perhaps that complex as extended

to include presuppositions, since every question has at least

one presupposition) is the unit of meaning, truth, and validity,

but in Q-AM meaning and validity are not discussed, and truth or

falsity is assigned primarily to propositions (a point which

seems to directly contradict Q-AA, which denies that truth or

falsity is a property of propositions as such).


594

Using this shift as a starting point for our subsequent

investigation, we set out to examine the extent to which Q-A

logic in either of its versions could meet the Q-AA claim to be

an alternative to F-logic. We found that when analyzed with this

claim in mind, far from being an alternative to F-logic, Q-A

logic seems on the contrary to presuppose it, or to presuppose

whatever F-logic presupposes; meaning, truth, and validity are

establishable independently of the P-Q-A complex, and this

independence is a necessary condition for deciding what counts

for something to be a meaningful element in that complex, what

can be true or false in it, and whether its elements are related

in a valid or invalid way. Since from a logical point of view

meaning is minimally a function of terms, truth a function of

propositions, and validity a function of complex propositions

linked by logical connectives, we deemed it unlikely that the

P-Q-A complex could minimally meet the specifications of all

three as Q-AA claimed it could. Furthermore Q-A logic fails to

sustain itself as a systematic structure (at least in its Q-AA

and Q-AM versions) since it fails to meet the requirements for

such a system--viz. consistency, completeness, and formality.

But if Q-A logic fails as an alternative to F-logic, and

can never hope to replace it as Collingwood proposes it, we find

that it has
595

nevertheless a unique logical structure of its own, something we

barely began to explore rather than conclusively demonstrated.

Since Collingwood recognized at least a significant part of this

structure (the central P-Q-A complex, the non-deductive

relationship existing between presuppositions and their

questions and answers, etc.) we speculated that perhaps the

comparison with F-logic was misleading, and that he had a

different intention in mind in describing it as an alternative

logic. Since so much of it is described in epistemological

terms, we proposed to explore Q-A logic in its relationship to

mental acts as described in his later philosophy of mind--the

three acts involved in grasping the meaning of terms, the truth

or falsity of propositions, and the validity of inferences.

(3) The first step in this direction was the examination

of D-logic as explicated in the Essay on Philosophical

Method--which in its format suggested itself to us as a better

candidate than Q-A logic for being an alternative to F-logic. We

found that the Essay described characteristics of the

philosophical concept, judgment, and inference vis-a-vis the

non-philosophical concept, judgment and inference, and in so

doing it described the structure of a D-logic as opposed to what

we recognized to be an F-logic of an Aristotelean pedigree. With

its overlapping classes, related in a scale of forms in which

there is a "fusion" of differences of degree, differences of

kind, relations of
596

opposition and relations of distinction, the philosophical

concept of universal differs from the class-concept employed by

"exact and empirical sciences," or from that concept in its non-

or prephilosophical employment. We noted that Collingwood makes

a point of not stating this distinction in a way which excludes

alternative presence of concepts which meet D-logical require-

ments, e.g. scalar overlap: concepts with such a structure ap-

pear in ordinary experience as well as exceptionally in science.

So also with philosophical judgments which, like those of

science, are universal, but are also "categorical" (or have

objective reference) rather than being merely hypothetical, and

inferences, which are "reversible" rather than being merely

deductive or inductive.

Unfortunately we found several obstacles in the way of

understanding Collingwood's discussion of universal categorical

judgments and reversible inferences, and as an aid to

understanding the views of the Essay on these matters we turned

to the letters between Collingwood and Ryle on the subject of

logic, and made some remarkable discoveries. We found

Collingwood confessing to a view of logic that sets it in a

frankly epistemological context, so that the deductive struc-

tures of F-logic are dependent upon or presuppose what he calls

"real thinking," in any example of which is contained all the

"element-types" of logical relations explored by F-logic, and

which the class-concepts of F-logic presuppose.


597

In the Essay and the ensuing correspondence with Ryle, then, we

found Collingwood arguing in something of the fashion of a

later-day Kantian, defending "transcendental deduction" in

arguments, judgments that are synthetic and a priori without

being merely hypothetically true, and universal concepts that

appear to be similar to Kant's schematized categories.

Noting that to pursue this discussion further would take

us into Collingwood's views on metaphysics, we observed that the

argument of the Essay culminates in a crucial chapter on

philosophical inference, which maintains that philosophical

arguments can be reversible without being viciously circular--a

view which puts great pressure on the assertion that philosophy

is a "self-justifying" enterprise. But this is only possible

insofar as the conclusions of philosophy are "established" by an

experience that anticipates them beforehand, so that the

anticipating experience establishes the principles used to draw

such conclusions, and the principles reciprocally "establish"

the conclusions. The non-circularity of philosophical inference

depends on the fact that the "establishing" of conclusions by

principles is done by a higher form of thinking, one for which

the lower states of thinking are "experience" to its

"conclusion." Philosophy (which must be one form of what he had

called "real thinking" in his correspondence with Ryle)

presupposes that experience is already somewhat systematic, and

it is only because of this


598

that its arguments (and the argument of the Essay as a whole)

escapes vacuous circularity.

Furthermore we noticed that although D-logic in the

Essay has the appearance of meeting the systematic requirements

of F-logic for consistency, and completeness (discussed in the

Essay under the rubric of "system") but not formality, the

claims of consistency and completeness are premissed on

Collingwood's providing convincing and unambiguous instances of

D-logical analysis. And once again we noted that D-logic, just

as had Q-A logic (and we can now say, on the strength of the

Essay and the Collingwood-Ryle correspondence, F-logic as well)

depends on a full-blown epistemology which is not provided by

the Essay itself. This we proposed to examine in the next two

sections in connection with the higher functions of

consciousness in the philosophy of mind as discussed in The

Principles of Art and The New Leviathan.

(4) Taking up The Principles of Art first, we noted that

in his discussion of levels of consciousness, the function of

expression is minimally essential, and language, discourse, and

the grammatical and logical analysis of language are all located

on a "scale of forms" of expression. Now although there is

nothing in The Principles of Art that could pass for a

thoroughgoing examination of the relation of language and logic,

and although the higher regions of intellectual consciousness

remain in this work largely unexplored, we found that defining

language
599

by means of a scale of forms of expression has important

consequences for Collingwood's view of logic.

The first of these consequences is that Collingwood

insists that the minimum specification of the genus, i.e. ex-

pression of emotion, is never entirely lost when it reaches the

level of symbolic language. Unfortunately Collingwood does not

support this point with convincing evidence or argument, and

does not develop it very far. But we recognize that Collingwood

struck a rich vein when he proposed that there are "emotions of

intellect" which are expressed by intellectualized

language--emotions which we recognized (through his example of

Archimedes--improbably as he stated it) to be those involved in

intellectual activities involved in the process of discovery,

for example--emotions like curiousity, interest, wonder, etc.

And we suggested that the "anticipation" of answers in question

is an expression of an intellectual emotion, but that this also

remains unspecified by Collingwood. Even though this theme

remains undeveloped in his writings, we noted that even at the

highest level of language (which would have to include the

grammatical analysis and F-logical extension of language) it

retains its continuity with the emotional life of a conscious

agent--a thesis which appears to run directly counter to the

formalistic claims to autonomy by most contemporary logicians.


600

We also examined several other secondary consequences of

defining language within a scale of forms of expressiveness. One

is the location of the grammatical and logical analysis of

language in a context which renders the more extreme forms of

their claims less credible. The belief that language is a

completed "thing" which can be sustaining pieces (words,

phrases, sentences, etc.)i.e. the assumption made in the

"grammatical analysis of language,” is a mythical claim that is

discredited when it is recognized that the "language of total

bodily gesture" escapes grammatical reduction to lexicographical

entries and grammatical rules. Similarly the "logical analysis

of language" relies on certain presuppositions (the

propositional assumption, the principle of homolingual

translation, and the principle of logical preferability), which

may suit the logician's purpose to transform language into a

perfect vehicle for the expression of thought, but must be

recognized as actually a proposal for the modification of

language rather than a statement of what language actually is.

In this context F-logic appears in the guise of what might be

called today an "ideal language" constructed for the purpose of

modifying a natural language to rule out the frustrations of its

obstructing and misleading meanings.

Finally, we noticed that there is a global or compre-

hensive aspect to each level of the scale of forms of expression

as Collingwood describes
601

it in The Principles of Art, so that each has its own principle

of organization which is presupposed by its successor on the

scale. We saw a connection between this global or summarizing

aspect. and what. he had called the "logical structure of real

thinking" in his correspondence with Ryle, as well as with the

"total imaginative activity" he discussed in connection with the

mental life of the artist--in each of which there is a

"whole-part." dialectical relationship. We suggested that

perhaps logic is a systematic study of the relations existing

within a given level of this scale, so that there is a logic of

concepts, propositions, and inferences, which is nonetheless

distinct from the logic of the overall relationships between

these levels themselves --the former explored by F-logic, the

latter by D-logic. (In a later section we noted that Q-A logic

may transect both F-logic and D-logic--but about this

Collingwood says nothing.)

(5) The last phase of our examination of Collingwood's

views on logic brought us to The New Leviathan, where we pursued

the relationship between language and logic into Collingwood's

analysis of the levels of mental functions. In so doing we found

that here too a "scale of forms" appears in which various orders

of consciousness are related in the manner that the forms of

expressiveness had been in The Principles of Art, and the

division of these levels (conceptual, propositional, and

rational
602

thinking) parallels the division of the subject-matter in the

Essay on Philosophical Method. Logic, language, and

consciousness appeared, therefore, each to have a parallel

structure that meets the D-logical description of a "scale of

overlapping forms" described in the Essay.

But we also found certain obstacles and peculiarities

which make an exact parallel problematic. The most noteworthy of

these obstacles is what we called the radical linguistic

thesis--that from the level of conceptual thought and above all

thinking is a linguistic function, so that language determines

thought and not vice versa. Some of the more glaring

contradictions on this issue between the assertions of The New

Leviathan and his previous writings can be cleared up, we found,

by careful attention to functions of consciousness which are

more fully described in his earlier writings--e.g. the function

of first-order consciousness in "apprehending" or "appreciating"

feelings before naming or classifying them. Still other

discrepancies concerning language are similarly softened by

attention to broader and narrower senses of terms like

"language," "thought," "knowledge," etc., each of which appears

at various levels in a scale of forms in which it appears. In

passing we noted that even "truth" and "meaning" are defined by

scales of forms, and consequently some of the apparent

discrepancy between Q-AA and Q-AM can be cleared up by

recognizing that there is "truth" even in concepts, so that it

is the narrower sense of the term that applies to proposi-


603

tions alone (as in Q-AM); and there is some sense even in the

Q-AA assignment of meaning and truth to Q-A complexes (for even

questions have their "truthfulness").

Other problems are less easily resolved, and in dis-

cussing them we found several novel concepts in The New Leviathan

which are revealing, but remain, like some other themes we have

turned up on this chapter, undeveloped. Two of these were (a)

the relationship between what we called prereflective "meanings"

at the level of first-order consciousness, and the function of

naming at the second level; and (b) the paradoxical notion which

we took the liberty of calling real (or concrete) abstraction

which appears at the second and all higher levels of

consciousness. What emerges from this discussion is an

idiosyncratic but interesting view of the relationship between

the various levels of consciousness which his "Retrospect"

chapter explicitly relates to the D-logical structure of a scale

of overlapping forms. Therefore rather than "repudiating" his

earlier views on the subject of thinking, consciousness, and

abstraction in Speculum Mentis (as Donagan maintains) we find

that much of his later work is an expansion and further

examination of the dialectical views expressed in that earlier

work (as Rubinoff and Mink have argued). Everywhere we find

D-logical structures and arguments, and everywhere we find

Collingwood pointing out the limitations of an abstract,

class-concept oriented F-logic in the analysis of language and

conscious mental acts.


604

Even his discussion of the linguistic aspect of the analysis of

mind is the development of a hint we found him (in Chapter VI)

making as early as Speculum Mentis, where philosophy is viewed

as "translation" into a language where error is not eliminated,

but reduced by recognizing the metaphorical nature of language.

But in the final reckoning, what can we say about the

autobiographical interpretation on the issue of Q-A logic? We

have found much that supports Collingwood's claim that from an

early date he argued that Q-A logic is a necessary antidote to

the tendency of realists to interpret everything in the

F-logical terms of what he calls the abstract class concept, and

in this sense he sought even in his later writings to defend an

"alternative" point of view, one which employed the principles

of Q-A logic with its characteristic P-Q-A complex. But we have

also found that he modified his logic as he developed his

thinking, and the guiding principles shaping the major lines of

this development were not those of Q-A logic either in its Q-AA

or final Q-AM version, but rather those spelled out as D-logic

in the Essay on Philosophical Method.

Does this mean that we must admit that the Autobiography

on this issue fails to be vindicated as an interpretation of his

later philosophy? Our answer in all honesty must be ambiguous:

yes and no. Yes, in


605

the sense that the Autobiography fails to provide us with a

clear sense of the actual relationship in Collingwood's thought

and writings between what we have been calling Q-A logic,

F-logic, and D-logic, all of which appear to operate in his

thinking and are, in one way or another, legitimate logics (in

some sense of that abused word, logic). But also no, in the

sense that in the Autobiography Collingwood (a) pointed to the

Essay on Philosophical Method as his "best work in matter" (a

clear indication that even at the time of writing of the

Autobiography he felt that the D-logical structures described in

the Essay were sound), and (b) related F-logic to realism,

against which a good part of his thinking was directed.

Thus although we cannot reasonably expect that the

Autobiography should say everything that could or should be said

about his views on logic and their role in his own philosophical

development, we believe that in the matter of Q-A logic it

remains in general (if not in every detail) a valid

interpretation of what he subsequently achieved, and certainly

more faithful to that achievement than any of the non--

autobiographical interpretations that have been offered thus

far. We suspect that if he had lived longer he may have pursued

a resolution of the remaining ambiguities about meaning, truth,

and validity; he may have developed the notion of the

"categorical" or referential aspect of judgment more fully,


606

perhaps distinguishing it from the meaning function of language;

and he may have written a more detailed epistemology to provide

us with a key to unlocking the Pandora's box of element-types

contained in his "real thinking." These themes and more remain

dangling threads in the unfinished carpet in which interpreters

like Mink and Rubinoff see a common figure.

But as we have not yet exhausted all that Collingwood

has said of significance on these topics in his later writings,

we may yet find more light shed on what sort of thinking he

accepts as "real." One candidate may be provided from the

writings that resulted from his lifelong defense of history as a

philosophical subject matter; a second from his heretical views

on metaphysics. The first is involved in his rapprochement

between history and philosophy which in the Autobiography he

claimed to be his major goal as a philosopher-historian; the

second is the extension of this endeavor at reconciliation to

the central battleground of philosophy--metaphysics. In Chapter

IX we shall examine the first, in Chapter X, the second.


CHAPTER IX

THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY

1. Introduction.

In our traversal of the later writings we come now to

the third great theme of the Autobiography, and the pattern of

the last six chapters indicates sufficiently what our next

general tasks must be. First, we seek evidence that

Collingwood's autobiographical interpretation of his development

is in its main lines carried out in his later writings on the

issue of the relationship of philosophy and history. Secondly,

we must take account of the major developments of his later

thought insofar as these impinge on our present subject--i.e.

the positions on logic and mind that we have been examining in

the previous chapters of Part III. Thirdly we must take up the

problems left unresolved on this subject from his earlier and

later writings, paying special attention to those aspects of it

which give the appearance of major reversal of opinion either in

conclusions or presuppositions, but especially the latter. We

may expect that in pursuing these general goals we shall see how

Collingwood responds to some of the classical issues that arise

in any discussion of the philosophy of history.

607
608

But in carrying out these tasks we encounter a special

textual problem that does not arise prior to this point in our

investigation. When it comes to the philosophy of history we

cannot rely on simply outlining the conclusions provided by the

evidence of his later published writings and then comparing them

to those of the Autobiography. The problem is the nature of the

evidence. Collingwood did not live long enough to complete The

Principles of History, which he had hoped to be his major

contribution to philosophy (IH, v-vi). What we inherit instead

is the posthumous publication, The Idea of_History, which is the

result of the editorial labors of T. M. Knox. In his preface to

that work Knox states that he assembled the resulting manuscript

out of materials from three sources: (a) a set of thirty-two

lectures on the philosophy of history, written during the first

six months of 1936 and revised in 1940 in preparation for

publication (note that this revision is after he wrote the

Autobiography); (b) various lectures and essays written by

Collingwood between 1934 and 1939; and (c) a 1939 manuscript

consisting of roughly the first third only of his incomplete

work, The Principles of History. As this material is passed to

us through Knox in the form of The Idea of History, from (a) we

are left with an Introduction and Parts I-IV, which consists of

the revised 1936 lecture survey of historiography from ancient

times to the early 20th century; and from (b) and (c) and some

material from (a) we get Part V, the "Epilegomena," a set of

terminal essays outlining


609

Collingwood's own philosophy of history. What remains is

Collingwood's work, but as arranged and selected by Knox. The

question arises, does this editorial arrangement reflect

Collingwood's autobiographical interpretation or Knox's

editorial reinterpretation?

Our problem is that we do not have access to the same

material as did both Knox when he wrote his preface and Col-

lingwood when he wrote the Autobiography. Although Collingwood

had authorized publication of the whole of (c), Knox saw fit to

include only those three excerpts that appear in The Idea of

History (IH, vi), along with a few very controversial quotes

from it in Knox's preface. The rest is now lost. We have already

found Knox's judgment faulty on this matter, not only because it

is inconsistent with his own editorial policy in publishing the

companion volume, The Idea of Nature, but also because it

conflicts with Collingwood's explicit statements in the

Autobiography. Critical historiography would demand that when

two authorities with access to the same materials disagree, one

is obliged to suspend judgment until further evidence or

convincing argument can be found to resolve the dispute. On

these grounds alone it seems we are forced to fall back on more

probable narrative arguments to reconstruct his thinking on the

matter.
610

But we are not obliged to remain at this impasse, and

this is precisely where our first general task blends with our

second and third. In our own survey of Collingwood's development

we have found ample indication to support his thesis in the

Autobiography that his starting point was located in his

criticism of the errors of realism. In Chapter III we found

Collingwood linking the errors of realists to the neglect of

history. These errors involved (among others) (a) the view of

the past as so many dead, atomic events--the "data" of history;

(b) a positivistic application of the methods of natural science

to history, based on the false analogy between historical and

physical events; (c) the assimilation of historical knowledge to

natural science (culminating in historical positivism and

philosophical psychologist); and (d) an abstract separation of

knowledge of fact from knowledge of self. The correction of

these erroneous views involved developing his thinking to

embrace (a) the notion of the past as a living process of

becoming, leading to the present and surviving as elements in

that present (ultimately becoming his doctrines of re-enactment,

Encapsulation, and historical evidence); (b) the concept of

history as the science of human affairs, (c) with methods of its

own not reducible to abstract deductive logic, but rather

employing a Baconian Q-A logic for testing evidence; and (d) a

philosophical rapprochement with historical understanding

insofar as knowledge achieved by historical inquiry is knowledge

of the historian's own situation which is at the same


611

time knowledge of himself, i.e. philosophy. In this issue we

therefore find joined together all of the principle themes we

have found to be the guiding ideas in the autobiographical

interpretation of Collingwood's philosophy--themes which we have

thus far confirmed to be the leading ideas in all his early and

later published writings.]

In criticizing the errors of realism concerning history

we also noticed at least one of the major issues from his later

philosophy beginning to emerge. In Chapter VI we saw a gradual

refinement of the

__________________
1 If we can ever expect to find a suitable instance of a
form of thought displaying the "real thinking" which binds
together in a single example all that Collingwood leads us to
expect of it, we have good reason to suspect that it will be
found minimally exemplified at the historical level in the scale
of forms of knowledge. Cf. per contra, Mink and Rubinoff. Mink's
"figure in the carpet" (roughly the overall point of view which
unites Collingwood's philosophy) is first encountered in art,
which is "the basic form of the figure in the carpet to which
every part of the rest of the design is related" (MHD, 237). For
Rubinoff this would probably not be art but religion, because it
is only with religion and especially the Christian religion with
its doctrine of redemption, that theory and practice are unified
and the theme of reconciliation appears explicitly (CEPC, 106;
cf. IH, 314-15). While each of them makes an impressive case in
defense of their own interpretation, we wish to note that (a)
art and religion hardly come in for mention in the
Autobiography, whereas there is a sizable discussion of the
rapprochement of history and philosophy; (b) even in the early
writings like Speculum Mentis, "concrete thought" (thought
dealing with individual facts and employing the concrete
universal) does not occur prior to historical thinking; and (c)
in his later writings the most noteworthy exercise of Q-A logic
and the use of philosophical method of the sort he described as
"real thinking" takes place in his discussion of history.
612

concept of history from its more realistic form in Religion and

Philosophy (history dealing with "facts" independent of anyone's

understanding of them) to the sort of view he sketched in the

Autobiography. We noted that in his early writings we could find

direct evidence that the principles of history we called LG and

ARCH 1, 2, and 3 are actually formulated in his essays on the

philosophy of history. But although some of the principles we

called HIST 1-4 were indirectly detectable or exemplified in his

earlier writings, they are explicit and literal only in his 1936

British Academy lecture, "Human Nature and Human History," at

which point the development of his thought on the subject as

outlined in the Autobiography may be said to be complete.

Between these two points we noted that there was a gradual re-

finement of the concept of the object of history from one which

(a) (in Religion and Philosophy) merely identified its object

with factual becoming or the whole of changing reality (hence

identifying history and philosophy as "the same thing"), to (b)

(in Speculum Mentis) a form of knowledge directed on an object

grasped as "the concrete universal," expressed in categorical

singular judgments, but limited insofar as it sought to grasp an

infinite world of fact which lies outside the consciousness of

the historian; and finally, to (c) (in the Essays on the

Philosophy of History written between 1921 and 1930) a concept

of history
613

as a multi-leveled structure in which, in its most precise form,

its object is specified as the deeds of men, done in the past,

known by critical evaluation of present evidence, and limited

only by the historian's own understanding of this evidence. Our

question from Chapter VI is whether there is any room in this

final concept of history as a scale of forms for the earliest

stage in this development, i.e. the realistic element of "fact"

as something which exists independently of anyone's knowledge of

it (RP, 49; FR, 83).

But if the work of reconciliation of philosophy and

history is complete when we have shown that the object of his-

tory displays the structure of a philosophical scale of forms,

why did Collingwood proceed, after his essays of the twenties,

to think and write on the subject? Obviously he had something

further to say, and we assume that this must have involved not

only the question of the multiple layers of meaning to the

philosophical concept of history, but also the question of the

sort of truths that are embodied in history and the form of

inference that historical thinking employs. In pursuing our

third general task we therefore contact Collingwood's handling

of the classic contemporary issues in the philosophy of history,

viz. issues concerning (a) the meaning of history, (b)

historical truth, and (c) the nature of historical


614

explanation.2 We have already met with Collingwood's response to

the first issue, and we shall have more to say about it in a

moment. We know at least that whatever else history might be, if

it is a philosophical concept its meaning has the structure of a

scale of overlapping forms. But thus far we have not found

Collingwood saying much about the nature of historical truth and

inference, and we anticipate that in The Idea of History these

will be the issues that occupy the foreground of his concern.

Therefore we expect to see that the task of reconciling history

and philosophy is carried forward in his later writings by

extending the dialectical logic of his Essay on Philosophical

Method to history at the propositional and inferential levels of

thought.

These considerations provide some substance to the

general tasks we have set for ourselves in this chapter. Our

immediate concern in the next section will be to show, first,

that in his overall reflection on the

______________________
2 Cf. W. H. Dray, "Philosophy of History," in The En-
cyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. by Paul Edwards (New York, 1967),
VI, 247-54. In his article Dray distinguishes between
speculative and critical philosophies of history, and within the
latter identifies the three major problem areas as those dealing
with historical explanation, the historical individual, and
historical objectivity. Since historical objectivity is
basically the question of the nature of historical truth, two of
the three of these issues in the critical philosophy of history
are directly addressed by Collingwood; the third is present, but
in slightly altered form. As we shall see Collingwood takes as
his historical individual the meaning of an historical act, so
that in this issue are bound both the speculative and critical
aspects of the philosophy of history.
615

nature of historical thinking Collingwood's orientation is

always displayed by a critique of the fundamental presupposition

which he called "realism." This critique depends on a definition

of history as a philosophical rather than a formal-logical

concept--i.e. one having the structure of a scale of forms

rather than that of a formally abstract class-concept. Secondly,

this critique leads directly to the formulation of his famous

"inside-outside" theory of historical events, i.e. that his-

torical events differ from physical events insofar as they are

essentially expressions of thought which the latter are not.

Thirdly, since the subject matter of history is thought,

Collingwood develops a minimal notion of what is to be included

in that concept and, fourthly, how it is grasped by an of

historical re-enactment. Fifthly, re-enactment presupposes the

activity of an a priori imagination, the functions of which he

sketches. And finally, this excursion from historical meaning to

mental functions climaxes in a remarkable debate in which

Collingwood's critique is extended beyond realism to the errors

of idealism as well, showing how on either presupposition

historical thinking, and hence historical truth, is not possible

at all.

It is at this point that we begin to see how Colling-

wood's later philosophy of history moves beyond the essays of

the twenties. We encounter arguments that exhibit the sort of

structure that he had described in the Essay on Philosophical

Method as peculiarly philosophical


616

--arguments that are reversible and conclusions that are

reciprocally established. We also are made increasingly aware of

the degree of his reliance on the theory of mental functions

that we were at pains to describe in the previous chapter. And

we see how, as might be expected, the issue of historical truth

leads directly to the problem of historical inference. In

section three we shall take up the topics of historical

methodology, Q-A logic, and historical inference, trying once

again to watch for hints that will help us to get a clearer idea

of what Collingwood understood by "real thinking" and the rela-

tionship between Q-A, F-, and D-logics.

Textually, what we are attempting is a reconstruction of

The Idea of History. In section two we will take up the

Introduction to The Idea of History and the first, second,

fourth and fifth of the seven Epilegomena--all of these being

works dating from around 1934-36 and proceeding his work on the

unfinished Principles of History. In section three we shall be

concerned with the remaining Epilegomena, but primarily the

third (which deals with historical inference)--all of these

being extracts from the 1939 draft of the Principles of History.

Our survey thus will have the effect of a counterbalance to

Knox's editorial arrangement of these essays, since it

approximates their actual chronological


617

order. Whether it also establishes their logical order as well

we leave to the judgment of the reader.

2. Anti-Realism and History: (a) The Definition of History.

The Introduction to The Idea of History presents, in

admirably concise language, a sketch of the nature, subject

matter, method, and aim of the philosophy of history--an ex-

position of which any scholastic philosopher would be proud.

Collingwood sets out to answer the questions, what is history?

what is it about? how does it proceed? and what is it for? (or

alternately, what is its value?)--and his answers are as

follows. (1) History is a kind of research or inquiry belonging

to the sciences, that is, "the forms of thought whereby we ask

questions and try to answer them"--an activity of "fastening

upon something we do not know and trying to discover it." (2)

The object of history or the kind of thing it finds out is "res

gestae: actions of human beings that have been done in the

past." (3) History proceeds by the interpretation of evidence,

where evidence is a collective name for things existing here and

now and of such

____________________
3 It is interesting to note that in spite of Colling-
wood's assertion in the Autobiography that in his early years as
a tutor and lecturer at Oxford he became something of a
specialist in Aristotle (the first lectures he gave were on De
Anima) (A, 27), few of his interpreters have followed up on this
lead. A case in point is the characterization of history as a
science, given in the Introduction, and another Aristotelianism
appears in his use of the potency-act distinction in connection
with historical evidence.
618

a kind that the historian, by thinking about it, can get answers

to the questions he asks about past events. And (4) the aim of

history, its value, is human self-knowledge, where knowing

oneself means "knowing, first, what it is to be a man; secondly,

knowing what it is to be the kind of man you are; and thirdly,

knowing what it is to be man you are and nobody else is"--a

knowledge achieved by knowing what one can do. (IH, 9-10).

History is, to put it shortly, scientific, humanistic, rational,

and self-revelatory (IH, 18).

Here in brief form is the sum, if not the entire sub-

stance, of Collingwood's philosophy of history, and the re-

mainder of The Idea of History consists of first a description

of how this complete idea came to take shape in the minds of

working historians (Parts I-IV), and secondly a commentary on

what each of these points means (Part V-The Epilegomena). Coming

to these four characteristics from the viewpoint of our recent

study of Collingwood's development to this point it is not

difficult to interpolate for ourselves how they are formulated

in opposition to realism. (a) When Collingwood calls history a

science and then describes science as "asking questions and

seeking answers" we recognize behind this assertion

Collingwood's assault on formal logic as a static relationship

between a completed set of propositions, and his "alternative"

proposal for a Q-A logic of discovery as the true instrument of

historical science.
619

(b) When Collingwood says that the object of history is res ges-

tae, we recognize that he is calling attention not only to the

fact that it is not knowable by direct observation or

"acquaintance" (on which realist epistemology is based), but

also that it requires a different description of knowing with an

epistemology of its own, one for which the basic model of

"explanation" by subsumption of particulars under a universal

law is inappropriate. (c) When Collingwood states that history

proceeds by the interpretation of evidence we cannot help

recalling the critique of "sense-datum" empiricism in The

Principles of Art. The way in which historical events of the

past are present to us requires the conscious act of

interpretation even more necessarily than does the perception of

objects which are immediately present before us. Although in

perception we can apprehend or appreciate something just as it

stands, before beginning to classify it (PA, 203), historical

evidence is only actual evidence insofar as it is known to be

what it is, i.e. insofar as it is historically interpreted (IH,

247, 280). And (d) when Collingwood insists that the aim of

history is for human self-knowledge, we hear the refrain of his

lifelong theme of reconciliation between the ancient

philosophical imperative to "know thyself" and the contemporary

view of history as the critical knowledge of human events. In

Collingwood's view the only way to effect this rapprochement is

by ridding philosophy of the notion that


620

it can live up to the sort of objectivity proposed for it by the

analogy with exact or empirical sciences. The reconciliation is

complete when both these errors are corrected, and both

philosophy and history are understood to be forms of

self-knowledge.

Lest we be accused of reading too much into The Idea

of_History we hasten to add that this aspect of rapprochement is

explicit in the Introduction where Collingwood writes that a

subject matter is philosophical insofar as it deals with "the

organized and scientific development of self-consciousness" (IH,

4), and adds that it is history rather than other forms of

knowledge that raises the peculiarly modern problems that shed

new light on this development.

The past, consisting of particular events in space and time


which are no longer happening, cannot be apprehended by
mathematical thinking, because mathematical thinking
apprehends objects that have no special location in space
and time . . . . Nor can the past be apprehended by
theological thinking, because the object of that thinking
is a single infinite object, and historical events are
finite and plural. Nor by ((empirical)) scientific
thinking, because the truths which science discovers are
known to be true by being found through observation and
experiment exemplified in what we actually perceive,
whereas the past has vanished and our ideas about it can
never be verified as we verify our scientific hypotheses.
Theories of knowledge designed to account for mathematical
and theological and scientific knowledge thus do not touch
on the special problems of historical knowledge; and if
they offer themselves as complete accounts of knowledge
they actually imply that historical knowledge is
impossible. (IH, 5).
621

It is noteworthy that although there is an indistinct

echo of the various forms of knowledge from Speculum Mentis,

there is no explicit connection made between history as itself a

philosophical scale of forms and as a form of self-knowledge

along with others (art, science, etc.). Thus we are faced from

the outset with a dilemma, if not an outright reversal from the

standpoint of his earlier writings: it appears that one can

either effect a rapprochement by pointing to a common element of

self-knowledge in both history and philosophy, thereby defining

both in terms of a universal and ignoring their structure as a

scale of forms, or define history in terms of its object as part

of a scale of forms of knowledge and lose its rapprochement with

philosophy as both forms of self-knowledge.

But this is less a problem than it appears. Collingwood

has not abandoned his requirement from the Essay on

Philosophical Method of defining a philosophical concept by

means of overlapping forms. In the Introduction he has merely

given us a brief sketch of the highest exemplification of the

concept (viz. scientific history) prior to showing how this

concept has developed to this point from its prior stages. It is

the burden of Parts I-IV of The Idea of History to trace this

development through its manifestations in historiography--a

remarkable overview which we shall not attempt to examine here

in detail. We wish to point out only


622

that both in Parts I-IV and in the Epilegomena of Part V,

Collingwood's strategy is to show that history, in its

development and in its present state, is the expression of mind

in its several overlapping functions--presentative perception,

re-presentative imagination, critical understanding and

reconciling reason. Each of these functions gives rise to a form

of historiography in which they form the guiding idea. Thus

Collingwood traces the idea of history (a) from its pre-historic

beginnings in mythology and sacred literature, through (b) its

first concrete manifestations in Greek histories with their

emphasis on eyewitness accounts, (c) subsequently developed in

the Christian era as "scissors and paste" history which relies

uncritically on "authorities" who in turn rest on eyewitness

accounts; then (d) to critical historiography originating in the

Renaissance but coming into its own in the 18th century with

philosophers like Vico who recognized that the historian can and

must employ his own reasoning to adjudicate conflicting accounts

of historical authorities; and finally (e) to the present era of

scientific historiography, in which the active role of the

historian is thoroughly recognized as essential to the very

process of historical thinking. It is not difficult to recognize

in these stages of the concept of history a schema we have

already encountered in The Principles of Art and The New

Leviathan in the process of thought in general. Thus we have (a)

history as the confused potential for bearing meaning (mythical

and
623

theological history), (b) as events perpetuated and domesticated

in perception by eye-witnesses (early Greco-Roman

historiography), (c) as chronicles represented in imagination

and memory ("scissors and paste"--e.g. Medieval historiography),

(d) as critically constructed into coherent narratives by

judgmental understanding (critical historiography), and (e) as

fully related to self-conscious reason by recognizing and

integrating the active role of the historian in the construction

of his narrative account (scientific historiography). It is in

this way that he offers recompense for the neglect of history by

the realists, and it is in this way that he shows that history

is a form of self-knowledge.

This overview of the argument of Part I is not totally

free of the inaccuracies that arise whenever oversimplification

occurs. Greco-Roman history, for example, is not completely or

even primarily based on eye-witness accounts: much of it is

mixed with legend, myth, and even outright inventions by the

historian (orations in Thucydides, for example). In Speculum

Mentis Collingwood made a point of describing how early

historiography is mixed with dramatic and religious elements, so

that there is some confusion in the mind of an historian like

Herodotus between the ideals of factual history per se and the

artistic ideals of drama (SM, 211-16). Collingwood was no less

aware of such an overlap when he wrote Part I of The Idea

of_History: but he was not concerned with


624

showing the relation of history to other forms of experience

(e.g. art), but rather with showing how the clear idea of

scientific history grew out of a confused idea of it. Our point

in bringing out the analogy between the development of

scientific history and the levels of mental functions is meant

to call attention to the shift in ideals of historiography, and

to show how in that shift a scale of forms is generated.

If the four elements of Collingwood's definition of

history are formulated in opposition to realism, how do they

form a challenge to the central realistic dogma on the rela-

tionship of knower and known? If the object known is not af-

fected by the knowing of it, then it appears that objectivity is

retained for history, but self-knowledge is not; but if the

events of history are altered in the process of coming to know

them, then historical objectivity is itself threatened. In

showing how the concept of history is preserved in the truths of

history, Collingwood will argue, as he already had in The

Principles of Art for perception, that historical events are not

created ex nihilo by historical imagination, but they are

preserved and prolonged by historical consciousness, and this is

based on the historian's operating presuppositions. As a first

step in showing how he works this out in detail in the

Epilegomena essays, we must clarify the notion of an historical

event, the minimum exemplification of the


625

concept of history, and the res gestae of his definition in the

Introduction.

(b) The Outside and Inside of Historical Events.—It is

interesting to note that the first two of these Epilegomena,

both lectures, are directed against views of history by realists

and idealists respectively. The first is Collingwood's 1936

British Academy lecture, "Human Nature and Human History," and

it packs a double anti-realistic punch. It makes as its major

thesis that "the science of human nature was a false

attempt--falsified by the analogy of natural science--to

understand the mind itself, and that, whereas the right way of

investigating nature is by the methods called scientific, the

right way of investigating the mind is by the methods of

history" (IH, 209). But rather than remaining content to refute

an 18th century error, Collingwood carries the argument forward

from empiricism to contemporary realism. He takes as his

proximate target the essay "The Historicity of Things" by the

avowed realist, Samuel Alexander.4 Alexander's essay identifies

historicity with the universal "timefulness" of things, a tactic

which results in resolving all knowledge to history (IH, 210).

In order to preserve the autonomy of both history and science,

Collingwood makes it a point to distinguish history not only

_____________________
4 In Philosophy and History, The Ernst Cassirer Fest-
schrift, ed. by Raymond-Klibansky and H. J. Paton (Oxford,
1936), pp. 11-25.
626

from physical change but also from "timefulness"--both resulting

from the confusion of the scientific conception of nature and

the historical conception of mind.

First he tackles an older concept:

Since the time of Heraclitus and Plato, it has been a


commonplace that things natural, no less than things human,
are in constant change, and that the entire world of nature
is a world of "process" or "becoming." But this is not what
is meant by the historicity of things; for change and
history are not at all the same. According to this
old-established conception, the specific forms of natural
things constitute a changeless repertory of fixed types,
and the process of nature is a process by which instances
of these forms . . . come into existence and pass out of it
again. Now in human affairs . . . there is no such fixed
repertory of specific forms . . . . (H)uman history shows a
change not only in the individual cases in which these
ideals are realized or partially realized, but in the
ideals themselves. (IH, 210-11).

Collingwood recognized that the evolutionary conception of na-

ture has replaced the older concept of a physical universe of

unaltered species, so that in the newer view, as expressed by

Whitehead, "the very possession of its attributes by a natural

thing takes time" and "the historicity of things" is proven by

the fact that there can be no such thing as nature at an instant

(IN, 212). But this presents an even subtler danger, since

history is still not reducible to science nor historical events

to scientific ones:

These modern views of nature do, no doubt, "take time


seriously." But just as history is not the same thing as
change, so it is not the same thing as "timefulness," whe-
ther that means evolution or an existence which takes time.
. . . According to him ((i.e. the
627

historian)), all history properly so called is the history


of human affairs . . . . There is a certain analogy between
the archeologist's interpretation of a stratified site and
the geologist's interpretation of rock-horizons with their
associated fossils; but the difference is no less clear
than the similarity. The archeologist's use of his
stratified relics depends on his conceiving them as
artifacts serving human purposes and thus expressing a
particular way in which men have thought about their own
life; and from his point of view the paleontologist,
arranging his fossils in a time-series, is not working as
an historian, but only as a scientist thinking in a way
which can at most be described as quasi-historical. (IH,
212).

It is in order to distinguish these two classes of events and

these two sorts of thinking activities that Collingwood in-

troduces his "inside-outside" theory of human acts.

He distinguishes between physical events and human acts

on the basis that physical events have only an "outside"

consisting of "everything belonging to it which can be described

in terms of bodies and their movements," whereas human acts have

in addition an "inside" or "that which can only be described in

terms of thought" (IH, 213). If this appears to be a mere

restatement of a kind of Cartesian dualism, Collingwood is

anxious to add that it is not the dualism of a pair of mutually

exclusive classes. The historian, he insists, is never concerned

with either of these to the exclusion of the other. "He is

investigating not mere events (where by a mere event I mean one

which has only an outside and no inside) but actions, and an

action is the unity of the outside and inside of an event"

(ibid.). While it is true that the natural


628

scientist goes beyond the immediate event by observing its

relations to others and bringing them under a general formula or

law of nature, to the scientist nature is always merely a

"phenomenon" or spectacle presented to his intelligent

observation. But the events of history are never mere phenomena

or spectacles, but "things which the historian looks, not at,

but through, to discern the thought within them" (IH, 214).

This last remark underscores the importance of viewing

Collingwood's inside-outside theory in the light of his

philosophy of mind. When he says that the historian looks "not

at but through" the outside of an event he is saying that the

historian takes such acts as expressions of thoughts, i.e. as

conveyers of meaning exactly like language (where language is

taken in its extended sense as including that "gesture language"

that Collingwood recognized as more basic than spoken language).

Acts, like sounds, ink-marks, gesture-signs, etc. are physical

"bearers of meaning"--they express the intentions of an

historical agent in acts as his words do in sounds. It is

because they have this character that they have the capacity or

potential to be evidence to the historian; but it is also the

reason that they require interpretation by an historian. To

paraphrase the situation for Collingwood, a physical event may

or may not be whatever it is without human interpretation; but

an historical event cannot. Sounds may or may not be bearers of

meanings,
629

but human actions, like words, do not have this alternative.

Unfortunately Collingwood's inside-outside doctrine has

generated a fair amount of misunderstanding, even among his more

sympathetic interpreters. Some of this appears to be the result

of his own overstatement--as when he writes that "the processes

of events which constitute the world of nature are altogether

different in kind from the processes of thought which constitute

the world of history" (IH, 217). It has led to the charges both

that he over-intellectualizes history and that he draws an

overly strict distinction between history and nature. Once again

the first charge seems to be directly supported by Collingwood.

Having said that history is not the same as change, natural

process or timefulness, he further limits the range of

historical research by insisting that it does not even include

all human activities:

It does not follow that all human actions are subject-


matter for history; and indeed historians are agreed that
they are not. But when they are asked how the distinction
is to be made between historical and non-historical human
actions, they are at a loss how to reply. From our present
point of view we can offer an answer; so far as man's
conduct is determined by what may be called his animal na-
ture, his impulses and appetites, it is non-historical; the
process of these activities is a natural process. Thus, the
historian is not interested in the fact that men eat and
sleep and make love and thus satisfy their natural
appetites; but he is interested in the social customs which
they create by their thought as a framework within which
these appetites find satisfaction in ways sanctioned by
convention and morality. (IH, 216; cf. IH, 315).
630

The question immediately arises, does this not

rule out a great deal of what is usually taken to be the

subject-matter of history? What about the rages of Ivan the

Terrible, Napoleon, or Hitler, or natural disasters like the

Lisbon and San Francisco earthquakes? We shall see in the next

section what Collingwood takes to be the true subject-matter of

history, but we see from the above quote what his general answer

to the objection is. Natural events are of interest to the

historian only to the extent that they impinge on human events

in the proper sense, or are incorporated into them as an aspect

of thought. Passions, natural disasters and other physical

phenomena are historical only to the extent that people

thinkingly react to them--Hitler's rages as instrumental or

obstructive to the discharge of Nazi warplans, the Lisbon

earthquake causing decisions on relocation of populations or

influencing government financial policies, etc. But regarded as

entities in themselves, i.e. as not the expression of human

thought, passions and feelings are the subject-matter for psy-

chology, land-mass shifts for geology, etc.

The second objection is more serious, and takes a bit of

sleuthing to uncover Collingwood's thought on the matter. We

have already suggested that while historical events necessarily

involve thought, since they express human intentions in

purposive acts, natural events do not. Does this mean they do

not as a matter of fact, or as a matter of necessity?


631

Collingwood appears to leave the question open, commenting only

that "The only condition on which there could be a history of

nature is ((on the assumption)) that the events of nature are

actions on the part of some thinking being or beings, and that

by studying these actions we could discover what were the

thoughts which they expressed and think these thoughts for our-

selves. This is a condition," he adds cryptically, "which

probably no one will claim is fulfilled" (IH, 302).5 What sort

of

_____________________
5 Collingwood could not have anticipated that someone
after his death would, in fact, make such a claim--but such is
the argument of J. Blachowicz in "History and Nature in Col-
lingwood's Dialectic," Idealistic Studies, VI, 2 (January,
1976), pp. 49-61. Although sympathetic to Collingwood's overall
aims, Blachowicz finds that Collingwood failed to extend his
dialectical analysis to nature itself, and is therefore guilty
of drawing an overly strict distinction between events of nature
and those of history--thus being open to an accusation of
falling prey to his own "Fallacy of False Disjunction.
Blachowicz argues that in order to extend his dialectical an-
alysis to nature Collingwood merely had to see that the "pre-
suppositions of nature ((may)) be disclosed by way of access
into its 'inside' as well" (p. 56). But for Blachowicz the
"inside" of physical events consist of their teleological as-
pect, which is contained in the fundamental parameter of com-
plexity or organization. "As the variable of internal organi-
zation assumes different values, the generic essence is quali-
tatively altered, generating the scale of forms which is the
scale of nature," so that "the presuppositional logic is fully
applicable" to development in nature" (p. 57). Now while we
agree with Blachowicz in bemoaning Collingwood's failure to
achieve a clearer rapprochement between Q-A and D-logics, we is
alien to Collingwood's purpose to attribute to physical,
non-human events. Presuppositions, whatever else they may be,
are essentially a part of a P-Q-A complex and essentially
“linguistic” in the sense of expressing the thoughts of persons.
Physical events do not ask questions (although they may, on
human interpretation, "raise" questions in the minds of
observers); therefore they do not "have” presuppositions in
Collingwood's sense. But Blachowicz is right to point out
Collingwood's curious neglect of the applicability of the scale
of forms to nature--a deficiency not shared by some other
contemporary cosmologies.
632

"thinking" Collingwood has in mind in the expression "thinking

beings" we shall see in a moment, but we have already seen that

he has in mind the sort of problem-solving choices that embody

the unification of theoretical and practical activities--what he

has elsewhere called "real thinking" or "concrete thought." The

outside and inside of an historical act are not themselves two

separate events, but two sides to the same act--exactly like

expressive language and thought. Thus when the historical agent

is mistaken in his theoretical assessment of the situation in

which he finds himself called upon to act, this mistaken thought

cannot be ignored by the historian who attempts to understand

the act: his mistaken thought is essential to understanding the

significance of the agent's act (IH, 316-17).

Now this point is crucial in understanding the inside-

outside theory: while Collingwood is willing to use the term

"event" for both history and nature, he is not able to bring

himself to do so for the term "action" because the latter term

requires the essential element of self-consciousness in the

awareness of alternative possibilities (IH, 215). Collingwood

finds it highly questionable, if not downright repugnant, to

predicate this state of affairs of nature. This becomes apparent

in an earlier portion of The Idea of History, in a discussion of

teleology--that aspect of "acting for an end" that is teetering

on the brink of the distinction between history and nature. The

issue arises in
633

Collingwood's discussion of Kant's distinction between natural

and human affairs, viz. that nature acts in accordance with law,

but only man acts in accordance with the concept or

consciousness of law. Nature, therefore, is the sum of processes

governed by laws blindly obeyed, but the world of human affairs

is governed not simply by law but by the consciousness of law

(IH, 92). He then cites with apparent approval Kant's

demonstration of why there should be such a thing as history.

Nature's purpose in creating any of her creatures is, of


course, the existence of that creature, the realization of
its essence. The teleology of nature is an internal
teleology, not an external: she does not make grass to feed
cows, and cows to feed men; she makes grass in order that
there would be grass, and so on. Man's essence is his
reason; therefore she makes men in order that they should
be rational . . . . Man is an animal that has the peculiar
faculty of profiting by the experience of others; and he
has this faculty because he is rational, for reason is a
kind of experience in which this is possible. . . .
Consequently the purpose of nature for the development of
man's reason is a purpose that can be fully realized only
in the history of the human race and not in an individual
life. (IH, 98).

