Sie sind auf Seite 1von 23

Meister Eckhart

First published Wed Jan 4, 2006; substantive revision Mon Apr 25, 2011
Education and culture were the two driving forces behind European urban development in the
13th and 14th centuries. Among the mendicant orders that had settled in the cities were the
Dominicans (ordo fratrum praedicatorum), dedicated to promoting in their teaching, way of life,
and preaching the ideal of mans self-discoveryself-cultivationas a singular cultural value.
The dynamics of this self-discovery can be said to be two-fold. For, on one hand, man discovers
himself by liberating himself from himself and therewith findingin himselfwhat transcends
him. On the other hand, what man finds in himself displays its own movement as all that remains
when his self-discovery has reached its end. In this developmental context, Meister Eckhart
directed his theoretical analysis towards elucidating the self-movement of intellect as such, in its
differentiation, as a movement representing in practical terms the only possible form of life.
Indeed, in this era of radical social upheaval, Eckhart put forward the dynamics of intellect
(reason, rationality) as the genuine wealth possessed by those who are poor in spirit. His
philosophical formulations and theological statements served, in their reciprocal convergence, to
unfold in theoretical terms the dynamics of intellect with a view to recommending the practice of
processive reason as the exemplary form of life. Eckhart explained these dynamics mostly on the
basis of texts from the Holy Scriptures, whose philosophical content he set out through
philosophical argumentssomething he was able to do because he regarded the Holy Scriptures
as a work of philosophy (cf. Echardus, In Ioh. n. 444; LW III, 380, 1214: evangelium
contemplatur ens in quantum ens: the Gospel treats of being insofar as it is beingAristotle,
as was well known, having defined the object of metaphysics in precisely this manner). Yet
Eckharts explanations of these dynamics were also based on philosophical theses closely linked
to notions from the Holy Scriptures. In both cases, he claimed to give unreserved expression to
the new and rare (nova et rara) in propagating what was for him the only possible form of life:
that of processive reason or of processes directed by reason. In so doing, Meister Eckhart
dedicated his life to philosophy: as a philosopher holding a chair of theology at the University of
Paris, as a philosopher leading the Dominican Order, and as a philosopher occupying the
preachers pulpit.

1. Life of Meister Eckhart

2. Works

3. Dietrich of Freiberg and Meister Eckhart

4. The Absolute Principle as Intellect without Being

5. Univocal Causality

6. One as Unity

7. Conclusion

Bibliography

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Life of Meister Eckhart


Eckhart was born in 1260 in Hochheim (Thuringia). He entered the Dominican Order quite early,
and received most of his education in the Studium Generale in Cologne that Albert the Great had
founded in 1248. In 1286 Eckhart went to Paris to study. From 1294 until 1298, he was Prior of
the Convent of Erfurt, at the same time carrying out the office of Vicar of Thuringia. Eckhart was
promoted to Master of Theology at Paris in 1302 and taught as Professor there in the academic
year 1302/1303. He was elected Provincial of the newly founded Province of Saxony in 1303,
and held this office until 1311. In 1307 Eckhart also took over the administration of the Province
of Bohemia as Vicar General. When the Provincial Chapter of the Province of Teutonia elected
him Provincial in 1310, the election was not accepted by the General Chapter in Naples (1311).
Instead, Eckhart was sent once more to Paris. After teaching there for a second period, Eckhart
went to Strasbourg in 1313, where from 1314 to 1322 he was increasingly active as a preacher
caring for Dominican convents there. From 1323 on, Eckhart resided in Cologne, most likely at
the Studium Generale, and probably as Lecturer. During this time, the campaigns against him
began that led, in 1326, to the opening of an inquisitional proceeding. In its course Eckhart
submitted a reply to the syllabus of errors attributed to him, protesting as well against the
proceeding itself, which was then continued at the Papal Court in Avignon. It resulted in the
papal bull In agro dominico from Pope John XXII, issued on March 27, 1329, condemning 17
articles from this syllabus as heretical and 11 more as suspect of heresy. Eckhart, however, did
not live to see his condemnation; he died sometime before April 30, 1328probably on January
28, 1328, possibly in Avignon.