Now it is worth noting that while Collingwood faults Kant for

locating the activating force for the plan of human history,

i.e. progress in rationality in human irrationality, i.e. pas-

sion, ignorance, and selfishness (IH, 103), he does not fault

him for the basic distinction between nature and the world of

human affairs. Such is not the case with his discussion of

Croce, whom he charges with blurring the distinction


634

completely. Collingwood quotes a passage in which Croce

challenges his reader to an experiment: if you wish to

understand the true history of a neolithic man, become a

neolithic in your mind; and if you wish to understand the true

history of a blade of grass, become that grass in your mind--but

if you cannot, content yourself with describing and arranging

artifacts or mechanisms in an external way. Then Collingwood

responds to Croce's challenge:

As concerns neolithic man, the advice is obviously good. If


you can enter into his mind and make his thoughts your own,
you can write his history, and not otherwise . . . . When
he made a certain implement, he had a purpose in mind; the
implement came into being as an expression of his spirit,
and if you treat it as non-spiritual that is only because
of the failure of your historical insight. But is this true
of a blade of grass? Is its articulation and growth an
expression of its own spiritual life? I am not so sure. And
when we come to a crystal, or a stalactite, my skepticism
reaches the point of rebellion. The process by which these
things form themselves appears to me to be a process in
which, through no lack of our own historical sympathy, we
look in vain for any expression of thought. It is an event;
it has individuality; but it seems to lack that inwardness
which, according to . . . Croce, is made (and I think,
rightly made) the criterion of historicity. (IH, 199-200).

The upshot of this discussion is that while Collingwood

is willing to grant an "internal teleology" to nature, he is not

willing to abandon the distinction between natural and his-

torical events, because the latter cannot be understood except

as the expression of human thought. It is less a matter of ne-

cessity than it is one of fact that nature is not so constitu-

ted; but it is a matter of necessity that history is, since,


635

on Collingwood's view, an historical event necessarily is an

action of a human agent (one is tempted to say "by definition"),

and this requires awareness of alternatives, or reflective

thought. And it is this difference in essential constitution

that he has in mind when he says that they are "altogether

different in kind" (IH, 217--notice the wording: the processes

of events which constitute the world of nature are altogether

different in kind from the processes of thought which constitute

the world of history).

The "inside-outside" terminology is therefore a meta-

phorical expression which Collingwood finds useful for de-

scribing what he takes to be an essential difference between

historical and physical events--a distinction that he maintains

both against positivistic6 historians who assimilate history to

science as if the nature of the "facts" or events were basically

the same (IH, 132-33), and against the idealistic historians who

assimilate nature to history by assuming that one can re-think a

physical event in the same way that one can re-enact an

______________________
6 The successors to the English empiricist tradition in
history are the positivistic historians, just as the successors
to that tradition in philosophy are the realists of Oxford and
Cambridge (IH, 126-33, 142, 163-64, 173-74). As we have already
noted, empiricism, naturalism, realism, positivism, and even
psychologism are products of the same frame of mind, and
Collingwood often uses the terms synonymously. He recognized in
all the root error of realism, i.e. the assumption that
knowledge consists of the confrontation of a mind with an object
outside the mind, where the latter remains unaffected by the
knowing of it.
636

historical one. The philosophy of history which is argued in the

Epilegomena is hardly intelligible unless it is understood

against the background of this opposition between realistic or

positivistic history and its idealistic counterpart--a theme we

shall encounter again in the discussion of historical

re-enactment.

(c) Individuality, Universality, and the Subject Matter

of History.-- In analyzing the res gestae of history Collingwood

has been more concerned with the differences between historical

acts and physical events than with the positive characteristics

of the acts themselves. Thus far we know minimally that history

is concerned with acts of men done in the past, acts which have

an "inside" consisting of thought. We know also that these acts

are done self-consciously or "on purpose," and that they involve

the practical resolution of situational problems expressing a

thoughtful choice between alternatives (IH, 215, 283). And

finally, they are experiential--they are, as he phrases it, "not

spectacles to be watched, but experiences to be lived through"

(IH, 218).

In the fifth Epilegomenon, "The Subject Matter of His-

tory," Collingwood reiterates these characteristics and adds

another which sheds some light not only on the minimal unit

presupposed for understanding historical processes, but also on

our previous discussion of universal concepts and abstract

classes. Reversing the order of the approach taken


637

in the first Epilegomenon, Collingwood this time proceeds from

the subjective to the objective. The subject matter of history

must first of all be experience and not the mere object of ex-

perience, i.e. the processes of nature that are the subject

matter for natural science. But it is not even experience as

such that the historian seeks, since immediate experience is a

"mere flow of consciousness consisting of sensations, feelings

and the like" which are carried away in the flux of sensuous

experience (cf. IH, 233). Nor is it even thought in its

immediacy, i.e. "the unique act of thought with its unique

context in the life of an individual thinker," since if this

were so, in thinking an historical subject matter "the historian

would be the person about whom he thinks, living over again

((acts)) in all respects the same" (IH, 302-03). What the

historian apprehends is not the individual in all its in-

dividuality, but something essentially universal:

The historian cannot apprehend the individual act of


thought in its individuality, just as it actually happened
((or in Ranke's words, wie es eigentlich gewesen--IH,
130)). What he apprehends of that individual is only some-
thing that it might have shared with other acts of thought
and actually has shared with his own. But this something is
not an abstraction, in the sense of a common characteristic
shared by different individuals and considered apart from
the individuals that share it. It is the act of thought
itself, in its survival and revival at different times and
in different persons; once in the historian's own life,
once in the life of the person whose history he is
narrating. (IH, 303).

Thus far we recognize Collingwood's epistemological setting

for the notion of a universal concept which "survives and


638

revives" in mental activities; but he here goes on to give it a

different perspective than we have heretofore encountered. The

passage continues:

Thus the vague phrase ((of Croce--IH, 199)) that history is


knowledge of the individual claims for it a field at once
too wide and too narrow: too wide, because the individuality
of perceived objects and natural facts and immediate
experience falls outside its sphere . . . ; too narrow,
because it would exclude universality, and it is just the
universality of an event or character that makes it a proper
and possible object of historical study, if by universality
we mean something that oversteps the limits of merely local
and temporal existence and possesses a significance valid
for all men at all times . . . . (T)hought, transcending its
own immediacy, survives and revives in other contexts; and .
. . individual acts and persons appear in history not in
virtue of their individuality as such, but because that
individuality is the vehicle of a thought which, because it
was actually theirs, is potentially everyone 's. (IH, 303;
cf. IN, 247, 280).

In this subtle and neglected theme we find Collingwood's un-

derstanding of universal concepts lit up from several directions

simultaneously. (a) Not only does it contrast the individual

(what he had called, in Speculum Mentis, the concrete universal)

with the abstract universal (or the class-concept of F-logic);

and (b) not only does this universality take part in the

survival and revival of a concept in the context of different

mental acts, thus transcending the local and temporal limits of

immediate feelings; (c) but also it binds the universality of a

concept to the individuality of the meaning of an historical act

which expresses a thought which, as he says, is potentially

everyone's because it was actually theirs. The universality of

historical thinking is bound by


639

Collingwood to the notion of meaning expressed in historical

acts, and this is the individuality with which history is

minimally concerned. This theme will be renewed when we come to

Collingwood's treatment of re-enactment, where it re-appears in

the critique of the distinction between acts of thought and

their objects.

It is also here that we encounter the self-consciousness

that is essential not only to historical understanding but in

the historical act of an agent in the first place. Both in his

definition of history as consisting of acts of historical agents

with their inside consisting of thought, and in his definition

of historical re-enactment on the part of the historian, the key

term is, of course, "thought." Collingwood does not back away

from stating what is included in this term.

How much or how little is meant to be included under the


term "thought"? The term "thought" . . . has stood for a
certain form of experience or mental activity whose pe-
culiarity may be negatively described by saying that it is
not merely immediate, and therefore is not carried away by
the flow of consciousness. The positive peculiarity which
distinguishes thought from mere consciousness is its power
of recognizing the activity of the self as a single
activity persisting through the diversity of its own acts .
. . . The peculiarity of thought, then, is that it is not
mere consciousness but self-consciousness. The self, as
merely conscious, is a flow of consciousness, a series of
immediate sensations and feelings; but as merely conscious
it is not aware of itself as such a flow; it is ignorant of
its own continuity through the succession of experiences.
The activity of becoming aware of this continuity is what
is called thinking. (IN, 306; cf. IN, 222).
640

Collingwood follows this continuity-achieving activity briefly

through its manifestations in perception, memory, and imagin-

ation--the stages of recognizing feelings as "mine," prolonging

them, etc. The account is a brief tour of the stages of mental

functions that we have already encountered in The Principles of

Art and The New Leviathan. As before, it emphasizes the active

role of thought at all levels of mental activity. But in this

case Collingwood is anxious to draw the distinction between

reflectively self-conscious thought and non-reflective or

"unconscious" thinking, and in so doing we again see it from a

new angle than we have previously.

(T)he thinking which we do in memory or perception as such


may be called unconscious thinking, not because we can do
it without being conscious, for in order to do it we must
be not only conscious but self-conscious, but because we do
it without being conscious that we are doing it. To be
conscious that I am thinking is to think in a new way,
which may be called reflecting. Historical thinking is al-
ways reflection; for reflection is thinking about the act
of thinking . . . . But what kind of thinking can be its
object? . . . In order . . . that any particular act of
thought should become subject-matter for history, it must
be an act not only of thought but of reflective thought,
that is, one which is performed in the consciousness that
it is being performed, and is constituted by that con-
sciousness. (IH, 307-08).

Notice that Collingwood does not find the expression "uncon-

scious thinking" self-contradictory (cf. per contra, Donagan,

LPC, 271) and that he accepts without hesitation the presence of

the activity of self-consciousness even at the level of

perception--a point to which we called attention earlier. Nor is

it a great surprise that he finds


641

historical thinking to be self-consciously reflective, although

we find him for the first time stating that it is "constituted"

by that consciousness. But then he continues:

The effort to do it ((i.e. think reflectively)) must be


more than a merely conscious effort . . . ; it must be a
reflective effort, the effort to do something of which we
have a conception before we do it. A reflective activity is
one in which we know what it is that we are trying to do,
so that when it is done we know that it is done by seeing
that it has conformed to the standard or criterion which
was our initial conception of it. It is therefore an act
which are enabled to perform by knowing in advance how to
perform it. (IH, 308).

At this point it should be perfectly obvious why, on Colling-

wood's grounds, physical events cannot be regarded as historical

actions: they are not acts performed with the foreknowledge of a

"standard or criterion" which is their initial conception of it.

To use Collingwood's lowly example, the blade of grass grows not

in order that the cow should eat it, or with the conception of

being food for herbivorous animals, but that there should be

grass. But even that is not correct, for it has no conception at

all of what it is to be grass rather than some alternative. But

historical acts cannot be thus regarded; their universal

character is part of their essential constitution:

An act is more than a mere unique individual; it is some-


thing having a universal character; and in the case of a
reflective or deliberate act (an act which we not only do,
but intend to do before doing it) this universal character
is the plan or idea of the act which we conceive in our
thought before doing the act itself, and the criterion by
reference to which, when we have done it, we know that
642

we have done what we meant to do . . . . Reflective acts


may be roughly described as the acts which we do on pur-
pose, and these are the only acts which can become the
subject matter of history. (IH, 309).

Now although Collingwood has phrased the distinction in temporal

terms, ("an act which we . . . intend to do before doing

it . . .") it is clear enough from the rest of the paragraph

that what he has in mind is what is also reflected in the basic

Kantian distinction between actions done in accordance with a

law and actions done in accordance with the concept of a law;

historical acts fall into the latter category, physical events

in the former. What Collingwood has added is the observation

that all such deliberate reflective acts are historical, that

they involve criteria by which success or failure may be

assessed, and that therefore these acts have aspects that are

both individual (as experientially one's own) and universal (as

reflectively intended).

Here we encounter a problem. In historical thinking (in

this case we mean the thinking of agents involved in the doing

of historical deeds) we find the sort of thinking Collingwood

called "concrete" in Speculum Mentis and "real thinking" in The

New Leviathan and his correspondence with Ryle concerning the

Essay on Philosophical Method. We recall from our discussion of

his philosophy of mind that all real thinking has both

theoretical and practical dimensions, and that the latter is

foundational to the former. In saying that historical acts are

those which we plan to


643

do before doing them Collingwood appears to be reversing this

priority --conceiving a plan being a theoretical activity and

executing it a practical one. Collingwood anticipated this

objection and even drew from it the logical conclusion that

acting is the only thing one can do on purpose, since thinking

on purpose would involve conceiving your own act of thought

before executing it, and having done so you would have executed

it already. Theoretical activities, it follows, can only be

non-purposive or, as he puts it, "done in the dark, with no

conception of what is to come from engaging in them" (IH, 311).

The reader familiar with the debate concerning Collingwood's

views on absolute presuppositions (i.e. that they are not

propositions, that one can make them without knowing that they

are being made, etc.) will realize that we are on the verge of a

crucial issue not only in his philosophy of history, but in his

view of metaphysics.

We know already what part of his answer to this objec-

tion is: any theoretical activity is already practical insofar

as it employs concepts that are made by acts of selective

attention. But his actual reply is interesting insofar as it

suggests a connection with Q-A logic which we shall have to bear

in mind when we come to examine his thesis that metaphysics is

an historical science.
644

Today it is no longer necessary to argue that art, science,


religion, philosophy, and so forth are proper subjects of
historical study; the fact of their being studied
historically is too familiar. But it is necessary to ask
why this is so . . . . In the first place, it is not true
that a person engaged in purely theoretical thinking is
acting without a purpose . . . . (E)very actual inquiry
starts from a certain problem, and the purpose of the
inquiry is to solve that problem; the plan of the
discovery, therefore, is already known and formulated by
saying that, whatever the discovery may be, it must be such
as to satisfy the terms of the problem . . . . In the
second place, the difference between conceiving and
executing a purpose was not correctly described as the
difference between a theoretical act and a practical one.
To conceive a purpose or form an intention is already a
practical activity. It is not thought forming an anteroom
to action; it is action itself in its initial stage. (IH,
311-12).

Collingwood's reply, therefore, is based on his Q-A logic as

grounded in his epistemology: thinking on purpose does involve

conceiving one's own act of thought before executing it, but as

a plan of inquiry based on the presence of a problem situation

or a question, whereas the execution of the plan involves

answering the question, solving the problem, or satisfying the

terms of the inquiry-initiator.

It is not difficult to make the application to histor-

ical inquiry. In order for an event to be of interest to an

historian it must be one which expresses the thought of an

historical agent in a situation in which alternative courses of

action are open to him, and in which he is responsible for

determining the event by acting according to his consciousness

of a "plan" or "idea"--the alternative meanings he not only finds

in the event-situation but gives to it by his chosen


645

actions. It will be helpful to keep this in mind as a sort of

archetype of what an historical event is--candidates for such

events occurring in politics, warfare, economics, morals, art,

science, religion, and philosophy (IH, 309-15)-the list is

stated as exemplary rather than exhaustive. The difficulty for

the historian in each of these cases is to identify the problem

from which the act proceeded, and to reconstruct the steps by

which its solution was attempted (IH, 312-13)--and not merely to

repeat the conclusion. Until this step has been taken the

historian cannot be sure that he has grasped the past at

all--that is, he cannot be certain that historical thinking in

the form of re-enactment or re-thinking has occurred at all.

But re-enactment raises us to a new level of thinking,

and to this issue we must now turn.

(d) Historical Re-enactment.--The deeds of men which

form the subject-matter of history must not only be known by

seeing them to be expressions of thought, or seeing "through"

them, they must be known as past deeds. The historian must

therefore be aware of himself as distinct from the past he

studies, while he is yet able to revive that past as thought in

his own mind (cf. IH, 174). In order to meet this requirement

Collingwood introduces his widely misunderstood doctrine of

historical re-enactment. The choice of the term "reenactment" to

describe the relationship between a historical event and a

historiographical
646

reconstruction of that event appears to be deliberately it calls

attention to the central concept of a purposive act as the

irreducible unit of history, while yet locating it in an

epistemological structure similar to the

presentation-representation schema of perception (the difference

being, of course, that the act of an historical agent can only

be re-presented through the intermediation of evidence and

interpretative argument). Collingwood is even careful to vary

his terms to bring out various aspects of reenactment, using

synonyms like re-create (IH, 97), reconstruct (IH, 65), relive

(IH, 172, 175), re-think (IH, 215), and revive (IH, 164)--an

assortment of expressions which can hardly be accidental (cf.

EPM, 205-07 on the in-appropriateness of technical terminology

in philosophy).

In this classic statement of re-enactment Collingwood's

approach is via the inside-outside doctrine:

The processes of nature can therefore be properly described


as sequences of mere events, but those of history
cannot.They are not processes of mere events, but processes
of actions, which have an inner side consisting of
processes of thought . . . . All history is

_______________________
7 Collingwood's first use of the term "re-enactment" in
The Idea of History occurs in Part I during his criticism of
Tacitus, where it is also linked to the discussion of the out-
side and inside of an event (IH, 39). It reappears in his
discussions of Vico (IH, 65) and Hegel (IH, 97), both of whom
are praised for recognizing the principle. In Part V it is
re-introduced in the first Epilegomenon along with the inside-
outside theory of human acts (IH, 215).
647

the history of thought. But how does the historian discern


the thoughts which he is trying to discover? There is only
one way in which it can be done: by re-thinking them in his
own mind. The historian of philosophy, reading Plato, is
trying to know what Plato thought when he expressed himself
in certain words. The only way in which he can do this is
by thinking it for himself. This, in fact, is what we mean
when we speak of "understanding" the words. So the
historian of politics or warfare, presented with an account
of certain actions of Julius Caesar, tries to understand
these actions, that is, to discover what thoughts in
Caesar's mind determined him to do them. This implies
envisaging for himself the situation in which Caesar stood,
and thinking for himself what Caesar thought about the
situation and the possible ways of dealing with it. The
history of thought, and therefore all history is the
re-enactment of past thought in the historian's own mind.
This re-enactment . . . is not a passive surrender . . . ;
it is a labour of active and therefore critical thinking.
The historian not only re-enacts past thought, he re-enacts
it in the context of his own knowledge and therefore, in
re-enacting it, forms his own judgment of its value,
corrects whatever errors he can discern in it (IH, 215;
emphasis mine).

The lines to which we have called attention in the above passage

are the principles of history cited in the Autobiography and

outlined in our chapter on Collingwood's autobiographical

interpretation as HIST -1, -2, and -3 (Table 4 ) . Since these

principles are explicitly stated in this essay, and the fourth

(HIST-4) is the major thesis of the first Epilegomenon itself,

it is clear that when Collingwood wrote that portion of the

Autobiography he had these essays before him.

But as if anticipating that his doctrine of re-enactment

would be misconstrued by assimilating it to an overly concrete

meaning of one of its secondary senses, Collingwood takes pains

to state what re-enactment is not before trying to exhibit what

it is. (1) We have already


648

quoted the passage from "The Subject Matter of History" where he

rejects a dramatic view of history in which "the historian would

be the person about whom he thinks, living over again in all

respects the same" (IH, 303). The historian in re-enacting the

event is not restaging it by repeating its outside motions; he

reenacts it by re-thinking that universal element that consti-

tutes its inside meaning. (2) But he is also not advocating an

intuitionist view of history which relies on a mysterious union

between the mind of an historian and that of the agent he is

studying. In spite of contrary appearances, as when Collingwood

uses expressions like "reliving" past experiences and "plunging

below the surface" of our minds where we "become" the person

whose acts we are discovering (A, 113), Collingwood has

something more direct in mind than what these dramatic

expressions might lead one to believe. Whatever else

re-enactment might involve, it is not concerned with immediate

experiences, nor is it a "passive surrender" but rather a

"labour of active and therefore critical thinking," which en-

tails envisioning for oneself the situation in which the agent

is called upon to act (IH, 215, 316; cf. A, 100). (3) This is

also the reason that re-enactment is not a simple exercise of

the memory. The past with which the historian is concerned is

not simply recalled, since there is an essential difference

between memory and the exercise of historical thinking. What

Caesar's memory may provide for him are a series


649

of outstanding images, but these he must present in a coherent

account, which involves not just the images but reconstruction

of the events. History is "a wholly reasoned knowledge of what

is transient and concrete" (IH, 234), whereas "memory is not

history, because history is a certain kind of organized or in-

ferential knowledge, and memory is not organized, not inferen-

tial at all" (IH, 252).

But if re-enactment is neither a dramatic restaging of

past events (1), nor an uncritical passive intuition of past

thinking (2), nor a replay of the graphic record of the

remembered past on the blank screen of the historian's mind (3),

it is also not (4) the creation ex nihilo of a fictitious past.

In the third Epilegomenon ("Historical Evidence"--a fragment

from The Principles of History) he writes that the business of

the historian is not to invent anything, it is to discover

something (IH, 251); and in the second Epilegomenon ("The

Historical Imagination") he writes:

As works of imagination, the historian's work and the


novelists do not differ. Where they do differ is that the
historian's picture is meant to be true. The novelist has a
single task only: to construct a coherent picture, one that
makes sense. The historian has a double task: he has both
to do this, and to construct a picture of things as they
really were and of events as they really happened. (IH,
246).

Just as, in The Principles of Art, Collingwood rejected any

radical theory of sensation which would allow for a creation ex

nihilo of sense,
650

so in The Idea of History he stops short of a creationist view

of historical events. Re-enactment presupposes that something

remains of the original event, and this something (we have

already identified it as the universal meaning of an individual

act) is not simply created by an historian's re-enactment.

Historical reference to past events presupposes an object that

retains some identity in both contexts, the original situation

in which it occurred, and the historian's re-enactment of that

event in the context of his own thoughts.

The question is, is anything important altered by re-

enactment, and if so, how is historical objectivity possible?

Since the issue is crucial not only for Collingwood's philosophy

of history, but also for rapprochement in general and his view

of metaphysics in particular,8 we must take care to present the

issue carefully and completely. We must go beyond saying what

re-enactment is not by giving a preliminary sketch of what it is

(which we are about to do), and then showing both that it

exercises some of the functions of a priori imagination and

_________________________
8 It is crucial not only because re-enactment is the
central thesis of his philosophy of history as described both in
the Autobiography and in The Idea of History, but also because
it is the key to unscrambling the central dilemma of the Essay
on Metaphysics. If metaphysics is an historical science, and if
history is the re-enactment of past thought, then metaphysics is
the re-enactment of past thought. But then, "reenactment" must
be taken in the sense that Collingwood meant for it, which does
not rule out critical thinking, as we have already seen.
651

that it rests on the central insight of his entire philosophy of

mind as a resolution of the realist-idealist dilemma (this will

occupy us in the two succeeding sections).

The preliminary sketch is presented as much by example

as by general description. The historian who sets himself the

task of understanding the Theodosian Code not only undertakes to

understand the document that he has inherited from the past,

i.e. the written words, but also to discover what the person who

wrote them meant by them, where the latter task also entails

envisaging for oneself the situation with which the emperor was

trying to deal: "he must see for himself, just as if the

emperor's situation were his own, how such a situation might be

dealt with; he must see the possible alternatives, and the

reasons for choosing one rather than another; and thus he must

go through the process which the emperor went through in

deciding this particular course" (IH, 283). Until he is able to

do this Collingwood insists that he cannot say that he has any

historical knowledge of the meaning of the edict.

In this description we have all the elements with which

we have become familiar--the original historical event with its

outside (the written code) and inside (the emperor's intentional

meanings), the representation of this event in the historian's

understanding by
652

re-thinking the universal element (the meaning of the code

as-understood by its author), and the necessity of

reconstructing that thought by understanding the context in

which it occurred (the emperor's situation with its possible

alternatives) and the agent's reasons for choosing this mode of

action rather than another (the emperor's choice of a legal code

to establish order rather than the use of military force under

his direct command, for example). Notice that this sort of

thinking is concrete (it never loses sight of its point of

reference--the decision of the emperor expressed in the written

code) at the same time that it is universal (it is concerned

throughout with the meaning of the code as a work of human

intelligence and purpose). Notice also that it proceeds by

locating its universal elements (the array of alternative

meaningful acts available in the situation the emperor was

facing). Are these not the embodiment of what we have

encountered in previous chapters as the "concrete universal"

(Speculum Mentis) or "categorical universal" (Essay on

Philosophical Method) in the first case, and the doctrine we

called "concrete abstraction" (from The New Leviathan) in the

second?

Although we have not yet examined the grounds for Col-

lingwood's remark that it is only on the condition that history

is the re-enactment of past thought that historical un-

derstanding is possible, we get a glimmering of his meaning in

this brief description. When he writes


653

that unless and until the event can be reconstructed, it cannot

be said to be historically understood at all, he is saying that

re-enactment is the necessary and sufficient condition for

thinking historically: necessary because without thinking out

the meaning of the event in its context of situational

alternatives, the significance of the event as historical (i.e.

as the action expressing the intentions of an agent) is

impossible to grasp; and sufficient because once that is done

nothing further is necessary--so that "historical explanation"

by subsumption of the event under a law governing other similar

events, as if it were a natural occurrence abstractly like

others of a class, marks the point at which the event loses both

its individuality as this event at this time (viz. the emperor's

situation) and its concrete significance (why the emperor chose

this course of action rather than another).

No doubt this leaves many loose ends, only some of which

we shall gather together in succeeding sections. A1though we

have not yet seen how Collingwood avoids the errors of the

idealist's view of history as he moves in his accustomed way

within the realism-idealism polarity, we foresee that unless he

expands on the role of the historian in viewing events a tergo,

and therefore capable of seeing more in them than did the

historical agent himself, his doctrine of re-enactment is in

danger of
654

appearing as nothing more than a repetition of the thoughts of

historical protagonists.9 In emphasizing the role of thought in

both the historical event and the historiographical re-enactment

Collingwood may have succeeded in damaging the realist's notion

of events unaffected by thinking, but he has done this by

emphasizing the way in which thoughts of agents and historians

are the same, which leaves the serious problem of how they

differ. This difference is apparent in their respective

linguistic modes of address: Caesar says, "I shall cross the

Rubicon;" the historian writes, Caesar said that he would cross

the Rubicon." He is aware of his own thought as distinct from

that of Caesar.

What is required is the doctrine of "encapsulation"

which the Autobiography would have us believe he had worked out

as the third "proposition" concerning history (A, 114), but

which is not mentioned by that name at all in The Idea of

History. If Encapsulation refers to the manner in which the

historian preserves a past thought within his own consciousness

without losing its aspect as past, and if this requires initial

__________________________
9 J. B. Bury could retrospectively see, for example,
that the Theodosian code and the founding of a university at
Constantinople were the two most important acts of Theodosius
II, because Bury saw in them the foundation that held civili-
zation together in the Eastern empire, while the Western fell
under successive invasions by barbarian tribes (A History of the
Later Roman Empire, quoted in The Historian's History of the
World, ed. Henry Smith Williams (New York, 1907), vol.VII, p.
45). It is unlikely that such an event was anticipated by
Theodosius, who nevertheless did not write the code--it was the
work of a committee of nine named by him for the purpose.
655

self-awareness, then it is clearly a function of what he calls

the a priori historical imagination, the notion of which we must

therefore consider next, bearing in mind that what Collingwood

must do is define the sense in which the historian's thought

retains its autonomy vis-a-vis the object of his historical

consciousness.

(e) The A-Priori Imagination.--Just as in the Kantian

critical philosophy, Collingwood felt that the first phase in

answering the question, "How is historical knowledge possible?"

is to show that there is a form of consciousness able to

re-present or re-think past thoughts, but not as simple

perception nor as memory nor even as abstract reasoning. From

our survey of Collingwood's philosophy of mind we know that any

sort of conscious re-presentation requires the functioning of

imagination. The topic of the historical imagination was chosen

by Collingwood as the subject of his Innaugural Lecture on being

appointed to the post of Waynflete Professor of Metaphysics in

1935, the text of that lecture being published by Knox as the

second Epilegomenon in The Idea of History.

We have already pointed out that while the first Ep-

ilegomenon (also a public lecture) is aimed at rejecting the

errors of contemporary realists concerning a "science of human

nature" on the natural model; the second is just as concerned

with correcting the errors of idealists on the subject--notably

those of Bradley. Collingwood praised Bradley as the


656

leader of the movement in England away from the positivistic

accumulation of facts and towards "scientific history," i.e.

history as a form of knowledge aware of itself as distinct from

natural science and yet valid in its own right (IH, 134-35). But

in his essay, The Presuppositions of Critical History 1O Bradley

mistakenly assumed that the criterion of history is experience

as informed by the knowledge of the laws of nature--a relic of

the positivism he sought to overcome. Induction of laws of

nature from observation can never give anything more than

probable laws, which fails to serve as a universal criterion for

what can or cannot happen in history, since much of history

deals with improbabilities (IH, 139). Collingwood points out

that Bradley's proposed criterion (a) does not adequately

distinguish history from fiction, since it claims to decide not

what did happen but only what could happen--which applies

equally well to fictitious narratives. (b) It leaves the

historian completely reliant on authorities, so long as their

accounts satisfy the negative criterion of being possible, which

hence leaves critical historiography unachieved. Finally, (c) it

leaves the historian unable to accept any unusual or improbable

experience not consistent with his own--e.g. odd social customs,

heroic deeds, improbable events, etc. (IH, 239-40; cf. IH, 139).

____________________
1O Recently reissued with introduction and commentary by
Lionel Rubinoff: Quadrangle Books (Chicago, 1968).
657

The thrust of Collingwood's Waynflete Inaugural Lecture

is therefore to propose an alternative criterion to that offered

by Bradley. It takes the form of an autonomous activity of

historical imagination different from perception (aisthesis) on

the one hand and scientific understanding (noesis) on the other,

and yet not reducible to the sort of history proposed by "common

sense" realists. Collingwood begins by distinguishing history

from perception, primarily to show that accounts of knowledge

that are based on the model of perception (e.g. the acquaintance

theory) make history impossible.

No doubt, historical thought is in one way like perception.


Each has for its proper object something individual . . . .
But what I perceive is always the this, the here, the now .
. . . Historical thought is of something which can never be
a this, because it is never a here and now. Its objects are
events which have finished happening, and conditions no
longer in existence. Only when they are no longer
perceptible to they become objects for historical thought.
Hence all theories of knowledge that conceive it as a
transaction or relation between a subject and an object
both actually existing, and confronting or compresent to
one another, theories that take acquaintance as the essence
of knowledge, make history impossible. (IN, 233).

We have been told in Part IV of The Idea of History that the

acquaintance theory of knowledge accepted one horn of the di-

lemma that Bradley bequeathed to his English successors: "either

reality is the immediate flow of subjective life, in which case

it is subjective but not objective, it is enjoyed but cannot be

known, or else it is that which we know, in which case it is

objective and not subjective, it is a world of real things

outside the subjective life of our mind and outside each other"
658

(IH, 141). Bradley accepted the former horn and realists (Cook

Wilson and Oxford realism on the one hand and Bertrand Russell

and Cambridge realism on the other) embraced the latter (IH,

141-42). Collingwood writes that Samuel Alexander admirably

expressed the acquaintance theory when he wrote that knowledge

is a relation between two things, a mind and its object, and the

mind therefore does not know itself, it only enjoys itself.

Collingwood hastens to add that such a view makes history as the

self-knowledge of mind (i.e. the philosophical concept of

history) impossible (IH, 142).

But notice that while he rejects this view he does not

deny that the object of history is something individual; he

merely neglects to tell us what that individuality is. We have

already found this designated as the individual meaning of an

historical event expressive of the thought of an agent He is

also not denying that there is some sense in which the objects

of history are events which are present, viz. as evidence. To

adopt a terminology that is not Collingwood's, evidence is not

something in itself, it is only evidence for another, i.e. for

an historian who recognizes it as such, so in this sense

historical evidence is not something co-present with a mind, but

is rather something dependent on it.

If it is not "aisthesis" historical knowledge is also

not "noesis," and in countering the latter Collingwood opposes


659

another tendency, one more prevalent today, in the guise of the

covering law model" of Popper and Hempel,ll than it was even in

Collingwood's day. Collingwood rejects the thesis that

historical events are "explained" like natural events by

deducing them from antecedent conditions and general laws.

In another way history resembles science: for in each of


them knowledge is inferential or reasoned. But whereas
science lives in a world of abstract universals, which are
in one sense everywhere and in another nowhere, in one
sense everywhere and in another nowhere, in one sense at
all times and in another at no time, the things about which
the historian reasons are not abstract but concrete, not
universal but individual, not indifferent to space and time
but having a where and when of their own, though the where
need not be here and the when cannot be now. History,
therefore, cannot be made to square with theories according
to which the object of knowledge is abstract and
changeless, a logical entity towards which the mind may
take up various attitudes. (IH, 234).

Notice again that Collingwood is not saying that history is not

reasoned or inferential, but that its subject matter is not

something abstract: it is something concrete and individual, an

act performed at a certain time and place. Later in this chapter

we shall examine what Collingwood understands by both historical

evidence and historical inference, but here we need to recognize

only that historical understanding is neither "aisthesis" nor

noesis" nor a combination of the two, but rather "a third

thing," i.e. "wholly reasoned knowledge of what is transient and

concrete" (IH, 234).

________________________
1l See Theories of History, ed. by Patrick Gardiner (New
York, 1959) pp. 276~85, 344-56, 428-43.
660

Such a view of historical thinking also breaks with the

"common sense" view of history, in which memory and belief in

authoritative testimony are taken as the essential functions of

the historian's thought. The scientific historian does not

merely repeat his acquaintance with the events first perceived

by a witness, then remembered, recollected, and repeated to

someone else and believed to be true. The contemporary historian

is aware that he must tamper with his authorities by selecting

what he considers important in the accounts of his authorities,

by interpolating in them things which are not explicitly said,

and by criticizing, rejecting, or amending what he recognizes to

be misinformation or outright falsehood (IH, 235). In this work

of selection, construction, and criticism the historian exhibits

his own autonomy, showing that his thought possesses "a

criterion to which his so-called authorities must conform and by

reference to which they are criticized" (IH, 236). And in all

three of these functions he gives evidence of the working of an

autonomous or a priori imagination--that is, a form of

consciousness that is a priori in the Kantian sense of being

indispensable or necessary (IH, 240).

Collingwood's portrait of the functions of the a priori

imagination is interesting for the light it sheds on the cri-

tical aspects of historical re-enactment. He points out that

historical imagination differs from two other functions of a

priori imagination, namely artistic


661

and perceptual imagination, not in being a priori, since the

artist's work has its own inner necessity, and in perception one

cannot help supplementing the "data" of perception by presenting

objects of possible perception which are not actually perceived

(e.g. the underside of a table, the back of a cube, the inside

of an unopened egg--imaginative functions well analyzed by

Kant), but "in having as its special task to imagine the past:

not an object of our thought" (IH, 242).

In this exercise the historian stretches his web of

imaginative re-construction between points which are at first

assumed to be fixed--the statements of "authorities" he uses as

his sources (IH, 242). But on analysis these fixed points also

resolve themselves into achievements of historical thinking

itself; statements first accepted as settled for the purposes of

a given inquiry are themselves called into question in other

contexts (IH, 244). It then appears that the fixed points are

not accepted facts or authoritative statements but criteria used

to justify the use of such authorities. But Collingwood insists

that these criteria are also provided by the a priori historical

imagination.

The a priori imagination which does the work of historical


construction supplies the means of historical criticism as
well. Freed from its dependence on fixed points supplied
from without, the historian's picture of the past is thus
in every detail an imaginary picture, and its necessity is
at every point the necessity of the a priori imagination.
Whatever goes into it, goes into it not because
662

his imagination passively accepts it, but because it


actively demands it. The resemblance here between the
historian and the novelist . . . here reaches its culmin-
ation. Each of them makes it his business to construct a
picture which is partly a narrative of events, partly a
description of situations, exhibition of motives, analysis
of characters. Each aims at making his picture a coherent
whole . . . . The novel and the history must both of them
make sense; nothing is admissible in either except what is
necessary, and the judge of this necessity is in both cases
the imagination . . . . Where they differ is that the
historian's picture is meant to be true. (IH, 245-46).12

With the raising of the issues of historical coherence

and truth it is clear that we have passed beyond discussing the

concept of history as a scale of forms. Collingwood immediately

points out that "being true" in this context means that the

historian abides by three "rules of method" in the construction

of his historical narrative: (1) his picture of the past must be

localized in space and time (i.e. it must refer to a

_____________________
12 Collingwood has been accused of emphasizing the ac-
tive role of the historian to the neglect of his passive func-
tion of relating received narratives--see W. B. Gallie,
Philosophy and the Historical Understanding (New York, 1964),
pp. 18-19. But Collingwood anticipated this objection. "The his-
torian, generally speaking, works at a subject which others have
studied before him. In proportion as he is more of a novice,
either in this particular subject or in history as a whole, his
forerunners are, relatively to his incompetence, authorities;
and in the limiting case where his incompetence and ignorance
were absolute, they could be called authorities without
qualification. As he becomes more and more master of his craft
and his subject, they become less and less his authorities, more
and more his fellow students, to be treated with respect or
contempt according to their deserts" (IH, 238). As the above
passage also makes clear, Collingwood's use of the term
"picture" of the past (part of which consists in a narrative of
events) is obviously a synonym for Gallie's "narrative;" cf. IH,
242, 245.
663

particular time and place); (2) it must be consistent with

itself; and (3) it must stand in a relation to evidence such

that the evidence, consisting of something here and now

perceptible (written documents, artifacts, ruins, etc.), can be

bound to the events by chains of historical inference (IH,

246-47). All three of these are rules to which the novelist need

not subscribe, and all three are criteria which are nowhere

"given" to the historian along with his "facts." They are not

among the statements of his authorities, but are rather criteria

for accepting such statements as "historical" in the first

place. They are, like Kantian categories, conditions for the

possibility of there being historical data at all.

Several comments are in order here. First, Collingwood

calls these three statements "rules of method," but it is clear

that they are presuppositions of historical inquiry rather than

procedural imperatives. They stand, relative to all progressive

questions in an historical inquiry, as their ultimate

presuppositions, and they are revealed only when the direction

of the inquiry is reversed. The question of who was the victor

of the battle of Waterloo arises only on the presupposition

(among others) that there was such a battle at a certain time

and place, as indicated by interpretation of certain evidence.

But if the historian were challenged (perhaps by a novelist who

is free to cancel the event in his imagination and pursue the

dramatic consequences) to state his reasons for


664

assuming that there was such a battle he would haul out his

evidence and begin constructing an elaborate argument aimed at

the conclusion that it did indeed occur. Now it would take

considerable Socratic cheek to force out the further question

about why he presumes that a battle must either have occurred or

not occurred, but if the interlocutor managed to do so, and in

the process completely reversing the direction of the inquiry,

the historian would (if he replied at all) say that history must

after all make "sense" (i.e. be consistent with itself). He

would, in short, be driven to display his presuppositions.

Secondly, it is noteworthy that these presuppositions

occur in a discussion of the autonomous a priori imagination,

even though it involves the relationship between propositions,

questions, and presuppositions, and involves the necessary re-

lations between them. This is not accidental; it is what he

means when he says that "the a priori imagination which does the

work of historical construction supplies the means of historical

criticism itself" (IH, 245), and it is what is involved when he

insists that in his thought the historian is engaging in an

autonomous activity of a priori imagination (IH, 249). This

confirms what we suggested earlier, that the functions of

imagination are not limited to the conceptual level of mental

acts, or to the pre-propositional level of linguistic

expression, but extend to higher intellectual functions as well.


665

Thirdly, they are a priori criteria, and this term ap-

pears to encompass a number of meanings. Insofar as historical

imagination is a priori it is said to be something not em-

pirically received (IH, 248) but rather "innate" or original to

the mind (IH, 247); it is not arbitrary, but necessary-something

clear, rational, and universal (IH, 240, 242, 248-49); it is a

criterion brought to bear in judgments concerning matters of

fact or evidence, and is used in interpolations and

constructions about these matters of fact (IH, 138, 240-41,

248); it is an original and fundamental activity of mind itself,

and is therefore a self-determining, self-justifying,

self-dependent form of thought (IH, 247, 249); and yet the

principles it employs are not finally fixed, but are capable of

change (IH, 248).

Finally, we must note that in The Idea of History we are

left largely unenlightened about the exact relationship between

historical presuppositions and the a priori imagination. We do

not know if the presuppositions of history can be regarded as a

priori in the same sense that historical imagination is, or if

on the contrary they can be regarded as products of the latter

(and hence at least in this sense posterior to its activity). It

is not difficult to see that if history is to be an autonomous

science, its presuppositions must be clear and rational,

universal and necessary (in some senses of these terms

acceptable to Collingwood). It is also clear that they are not

empirically received and


666

that they are used as criteria in the judgments of history

concerning matters of fact. But we do not know in what sense

Collingwood sees them as "innate" or original to the mind, or

how they are part of a self-determining, self-justifying,

self-dependent form of thought.

Nor is this an extraneous issue for Collingwood's

philosophy of history. We noted at the beginning of this section

that in this essay one of Collingwood's major goals was to state

the "criteria" of history alternative to those proposed by

Bradley (IH, 238-89). The criteria he proposes turn out to be

strangely enigmatic. On the one hand he says that the criterion

of historical truth is "the idea of history itself: the idea of

an imaginary picture of the past," which he calls innate in the

Cartesian sense and a priori in the Kantian sense (IH, 248). But

as if he knew that this idea was insufficient to say not only

how that idea differed from that of the novelist (who also has

an "imaginary picture of the past"), but how one uses such an

idea to judge historical evidence, he also proposes his three

"rules of method" or presuppositions of history as a science. It

is only the latter that serves to correct Bradley's earlier

attempt to state such a criterion, and it is only such

presuppositions which can in any real sense be said to "change."

Once again, Collingwood seems to stop just short of the sort of

questions that are"metaphysical"


667

in the sense of being ultimate: how are activities of

imagination responsible for presuppositions or vice versa? How

can presuppositions be both necessary and changeable? Why are

facts and evidence necessary for an "imaginary picture of the

past"?

(f) Re-enactment: Beyond Realism and Idealism.--Although

in Knox's editorialized version of The Idea of History we are

left at this point without direct answers to these questions,

there is an heroic assault on the question that Collingwood

regarded as the ultimate task of a philosophy of history to

answer. Just as Kant in his Prolegomenon assumes that a certain

kind or kinds of knowledge exists and goes on to ask the further

question how it is possible, Collingwood in his Epilegomena

assumes that his survey of historiography in Parts I-IV has

sufficiently demonstrated that historical knowledge exists, and

goes on to ask how it is possible. Hence the fourth

Epilegomenon, entitled "History as Re-enactment of Past

Experience," begins with the question, "How, or on what condi-

tions, can the historian know the past?" (IH, 282). His answer

to this question is his reasoned justification of historical

thinking. In the fourth Epilegomenon this takes the form of a

series of arguments put forward as answers to objections about

re-enactment from realistic and idealistic standpoints.


668

In proceeding sections and chapters we have tried to

indicate why Collingwood believed that historical thinking is

not possible on realistic presuppositions. From his earliest

publications Collingwood maintained that any epistemology which

tried to justify historical knowledge by assimilating it to

perception, as if historical events were present to con-

sciousness in the same manner as perceived objects, overly

concretizes the past and is therefore utterly misleading. In the

second sentence of the present essay he calls our attention once

again to the fact that the past as past simply does not

exist--its events are not present but past: "the past is never a

given fact which we can apprehend empirically by perception"

(IH, 282). Nor does the historian merely repeat what is said by

an eyewitness of the facts, since the facts he is concerned with

are past events mediated by critical evaluation of evidence,

involving inference on the part of the historian --inference

about the value and reliability of his evidence. His knowledge

is not direct or immediate in an empirical or perceptual sense,

but rather is mediated or inferential.

But if the past known by an historian is mediated by

historical thinking, it is not simply absorbed by that thinking,

and in the attempt to preserve historical objectivity we find

Collingwood taking the unusual tack of granting the realistic

devil his due. Collingwood agrees that the past must be

preserved in its aspect as past, and not utterly assimilated


669

into the present. He therefore finds it necessary to take a

stand opposed to views of history offered by some of his

idealistic contemporaries. Although he agrees that a more

fruitful line of inquiry is initiated when it is recognized that

our imaginary picture of the past is an a priori idea, so that

justification of historical thinking takes the form of showing

on what grounds such an idea is possible, he finds himself

unable to accept those proposed by some idealists. We have just

seen why Collingwood rejected Bradley's presuppositions of

critical history as inadequate for grounding scientific history.

In his review of historiography in Parts IIV Collingwood also

criticized idealistic philosophers of history like Croce and

Oakeshott for absorbing the past into the present: by

overemphasizing the role of historical thinking in the

construction of historical narratives they made the past merely

an aspect of the present thinking of the historian (IN, 154-55,

202, 289).

So where the realist is forced, by his assumption that

all true knowledge is based on immediately perceived objects, to

overly concretize the past and underplay the role of historical

thought in re-creating that past, the idealist makes the

complementary error of dissolving the past altogether by

reducing it to an aspect of present consciousness. What makes

the essay we are presently concerned with such a remarkable

piece of thinking is Collingwood's care to avoid both of these

errors. The key to


670

understanding the complex argument of this essay is to bear in

mind that in it he is trying to overcome the dilemma that

Bradley bequeathed to his successors and which, in his treatment

of scientific history in Part IV, Collingwood had singled out as

crucial (IH, 141). His escape from this dilemma takes the form

of three arguments in the fourth Epilegomenon --one overall

argument aimed at overcoming Bradley's dilemma, and two

subsidiary arguments aimed at refuting objections to

re-enactment by realists and idealists respectively. All three

arguments draw on Collingwood's theory of mind and his analysis

of acts of consciousness, and brilliantly illuminate its central

insight.

Since the arguments are complex, and since in the essay

the main argument is reserved until the end, we shall give here

a brief synopsis of all three arguments, and then take them up

again in the order that Collingwood gives them in the text.

Bradley's dilemma, as Collingwood states it, is that

reality is either the flow of subjective life, in which case it

is subjective but not objective, or else it is that which we

know, in which case it is objective but not subjective, a world

of real things outside the subjective life of our minds.

Collingwood answers that historical reality escapes this dis-

junctive description because it is both subjective and objec-

tive. This is so because the object of history is itself

thought, i.e. the intentional


671

meaning of an historical agent expressed as an event localized

in space and time (its "outside") and having an "inside"

consisting of thought. Because this object is thought it can be

re-thought or revived or reenacted in further acts of thought by

the agent himself or by another, e.g. by an historian critically

interpreting evidence.

But to be truly historical a re-enacted thought must be

known to be both the same thought as that of the historical

agent, and yet distinguishable from that of the historian; for

if it were not the same then the historian could never be sure

that he has grasped his object (and hence historical objectivity

would be sacrificed), and if it were not different he could not

distinguish it from his own thought (and the past would be

absorbed into the present thought of the historian). The realist

denies that two acts of thought can be the same (for no two acts

of thought can be literally identical) and the idealist denies

that they can be different. On either premise historical

thinking is impossible.

But an act of thought is not something wholly immediate,

like the flow of consciousness involved in mere feeling. Our

experience as thinkers shows us that an act of thought is

inseparable from its object, i.e. meanings as expressed in

physical acts, statements, arguments, etc. An act of thought is

something someone does deliberately, and it is not irretrievably

carried off in the flow of feelings; on the contrary it is that


672

which has the power to survive and revive over time (two

characteristics of all thought from his philosophy of mind), and

in various contexts. Nor is an act of thought something wholly

mediate, totally dependent on its context for its meaning. An

act of thought is capable of retaining its identity of meaning

in various contexts. Therefore thought is both mediate and

immediate. Historical thought as re-enactment is thus possible

because the historian is concerned with an object which has the

power to revive in other contexts, and the historian has the

power to re-think that thought in the context of his own

thoughts. Historical thinking is therefore both objective (the

historian can distinguish himself from his object because the

object can retain its identity in various thought-contexts) and

subjective (the historian's re-enactment occurs in the context

of his own thinking and he knows it as his own experience).

History is possible because re-enactment of thought is possible,

and re-enactment presupposes an object that is both mediate and

immediate, objective and subjective. Such an object is within

our own experience as thinkers, and such a reality escapes

Bradley's dilemma.

Now one cannot help but notice from this synopsis that

there are several key concepts on which the whole argument is

hinged, and that the success of the argument depends on how

Collingwood handles these concepts.


673

Ultimately, as we shall see, they depend on his description of

the several functions of mental activity. (1) In particular the

success of the argument depends on the meaning of the

expression, "act of thought," and in the first objection to

re-enactment Collingwood calls attention to the controversy

surrounding this phrase. The first objector (invented by

Collingwood, but evidently a realist) assaults re-enactment as

an ambiguous concept which ignores the act-object distinction:

To re-enact an experience or re-think a thought, he might


argue, may mean either of two things. Either it means en-
acting an experience or performing an act of thought re-
sembling the first, or it means enacting an experience or
performing an act of thought literally identical with the
first. But no one experience can be literally identical
with another, therefore presumably the relation intended is
one of resemblance only. But in that case the doctrine that
we know the past by re-enacting it is only a version of the
familiar and discredited copy-theory of knowledge . . . .
In every experience, at any rate so far as it is cognitive,
there is an act and an object; and two different acts may
have the same object . . . . The two acts are different
acts but acts of the same kind. They thus resemble one
another, and . . . hence the conclusion that the doctrine
we are considering is a case of the copy theory of
knowledge. (IH, 283-85).

As an example of a thought that can be re-enacted Collingwood

suggests Euclid's proposition that the angles at the base of an

isosceles triangle are equal l3--which we shall abbreviate as

EP. An objector upholding the

________________________
13 Collingwood's examples are not always felicitous, and
in this case one might, with some justice, accuse him of
choosing a judgment that prejudices the argument by dealing with
mathematical entities. Why not a more typical case like Caesar's
decision to cross the Rubicon? In Collingwood's defense it might
be pointed out that the case is not
674

act-object distinction, he argues, would naturally enough

understand re-enactment as a case of a relation between two

thoughts such that the enacted thought and its re-enactment are

numerically different but specifically identical. Since they

have the same object in mind (EP) they are instances of a single

species or class (the class of all instances of EP); but since

they occurred at two different times or to two different

persons, they are numerically different. But this is not the

only sort of identity-in-difference relation that can exist

between mental acts, and in order to demonstrate another variety

of this relation Collingwood suggests considering three cases:

Case 1: I think EP for five seconds continuously.

Case 2: I think EP for five seconds continuously, then


cease thinking about it for three seconds, then
think EP.

Case 3: Euclid thinks EP and after a lapse of several


centuries I think EP.

Collingwood argues on the basis of the first case that the unity

of the

____________________
exceptional, since an historian of geometry could very well be
rethinking EP in rethinking Euclid's contribution, and in Col-
lingwood's view, intellectual history is just what history
is--all history is the history of thought. Furthermore the
example is chosen for its appeal to just those who regard ma-
thematical propositions as exemplary of the act-object dis-
tinction (Frege, Russell, etc.). Finally, it would not be
difficult to rephrase the argument using an example of a more
recognizably typical historical act instead of EP, as he does in
the fourth Epilegomenon, where he uses the example of the
Theodosian Code.
675

act of thinking EP is not dependent on the duration of time

during which it is thought. "There is no more reason to

correlate the unity of a single act of thought with the

time-lapse of one second, or a quarter of a second, than with

any other. The only possible answer is that the act of thought

is one sustained through five seconds"--that is, it has the

"identity of a continuant" (IH, 286). From the second case

Collingwood concludes that if one is to say that EP is the same

act of thought then one is forced to say that the act of thought

is not merely sustained, but revived after an interval.

(Presumably, to deny this would involve one in an infinite

regress similar to Plato's "third man" argument.)

Now where the act-object distinction fails adequately to

describe the sort of experiences we have as thinkers in the

first two cases, its defenders would argue that the third dif-

fers significantly from the previous two, and for this case

Collingwood puts forward his anti-realist argument in the mo-

dified form in which we stated it in Chapter VII:

The objector . . . maintains that although the object of


two people's acts of thought may be the same, the acts
themselves are different. But in order that this should be
said, it is necessary to know "what someone else is
thinking" not only in the sense of knowing the same object
that he knows, but in the further sense of knowing the act
by which he knows it: for the statement rests on a claim to
know not only my own act of knowing but someone else's
also, and compare them. But what makes such comparison
possible? Anyone who can perform the comparison must be
able to reflect "my act of knowledge is this"-and then he
repeats it: "from the way he talks, I can see that his act
676

is this:--and then he repeats it. Unless that can be done,


the comparison can never be made. But to do this involves
the repetition by one mind of another's act of thought: not
one like it (that would be the copy theory of knowledge
with a vengeance) but the act itself. (IH, 288).

Therefore in order to affirm that the third case is not like the

first two, one would have to presuppose that one simultaneously

claimed to deny, i.e. that one act of thought can be shared by

two different people separated by a span of time. Collingwood

concludes that thought can never be a mere object, since to know

what someone is thinking or has thought involves thinking it for

oneself, and to deny that this is possible is to back onself

into a solipsistic corner in which it only possible to think

one's own thoughts (IH, 288-89). Collingwood is content to leave

his realistic objector parked in this corner.

Before taking up the objection to re-enactment by the

idealist, we would like to pause for several observations about

the course of this argument so far.

Notice first that Collingwood does not further pursue

the issue of abstract universality (specific identity with nu-

merical difference), nor does the argument based on the three

cases of re-enacting acts of thought really depend for its

conclusion on this incomplete discussion. What Collingwood left

unsaid was that the kind of identity-in-difference that is

involved in re-enactment is a case wherein the second thought is

not
677
merely a copy of the first, nor is it another replacement

instance of the class of thoughts that includes the first, but

rather the second includes the first as part of its content. It

is almost trivially true to note that when as an historian I

assert "Euclid thought that EP" the second proposition (HP)

includes the first (EP) as part of its content. What Collingwood

is trying non-trivially to point out is that when someone asks

how this expression is possible and answers it, as the realist

does, by denying that the EP used in the first assertion can be

identical to the EP mentioned in HP, he has explicitly

contradicted himself.14

But of course the realist does not assert that they are

unqualifiedly not identical, but only that they are not

identical acts of thought; they are identical in having iden-

tical objects. Therefore Collingwood bears down on the phrase

"set of thought," and our second observation pertains to this

phrase. When the realist insists on the abstract distinction

between an act of thought and its object he opens himself to the

criticism that the act of thought as a mere event has no direct

relationship to the object of the act, and Collingwood's

______________________
14 Collingwood gives no indication that he is cognizant
of the use-mention distinction as such, but the argument ad-
dressed to the realist objector presumes that the historian
thinking HP does not merely mention EP but also uses it in the
sense of enacting the proposition for himself. Although the
historian is not using EP to make a geometrical point as part of
a systematic inquiry in that subject, he must understand it
sufficiently to grasp its meaning for the development of geo-
metry, the history of which he is narrating.
678

strategy is to call attention to this epistemic gap and its

necessary presupposition that somehow the event and the object

both belong to the same thought. In the ensuing argument with

the idealist objector Collingwood will make an equivalent and

complimentary point about the object of an act of thought, and

displaying the unity of these two sides to thought--as an act

and as an object--is the way in which he resolves the Bradleyan

dilemma.

Thirdly, we wish to note in passing that Collingwood

appears to be employing the sort of argument that he had char-

acterized as philosophical in the Essay on Philosophical Method.

Even though the argument is incomplete at this point we are

aware that, for example in the three cases of a reenacted

thought, a conclusion (the impossibility of re-enactment) is

being checked by comparing it to experiences that should

anticipate it (the three cases of our experience as thinkers);

and the principle from which the conclusion is drawn (the

act-object distinction) is as a premise being revised (it is

not, as an abstractly universal principle, defensible vis-a-vis

our actual or concrete thinking, and is in need therefore of

revision). We are witnessing an argument in the process of

reversing itself (revision of the act-object distinction)--not

an abstract reductio ad absurdum that merely negates a premise,

but one which aims at revising a starting point in the light of

its conclusions so that it can explain


679

how experience as it actually exists is alone possible (EPM,

156). How the premise is revised we are about to see.

Finally we have to call attention to Collingwood's

phrasing of the anti-realist argument in the quotation above,

where he says that the assumption that two acts of thought can-

not be the same rests on the ability of the objector to perform

a comparison which involves asserting in addition to one's own

act the further one, that "from the way he talks, I can see that

his act is this" which he then repeats (IH, 288). Is there not

some significant qualification overlooked in this deceptively

simple argument, and is this not disguised under the simple

phrase, "from the way he talks I can see that . . . ."? It

appears that I can know what I mean by an act of thought, my own

thought, by simply repeating it and examining it; calling it an

"act of thought" in the context of Collingwood's philosophy of

mind precisely means that it is something that I can do on

purpose--it is an achievement. But how is it possible to achieve

someone else's act of thought, or do his thinking "on purpose"?

It seems I can only know what someone else means by his act of

thought by interpreting what he says he means, and in that

interpretation I may be mistaken, since meaning for Collingwood

is intentional. Can I miss another's intention in a way that I

cannot miss my own?

We must keep this in mind as we proceed, but if there is

an assumption here it is the same assumption that is made,

Collingwood would
680

surely say, in re-thinking my own thoughts, since I may be

mistaken in interpreting my present intentional meaning as the

same one I had several moments ago. Collingwood's point is that

to say that it is not the same is to presume that one knows what

that act was, i.e. "not this," and for that difference to be

sustainable one must see it as a meaning difference, one

graspable by a comparing act of thought which holds both

together and declares them to be non-identical or different in

some discernible or meaningful fashion. The mere temporal

counting is not a meaningful difference between EP as thought by

Euclid and as re-thought by me. To say it is the same meaning is

to say something essential about the act of thought, not its

accidental temporal correlation.

Nonetheless, one wishes to persist against Collingwood,

is there not some significant difference in the fact that Euclid

thinks EP and I think EP? For this we turn to the next phase of

the argument.

(2) Having disposed of one aspect of the act-object

distinction, Collingwood proceeds to take up the cudgels against

the idealist objector to re-enactment. Where the realist would

claim that re-enactment proved too little (because it failed to

show how two acts of thought can be identical), the idealist

would claim that it proved too much.


681

It has shown that an act of thought can be not only per-


formed at an instant but sustained over a lapse of time;
not only sustained but revived; not only revived in the
experience of the same mind but (on pain of solipsism) re-
enacted in another 's. But this does not prove the possi-
bility of history. For that, we must be able not only to
re-enact another's thought but also to know that the
thought we are re-enacting is his. But so far as we reenact
it, it becomes our own; it is merely as our own that we
perform it and are aware of it in the performance; it has
become subjective, but for that very reason it has ceased
to be objective; become present, and therefore ceased to be
past. (IH, 289).

In order to leave no doubt in the reader's mind that this is an

idealistic objection, Collingwood points out that this is just

what leading idealistic philosophers of history were maintaining

when they asserted that history is one's own experience arranged

sub specie praeteritorum (Oakeshott) and that all history is

contemporary history (Croce) (cf. IN, 151-59, 190-204).

What is at issue here is the very past-ness of the past.

Collingwood is willing to grant the idealist's demand that in

order for a re-enacted thought to be historical it must be known

that it was thought not only by myself but originally by the

historical agent. Propositionally this is the demand that the

difference between the assertions of EP and HP must be

preserved, since merely to re-think EP would be to think

geometrically rather than historically. Collingwood goes even

further down the path toward idealism insofar as he affirms that

thinking historically is a self-conscious process: "unless he

knows that he is thinking historically, he is not thinking

historically. Historical thinking


682

is an activity . . . which is a function of self-consciousness,

a form of thought possible only to a mind which knows itself to

be thinking in that way" (IH, 289). This much he had to admit on

the grounds of his own philosophy of mind, which argued that

reflective thought is criteriological, i.e. contains within

itself the criterion for judging itself to be a successful or

unsuccessful piece of thinking.

But Collingwood insists that the idealist objector is

making a second point, that this necessary condition for his-

torical knowledge cannot be fulfilled if historical thinking is

re-enactment because re-thinking a thought for oneself prevents

one from recognizing it as another 's. On the basis of our

abbreviated propositions, the idealist appears to be saying that

because one asserts EP one cannot also assert HP, because

thinking EP prevents one from doing so (in becoming my thought

it becomes subjective and therefore ceases to be objective or

something shared with someone else). Collingwood adds that if

the idealist were maintaining that one of the conditions for

historical knowledge to occur is that the historian first

mistakes his agent's thinking for his own and then overcomes

this error by recognizing that his own thought is distinguished

from that of Euclid's, then it might be of interest as showing

one way that re-enactment could be a pre-condition for

historical thought. "But the re-enactment of past thought is not

a pre-condition
683

of historical knowledge, but an integral element in it; the

effect of the ((idealist's)) contention, therefore, is to make

such knowledge impossible" (IH, 290).15 If we cannot know

ourselves to be engaged in re-enacting the thought of historical

agents, we cannot be said to be thinking historically, and the

idealist's contention is that we cannot have such knowledge.

Collingwood sees the objection as hinging on the

impossibility of an act of thought being both subjective and ob-

jective. Being subjective means being aware of an experience as

my own; therefore, since "experience" may mean several things,

"being aware of an experience"

_____________________
15 Collingwood is here tacitly rejecting the view he
held in Speculum Mentis concerning the way in which the mind
attains to truth. In the earlier work he argued that history,
like all other forms of experience, proceeds through the via
dolorosa of error to truth. "The progressive alienation of the
mind from its object is in history complete. The world is
triumphantly unified as ((an individual, concrete, infinite))
object, only to find itself separated from the mind by a gulf
which no thought can traverse. But in this process, which seems
to travel at every step further from that intimacy of subject
with object which constitutes knowledge, the indispensable
condition of knowledge is progressively and inversely realized .
. . . For an infinite given whole of fact cannot at any point be
grasped by the mind." (SM, 238-39). Although he adds that this
gulf is bridged from both sides (which foreshadows a doctrine
about evidence in The Idea of History, as we shall see), these
passages seem to point to the zero-line of complete scepticism,
saved only (so the early Collingwood thinks) by the existence of
absolute knowledge. But in The Idea of History in general,
Collingwood gives not the slightest indication that re-enactment
is an exercise of the "absolute standpoint," or that absolute
idealism had found the solution to the problem of necessary
historical error. Cf. Rubinoff, CRM, 292-306.
684

is also an equivocal expression. It may mean (1) the immediate

feeling of something such as a pain; or (2) the perception of

objects; or (3) the self-conscious awareness that is involved in

acts like being aware of losing one's temper--the third sense

being the most proper English use of the term (IH, 291). We here

recognize Collingwood's analysis of consciousness as a scale of

forms of mental acts. In this case he is interested in the sense

of the term "awareness" as it applies to historical knowledge,

where at least that degree of self-consciousness must be present

which allows the historian to distinguish his own thought from

that of the historical agent he is studying. Historical thought

must have at least that degree of subjectivity that allows one

to recognize an act of thought as not merely an experience, but

my experience; and it must have that degree of objectivity that

allows one to recognize this same act of thought as having a

certain cognitive character, a determinate meaning, etc. (IH,

291). Collingwood's justification of this kind of thinking takes

the form of exploring the contradictions that arise from

attempting to deny that a thought can be both subjective and

objective.

Indeed to say that would be to contradict oneself. ((1)) To


say that an act of thought cannot be objective is to say
that it cannot be known; but anyone who said this would be
claiming thereby to state his knowledge of such acts. ((2))
He must therefore modify it, and will perhaps say that one
act of thought may be an object to another act, but not to
itself. But this again needs modification, for any object
is properly the object not of an act but of an agent, the
685

mind that performs the act. True, a mind is nothing except


its own activities, but it is all these activities
together, not any one separately. ((3)) The questions is,
then, whether a person who performs an act of knowing can
also know that he is performing or has performed that act.
Admittedly he can, or no one would know that there were
such acts, and so no one could have called them subjective;
but to call them merely subjective, and not objective too,
is to deny that admission while yet continuing to assume
its truth. (IH, 291-92).

Notice that in both (l) and (3) Collingwood tacitly

appeals to his anti-realism argument and uses it against an

idealist objector--thus supporting Post's suggestion that the

argument cuts both ways. But the "together" in (2) calls for

special comment, since it is revealing about Collingwood's grasp

of the relationship between individual acts of consciousness and

the contexts in which they occur. In Collingwood's philosophy of

mind it is axiomatic that "thought is not mere immediate

experience but always reflection or self-knowledge, the

knowledge of oneself as living in these activities" (IH, 297)--a

principle quite contrary to any view of conscious acts which

attempts to analyze them as atomically distinct from one

another. Nevertheless, Collingwood insists, they do retain a

certain identity. Although an act of thought occurs at a given

time, and in a context of certain other acts of thought, of

emotions and sensations and memories, etc., the peculiarity of

thought is that it can sustain itself through a change of

context and revive in a different one. As true as it may be that

the immediacy of thought in its given context cannot be

re-enacted, the self-identity of an act of thinking is


686

independent not only of its context of feelings and emotions but

also its context of other thoughts.

This has sometimes been denied. It has been said that


anything torn from its context is thereby mutilated and
falsified . . . . Others . . . have embraced the opposite
doctrine that makes it both easy and legitimate to detach
them from their context; for there is no context; there is
only a juxtaposition of things standing to one another in
merely external relations. On this view, the unity of a
body of knowledge is only that kind of unity which belongs
to a collection: and this is true both of science, or
system of things known, and of a mind, or system of acts of
knowing. (IH, 298-99).

We do not have to be told that the view that holds that

"anything torn from its context is thereby mutilated and

falsified" is that of the idealists from which Collingwood

wishes to distinguish himself. In criticizing this view he

indicates as plainly as one might expect that he could no longer

affirm a view accepted in unregenerate days by himself (cf. IH,

299)--for this in fact is the position he maintained in Speculum

Mentis, where abstraction and falsification are identified.16

But notice

__________________________
Cf. Rubinoff, CRM, 112-13, 147-49, 297-99. Rubinoff
recognizes the problem of the difference between Speculum
Mentis, in which history is a knowledge of facts independent of
mind and therefore abstract and false, and The Idea of History,
in which history is the "knowledge of a part of mind itself"
(CRM, 297). But Rubinoff's solution strikes us as fantastic and
ungrounded: he sees both works as part of his grand scheme of
the "three ontological levels of consciousness" and therefore
bound together in the necessity of "the dialectic." He writes:
"This dialectical requirement is a result of the inherent
contradiction which . . . pervades the whole of Speculum Mentis,
between the presuppositions of realism (for which there is a
distinction between subject and object) and the presuppositions
of idealism (for which this distinction is overcome). When this
conflict is dialectically resolved, consciousness elevates itself
687
that he immediately castigates the opposite view that all acts

of thought are atomically distinct from one another. He writes

that such a view "by substituting logical analysis for attention

to experience overlooks the immediacy of thought, and converts

the act of thinking, from a subjective experience, into an

objective spectacle" (IH, 299).17 Whatever Collingwood's

familiarity was with logical atomism and

___________________________
to the third ontological level of existence. Once having arrived
at this level, history reconstitutes itself, this time under the
influence of philosophy which is the final consummation of the
rapprochement between subject and object" (CRM, 298). Aside from
the unrestricted use of the misleadingly florid language of
Hegelianism in passages like this one (in talk about the
dialectic, consciousness elevating itself or arriving somewhere
where history reconstitutes itself and reaches its final
consummation --metaphors inadequately resolved by Rubinoff and
nowhere found in The Idea of History), one wonders why, if
Collingwood had such a scheme in mind, he nowhere said so
explicitly--a remark which Knox, himself a Hegel scholar, would
certainly have passed on to us. We find it more likely that the
reconciliation between idealism and realism which Collingwood,
judging from the essay we are considering, surely aimed to
achieve, did not occur by absorbing the one into the other or
both into the "absolute standpoint (itself an abstraction) or a
"third ontological level" but rather by the correct analysis of
historical thought as the re-enactment of expressions of acts of
thought in which meaning grounds both its subjective and
objective dimensions--its aspects as my experience and as
universally comprehensible language. In fairness to Rubinoff we
must add that on occasion he makes it clear that his "tran-
sition" resolving the "dialectical opposition" between Speculum
Mentis and The Idea of History is his own reconstruction (as at
CRM, 297), but the distinction between Collingwood's assertions
and Rubinoff's reconstruction is not always clearly maintained.

17 Donagan's "Principle of Order" (LPC, 28) commits him,


in our opinion, to interpreting Collingwood's philosophy of mind
in an atomistic fashion, since Donagan appears to take an act of
thought as an event occurring in the mind: in order that it be
an object of consciousness (on Donagan's "Principle of Order")
it requires another act--a second event--of a higher order, for
no act of consciousness is self-illuminating. A literal
adherence to this principle would render
688

its successor, logical positivism (and the Essay on Metaphysics

indicates that he was at least knowledge able with Ayer's

version of the latter, which he traced to its pedigree in John

Stuart Mill--see EM, 143, 163), we know he rejected its approach

not only to historical experience but to the reductionistic

analysis of mental acts as well.

Collingwood's rejection of rigid adherence to either an

atomistic or an equally untenable context-bound view of mental

acts raises once again the problem of "encapsulation" from the

Autobiography. For it appears that not only is the term not used

in The Idea of History, but on the present account of

re-enactment there appears to be no need for a critique (or any

other argument) to "incapsulate" or confine the historical past

from the superficial or obvious present of the historian

_______________________
re-enactment impossible; it is simply epistemological atomism.
We have already argued that Donagan's "Principle of Order" as he
phrases it (a) is an illegitimate modification of what Col-
lingwood has said about the hierarchy of forms of mental acts,
and (b) that it is not itself a tenable principle concerning
mental acts, because it appears to rule out the possibility of
having a concept about concepts, propositions about propositions
(since the act which reflects must be of a higher order). We
wish to add now that (c) it cannot be regarded as a pre-
supposition of Collingwood's entire philosophy of mind, because
it ignores the sort of knowledge Collingwood calls self--
knowledge, the "knowledge of oneself as living in these activi-
ties" of thought (IN, 297), as well as his explicit assertion
that it is by that act itself that one knows that he is per-
forming it (IH, 292). Although Collingwood is saying that it is
the person who knows it, he has stated plainly that the mind of
that person is all the acts of thought together, not separately.
Such a holistic assertion is incompatible with epistemological
atomism.
689

(what might be called by other philosophers the world of the

historian's lived experience or his Lebenswelt). This would be

the attempt to mediate an immediacy, the immediacy of experience

as one's own, or subjective. It appears, in short, to be an

example of what Collingwood called the Fallacy of Misplaced

Argument, since there is no initial confusion between one's own

experience and that of another in the first place, nor is there

any initial loss of identity of the enacted meaning or the

re-enacted thought in its several contexts.

But as Collingwood stated in the Autobiography, in-

capsulation is not an occult entity; it refers to the retention

of an identity of meaning (or what he calls an "unconverted

residue") in more inclusive acts (A, 141)--in our model, the

unaltered presence of EP in HP. Therefore incapsulation is not

excluded from the theory or re-enactment, but is rather its

negative side. It is merely a short-hand way of calling

attention to the necessary bi-valence of all thought (a) as acts

of meaning embedded in the immediate experience of one's own

life and forming part of the continuity of the personal

consciousness of that life, and (b) as capable of retaining an

identity of meaning in other contexts, and especially in the

thoughts of historians. To press the juice from the metaphor,

the "capsule" is the preservation of the objective identity of

meaning (usually the plan of the historical agent in its context


690

of alternatives) from being simply absorbed into the subjective

life of the historian by an awareness that that meaning as

historically re-enacted is not merely the solution to a problem

in the personal life of the historian.

(3) Several pages later Collingwood sums up his major

argument against both realists and idealists and relates them to

Bradley's dilemma:

To disentangle ourselves from these two complimentary er-


rors, we must attack the false dilemma from which they both
spring. That dilemma rests on the disjunction that thought
is either pure immediacy, in which case it is inextricably
involved in the flow of consciousness, or pure mediation,
in which case it is utterly detached from that flow.
Actually it is both immediacy and mediation. Every act of
thought, as it actually happens, happens in a context out
of which it arises and in which it lives, like any other
experience, as an organic part of the thinker's life. Its
relations with its context are not those of an item in a
collection, but those of a special function in the total
activity of an organism. So far not only is the doctrine of
the so-called idealists correct, but even that of the
pragmatists who have developed that side of it to an
extreme. But an act of thought, in addition to actually
happening, is capable of sustaining itself and being
revived or repeated without loss of identity. So far, those
who have opposed the "idealists" are in the right, when
they maintain that what we think is not altered by
alterations of the context in which we think it . . . .
Because it is a thought and not a mere feeling or sensa-
tion, it can exist in both these contexts ((i.e. the con-
text of my own thoughts and those of another)) without
losing its identity, although without some appropriate con-
text it could never exist. (IH, 300-01).

The example that Collingwood uses for a thought that is both

mediate and immediate is Plato's argument in the Theatetus

against the view that knowledge is merely sensation (a pregnant

example, incidentally). The argument as it can be developed

either in Plato's mind or mine or


691

anyone's is what he calls thought in its mediation; the argument

in the context of discussion and theory as Plato placed it in

his own thinking is the thought in its immediacy--i.e. the

immediate thought-context in which Plato conceived it as part of

his own project of thinking out the problem (IH, 301). We assume

for Collingwood that it is possible to re-enact a proposition or

a concept as well as an argument, so that the meaning being

re-enacted extends not only to the inferential but also to the

propositional and conceptual levels of thought as well.

Here we have Collingwood's final reply to both realists

and idealists on the act-object distinction. It rests firmly on

an insight foundational not only to his philosophy of history

but his entire philosophy of mind, the insight that meaning is

the irreducible and indivisible unity of an act of thought, and

that both an act of consciousness and the object of the act are

two aspects to, or contexts for, one and the same entity.

Calling the enactment or re-enactment of a meaning an "act"

means calling attention to its personal. experiential, immediate

presence in the mental life of a person (something that someone

does "on purpose"), whereas calling attention to this same

meaning as social, communicable, and mediate means calling it an

"object" of consciousness. It is not a matter of trying to find

a way of putting together an "event" occurring in the mind, an

event called an "act of


692

consciousness," and an object of such a point-occurrence; they

are two sides to one and the same reality--a meaning whose

identity survives alteration in context and is capable of being

revived (or re-enacted) after a lapse of time. Collingwood's

rejection of both an atomistic realism and an absolute idealism,

as we have just encountered it, does not display any need for an

absolute identity of subject and object, nor does it retreat

into an endless order of acts of consciousness external to and

atomically distinct from one another--neither an absolute

experience nor a schizophrenic hall of mirrors. On the contrary

it takes its stand on the unity of meaning of singular acts of

consciousness, and its ability to survive and revive in various

contexts, so long as that context is part of the life of thought

of someone capable of doing things "on purpose."

But successfully defending re-enactment against attacks

from hypothetical objectors is not the same as demonstrating

that it is the necessary and sufficient condition for historical

thinking, and therefore we have not finished with Collingwood's

demonstration of how history as a science is possible. Suppose

we accept his argument that for history to be possible as

knowledge the past must be capable of being re-thought or

re-enacted, and that re-enactment presupposes an invariance of

meaning in several contexts without loss of experiential imme-

diacy. Is this sufficient to show that historical knowledge is

reliable? Obviously not,


693

since we do not yet know under what conditions we can say that a

re-enactment has been successfully carried out, historical error

being, we presume, possible.

If we return to Collingwood's three presuppositions for

historical thought, we appear to have three candidates for a

possible sufficiency criterion. A historical account may thus be

said to be a successful re-enactment (a) when it refers to human

acts localized in space and time; (b) when it is a coherent

narrative; and (c) when it stands in a relation to evidence such

that it can be bound to historical events by chains of

historical inference. Both (a) and (b) have been more or less

specified by Collingwood: (a) refers to the res gestae that form

the subject matter of history as distinct from the study of

merely physical events in nature; and (b) is a restatement of

the requirement that the subject matter of (a) be handled as

part of a systematic inquiry. But these alone would fail to

distinguish history from good fiction. In order that there be

that degree of certitude necessary to call historical narrative

knowledge, and not the literary expression of someone's artistic

fantasy, there must be a way to decide when (a) succeeds in

actually referring to a publicly accessible past. What

distinguishes history from romance is (c), and to this double

issue of historical evidence and historical inference we must

now turn.
694

3. Evidence, Inference, and Necessity: (a) Historical Evidence.

Why is it a double issue? From our present perspective

this should not be a difficult question to answer. It depends on

the view of history that it being presupposed by someone for

whom evidence is one thing and thought about it is another, and

their conjunction requires an argument. It is the sort of

question which assumes that historical thinking occurs when a

mass of facts, contained in documents called "testimony"

(ultimately resting on eyewitness accounts) is examined with a

view to constructing a written history of the period or event

under consideration. The work of the historian would then be one

of selecting relevant testimonial assertions, arranging these

propositions into a coherent narrative, and engaging in

reasoning only when there is a break in the continuity of the

narrative--conflicting testimony, gaps to be filled, or his-

torical peculiarities which require the intervention of the

narrator to "explain" something unusual to the reader.

This is the historiography that Collingwood disparag-

ingly calls "scissors and paste" (IH, 257), and "evidence" on

this view of history is merely the mass of records or "sources"

pertaining to the period the historian is considering (IN, 278).

In this sort of historical thinking the "data" are thus external

to the mind itself: they are contained in the set of all

relevant documents preserved in archives, libraries, and

museums. The need for inference arises only when various

authorities
695

disagree, and the only issue is whether to accept or reject a

piece of evidence as a true account of what happened. But even

though the audience to which Collingwood's remarks are addressed

is one which assumes that historical thinking and its object are

independent of one another--hence exhibiting the realistic

outlook on the relation of mental acts to their objects--it is

also an audience Collingwood hopes to convince that the role of

historical reasoning is far more intimate and interdependent

than is being presumed.

We can therefore anticipate that in the essay entitled

"Historical Evidence" (a fragment from The Principles of History

and the longest of the seven Epilegomena) his strategy will be

to propose an alternative account of historical reasoning, and

this in fact is what he does. Instead of beginning with a

definition and classification of historical evidence--i.e.

starting out as if one began with a ready-made ob-

ject--Collingwood first characterizes scientific historical

thinking and then describes its special relation to evidence,

where evidence is decidedly the derivative concept. The thrust

of his argument in this essay is to show that history is a

science in the sense of being an organized body of knowledge.

But it is organized in a way different from the exact or

empirical sciences, insofar as it approaches its data and

constructs its conclusions using a kind of inference that is

unique to history and different from that of the other

sciences, while yet being compelling


696

in its conclusions and having a necessity of its own. Evidence

in this schema of historical inference is correlative to the

historian's questioning activity and is not simply a property of

certain sets of propositions. Evidence is not the set of "facts"

which verify or falsify our historical propositions by

"corresponding" to them; it is whatever serves as a locus for

the historian to answer the questions which allow him to

re-enact past acts of thought.

Now although we have made the case in previous chapters

that Collingwood's use of Q-A logic suggests that it is more

favorably compared to a logic of discovery than to a formal

deductive system (in spite of his own misleading rhetoric that

Q-A logic is an "alternative" to F-logic), it is noteworthy that

in the Introduction to The Idea of History when he asks how

history proceeds or what its method is, his answer is not "by

the application of Q-A logic" but rather "by the interpretation

of evidence" (IH, 9-10). Q-A logic appears in the answer to the

first question he asks, i.e. "What is the nature of history?"

the answer to which is "a kind of research or inquiry"--a form

of thought whereby we ask questions and try to answer them (IN,

9). What any science does is to employ Q-A logic; what

historical science does is answer questions by the

interpretation of evidence.
697

Since we already have some idea of what he takes his-

torical thinking to be, it may be well briefly to characterize

what Collingwood has to say about evidence in this and the other

Epilegomena. We recall that the universality of an historical

event is an act expressing an intentional meaning in the context

of an array of situational alternatives confronting an

historical agent, and that this universal meaning is the

individuality sought by the historian who would re-enact the

event. Furthermore in describing the process of re-thinking the

past Collingwood leaves room for a contribution made by the

object--in this case the past thought. In discussing history as

re-enactment in the fourth Epilegomenon, for example, he writes

that "historical knowledge is that special case of memory where

the object of present thought is past thought, the gap between

present and past being bridged not only by the power of present

thought to think of the past, but also by the power of past

thought to reawaken itself in the present" (IH, 294). Nor is

this an isolated remark; it is a recurrent theme in The Idea of

History. In discussing the subject matter of history in the

fifth Epilegomenon we have already quoted the striking passage

where he speaks of the individuality of a particular historical

act being something that "oversteps the limits of merely local

and temporal existence and possesses a significance valid for

all men at all times," and adds that this act transcends its

immediacy because "that


698

individuality is the vehicle of a thought which, because it was

actually theirs, is potentially everyone's" (IH, 303). And in

the second Epilegomenon Collingwood expands further on this

"potential-actual" distinction as it pertains to evidence:

Everything is evidence which the historian can use as evi-


dence. But what can he so use? It must be something here
and now perceptible to him: this written page, this spoken
utterance, this building, this fingerprint. . . . The whole
perceptible world, then, is potentially and in principle
evidence to the historian. It becomes actual evidence in so
far as he can use it ((as evidence on some question)) . . .
. Evidence is evidence only when someone contemplates it
historically. Otherwise it is merely perceived fact,
historically dumb. (IH, 247; cf. 203).

It should be clear at this point why Collingwood begins

a discussion on evidence with a discussion of the nature of

historical thinking: it is the thinking that determines what is

evidence, and not the other way around. It should also be clear

that while historical thinking makes the difference between a

perceived fact being merely that or historical evidence, there

is a contribution being made by the "perceived fact" inasmuch as

it has a "power to re-awaken itself" in the present. Once again

the difference that historical thinking makes to its object is

not creational but constitutional; it does not create the fact

but determines it as evidence. "His business is not to invent

anything, it is to discover something" (IH, 251).

In the third Epilegomenon this useful distinction be-

tween actual and potential evidence is redefined in terms of

scientific history.
699

If history means scissors-and-paste history . . . a source


is a text containing a statement or statements about the
subject . . . . If history means scientific history, for
"source" we must read "evidence." And when we try to define
evidence in the same spirit in which we defined "sources,"
we find it very difficult . . . . In scientific history
anything is evidence which is used as evidence . . . . Let
us put this by saying that in scissors-and-paste history,
if we allow ourselves to describe testimony--loosely, I
admit--by the name of evidence, there is potential evidence
and there is actual evidence. The potential evidence about
a subject is all the extant statements about it. The actual
evidence is that part of these statements which we decide
to accept. But in scientific history the idea of potential
evidence disappears; . . . everything in the world is
potential evidence for any subject whatever. (IH, 278-80).

The obvious question is, how does the historian manage

to restrict this infinite domain? Once again Collingwood seems

to be overstating his case. It is clear that his intention is to

display the active role of the thinking historian in

constructing his narrative. To this extent there is an exact

parallel between Collingwood's historian, whose task is to

re-enact past acts of thought in his own mind, and Collingwood's

artist, for whom the act of expressive imagination takes place

"in his head." But just as the latter tends to render art

inaccessible to public examination (how do you examine the

inside of someone else's head?), so also the scientific

historian's "evidence" appears to be not only thought-dependent

but inseparable from the infinite array of everyday artifacts.


700

Collingwood's reply is that this is only a problem for

the scissors-and-paste historian, who relies on there being a

manageably small amount of testimony (IH, 278). For the

scientific historian evidence is strictly correlative to the

questioning activity, and it is his arrangement of questions

that guides what the historian chooses to consider as evidence.

In an extended example (one that has often been excerpted in

collections of essays on the philosophy of history) Collingwood

uses the fictional example of an inspector investigating a

murder ("Who Killed John Doe?") as a paradigm for what a

scientific historian does. The example is too familiar to

require repeating here, but it is important to note the lessons

that Collingwood derives from it. (1) Each step of the

investigation is dependent on the asking of a question, and each

question is asked in the right order (IH, 273). One assumes that

"the right order" here, based on the example, is one in which

the answer to one question is the presumed basis for the next

question, and that the whole series is governed by the intention

to solve a single problem. (2) The questions are put by the

investigator to himself--a process which calls attention to the

autonomy of the historian's inquiry, "where by autonomy I mean

the condition of being one's own authority, making statements or

taking action on one's own initiative and not because these

statements or actions are authorized or prescribed by anyone

else" (IH, 274-75).


701

What distinguishes the scientific historian from his

predecessors is precisely this ability to act on his own without

waiting for statements to be made to him. In this the historian

is in the position of a Baconian cross-examiner, who puts

evidence to the test (IH, 269), and it is this activity which

determines what actual evidence is.

Question and evidence, in ((scientific)) history, are cor-


relative. Anything is evidence which enables you to answer
your question--the question you are asking now. A sensible
question (the only kind of question that a scientifically
competent man will ask) is a question which you think you
have or are going to have the evidence for answering. If
you think you have it here and now, the question is an
actual question . . . . If you think you are going to have
it the question is a deferred question . . . . (IH, 281).

One might say for Collingwood that in this context actual evi-

dence is determined by actual questions, potential evidence by

deferred questions.

Once again, this account leaves serious questions un-

answered. What counts for a relevant question in this series,

and what dictates the choice of observable evidence? Colling-

wood's response tends to be circular: the historian chooses

those questions which his evidence permits him to answer (IH,

281). But since the evidence is chosen on the basis of the

questions, the process seems to be one of chasing one's own

tail. What makes the circularity all the more glaring is that

two pages previous to this discussion of the correlativity of

question and evidence Collingwood had charged that the

scissors-and-paste man, like the nineteenth century


702

landscape painter, protects himself by choosing subjects that he

is able to "get away with" (IH, 279). In either

case--Collingwood's or the sub-scientific scissors-and-paste

man--one chooses one's questions to suit the evidence, and the

evidence to suit the question.

In his zeal to put forward his thesis that scientific

thinking is more of a question and answer process than it is one

of deriving logical inferences from ready-made statements, has

Collingwood failed to make important distinctions--e.g. between

the way a piece of evidence first presents itself and the way it

is subsequently treated in an investigation? Has Collingwood

once again lost sight of the real contribution of the object in

his efforts to counteract the presumed realistic bias of his

readers? Or have we overlooked something?

Now it is in a section entitled "Statement and Evidence"

that Collingwood provides us with a hint of a missing element in

this entire discussion. The way out of the circularity of the

correlativity of evidence and question has to do with the sort

of question that the scientific historian asks as opposed to

that of the scissors-and-paste man.

Confronted with a ready-made statement about the subject he


is studying, the scientific historian never asks himself:
"Is this statement true or false?" . . . The question he
asks himself is: "What does this statement mean?" And this
is not equivalent to the question "What did the person who
made it mean by it?" although that
703

is doubtless a question that the historian must ask, and


must be able to answer. It is equivalent rather to the
question "What light is thrown on the subject in which I am
interested by the fact that this person made this
statement, meaning by it what he did mean?" This might be
expressed by saying that the scientific historian does not
treat statements as statements but as evidence: not as true
or false accounts of the facts of which they profess to be
accounts, but as other facts which, if he knows the right
questions to ask about them, may throw light on those
facts. (IH, 275).

When Collingwood writes that the historian treats

statements as other facts the reader is obliged to recall that

the irreducible datum of history is the universal meaning of an

intended event--the "inside" of an action. If the historian is

limited by the truthfulness of the statements of his sources,

then his efforts to construct a coherent narrative by stringing

together true propositions about the past are seriously

threatened by testimony which contains conflicting accounts of

the same event (IH, 257). What Collingwood is arguing is that if

history is not bound by this presupposition it is not in danger

of such a loss of coherence. By treating testimony as factual in

the sense of seeking interpretation of it just as one does of

all evidence, i.e. by asking what it historically means, the

historian may preserve the coherence of his inquiry while at the

same time preserving evidence as evidence rather than simply

discarding it as useless. In Collingwood's view this is

precisely what makes history scientific: instead of being the

passive spectator--a condition in which thought is barely

occurring, as Collingwood often says --the historian is

providing a measure of control over his subject matter.


704

The historian's laboratory is his own a priori imagination, and

he is only limited by his ability to exercise that imagination

in the form of revealing questions aimed at eliciting meaning

from present evidence.

(b) Historical Inference.--If historical thinking occurs

by means of an ordered sequence of questions, what is the role

of inferential reasoning? If we were correct in our

reconstruction of Collingwood's functions of higher-order con-

sciousness in the last chapter, then can we find confirmation

here that by an application of the Law of Primitive Survivals

the meaning-seeking function of consciousness is extended to the

level of inferential thought in the form in which one pro-

positional meaning is related to another as ground to consequent?

At first glance this does not seem to be the function

that Collingwood assigns to it. What historical inference does

is to form a bridge between present evidence and past

events--the former being question-correlative and perceptible,

the latter being answer-correlative and imperceptible, but

re-thinkable (IH, 251-52). But at the same time that he is

preoccupied with saying what historical inference is not, he

lets slip the opportunity to say more explicitly what it is. We

shall first let Collingwood tell us what it is not, and then try

to reconstruct what it is.


705

History has this in common with every other science: that


the historian is not allowed to claim any single piece of
knowledge, except where he can justify his claim by exhib-
iting . . . the grounds upon which it is based. This is
what was meant . . . by describing history as
inferential. . . . Different kinds of science are organized
in different ways; and it should follow . . . that
different kinds of science are characterized by different
kinds of inference. The way in which knowledge is related
to the grounds upon which it is based is in fact not one
and the same for all kinds of knowledge. That . . . a
person who has studied the nature of inference as such--let
us call him a logician--can correctly judge the validity of
an inference purely by attending to its form, although he
has no special knowledge of its subject-matter, is a
doctrine of Aristotle; but it is a delusion, although it is
still believed by many very able persons who have been
trained exclusively in the Aristotelean logic and the
logics that depend upon it for their chief doctrines. (IH,
252-53).

What is worth noting in this passage is the positive

assertion disguised as a negative one, i.e. Collingwood's in-

sistence that it is a delusion that knowledge of the subject-

matter has no bearing on the validity of scientific inference

and that it depends solely on its form. Positively stated this

means that the subject-matter does have a bearing on determining

the validity of inference. It is also worth noting that

throughout this and the subsequent discussion of inference,

everything is phrased in epistemological terms; inference is a

kind of thinking rather than a formal relationship between

propositions, assertions, or the like. Finally it must be

recalled that when Collingwood refers to the logic of Aristotle

"and the logics that depend upon it for their chief doctrines"

he has in mind all F-logics of a propositional pedigree, as we

noted in the previous chapter.


706

Now in this inferential process of justifying knowledge

by exhibiting the grounds upon which it is based, Collingwood

contrasts historical inference to deductive and inductive

inference in a manner very reminiscent of the Essay on

Philosophical Method, but this time with emphasis on the

"compulsion" with which the conclusion follows from the pre-

misses. Proof, he writes,

might be either compulsive, as in exact science, where the


nature of inference is such that nobody can affirm the
premises without being obliged to affirm the conclusion
also, or permissive, as in "inductive" science, where all a
proof can do is to justify the thinker in affirming its
conclusion, granted that he wishes to do so. An inductive
argument with a negative conclusion is compulsive, that is
to say it absolutely forbids the thinker from affirming
what he wishes to affirm; with a positive conclusion it is
never more than permissive. If history means
scissors-and-paste history, the only kind of proof known to
the historian is of this latter kind . . . . If criticism
leads him to a negative conclusion, viz. that the statement
of its author is untrustworthy, this forbids him to accept
it, just as a negative result in an "inductive"
argument . . . forbids the inductive scientist to affirm
the view he hoped to affirm. If criticism leads him to a
positive conclusion, the most it gives him is a nihil
obstat. (IH, 261).

One has to wince at calling a conclusion to a proof a view

someone "hoped to affirm," for why could a proof not be one that

concludes to a view that the author either has no hope for

whatever, or even is one he hopes to deny? Yet with some

correction (e.g. replacing dispositional terms like "hoping"

with logically relational or at least more neutral terms) the

line of thought is clear enough, and poses no particular problem

to the reader. Since he has just been told what constitutes sub-

scientific
707

historical inference, he is led to expect that he will next be

enlightened about actual scientific inference. What he gets

instead are more dispositional terms--the "compulsion" that is

contrasted with "permissive" inductive arguments.

One hears it said that history is "not an exact science."


The meaning of this I take to be that no historical argu-
ment ever proves its conclusion with that compulsive force
which is characteristic of exact science. Historical in-
ference, the saying seems to mean, is never compulsive, it
is at best permissive; or . . . it never leads to cer-
tainty, only to probability. Many historians . . . must be
able to recollect their excitement on first discovering
that it was wholly untrue, and that they were actually
holding in their hands an historical argument which left
nothing to caprice, and admitted of no alternative conclu-
sion, but proved its point as conclusively as a demonstra-
tion in mathematics. (IH, 262).

An argument that admits of no alternative conclusion and proves

its point conclusively is one whose compulsive force must be

that of necessity. Once again the reader anticipates that he

will be enlightened about the special nature of the necessity

involved in historical inference. What follows next is utterly

astonishing.

If any reader wishes to rise here on a point of order and


protest that a philosophical question, which ought there-
fore to be settled by reasoning, is being illegitimately
disposed of by reference to the authority of historians,
and quote against me the good old story about the man who
said "I'm not arguing, I'm telling you," I can only admit
that the cap fits. I am not arguing; I am telling him. Is
this wrong of me? The question I want settled is whether an
inference of the kind used in scientific history, as
distinct from scissors-and-paste history, yields compulsion
or only permission to embrace its conclusion (T)he only way
of knowing whether a given type
708

of argument is cogent or not is to learn how to argue that


way, and find out. Meanwhile, the second best thing is to
take the word of people who have done so for themselves.
(IH, 263).