2. Works
At the beginning of the academic year 1293/94 Eckhart held an inaugural lecture (Collatio in
libros Sententiarum) that has been preserved. An academic sermon, the Sermo Paschalis a. 1294
Parisius habitus and the Tractatus super oratione dominica date from the same time. Between
1294 and 1298 Eckhart composed his Instructional Talks (Die rede der underscheidunge), tabletalks for his confratres in the Erfurt monastery. From his first teaching period in Paris (1302/03)
come the Quaestiones (Quaestio Parisiensis I, II and the rationes Equardi from one of the
disputed questions of Gonsalvus Hispanus), as well as the Sermo die beati Augustini Parisius
habitus, a feast-day sermon in honor of Augustine (August 18, 1302 or February 28, 1303), and

perhaps two other Quaestiones. Between 1303 and 1310, during a General Chapter, Eckhart held
the Sermones on Ecclesiastics 24: 2327a and 24: 27b31. In 1305 he began composing the
Opus tripartitum, his major work, comprising three parts: the Opus propositionum (Work of
Theses), with over 1,000 theses in 14 treatises, the Opus quaestionum (Work of Problems) and
the Opus expositionum (Work of Interpretations). Much of the Opus tripartitum remained
incomplete. What we have are the Prologus generalis in opus tripartitum, the Prologus in opus
propositionum, the Prologus in opus expositionum I and II, and various commentaries (above all
the Expositio sancti evangelii secundum Iohannem). Also preserved is an Opus sermonum
containing drafts of Latin sermons. From the Strasbourg and Cologne period come the treatise
Daz buoch der goetlchen troestunge and the sermon Von dem edeln menschen. (The authenticity
of the treatise Von abegescheidenheit has been disputed in the past, but it has been recently
accepted once more as a work of Eckhart.) The most important German sermons also go back to
this last period. Among these is Predigt 52, which due to its extremely innovative content was
later translated from Middle High German into Latin.

3. Dietrich of Freiberg and Meister Eckhart


Of all those following in the tradition of Albert the Great who developed theories of the intellect
in the 13th and 14th centuries, Dietrich of Freiberg went the furthest. In treating of the active
intellect (intellectus agens), Dietrich identified a three-fold object, which, however, the intellect
knows in a single intuition (uno intuitu): its principle (deus), its essence (essentia) and the
totality of beings (universitas entium). According to Dietrich, the intellect knows its essence and
all beings not only according to its essence, but also in its principle, according to the mode of
this very principle (in suo principio secundum modum ipsius principii; cf. Dietrich of Freiberg,
De intellectu et intelligibili II 3740, ed. Mojsisch, 1977, pp. 17577). This mode of knowing is
the highest that we can identify. Before Dietrich, no one had formulated this mode of knowing in
such a progressive manner by making such a radical claim. Nevertheless, Dietrich did not further
elaborate how to think this mode of knowing in its individual moments, that is, the way the
intellect actually knows in its principle, according to the mode of this very principle.
Meister Eckhart begins where Dietrich of Freiberg leaves off. Nowhere in his writings does
Eckhart mention Dietrich by name, although they were personally acquainted, and although
Dietrich used his influence to see that Eckhart received significant posts within the Dominican
Order. Yet Eckhart goes a step beyond Dietrich by expanding upon what Dietrich had given only
general expression to, unfolding how the intellect actually moves in itself and therewith
demonstrating what it means for the intellect to know according to the mode of this very
principle. Briefly put, understanding how the intellect returns to its principle, where it might
know according to the mode of its principle, requires that we first identify the way in which
this principle itself knows, so that we might then grasp how the intellect comes to know there.

4. The Absolute Principle as Intellect without Being


In the initial stage of his career, Meister Eckhart composed some not very exciting table-talks for
his confratres and, in his lost Commentary on the Sentences (Goris/Pikav, 2001), most likely
advocated doctrines based on the theology of Thomas Aquinas. Once back in Paris, however,

Eckhart inaugurated his teaching with a bombshell. With a new thesis directed against Thomas
Aquinas, as well as against his own Thomistic thinking prior to 1302, Eckhart contends that the
absolute principle (or the absolute cause: God) is pure intellect and not being. According to this
view, being (esse) is always caused and thus presupposes intellect, itself without being, as the
cause of being. In line with Neoplatonic modes of thinking (cf. Liber de causis, cap. XI;
Fidora/Niederberger, 2001, 76: Causatum ergo in causa est per modum causae : What is
caused is in the cause in the mode of the cause ), Eckhart holds that being is, in intellect,
nothing other than intellect and, therefore, not simply being, but instead being that has been
elevated to intellect. If someone should nonetheless object that in God knowing or anything else
might be described as being, the proper response for Eckhart is that this being still
presupposes the knowing of intellect (Et si tu intelligere velis vocare esse, placet mihi. Dico
nihilominus, quod, si in deo est aliquid, quod velis vocare esse, sibi competit per intelligere:
And if you wish to call intelligizing being, that is all right with me. Nonetheless, I say that if
there is something in God