If this is the manner in which the historian exhibits the

grounds upon which his knowledge is based, then surely one may

be excused from affirming the claim that history is a science.

For how can it provide anything but an authoritative criterion

for successful historical inference? On such grounds as these

one could excuse anything that even pretends to be an inference;

if it is true that whatever I do is historically valid

inference, then any inference is valid so long as it is what I

do. One could hardly ask for a more blatant example of what Knox

called Collingwood's dogmatism.

What has happened to the role of philosophy

which, in Speculum Mentis, judges whether a particular form of

knowledge explicitly lives up to its implicit promise? Do we not

rather appear to be in the full grip of a form of thought that

is attempting to justify itself from within--what he had once

himself called historical dogmatism? Has Collingwood abandoned

the role of philosophy as outlined in the Essay on Philosophical

Method of being a self-justifying form of thought which avoids

dogmatism or assuming certain principles to be true without

justification? Are we not now in the more cloistered atmosphere

of The New Leviathan, where the "Fallacy of Misplaced Argument"

forbids us to argue about objects given directly to

consciousness?
709

If we try again to look past what Collingwood said to

what he meant, where that meaning is informed by what is un-

deniably his overall intention in these essays, a mitigating

argument can be put forward to soften the apparent intransigence

of this remark. We have noted in passing the epistemological

orientation of the entire discussion of inference-just as in the

Essay on Philosophical Method. When Collingwood calls history a

science and then defines science as an organized body of

knowledge, and finally states that knowledge is organized when

it can exhibit the grounds on which it is based, one cannot

expect that a formal account of historical inference is what

will follow. If one were to succeed in formalizing an historical

inference Collingwood would surely say that not only was it

historically unenlightening to focus on the function of logical

connectives and their formal meanings (if-then, and, or, all,

some, etc.) rather than the content of the expressions being

linked together, but also that what was peculiarly historical

about it would be completely left out in the interest of showing

how it was isomorphic with other forms of inference. The sort of

coherence aimed at in historical thinking is not formal validity

but narrative continuity. This continuity is demonstrated when

the meaning of an act is related to the meaning of another act

as historical ground and consequent.


710

Furthermore Collingwood often repeats the point that in

order to be history it is a necessary condition that particular

events be related in a coherent fashion, and not as instances of

a class of similar events. If this requirement is added to the

previous observation it follows that an historical inference is

the establishment of coherence in the form of narrative

continuity between the meaning of one particular historical act

and another such that the one is the historical ground and the

other its consequence. What Collingwood's dogmatic assertion

amounts to is a statement of an historian's autonomy in this

context, so that in order to find out if such a narrative has a

coherent continuity one has to repeat the process of re-thinking

it for oneself, which necessitates re-thinking the meaning of

this act as grounds for the meaning of another particular act,

not another like it in its class. Rehearsing another argument

like it will not do either, for the argument is

meaning-dependent. If a would-be historian is unable or

unwilling to re-enact the argument for himself, he can only rely

on the testimony of another (which means that he ceases to be a

scientific historian at this point), in which case Collingwood,

the Roman-British historian, announces that his testimony is as

good as any other, and he finds that such narrative coherence

does exist, and is compelling.


711

There are many difficulties with this reconstruction, as

well as with Collingwood's entire handling of the question of

historical inference. For starters there is the need for a

clearer distinction between the kind of inference that the

historian uses to link evidence to his proposed or received

narrative events, and the inference that occurs when the his-

torian links events to other events within his narrative. All of

this borders on a discussion of the issue of historical ex-

planation, around which has grown an extensive secondary liter-

ature for the last thirty years (cf. CEPC, 331-48). To deal with

this in even a cursory way would require a separate treatise.

Our concern here is first with evaluating the philosophy of

history expressed in The Idea of History as legitimately

interpreted in the Autobiography; and secondly understanding

this philosophy of history in the light of developments of his

ideas in the other later writings, especially concerning

epistemological logic and the philosophy of mind.

But it is precisely here that our major difficulty with

Collingwood's handling of the issue of historical inference

arises. For just as the Essay on Philosophical Method leaves us

wondering when a philosophical inference is unsuccessful, so The

Idea of History does not provide us with grounds for determining

when historical inference fails to achieve coherent narrative

continuity. For if, lacking Collingwood's assurance on any

particular historical inference, we decided to be scientific

historians ourselves, what assurance do we have that the


712

"compulsion" to a given conclusion is not an utterly subjective

conviction that is merely shored up by the evidence we choose to

consider as governed by the questions we ask, which are in turn

based on our own presuppositions? And if the shade of

Collingwood were to retort, "what assurance do you require?" the

reply is the quite Collingwoodean requirement that it be first

and foremost a self-assurance. How is that achieved?

(c) Historical Necessity.---The issue is one of valid

vs. invalid historical inference, and such a de Jure issue is

not settled by a de facto exemplification or description (we are

not asking Collingwood, we are telling him). The answer that

seems appropriate to the argument as Collingwood has been

developing it is that historical inference succeeds when it is

grounded in evidence. But we have just seen that there is an

apparent circularity here inasmuch as evidence and questions

are, in Collingwood's view, strictly correlative. It simply

postpones the inevitable need to state the missing criteria,

since not just any sequence of completed questions and answers

nor any haphazard choice of evidence will satisfy an intelligent

historian.

Although the challenge may seem unfair, it would be

enlightening in this regard to conduct a thought-experiment in

which Collingwood's canons of scientific history would be

applied to an outrageously bad piece


713

of historiography, such as Erich von Daniken's Chariots of the

Gods? l8 Von Daniken exasperates the learned and delights the

ignorant by declaring that he has sufficient evidence to

demonstrate that ancient astronauts visited the earth in

prehistoric times, and that the legends of gods descending from

the skies in fiery chariots are merely a dim memory of these

events. Von Daniken plies himself and his readers with hundreds

of questions, constructs historical arguments linking his

evidence to these astronautical events, and uses his a priori

historical imagination to construct a narrative of events which

refer to deeds of men (?) done in the past--events he is trying

to re-enact in his own mind. He engages in this historical

reconstruction for the purpose of self-knowledge, and especially

in the light of pre-suppositions drawn from 20th century science

and its expansion by space exploration. He even appears to

cross-examine evidence by putting questions to it, and chooses

evidence that he thinks will allow him to answer the questions

to it, and chooses evidence that he thinks will allow him to

answer the questions that he has. And some--presumably himself

included--would say that his historical arguments are compelling

and admit of no other rational conclusion.

What is missing here? It appears that Collingwood's

criteria of scientific history is superficially well suited to

justify the work of

____________________
18 Translated by Michael Heron (New York, 1969).
714

both respectably orthodox practitioners and disreputably

heretical dilettantes. In order to demonstrate that "history"

like that of Erich van Daniken is spurious and fantastic it

would be necessary to take into account the reaction of the

community of historians and their own work interpreting the same

evidence pertaining to the same "events." Collingwood, of

course, knew this quite well, as indicated by his requirement

that second-order history, the history of historiography, is

itself an integral part of the historian's task. He would also

have found Von Daniken's books beneath contempt and quite

acceptably dismissed by equally amateurish rebuttals like that

of the Christian fundamentalist, Clifford Wilson.l9 Nevertheless

the serious question remains: on Collingwood's grounds, how is

bad history--history that fails to be scientific--eliminated?

Evidently by critical historiography. But then scien-

tific history presupposes critical history rather than replacing

it, just as critical history builds on scissors-and-paste while

yet modifying and correcting it. Collingwood's efforts to

proclaim a historian's version of the Copernican revolution may

have led him to express himself in a way that misleads the

reader into overlooking Collingwood's discovery that history is

a philosophical concept and therefore defined as a scale of

forms in which two successive stages in the scale are related by

opposition and

________________________
19 Crash Go the Chariots (New York, 1972).
distinction, and have differences of both degree and kind.

Scientific history may be opposed to critical history in the

sense that it rejects any attempt to make historical objects

independent of the historian's questioning thought (therefore

ignoring the essential ideality of the past); but it is also

distinct from critical history insofar as it is self-consciously

aware that when it replaces the concept of "evidence" for the

critical historian's "sources" and the scissors-and-paste

historian's "testimony" the concept of evidence includes the

lesser forms in its meaning. It is therefore not only a

different kind of history but is a more perfect embodiment of

the generic concept than is critical history, just as critical

history is a more perfect form than scissors-and-paste.20

But it is not obvious that the same can be said for the

necessity that Collingwood claims for historical inference.

Since Hume it has been natural to suppose that the only sort of

necessity admissible in inference is strict logical neces-

sity--what Collingwood is calling deductive

_____________________
20 What is the minimum specification of the scale of
forms of the concept of history? It cannot be direct observa-
tion, because to be history at all it must deal with res gestae
incapable of present perception. Can it be memory? While
Collingwood rejects memory as grounds for history because his-
tory is organized and memory is not (IH, 252), this is from the
point of view of scientific history--the highest point on the
scale of forms of history. The generic concept must be minimally
specified by an act that re-enacts, and by a thought about
thought. Minimally what else can this be but an act of memory?
That an act of memory is not organized and not inferential means
only that it has the status of a confused potential for
interpretative acts of meaning.
716

compulsion, with some allowance made for inductive inference

(yielding the "virtual compulsion" due to preponderant

probability). But in the strict sense, when the meaning of an

event is related to the meaning of another event as ground to

consequent, how can this be a necessary relation? In the realm

of human affairs it is always possible that the outcome could be

otherwise than the way it was. And if the historian's work of

exhibiting the evidence as grounds for the coherence of his

narrative of these events is also an inferential process, in

what sense is the conclusion--the particular narrative of

events--a necessary conclusion from the evidence? It is clearly

this latter question that occupies the foreground of

Collingwood's concern in The Idea of History, and our question

at this point concerns the nature of a "compulsion" which is

neither deductively necessary nor inductively permissive, but is

yet just as binding in its conclusion as is a mathematical

proof. It is also clearly not Collingwood's intention to reduce

this compulsion to a subjective or psychological state. He means

to assert that historical inference compels like all scientific

inference compels--i.e. with necessity.

When historical inference refers to the ground-conse-

quent relation between narrated events there is a sense of ne-

cessity in which it is understandable to say that past events

cannot be other than the way they are. Necessity has a human-

based usage wherein some event or state of


717

affairs is said to be necessary if it cannot be made by me or

anyone else to be other than the way it is. As we shall see in

the next chapter, this is the way Collingwood analyzes the term

"cause" in the Essay on Metaphysics. In this sense the past is

beyond human causality: it cannot now be made by me or by anyone

else to be other than the way it is. But this is not the

interesting sense of the term so far as the argument of The Idea

of History is concerned. We are interested in the relation of

evidence to reconstructed events of the past, and reconstructing

or re-enacting that past is within the non-necessary realm of

causable or alterable events.

But there is one way that I can see to salvage Colling-

wood's treatment of historical inference. When the question-

evidence correlation came up for discussion in the previous

section we noted that the kind of question that the historian

asks aims not at "the truth" but at the meaning of the evidence.

It is this hermeneutical preoccupation that provides us with a

way of understanding a non-deductive but necessary inferential

compulsion.

The missing link in this entire discussion is a proper

elucidation of the term "interpretation"--an axial process since

it is by means of the interpretation of evidence that the

historian draws his inference about the meaning of past events.

It follows that the correctness of the inference is dependent on

the correctness of the interpreting process.


718

Now in the interpretative process there is one sense of

"necessity" that is both legitimate and appropriate for Col-

lingwood's use in this connection. Collingwood seems to have in

mind a view of inferential necessity that is parallel to his

notion of conceptual truth. Just as truth is not only a property

of judgments or propositions but extends to concepts as well in

the sense that a concept may truly or falsely express an

intended meaning, so also necessity extends to concepts,

statements, and inferences in the sense of "fitness" (like the

elements in a Gestalt are seen as necessary to the

interpretation of the pattern). In the hermeneutical sense

something is said to be necessary when it cannot be other than

the way it is without losing its identity of meaning. In the

historical sense the hermeneutical demand for meaning proposes

an a priori necessity in the sort of fitness that makes a

conclusion necessary only when it makes both narrative and

evidential sense, so that the meaning of both the evidence and

the event are fused together so tightly that nothing essential

is left out of account. The necessity is one of referential

narrative meaning, i.e. by means of this argument (a set of well

interpreted pieces of evidence) such a conclusion (the

re-enacted event) makes historical sense.

This is what Collingwood seems to mean when he says that

the necessity of the historian's picture of the past (i.e. his


719

narrative account) "is at every point the necessity of the a

priori imagination" (IH, 245-46) whose functions are selection,

construction, and criticism (IH, 236).

Conclusion.

In this chapter we have had the opportunity to examine

how Collingwood carried out the rapprochement between philosophy

and history, and although we were left with several unanswered

questions and some serious problems in understanding what

Collingwood meant us to understand by historical inference, it

is clear enough that the autobiographical interpretation in its

main lines is carried forward into The Idea of History, even

though it is a posthumous publication and is the product of the

editorial re-arrangement in its present form. We saw that in

Part I of The Idea of History the scale of forms of mental

functions is reflected in the development of the concept of

history as it is expressed in historiography. We also saw that

the Epilegomena provide some striking illustrations not only of

Collingwood's mature philosophy of mind, but also of the kinds

of judgments and arguments that were described, but not

exemplified, in the Essay on Philosophical Method. And finally

we saw how Collingwood attempted to free himself not only from

the errors of realism but from those of idealism as well. And in

the process we had a glimpse of Collingwood's use of a basically

interpretative approach to his subject matter, an approach that

allowed for the self-conscious control by


720

the historian of his narrative by means of inference based on

the interpretation of evidence. The reconciliation of history

and philosophy does not merely take the form of a reduction of

both to forms of self-consciousness--although that is, in

Collingwood's view, generically the case. It takes the form of a

demonstration that self-knowledge (the goal of philosophy) is

possible only on condition that meanings can be re-enacted in

such a way that they retain both their objectivity (their

identity as meanings) and their subjectivity (as experience).

What we have not shown is what the limitations of this

reconciliational process are. Does history simply absorb

philosophy without remainder in this re-enactment? What is the

independent role of philosophy?


CHAPTER X

METAPHYSICS AND RAPPROCHEMENT

1. Introduction.

With this chapter we come to the end of our journey

through the published writings of R. G. Collingwood, and to the

central paradox of the Essay on Metaphysics, which has been the

cause of so much critical discussion among the students of

Collingwood's philosophy.

In Chapter I we noted that it was this work (and those

portions of the Autobiography that support it) which so

scandalized Knox, who argued that at the end of his life

Collingwood "turned traitor" to his philosophical profession by

absorbing philosophy into history. According to Knox, until 1936

Collingwood still held that metaphysics as a separate study of

the One, the True, and the Good, a study distinct from history,

was still possible; but after 1938 he did not, as evidenced by

the historicism of the Essay on Metaphysics and the

Autobiography. Knox concluded that sometime between 1936 and

1938 Collingwood's philosophical standpoint radically changed,

and while the major evidence for this change is taken by Knox

from unpublished manuscripts, he makes an impressive case for it

from the published writings themselves (IH, x-xi).

721
722

The fact that there is no mention of a major reversal of opinion

in the Autobiography is one of the main reasons Knox rejects it

as a legitimate interpretation of the development of

Collingwood's philosophy.

In Chapter I we also noted that this is the major dif-

ficulty to which most of Collingwood's subsequent interpreters

addressed themselves. Donagan grounds his interpretation of

Collingwood's later philosophy on the disparity that he finds

between the earlier idealistic philosophy, in which all ab-

straction is rejected as falsification, and the later analytic

philosophy of mind which "repudiates" this position by re-

cognizing that all thinking is conceptual and that all concepts

are abstract (LPC, 14, 18). While we have had occasion to

question Donagan's analysis of the abstractness of thought in

Collingwood's later philosophy, it is difficult to escape his

conclusion that the Essay on Metaphysics represents an

abandonment of views expressed earlier, in which philosophy is

said to consist of universal judgments: for if historical

statements concern particular matters of fact, how can meta-

physics as an historical science preserve its universal aspect

as philosophy? Donagan argues that Collingwood came to think

that it was impossible to have a non-abstract idea of pure

being, and therefore attempted to save metaphysics by giving it

an orientation away from ontology and towards the history of

science. But what he proposed was a contradictory and

indefensible science of
723

truth-neutral absolute presuppositions, which is incompatible

with his later philosophy of mind (CEPC, 15).

It is this reformed metaphysics which Walsh, Roten-

streich and others have also found to be neither conceptually

justifiable nor historically accurate, representing what Walsh

has called "metaphysical neutralism"--the refusal to take a

metaphysical position (CEPC, 149, 197). The attempt to extricate

Collingwood from this blind alley has led at least two of

Collingwood's gifted defenders--Mink and Rubinoff--to engage in

feats of interpretative excess, which we spent part of Chapter I

examining. While we have learned more from these studies of

Collingwood than we can accurately and adequately acknowledge,

we decided that there was still room for a study of

Collingwood's public philosophy based on the guidelines provided

by the autobiographical interpretation.

In Chapter II we laid the groundwork for this self--

interpretative study by locating the four major themes around

which Collingwood organized his Autobiography: his opposition to

realism, Q-A logic, the philosophy of history, and the

philosophy of rapprochement. In Parts II and III we have

verified that the autobiographical interpretation is a remark-

ably concise overview of themes that recur constantly throughout

Collingwood's early and later writings, and often enlightens the

strategy of argumentation in
724

these works. We have had occasion to find fault with what

Collingwood maintained at one place or another; we have

witnessed apparent contradictions not only between one

publication and another but within the same treatise; and we

have found themes latent in these writings that help to overcome

puzzling and frustrating obscurities in some difficult

passages--themes that were not explicitly discussed in the

Autobiography. But we have found no evidence thus far of a major

reversal on any of the central issues of the autobiographical

interpretation.

But with the Essay on Metaphysics we face our greatest

challenge. Approaching this work from the background of our

survey of the other published writings we find both striking

parallels and equally striking reversals. We observed in Chapter

III that even before Collingwood's opposition to realism

hardened during World War I, his outlook on many substantial

philosophical issues was already formulated. Thus it is

noteworthy that seven of the ten chapters of Religion and

Philosophy are assembled under the sub-headings, "Religion and

Metaphysics" (Part II) and "From Metaphysics to Theology" (Part

III), and contain discussions about proofs for the existence of

God, materialism and idealism, personality, identity and

difference, the Absolute, the problem of evil, and God's

self-expression in man (RP, viii-xii). In this earliest work

Collingwood writes as if there is a legitimate function of

metaphysical analysis not merely in locating and propounding


absolute presuppositions,
725

but in deciding which of them are acceptable and which are not.

For example, when he examines the three presuppositions (he

calls them "hypotheses") that "(e)ither the world is entirely

material, or it is entirely spiritual, or it is a compound of

the two" (RP, 73), he reaches some conclusion concerning the

issue: he rejects both materialism and a crude idealism in favor

of a modified form of idealism which accepts "mind as the one

reality" in the sense that "the world is the place of freedom

and consciousness, not of blind determinism" (RP, 94-95).

Surely "the world is entirely material" is as much a

metaphysical presupposition as "all events have causes" (EM,

51), and in rejecting this "hypothesis" Collingwood is not

merely stating that it is no longer an absolute presupposition

of science (although he does indicate that this is the case--cf.

RP, 82), but is deciding the issue in favor of idealism--which

is hardly remaining neutral on its truth or falsity. Nor is this

an isolated case. When he analyzes the immanence-transcendence

dualism with respect to God's identity in the universe, he does

not leave the matter in unresolved conflict, but reconciles them

through the "concrete identity of activity"--i.e. "the identity

of two minds which think the same thing" in the sense of sharing

the same thoughts and volitions: "so far, that is, as they know

any truth or will any good"


726

(RP, 117-18). Thus in stating that God cannot be simply immanent

in the world or transcendent to it, but rather present in it in

the same sense that personality is self-identical and yet

inter-personal in action, he is not merely stating what thinking

Christians believe, he is affirming the truth of a theological

presupposition and rejecting two heretical versions.

But it is also in this early work that we found the

following passage in which there is a striking anticipation of

the rejection of metaphysical ontology in the Essay on

Metaphysics:

It is often maintained that ultimate truths are incapable


of proof, and that the existence of God is such an ultimate
truth. But I venture to suggest that the impossibility of
proof attaches not to ultimate truths as such, but only to
the truths of "metaphysics" in the depreciatory sense of
the word; to truths, that is, which have no definite
meaning. We cannot prove that Reality exists, not because
the question is too ultimate (that is, because too much
depends on it), but because it is too empty. Tell us what
you mean by Reality, and we can offer an alternative
meaning and try to discover which is the right one. No one
can prove that God exists, if no definite significance is
attached to the words; not because . . . the reality of God
transcends human knowledge, but because the idea of God
which we claim to have is as yet entirely indeterminate.
(RP, 64).

This is essentially the same argument that we

find Collingwood making in the Essay on Metaphysics to reject an

ontology of "pure being," and the existence of "truths" which

are incapable of proof is remarkably close to the later concept

of absolute presuppositions. It is clear from this early work

that at this time Collingwood accepted a


727

legitimate function to metaphysics and rejected some

metaphysical arguments as vacuous and therefore illegitimate.

Eight years later Collingwood appears to have less hope

for the legitimacy of the enterprise of metaphysical analysis.

In Speculum Mentis metaphysics is described as the scientific

form of experience abstractly (and therefore falsely) extended

into philosophy: it is that form of dogmatic philosophy in which

scientific thinking justifies its objective validity "by showing

that the real world is constructed in such a way that, in

thinking it scientifically, we are thinking of it as it really

is" (SM, 272). But this involves showing that the laws of

thought (logic) are really the laws of being (metaphysics), and

this cannot be done.

Metaphysics is impossible; for its task is to vindicate the


objective validity of the ways in which we think, and if
there are any flaws in our methods of thought, these will
affect our metaphysical theory of reality and introduce into
it the very mistakes which by its help we had hoped to
eradicate. Hence the theory of being as distinct from
thinking (metaphysics) will only be the theory of thinking
as distinct from being (logic) expressed in a different
terminology but subject to the same fatal weakness, namely
that just as logic can never analyze real thinking--the
thinking that, going on in the logician's mind, always lies
behind his analysis--so metaphysics can never analyze real
being, being as it is in itself untainted by thought. (SM,
274).

Thus as we have seen in these two early works, Collingwood's

antipathy to metaphysics defined as a science of "pure being"

has its origin in his early philosophy, and the Essay on

Metaphysics does not represent a departure from this tendency.


728

Where they part company appears to be over the recon-

ciling role of philosophical thought. Speculum Mentis leaves

open the possibility that as the exercise of "absolute knowlege"

philosophy can achieve, by unification of subject and object,

what cannot be achieved by scientific metaphysics. In the Essay

on_Metaphysics the role of philosophy seems to be restricted to

the discovery and analysis of absolute presuppositions by

historical means, and the gap between the metaphysical subject

and his historical object is measureable by the attitude of

natural piety or even numinous terror that surrounds absolute

presuppositions. From Part II we are therefore left with the

problem of trying to understand how history can establish what

science cannot, and how philosophy can be content with leaving

absolute presuppositions in an unreconcilably truth-neutral

state.

Part III has provided us with the means for resolving

this issue at the same time it deepens our understanding of the

problem. On the one hand our view of history from Collingwood's

analysis of it, as we reviewed that analysis in The Idea of

History, helps us to understand why the obstacle of infinite

factuality, which wrecked the historical enterprise in Speculum

Mentis, is no longer a difficulty for the scientific historian.

On the other hand, the scale of forms of conscious acts that

provides the foundation for historical thought seems to leave no

place for the absoluteness of presuppositions. Not only is

there no upper limit


729

to the levels of consciousness to correspond to the "absolute

knowledge" of Speculum Mentis, but the very facticity of

evidence is generated by the questioning activity of the

historian--so that absolute presuppositions appear to be neither

absolute nor, from an historical perspective, truly pre-supposed.

To add to this distressing situation we are confronted

with a statement from the Essay on Philosophical Method, which

has the highest blessings from Collingwood in his Autobiography,

about the nature of metaphysics--a statement which seems to run

directly counter to the rejection of metaphysical ontology both

in the earlier works and in the Essay on Metaphysics. He writes:

metaphysics, even if it is regarded as only one among the


philosophical sciences, is not unique in its objective re-
ference or in its logical structure; all philosophical
thought is of the same kind, and every philosophical science
partakes of the nature of metaphysics, which is not a
separate philosophical science but a special study of the
existential aspect of that same subject-matter whose aspect
as truth is studied by logic, and its aspect as goodness by
ethics. (EPM, 127).

It is also in the Essay on Philosophical Method that the

distinction is made between "the categorical singular judgement

which composes the body of historical thought and the categor-

ical universal of philosophy" (EPM, 136), where categorical

thinking means thought which "in fact is never devoid of ob-

jective or ontological reference" (EPM, 125).


730

It appears that the Autobiography overlooks this distinction and

that it is denied altogether in the Essay on Metaphysics.

Is it possible that Knox was correct on this matter, and

that it was only in his mature middle period that Collingwood

succeeded in freeing himself from the scepticism and dogmatism

of his earlier and later periods? In the light of the evidence

we called forth in Part III this seems hardly credible. On all

the major autobiographical themes that we have examined thus far

Collingwood shows a steady and continuous development.

Nevertheless we cannot easily integrate the positions expressed

in the Essay on Metaphysics with the rest of Collingwood's

philosophy as we have investigated it thus far, nor can we

simply refuse to consider it or relegate it to a lower status

than the rest of his published writings-and especially not in

the light of the agreement between this essay and the

Autobiography. For when we read in the former that "All

metaphysical questions are historical questions, and all

metaphysical propositions are historical propositions'' (EM,

49), and that "The problems of metaphysics are historical

problems; its methods are historical methods" (EM, 62), and even

that "Metaphysics has always been an historical science" (EM,

58), we are certainly inclined to the opinion that Collingwood

has reduced, if not all of philosophy, at least all of

metaphysics to history. And when one considers that it was

Collingwood's judgment that metaphysics is the very heart of

science and civilization,


731

which stand or fall with it (EM, 22, 46, 103, 224, 233), it is

difficult not to draw the conclusion that history has replaced

philosophy as the central reconciling force, and that therefore

the role of philosophy has indeed been "liquidated by being

converted into history" (IH, x).

Even if we were to accept this as Collingwood's complete

and final judgment on metaphysics, our thesis concerning the

autobiographical interpretation as we developed it in Chapter II

would not be entirely wrecked, because the Autobiography largely

agrees with the Essay on Metaphysics on this matter:

This was my answer to the rather threadbare question "how


can metaphysics become a science?" If science means na-
turalistic science, the answer is that it had better not
try. If science means an organized body of knowledge, the
answer is: by becoming what is always has been; that is,
frankly claiming its proper status as an historical
inquiry . . . . (A, 67; cf. EM, 77).

What seems to be called into question is rather the role of

philosophical rapprochement, which plays a large part in the

Autobiography, but is not even mentioned in the Essay on Me-

taphysics. It is for this reason that we have chosen to consider

both of these issues in our final chapter: it is our belief that

when examined together these two issues-- rapprochement and

metaphysics--will illuminate one another in a way that examining

either alone will not.


732

But in pursuing our inquiry to this final point we will

be, in our own way, undergoing an experience not unlike one

which Collingwood describes in the Autobiography. For it was in

our second chapter that we encountered those peculiar passages

in which Collingwood described the turning point in his early

thinking--the closest thing to a "conversion" that is even

hinted at in the Autobiography. In two crucial chapters--the

ones in which Collingwood writes about his discovery of Q-A

logic and his rejection of the realist philosophy he had been

taught at Oxford--he writes about his experience of the Albert

Memorial which, though he describes it in grotesque terms,

became an event the assimilation of which reshaped the direction

of all his future thought.

A year or two after the outbreak of war, I was living in


London and working with a section of the Admiralty Intel-
ligence Division in the rooms of the Royal Geographical
Society. Every day I walked across Kensington Gardens and
past the Albert Memorial. The Albert Memorial began by
degrees to obsess me. Like Wordsworth's Leech-Gatherer, it
took on a strange air of significance; it seemed Like one
whom I had met with in a dream; Or like a man from some far
region sent, To give me human strength, by apt admonishment.
Everything about it was visibly misshapen, corrupt, craw-
ling, verminous; for a time I could not bear to look at it,
and passed with averted eyes; recovering from this weakness,
I forced myself to look, and to face day by day the
question: a thing so obviously, so incontrovertibly, so
indefensibly bad, why had Scott done it? . . . What relation
was there, I began to ask myself, between what he had done
and what he had tried to do? . . . If I found the monument
merely loathsome, was that perhaps my fault? Was I looking
in it for qualities it did not possess, and either ignoring
or despising those it did? (A, 29-30).
733

In a later passage Collingwood relates this experience

to his rejection of the realists' attitude toward the history of

philosophy, leading to his rejection of the view that there are

"eternal problems" in philosophy (A, 60). It led to the

discovery that every philosophical problem has its history in

which the sameness of an issue is not the sameness of a uni-

versal but that of an historical process, and the difference

that between two phases of this process (A, 62). Two pages later

Collingwood writes about his reform of metaphysics based on both

the non-existence of eternal problems and the uncovering of the

absolute presuppositions of science (A, 6667).

Collingwood's Essay on Metaphysics is our Albert Me-

morial. It is a grotesque piece of work, and like the young

Collingwood we must force ourselves not to avert our gaze from

it, and to ask ourselves what relation there is between what he

did and what he was trying to achieve. For one cannot avoid the

embarassment that arises when faced with its seemingly

intemperate and radically simplistic assertions. It seems to be

a work that is indefensibly and incontrovertibly bad, unworthy

of the subtle and sometimes vigorous mind of the Waynflete

Professor of Metaphysics, the archeologist of Hadrian's Wall,

and the author of the Essay on Philosophical Method.


734

But it is here that we must also take our cue

from Collingwood's reflections on the Albert Memorial, for we

must ask ourselves if we are looking in it for qualities it does

not possess, and either ignoring or despising those it has. Thus

we will be wary of accepting even Collingwood's own assessment

of what he is doing in this essay. Our examination of the Essay

on Philosophical Method forewarns us against accepting at face

value any advance disclaimer at the beginning of a work of what

he is not going to do; so when he writes in the Preface to the

Essay on Metaphysics that "This is not so much a book of

metaphysics as a book about metaphysics," and adds that it does

not expound his own metaphysical ideas nor criticize those of

others (EM, vii), we can be reasonably sure that he will violate

this contract with the reader just as he did in his essay on

method. To talk about philosophy in any meaningful way is to

philosophize, and this is no less true of metaphysics, as the

examples in Part III of the book make clear.

Nevertheless to a degree not necessary up to this point

we must rely on the latent principles that we have found coming

to light in our survey of the later writings thus far in Part

III. These themes may yet provide us with a means for uncovering

the consistent core of meaning underlying the paradox of

metaphysics as an historical science. For we may anticipate that

metaphysics, like history, is a philosophical concept and


735

therefore is defined by a scale of forms in which occur

oppositions such as those between a science consisting of

categorical universal statements and the same science defined as

dealing with individual matters of fact. In a scale of forms

such an opposition is reconciled when it is shown that the two

forms are phases of the same generic concept, one being a more

perfect embodiment or expression of the other. Furthermore our

analysis of the functions of consciousness and language in

Collingwood's philosophy of mind leads us to suspect that the

priority and irreducibility of the meaning-seeking role of

unifying consciousness will have considerable impact on any

discussion of absolute presuppositions. And finally, as we saw

the concept of history being refined and re-shaped in the last

chapter, we could not help but recognize the profound importance

of understanding what Collingwood means by "historical thinking"

when considering what it means to say that metaphysics is an

historical science. For if at the heart of historical thinking

is re-enactment, then calling metaphysics an historical science

means calling it a re-enactment with all that that

implies--especially the recasting of the act-object distinction

as Collingwood envisions it.

This provides us with our strategy for the rest of this

chapter. In the next section we will attempt a brief outline of

the Essay on Metaphysics, especially attending to the way in

which it reflects
736

the four major themes of the Autobiography. In section three we

shall continue this "forced look" at the essay by analyzing the

obstacles that Collingwood has placed in the path of first

philosophy in the first two parts of the Essay on Metaphysics.

In section four we shall attempt to reconstruct the unity of the

four autobiographical themes prefatory to returning to the

obstacles to first philosophy, the overcoming of which is the

aim of our fifth and final section.

We must add a final word on the limitations of this

chapter. Our program necessitates restricting our discussion to

the four major autobiographical themes. For this reason we are

not attempting a complete discussion of the contents of the

Essay on Metaphysics, which involves passing over a good deal of

interesting and perhaps even relevant material. A complete

treatment of Collingwood's metaphysics will only be possible

after a thorough study of the unpublished manuscripts,

especially those on cosmology, epistemology, logic, and, of

course, metaphysics itself. This chapter is to be regarded as a

prolegomenon to such a study--as is the entire dissertation.

2. The Autobiographical Themes in the Essay on Metaphysics.

If we are to accomplish even the first stages of this

"forced look" at Collingwood's Essay on Metaphysics we must

disabuse ourselves of
737

several pre-conceptions that we may bring to the

discussion--some of which arise from our own previous

investigation. It is only in this way that we will prevent

ourselves from looking in it for qualities it does not possess.

For if we are expecting that the Essay on Metaphysics will place

a capstone on the arch of thought that we have seen Collingwood

erecting for the last eight chapters, we will be sadly

disappointed. Ontology is dismissed. There is no discussion of

the nature of categorical universal propositions, no analysis of

the nature of "real thinking," and no final synthesis of formal,

dialectical, and Q-A logics. Realism and idealism are left in a

state of unresolved opposition. And while some of the

traditional concepts of metaphysics come up for discussion,

others are ignored altogether. Thus the existence of God is

discussed, but in a way which orthodox Christians would find

alien at best and heretical at worst; and while various senses

of the term "cause" are examined, other concepts like substance,

matter, activity, process, etc. are not. And where we might have

wished for clarification, in "first philosophy" that explicates

the presuppositions of historical science, of terms like event,

evidence, reference, inference and necessity (cf. A, 77), such

hopes are left unfulfilled. In short, the Essay on Metaphysics

is not the First Philosophy of Collingwood we might have hoped

for, and to this extent his warning in the first sentence of the

Preface is precise: it is not a book of metaphysics.


738

As we have already noted, where the lack is most sorely

felt is in the area of rapprochement. Where we might be led to

expect that a work on metaphysics by the author of the

Autobiography might have important things to say about the

identity that is sought by a reconciliational philosophy --what

in another context he might have called an object that would

completely satisfy the mind--there is not a word on such a

desperately needed topic to complete the recapitulation and form

an apotheosis of the four autobiographical themes in the later

writings. A glance at the contents of the essay tends to confirm

this observation insofar as there is considerably reflection of

the other three autobiographical themes-which makes rapprochement

conspicuous by its absence.

The first three chapters are devoted to examining

several senses of the term "metaphysics" as indicated by the

three names that Aristotle gives to "first philosophy" in the

collection of treatises following the physics

(τ α µ ε τ α τ α φ υσ ι κ α ). In these chapters Collingwood

rejects the Aristotelian proposal for metaphysics as ontology on

the grounds that a science of pure being would be so general

that it would be lacking in any determinate subject matter. But

Aristotle's description of metaphysics as a science of the first

principles of physics is defended by Collingwood as the true

subject matter of metaphysics, which is a study of the absolute

presuppositions of science. Chapters IV and V present the

version of Q-AM
739

logic which we examined in detail in our chapter on logic,

language, and mental acts, in which absolute presuppositions

(APs) are located at the apex of P-Q-A complexes in a systematic

inquiry. Chapters VI and VII develop the concept of metaphysics

as an historical science of absolute presuppositions--the

radical thesis of the Essay on Metaphysics. Chapters VIII

through XVII are devoted to what Collingwood calls

anti-metaphysics. Chapter VIII defines anti-metaphysics as

metaphysics done out of a motive of either resentment or fear,

by an amateur thinker whose attitude toward actual metaphysics

appears as hostility to it. Chapters IX through XVI examine two

versions of anti-metaphysics--psychology as the pseudo-science

of mind, and positivism from J. S. Mill to A. J. Ayer. Chapter

XVII, which concludes Part II, contrasts Collingwood's view on

absolute presuppositions with those of the modern realist,

Samuel Alexander, whose attitude of "natural piety" or

unquestioning acceptance toward APs Collingwood approved, but

whose epistemology failed to appreciate the degree to which APs

are historically grounded.

Part III is a collection of examples of metaphysical

analysis of the sort that Collingwood proposes as acceptable,

and presumably illustrating the principles of metaphysical an-

alysis as he outlined them in Part I. Chapters XVIII through XXI

take up the problem of the existence of God, especially as the

statement "God exists" is analyzed by the


740

logical positivists. Collingwood analyzes the statement not as a

verifiable or falsifiable proposition, but as an absolute

presupposition of 20th Century science, which could not exist

without the AP that there is one God or "in other words, that

there is one world of nature with one system of laws running all

through it, and one natural science which investigates it" (EM,

213). Chapters XXII through XXVIII set forth a radical

re-interpretation of Kant's metaphysics as contained in the

Transcendental Analytic section of the Critique of Pure Reason.

According to Collingwood this is "an historical study of the

absolute presuppositions generally recognized by natural

scientists in Kant's own time" and for some time afterwards (EM,

245). And finally, Chapters XXIX through XXXIV are a slightly

altered version of the article on causation that he had

published in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society for

1939. In it Collingwood distinguishes three developing senses of

the term "cause": as a motive for the free and deliberate act of

a conscious agent (the historical sense); as the way in which a

natural event can be produced or prevented by human intervention

(the engineering science sense), and as the relation between two

events or states such that one is related causally to another

called its effect (the theoretical science sense) (EM, 285-87).

Collingwood argues that the first is the true sense, the second

a legitimate but restricted extension of the first, and the

third an abandoned presupposition of natural science (EM, 289,

327).
741

From this bird's eye view it is an easy matter to locate

three of the four autobiographical themes. The chapters

rejecting metaphysics as ontology as well as the whole of the

section on anti-metaphysics are directed against current forms

of realism. Ontology as Collingwood describes it is the ultimate

product of universal abstraction--the limiting case when

everything determinate that can be said of an object is left out

of account and a subject matter is reached which is totally

lacking in any distinctions whatever--"pure being." There being

no definite subject matter, there is consequently nothing for

science to investigate (EM, 13-14). We recognize the view of

abstraction here that Collingwood attributes to the realists,

and "pure being" is an object so unaffected by the knowing of it

that it remains entirely indeterminate and hence unknowable.

Similarly the sort of psychology that Collingwood takes to be

anti-metaphysical is the behavioristic attempt to reduce mental

processes to mechanical events--a "pseudoscience of mind" which

adopts a materialistic and mechanistic attitude towards thought

and deliberately ignores its "criteriological" aspect (generally

its truth or falsity)--in short, treating thought as an inert

object (EM, 114-15). And the logical positivism of Ayer is

faulted for its simplistic and erroneous description of

observation in science, which assumes that "facts" are simply

observed without recognizing that observation itself presupposes

interpretation (EM, 143-46, 163). Positivism is guilty of the

error of assuming, as does Samuel Alexander,


742

that the process of knowing is a simple apprehension of

"compresence" of two things, one of which happens to be a mind

(EM, 170, 177)--the root error of realistic epistemology.

It is also not difficult to find many of the pernicious

consequences of realism cited in the Autobiography also

represented in the Essay on Metaphysics. In the form of anti-

metaphysics, realism provides the propaganda for the spread of

irrationalism in science, religion, and civilization (EM, 13342,

234). Where the survival of each of these requires the

responsible agency of human intelligence--the belief that a

person's knowing can have an effect on the outcome of a syste-

matic inquiry or a series of actions--anti-metaphysics denies

such agency, and therefore threatens the survival of the sort of

civilization that Collingwood portrayed in The New Leviathan.

Similarly Q-A logic--the second major autobiographical

theme--is not only made the groundwork for the revision of

metaphysics as a science of absolute presuppositions, but is

formulated in conscious opposition to the pronouncements of the

logical positivists, whose acceptance of an F-logical criterion

for deciding truth claims (at least for analytical statements)

is well recognized. In fact it is apparent that the peculiar

form that Q-A logic takes in the Essay on Metaphysics is due to

the fact that it is being formulated with one eye fixed on the

pronouncements
743

of logical positivism, and if it were not for this polemical

tendency we might have been offered a Q-A logic better able to

stand on its own merits rather than those it has by not being

some other unacceptable thing. Therefore Collingwood tells us

only enough about absolute presuppositions to allow us to escape

the trap laid for metaphysical statements by the logical

positivists--that they are neither tautologous (F-logically

analytical statements) nor empirically verifiably/falsifiable,

and are therefore meaningless. Collingwood charges them with

failing to ask the further question of what else they might be

before declaring them to be meaningless (EM, 162-65), and when

he asks the question for them he concludes that while it is true

that they are not verifiable or falsifiable propositions, they

nonetheless retain an inquiry-dependent function as the grounds

from which questions proceed--the function he calls

presupposition (EM, 29-31). But were it not for this preoccu-

pation with escaping from the positivistic trap Collingwood

might well have gone on to say in what sense absolute presup-

positions can be said to be true or false in a way which does

not mean verifiable or falsifiable in the empirical sense.

Instead we are left with metaphysical statements that are not

propositions (as the term is understood by positivists), not

tautologous, but yet not meaningless--all negative character-

istics. All that is left of a positive nature to absolute

presuppositions is their
744

role in logically grounding questions in a systematic inquiry.

This is precisely the role assigned to them in the Autobiography.

Of course it is the third autobiographical theme that is

dominant in the Essay on Metaphysics, since the reconciliation

of history and philosophy is made the template upon which is

forged a reformed metaphysics. When the questions, propositions,

problems and methods of metaphysics are said to be those of

history, the identification of the two is as plainly stated as

one can expect. In fact the identity is so lacking in

qualification that the reader is obliged to think as far back as

Religion and_Philosophy to find a reconciliational identity of

equivalent unsophistication. But if what is overlooked in the

reconciliational identity is, like the earlier identities of

religion, philosophy, and history, the sense of how they are

related in a process of development or in a scale of forms, is

it not the logical outcome of the line of thought in the

Autobiography whereby Collingwood decided that there are no

eternal problems? For if it is true that there are no timeless

truths, then all truths are indeed historically relative, and

the Essay on Metaphysics is an attempt to explore what that

would mean for scientific inquiry.

Nevertheless we cannot be content with this state of

affairs. In Part II and Part III we have observed how the

earlier version of reconciliation, based on the rather

simplistic orientation of religion,


745

science, history, etc. to a common object ("all of reality"),

gave way to the more sophisticated but unstable dialectical

scale of forms of knowledge which distortedly approximated to an

ideal of Absolute Knowledge, expressed as philosophy. We

followed this progression to the Essay on Philosophical Method,

where opposition and distinction are relations accepted as

normal staging between two phases of a developing concept, one

being not merely different from the other but also a more

perfect embodiment of it. And finally we found that such

hierarchical scales were found exemplified in Collingwood's

analysis of mental functions and expressive linguistic acts. In

the last chapter we found that the concept of history exhibited

this structure, and in reconciling conflicting historiographical

traditions Collingwood locates them on a developing scale

culminating in scientific history.

It was when Collingwood sought to go beyond reconcili-

ation by means of a scale of forms, and to explore the senses in

which higher levels of mental activity were expressed in

historical thinking that he reached both the high and low points

of his philosophical career: the high point being the

demonstration that history is possible only on the basis of

re-enactment--an argument which balances realism and idealism in

a remarkable re-interpretation of the act-object distinction;

and the low point being the collapse of his defense of

scientific history as a
746

separate discipline for lack of a sufficiently unique

characterization of "historical inference." It is exactly at

this critical juncture that we must pick up the thread of our

interpretative reconstruction once again.

Before doing so we must press our "forced look" to its

final stage by extracting the discomfitting features of the

Essay on Metaphysics and confronting the obstacles to first

philosophy which these features present for us. To help us with

this task we end this section with a tabulated synopsis of the

principal ideas of Parts I and II of the essay.


747

TABLE 14

METAPHYSICS AND ANTI-METAPHYSICS

1. A metaphysics of the sort indicated by Aristotle in the


treatises by that name may be regarded either as ontology,
i.e. the science of pure being, or as the organized knowledge
of the presuppositions underlying ordinary science, where
science is a body of systematic or orderly thinking about a
determinate subject matter (EM, 11).

a. But it cannot be ontology, since there cannot be orderly


thinking about an indeterminate subject matter, and pure
being is a completely indeterminate subject matter
because it represents the limiting case of the
abstractive process, where abstraction is the ignoring
of differences between individual things and the
attending only to what they have in common. When ab-
straction is pushed to the limiting case in which
everything determinate is left out, there is nothing
left for science to investigate. (EM, 12-15).

b. Metaphysics may therefore be the science of the pre-


suppositions that are logically prior to, or form the
underlying ground for, ordinary science, where ordinary
means not a constituent part of metaphysics (EM, 11-12,
20).

2. To think scientifically is to be aware that every statement


made is in answer to a question which is logically prior to
its own answer. What is stated is a proposition which can be
either true or false. Every question involves a
presupposition. To say that a question "does not arise" is
the ordinary English way of saying that it involves a
presupposition which is not in fact being made, and the fact
that something causes a certain question to arise is the
logical efficacy of that thing. The logical efficacy of a
supposition does not depend on the truth of what is
supposed, or even on its being thought true, but only on its
being supposed. To assume is to suppose by an act of free
choice. A presupposition is either relative or absolute. A
relative presupposition is one which stands relatively to
one question as its presupposition and relatively to another
question as its answer. An absolute presupposition is one
748

which stands, relatively to all questions to which it is


related, as a presupposition, never as an answer. Absolute
presuppositions are not propositions; the distinction
between truth and falsehood does not apply to absolute
presuppositions at all. (EM, 21-32).

3. The discovery of presuppositions and the distinction between


relative and absolute presuppositions is not accomplished by
low-grade thinking, such as apprehension or intuition (as in
realist theories of knowledge), nor by simple introspection.
It is accomplished by high-grade thinking, a skillful mental
effort which brings about not only a difference of degree in
the intensity of thinking, but also a difference of kind in
its quality. Instead of passive apprehension, high-grade
thinking is an active process of asking questions in a
systematic and orderly fashion. The thinking that is
involved in the disentangling and arranging of questions is
called analysis, and the analysis which detects absolute
presuppositions is called metaphysical analysis. Since
analysis is what gives science its scientific character, and
since in their method of operation science and metaphysics
are the same (i.e. insofar as they both distinguish between
relative and absolute presuppositions), science and
metaphysics stand or fall together. (EM, 34-41, 170-71).

4. All metaphysical questions are historical questions, and all


metaphysical propositions are historical propositions. The
problems of metaphysics are historical problems; its methods
are historical methods. Metaphysics is the attempt to find
out what absolute presuppositions have been made by this or
that person or group of persons, on this or that occasion or
group of occasions, in the course of this or that piece of
thinking. The metaphysical rubric proceeding an absolute
presupposition is: "In such and such a phase of scientific
thought it is (or was) absolutely presupposed that . . . ."
(EM, 47, 49, 55, 62).

5. The historian makes his own statements on his own authority


according to what he finds the evidence in his posession to
prove when he analyzes it with a certain question in mind.
The subject matter of metaphysics is about a certain class
of historical facts, namely absolute presuppositions. Its
methods are the methods of history, i.e. to get at the facts
by the interpretation of evidence. In its form metaphysics
is systematic in the sense in which all historical thought
is systematic, i.e. as exhibited in the clear and orderly
749

manner in which it states its problems and marshals and


interprets evidence for their solution; but it is not
systematic in the sense of being a deductive science. As an
historical science, metaphysics shares the presuppositions
of all history. (EM, 59-65).

6. Absolute presuppositions, like historical facts, do not


occur singly, but in sets or constellations. The presup-
positions in a constellation are logically related as a
single fact; they are made at once in one and the same piece
of thinking, and each is consupponible with all the others.
To be consupponible means that it must be logically possible
for a person who supposes any one of them to suppose
concurrently all the rest. Within the constellation each
presupposition taken separately is also a single historical
fact, and is not deductively related to the others. The
metaphysician's business is not only to study the likenesses
and unlikenesses of several different constellations of
absolute presuppositions but also to find out on what
occasions and by what processes one of them has turned into
another. One phase changes into another because the first
phase was in unstable equilibrium in which its fabric was
under strain, and the historian analyzes the internal
strains to which a given constellation is subjected, and the
means by which it takes up these strains or prevents them
from breaking into pieces. (EM, 66-67, 72-74).

7. Anti-metaphysics is metaphysics undertaken by an amateur who


does not consider it his proper job, but is impelled to do
so for various motives. It takes three forms. (a)
Progressive anti-metaphysics is metaphysics undertaken by
someone whose proper job (science) demands it, but because
it has been neglected by the professionals he has to
undertake it, and his resentment makes him feel himself to
be the professional metaphysician's enemy, and his own work
as an attack on their work. (b) Reactionary antimetaphysics
is metaphysics undertaken because one wishes to do
metaphysics consistent with the principles of obsolete
pseudo-metaphysical doctrines, but inconsistent with
contemporary metaphysics, which he fears as a danger to his
own work, and therefore his fear of this inconsistency makes
him regard his own work as an attack on metaphysics in the
contemporary sense. (c) Irrationalist antimetaphysics is
metaphysics undertaken because one wishes to abolish
scientific thinking itself in order to bring into existence
a form of life in which all the determining factors should
be emotional. (EM, 82-83, 88, 99-100).
750

8. Positivistic (progressive) anti-metaphysics fails because it


presupposes what it simultaneously denies. What it denies is
that metaphysics is possible, because the statements of
metaphysics are actually propositions which are not
empirically verifiable or falsifiable, and are therefore
pseudo-propositions. But the position which states that
metaphysical assertions are true or false propositions is
not the true science of metaphysics (i.e. the historical
science of absolute presuppositions) but pseudo-metaphysics,
and is the result of the logical mistake of confusing
presuppositions with propositions, and of assuming that it
is only propositions that can have logical efficacy in
causing questions to arise in scientific inquiry. What
positivistic anti-metaphysics presupposes is that scientific
thinking is possible and legitimate, which means that
thinking which makes absolute presuppositions (science) is
possible. But since absolute presuppositions are the
assertions that are truly metaphysical, the denial of
metaphysics is the denial of scientific thinking. Therefore
the only way that positivistic metaphysics can survive its
own criticism is by confusing true metaphysics with
pseudo-metaphysics. (EM, 148-49, 162-64, 169-71).

9. Reactionary anti-metaphysics (Samuel Alexander's realism)


fails because it does not recognize that absolute presup-
positions are not timeless truths, but have a history of
their own. This position recognizes both that the subject
matter of metaphysics is absolute presuppositions and that
these are not proven but recognized as facts and held with
an attitude of unquestioning acceptance. But what it fails
to acknowledge is that absolute presuppositions are not
facts apprehended by compresence of a mind with an object,
or even perceived as a pervasive set of characteristics of
everything that exists. They are arrived at by analytical
questioning aimed at discovering what is presupposed in a
particular case of scientific thinking. These
presuppositions are not truths recognized semper, ubique, ad
omnibus, but are presupposed by scientific thinking at a
particular time, and are themselves subject to change and
development. (EM, 172-80).

10. Irrationalist anti-metaphysics (psychology as the pseudo-


science of mine) fails because it confuses thinking with
feeling, and refuses to recognize that all thought is cri-
teriological. metaphysics is one branch of the science of
thought, because it aims at discovering absolute presup-
positions, which are thoughts. If psychology is the science
which tells us how we think, its claim to be the sciency of
absolute presuppositions appears to be legitimate.
751

But psychology treats thought not as criteriological (i.e.


as including as an integral part of itself the thought of a
standard or criterion by reference to which it is judged to
be a successful or unsuccessful, or true or false, piece of
thinking), but as an empirical (non-criteriological)
feeling--a relic of 18th century materialistic epistemology.
But to treat thought without regard to its truth is to treat
scientific thought in the same way, which makes science
itself a meaningless word. Since the conclusions of
empirical psychology with respect to thought are not
established by its methods (experimental observation of
feelings), they must arise elsewhere, and such prejudice
that teaches by precept that thought is only feeling serves
as the propaganda of irrationalism. (EM, 101-03, 107,
111-14, 117, 120, 129, 142).
752

3. Obstacles to Understanding Collingwood's Reformed Metaphysics.

If the architecture of the Essay on Metaphysics presents

us with a design that is at least three-quarters familiar, the

interior is an alienating nightmare. The reader encounters

difficulties understanding the strategy of arguments, the

absence of satisfying conclusions to a line of thought, what

appears as abusive insults rather than convincing critical

elenchi, and failure to define adequately key concepts in a way

that alleviates the reader's growing sense of puzzlement.

(a) The first obstacle one encounters is Collingwood's

unhistorical and unscholarly treatment of Aristotle's meta-

physics, which is misrepresented as a science of "pure being"

--a term that Aristotle did not use, and would not be acceptable

to him as an equivalent to his own expression, "being as being"

(τ ο ο ν η ο ν ). As a prologue to a study of metaphysics as an

historical science it is startling to find Collingwood ignoring

the obvious orientation of Aristotle's metaphysics towards

individual substance (ο υ σ ι α or τ ο δ ε τ ι ο ν ) that has a

separate existence as opposed to an attribute

(π α θ ο s κ α τ α σ υ µ β ε β η κ ο s) which can only exist

secondary to, or dependent upon, a substance.1 Furthermore it is

axiomatic

_____________________
1 Hippocrates G. Apostle, tr., Aristotle's Metaphysics
(Bloomington, 1966), 1017b 23-26, p. 83; cf. 1003b 5-10, p. 54.
753

with Aristotle that universals are incapable of separate

existence, and Collingwood need not have read far into

Aristotle's treatise to find it stated as a major obstacle

(α π ο ρ ι α ) and a definitive objection to Plato's theory of

forms that being cannot be a genus, because to be is to be a this

or something particular but a genus is something general.2 In

fact what Collingwood is describing when he writes of pure being

is what Aristotle would recognize as matter--its only

characteristic being its complete indeterminacy.

The reader is also puzzled when Collingwood, with

slightly more accuracy, cites the three titles Aristotle gave to

the kind of inquiry presented in the collection of treatises

known as the metaphysics, i.e. First Science, Wisdom, and

Theology, and then, after paraphrasing what these terms mean

(presumably for Aristotle), ignores or slightly glosses over the

reasons why Aristotle considered these different names for one

and the same science with the same object.3 Instead he

arbitrarily chooses to consider only two definitions of

metaphysics: as the science of

_______________________
2 Ibid, 998bl5-35, p. 45: "Thus if 'unity' or 'being' is
indeed a genus, no differentia will be either a being or one."
Cf. 1038al-30, p. 128: definition by downward division, i.e. by
differentiae, leads to substance.

3 In fairness to Collingwood it must be added that the


triple orientation of Aristotle's Metaphysics has proven re-
sistant to two millenia of attempts at unification until Fr.
Joseph Owens' monumental study, The Doctrine of Being in the
Aristotelian Metaphysics (Toronto, 1951).
754

pure being, and as the science of the presuppositions underlying

ordinary science (EM, 11). Since it is not transparent that

these two senses are mutually exclusive alternatives, why does

Collingwood assume that rejecting the one, i.e. metaphysics as

ontology, necessarily affirms the other? In fact they seem to

overlap, since it is an absolute presupposition of ordinary

science that its objects exist, and conversely an absolute

presupposition must exist to be a fact. And what of metaphysics

as theology, which is not further discussed in Parts I and II,

but appears again as the first example in Part III ("The

Existence of God")?

(b) Of course Collingwood can be forgiven for what might

turn out to be a creative misinterpretation of Aristotle, as

well as for an arbitrary starting point for his essay, if they

were justified by subsequent maneuvers. If metaphysics is not

the ontological analysis of pure being, perhaps it can still

survive as the grounding science of first principles that

Aristotle thought it could be (EM, 19-20). Unfortunately this

presents us with a second set of obstacles. For Aristotle such a

First Philosophy was grounded on an analytic of scientific

knowledge in general (ε π ι σ τ η µ η ) as presented in the

Organon. For Collingwood this involves first redefining science

as a Q-A process of on-going inquiry rather than a deductive

system of propositions (EM, 22-24), and then identifying the

first principles for such a system as the absolute


755

presuppositions which underly all its questions (EM, 25-28). The

third stage is to distinguish between relative and absolute

presuppositions, where the former are themselves answers to

questions and the latter are not (EM, 29-33). The province of

metaphysics is the discovery, comparison, and organizational

structure of absolute presuppositions (EM, 37-40).

The force of this argument for a science of metaphysics

depends on Collingwood's ability to maintain successfully the

distinction between relative and absolute presuppositions, for

without it there is only an arbitrary stopping point for a

regressive inquiry from answer to question to presupposition to

question to presupposition, . . . (etc.). But if an absolute

presupposition is one which stands, relatively to all questions

to which it is related, as a presupposition and never as an

answer (EM, 31), and if every statement that anybody ever makes

is made in answer to a question (EM, 23), then how can absolute

presuppositions ever be discovered? For surely discoveries are

made by asking questions, in this case of the form, "What is the

absolute presupposition of this and all other questions in this

inquiry?"

Perhaps Collingwood meant us to understand that an

absolute presupposition is never the answer to a question in a

progressive inquiry--something one comes upon along with other

answers to questions in
756

a systematic inquiry. Thus the absolute presupposition that

"every event has a cause" (EM, 50, 52, 179) is not something a

scientist discovers while pursuing the answer to a question

about the cause, for example, of an eclipse. It occurs when he

leaves off investigating particular causes and asks the

metaphysical question, "Why do I assume that there is a cause of

this or that or any event?" This is a retrogressive

question--one which is not progressing toward an answer but

retrogressing from a question to its presupposition. There would

thus be two inquiries, one being that of progressive ordinary

science and the other the retrogressive metaphysical science,

and the restrictions concerning absolute presuppositions would

refer to questions in the former inquiry, not the latter.

If this is what Collingwood meant us to understand. then

we might say that once again he has expressed himself in an

unfortunate manner, and this failure is not mitigated by his

poor choice of examples to illustrate his reformed metaphysics.

The issue of causality, for example, is a metaphysical issue of

great antiquity, yet still a contemporary problem and suitably

general enough to be a subject for reformed metaphysical

analysis. But as an example of an absolute presupposition, as

Collingwood presents it, it creates more problems that it

solves. In Chapter VI Collingwood gives the following three

versions of the principle of causality as exemplary of

Newtonian, Kantian, and Einsteinian sciences


757

respectively: (i) some events have causes; (ii) all events have

causes; and (iii) no events have causes (EM, 51-52). Setting

aside difficulties with accepting this as an historically ac-

curate assessment of the principle of causality for the phases

of physical science mentioned, the reader is still puzzled by

the apparent non-absoluteness of these presuppositions. Surely

any one of them is an answer to the question, "Do all, some, or

no events have causes?"--a question which Aristotle may well

have pondered. And are there not questions of even greater

priority, which Aristotle definitely did ponder, viz. "What is a

cause?" and "Are there any causes?" Is not Collingwood's

analysis of causality in the final example of the Essay on

Metaphysics itself an examination of these two questions,

insofar as (in Chapter XXIX) he discusses the three meanings of

the term "cause" and rejects the third as an abandoned AP of

contemporary (Einsteinian) science?

And even these three senses of "cause" as Collingwood

defines them are not primary, since they can themselves be the

answer to further questions. For example in Sense I, "that which

is 'caused' is the free and deliberate act of a conscious and

responsible agent, and 'causing' him to do it means affording

him a motive for doing it" (EM, 285). If a cause is a kind of

motive, what is a motive? Are there various motives, of which

cause is but one, or are cause and motive equivalent terms in

every sense? Are there free but not deliberate acts of agents,

or not-free but
758

deliberate acts? Etc. If to have an attitude of unquestioning

acceptance toward APs is to stifle as illegitimate questions

such as these, then Collingwood's reform of metaphysics takes on

the appearance of an intellectual purge, an example of an anti--

metaphysics which inhibits scientific inquiry rather than pro-

moting it. And if it is possible for an historian as acute as

Collingwood to be mistaken about the absoluteness of pre-

suppositions in a case as relatively simple as this one, what

about more complex and subtle systems of APs in science? What is

the measure of the absoluteness of presuppositions?

But even accepting some friendly modifications of his

Q-A logic as applied to his metaphysical program, there are

further difficulties with the doctrine of absolute presupposi-

tions. The problems start with the fact that Collingwood never

says what an absolute presupposition is. Is it at least a

statement? One assumes it must be, since it has a sentential

form, and is made in answer to a metaphysical question, or

during a metaphysical analysis. But why does Collingwood then

forbid us, on penalty of lapsing into metaphysical absurdity,

from asking the further question, "Is this statement (we do not

call it a proposition, since propositions are statements made

only in answer to progressive questions in an inquiry) true or

false?" For if it is not true or false in the same sense that a


759

proposition in the progressive inquiry is, does that mean that

it is not true or false in any sense whatever?

The problem becomes acute when it comes to constella-

tions of presuppositions, since Collingwood allows that meta-

physical analysis can uncover absolute presuppositions in groups

called constellations, and can furthermore determine if within

that constellation one or more presuppositions can be

"con-supponible" with the others (EM, 66, 76, 287). If not, then

there will be "strains" in the constellation, which will make it

"unstable" and therefore eligible for the process of

transformation into another constellation (EM, 48 n.l; 74, 76).

But how is it possible to recognize that one AP is not

con-supponible with another without deciding which APs within

the constellation are more stable, or at least less stressful,

than the others? Does that not assume that because one group of

APs are what they are, a given AP or group of APs cannot

consistently be included in the con-supponible group? And is not

consistency one acceptable sense of the term, "true" and

inconsistency of "false"?

And even if we ignore Collingwood's own statement that

the "strains" in a constellation of APs is due to their "mutual

incompatibility" (EM, 287) and suggest that such strains be

analyzed solely on the grounds of their decreased adequacy or

efficacy in causing questions to arise, the problem is not

resolved--only shifted to even more


760

obscure territory. Certainly a presupposition such as the

perfection of circular celestial orbits was "efficacious" in

causing questions to arise, and that is not the sense in which

it caused "strains" in the constellation of presuppositions

which led to the passage from Ptolomaic to Keplerian astronomy.

What we are left with is a situation in which the

metaphysician-historian, lacking adequate definitions of terms

like "absolute presupposition," "constellation," "con-

supponible," "strain" etc., is set a seemingly impossible task.

Lacking any clear idea of his subject matter, we must ask, like

Plato's Socrates, how he is to know when he has succeeded in

finding an instance of what he is looking for?

(c) Which brings us to our third set of problems. Even

if we could accept a non-ontological metaphysics of absolute

presuppositions, the announcement that these are discovered by

historical methods, and that all metaphysical propositions are

historical propositions is an expression of historicism extreme

enough to warrant assigning Collingwood a paradigmatic position

in the checkered career of the subject of radical revisions of

traditional metaphysics. As we have already pointed out, the

doctrine that metaphysics is an historical science is the

positive version of the principle stated negatively in the

Autobiography that in philosophy there are no eternal problems

(A, 60; cf. EM, 64-65). But when coupled with the remarkable

statement that metaphysics has always been an historical


761

science (albeit not fully conscious of the fact and for that

reason never fully scientific) it appears to be a revision not

compatible with even the acceptable version of Aristotle's

metaphysics. For it certainly cannot be denied that when

Aristotle tried to uncover the first principles of physics he

did not have in mind a science bound to 4th century B.C. Greek

culture, but one which would achieve the status of ε π ι σ τ η µ η

--science as a stable understanding of change based on

unchanging first principles. And when Kant set himself the task

of discovering how metaphysics as a science is possible, he did

not think its possibility rested on truth-neutral

presuppositions which would change with time (CEPC, 137). On the

contrary, every indication is that he thought himself to have

discovered all the true principles of scientific thought, and

that synthetic a priori judgments have a necessity that is not

historically contingent but is rooted in the structure of the

knowing mind.

Of course, Collingwood was aware that his predecessors

did not explicitly say that what they were doing was history,

and he merely chides them for not understanding what they were

in fact doing (EM, 18-20, 58). Our difficulty with Collingwood's

historical metaphysics is deeper than a factual error on the

matter of what metaphysics has "always" been. It has to do with

the sort of "facts" that the metaphysician is setting out to

discover. In the last chapter we found Collingwood arguing that


762

what makes history scientific is precisely the degree to which

the historian decides what is to be accepted as a fact, and that

this is dependent on the historian's questioning activity. Now

we find Collingwood taking just the reverse position: it is a

certain kind of fact (AP) that determines what questions are

asked. Approaching the Essay on Metaphysics from this

perspective we are forced to conclude that as fact to be

discovered, an AP must be the answer to a question. Collingwood

appears to acknowledge this himself when he indicates that the

"metaphysical rubric" (i.e. "In this or that piece of scientific

thinking by this person or group of persons at such and such a

time it was absolutely presupposed that . . . ") is necessary

for the factuality of an AP to be established.

But this appears to involve Collingwood in a contra-

diction: if it is an historical fact, an absolute presupposition

is determined by questions; and if it is metaphysically

absolute, a presupposition is not determined by any question,

but is that which specifies which questions sensibly arise in a

systematic inquiry. This time the avenue of escape by pos-

tulating the bi-directionality of inquiry has been cut off by

the fusion of both routes: the methods of metaphysics are the

methods of history, and the presuppositions of metaphysics are

those of history. Therefore if history has presuppositions (and

Collingwood admits that it does), there is at least one case

where absolute presuppositions


763

are the answers to questions in a progressive inquiry, namely

the case of history. Is Collingwood prepared to defend the

thesis that the absolute presuppositions of history are

determined to be facts by the questions of history? Can the

serpent swallow its own tail?

The issue of the presuppositions of history brings us up

before another aspect of the obstacle, and this one joins with

the first to form the beginning of a barricade. In the

Autobiography Collingwood has told us that the re-enacted his-

torical event is prevented from becoming confused with the

present thinking of the historian by being "incapsulated in a

context of present thoughts." In the last chapter we found

Collingwood arguing that the historian is able to keep his own a

priori imagination from becoming unglued, so that the historian

is prevented from confusing himself with Admiral Nelson at the

Battle of Trafalgar. But to deny ontology its day runs the risk

of being incapable of distinguishing such realms as these in

anything but a hypothetical way. By what presuppositions does

the historian distinguish between his own "real" life (the

ordinary world of lived experience or lebenswelt) and the "real"

world of his historical protagonists? Aside from the practical

observation that any bonafide confusion between these realms may

make life-sustaining decisions rather poorly grounded, the

theoretical implications for Collingwood's reformed metaphysics

threaten to be equally tragic. For it will not


764

do to define the domain of history as the "deeds of men done in

the past," and then refuse to deal with the ontological question

of how past and present are distinguished in one's "real"

situation. Somehow the presuppositions of what we are calling

ordinary experience are the ground from which and within which

the presuppositions of history are located. That distinction and

that relationship are not well served by the simple

identification of history and metaphysics.

(d) Having raised the spectre of an a priori imagination

run amuck, we turn to our final group of obstacles, those

centering on his discussion of anti-metaphysics, and especially

his vituperation on psychology. For while he castigates

psychology as the pseudo-science of thought, in the entire

section on anti-metaphysics he himself engages in the crassest

kind of popular psychologizing. When he describes those

philosophical "amateurs" who are thrust into doing metaphysics

in the guise of anti-metaphysics, he says that they take an

attitude opposed to metaphysics because they either fear or

resent the subject matter. On what grounds does he make this

assertion? In this imputation of motives, is not Collingwood

out-psychologizing the psychologists? Completely ignoring any

positive benefit which behavioral science has had on

civilization, Collingwood's assault appears to itself contribute

to the "propaganda of irrationalism" that he attributes to

psychologists: for certainly there is


765

a kind of irrationalism to rationalism--i.e. reason which fails

to provide reason with respect to un-reason or sub-reason--and

this is where psychology has made its greatest inroads, racing

in where philosophy feared to tread.4 But at best Collingwood's

diatribe is anti-metaphysics in the sense that it not only

discovers an absolute presupposition of what is generally

accepted to be a contemporary science (psychology) but also de-

clares this presupposition to be false; for what else would it

mean to call psychology a "pseudo-science" of thought? Does the

Greek prefix succeed in disguising the fact that a false-science

is one which proceeds from a false absolute presupposition?

What is worse, the criticism that Collingwood levels at

psychology appears to be equally applicable to his own reformed

metaphysics--i.e. that it fails to treat thought as

criteriological, meaning that it ignores the aspect of thought

as true or false (EM, 107, 115). For are not

_______________________
4 Is there any place in Collingwood's version of civi-
lization, or in his philosophy of mind, for the less-than-fully
rational man? Surely children have a place, according to The New
Leviathan, since they are in process of becoming fully rational.
But what about those who never will--the mentally handicapped
and the mentally ill? Collingwood comes close to aristocratic
arrogance when he sets standards below which what is occurring
does not deserve the name of thought. Psychology, whatever its
faults, has made advances in the understanding and treatment of
sub-rational behavior, and Collingwood's failure to acknowledge
this progress in the Essay on_Metaphysics is not to his credit.
766

absolute presuppositions thoughts? And treating them as

true/false neutral--does this not mean treating them as "data"

or facts on a par with feeling and its objects? To say that they

may be something of which one may not be aware either dodges the

question or severs absolute presuppositions from their logical

function--their efficacy in causing questions to arise, a

function that Collingwood is anxious to maintain. Once an ab-

solute presupposition is discovered it is invalid to ask if it

is true, or on what evidence it is accepted, or how it is to be

demonstrated, or by what right it is presupposed (EM, 47). In

short, the acceptance of an absolute presupposition as a

truth-neutral fact precludes any question of treating it as a

thought, and therefore renders it on a par with objects of

feeling. It reduces a thought (an absolute presupposition) to

something that is not thought (something that is not cri-

teriological) and is therefore as much a pseudo-science of

thought as psychology. By what right does Collingwood then

declare that metaphysics is one branch of the science of thought

(EM, 101)?

And while he appears to be less vulnerable in his as-

sault on A. J. Ayer and logical positivism, one still cannot

help but notice that Collingwood is guilty of some of the same

charges that he levels against them. The most serious is that

after conceding the victory to them by admitting that absolute

presuppositions are not verifiable or falsifiable,


767

he then counterattacks with the weaker charge that they did not

ask what metaphysical assertions are before declaring them to be

either tautologous or meaningless (EM, 165). But has Collingwood

not made the same mistake? Instead of asking what absolute

presuppositions are if they are not true or false as answers to

questions, he leads the reader to believe that they are not true

or false in any other sense either. He never really tells us

what absolute presuppositions are.

4. The Unity of the Autobiographical Themes.

Is there some standpoint from within the framework

provided by the autobiographical interpretation that will allow

us to overcome these obstacles, or at least to soften some of

these harsh features of the Essay on Metaphysics? Having forced

ourselves to face the paradoxes of Collingwood's reformed

metaphysics, if we are determined to assimilate our experience

of this grotesque memorial we must ask ourselves what relation

there is between what Collingwood did and what he was trying to

achieve. But this requires understanding it not just in the

negative and partial sense in which it is an expression of his

opposition to "realism" as a philosophical movement that

(arguably) threatened to disrupt science and civilization, but

in the positive sense of a work that issued from the unified

center of his thought.


768

For another thinker this might not be necessary or even

possible, since it might not be considered an ideal worth

striving for. A philosopher who conceives of his role in a more

analytic or critical vein, for example, might be content to put

forth his thought in a series of vignettes on various subjects,

and it may be of no concern to him what the relationships are

not only between the subjects chosen but even among the

conclusions reached by his analysis--so long as it was done in a

craftsmanly manner. But for the Collingwood of the

Autobiography, for whom the goal of philosophy is rapprochement,

this is not a satisfactory state of affairs. To this extent

Collingwood was never an analytic philosopher.

Nor did he set out to be. One of Collingwood's first

public addresses was delivered at the 1919 Ruskin Centenary

Conference held near his home in Coniston--where he also spent

his final days. In this address, given at the beginning of his

intellectual career, Collingwood laid out, with his char-

acteristic self-assurance, what is to be expected of a phil-

osopher. Speaking of Ruskin's failure to achieve a fully

philosophical outlook (and bear in mind that Collingwood's

father was Ruskin's biographer and close friend), he then

distinguished between "having a philosophy" and "being a

philosopher." Ruskin had a philosophy, but he was not a phil-

osopher (EPA, 11). What does this mean?


769

When I speak of a man's philosophy, I mean something of


this sort. I see a man living a long and busy life; I see
him doing a large number of different things, or writing a
large number of different books. And I ask myself, do these
actions, or these books, hang together? Is there any reason
why the man who wrote this book should have gone on to
write that one, or is it pure chance? Is there anything
like a constant purpose, or a consistent point of view,
running through all the man's work? Now if you ask these
questions about a particular man, you will generally find
that there are certain central principles which the man
takes as fundamental and incontrovertible, which he assumes
as true in all his thinking and acting. These principles
form, as it were, the nucleus of his whole mental life:
they are the centre from which all his activities radiate.
You may think of them as a kind of ring of solid
thought--something infinitely tough and hard and
resistant--to which everything the man does is attached.
The ring is formed of a number of different ideas or
principles, welded together by some force of mutual
cohesion. This ring of thought . . . is what I mean by a
man's philosophy . . . . The fact seems to be that a man's
deepest convictions are precisely those he never puts into
words . . . . (E)verybody has a philosophy, but only the
philosopher makes it is his business to probe into the mind
and lay bare that recess in which the ultimate beliefs lie
hidden. (EPA, 9-11).

Here we have the basic program for the discovery of absolute

presuppositions that only came to fruition twenty years later in

the Essay on Metaphysics. But can we apply this standard to

Collingwood himself? Are there certain central principles which

he takes as fundamental and incontrovertible, and which he

assumes as true in all his thinking?

Throughout both cycles of our carrousel excursion

through Collingwood's published writings we have repeatedly

tried to catch hold of this "ring of thought" and to measure the

degree to which it conforms to the autobiographical in-

terpretation. We have examined the four


770

autobiographical themes as they occur and re-occur in the

earlier and later writings. But we have examined them separately

rather than as a coherent system, and the weakness of this

strategy is now apparent; for as we confront the obstacles to

first philosophy in the Essay on Metaphysics it is not clear how

the four themes form a "consistent point of view" from which

vantage point we can measure the strength of his self-interpre-

tation by its ability to aid us in untying the knots and laying

claim to Collingwood's metaphysical inheritance for ourselves.

In particular it is not apparent why an anti-realist

position necessarily implies an anti-F-logic, or why the latter

gives rise to either the Q-A logic of the Autobiography and the

Essay on Metaphysics, or the D-logic of Speculum Mentis and the

Essay on Philosophical Method. Nor is it evident how either of

these themes is related to an ideal of rapprochement, which

seems to have more to do with resolving experiential alienation

than with formal contradiction or dialectical opposition. Nor

again is it clear how a reconciliation between history and

philosophy can be regarded as a paradigmatic for rapprochement

philosophy in all its forms, or finally how such a philosophy

can remain opposed to realism root and branch, given its

orientation toward unification of opposing viewpoints like that

of realism and idealism. So while we have steadfastly


771

resisted the temptation to provide the missing "figure in the

carpet" where Collingwood has not done so himself, this

unfortunately leaves us with a badly fractured Collingwood who

remains for the most part true to the autobiographical

self-interpretation, but at the expense of a clear understanding

of the unity of his thought, by which standard he would surely

wish his own philosophy to be judged.

Therefore we pause at this point to take a final overall

look at Collingwood's philosophy as we have examined it to this

point, trusting that by compressing it into the span of a few

pages we can reveal its architectural strengths and shed its

decorative weaknesses.

We began our survey with his earliest published book,

Religion and Philosophy, the highlight of which, Collingwood

recalled (some twenty-two years later in the Autobiography), was

a passage in which he criticized psychological studies of

religion for their treatment of mind as an external phenomenon

or thing. Such an approach to mind renders religious con-

sciousness opaque, because it refuses to participate in the

thought processes it claims to be studying, which leaves "the

cold unreality of thought which is the thought of nothing, ac-

tion with no purpose, and fact with no meaning" (RP, 42; FR,

77). With the unbalanced negativism typical of much of his later

philosophy, he failed to tell his readers in the Autobiography

what the positive phase to this criticism was. This we found


772

for ourselves by examining the argument of Religion and

Philosophy, which pivots on the reality of communication and

inter-personal identity: for it was in this earliest work that

we found Collingwood already arguing that the starting point of

any investigation of mind or any theory of knowledge is the fact

that persons do communicate their knowledge, and this means that

two or more persons can actually share the same knowledge (RP,

98-99; FR, 170-71). He goes so far as to say that since the esse

of mind is de hac re cogitare, when two minds think the same

thought they become actually one mind, sharing between them the

unity of consciousness which is the mark of the individual (RP,

101; FR, 173), and by de hac re it is clear that he did not mean

primarily a material entity but a meaning. His argument about

re-enactment in The Idea of History is the final refinement of

this very same line of thought: re-enacting someone else's act

of thought means thinking that same thought for oneself, not one

like it (IH, 286-92). The proper context for his early

rapprochement philosophy is therefore to be found in the

communicative relationship of minds with one another, the

failure of which (as error) calls forth the effort of

reconciliation.

But so much cannot be said without saying more, since it

is evident that a mind can communicate with itself--or fail to

do so. This becomes the overall concern of his second

philosophical work, Speculum


773

Mentis, which expands the ideal of rapprochement to include the

overcoming not only of the communication gaps in meaning between

persons but also the same kind of disunity within oneself. The

forms under which we interpret our own experience--as imagined,

believed, observed, inferred, etc.--are in the modern world

alienated from one another, which tends to render the unity of

self-consciousness in need of internal rapprochement (SM, 30,

4142). The basis for achieving this inner reconciliation is

modeled on the same process that occurs when failure to com-

municate makes the reconciliation between persons necessary.

This cannot be by the kind of knowing that occurs in art, where

the mind contemplates monadic imaginary objects (SM, 60-61); nor

by religious consciousness, where the mind asserts as true a

sacred object (God) as a symbol, the meaning of which it can

never literally translate (SM, 119, 128-29); nor yet by

scientific thinking, which leaves its object always separated

from mind by the distance measurable by the difference between

universal and particular, law and instance (SM, 185-86). The

kind of reconciling knowledge we seek to repair the torn fabric

of self-consciousness is first fully exemplified in historical

thinking, which is the first truly non-abstract or concrete

knowledge, because it is the first form of experience in which

the object is individually recognizable as something wholly the

same as the mind which seeks it--i.e. thought as an active

agency.
774

While the concept of history and its philosophy has a

long and complex development in Collingwood's career, he never

abandoned this insight. He always returned to the historical act

of an agent as the model for sense-location in thinking, the

active dimension of mind stressed by the Italian and other

post-Kantian idealists, with whom he felt a spiritual kinship.5

With historical thinking there is no feature of experience, no

attitude of mind towards its object which is alien (SM, 218),

because it is all the work of mind itself. And where history

appears to set itself the impossible task of understanding the

infinite whole of fact (SM, 239), it is relieved from this

impossible burden by the limiting reflection of itself in each

of its objects, each being a "mirror of the mind." This is where

historical thought provides a challenge to typically

sensation-bound empiricist epistemologies. Where the "plain

man's metaphysic" places mind and matter out side one another,

and then finds itself unable to bridge the gap that it has

postulated (RP, 73), empiricist epistemology provides an

intermediary in the form of sensation, but is equally baffled by

the lack of unifying meaning in the flux of sensation (SM, 188).

In both cases that which is known is an object presumed to be

indifferent to the act which seeks to grasp it. But in the

_____________________
5 Cf. "The Present Need of a Philosophy," Philosophy, 9
(1934), 262-65: "What is needed to-day is . . . a philosophy
showing that the human will is of a piece with nature in being
genuinely creative, a vera causa, though singular in being
consciously creative."
775

case of history the object is itself a thought which seeks

understanding (IH, 294). Historical thought is saved from the

ultimate frustration of trying to penetrate the infinite and

unknowable realm of the "thing in itself" by the recognition of

itself in each of the objects it studies, each of these being a

"concrete universal" or individual meaning expressed as a

deliberate act--a "part" in which the whole mind is present and

in which the whole agent is reflected (SM, 218-19).6 With

historical understanding the gap between mind and its object is

bridged from both sides, the object reaching out to be

understood (as evidence), and consciousness reaching to grasp

the same act in its aspect as past thought (as historical

interpretation) (IH, 304). Reconciliation at this point is

successful because the mind has found something wholly

intelligible: that which is object is also subject (SM, 242-45,

249).

In the essays on the philosophy of history which Col-

lingwood wrote in the decade of the twenties we find him con-

tinually trying to reverse the naturalistic or empiricistic bias

of his readers, including that of some of his idealistic

contemporaries (like Croce, whose work he admired).

__________________________
6 Caesar's crossing the Rubicon was not the mere physi-
cal passage of a body across water, nor was it the mere act of
his legs. It was also not an imaginary or hypothetical crossing.
It was an expression of the reality that was Caesar, and
expressed that which Caesar represents in history. But it also
is only a "part" of Caesar's life--but a significant part, a
part that reflected the whole of it: his courage and daring, his
foresight and confidence in risking the fortunes of Rome.
776

In these essays it becomes increasingly more obvious that in

making the history-philosophy reconciliation paradigmatic for

all other kinds of rapprochement between forms of experience, he

is suggesting that rather than using the mind-thing or mind--

object polarity as the primary instance of knowing and then

extending this to historical events (which tends to render

events thing-like or objective, but at the expense of always

remaining distantiated from the event by the same attitude of

abstract objectivity) the exact reverse of this situation is

what is called for in 20th Century thought. In historical

thinking the mind-mind polarity is regarded as primary, and as

paradigmatic for thinking; the mind-object situation is

secondary or derivative. Collingwood's entire philosophical

development is an attempt to carry out the program implicit in

this paradigm shift.

But if the mind-object dichotomy is overcome by taking

the mind-mind identity exemplified in historical understanding

as the primary instance of what it is to successfully know

something, and if Collingwood found himself allied with the

Italian idealists in such a fundamental standpoint, his

articulation of this conviction took a direction all its own. It

has both realistic and idealistic dimensions. Its realistic

moment is in the recognition of the factuality of history and

its bonds with evidence; its idealistic moment is in analysis of

the thought processes


777

that are involved in interpreting that evidence, and the

criteria for deciding when the interpretative effort results in

the unification of thought that is being sought. As we traced

his thought through its development in the essays of the

twenties into the period during which he composed the Essay on

Philosophical Method, we found Collingwood showing a growing

awareness of the levels of meaning to the concept of history,

and an increasing sensitivity to the criteria whereby one can

decide not only when minds are reconciled, or even when forms of

consciousness within a mind have attained rapprochement, but

when individual acts of consciousness are unified as an

achievement of the overall nisus of consciousness toward meaning

at all levels of thought. (a) In Religion and Philosophy

reconciliation is regarded as complete when it is shown that two

forms of thought (such as religion and philosophy) intend the

same object, or mutually co-imply (or presuppose) one

another--without recognizing any difference of degree or kind in

the resulting identification (RP, 107-19; FR, 178-88). (b) In

Speculum Mentis this "concrete identity of cooperation" becomes

a reconciliation by means of a developing "dialectical series"

in which each of the reconciliata is a modification of its

predecessor, but in which relations of opposition and

differences of kind do not yet entail relations of distinction

and differences of degree (SM, 55, 206-208). (c) In the Essay on

Philosophical Method
778

Collingwood completed this line of thought in his "scale of

forms" in which the rapprochement (or "overlap") of concepts

entails that between the reconciliata are relations of both

opposition and distinction, and differences of both degree and

kind (EPM, 73-76). The ultimate grounding of rapprochement at

this point is dependent on the inclusive and exclusive

relationships that are involved in the intensional structures of

meaning.

But while we have found that there is an increasingly

more prominent awareness of the meaning-component to knowledge

in Collingwood's later philosophy we have been careful to note

in our survey of the earlier works that this is neither an un-

heralded arrival nor a novel idea. Thus in addition to being his

point in common with the Italian idealists, before that alliance

became explicit we find Collingwood (in Religion and Philosophy)

arguing that the true task of historical theology is to find out

not only what was said by the historical Jesus, but what was

meant (RP, 43; FR, 78), and that proving the existence of matter

or of God requires understanding first what meanings are

attached to the words (RP, 62-63). And in Speculum Mentis

Collingwood carries this thought one step further by arguing

that each of the forms of experience is characterized not only

as a form of consciousness but by its typical form of expression

in language--questioning, asserting, generalizing, referring,

inferring, etc. He went as far as to say that the (unifying)

activity of philosophy is its "translation" of various forms of


779

experience into language literally true--an activity which is

called forth especially where there is a fusion of symbol and

meaning, as in art and religion (SM, 128-30). The process of

translating, interpreting, or developing truth out of the

partiality and abstractness of error is the dialectical

self-criticism of thought, and the task of philosophy as

absolute knowledge (SM, 252-53).

Of course it was only in the Essay on Philosophical

Method that the idea of dialectical development is made explicit

and rapprochement is linked to the overlap of concepts and their

relationship in a developing scale of forms. Here we found

Collingwood contrasting philosophical and non-philosophical

concepts as two phases in the development of an idea, and

stressing how one can recognize when the concept has been

typically worked out philosophically (EPM, 59-61, 73). This

rapprochement of the inner alienation between concepts is now

made the basis for deciding how and when the process of

reconciliation is complete, and carries the unity of

philosophical meaning forward from the conceptual to the

propositional and inferential levels of thought (EPM, 100-101,

161-63). It was the closest that Collingwood would be able to

come to developing a complete philosophical logic based on the

ideal of rapprochement, and the key to understanding it is to

fully grasp the clue that he himself provided at the beginning

of the investigation: philosophical reconciliation is


780

recognized by the overlap of concepts, which is an overlap of

intension between meanings rather than an overlap of extension

between classes.

The Essay on_Philosophical Method called attention to

the characteristic way in which a philosophical concept is de-

fined by means of a scale of overlapping forms, in which any

point on the scale intentionally includes all the meanings in

the scale up to that point (EPM, 90, 101). It also pointed to

the peculiarity that in such a scale there is no zero point--no

point at which a concept's meaning vanishes altogether (EPM,

81). In Part III we have encountered both of these

principles--definition by means of a scale of forms and the

irreducibility of meaning structures--exemplified in his

philosophy of mind at all levels of consciousness. In The

Principles of Art the development of feeling is described first

as the uninterpreted flux of sense, then as prepared for

interpretation by being perpetuated and domesticated by

consciousness or attention, and then finally as explicit

thought, where thinking about a sensum means interpreting it

(PA, 194, 212-13). And in that same work language is defined as

a scale of forms of expression, where psychical expression,

gestures, speech, and intellectualized or symbolic language form

a developing series in which each term sums up and intensionally

includes those which preceed it (PA, 228-61). In The New

Leviathan the fundamental parameter of meaning is re-affirmed

when language is defined


781

as any system of bodily movements whereby the men who make them

mean or signify something (NL, 6.1), and is described as an

abstraction from discourse--a system of sounds or the like as

having meanings (NL, 6.11, 6.18). The ensuing scale of forms of

consciousness is the product of language (NL, 6.4-6.41). And

finally in The Idea of History the meaning of an historical act

is the individuality aimed at in historical understanding (IH,

303), and is at the center of his radical re-interpretation of

the act-object distinction on the grounds of which he showed how

history as re-enactment is alone possible (IH, 282-302).

However it is the realistic moment to this process of

thought that has haunted our reflections on Collingwood's

thought, and this is the ghost that confronts us once again as

we approach the central paradox of historical metaphysics. For

in the previous chapter we wondered if the essential ideality of

the past left any room for factuality as something not only made

but also found, not only accepted but also given. But the

factuality of history is not an abstract, brute given-ness, it

is itself a thought and therefore mediated by meaning. The

reconciliation between ideality and factuality is an extension

of the rapprochement between persons and concepts: it is carried

out by an act of interpretation. Just as the reconciliation

between persons is premissed on the fact of communication, the

rapprochement between the historian and the thoughts


782

which constitute his subject matter is mediated by historical

inference, which takes the form of critical reflection on

evidence (IH, 133). It is by the interpretation of evidence that

we communicate with the past: history is the knowledge of a

significant present (evidence) by means of acts of

interpretative thought informed by principles which govern all

evidence as such (philosophical principles, such as the

distinction between universal judgments of the form, "All S is

P." particular judgments of the form, "Some S is P." and

individual judgments "This S is P." this last being the

interpretative judgment of history (EPH, 136)), and principles

which govern specific groups of evidence (scientific principles,

such as this historical presupposition that events of the past

are localized in space and time, and that historical narrative

must be consistent with itself (IH, 246-47)) (EPH, 136-37). The

act of interpretation is not a process extrinsic to the fact

itself: interpretation is only the historical fact further

specified (RP, 46; FR, 80; EPM, 170), because a common meaning

is the irreducible basis of them both. In this the process of

historical interpretation is not different from the general

interpretative processes of all perception and thought.

Perception is nothing other than the interpretation of sense

(SM, 204-05), and to think a concept is to interpret a fact in

terms of it (EPH, 28-29; PA, 194). Therefore it is but an

extension of the reconciliational process of interpretation when

from potential historical evidence (the whole


783

perceptible world) actual evidence is selected and perpetuated

by means of historical inference based on the exercise of a

priori historical imagination (IH, 246-47, 280-81).

But how is such knowledge achieved? How is evidence

interpreted and individual narrative judgments formulated? Here

again we must return to Collingwood's paradigm for re-

conciliational thinking, the mind-mind polarity and the fact of

inter-personal communication--but this time the trail of

evidence is less distinct. Closest to us are the unmistakable

assertions in The Idea of History that evidence is interpreted

by the systematic placement of intelligent and informed

questions (IH, 273-75), and in the Essay on Metaphysics and the

Autobiography that all scientific knowledge is an application of

Q-A logic (EM, 22-24, 38; A, 30-37). But as we traced this

evidence into Collingwood's earlier philosophy, in the direction

indicated in the Autobiography, we were startled by several

unexpected (and autobiographically unindicated) developments.

Where the Autobiography leads us to believe that Q-A logic was

meant to be an alternative to F-logic, the latter being the only

methodic tool of the realists, our own findings indicated not

only that in his early writings the alternative to F-logic is

not Q-A logic, but dialectic or D-logic, but also that Q-A logic

is not a defensible substitute for F-logic. In the case of

dialectic, the appearance of deliberate concealment in the

Autobiography was dispelled by the recognition of D-logic as the

final
784

form of the criteria for reconciliational completion in the

Essay on Philosophical Method. But what of the indistinctness of

Q-A logic in the early phases of his thought, and how does Q-A

logic relate to the unity of that thought as we have been

developing it in the last few pages?

Part of the answer to these questions is available to us

from the published writings, but part of it remains for us to

reconstruct for ourselves. In our examination of the early works

in Part II we found Collingwood identifying logic with the

theory of knowledge: abstract logic deals with processes of the

subject and does not consider differences of the object (RP, 15;

FR, 53). It is contrasted with concrete or dialectical logic,

which considers thought in its relation to its object (SM,

274-77), and it is the latter that is the true instrument of

philosophy. However if thought is regarded as a process rather

than as a product, the way in which it comes to be is by

questioning or supposal--the process whereby assertion develops

from non-assertive (hypothetical or questioning) thought (SM,

186-89). In Part III we traced this argument forward into the

Q-A logic of the Autobiography and the Essay on Metaphysics

(Q-AA and Q-AM respectively), where the ambiguity of hypothesis

as non-assertive and as pre-assertive is resolved by the

distinction between supposing and questioning, which ultimately

issued in the distinction between presuppositions and questions

(A, 30-39; EM, 27-29). In Part III


785

we also found that when taken as a whole his views on logic

indicate that Q-A logic is not a competitor to, or substitute

for, F-logic, but is rather an informal presentation of some of

the rules that pertain to the elements of rational inquiry as an

application of the reconciliational process of interpretation.

We thus found ourselves with a striking example of Collingwood's

irony: a philosophical logic posing as a work on philosophical

method, and a philosophical methodology described as Q-A logic.

But if we resist the temptation to be misled by such labels, it

is clear (a) that for Collingwood all logic pertains primarily

to the meaning dimension of thought rather than to any sort of

meaning-independent formal system; (b) that the criteria for

deciding when thought has become philosophically consistent or

reconciled with self-knowledge are presented by the D-logic of

the Essay on Philosophical Method; and (c) that Q-A logic is the

methodology for acquiring knowledge, and the means by which the

interpretative processes of thought are directed at achieving

unified meanings.

The part of this process that remains indistinct, and

which we are left to reconstruct for ourselves, is the logical

genesis of these ideas within Collingwood's overall plan for

rapprochement philosophy. Here we have only a few scant hints

from the Autobiography to guide us. We are


786

told there that Q-A logic, the primacy of historical thought as

the rapprochement paradigm for all forms of experience, and the

rejection of realist epistemology are all recalled by him as

having occurred during the period, and as an outcome, of his

reflections on the Albert Memorial (A, 30, 60, 67). But we are

not told how the monument served to focus these lines of

thought, how the coalesced to form a pattern, or what central

idea allowed him to think that the solution to one of these

problems is tied to the solution of all of them. The only clues

he leaves for us are the questions that he began to put to

himself during his daily communings with the Albert Memor-

ial--why Scott had created such an aesthetically offensive

monstrosity, if its true purpose is masked by asking the wrong

questions about it, and if such questions arise due to false

expectations which prevented him from appreciating its true

worth.

Unless there are, in the unpublished writings and

diaries, indications of how these ideas evolved, we shall

probably never know what went through Collingwood's mind during

these encounters. Without knowing what particular features of

the monument he found offensive, or what his expectations were,

or the insights that he had that allowed him to overcome his re

wlsion, we can only surmise a framework for this intellectual

and personal event. But we do know what feelings the Albert

Memorial invoked in him, and we believe we are in possession of

the
787

general way in which he overcame these feelings. The monument

not only was a representation of the alienating distance that

Collingwood felt between himself and Scott, it was also the only

piece of evidence that could serve as a bridge by means of which

Collingwood could reconcile himself with Scott by re-enacting

the thoughts which are embodied in the monument itself. Were the

architect a contemporary the question might be addressed to him,

since (short of third party intermediation) the ordinary way to

overcome the space between estranged people is for them to

converse, to put questions to each other, to elicit answers. But

in this case, as in the case of all historical artifacts, direct

dialogue was not possible, and intermediation is necessary.

Collingwood's reflections on the Albert Memorial must have

focused on this acute problem: how does one communicate with the

past? For the living, traces of the past surviving in the

present are the only expressions by means of which historical

conversation can continue, and in this process of interpretation

it is the historical understanding which asks questions, and it

is present evidence--like the mute yet immensely expresive

Albert Memorial--which the only source of assuring ourselves

that our answers and our interpretative efforts have been

successfully carried out. Somehow the gap is bridged: the

memorial speaks, the observer is moved, the dialogue takes place.


788

How is this possible? On what model of thought can such

an event occur? Collingwood was convinced that it was not

possible on the grounds of empirical or realistic premisses (IH,

208-209), nor even by the principles of subjective idealism. It

is not accomplished by using the tools of objective thinking

employed in the natural sciences, nor by disregarding such

methods altogether and adopting an intuitive or subjective

approach, which still assumes the mind-object polarity, but opts

for the primacy of the subjective pole over the objective one

(IH, 124, 292-97). It is accomplished by adapting for history

the usual method employed to cross the gap between persons in

the mind-mind situation, i.e. questions and answers eliciting

unification through shared meanings. If I wish to learn

something about someone it is not achieved by inventing him like

a character in a novel, nor by observing him like a bug on a

pin, nor by experimenting with him like a ball on an inclined

plane, nor even by seeing in him the symbol of the creator.

While all these approaches may be helpful in one way or another,

they tend to make something of the person that he is not--an

imagined entity, an abstraction, a thing, a creature. And the

same is true in learning about oneself--this much we take to be

the final message of Speculum Mentis. If I wish to find out what

a man is, I have to do so by finding out what he thinks, for

this is what he is (IH, 10, 218-20; NL, 1.61); and the ordinary

way to do this is by asking him


789

questions aimed at responses which will help to find out what he

means, where he stands, what he stands for, what he means to do,

what he means for us to do, etc. And if one wishes to find out

what a man was, one has to do so by asking questions aimed at

eliciting responses from existing evidence which will help to

find out what his intentions were, how he perceived his

situation, what he stood for, what he meant to accomplish, etc.

In the latter case one must overcome the distance of historical

time, and the way this is done is by examining and

cross-examining present evidence. The scientific historian is an

intelligent, inquisitive interpreter of evidence.

And just as a person may minimally be said to be acting

rationally not when he can show that his actions follow

deductively from some general principle, nor when he can relate

it to some other act as a reaction, but when he can in-

telligently answer questions about why he did one thing rather

than another, so also one may minimally be said to know some-

thing not when he can show that it is the conclusion of a de-

ductive inference, nor when he can show that it is disting-

uishable from its opposite, but when he can intelligently answer

questions about it (NL, 4.31-4.35, 11.1-11.12, 14.114.37). Q-A

logic, as Collingwood informally schematizes it, is the

linguistic expression of the living process of seeking out and

establishing meaning, exhibiting both phases in the discovery of

meaning--as consciously known to be incomplete (the question)


790

and as having sense-completion (the answer). To ignore the

aspect of the conscious nisus for meaning by presenting answers

as propositions, as if they were only related by formally

explicit logical connectives, is a falsification of the true,

humanly grounded process of inquiry. In this sense Q-A logic is

the true logic of thought, and "replaces" F-logic, which does

not recognize the process of passing from incomplete to

completed meaning. It is only Q-A logic which calls attention to

the active role of the conscious agent in the process of

inquiry, for it is only persons who ask questions and seek

meaningful answers. Q-A logic is the logic of interpretative

inquiry, and as a meaning-seeking function cuts across all

levels of consciousness; it is not bound to the conceptual,

propositional, or inferential levels of thought.

Finally, historical events themselves have a Q-A logical

structure: in the world of practical affairs the paradigm for

sense-location is the historical act of an agent, in which a

questionable situation is resolved by the answering act of a

protagonist aware of alternatives and conscious of the possible

consequences of his acts. To act is to endow a gesture with

meaning and at the same time to express that meaning as an act

(cf. IN, 212). Because such an act is actually the agent's (his

experience) it is potentially everyone's (a shared


791

experience)--that is, it is capable of being re-enacted (IH,

247, 280, 303). That which can be re-enacted is an historical

event, so that the historian, in discovering what it is to think

historically (to re-enact a meaning) realizes at the same time,

and by this act, what it is to be a man. It achieves the

philosophical mandate given by the oracle at Delphi: it is

knowing himself, i.e. knowing what it is to be a man (an enactor

of meaning), to be the kind of man he is (the enactor of meaning

in the context of his own experience) and to be the kind of man

he is and no one else is (the enactor of meaning in this

situation with these perceived alternatives). Historical action

therefore constitutes meaning by bringing it into the world--a

primacy that supercedes the merely theoretical sense of meaning

as something latent in the world (e.g. verbal or lexicographical

meaning). A historian re-enacts this primal activity, and the

coherence of his narrative is built upon the historical meaning

which is both found by the historian in the evidence of the act,

and made by the historian through interpretation of that

evidence.

If history is a kind of understanding in which no pro-

duct of human action is foreign, and if it is posited as the

science of human nature and therefore as a model for reconcil-

iation of all alienation situations in which understanding is

called forth to mediate between self and not-self, it does not

appear to be alone in this effort. Behavioral science makes


792

the same claim, and from his earliest writings Collingwood re-

cognized it to be his natural enemy (RP, 40-42; FR, 75-77; SM,

274-78; A, 92-95). It claimed to deal with the same subject, but

employed a methodology drawn from an empiricistic epistemology

which takes the mind-object polarity as primary. This is a

vestige of the "naturalistic" viewpoint, which he recognized in

historical positivism, and from which he struggled to free both

himself and his readers (cf. EPH, 12-20, 25, 31; IH, 126-33). It

is characteristic of this viewpoint that facts are independent

of anyone's knowledge of them; that objects are active and mind

is plastic and passive; that in the act of knowing the object is

therefore unaffected by the knowing of it; and that individual

acts of knowledge are both atomically distinct from one another

and capable of being analyzed like objects in the perceptible

world. Collingwood denied all of these assertions, and did so on

the strength of the mind-mind paradigm for reconciliational

philosophy: for historical thinking provides an instance of

successful understanding in which the object is another thought.

It exemplifies a case in which, without the activity of thought,

the object would cease to be what it is--instead of being a

metal arrowhead, a Grecian shard, or an Egyptian manuscript,

without historical interpretation it becomes a piece of metal, a

chunk of clay, black marks on flattened papyrus. The past is

therefore so far from being indifferent to its being known that

it would
793

cease to be past at all if it were not for the exercise

of the historical a priori imagination.

But Collingwood did not stop there, and in generalizing

this principle he came to regard all knowing as entailing an act

of interpretation not basically different from that which is

involved in historical thought. He came to realize that meaning

is never something merely found, it is something made by the act

of attention (PA, 213-16; NL, 4.5, 6.1-6.21, 7.2-7.22). Just as

an ambiguous historical situation is resolved by the decisive

act of an agent, the field of sensual flux is stabilized by acts

of attention which domesticate and perpetuate sense, allowing

them to survive and revive in other contexts (PA, 209-10; IN,

303). Meaning is an achievement of personal consciousness, the

means whereby a person appropriates not only his own experience

but that of others. It is also the source not only of all

perceptual and imaginative unity, but of the continuity of all

unified acts of thought (IH, 306).

The deliberate effort to achieve reconciliation by the

act of interpretation aimed at the unity of meaning, therefore,

runs contrary to the effort to define by atomic dissolution into

non-meaning elements, or by subsumption of such elements into

arbitrary sets or classes viewed as collections of

inter-changeable terms indifferent to their generic essence. It

presupposes that the object of knowledge (meaning) cannot be

unaffected by the knowing of it, because it is only human

knowing that
794

seeks and creates meaning in the world through intentional acts,

without which there is nothing definite to be known. It has,

therefore, an opposite orientation to any philosophy which makes

as its fundamental presupposition the assumption that the object

of knowledge is unaffected by, or indifferent to, the knowing of

it. Such a presupposition has been made by some philosophers who

have been known as realists (Cook Wilson, Samuel Alexander, G.

E. Moore, and Bertrand Russell being some examples). Whatever

places the object of consciousness over against it as something

beyond its ability to absorb creatively by the medium of mean-

ing, is the natural enemy of that consciousness: it is the

originator of non-meaning not as that from which meaning arises,

but as that which is forever beyond meaning, unassimilable, the

"thing-in-itself" which is not a thing, not an it, and not a

self. It is the "pure being" which Collingwood rejected as a

subject matter unsuitable for any science, because it is utterly

undifferentiated and lacking in all specification, and hence

indistinguishable from nothing.

And at this point we arrive where we set out from-with

the critique of realistic epistemology. We also find ourselves

at the doorstep of the Essay on Metaphysics.


795

5. The Rehabilitation of Reformed Metaphysics.

We should now be in a position to clear the obstacles to

first philosophy that we presented in Section three. If our

reconstruction of the unity of Collingwood's thought is correct,

it should remain as a solid ring of thought when brought up

against the barriers that are presented in the Essay on

Metaphysics.

But to begin we must ask ourselves why Collingwood un-

dertook to write on metaphysics at all, for as we have seen he

certainly gives indication in the early writings of a typically

British antipathy to the subject. It appears to be just as

accidental that Collingwood should find himself named to the

chair of Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy in 1935

as it was that he should have worked for the British Admiralty

Intelligence in World War I and found himself walking past the

Albert Memorial. Are his reflections on metaphysics as much the

result of a coincidence as his reflections on logic? What is

required is not to account for an accidental feature of his

biography but an essential feature of his thought. The situation

in which any philosopher is placed is always to some extent

fortuitous. But as Collingwood notes, it is not so much what

happens to a figure in history but what he does with what

happens to him that creates historical interest. Collingwood

chose to reflect on the A1bert Memorial, and he chose to reflect

on metaphysics,
796

and our question is how that reflection is a product of the

unity of this thought rather than a response to something that

is thrust upon it, as it were, from without.

For someone committed to the primacy of historical

thinking and the mind-mind paradigm in epistemology, what is it

to do metaphysics? Traditionally metaphysics has always been

thought directed at uncovering the stable basis for change--not

only that which "follows the physics" in the literary sense of a

set of treatises attributed to Aristotle, but also that which

seeks to discover the principles which lie beyond the changing

physical world. Very early in his career Collingwood decided,

with the Italian idealists, that change is a realistic concept

and history an idealistic one, since what changes is a material

thing, but that which historically develops is a mind. If a

philosopher with a strong inclination toward epistemology were

to begin, like Kant did, with the assumption that the mind has a

definite structure which determines its active construction or

synthesis of the world of experience, metaphysics would take the

form of discovering what that unchanging structure of mind is.

But Collingwood also decided early in his career that a mind is

what it does, and therefore that there is no such thing as a

fixed "human nature" for all time and all men, so far as mind is

concerned--so this is not a promising direction in which to find

the object of metaphysics. And


797

finally, we have seen that Collingwood ruled out an ontology of

pure being not only because it is arrived at by abstraction from

the mind-object situation, but also because in his study of

cosmology he found that modern physics had abandoned the notion

of substance altogether, replacing it with the concepts of

function, process, and motion.

What is left? For Collingwood what remains is precisely

the fact of interpersonal communication within the field of

mental phenomena. What grounds change within this domain of

reality is whatever provides the basis for reconciliational

identity between minds, or within mind, and that is whatever is

being presupposed. What grounds change in a world of developing

thought is the assumed shared meanings that make diachronic and

synchronic communication possible, and the reestablishment of

significance by a question-and-answer process is the work of

reconciliational philosophy. A metaphysics of rapprochement is

therefore an inquiry into the presuppositions of questions on

the basis of which inquiry proceeds: metaphysics is the science

of absolute presuppositions.

(a) From Anti-Metaphysics to Reformed Metaphysics.--

Collingwood makes it easy for his readers to grasp the negative

element in his critique of anti-metaphysics (itself a negation

of a negation), but difficult to get beyond that to what the

positive basis is for this critique. It is therefore quite

possible to overlook the fact that


798

his elenchus may be an utter failure without touching the

positive thought from which it springs, and which it ultimately

disguises. From the perspective of rapprochement philosophy we

may now be able to see past the disguise.

Collingwood examined in detail two forms of anti-

metaphysics: psychologism and logical positivism.7 His objection

to psychologism is basically that as "materialistic

epistemology" it treats all thought as if it were a datum-i.e.

as if it were a feeling or an aggregate of feelings, and

consequently as non-criteriological (EM, 109, 114-15); and his

objection to positivism is that it refuses to recognize that

______________________
7 Collingwood distinguished three forms of anti-meta-
physics, which he called progressive, reactionary, and irra-
tionalist (EM, 82-84). If we are correct in assuming that
positivism is the progressive form of anti-metaphysics, and
psychology is the irrationalist form, what is the reactionary
form? Probably the sort of philosophy represented by Samuel
Alexander's realism, examined in Chapter XVII of the Essay on
Metaphysics, since he accuses Alexander of being "influenced by
the quaint, characteristic eighteenth-century dogma" that there
is an underlying or pervasive character of everything which
exists-- expressible as the law of universal causation (EM, 175,
179). This is the way he described reactionary anti-metaphysics
(EM, 93-94). But both of these sections are excessively vague,
full of broad historical generalizations, and fail to satisfy
the reader's desire for a clear presentation of the viewpoint
being opposed. A perfect candidate for reactionary metaphysics
would be twentieth-century Thomism (cf. EM, 91, where the
reactionary anti-metaphysician "embraces x as his own
'doctrine,' claims x was 'right,' and professes himself an
'Xist"'). But astonishingly, Collingwood does not draw a bead on
this elephantine target, but instead takes potshots at Watt's
steam engine and Locke's political views in the 19th century.
799

thinking rests on presuppositions, and assumes that all gener-

alization is based on observation of matters of fact (EM, 146-

47). What are the positive equivalents to these critical re-

marks? In the matter of thought, it is clear that Collingwood

wishes to maintain that all thought is "criteriological," mean-

ing that in every act of thought it is necessary that the

thinker himself should judge its success or failure--a self--

critical judgment that Collingwood distinguishes from the (real

but irrelevant) possibility that one man's thought may be judged

successful or unsuccessful by someone else (EM, 109, 115). In

the matter of presuppositions, it is clear that Collingwood

wishes to maintain that there are such thoughts, and that they

are to be distinguished from empirical generalizations which are

verifiable or falsifiable by induction from observable facts

(EM, 147). Our difficulty arose from trying to conjoin these two

ideas: for if presuppositions are neither true nor false, they

do not appear to be able to retain their criteriological

aspect--i.e. the use of "a criterion, the double notion of truth

or falsehood, by reference to which he judges a thought" (EM,

115); and if all thought is based on presuppositions, then

thinking is based on that which is non-criteriological, i.e.

that which is not thought.

The first step toward resolving this difficulty is one

which we have already suggested: to expand the notion of truth

so that it is not bound by the propositional criterion, i.e. by

that which is verifiably


800

true in answer to a question. Now in Chapters VII and VIII we

took considerable effort to demonstrate that Collingwood

recognized levels of mental functioning that could definitely be

called thought, and were not yet at the propositional level of

truth. While the early Collingwood recognized that questions

themselves were non-assertions, he failed to distinguish various

kinds and degrees of non-assertive thought--a deficiency that

was remedied in his later writings, where concepts are described

as the entertainment of meanings in imagination, having the

status of thoughts which are non-assertive and pre-propositional

in the logical sense. One function of conceptual imagination is

precisely to consider a meaning in isolation from, or

indifferent to, any reference to anything else (i.e. any

predication): 8 imagination is essentially the

_____________________
8 To consider a meaning in isolation from, or indiffer-
ent to, any reference to anything else is to consider it ab-
stractly. Since all thinking is based on pre-suppositions, does
this mean that Collingwood had come to believe that all thinking
is conceptual and hence abstract? Was Donagan right after all?
We think there are several decisive reasons for believing that
this is not the case. (1) Collingwood never denied that it is
possible to think abstractly: he merely argued that such
abstract thinking cannot bear the weight of unconditional truth
that we wish to place on it (SM, 252-53; NL, 26.18). (2) He also
argued that it is only a phase in our thinking (like the bud is
an abstraction of the flower), and that in thinking abstractly
we are not condemned to remain at this point--or as he says, to
live in Ezekial's Ezekiel’s Valley of Dry Bones (NL, 7.65 7.64).
Our release from such confinement occurs in the form of further
acts of propositional thinking, where a proposition is an answer
to a question, and a question offers alternatives (NL, 11.22,
11.34-11.35). (3) Abstraction always occurs in what Collingwood
calls a "context of evocations," over which preside acts of
evocative thinking governed
801

"suspension of the activity of asserting" (SM, 78), and in this

activity it "is indifferent to the distinction between the real

and the unreal" (PA, 136). Yet there is a kind of truth that is

involved in the act of imagination, and this pertains to its

expressiveness--the very function which relates imagination in

an essential way to art. The truth of art is not a truth of

relation but a truth of fact: its truths are concrete individual

experiences, and the truth of art is the truth of its

expressiveness of these experiences (PA, 288). Its opposite--its

untruth--is the "corruption of consciousness" which disowns a

feeling by expressing it misleadingly or self-deceptively (PA,

219-20). The function of imagination is the perpetuation and

domestication of meaning as the ground or material out of which

further acts of consciousness will shape questions,

propositions, inferences, and other expresions of higher-order

thought.

Here we have a relation of presupposition which fits the

description Collingwood has for it in the Essay on Metaphysics.

It is thought, but in the form of imagination; it is

criteriological in the sense that it has its own standard of

success or failure, as the true expression of a felt meaning,9

but not in the sense of true or false

________________________
by logical relations (NL, 7.32-7.39). As we have pointed out in
previous chapters, this is a very different description of ab-
straction than the one he had condemned as falsification in
Speculum Mentis.

9 It should be recalled that Collingwood found nothing


absurd about there being such things as "emotions of intellect"
802

propositions; and it is a function prior to, and the logical

ground of, further acts of higher-order thinking--e.g. the

verificational acts involved in scientific inquiry, within which

absolute presuppositions are embedded as primitive survivals.

Absolute presuppositions are a priori, concrete meaning-concepts

of imagination, not unlike the Kantian categories.l0 This

conclusion evidently relies on the theory of

______________________
(PA, 267), and that there would therefore be nothing absurd
about there being an "emotional charge" on a presupposition. In
fact, Collingwood's remarks about being "ticklish in one's
presuppositions” (EM, 44), as well as about the numinous terror
that may surround them (EM, 46) confirms this observation. What
would be interesting is what Collingwood might have had to say
on the manner in which questions arise due to the causal
efficacy of absolute presuppositions: has this anything to do
with the emotions of intellect?

10 On the interpretation of absolute presuppositions as


a priori concepts there is considerable agreement by Collingwood
s commentators: cf. Mink, MHD, 144-48; Rubinoff, CRM, 234-35;
and Toulmin, CEPC, 205-08. With respect to their similarity to
the Kantian categories, we suspect that not all would
agree--particularly Rubinoff, who adopts a basically Hegelian
interpretation of Collingwood. Our own reading is that
Collingwood had more Kantian leanings: in spite of such passages
as that in The New Leviathan, where he denies the "German"
belief that it is possible to compile a list of the logical
relations which govern conceptualization (NL, 7.34), what he is
describing in that process is the Kantian schematism of the
categories. His rejection of any categorical compilation as
consistent with the passages in the Essay on Metaphysics, where
Kant's transcendental analytic is treated as an attempt to state
what the presuppositions of physics were in Kant's own time (EM,
231-81). Collingwood is not denying that there are such
relations (as even his remarks about the "element types" of
logical thought, in his correspondence with Ryle, would
indicate), but only that Kant's list is not definitive,
exhaustive, or independent of the state of thinking on physics
at that time. On absolute presuppositions as a priori concepts,
see also David Rynin, "Donagan on Collingwood: Absolute
Presuppositions, Truth, and Metaphysics," The Review of
Metaphysics, XVIII (December,
803

meaning that we have extracted from Collingwood's writings only

in bits and pieces, an incomplete but pervasive view of

inter-relating acts of consciousness and linguistic expressions,

some of which we explored in Chapter VIII. At this point we only

claim to have indicated enough of this theory to show that the

relationship of presupposing is one that is not unheralded in

Collingwood's philosophy of mind, nor does it defy the demand

that thought be regarded as "criteriological"--so long as the

definition of "criteriology" be wide enough to include the

double aspect of truth as the truthful expression of meaning and

falsity as the corruption of consciousness.

But if we can congratulate ourselves for having cleared

the main difficulty of our fourth obstacle,ll can we say that we

have resolved all our problems about anti-metaphysics? Not

quite. The psychologizing in which Collingwood engages in this

portion of the Essay on Metaphysics remains for us an unresolved

embarrassment, but one which should not

_______________________
1964), 301-33. It is interesting that Rynin, who claimed to be
the last living logical positivist (ibid., 331), would undertake
a defense of Collingwood's view of metaphysics as a science of
absolute presuppositions, and to mount a scalding attack on
Donagan for treating Collingwood as "a very third rate thinker,
struggling without success under a burden of ineptitude that
would be a source of concern in a not very promising
undergraduate" (ibid., 332). Rynin's own estimate of Collingwood
is considerably higher.

1l We are approaching the obstacles from Section 3 in


reverse order, for reasons that will become obvious as we con-
tinue: the main reason is that we wish to reserve the question
of ontology until last.
804

obstruct our passage toward the positive aspects of his reformed

metaphysics. As universal as were Collingwood's interests, we

cannot expect him to have accurately evaluated every major sci-

entific development of the last century, and his failure to

appreciate the true worth and benefits of behavioral sciences

should not deter us from recognizing in his own work an equally

important observation: that historical thinking can contribute

an essential dimension to the self-understanding of man. From

this point of view his warnings to us about the pretensions to

wisdom of some who look to behavioral science as a "guide to

life" are only a counsel to beware of such a one-sided prejudice

about the nature of thought. It is a warning that he first

issued in Religion and Philosophy and is repeated in no less

than six of his other mature works. And while Collingwood seems

less concerned about the ill effects of logical positivism (he

did not seem to be convinced that they would be taken with much

seriousness by the scientific community), the danger here is

that in attacking metaphysics the positivists would unwittingly

contribute to the attack on reason in the contemporary world,

because an attack on the doctrine that thought has

presuppositions is an attack on the foundations of science, and

an attack on science is an attack on rationality and therefore

on civilization. Collingwood's fear is that we would fall victim

to a kind of belief about our own abilities to think that would

paralyze us by convincing us that we are not able to think for

ourselves, to judge if the products of our


805

own thought are well or ill done, and to behave in general as if

our thinking would not make any difference to what we are trying

to achieve. A belief about our own minds is one that is

reflected in the way we behave, and therefore if we believe that

we are a conglomerate of feelings, we shall surrender the

imperative to know ourselves by giving up the effort that

consciousness must put forward to achieve continuity in

experience. In Collingwood's estimation this is tantamount to

giving up on rationality and on civilization altogether.

Considering what was happening in Europe at the time he was

writing, he did not care if he was regarded as a cackling goose.

(b) Metaphysics as an Historical Science.--If we can say

that an absolute presupposition as an a priori concept of

imagination is a kind of thought (but not propositional

thought), we can also say that it is minimally eligible for

being a subject matter for historical re-enactment. But there is

much that we still do not know about it. We are not yet in a

position to overcome our third obstacle, the unlikely match of a

science traditionally oriented towards universal and timeless

truths, and a kind of research concerned only with particular

and spatio-temporally localized matters of fact. This is the

central paradox of the Essay on Metaphysics with its thesis that

metaphysics is an historical science. In fact it appears to be

doubly paradoxical, because it is puzzling when approached


806

from either direction. For if the methods of history are

designed to "get at the facts" by the interpretation of

observable evidence, why should a science of absolute

presuppositions, for which there can be no directly observable

evidence (not being propositional, and therefore neither

verifiable or falsifiable), be interested in adopting the

methods of history? What sort of a fact is an a priori concept?

And contrariwise, if historical truth is always ad hoc and is

therefore only true for a particular time and place, of what

interest is it to an historian to deal with matters that are a

priori and conceptual? What light is thrown on the relationship

of presupposing by saying that it is brought into awareness by a

kind of analysis which is drawn from the science of history?

To begin with we must first find out why Collingwood

believes that absolute presuppositions constitute an appropriate

subject matter for historical thought. Then we must approach the

other side of the question by asking why the presuppositions,

questions, propositions, problems and methods of metaphysics are

the same as those of history. Now we have already suggested that

absolute presuppositions are thoughts, but on the criteria

offered in The Idea of History, this is not enough. In Chapter

IX we found Collingwood telling us that to be a proper subject

matter for history, an act must not only be an act of thought

but of reflective
807

thought, where reflective thought means an act done in the

consciousness that it is being done (IH, 307-08). While it is

possible for a concept to be the object of an act that is

"conscious of. . . ," what is required for an act that is

"conscious that . . .” is a proposition. But then does this not

imply that to be an object of history an absolute presupposition

must be a propositional act of thought, and therefore that it

cannot be simply a concept? And does it not further imply that

as an act of reflective thought an absolute presupposition

cannot be unconsciously presupposed in any sense that is his-

torically relevant?

These are difficult questions, and have wrecked the

efforts of more than one of Collingwood's interpreters to sal-

vage sense from the Essay on Metaphysics. But if we are to test

the strength of our reconstruction of Collingwood's central

"ring of thought," we must risk the same fate. In that

reconstruction we noted that at the center of the object of

historical interest is the resolution of an indeterminate

situation by the act of an historical agent. This is an act made

consciously, in the face of perceived alternatives, and having

consequences beyond the act itself--consequences which the act

brings about, but not with apodictic necessity. One phase of

Collingwood's reform of metaphysics is carried out by drawing

out the implications from the insight that the same sort of

process is operative in the acts of thought


808

that bring science into being. In spite of what positivists and

other formalists may believe, a science like physics does not

spring like Athena fully armed from the head of Zeus; it grows

in human fashion by the deliberate process of inquiry, the

processes he informally described under the title of Q-A logic.

It grows by putting questions in an orderly sequence and

marshalling intelligence at all levels of consciousness in the

effort to answer them. The sequence of thoughts in a scientific

inquiry therefore parallels the sequence of thoughts which con-

stitute the significant "inside" of historical events. And if

one wishes to understand a scientific event, one must re-enact

the sequence of thoughts which brought the scientist to draw the

conclusions he did, just as one understands an historical event

by re-enacting the thought processes involved in it.

Such understanding is, like all thinking, an interpre-

tative process, and requires that the re-enactor be adept at

forging questions which can overcome the discontinuities that he

encounters. As an historian Collingwood was aware that there are

many of these--that scientific thinking is a discontinuous

process with interruptions, detours, inconsistencies, even

revolutions; and that the manner in which these are reconciled

is not the same for different subjects, different people, even

different places and times. Therefore while the way rapprochement

occurs is by achieving common understanding of shared meaning,

Collingwood's
809

historical experience convinced him that true meaning is always

individuated and concrete, and the way in which shared meaning

is achieved is not the same for all inquiry situations. The kind

of answer that will satisfy a physicist is not the sort of

answer that will satisfy an artist or theologian; and the sort

of answer that would satisfy a classical Greek physicist would

not be the same as an answer that would satisfy his medieval,

renaissance, or modern counterpart--not because the phenomena

have changed, but because the expectations of what the phenomena

can mean have shifted, and this represents a change in the

heuristic presuppositions which ground the questions. This is no

less true at the personal level, for even within the con-

sciousness of a single individual the questions asked at one

point in a person's lifetime will have a different basis than

those asked after his thought has developed beyond that point.

Therefore one cannot begin by assuming that there is an

unchanging, generic sense of "knowing," and an equally univocal

meaning for the answers, questions, and presuppositions of all

inquiry per se. An inquiry about inquiry is an ad hoc affair,

and one should not expect to find the common and unchanging

ground of all possible inquiries, semper, ubique, ad omnibus,

for this would be the epistemological equivalent of a search for

an unchanging substance. Like all efforts of rapprochement, the

way in which continuity of meaning is established in a given

context is by
810

showing how thought develops in that context, i.e. by showing

how particular meanings become progressively more inclusive, how

the variable (knowing in this particular situation) modifies the

generic essence (inquiry) and becomes identified with it.

Rapprochement is complete when that development can be

demonstrated as a scale of forms. In the case of science such a

scale takes the form of a conceptual system, i.e. a nexus of

meanings produced by the exercise of an act of real (or

"concrete) abstraction by which a concept is located in a

context of other concepts.

But while these comments may help us to understand how

an absolute presupposition can be cogently interpreted as an a

priori concept compatible with Collingwood's philosophy of mind,

we do not seem to be much closer to an understanding of how it

can be both a priori and factual, conceptual and reflective. For

this we need to turn to the other aspect of the process of

re-enactment, the thought of the historian. For just as in the

process of discourse by which reconciliation is achieved between

minds there are moments of listening but also moments of

questioning, so also in historical thinking there is a kind of

discourse in which the historian reaches beyond being a passive

listener and takes charge of his subject matter by

cross-examining it. In re-enacting the sequence of thoughts

which form the body of some piece of scientific inquiry the

historian may well ask questions that the scientists never

asked. He may thus ask why the initial scientific question


811

arose--a questions which (if the historian does not want to

distort the nature of thinking itself) is directed at the

objective or logical (rather than subjective or psychological)

basis from which the question arose, i.e. its relation to

meanings already established and unquestioned. It seeks to

uncover what the scientist is assuming that allowed him to ask

the question he did. In pressing this process or

cross-examination to its conclusion the historian reaches a

point where he recognizes that all the questions of a given

systematic inquiry on a particular occasion presuppose a meaning

or set of meanings not given as a result of any prior and

similar questions in the inquiry, but forming the necessary

condition for all questions to arise within that inquiry. But in

stating what those absolute presuppositions are, the re-enactor

of the inquiry sequence is doing something that the original

agent, the scientist, may never have done, i.e. to express an a

priori concept in the form of a statement.

Only someone who expects history to be a scissors-and-

paste affair, a mere reportage, would be put off by this ex-

pansion of the historian's role. For Collingwood it was of the

essence of scientific history that it be autonomous, which means

that the active processes of the historian's thought are always

involved. Such is the active nature of historical reenactment

that it is not bound by the requirement that only


812

what occurred in an historical sequence is what can re-appear in

the continuity of past events, of reconciling himself or his

thought to the thinking of the scientist, he may put questions

that may never have occurred to his protagonist, and he does so

on his own initiative, because he is the only one who can know

what he expects to find out, or when he has achieved that

rapprochement that his narrative seeks to achieve. But in this

autonomous placement of questions we begin to get the sense of

how Collingwood sees a way to overcome what appears to be a

fundamental and irreconcilable difference between two

traditional ways to approach factuality--the diachronic narra-

tive approach of the historian and the synchronic logical ap-

proach of the metaphysician. If the scientific inquirer had to

think some thoughts (absolute presuppositions) in order to think

others (the questions and answers that form the body of his

inquiry), and if the first thoughts are concepts embedded in the

meaning of all the questions of the inquiry itself, then they

can be said to be thoughts which occurred simultaneously

(synchronically) with that inquiry. But this does not mean that

they suddenly drop out of historical interest and become the

province of the metaphysician-as-logician. It is what is

involved in understanding the scientific event itself. In

re-enacting that event historical thinking brings a latent

thought (an a priori concept) into explicit consciousness (an

act of propositional thought) in the form of an absolute pre-

supposition, something that is therefore


813

both found and made by the act of historical understanding.

It is in this sense that absolute presuppositions are

factual, and can be both the result of a question (the active

question of the historian rather than those he receives from the

historian in his inquiry) while yet remaining, as definitions of

a priori concepts, pre-varificationally truth-neutral. Where

such thoughts do not necessarily form a temporal sequence, the

historian puts them into such a sequence (diachronically)

through his narrative reasoning. He is expressing a ground

consequent relationship in narrative form. Nevertheless this is

not mere invention on his part, on pain of ceasing to think

historically: it must be rooted in evidence, such evidence

being, of course, the documentary materials of the scientific

inquiry articulated in language--with all that that implies.

We cannot claim to have accounted for all the problems

that we have raised concerning the historical re-enactment of

absolute presuppositions. Some of these issues shall be dealt

with further in subsequent sections; others are obscured by

shadows we have never succeeded in penetrating with light--the

nature of historical inference, the relationship between Q-A

logic and formal structures in language and thought; and still

others seem both to retain striking echoes from his early re-

conciliational philosophy, and to suggest further thought which

never had the opportunity to take place. What we are left with

is a very general argument for reconciling history


814

and metaphysics--an argument that shows how it is possible to

employ the methods (the interpretation of evidence by the active

and systematic process of questioning), the presuppositions

(that thought is capable of being re-enacted due to the

invariance of meaning in different contexts), and the proposi-

tions (the ad hoc nature of inquiry about inquiry, the use of

evidence, etc.) of history to do the work of metaphysical an-

alysis (bringing to consciousness, or expressing in statements, a

priori concepts, in the form of absolute presuppositions,

incorporated in acts of scientific inquiry).

But this sort of argument employs rapprochement only at

the level that it had reached in the earliest phases of

Collingwood's development: the identification of metaphysics and

history is an abstract rapprochement identity of the sort that

we originally encountered in Religion and Philosophy. Obviously

not all of history is metaphysics, because not all of history is

concerned with the absolute presuppositions of scientific

inquiry; and it would appear that not all of metaphysics is

history, because the logical analysis in which a given

constellation of metaphysical presuppositions is shown to

display incompatibilities is not part of the usual business of

construction of coherent narrative, or at least not to the

extent that it is not a thing of the past. The next step in the

reconciliational process would be to show the way in which

history
815

and metaphysics are defined by a scale of forms. In The Essay on

Metaphysics we find not the slightest gesture in this direction.

(c) The Absoluteness of Presupposing.--So far we have

argued that by making use of our reconstructed "ring of thought"

in our approach to the major obstacles to Collingwood's reformed

metaphysics, it is possible to make limited sense of The Essay

on Metaphysics. We may summarize this argument thus far as

follows. (1) As an application of rapprochement philosophy,

metaphysics seeks to overcome failures in the continuity of

scientific inquiry by establishing the unified ground of shared

meaning upon which systematic inquiry is based. (2) The way this

is done is by applying the interpretative methodology of Q-A

logic to concrete examples of scientific thinking, not in the

forward direction of the inquiry itself, but in the

retrogressive direction--i.e. towards the presuppositions of the

inquiry's questions. (3) When this retrogressive inquiry is

pushed to the limit, what is uncovered are the a priori concepts

which form the logically connected system (or constellation) on

the basis of which all the questions of the inquiry are possible

(i.e. make unified sense), and from which they all arise. (4)

Metaphysical reconciliation is complete when the system of such

concepts is made explicit (or is brought into consciousness) and

articulated in the form of a conceptual framework (a

constellation of absolute presuppositions) having the structure

of a philosophical scale of forms. (5) Such a system


816

of concepts linked by intentionally more inclusive meanings

becomes expressed by acts of interpretative thought which bring

absolutely presupposed concepts into consciousness in the form

of definitions. (6) Such interpretative acts are historical

insofar as history is the sequence of past acts of reflective

thought, reenacted in the context of present thought by the

intelligent cross-examination of evidence--the evidence in this

case being concrete instances of scientific inquiry. (7) In such

a re-enactment historical thinking affects its objects (a priori

concepts) by locating them in a context of other concepts, i.e.

by putting them in propositional form.

We are thus now in a position to understand how someone

could mistake an absolute presupposition for a proposition.

While an absolute presupposition is an act of a priori

imagination at the conceptual level of thought, it is expressed

in a form that appears like a proposition: it is expressed in a

sentence, having the apparent unity of a judgment, and therefore

posing as a candidate for that level of consciousness. But it is

only in the retrogressive, metaphysical inquiry that it takes

such a form, and we now understand that it is actually put there

by the active process of historical thinking, and as a result of

deliberate interpretative questioning.


817

But this glosses over difficulties to which we must now

attend, not the least of which is the problem of the distinction

between absolute and relative presuppositions. We recall that

this distinction is made on the basis of the fact that there are

some presuppositions which are not themselves the answer to any

higher-order question in the progressive systematic inquiry. On

our present line of thinking this is no longer a tenable

distinction; it must be the answer to a question in some inquiry

or it cannot be said to be a thought, or at least not a

reflective thought (which it must be to be of interest to the

historian)--i.e. one made in the consciousness that it is being

made. And if it is the answer to a question in the retrogressive

metaphysical inquiry, how are we to understand the way in which

such a question arises? For to say that it "arises," on

Collingwood's view of the matter, is to say that it has a

logical connection with our previous thought and does not arise

by capricious curiosity. But that would mean that it arises due

to the causal efficacy of another presupposition, in which case

it is no longer absolute but relative.

How can our "ring of thought" get us out of this maze?

Surely the very concept of rapprochement presupposes that there

is something to be reconciled, i.e. two thoughts which do not

share the continuity typical of self-consciousenss. The kind of

consciousness employed to achieve the


818

first stage of reconciliation is questioning--that expression of

the acknowledged incompleteness of an act of propositional

consciousness which anticipates its requisite completion in ar,

act of assertion. Where the discontinuity occurs in a systematic

scientific inquiry, which represents the articulation of a

single question or set of related questions, it indicates a

failure to grasp a prior step in the inquiry, which leads to a

regressive type of question and reverses the direction of the

primary inquiry. Such a reversal and its resultant questions are

the result of a higher stage of consciousness which Collingwood

described as "reason" in The New Leviathan, namely "thinking one

thing, x, because you think another thing, y; where ~ is your

'reason' or, as it is sometimes called, your 'ground' for

thinking x" (NL, 14.1). It is a kind of thinking that arises as

a "practical act of trying to alleviate the distress caused me

by the untrustworthiness of my knowledge" (NL, 14.3), and never

loses this practical aspect. In the case of a scientific inquiry

the "distress" is due to the discontinuity in the inquiry, and

the historical, retrogressive question is an exercise of the

rationality of the historian, the absolute presupposition being

the "ground" or "reason" which will reassure him of the

trustworthiness of a certain line of questioning.

Now such a reflective reversal may be part of the in-

quiry process itself (regression to an hypothesis--e.g. one

which requires further definition) or it may be one which arises

when the entire inquiry itself


819

is called into question. Once again in the latter case this may

occur in the process of normal scientific inquiry (as in the

early stages of scientific revolution), or it may occur due to

failure in the process of trying to re-enact a piece of science.

In the latter case the historian may actually invent the

question for the purpose of eliciting from the inquiry its

presupposed concepts, or its conceptual framework. But these two

cases seem to be very different: if the historian, in exercising

his autonomy in raising questions on his own initiative, is free

to invent a metaphysical question, it is clear he is creating

the discontinuity that the absolute presupposition is meant to

repair; but the scientist in a period of scientific crisis

perceives or feels the discontinuity in the experience of his

own scientific consciousness, and therefore does not create it

but finds it. Once again we find ourselves confronting the

idealistic dimension of Collingwood's philosophy, and uneasy

about what to make of it. If we define the "idealistic turn" as

that point at which a philosopher decides that meaning is

something not found but made, then there can be little doubt

that Collingwood made that turn early in his career, and never

went back on it. But we have repeatedly witnessed Collingwood

arguing that meaning is something both found and made: this is

the celebrated "unity of act and fact" of Gentile and the

Italian idealists, and the basis of Collingwood's later

re-interpretation of the act-object distinction.


820

The distinction between relative and absolute presup-

positions is our present case in point, and we wish to under-

stand if an absolute presupposition is something found or made

or both. Clearly Collingwood wants to say both, but can he do so

consistently? For if it is both, then the absoluteness of

presuppositions threatens to vanish altogether: as something

found its reality is affirmed, but only as contingent to an act

of historical interpretation which establishes its factuality;

and as something made its independence is surrendered to that

which is responsible for its creation. In either case it turns

out that an absolute presupposition is something that is always

dependent on something else, and is therefore only relatively

absolute--a paradoxical conclusion to be sure.

The relativization of absolute presuppositions also

bears down on us form a different direction, for we are forced

to recognize that in calling absolute presuppositions a priori

concepts we have vastly oversimplified the logic of presuppos-

ing. The deciding factor in considering whether a thought is a

concept, a proposition, or an inference is not the form that one

or the other takes when it is expressed in words, but the way it

functions in the process of thinking. Thus one and the same

linguistic entity--the indicative sentence--may express a

concept in the form of a definition, or may predicate one

concept of another in the form of a proposition, or may re late

one concept to another as ground and


821

consequent in the form of an inference. While we have argued

that a presupposed concept may appear in indicative sentential

form because we typically express ourselves in sentences in

order to communicate a complete thought, this does not tell the

whole story. For in much of what Collingwood says about it,

presupposing is treated as a complex relationship rather than as

a simple linguistic or formally logical entity. He would say,

for example, that one form of experience presupposes another (as

science presupposes religion in Speculum Mentis, where "science"

and "religion" are concepts representing whole regions of

experience)--indicating that the relationship was one of logical

dependency but not of deductive entailment. Such a usage is

virtually repeated when he writes in the Essay on Metaphysics

that contemporary science is "monotheistic" in that it presup-

poses that God exists. And again in the "retrospect" chapter of

The New Leviathan he writes that each of the levels of con-

sciousness presupposes its predecessor as that out of which it

develops, while the successor is not rendered necessary by the

form of consciousness which proceeded it (NL, 9.43). In fact it

is this section of The New Leviathan that comes closest to

defining the relationship of presupposing than any other place

in his published works, since it is set in the context of a

description of development which he defines as "a logical pro-

cess in which B 'presupposes' A, C 'presupposes' B. and D 'pre-

supposes' C" without the earlier terms necessitating the later

ones (NL, 9.47-9.48).


822

This clarifies the relationship at the same time that it

complicates and relativizes it. For if the scale of forms of

consciousness is such that any point on the scale not only

summarizes and completes the terms below it but also presupposes

them, then in what sense can we say that absolute pre-

suppositions are confined to the conceptual level (or should we

say "located" at the conceptual level?) of consciousness? We are

at a loss to say what the criterion is for the absoluteness of

presuppositions. While it would appear that the minimum

determination of meaning is at the conceptual level of thought,

that would seem to leave us with as many absolute

presuppositions as there are conceptual meanings, a situation

which achieves ultimacy at the expense of complete dissipation.

What we seem to be left with is a glimpse into an

epistemological concept of remarkable complexity--one which has

yet to be dealt with in a satisfactory manner by anyone with

whom this author is familiar.l2 We know that Collingwood un-

derstood an absolute presupposition to be pre-propositional and

also pre-interrogative (both in the logical rather than temporal

sense), and that it has efficacy in causing questions

______________________
12 However the issue of conceptual change in constel-
lations of presuppositions has been recognized and discussed
with considerable Insight by Stephen Toulmin, who acknowledges
his debt to Collingwood on this subject. See his Human
Understanding: The Collective Use and Evolution of Concepts
(Princeton, 1972), pp. 52-85.
823

to arise--these being epistemic functions. We also know that it

has certain logical properties which tend to apply to pre-

suppositions regardless of their semantic content--that a pre-

supposition acts as a unifier in a systematic inquiry; that its

relationship to questions and propositions resembles inference,

but yet is not deductively or inductively related to questions

and answers in the P-Q-A complex; that it has relations of

consupponibility with other presuppostions, and with these

others forms a constellation or synthesis which, like a

deductive system, is subject to conflicts or strains due to

inconsistencies. But yet it has some of the properties of

religious belief: it has the character of a decision with

practical consequences; it is held with an attitude of un-

questioning acceptance or natural piety; it can be embraced or

abandoned, but never verified or falsified; and it is sometimes

surrounded by a kind of "numinous terror" ordinarily evoked by

sacred objects. And finally Collingwood called attention to its

historical dimension: the establishment of its factuality by

cross-examination and interpretation of evidence, its

development to full consciousness by rational acts of

metaphysical analysis which shares the premise of historical

understanding that acts of thought are capable of reenactment

without essential loss of universal meaning.

Even a cursory examination of this set of properties

could well keep us busy for several more chapters, raising as

they do questions which


824

touch not only on epistemology, but also on logic and the

philosophy of religion. At this point we can only admit that it

does not seem possible to maintain the unconditional distinction

between absolute and relative presuppositions, where that

distinction pertains to all possible inquiries. but in any given

inquiry such a distinction is not only possible, it is

essential: for without the presuppositions that ground the

entire set of questions, no scientific inquiry can achieve its

objectives--i.e. to fulfill the intention to answer the

questions that arise only due to the causal efficacy of these

presuppositions, and ultimately to be grounded in these

presuppositions as their rational justification. It is not a

complete disaster for rapprochement philosophy, therefore, to

argue that absolute presuppositions are inquiry-dependent

meanings and therefore only relatively absolute. They are at

least inquiry-constant within that inquiry, and this suffices

for Collingwood's purposes, since it is consistent with the ad

hoc character of all historical interpretation.

Our disappointment at Collingwood's failure to satisfy

us on the nature of the relationship of presupposing should not

prevent us from acknowledging our debt to him for what he did

achieve in this area. In marking out the realm of absolute

presuppositions he pointed the way beyond the empiricistic and

positivistic attempts to eliminate general


825

metaphysics. Like Caesar, he crossed the river even if he did

not totally succeed in subduing the territory on the other side.

He showed us a way in which a science of metaphysics is

possible, without actually accomplishing the construction of

that science. Others who have followed him--men like Errol

Harris and Stephen Toulmin--have since taken the banner to

higher ground. It is still a territory left largely unexplored.

(d) Ontology and Reformed Metaphysics.--We come now to

the final obstacle, Collingwood's rejection of ontology as a

fitting subject-matter for metaphysical analysis. Of all our

obstacles, this is the most difficult for us to surmount, not

only because Collingwood was so perfunctory and uncompromising

about it, and not only because it represents an unhistorical and

unscholarly dismissal of a subject matter of great antiquity and

coeval with philosophy itself, but also because it runs contrary

to attitudes that he espoused from an early date, and defended

for many years. For while the rejection of a science of abstract

being is a recurrent theme, so also is the requirement that the

object of philosophy is no mere ens rationis, but one which has

ontological reference (EPM, 125); "philosophy is the theory of

existence; not of existence in the abstract, but of existence in

the concrete; the theory of all that exists" (RP, 16; FR, 54).

Such is also the significance of Anselm's ontological argument,

which is defended in works from all stages in his philosophical

career (RP, 66; EPM, 124-25; EM, 189-90), and such is


826

the essential nature of all philosophical judgment: it is always

both universal and categorical, stating what is both common and

essential in that which exists (EPM, 127, 136). To abandon this

requirement is not merely to reject one erroneous form of

metaphysics, it is to strip philosophy of its distinguishing

feature. To fail to overcome this obstacle is therefore to fail

to defend the role of philosophy as Collingwood had defined it

in the Essay on Philosophical Method, which the Autobiography

singled out as his best and "only" book.

Is there any way that our reconstructed "ring of

thought" can aid us in adopting a viewpoint that will allow us

to see our way beyond this final obstacle? After providing us

with a means to understand how metaphysics is possible as a

science of absolute presuppositions re-enacted by a form of

thought using the methods of historical interpretation, can we

now find a way to re-establish the continuity between reformed

and traditional metaphysics, between scientific history and

Aristotle's metaphysics? For rapprochement philosophy, what is

the meaning shared by a science of absolute presuppositions and

a science of being as being? To reconcile ontology and reformed

historical metaphysics would require redefining ontology in a

way which would allow for a non-abstract concept of being, one

which does not arise at the limit of the abstractive process by

leaving out determining characteristics, but


827

rather takes such individuating marks as essential to it. This

would be a science of "concrete being"--a reformed ontology that

would be a part of reformed metaphysics.

Collingwood himself leaves open the possibility that

rejecting one sense of "ontology" leaves other senses of the

term untouched by the criticism (EM, 16). But our concern is

less with his rejection of the title than it is with his

rejection of the concept which the title represents. For in

spite of his claims about what philosophy should be, in most of

what he writes he refuses to entertain any questions concerning

ontological reference in the sense of a science which says

something directly about reality rather than something about

knowledge of that reality. In Speculum Mentis this refusal takes

the form of a denial that metaphysics can ever analyze real

being, being as it is in itself untainted by thought (SM, 274);

and in the theory of perception offered in The New Leviathan it

is expressed in the denial that feelings have objects as well as

modes (NL, 5.39). In such places as these it has been hard for

us to defend Collingwood against the charge of radical

subjective idealism. But in other passages in his works it is

possible to see a different thought process at work, a process

which allows him (for example in his correspondence with Ryle)

to recognize the metaphysical legitimacy of such statements as

"mind exists," "matter exists," and "God exists"--statements

which are both categorical(or referential) and


828

universal. Can we leap to the conclusion that such statements of

ontological commitment form the body of absolute presuppositions

that we have found so elusive throughout this chapter? They

certainly appear to be ultimate and primitive enough to present

themselves as candidates for inclusion in reformed metaphysics,

and the only sort of question to which they could be the answer

would be equally primitive, viz. what exists? But then why is it

not legitimate for reason to press this retrogressive inquiry

one step further by asking for reassurance for these assertions?

Why should reason be prevented from asking the ontological ques-

tion, "why is there something rather than nothing?"

Perhaps we are once again asking more of the Essay on

Metaphysics than it was intended to achieve. it is nonetheless

not unreasonable to put such questions to Collingwood, since

metaphysics is one branch of the science of thought (EM, 101),

and therefore seeks meaning just as all science and all thought

does; and if it is an absolute presupposition of science not

only that reality is intelligible or conforms to law, but also

that there is a reality to investigate (EM, 213, 222-27), then

it seems that on either view of metaphysics--Collingwood's or

Aristotle's--the examination of the meaning of being is a

legitimate enterprise. Surely we must assume that Collingwood's

intention was not primarily to write a treatise on Aristotle or

his metaphysics, but to write an essay or series


829

of essays showing how a conception of metaphysics on the mind--

mind model is still possible, and in doing so he found suffi-

cient basis in Aristotle for making the points he had to make to

the audience he presumed he had. Collingwood's rejection of

Aristotle's ontology is not so much an attempt to re-write

Aristotle as it is an attempt to show that he was in basic

agreement with those critics of Aristotle who rejected a science

of pure being, and to indicate that such a fruitless inquiry had

its roots in some of the ideas put forward in the treatises on

metaphysics attributed to Aristotle. Presumably his readership

included some of the same critics who found A. J. Ayer's

Language, Truth, and Logic of some interest, and at the

beginning of an essay which by its title threatened to raise

again the metaphysical spectra he was anxious to show this

audience that he was not about to revive this long-dead topic.

But for such a presumed, postivistically influenced audience he

was equally anxious to show that in rejecting one meaning of

metaphysics one has not demonstrated the impossibility of

metaphysics in any sense whatever, and metaphysics as a science

of first principles also has its pedigree in Aristotle's

treatises.

But having said this there is the additional problem

that Collingwood is sidestepping a discussion of what we have

demonstrated beyond all reasonable doubt to be one of the most

important issues in his own philosophy--its basic opposition to

realism. Even if "pure being"


830

is the metaphysical counterpart of an object unaffected by the

knowing of it, it is also the generic concept of a scale of

forms of being that Collingwood could hardly refuse to

investigate as one of the absolute presuppositions of science.

For on his own grounds, he not only accepted in his philosophy

of mind the precepts that the esse of mind is de hac re cogitare

(RP, 100; FR, 172), and in his theory of perception that the

esse of a sensum is sentiri (PA, 198), but also in cosmology

that the modern conception of nature presupposes that being is

becoming. "For an evolutionary science of nature, the esse of

anything in nature is its fieri," which requires that the old

conception of substance that grounded mechanistic physics (and

before that the animistic physics of the Greeks) is resolved

into the concept of function (IN, 15-16). With these clues in

mind, can anything be legitimately said about the meaning of

being that would be acceptable to Collingwood in his role as

metaphysical reformer?

Surely Collingwood would continue to argue that there

can be no science of something as lacking in distinction as pure

abstract being. But at the lowest level of consciousness

something present but indeterminate must survive and be per-

petuated long enough for sensation to occur at all (PA, 212-13).

The first specification of the generic essence of being is

therefore minimally the indeterminate presence of something to

sensation. As this is perpetuated and domesticated in con-

sciousness the meaning


831

of being of the object is refined and modified: from being an

indeterminate presence it becomes a sustained object for

perception, an imagined whole, a coherent imagined whole, a

referred-to imagined whole, etc.--in accordance with the

progressively higher activities of consciousness. At each stage

the meaning of the object's being is determined by the form of

consciousness, and the unique stage of the demand for meaning

made by that form of consciousness on the object.

Is there anything that lies at the summit of this scale?

Is there an object so rich in meaning, so determinate in its

being, that it utterly satisfies the highest demands of the mind

for significance? We have very little to build upon in the

published writings to reconstruct an answer to this question,

since the entire question of concrete ontology is left

unresolved in the Essay on Metaphysics. What we are lacking is

any adequate idea of Collingwood's cosmology-something he

lectured on repeatedly, and which he declared to be one of the

most pressing needs in contemporary philosophy. There is some

indication in The Idea of Nature that Collingwood supported

Hegel's division of reality into the realms of matter, life, and

mind, where each is in the process of turning into the next

higher form, and each is a more perfect embodiment of the

Absolute Idea (IN, 159). But he is also critical of the residue

of mechanism and
832

logicism in Hegel's philosophy of nature (IN, 121-32). The

modern idea of nature, Collingwood argues, recognizes not only

that there is no nature at an instant (as Whitehead phrases it),

but also that a thing is what it does, so that there is no

distinction between motion and that which moves: "modern

physical theory regards matter as possessing its own

characteristics, whether chemical or physical, only because it

moves; time is therefore a factor in its very being, and that

being is fundamentally motion: (IN, 151-52). Furthermore the

older conceptions of space and time--postulated as infinite

extension and succession--"seem to be nothing but abstractions

from the idea of movement" on the one hand, or logical

presuppositions of that idea on the other. But then one

encounters this remarkable passage:

This at any rate seems clear: that since modern science is


now committed to a view of the physical universe as finite,
certainly in space and probably in time, the activity which
this same science identifies with matter cannot be a
self-created or ultimately self-dependent activity. The
world of nature or physical world as a whole, on any such
view, must ultimately depend for its existence on something
other than itself . . . . (M)odern science, after an
experiment with materialism, has come back into line with
the main tradition of European thought, which has always
ascribed to nature an essentially derivative or dependent
status in the general scheme of things. It is true that the
most varied proofs have been offered as to why nature must
be dependent, and the most varied theories as to what it
depended on; but in general, with strikingly few
exceptions, scientists and philosophers have agreed that
the world of nature forms only one part or aspect of all
being, and that in this total realm its place is a
secondary one, one of dependence on something prior to
itself. (IN, 155).
833

But while Collingwood points out that many contemporary cos-

mologists argue, as did their classical and medieval prede-

cessors, that what nature depends upon is God, Collingwood comes

up with a less traditional solution:

Throughout the long tradition of European thought it has


been said . . . that nature, though it is a thing that
really exists, is not a thing that exists in itself or in
its own right, but a thing which depends for its existence
upon something else. I take this to imply that natural
science . . . is not, as the positivists imagined, the only
department or form of human thought . . . and is not even a
self-contained or self-sufficient form of thought, but
depends for its very existence upon some other form of
thought which is different from it and cannot be reduced to
it . . . . What is this other form of thought? I answer,
"History." (IH, 175-76).

What can this mean? What sense of "History" (with a

capital "H") can he have in mind? This brings us face to face

once again with the central paradox of the Essay on Metaphysics,

for while Collingwood has made a fairly convincing case in The

Idea of Nature that the modern idea of nature is modeled on

evolution, and evolution is modeled on the idea of history (IN,

9, 132), at precisely the point where we expect him to complete

the argument on the ontological side he appears to swap horses

and ride out on an epistemological charger, a kind of equus ex

machina. If natural science is dependent upon something else

because nature is dependent on something else, then by force of

the same analogy if what natural science depends upon is history

(in the sense of a kind of knowledge), what nature depends upon

is the ontological referent


834

of historical knowledge. What can this be? Certainly not the

deeds of men done in the past. Is "History" (with a capital "H")

to be taken in the sense of cosmic development, in spite of the

fact that there is nothing in the development of Collingwood's

thought to prepare us for this sudden expansion of the idea of

history, and everything to indicate that it was moving in just

the opposite direction?

Or is there some reality that grounds both nature and

history? Such would seem to be the sense of those early passages

in his writings such as that in Speculum Mentis in which

Descartes' cogito ergo sum is interpreted to mean that "the

concrete historical fact, the fact of my actual present aware-

ness, ((is)) the root of science," and consequently that "Sci-

ence presupposes history and can never go behind history" (SM,

202). Such is the idealistic strand in Collingwood's braided

ring of thought. But opposed to this is the realistic counter--

tendency:

modern thought is disentangling itself from the cobwebs of


subjective idealism . . . . Kant would suggest a very dif-
ferent conclusion: namely that if nature bears on its face
the marks of dependency for its existence on something
else, that something is the human mind . . . . This is bad
philosophy . . . . The most rigorous thought of our own
time, scientific and philosophic alike, has turned
resolutely away from these subjectivist or phenomenalist
doctrines, and agrees that whatever nature depends upon it
does not depend on the human mind. (IN, 156).
835

What is left? Could Collingwood, whose respect for religious

consciousness remained unquestioned throughout all his published

writings, fail to see that a mind unreconciled to the mind of

God has failed in its primary metaphysical obligation? It would

not seem so, judging solely from the following passage from

Chapter XXI of the Essay on Metaphysics, "Quicunque Vult," which

may well be taken as Collingwood's final offering of

rapprochement philosophy:

If metaphysics is our name for the statement of absolute


presuppositions, and if metaphysics and theology are the
same, there are three ways in which the existence of a
world of nature might be made to figure among the doctrines
of theology. 1. It might be a proposition in metaphysics,
as it is for Spinoza, that God and nature are the same. But
this would entail the consequence that natural science is
the same thing as metaphysics: which cannot be right if the
business of metaphysics is to state the absolute pre-
suppositions of natural science. 2. It might be a propo-
sition in metaphysics that the world of nature exists, but
this proposition might be left wholly unrelated to the
proposition that God exists. But then it would not be a
proposition in theology; and therefore, if theology and
metaphysics are the same, not a proposition in metaphysics.
And what about the presupposition of which it was the
statement? The act by which we hold such presuppositions, I
have said elsewhere, is religious faith; and God is that in
which we believe by faith; therefore all our absolute
presuppositions must be presuppositions in holding which we
believe something about God. 3. It might be a proposition
in which the existence of the world of nature was stated in
the form of an attribute or activity of God; and this seems
the only possible alternative. (EM, 215-16).
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aristotle. Metaphysics. Translated with Commentaries and


glossary by Hippocrates G. Apostle. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1966.

---------. The Metaphysics. With an English translation by Hugh


Tredennick. (The Loeb Classical Library). Two Volumes.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1933.

Belnap, Nuel D., and Thomas B. Steel. The Logic of Questions and
Answers. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1976.

Blachowicz, James. "History and Nature in Collingwood's


Dialectic." Idealistic Studies, VI (January, 1976),

Bochenski, I. M. Contemporary European Philosophy. Translated


from the German by Donald Nicholl and Karl
Aschenbrenner. Berkeley: University of California Press,
1969.

---------. The Methods of Contemporary Thought. Translated from


the German by Peter Caws. New York: Harper and Row,
Publishers, Incorporated, 1968.

Bosanquet, Bernard. Knowledge and Reality. London: S.


Sonnenschein and Company, 1892.

---------. The Principle of Individuality and Value. London:


Kraus Reprint, 1927.

Bradley, F. H. Appearance and Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press,


1893.

---------. The Presuppositions of Critical History. Edited with


an introduction and commentary by Lionel Rubinoff.
Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1968.

---------. The Principles of Logic. Two Volumes. Second edition


revised with commentary and terminal essays. London:
Oxford University Press, 1922.

Bury, J. B. A Historv of the Later Roman Empire. London:


Macmillan and Company, Ltd., 1923.

836
837

Chisholm, Roderick M. Realism and the Background of


Phenomenology. New York: The Free Press, 1960.

Collingwood, Kate. Personal letter to the author, dated 26


October 1969.

Collingwood, R. G. An Autobiography. London: Oxford University


Press, 1939.

---------. Correspondence with G. Ryle, 9 May 1935 and 6 June


1935. The Bodleian Library, 1964: Ms. Eng. lett. d. 194.

---------"Economics as a Philosophical Science." International


Journal of Ethics, XXXVI (1925), 162-185.

---------. An Essay on Metaphysics. Oxford: The Clarendon Press,


1940.

---------. An Essay on Philosophical Method. Oxford: The


Clarendon Press, 1933.

---------. Essays in the Philosophv of Art. Edited by Alan


Donagan. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1964.

---------. Essays_in the Philosophy of History. Edited by


William Debbins. New York: University of Texas Press,
1965.

---------. Faith and Reason: Essays in the Philosophy of Religion


Edited by Lionel Rubinoff. Chicago: Quadrangle Books,
1968.

---------. The Idea of History Edited by T. M. Knox. Oxford:The


Clarendon Press, 1945.

---------. The Idea of Nature. Edited by T. M. Knox. Oxford: The


Clarendon Press, 1945.

---------. The New Leviathan. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1942.

---------. "Political Action." Proceedings of the Aristotelian


Society, XXIX (1928-1929), 155-176.

---------. "The Present Need of a Philosophy." Philosophy, 9


(1934), 262-265.

---------. The Principles of Art. Oxford: The Clarendon Press,


1938.
838

---------. Religion and Philosophy Company, 1916. London:


Macmillian and Company, 1916.

---------. "Sensation and Thought." Proceedings of the


Aristotelian Society, XXIV (1923-24), 55-76.

---------. Speculum Mentis. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1924.

Däniken, Erich van. Chariots of the Gods? Translated by Michael


Heron. New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1970.

Donagan, Alan. The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood.


Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1962.

Dray, W. H. "Philosophy of History." The Encyclopedia of


Philosophy. Edited by Paul Edwards. New York: Macmillan
Publishing Company, Inc. and The Free Press 1967, VI,
247-254.

Gallie, W. B. Philosophy and the Historical Understanding. New


York: Schocken Books, 1964.

Gardiner, Patrick, editor. Theories of History. Glencoe: The


Free Press, 1959.

Geach, Peter. Mental Acts. 1957. London: Routledge and Kegan


Paul,

Harris, Errol E. "Collingwood on Eternal Problems."


Philosophical Quarterly, I (April, 1951), 228-241.

---------. Hypothesis and Perception. London: George Allen and


Unwin, Ltd., 1970.

---------. "Mr. Ryle and the Ontological Argument." Mind, XLV


October, 1936), 474-480.

---------. Nature, Mind, and Modern Science. London: George


Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1954.

Hegel, G. W. F. Logic. From The Encyclopaedia of the


Philosophical Sciences. Translated by William Wallace.
Lon. Oxford University Press, 1873.

Hick, John H., and Arthur C. McGill, editors. The Many-faced


Argument. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1967.

Johnston, William M. The Formative Years of R. G. Collingwood.


The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1967.
839

Kant, Immanuel. The Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by N.


Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press, Inc.,
1929/1961.

Klibansky, Raymond, and H. J. Paton, editors. Philosophy and


History. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1936.

Knox, T.M. "Notes on Collingwood's Philosophical Work, with a


Bibliography." Proceedings of the British Academy, XXIX
(1944).

Krausz, Michael, editor. Critical Essays in the Philosophy of R.


G. Collingwood. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972.

Langer, Susanne K. Feeling and Form. New York: Charles Scribner


s Sons, 1953.

MacKay, Donald S. "On Supposing and Presupposing.'' The Review


of Metaphysics, II (September, 1948), 1-20.

McCallum, R. B. "Robin George Collingwood." Proceedings of the


British Academy, XXIX (1944), 463-468.

Mink, Louis 0. Mind, History, and Dialectic: The Philosophy of


R. G. Collingwood. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1969.

Owens, Joseph. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian


Metaphysics. Toronto: The Pontifical Institute of
Mediaeval Studies, 1951.

Passmore, John. A Hundred Years of Philosophy. Baltimore:


Penguin Books, 1957/1968.

Paton, H. J. "Fifty Years of Philosophy." Contemporary British


Philosophy, Third Series. Edited by H. D. Lewis. New
York: Humanities Press, 1956/1961.

Post, John F. "A Defense of Collingwood's Theory of


Presuppositions." Inquiry, VIII (1965), 332-354

--------. "Does Knowing Make a Difference to What Is Known?"


Philosophical Quarterly, XV (1965), 220-228.

Robinson, Richard. Plato's Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: The


Clarendon Press, 1953.

Rubinoff, Lionel. Collingwood and the Reform of Metaphysics.


Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970.
840

Russell, Bertrand. "Logical Atomism." Contemporary British


Philosophy, First Series. Edited by J. H. Muirhead.
London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1924.

---------. "Meinong's Theory of Complexes and Assumptions."


Mind, XIII (1904).

Ryle, Gilbert. "Mr. Collingwood and the Ontological Argument."


Mind, XLIV (April, 1935), 137-151.

Rynin, David. "Donagan on Collingwood: Absolute Presuppositions,


Truth, and Metaphysics." The Review of Metaphysics, XVIII
(December, 1964), 301-333.

Strawson, P. F. Introduction to Logical Theory. London: Methuen


and Company, Ltd., 1952.

Thayer, H. S. Meaning and Action: A Critical History of


Pragmatism. New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc.,

Toulmin, Stephen. Human Understanding: The Collective Use and


Evolution of Concepts. Princeton: Princeton University
Press,-T972.

Warnock, G. J. English Philosophy Since 1900. Oxford: Oxford


University Press, 1969.

Warren, Howard C. A History of Association Psychology. New York:


Charles Scribner's Sons, 1921.

Wilson, Clifford. Crash Go the Chariots. New York: Lancer Books,


Inc. 1972.
BETWEEN THE HORNS:

SOME COLLINGWOOD DILEMMAS AND THEIR SOLUTIONS

By Glenn Shipley

1. The Four Autobiographical Themes and Their Dilemmas.

Many students of R.G. Collingwood report that their interest in his thought was
awakened by An Autobiography, the remarkable testimony of an Oxford don running counter to
the currents of thought of his day and passionately devoted to the archeological, historical and
philosophical life that he led. But reading beyond the Autobiography to his other published
writings forces those of us drawn to his thinking to wonder to what extent his theory and his
practice coincided. We are thrust into a consideration of this matter by dilemmas that arise
directly from his autobiographical self-interpretation. This paper will take a direct look at four
dilemmas arising from Collingwood’s Autobiography, then proceed to an examination of how he
himself approached some related philosophical dilemmas, and finally it will draw on themes
revealed in Collingwood’s actual praxis to point the way towards resolving the dilemmas he left
for us.

I have argued elsewhere that a careful reading of the Autobiography reveals four
dominant themes that indeed carry over into all of his early and later published writings: (1)
Collingwood’s reaction to the Oxford “realist” philosophers; (2) his development of question-
and-answer (Q-A) logic; (3) the theoretical and practical relationship of history and philosophy;
and (4) the overall goal of a rapprochement philosophy that could provide a reconciliational
bridge not only between history and philosophy, but also theory and practice, etc.1

Aside from the Autobiography’s supposed “errors of omission," there remain dilemmas
which still gore those of us who want to make sense of Collingwood’s philosophy. Chief among
them are some arising from these very issues - the idealism-realism controversy, Q-A logic as an
alternative to propositional logic, metaphysics as an historical science of absolute, truth-neutral
presuppositions, and philosophy as absolute or relative. While I will have a few things to say
about all of these issues, my primary concern will be with the issues of anti-realism and
rapprochement philosophy.

(A.) Let us start where Collingwood starts, with the realism-idealism controversy.
Collingwood wants us to be clear that the assertion of an object unaffected by the knowing of it –
the fundamental standpoint of the position he unwaveringly calls “realism” – is the root error he
1
From Realism to Rapprochement: The Autobiographical Interpretation of Collingwood’s Philosophy (FRTR),
Loyola University of Chicago, 1983. This work is available in digital format to anyone who requests it.
has devoted his intellectual life to overcoming. The key argument overturning this philosophical
position is one which demonstrates that the realist's position affirms what it simultaneously
denies: it claims to know what it admits it does not know - i.e. what the object is like outside of
the condition of being known.

The dilemma that emerges is as follows. As John Post points out,2 Collingwood’s anti-
realism argument cuts both ways: it is as effective against the idealist position as it is against the
realist one. To say that one knows that the object is affected by the knowing of it is ruled out by
the same inability to satisfy the conditional premise. The logical outcome of the argument would
then seem to be a confirmation of a basically skeptical position, that one cannot know whether an
object is or is not affected by the knowing of it. The goring occurs because Collingwood
claimed not to be a skeptic.

Now if Collingwood were to construct a comparable argument to rule out skepticism, it


would need to address the inversion of the fundamental realist presupposition to show that
“Knowledge is unaffected by the object known” is absurd. He would need to tread carefully
between the objectivity-subjectivity dilemma. An object totally determined by acts of knowledge
possesses a meaning that is made rather than found, and which affirms subjectivity at the
expense of abandoning any independent claim for objectivity. An object totally determining the
act which knows it has a meaning which is found rather than made, which affirms objectivity at
the expense of subjectivity, which then appears passive, plastic, and dependent.

Even if we are careful to distinguish broader and narrower meanings for terms like
"knowledge," "affected by," and "object," in Collingwood's philosophy of mind it is still difficult
to find any room for the object to have any affect on the act of knowledge. Even though he states
in The Principles of Art that in the case of perception knowledge does not make such a difference
to the object known that it creates the object ex nihilo, and that something must be present to
sensation with sufficient strength and for long enough time for attention to focus on it (PA, 291-
92), nevertheless in The New Leviathan Collingwood abandons even this concession to realism.
He holds that objects of sensation are utterly ambiguous with respect to all interpretative
categories of understanding, going so far as to assert that in a field of sensa a red patch is not
distinct from any other characteristics in that visual field (NL, 4.45-4.63). In fact he claims that
attention “draws the line” that makes such distinctions in a field of sensa possible (NL, 5.62-
5.65). What we are left with is "a flux of things within us and without, and … although this is
actually present to us (nothing else, indeed, is present) it is not intelligible" (PH, 173). If it is an
act of consciousness that makes all perceptual distinctions, then it would appear that perceptual

2
John F. Post, "Does Knowing Make a Difference to What is Known?" Philosophical Quarterly, xv, no. 60 (July,
1965), pp 220-28.
objects are “made” rather than “found,” and Collingwood has exhibited a basically Kantian
orientation and crossed the line into subjective idealism.3

Now while this anti-realist stance may be consistent with his autobiographical
interpretation, it leaves the reader lacking resources to solve the dilemma. It is particularly
vexing in the light of Collingwood’s insistence that scientific history requires the critical
interpretation of evidence, where evidence is not something completely determined by the act of
historical interpretation. In any version of re-enactment, the question arises concerning the
original historical enactment, whose encapsulation, one assumes, has some fabrication-resistant
substance to it in order to avoid historical fraud or charlatanism.4 In essence, then, this is the
recurrent “found” vs. “made” ambiguity, and future interest in Collingwood hinges on the ability
of interpreters to either resolve the paradox or remain impaled on the horns of yet another
version of the realist-idealist dilemma.

(B.) This dilemma carries over into the second theme, Collingwood’s “discovery” of Q-A
logic. Collingwood wants us to see Q-A logic as an alternative to propositional or formal logic,
which he portrays as the realist's only "method" of philosophical analysis. As presented in quasi-
axiomatic form in the Essay on Metaphysics it would appear that since a one-one correspondence
between indicative sentences in a language and propositions in a formal system is not possible,
one might be free to dispense with formal logic altogether, and engage in a free-form (if
Baconian) cross-examination of evidence based on unquestioned presuppositions.

But even at a very rudimentary level it is clear that Q-A logic cannot serve as a
replacement for formal logic. It does not provide any way to decide such simple issues as when
one proposition is validly or invalidly inferred directly from some other proposition, or how one
is to decide issues of logical competence. Interposing a question within an inference adds
nothing to it: from a logical point of view it is unnecessary to the derivative relationship of a
conclusion to its premises.

But we need to feel the tips of the horns of this particular dilemma a bit more acutely. In
both versions of Q-A logic - in the Autobiography and the Essay on Metaphysics, Collingwood
describes the process in person- or thought-dependent terms: "Every statement that anyone ever
makes is made in answer to a question (EM, 23); "'Proposition' denotes an assertive act of
thought or what in those acts of thought is asserted" (A, 30). Yet as "logic" Q-A hopes to
preserve its compulsive, necessary force as "criteriological." A proposition is always a logical
3
Collingwood’s attempt in The New Leviathan to evade this conclusion by calling the denial of sense-objects a
“methodological” negative is not convincing.
4
Grace Simpson’s defense of Collingwood’s archeological practice in the 1937 excavation at King Arthur's Round
Table is interesting in this regard. "I saw Bersu push his trowel to demonstrate to my father how Collingwood 'made
a post-hole'. I heard those shocking words. One does not make a post-hole, one finds one. I have never forgotten
how upset my father was." "Collingwood's Latest Archeology Misreported by Bersu and Richmond," Collingwood
Studies, vol. V (1998), p. 114.
and not merely a linguistic entity - i.e. it states what ought to be the case rather than what merely
is the case concerning assertive acts of thought (A, 31). A question is said to "arise" because
some presupposition has "logical efficacy" to make it arise (EM, 27). Now if what "logic" and
"logical" means is something like "how a real person really thinks when he is being careful and
scientific" this is either a tautology (logic is thinking logically) or it is embedded in personal
consciousness. But if it is thought or person-dependent, a proposition loses its compulsive force
as following necessarily from premises, whether it is in F-logic or Q-A logic.

So the dilemma is that if logic is person or thought-dependent, it lacks necessary


compulsion: "it" (the conclusion or proposition) does not "follow" or "arise," I make it do so. In
other words logic is not psychology, but it is psychology.5 No self-respecting formal logician
would agree to this. Whatever else logic is, it is not epistemology, and it is not dependent on
what any person happens to think. But if logic is neither person nor thought dependent, it ceases
to be a product of human intelligence and becomes an "automatic" or mechanistic process over
which man has no control.

(C.) The third autobiographical theme - the philosophy of history - is the issue that has
drawn the most attention by students of Collingwood. The issue I wish to focus on is the sort of
"reconciliation" that Collingwood finds between these two modes of thought. It is plain that the
remainder of his reconciliational program hinges on this, since Collingwood clearly wanted to
make the history-philosophy rapprochement paradigmatic for all of its other manifestations.

In order to satisfy the conditions of the Autobiography for minimal reconciliation,


Collingwood needs (1) to analyze the concept of history and exhibit philosophy as necessarily
contained within it, and (2) to analyze the concept of philosophy to exhibit history within it.
Philosophy is in history insofar as history is a variety of self-knowledge, is the history of
thought, is the exercise of a priori imagination, deals with a past that is actually an aspect of the
present, reasons to its conclusions using evidence and inference, aims at a kind of truth, etc.
History is in philosophy insofar as reality is a process of change, there are no eternal truths or
unchanging entities, no such thing as human nature, its metaphysical subject matter has
presuppositions rooted in the science dominant in its day, etc. It is not surprising that some
students of Collingwood have found that this relationship puts philosophy in a very negative
light.

5
" Take the mental activity as a self-contained fact; refuse, so far as that is possible, to treat of its metaphysical
aspect, its relations with real things other than itself and you have psychology. Thus in scientific thought as studied
by logic we have a judgment in which the mind knows reality: psychology, treating the judgment as a mere event,
omits its reference to reality, that is to say, does not raise the question whether it is true" (RP, 40). In a footnote to
this passage, Collingwood adds: "The same omission or abstraction is made by Formal Logic, which I take to be a
psychological rather than a philosophical science."
The stance of the Essay on Metaphysics puts a sharper point on this dilemma. If the
metaphysician's task is simply to ferret out the absolute presuppositions of science and in the
process be restricted from showing how one set of absolute presuppositions is better as "truer"
than another, or how one sort of science is better as having more "con-supponible" absolute
presuppositions than another, or how absolute presuppositions in one constellation give rise to
absolute presuppositions in another, or why one science is replaced by another, then the
metaphysician starts to resemble a rather sophisticated scissors-and-paste man. He is producing
a "catalogue" of principles. The kind of historian this metaphysician is reduced to is one who
cannot be truly evaluative or criteriological, who cannot demonstrate what is progressive in
historical process, and whose attitude towards his subject matter is less respectful than
idolatrous. But if on the contrary the metaphysician takes his historical work as seriously as
Collingwood would have him take it in his exhortations elsewhere about scientific history, then
his hold on the truth-neutrality or absoluteness of presuppositions starts to slip. So Collingwood
seems to be saying both that metaphysics is an historical science while simultaneously denying
that there is anything particularly historical about it (it consists in logical analysis of systems of
inquiry to expose their absolute presuppositions - which has nothing transparently to do with
deeds of men done in the past, re-enacted and narratively presented, etc); and that history is a
metaphysical science while simultaneously denying that there is anything metaphysical about it
(it rests on truth-neutral presuppositions, is not grounded in ontology, etc.).

(D) This leads us into our fourth and last autobiographical theme, the issue of
"rapprochement philosophy". The Autobiography is somewhat vague about what that is, even
while it is explicit in what it applies to - primarily theory and practice and issues in moral, social
and political philosophy. But if we are to take the examples of this rapprochement as they occur
in his actual published writings, the meaning of "reconciliation" varies from (1) the mere
sequencing of two modes of thought in a "process of development," to (2) a complementarity
between two modes of thought able to approach one another and yet retain their separate identity,
to (3) a dialectical relationship of sub- and super-ordination in a scale of forms with necessary
relations of opposition and distinction, differences of degree and kind, to (4) a complete unity or
identification of the reconciliata.

While the main issue here is what the ultimate goal is for reconciliational philosophy, the
brunt of the dilemma is felt on the issue of whole vs. part. What is the overall context within
which rapprochement works? Are the reconciliata parts of some larger whole, or is the whole
merely the sum of its parts?

Now there is no apparent reason that there cannot be many forms of reconciliation, and
for different purposes, but for an anti-realist philosopher like Collingwood who repeatedly
directs his readers to seek truth in "the whole" rather than "the part," this does not seem
satisfactory. Is there an Absolute end-point to the reconciliational process? While philosophy is
portrayed as “absolute knowledge” in his early writings, one looks in vain in the Autobiography
for any hint of "the Absolute" or mention of dialectic. In his final published works "the
Absolute" no longer appears as a noun, but only as an adjective - a qualifier regarding
presuppositions, and that only in the Essay on Metaphysics. We wish to know if in his final view
Collingwood abandoned the absolute idealism of his youth, as in the cryptic description of the
"unified life of the mind" sought in Speculum Mentis, or if he became a complete relativist with
no final anchor for any scale of forms of knowledge. In short, if there is no common ground for
reconciliata - no anchor or absolute standpoint - they remain unreconciled.

2. Getting Between the Horns: Theory and Practice

An electronic search on the term "dilemma" across all of Collingwood's published


writings calls up references to the term in virtually every one of them - the Autobiography and
The New Leviathan being the sole exceptions.6 Some of these references are not really to the
point of this paper, but of those that are, the discussion is often revealing of how Collingwood's
mind worked.

1. Collingwood's earliest published work, Religion and Philosophy, is remarkable for the
interesting and undisguised glimpses it gives us into positions that he will elaborate in his later
works. For example in the key chapter on personality he points to the fact and continuing ideal
of inter-personal communication as the fundamental starting point for any theory of knowledge,
and takes it as evidently true that two minds can think the same thought (RP, 98-103). Since the
mind is its thoughts, two minds which think the same thought or will the same action share the
unity of consciousness which is the mark of the individual (RP, 101-2). Not only can two persons
have "one mind" insofar as they share the same thought or will the same action, but two forms of
thought like history and philosophy are called "the same thing" in the sense of referring to the
same reality or the same intentional object - the "one real world" (RP 51). Each presupposes the
other, as the particular presupposes the universal and vice-versa (RP, 49; cf. PH, 352).

In a chapter entitled "matter" Collingwood develops an argument aimed at resolving the


"materialism-idealism" dilemma - namely the disjunction made by the "plain man's metaphysic"
between mind as a non-extended or spaceless reality consisting of thought, and matter which
6
An electronic word search for "dilemma" yields the following references: RP, 71, 88, 120, 122, 129; SM, 21, 66,
232-35, 238, 240-41, 283-86; EPM, 21, 61, 68-69, 80-81, 85, 161: PA, 34-36, 311; A, [none}; EM, 333-35; NL,
[none]; IH, 141-42, 151, 157-58,163-65, 174-75, 278-79, 291-301, 353-54, 482; PH, 14, 33, 197, 200-01, 226-28;
IN, 41-2, 51, 140, 174. Since Collingwood sometimes refers to a dilemma as a paradox, contradiction or
opposition, it would be useful to do electronic searches on these terms as well. "Paradox," for example, appears at
NL, 5.34, 6.52, 6.54, 7.16, 26.61, and 36.91.
occupies space and is subject to the law of causation, but has no consciousness of itself (RP, 72).
The dilemma is escaped once it is shown that matter is inconceivable without ascribing to it
some qualities of mind (it is active as well as passive) and mind without ascribing to it some
qualities of matter (it is passive as well as active) (RP, 94). In these demonstrations it is assumed
that real thought cannot be self-contradictory without being self-destructive (RP, 129), so it
would appear that dilemmas are always abstract and merely apparent.

Collingwood claims that the position he is advocating violates neither realism nor
idealism in their more satisfactory forms (RP, 101, n.1). In the chapter on materialism in Part II
(Religion and Metaphysics) he argues that the materialist position (which he identifies as a kind
of realism - see RP, 73, n 1) leads to a part-whole dilemma ("either know the whole or do not
pretend to know even this one part") and ultimately to skepticism (knowledge of reality as a
whole is knowledge of an endless series of discrete parts, so it is impossible), and that both
problems are escaped by arguing that "knowledge of this single part is already knowledge of the
whole" (RP, 88; cf. PH, 188).7 But in the end, in the choice between a crude materialism (read:
"realism") that reduces all of mind to matter, and an "equally crude idealism" that reduces all of
matter to mind, even the youthful Collingwood will opt for idealism - but only if "mind" is
understood as a concept with layers of meaning. The mind, he argues, is not a mechanical
structure automatically producing thought. It is an activity whose esse is not just simply
cogitare but de hac re cogitare (RP, 100).

To ask whether mind is a form of matter or matter is a form of mind is very largely a
question of words. The important thing is that we should be able to bring the two into
relation at all; that we should hold such a conception of matter as does not prevent us
from admitting truth, morality, and life as a whole to be real facts, and that we should
hold such a conception of mind as does not reduce the world to an illusion and experience
to a dream. The first of these errors is that of a crude materialism, and the second that of
an equally crude idealism. The view for which we are contending would claim the title
of idealism rather than materialism, but only because the current conception of mind
seems a more adequate description of the world than the current conception of matter.
We are laying stress on the fact that the world is the place of freedom and consciousness,
not of blind determinism; at present this can best be conveyed by saying that mind is the
one reality. (RP, 94-95.)
The fact and ideal of complete interpersonal communication, along with the themes of "thought"
as a meaning-seeking activity, the reciprocity of part and whole, the description of mind as
intentionality, the non-mechanical nature of human understanding, and the insistence on
describing knowing in such a manner that determination of the object by mind is not ruled out -
all these are themes that recur throughout his later writings - modified, but never abandoned.

7
This argument re-appears in a different context in the Essay on Philosophical Method as the solution to another
dilemma (the circularity of philosophical argument) by showing how "coming to know means coming to know in a
different and better way" what is to some extent already known (EPM, 161).
2. Speculum Mentis explicitly rejects his earlier solution to the realist part-whole dilemma
(SM, 240), and then attempts an alternative escape by showing that "the infinite given whole of
fact is the nature of the knowing mind as such" (SM, 241). In each of the five forms of
experience that he explores, a distinction and separation is made between subject and object, "a
relation of difference without identity" characteristic of the abstract concept (SM, 243). In all
such distinctions each side - subject and object - represents a false abstraction, and getting
between the horns occurs when both subject and object are shown to be part of the same concrete
universal in all forms of experience. Speculum Mentis also hints at a dialectical development
wherein two concepts are synchronically opposed by ignoring their diachronic development.
This occurs by making explicit what was only implicit in a previous, subordinate, preceding
mode of thought. Philosophy is therefore self-knowledge achieved by correcting errors made by
subordinate forms of thought (art, religion, science, history and the like), each of which is seen as
a philosophical error as a "logical consequence of realism" which continually mistakes the
product of abstraction as something independent of the mind which makes it (SM, 249-52).

But on the way to "absolute knowledge" - the philosophical self-knowledge of mind -


Collingwood writes the following, remarkable passage. Speaking of the transition from religion
to philosophy he says:

the task of philosophy, regarded as the philosophy of religion, is the simple translation of
this solution of the riddle of life out of the language of mythology into that of philosophy.
… Translation itself is based on the fact that the meaning takes new colour and shines
with a new light when we express it in different words. To set the meaning as an abstract
self-identity over against the language makes translation pointless: to swamp it in a mere
immediate union with the language itself makes translation impossible. Meaning and
language are simply the universal and the particular. Abstract logic, the false theory of
science, sets them outside one another. Abstract aesthetic, the false theory of art and
religion, swamps the one in the other. Concrete logic sees them as distinct yet
inseparable. (SM, 253).
The function of philosophy is thus "the process of translation into progressively adequate
language," which "is simply the dialectical self-criticism of thought" (SM, 253-54). Once again
idealism and realism are pitted against one another, but this time Collingwood accuses them both
of "committing the fundamental error of separating the metaphysical inquiry as to what the world
is in itself from the psychological inquiry as to how we come to know it" (SM, 266). Idealism
leaves the opposition of subject and object unreconciled, or else it reconciles them by turning the
object into another mind or a society of minds or an infinite mind - all of which he rejects. (SM,
266-67)8 In its place he proposes a philosophy of absolute knowledge reconciling realism as a
background and idealism as a foreground as products of "abstraction" - the adoption of the

8
In a later section on historical philosophy, Collingwood concedes that it was the achievement of the great German
idealists that they "killed scientific realism - the popular philosophy of today - as dead as a door-nail" (SM, 287).
externality of the object, which in reality is mistaking the imaginary for the real (SM, 291-98).
What remains of his "map of knowledge"9 in the end is summarized as follows:

Our position at the start was wholly realistic, and there is a sense in which it is realistic to
the end. … [But} we did not assume that any one form of experience could be accepted
as already, in its main lines, wholly free from error. Led by this principle, we found that
the real world was implied, but not asserted, in art; asserted, but not thought out, in
religion; thought out, but only subject to fictitious assumptions, in science…. The real
object is the mind itself, as we now know. But in abolishing the notion of an external
world other than the mind we do not assert any of the silly nonsense usually described…
as idealism. … The very essence of trees and hills and people is that they should be not
myself but my objects in perception: they are not subjective but objective, not states of
myself but facts that I know. None the less, my knowing them is organic to them: …
They and I alike are members of one whole…. (SM, 311).
We shall have more to say about the nature of this "one whole" in the next section. But note that
throughout Speculum Mentis the “forms of experience” are characterized by their mode of
expression in language – as metaphorical, implied, asserted (SM 252-53; cf. FRTR, 312-13).

3. The Essay on Philosophical Method works these relationships into a set of criteria for
deciding whether apparently opposing viewpoints (e.g. the horns of a dilemma) are fully
reconcilable or represent a pre-philosophical stage in which two reconciliata are opposed but not
distinguished, or are distinguished but not opposed. When they are seen as fully philosophical,
they are integrated into an overlapping scale of forms in which differences of degree are
coordinated with differences of kind, so that opposites are located at different points on a
hierarchical scale (EPM, 68). One is impaled on the horns of a dilemma by acceptance of a false
disjunction (EPM, 80-81) and all disjunctions are ultimately false, once they are understood
philosophically.

Later in the essay Collingwood takes up the issue of the circularity of philosophical
argument as "justifying its own starting point" (EPM, 160). With a significant glance back at
Kant, he writes:

If the first principles of philosophy are to be justified, they must be justified by that
philosophy itself. This can be done only if the arguments of philosophy, instead of
having an irreversible direction from principles to conclusions, have a reversible one, the
principles establishing the conclusions and the conclusions reciprocally establishing the
principles. But an argument of this kind, in which A rests on B and B rests reciprocally
on A, is a vicious circle. Are to conclude that philosophy is in the dilemma of either
renouncing this characteristic function and conforming to the irreversible pattern of exact
science, or else losing all cogency in a circular argument?
The solution of the dilemma lies in a feature of philosophical thought… the Socratic
principle that philosophical reasoning leads to no conclusions which we did not in some
sense already know already… [F]or if the species of a philosophical genus overlap, the
distinction between the known and the unknown, which in a non-philosophical subject
9
It is interesting that the dual metaphor of “mirror” and “map” are employed in Speculum Mentis - in its title (mirror
of the mind) and its subtitle (“a map of knowledge”). With characteristic compression, Collingwood identifies the
two (SM, 315) without recognizing the radically different representative function of each.
matter involves a difference between two mutually exclusive classes of truths, in a
philosophical subject-matter implies that we may both know and not know the same
thing; a paradox which disappears in the light of the notion of a scale of forms of
knowledge, where coming to know means coming to know in a different and better way.

4. Following the Essay on Philosophical Method, Collingwood worked out a theory of


linguistic expression as part of his philosophy of mind. This is accomplished in The Principles
of Art and The New Leviathan - but only in brief outline, and ignoring other riches in these
domains. In The Principles of Art, for example, Collingwood takes the wraps off some of his
anti-realistic weaponry and takes aim at psychological behaviorism and the "stimulus-response"
model of art appreciation as a form of anti-aesthetics (PA, 34) - issues we shall not pursue here,
except to note that his strategy again is dissolving a dilemma by focusing on the "false
disjunction" from which it arises.10 What I wish to call attention to in The Principles of Art is the
theory of perception and the characterization of language that he develops there. Concerning
perception, he allows room for the analysis of consciousness (basically a phenomenological
method) to develop answers to questions which an analytic philosophy of mind (putting
questions to consciousness) cannot (PA, 205-06; see FRTR, 382-83 & 383, n.1). Concerning
language, he positions it as a further specification of expression of emotion by means of bodily
acts (PA, 109-14), and speech as a further specification of language (PA, 242-51). In the midst
of this discussion is one of Collingwood's wonderfully lucid paragraphs - this about meaning:
Language in its intellectualized form has both expressiveness and meaning. As language,
it expresses a certain emotion. As symbolism, it refers beyond that emotion to the thought
whose emotional charge it is. This is the familiar distinction between 'what we say' and
'what we mean'. 'What we say' is what we immediately express: the eager or reluctant or
triumphant or regretful utterance in which these emotions and the gestures or sounds that
express them are inseparable parts of a single experience. 'What we mean' is the
intellectual activity upon which these are the emotional charge, and towards which the
words expressing the emotions are a kind of finger-post, pointing for ourselves in the
direction from which we have come, and for another in the direction to which he must go
if he wishes to 'understand what we say', that is, to reconstruct for himself and in himself
the intellectual experience which has led us to say what we did. (PA, 269)
In The New Leviathan this positioning of language is carried further, where Collingwood
calls discourse "the activity by which a man means anything;" it is the activity of meaning
something (a) by something else (b), where meaning (a) is an act of theoretical consciousness,
and (b) is a practical activity, the production in oneself or others of a flow of sounds or the like

10
"And we do frequently… impale ourselves on the horns of a dilemma by arguing that either the artistic attitude
towards reality is the right one and the scientific the wrong, or the scientific is right and the artistic wrong; where
right or wrong mean justified or unjustified by the unalterable character of reality itself. But the answer to the
dilemma is that both are right, and that each is wrong if it claims to exclude or supersede the other; because the
opposition between them is like the opposition of unity and plurality – an opposition in which each term is necessary
to the other. As unity and plurality are categories or transcendentals of pure logic, which means that any object of
logical thought must necessarily be thought of as both one and manifold, so art and science are categories or
transcendentals of the mind, which means that any activity or operation of the mind must have the characteristics of
art and also the characteristics of science." - The Idea of a Philosophy of Something, 1927 (IH2, 353).
which serve as the vehicle of that meaning. (NL, 6.1-6.19). Language is an abstraction from
discourse: it is the system adopted, the means employed, the rules followed in the activity of
discourse - a system of sounds or the like as having meanings, these meanings being what a
person using that word means by making that sound or gesture (NL, 6.11, 6.18, 6.41, 6.58). This
is developed into a scale of forms of thinking from conceptual thinking (selective attention,
naming, classification, evocative thinking, formation of concepts, and abstraction) to
propositional thinking (with its subject-predicate form, questioning and answering, truth and
error, etc) to rational thinking (simple knowledge, reflection, theoretical and practical reason) -
all within a "field of feeling" over which ranges "simple consciousness" in the form of attention.
In all this at the very lowest level of consciousness "meaning" is introduced. At the first stage of
mental life a man is said to be conscious of a confused mass of feeling because he has found a
language of some kind by which he can "mean" it (NL, 7.24), where "meaning" here applies
down to the level of gesture-language (included in the genus "discourse"), wherein in its
primitive function consciousness can mean something without naming it (NL, 6.1). Pre-
reflective meaning in first-order consciousness can therefore be discursive without being
properly speaking linguistic (cf. NL, 6.11).

In sum, we find Collingwood developing a theory of meaning and interpretation from his
analysis of language and mind. This has huge implications but largely unexplored for his
handling of philosophical dilemmas and his location or mapping of the logical functions of mind.

5. The climax of what turns out to be Collingwood's re-interpretation of the act-object


distinction in epistemology occurs in The Idea of History. Leading up to it Collingwood
discusses what he came to call Bradley's dilemma - that

Either reality is the immediate flow of subjective life, in which case it is subjective but
not objective, it is enjoyed but cannot be known, or else it is that which we know, in
which case it is objective and not subjective, it is a world of real things outside the
subjective life of our mind and outside each other. Bradley himself accepted the first
horn of the dilemma; but to accept either horn is to be committed to the fundamental error
of conceiving the life of mind as a mere immediate flow of feelings and sensations
devoid of all reflection and self knowledge. So conceived, mind is itself, but it does not
know itself; the being of mind is such as to make self-knowledge impossible. (IH2, 141)

Collingwood credits Michael Oakeshott with overcoming Bradley's dilemma by showing


that experience is not immediate, but contains mediation or thought within itself, so that "the real
is no longer divided into that which 'knows' but cannot be known… and that which is 'known' but
cannot know" (IH2, 152). But Oakeshott falls prey to a further dilemma concerning the dead
past and the living present, assuming there is no third alternative. Collingwood finds that there is
an "escape between the horns" by means of a the concept of a "living past which, because it was
thought and not mere natural event, can be re-enacted in the present and in that re-enactment
known as past" (IH, 158) In other words, he denies the disjunction.

Collingwood builds this into the remarkable discussion of re-enactment in The Idea of
History. There Collingwood states that a re-enacted thought, whether the original thought was
one's own or someone else's, is neither immediate as imbedded in the total flow of consciousness
(as idealists would assert) nor atomic and merely mediate (as "those who have opposed the
idealists" argue), but is both mediate and immediate - immediate in being part of the flow of
experience in a personal life and mediate in being something revived and repeated in separate
instances of being thought (IH2, 300-1). Here the dilemma is dissolved by proposing a "third
alternative" - the "double character of thought" - that denies the disjunction, which had mis-
described the mental reality. In the context of his philosophy of mind, this bi-directional aspect
of thought is what he would refer to as the "double object" of consciousness.

3. The Unity of the Autobiographical Themes

So where is the unity of the Collingwood's philosophy in all of this? What guidance do
these examples give us for solving the autobiographical dilemmas –the "found" vs. "made"
dilemma of realism and idealism, the person or thought dependency or autonomy of logic,
metaphysics as an historical science of absolute presuppositions which are neither metaphysical
nor historical; and rapprochement philosophy which leaves reconciliata unreconciled. Where is
rapprochement when we really need it?

If we were to take his autobiographical self-interpretation as final and complete, we


might have expected to find something like the following scenario carried out in his later
philosophy: The agenda of philosophy is spread out on the axis of the idealism-realism debate,
which takes the form of an epistemological dilemma concerning knowledge, its object, and an
affective relationship between them, and a metaphysical dilemma between subject and object.
The solution to these dilemmas is not by employing formal logic and ruling out one of these or
the other as an isolated proposition, but by employing Q-A logic and exhibiting the
presupposition of the question common to both positions - seeing them as attempts to answer the
same question. There would follow an historical re-enactment of the process of development of
the problem, in which it would become evident that each is necessary to the other and showing
how they form a sequential developmental pattern. Completed reconciliation would exhibit the
structure of the resolved dilemma within a dialectical scale of forms.

But this is not what a careful and honest interpreter of Collingwood will find, at least not
explicitly among the published writings. Concerning the realism-idealism debate, for example,
Q-A logic is seldom if ever in evidence. Clearly there is no treatment of dilemmas by continual
location of a common question, or the exposition of underlying presuppositions of which we are
unaware. Instead we frequently find Collingwood denying the disjunction by finding some
mediating term which the disjunction ignores, or by showing that each horn of dilemma implies
the other (is not truly disjunctional). But sometimes he accepts it as a refutation of a position,
and takes one horn over the other. In short, we find that in his actual praxis, Collingwood
displays the time-honored argumentative skills and logical strategies of the philosopher. And
while there are plenty of instances of historical analysis where idealism is portrayed as the proper
epistemological successor to realism (in one of its guises as empiricism, naturalism or
positivism), no final historical reconciliation between realism and idealism is ever carried out,
and the two positions are never fully exhibited as successors in a process of development or
coordinated concepts in a scale of forms. What we also find is the emergence of a pattern of
thought that is not made explicit in the Autobiography, and at the risk of some repetition, I would
like to take one final look at this territory.

In his earliest writings, Collingwood's philosophical touchstone is the fact and ideal of
inter-personal communication and language, and this is taken as his launching point for resolving
serious dilemmas and complete scepticism. In Religion and Philosophy Collingwood defines
personality in terms of the identity of minds engaged in acts of communication and meaning. He
distinguishes between abstract and concrete identity, portraying dilemmas as abstract and
denying that there can be anything like a concrete contradiction or a real paradox. In this same
work intentional unity is made the basis for reconstructing the "identity" of the separate
disciplines of religion and philosophy, history and science – his earliest version of
rapprochement.

In Speculum Mentis Collingwood says his "mea culpas" for his neglect of the implicit-
explicit distinction of his earlier work and then surveys the same territory with a dialectical
instrument forged from linguistic variations in the various "forms of experience" - wherein the
object of knowledge is expressed metaphorically (art), assertively (religion), as abstract universal
generalizations (science) or as narrative statements of concrete matters of fact (history), each of
which generates its own dilemmas when seen from the point of view of "dogmatic" realistic
philosophy. He then assigns the proper role of philosophy as "absolute knowledge" to
"translation" into more adequate language, i.e. language free of systematic or misleading
(realistic) ambiguities. The Essay on Philosophical Method gives us an example of what that
language would look like (its classes would overlap and form a scale of forms, it would be
expressed in categorical propositions, etc.), and indicates that in philosophy the mutual cross-
justification of starting-point by conclusion and conclusion by starting point escapes vicious
circularity only by recognizing that knowing an object is not a total revelation but rather is
knowing better something which one already knows.

In The Principles of Art and The New Leviathan, language is located within a discursive
context of total bodily expression, and both works present higher levels of mental functioning as
a progressive structuring made possible by the practical extension of intentional meaning into
language and other symbolic expressive forms. This line of thinking reaches its apex in The Idea
of History, where Bradley's dilemma - reality as either subjective or objective - is resolved by
showing that the disjunction is false. Reality is both subjective and objective, because real
thinking has a double character: it is both immediate as embedded in a context of personal
consciousness, but is also mediate in that it is capable of being revived, repeated, or re-enacted as
the content of what is thought about.

When I look at this trajectory of his thought, what I see as a unifying theme is the
growing emphasis by Collingwood on the fundamental and irreducible activity of a person's
mind as a progressively contextualized engagement with meaning in such a way that everything
felt, attended to, imagined, represented, expressed, grasped, supposed, questioned, affirmed or
denied, enacted, re-enacted, narrated, explained, communicated, recommended, instituted,
legalized, and died for, is of the nature of inalienable human meaning, and never merely an
object unaffected and utterly separate from the acts of understanding which constitute the
knowing of it. I find this to be the founding insight of his "re-enactment" argument in the Idea
of History, where "meaning" is the only presumed sense in which two minds can think the same
thought or the same mind think a thought two times in succession or continuously through time.
If that mind-mind re-interpretation of the act-object distinction based on meaning and the fact
and ideal of inter-personal communication is taken as paradigmatic for all other kinds of thought,
we have a strategy for escaping between the horns of some of the autobiographical paradoxes.
And to these we must now turn.

The first dilemma whose horns we are trying to avoid is the idealism-realism controversy.
In particular we wish to know how it is possible to preserve the integrity of an act of knowing
such that it remains true both that an object is affected by the knowing of it (“made”), and the
knowing is affected by the object known (“found”) - in short, one in which both subjectivity and
objectivity are preserved. We need an act of knowledge in which the esse of mind is not merely
cogitare simply but de hac re cogitare

Idealism and realism both tend to pit knower against known, subject against object, as if
these are anything more than "false abstractions" or entities isolated from within the overall field
of total meaning - two fixed objects defined or imagined as confronting one another. We know
that this description fails in the mind-to-mind act-object situation, where subject and object are
unifiable and even reversible. What provides a common matrix for both situations is the concrete
world of meaning. When both poles of these oppositions – knower-known, subject-object - are
located within the horizon of meaning they are no longer disjunctive isolates. Therefore when
one asks how such knowledge is possible, it is only on condition that no object in its
presentational immediacy is so unaffected by the knowing of it that it lacks meaning altogether,
since if it did, it would be in principle inhumanly alien. Nothing touching a human has that
characteristic. Similarly no knowing act is so immune from the intrinsic meaning of its objects as
to be in principle unaffected by them by a failure of shared or re-enacted meaning.

In the scale of forms of knowledge, there is no zero-point on the scale, because the
generic essence that is successively exemplified and concretized is meaning as such. We are
coming to know better (refined meaning) what we in some sense already know (presentational,
uninterpreted, pre-reflective meaning), not creating what we know ex nihilo. But the reverse
situation is also true: no act of knowledge is so independent of the object known that it cannot be
determined in its meaning by the object: the esse of mind is not simply cogitare but de hac re
cogitare. Meaning escapes between the horns of the dilemma insofar as it is an object of
knowledge that is both found and made.

The second autobiographical dilemma concerns Q-A logic as an alternative to formal


logic, and here again the dilemma is resolved by recognizing that, as Mink11 and van der Dussen
pointed out,12 what Collingwood was proposing was not a "logic" at all, at least not in the form
of a mechanical process of relating formal entities like propositions to one another in an
inferential fashion and not as related to human reasoning. “Logic” is part of an essentially
human enterprise of the sort more recently entitled "hermeneutics" or interpretation theory, with
its characteristic emphasis on human understanding, the primacy of textual and contextual
meaning, the "hermeneutic circle," and the historical rootedness of the acts of interpretation.

In his later writings Collingwood increasingly emphasized the linguistic component of


the act of knowing. He locates it within the global range of activities of a personal, active,
knowing mind. This puts him in the company of like-minded philosophers like Gadamer13 and
Ricoeur14 who have argued for a hermeneutic solution to the problems of philosophy, where

11
Louis O. Mink, Mind, History, and Dialectic: The Philosophy of R.G. Collingwood (Bloomington, Indiana
University Press, 1969), 131.
12
Jan van der Dussen, History as a Science: The Philosophy of R.G. Collingwood (The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers, 1981), 296.
13
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics, translated and edited by David E Linge (Berkeley, University
of California Press, 1976). It is interesting to note that Gadamer explicitly credits Collingwood as "almost the only
person I find a link with" concerning question and answer logic and historicity: Truth and Method (New York, The
Continuum Publishing Company, 1993), 370.
14
Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth, The Texas Christian
University Press, 1976).
forms of experience, categorical acts of knowing and the like are viewed as part of a
hermeneutical “horizon of meaning.”

The issue here has to do with the degree of engagement of a mental agent, a thinking
person, with the subject matter he or she is trying to understand. To the extent that it is an on-
going inquiry, the subject is actively involved and utilizes a wide range of intellectual tools,
some of which may include operations with minimal need for contextual reconstruction - e.g.
employing established formal logic or mathematics. Seen in that light, formal logic and even the
sort of dialectical logic that Collingwood works out in the Essay on Philosophical Method, are
tools taken up by understanding for the interpretation of meaning which engages the mind in the
form of questions, problems, puzzles, paradoxes, contradictions - in short, meaning-conflicts or
tears in the fabric of discourse which understanding is challenged to repair.15 But in such cases it
is still the inquiring agent who is responsible for carrying out such operations - picking up the
tool or putting it down - asking and answering these sorts of questions at any point in the inquiry.
There simply is no inquiry without an inquirer.

This answers the second dilemma: Q-A logic is not really "logic" at all, it is a form of
hermeneutics focused on the meaning of whatever "text" requires understanding, and assuming
that both the knower and the known are part of an overall context of meaning. Formal logic and
dialectical logic are both basic linguistic tools that we employ to achieve the understanding we
seek within the questioning process. They are only as "automatic" as we allow them to be, since
we grasp them for the handiness they have in dealing with the meaningful world as logically
structured. Q-A logic is unintelligible and inconsistent as an alternative to formal-propositional
logic, but not as a hermeneutic methodology of an understanding agent.

We are on less secure grounds on the third and fourth autobiographical themes – the
philosophy of history and rapprochement, but we can see an escape route between the horns of
the absolutist-relativist dilemma posed by the Essay on Metaphysics by suggesting a more
flexible meaning for "absolute presuppositions." If an absolute presupposition rather than being
a quasi-propositional entity in a formal system is regarded as an orienting concept for a knowing
subject's placement within the horizon of meaning of a systematic inquiry, the dilemma is
resolvable.

I say "resolvable" rather than "resolved" because there are aspects of the ontology and
epistemology of this placement which are still problematic. It is still not clear what sort of entity
an absolute presupposition is, or what overall status it has concerning knowledge acts, or even if
it is a really describable in such terms at all. Concerning history as a concrete endeavor, the issue

15
In an experimental essay Collingwood goes so far as to say that the basic function of understanding is "seeing
continuities." Reality as History, dated December, 1935 (PH, 184).
is critical. The philosophical problem is with providing an ontological anchor or grounding for
locating any such historical interpretative act of understanding, or in epistemological terms
establishing an actual "reference" which has intrinsic connection with the possible "meaning" or
"sense" or "thought" corresponding to it. Using other clues that Collingwood leaves, one might
describe absolute presuppositions as pre-assertive entities functioning as orientational anchors
for some entire process or sequence of understanding, establishing what will ultimately count as
a meaningful answer to questions within that inquiry. But that grounding must be historically
rooted, for without it two people would not be able to share in the same inquiry, and the same
person would not be able to consistently pursue it over time.

Here Collingwoodians may find helpful the recent work in what he calls "cognitive
science" by the American philosopher, John Searle.16 Searle describes meaning as the name we
give the practical act of imposing intentionality on an expressive but plastic medium like
language (speech acts or some other symbolic system). Just as intentionality is the directedness
of mind to an object, speech acts are a representation of intentional mental acts. Each intentional
state with a "direction of fit" has conditions of satisfaction. Searle describes only a "mind-to-
world" or a "world-to-mind" or "null" directions of fit, which fails to capture what Collingwood
would call the "mind-to-mind" direction of fit. We wonder if Searle would regard absolute
presuppositions as having a "null direction of fit," which would require metaphysical analysis to
determine its "conditions of satisfaction."

Finally, what is not clear in all this is the overall context within which one or any number
of minds could be said to have achieved a final reconciliation overcoming the paradox of their
estrangement from one another or even an estrangement within the same mind between various
forms of experience understood as intersecting horizons of meaning.

This brings us directly up against the fourth and final autobiographical dilemma. Here
Collingwood's treatment of absolute knowledge as a form of translation is interesting, as is the
issue of the circularity of interpreting the part in terms of the whole and the whole in terms of the
part - the "hermeneutic circle." Seeing the meaning of the part in terms of the meaning of the
whole and the meaning of the whole in terms of the meaning of the part is only not circular
insofar as in each of these movements - from part to whole and back again - involves shifting
one's location between them within the horizon of meaning, and in the process get to understand
better that which we already know. Is it possible, then, that reconciliation is this circular weaving
process by human understanding, restoring the continuity in a torn fabric of meaning? And is it
possible that there could be a “space of perspectives” (Collingwood’s version of the “fusion of

16
John Searle, The Philosophy of Mind (The Teaching Company, Springfield, 1998), Lecture Nine: How to Study
Consciousness Scientifically.
horizons”) between persons such that further questions are unnecessary, as expressed in a
language free of systematic errors? 17

Here again we would like to follow up on a fertile suggestion by John Searle. Searle
argues that a science of mind or intentionality requires an explicit acknowledgement that any
particular intention (and a forteriori its expressed meaning in language) is not understandable as
an atomic or isolated unit, but rather requires a large number of other such intentions in a context
he calls "holistic."18 I believe this is precisely what Collingwood was describing in The New
Leviathan when he wrote about the "context of evocations" within which acts of intellectual
abstraction occur (NL, 7.32-7.33). By relocation of a meaning in its originative context of
evocations we restore the part to its context in the whole, and this is a question-and-answer
process.

If achieving an "absolute standpoint" requires that there be a final end to this process, it
would seem that for Collingwood, this is not possible. All that one can aim for is the continuing
efforts at "translation" uniting people of intelligence and good will. How would one know when
this is successful? Only by engaging in further acts of meaningful communication, to see what
questions arise. But in doing so, one must be willing to be surprised by what happens next -
when object-meanings shape further acts of knowledge and understanding.

So even if it is still incomplete, the evidence seems to me to be persuasive that for


Collingwood, reconciliational philosophy is achieved by a hermeneutic approach to experience.
If this is so, we have solved the last of the Collingwoodian dilemmas. It is easy to find texts of
Collingwood where he appears as either a relativist or an absolutist, but in the end he escapes
between the horns, because the goal of his philosophy was to repair the torn fabric of meaning
wherever it occurs. One does not know where such discontinuities occur until questions arise;
and when these questions take the form of a dilemma, philosophical rapprochement is necessary.

4. Conclusion: Collingwood for the 21st Century.

In this paper we have attempted to review how Collingwood’s autobiographical self-


interpretation holds up to his actual practice as illustrated by his handling of philosophical
dilemmas in his published writings. We have found that what the evidence reveals is contrary to
what we might expect from a literal reading of the Autobiography. His treatment of dilemmas
follows traditional modes of philosophical argumentation, and does not reveal the marks of Q-A

17
Collingwood uses the term "perspective" in the manner that hermeneutics uses "horizon," and in several passages
he makes reference to the historian's "space of perspectives" and "the problem of relation between perspectives" -
see EPH, 53-56 and PH, 128-29.
18
Searle, Ibid.
logic as he describes it. And there is no final resolution or rapprochement between realism and
idealism, nor is there an explicit absolute presupposition to serve as a context to resolve the
controversy.

But careful attention to his treatment of dilemmas also reveals a subtle direction to his
thinking that is recognizable to anyone familiar with the continental philosophical movement
known today as “hermeneutics.” Without carrying this analysis forward beyond the themes of
the Autobiography, we have suggested that this approach may help to resolve many if not all of
the dilemmas that Collingwood has left as part of his own legacy to the next generation of
philosophers.

So I suggest that the way to pull Robin George Collingwood through the 20th century
speculum and into the 21st century, to satisfy our present need for a philosophy, is to further
explore and expand the unifying aspect of this hermeneutic dimension of his thought. In so
doing we may be able to complete the reconciliation that he left as part of his unfinished
heritage.

Chicago, June 24, 2001

*An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Collingwood Conference held at St.
Catherine’s, Oxford in July of 2001. It was subsequently revised and published in the journal,
Collingwood and British Idealism Studies,
A Review of
Collingwood’s Essay on Metaphysics – 1998 Revised Edition.
Edited with Introduction by Rex Martin

by Glenn Shipley

A. The Reviewer’s Job.

It is the duty of a book reviewer not only to provide the reader with a preliminary
overview of what he will encounter upon reading the actual text, but to recommend, forewarn,
or even suggest restructuring the reader’s engagement with that text. In what follows I wish to
be clear that this new edition of the Essay on Metaphysicsi is an important publishing event for
students of Collingwood, and I wish to express my respect and gratitude to Rex Martin for the
scholarly work he has done in preparing it for the reading public. For reasons that will become
plain, however, I hope to caution the reader about relying too heavily on the introductory essay
as a guide to what follows. In the sequel I will recommend a different order for reading the text,
which I believe makes the work more approachable than it is in its present form.
Two further remarks about the scope of this review. Rather than embark on an overview
of the entire Essay on Metaphysics, we will focus on the newer material of the Revised Edition,
and to its Editor’s Introduction. Secondly, since even a casual reader of Collingwood’s Essay on
Metaphysics is aware that its two central issues are absolute presuppositions as the primary
subject matter of metaphysics, and the claim that metaphysics is an historical science, in what
follows we will concentrate on these two issues and what Martin wants us to understand about
them.

B. What OUP Hath Wrought.

In issuing a revised and expanded version of the Essay on Metaphysics (EM2), the
delegates of Oxford University Press (OUP) have continued the tradition of both honoring and
obscuring the late, great Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy, R.G. Collingwood.
They do so by publishing and keeping his original works in print, while simultaneously adding
further layers of interpretative mystique to his intellectual legacy.
In the present case, the delegates have utilized the services of a well-qualified editor, Rex
Martin, who not only presents new and previously unpublished material to the interested public,
but also offers an interpretation that adds both light and shadows to the portrait of Collingwood’s
legacy. Thus the delegates have continued what was begun a half-century ago, when T.M. Knox
was chosen to edit the manuscripts that were subsequently published as The Idea of History and
The Idea of Nature, and now continues with The Principles of History. These works have
greatly expanded Collingwood’s influence and made available works that have continued to
enlighten, delight, and perplex several generations of readers. So also the Essay on Metaphysics
in its expanded form offers a view of metaphysics that is well on its way to becoming a classic in
its own right, but is overlaid with an interpretation by its editor that is itself not free of
controversy.ii

The bulk of this new edition is still the whole of the original published text of the Essay
on Metaphysics with a few corrections, some of which were indicated by Collingwood in his
own marked copy of the published work. Readers familiar with the original work will find the
same set of topics in the same order: a general overview of the nature of metaphysical study,
beginning with Aristotle; the rejection of metaphysics as an ontology of pure being; metaphysics
as an inquiry concerning the absolute presuppositions of science; inquiry as the exercise of
question-and-answer (Q-A) logic; the reform of metaphysics as an historical science; positivism
and psychology as self-refuting forms of anti-metaphysics; and three specimens of metaphysical
analysis. As in the original, there is no detailed analysis of Bradley’s Appearance and Reality,
practically no discussion of Hegel (8 page references compared to 46 for Kant), no discussion of
mind and its relation to nature (as in the conclusions to his lectures on the subject in 1934, 1935,
and 1937),iii and no explicit connection to his other writings - neither to earlier works like
Religion and Philosophy and Speculum Mentis, nor to the mature positions he had staked out in
the Essay on Philosophical Method and The Principles of Art and the lectures which
subsequently formed the basis for the posthumous publications, The Idea of History and The
Idea of Nature.
Some of these issues are addressed in wholly new materials added to the original text.
Bracketing this text are a 103-page section at the beginning, including Martin's 4-page Preface
and 57-page Editor’s Introduction with notes and a bibliography, and at the end a section which
includes a valuable and accurate set of notes about the composition and publishing history of the
original book. This 84-page “Endnotes” section includes previously unpublished texts,
interspersed with Martin’s helpful comments: "The Nature of Metaphysical Study” (NMS); and
“Function of Metaphysics in Civilization” (F) - the former being the second of two lectures
Collingwood delivered “opening a course of 16 lectures on metaphysics by various speakers, to
be delivered 15 and 17 January, 1934” – five years before completing the manuscript of the
Essay on Metaphysics (April, 1939), and the latter a lecture delivered in 1938. It also includes
the complete letter of A.D. Lindsay, which resulted in Collingwood’s remarkable footnote on p
48 about conceptual change. Martin handles all of this material in a manner which displays his
craftsmanship and respect for the subject matter and its author.
But while the reader is grateful for the appearance of all this new material, one cannot
help but wonder about the peculiar bundling that seems to be occuring. While there was a strong
need for an editorial introduction when the original Idea of History was published because
Collingwood did not live to see this work through the press, this is not true for the Essay on
Metaphysics, which he finished in 1938 and regarded as a complete work (EM2, xviii). Treating
the completed Essay on Metaphysics as if it were an unfinished work requiring additional
materials and an extensive introduction like The Idea of History may thus prove misleading to
the reader.
So in spite of Martin’s explanation (EM2, lxviii) the reader is still curious about the
justification for the choice of materials included in this expanded edition – just as he was puzzled
about Knox’s choices for IH and IN. For example in the “Endnotes” section Martin includes a
wonderful essay entitled “The Nature of Metaphysical Study,” containing an interesting analysis
of F.H. Bradley’s Appearance and Reality, which Collingwood apparently studied with some
care. But then Martin teases the reader (in “A note on provenance” – pp. 376-78) with the
remark that “Bradley’s philosophical contribution is elaborated at greater length in another of
[Collingwood’s] unpublished manuscripts, entitled ‘The Metaphysics of F. H. Bradley: An
Essay on Appearance and Reality’ (dated Christmas, 1933).” As in the case of Knox’s selection
of a completely unsatisfying conclusion to The Idea of Nature, one wonders why Martin agreed
to publish this essay on Bradley, and not the evidently more thorough one from 1933 – or better
yet, both of them. And one wonders why the Delegates of OUP agreed to couple the two
conclusion to Collingwood’s lectures on Nature and Mind with their publication of The
Principles of History rather than a revised edition of The Idea of Nature or perhaps even a
separate volume consisting of these and other of Collingwood’s unpublished manuscripts.iv

C. What Rex Martin Hath Wrought


The answer to some of the questions about selection and omission of textual materials is
addressed by the editors of the posthumous publications. Increasingly it appears to lie not with
Collingwood’s instructions and wishes, but with considerations of editorial interpretation. In
sections 2-6 of his introductory essay to this new edition of the Essay on Metaphysics Martin
struggles with the same difficulty manifested by most other Collingwood scholars: how to
separate what is properly said about the issues that Collingwood was addressing from what is
specified in Collingwood's own presentation of those issues during his productive lifetime. With
respect to the former, one is free to say whatever a commentator is prepared to defend; with
respect to the latter, the reader requires convincing evidence from the texts, and the interpreter is
(or should be) bound by the rules of responsible interpretation.v
And herein lies the interpreter’s field of battle. Where many less cautious commentators
would have tripped over one of the many land mines that Collingwood has left in the war zone of
his later writings, Martin skillfully and bravely rises to the occasion by offering an interpretation
which makes use of Collingwood’s own roadmaps rather than the far riskier plan of using a
ready-made one provided by continental or analytic philosophy, or an antiquated one left by
Hegel or even Croce, or one designed for an entirely alien territory by Ryle or Wittgenstein (or
Nietzsche). Martin is further to be commended for prudently choosing as his primary guide the
Essay on Philosophical Method, which Collingwood himself called his best book and the only
one he had time to finish as well as he knew how (A, 118), and one which he clearly intended (at
least at one time) as a companion piece to the Essay on Metaphysics.
But that does not mean that Martin emerges from the minefield unscathed – that would be
expecting too much. One would have a better chance finding a formula for lasting peace in the
Balkans. Martin even risks scholarly life and limb by including previously unpublished
manuscripts, parts of which are in direct conflict with the interpretation he is offering – thereby
virtually ensuring that he will return from the frontlines, bandaged and limping from assorted
injuries.
Also to his credit, Martin’s Introduction exhibits both a sincere effort to present the
precise details of the composition of the materials subsequently published as the Essay on
Metaphysics, but also an interesting set of observations about the issues Collingwood was
addressing, and suggestions for what approach the reader can take for assimilating that material.
After (1) an enlightening initial section discussing how EM came to be written, Martin devotes
four sections to the topics respectively of (2) absolute presuppositions (APs), (3) metaphysics as
an historical science, (4) the character of metaphysics (as displaying the structure of science as a
scale of overlapping forms), and (5) the tasks of metaphysics (assessing comparative scientific
progress). A final section (6) is devoted to a detailed analysis of Collingwood’s discussion of
causation. Of the three examples of metaphysical analysis offered by Collingwood in EM,
Martin calls the section on causation the only true example of present day metaphysical thinking
(EM2, liv), and so it is the only one for which he offers a commentary.
If I understand him correctly, Martin wants to soften some of the harsher statements
about these primary concerns presented in EM by overlaying them with an interpretation which
isolates Collingwood’s theory of absolute presuppositions from his radical exposition of
question and answer logic (Q-A logic), and separates the concept of metaphysics as an historical
science from the procedure of historical re-enactment.
With respect to the former, Martin convincingly argues that until the appearance of the
Autobiography there is no evidence that Collingwood linked APs to Q-A complexes or to an
organized Q-A logic, even though the concept and function of APs have a much longer history in
Collingwood’s writings – a history independent of the Q-A logic he espoused in both A and EM.
This later radical linkage of APs to Q-A complexes, in fact, would render them not only true-
false neutral, but also meaningless.
With respect to the latter (metaphysics as historical but not as the exercise of re-
enactment), Martin argues that re-enactment only properly applies to deliberate human actions,
whereas APs (as somewhat “unconscious” entities) are not really actions in the true sense of the
term. APs are best understood in the light of the doctrine of a “scale of forms” which
Collingwood had worked out in the Essay on Philosophical Method. In such a scale the higher
forms incorporate and exemplify the lower forms in such a way that differences in kind are
inseparable from differences in degree, so that a constellation of APs at its higher
implementation – in a body of scientific inquiry – will not only differ qualitatively from its lower
manifestations (as Newtonian science differs from Aristotelian, or Copernican astronomy differs
from Ptolomaic), but will also be more adequately what the lower form was inadequately.
Martin links this view of APs with a treatment of historical understanding which views
the object of history not as a spectacle of isolated events and evidence, but as activity or a
process of cumulative development (EM2, xxv). Since history is concerned with processes
(activities) which exhibit such a cumulative development, APs can change and be subject to
analysis which demonstrates their increasing adequacy – and hence, in some sense, their “truth.”
This, Martin argues, allows Collingwood to claim that metaphysics is an historical science
without abandoning its aspect as criteriological. But Martin asserts that Collingwood is not
saying that what a metaphysician is doing is to engage in what he had in IH famously called “re-
enactment”. Martin goes so far as to say that “the idea of reading re-enactment into
Collingwood’s account of metaphysics is largely off the point” (EM2, xxxi, repeated at xxxii).
Minimizing this particular historical dimension to metaphysical thinking would allow one to
maintain the criteriological or normative aspect of metaphysics as philosophy, and thereby avoid
the “demons of scepticism and relativism” that so horrified Knox (EM2, liii, repeated at liv).
D. Problems with What Rex Martin Hath Wrought.
It is at this point that the reader may become suspicious. Encouraged by Collingwood to
turn to original sources to check for oneself if the criticisms are valid, one finds that in his
Preface to the first edition of the Idea of History Knox repeatedly charges Collingwood with the
twin problems of scepticism and dogmatism (IH, xi, xv, xvii, and xix). While the third issue of
"relativism" is raised by Knox (IH1, xiii), Martin assumes the linkage to "skepticism," as if
equating, for Knox, dogmatism with relativism. In the preface to IH1, Knox cites Collingwood’s
admonition to adopt an attitude of “unquestioning acceptance” toward APs, which Knox argues
is a surrender to the dogmatic strain in Collingwood’s philosophy present ever since his youthful
composition of works like Religion and Philosophy. Furthermore the quality of APs as neither
true nor false signaled for Knox the sceptical side, since it denied there was any criterion for
deciding the truth or falsity at the very foundations of scientific inquiry.
Now this might appear as a trivial mis-emphasis on Martin’s part, but it heightens the
attentiveness of the cautious reader, and it is not the only problem I encountered with the Editor's
Introduction. My overall discomfort has to do with the proper limits of responsible
interpretation. There is no problem with finding alternative approaches to the subject matter in
EM, and surely there is merit in Martin’s suggestion that the reader approach the issue of
metaphysics as the science of absolute presuppositions without paying undue deference either to
its controversial “question-and-answer (Q-A) logic” or to the kind of historical thinking specified
by Collingwood in his discussion of historical "re-enactment." But it is another thing altogether
to say that these recommendations conform to Collingwood's settled view of the matter. As we
shall see, they are particularly difficult assertions in view of Collingwood’s explicit statements
that re-enactment is the very condition of the possibility for historical thinking to take place at all
(so that removing re-enactment would completely eviscerate high-grade historical thinking), and
that the metaphysician cannot evaluate one system of APs as better than another.
Now it would be hard to charge Martin with failing to understand either Collingwood’s
Q-A logic or his analysis of history as an exercise of imaginative re-enactment, given not only
Martin’s familiarity with all the published and unpublished manuscripts but also his careful
analysis of re-enactment in his book, Historical Explanation: Re-Enactment and Practical
Inference. Nonetheless, given the entire body of Collingwood’s work as published to date, his
solution is still open to question. As representative of Collingwood’s currently published
thought, Martin’s suggested reinterpretations appear puzzling at best, and perhaps ultimately
insupportable.
(1) Meaning and Truth in Q-A Logic. Martin correctly argues that by identifying APs as
non-propositional insofar as they are defined only by means of the P-Q-A complex in Q-A logic,
APs not only lose the ability to be true or false, but also lose their meaning. The problem here is
that Martin fails to call the reader’s attention to the subtle shift in the two extant versions of Q-A
logic - as presented “for the first time” in the Autobiography (Q-AA) and Q-A logic as it appears
in the Essay on Metaphysics (Q-AM). In point of fact there are significant differences between
these versions, not the least of which has to do with the very issue Martin raises. The reader
approaching the present work without having first read the Autobiography would find Martin’s
assertion puzzling, since it is only in Q-AA that the P-Q-A complex is declared to be the unit not
only of truth, but of meaning and validity (contradiction). In the quasi-axiomatic presentation of
Q-A logic in the Essay on Metaphysics there is no mention at all of the P-Q-A complex as being
the minimal unit of meaning and logical validity.vi
This is no small matter, since the whole purpose of Martin’s separation of APs from Q-A
logic is to avoid the situation in which an AP would not only be T-F neutral but also
meaningless. If it should turn out that Collingwood could successfully maintain by means of a
Q-A logic that an AP could both be T-F neutral but yet retain meaning, there would be little
point in this aspect of Martin’s reconstruction.
(2) Absolute Presuppositions Not A Priori Concepts. Martin flatly rejects the
interpretation of the truth-neutral property of APs as being due to their status as a priori concepts
rather than propositions (EM2, xxvii) - in spite of the fact that there is fairly widespread
agreement by many Collingwood interpreters on this pointvii. There is no convincing argument or
counter-evidence to demonstrate this assertion.viii Certainly no one expects that all bases can be
covered in a 100-page introduction, but this is another key issue concerning the status of APs
and metaphysics, so it can reasonably be expected that it would be rigorously defended.
Furthermore two of the three examples that Collingwood examines in EM, Part III,
suggest that APs are conceptual entities. The concepts Collingwood examines are God,
causality, and the principles Kant discusses in the transcendental analytic section of the first
Critique. Of these Martin chooses only to consider the concept of causality in his Introduction,
claiming that of those examples proposed, only Collingwood’s analysis of causality is an
example of contemporary metaphysics. Whereas Collingwood is proposing all of these concepts
as specimens of metaphysical analysis, no satisfying argument is offered for Martin’s restriction
of these topics to causality alone. Would not a discussion of the Kantian principles have
solidified his argument that APs are proposition-like entities rather than concepts?
(3) Absolute Presuppositions and the Scale of Forms. It is ironic that while Alan
Donagan totally neglects definition by means of a scale of forms (SF) in discussing APs,
Martin’s tendency is to go to the other extreme. On the grounds that the expression “scale of
forms” nowhere occurs in EM, but occurs 20 times in Martin’s Introduction to EM2, one might
be forgiven for leaning towards Donagan on this issue. Martin wishes to dissociate the Q-A
logical treatment that Collingwood offers in EM by substituting for it a definition of APs by
means of SF, without sufficient recognition that in EPM the discussion of the SF occurs in the
context of the traditional epistemological structure of concept-judgement-implication (paralleling
the logical term-proposition-inference schema) of the whole of EPM, and occurs in the section
that deals with concepts or terms, not judgements or propositions. In other words, a SF applies
to philosophical concepts that are contrasted with classes – not primarily to whole theories,
which are more at the level of a complex of propositions related in a scientific exposition.ix
(4) The subject matter of re-enactment. Martin asserts that re-enactment is restricted to
actions of agents, and is not properly applied to beliefs per se (EM2, xxxi). But this ignores the
fact that in IH Collingwood’s prime example of historical re-enactment is an axiom of Euclid’s
geometry (IH 284-85). Now one might argue that Collingwood’s examples are not always
felicitous, but that does not explain why he would choose such an example if the application of
the principle he was trying to explore fell entirely outside its province. It would be hard to
portray an axiom of geometry as the action of an agent in Martin’s restricted sense, and not a
“belief.”
Martin leaves the reader a huge escape-hatch when he later asserts that “unless absolute
presuppositions are actions or can be the more or less direct effects of actions… there is little
point in making re-enactment the focal point of any Collingwoodian assimilation of metaphysics
to history” (EM2, xxxii). Little point, that is, unless one were to take into account that for
Collingwood all thought is action or the result of action (cf. NL, 1.61-1.66, 5.91, 6.19) – even
so-called “unconscious” thought, and that Collingwood argued that re-enactment is the very
condition that makes all historical thought possible (IH, 282).
But even if he were right on this matter, there would then be little point in Martin’s
equating metaphysics qua historical understanding with APs , since even on his own grounds
“mind-as-thought… is completely involved in process” (EM2, xxxv). So if one were to accept
Martin’s approach to them, APs would have to be mental entities, therefore involved in
processes, therefore activities of subjects, and therefore historically re-enactable. Other writers
have confirmed such a linkage, particularly in connection with the mental activity of language.
For example, David Boucher quotes from Collingwood’s “Observations on Language” (an
unpublished mss) that: “language is a mode of conduct, an activity;” that meaning is an essential
attribute of language as activity; and that words have no meaning except as used in context by a
speaker (SPTC, 137). Further, Peter Lewis points out that “For Collingwood and Wittgenstein,
language is characterized, first and foremost, by activity” (CS V, 35). Is it Martin’s position that
APs are not mental, not meaning, and not linguistic? And if he admits that they are, must he not
also admit that they are actions, and as such re-enactable by historical understanding?
(5) Process and progress: Not only in the original EM but also in “The Nature of
Metaphysical Study” which Martin includes in the Endnotes of EM2, Collingwood explicitly
denies that a metaphysician can show that one school of science or one metaphysical system
(presumably of APs) can be demonstrated to be “better” than another (EM, 52-53; EM2, 389-
94). Martin notes this as a “discontinuity” with the later published work (EM2, lxxiv), but the
bridging argument that he offers fails to make the link between the two senses of “right” that
Collingwood proposes for an AP - as a fitting description of what someone actually presupposes
in their thinking, and as one that is better than another as a description of what a superior science
presupposes over its predecessor on a scale of forms. Failing this, how can Collingwood, much
less Martin, successfully defend that metaphysics is normative or criteriological? It appears to
be capable of historical reportage only.
To secure this point, we need to take a minute to examine what Collingwood actually has
to say about the matter in the “Function of Metaphysics in Civilization” (EM2, 379-420). “The
question will certainly be asked, whether, even so, one kind of metaphysical system may not be
better than another,” Collingwood writes, and then sets out two stages in answering the question.
In the first (the intuitionist approach, which would claim to answer it by simply inspecting them
to see which of the two is better), he argues that in such a comparison there is no real standard,x
since the metaphysician is incapable of standing on a neutral ground where both appear equally
inspectable. “Working on this assumption” (he writes) “I can see no way of answering the
question definitely….” (EM2, 391-2). In the second alternative he presents the case as one of
choice: “deciding which of two things is the better is the same as choosing between them.” But
in this form the question is meaningless, since “It could have meaning only if there were
somebody who had before him the option of pursuing whichever kind of science he chose.
There is no such person. The question which kind of science is the better, therefore, is a
nonsense question because to ask it presupposes the existence of a situation which does not
exist.” Collingwood goes on in the same passage to say that it is meaningless to ask which
metaphysics is intrinsically better than the other, the Aristotelian pluralistic metaphysics or the
Kantian monistic metaphysics – as it is meaningless to ask if the system of science resulting from
them, or even the sciences themselves, are better than the other. (EM2, 393-94).
Whether or not one accepts this argument as valid (and I do not),xi nevertheless to this
reader, this passage and one’s similar to it in the original EM represents an immovable obstacle
to Martin’s recommended re-interpretation of Collingwood’s agenda for metaphysics as an
historical science – i.e. as a non-re-enactable, analytic, historical study of the “processes” of AP
transformation, viewed as a progressive scale of forms. It is a wonderful recommendation, but it
simply goes beyond Collingwood’s last words on the subject as we have them.
D. Rending Asunder What Rex Martin Hath Wrought.
Martin addresses some of these issues in the last section of the Introduction, where he
offers a detailed commentary on the unpublished mss which form the Endnotes section of EM2.
By then, the credulity of anyone familiar with Collingwood’s published writings has been
stretched to the breaking point. I suggest, therefore, that readers approach EM2 in an order
different than the one Martin and OUP have presented. To this reviewer, given the problems with
Martin’s Introduction outlined above, it makes more sense to read EM2 in the following order:
1. Martin’s Introduction, Section 1: The Composition of the Essay on Metaphysics (pp.
xv-xxi).
2. Martin’s Endnote A: The publishing history of the Essay on Metaphysics (pp. 344-
48); Endnote B: Emendations made by Collingwood himself (pp. 348-50); and
Endnote C: A Letter from A.D. Lindsay (pp. 350-55).
3. Collingwood’s Essay on Metaphysics (the original published text).
4. The three unpublished pieces by Collingwood.
5. Martin’s Introduction, Sections 2 through 7.
The reason for this suggested rearrangement is that Martin’s thesis makes a great deal
more sense (even if problems remain about accepting it as final) after first understanding how
EM came to be written, then reading the work itself, and then seeing how it appears in the
context of Collingwood’s other works in progress on the same issues. Finally, it is only after
surveying all this material that one can reach conclusions even remotely similar to those Martin
proposes – just as Martin himself did. He cannot spare the reader’s discomfort with this
difficult-to-assimilate work by predigesting it in his Introduction – it simply does not work.
I would also recommend that the reader spend some time reading over the two
conclusions to the lectures on nature and mind, presently published with The Principles of
History.
Finally, I offer this as a personal concluding note: it seems to me that, like
Collingwood’s experience of the Albert Memorial, there remains something irreducible and yet
indigestible about the set of ideas represented in the Essay on Metaphysics. In it Collingwood
recognized that, just as in a work of art, there is something trope-like about the relationship of
APs and the science based on them, but he had difficulty analyzing and expressing that
relationship. His account of them on the basis of Q-A logic appears to be as close as he came to
expressing the insight that an AP is bound in a logical and unifying way to an entire body of
propositions in a scientific inquiry, but is yet itself non-propositional. But while the suggestion
to amplify this relationship in terms of a scale of forms may add significantly to the
understanding of it, simply assimilating APs to this somewhat abstract and still-obscure doctrine
from EPM does not succeed in accounting for it or even adequately expressing it. A complete
discussion of APs would require locating them not only in a logical frame of reference (and
perhaps more than one, since Collingwood recognized not only formal logic but also dialectical
and Q-A logics), but also in a schema which displays their status and structure as ontological,
epistemological and psychological entities.
It also seems to me that Collingwood recognized metaphysics as a unique form of inquiry
which has links both to Aristotle’s “First Philosophy” and to a more contemporary view of
historical understanding (which requires a radical reformation of the original subject matter), and
that the object of this inquiry is a kind of presupposition not affirmed in any conventional or
conditional manner, but held “absolutely” in some sense of that much-maligned word. But to
divorce this understanding from the sort of thinking characterized by Collingwood as re-
enactment is to remove the very process of thought by which a metaphysician would assimilate
the subject for himself.
What this metaphysical inquiry actually is – even after the sixty years since the Essay on
Metaphysics first appeared – remains inadequately described and unsatisfactorily explained.
i
In this review the generally accepted abbreviations are used for Collingwood’s published writings and those of
his major interpreters. An exception is EM2, which I propose for the Revised Edition of the Essay on
Metaphysics in order to distinguish it from the first edition. On the same basis I also suggest IH2 for the revised
edition of the Idea of History, particularly important since IH2 omits Knox’s original Preface and adds an
Introduction by Jan van der Dussen. In addition to these abbreviations, Q-A stands for Question and Answer,
and AP for Absolute Presupposition. FRTR refers to From Realism To Rapprochement: The Autobiographical
Interpretation of Collingwood’s Philosophy – my 1983 doctoral dissertation at Loyola University of Chicago,
available free of charge to anyone who asks for it (send email to glennshipley@comcast.net or
sophologist@poetic.com ).
ii
By comparing Rex Martin’s Introduction with the Preface by T.M. Knox to The Idea of History, I do not mean
to attribute to Martin the same sort of misunderstanding, bias and irrelevancy that Knox imposed on
Collingwood studies.

David Boucher, “The Principles of History and the Cosmology Conclusion to the Idea of Nature,”
iii

Collingwood Studies II (Swansea, 1995), p. 152.

In their introductions to the works in question, Martin, Dray and van der Dussen address the problem of the
iv

unpublished mss and provide reasons for including the manuscripts that they did. The question I am raising has
more to do with exclusions and overall organization of textual materials in their present arrangement.
v
I assembled a set of these in my dissertation, FRTR, Chapter I, pp. 44-46.
vi
Shipley, FRTR, Chapter II, table 3 and pp. 84-89; Chapter VIII, table 9, and pp. 430-458.

Cf. Mink, MHD, 144-48; Rubinoff, CRM, 234-35; Toulmin in Krausz, CEPC, 205-08; and Shipley, FRTR,
vii

802, n 10.

Later in the Introduction (EM2, lxxv) , Martin does make the point that APs are “assertion-like” entities, and
viii

he also acknowledges something like an a priori status for them inasmuch as they are adopted independently of
experience. But I do not see where he presents any argument or evidence against the position that as “non-
propositional” and as mental entities, APs might actually be something closer in structure and function to
concepts (which have discernible meanings, but are not appropriately called propositionally true or false) than
they are to judgements. Furthermore as “descriptive” framework entities, regarding APs as definable concepts
rather than as verifiable propositions or judgements, seems to point in that direction.
ix
In fairness to Martin, at EM2, xl, he does examine the issue of whether there are limits or modifications that
must be made when applying a SF as a definition of an AP. But even as articulated in this discussion, I do not
see how it can escape Collingwood’s own restriction on the non-comparability of various systems of APs.
x
Collingwood makes a similar case against Sir W.D. Ross concerning a scale of forms of goods, on the grounds
that they lack a common standard for measurement. See Boucher, EPP, 34.
xi
The reason I do not is because a de facto lack of instantiation does not resolve a de jure issue of principle.
Collingwood has not demonstrated that it is not possible for someone to choose which science he engages in. To
say, as Martin does, "That is not the way things happen" (EM2, xlviii) fails to wring the withers of someone who
might argue that there is nothing preventing it. In fact it would be hard to understand how science could
significantly change if for someone the process was not stipulatively determined. When Newton wrote the
Principia he was not merely reflecting how the science of his day was done, he was saying how it ought to be
done and providing an instance of it.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen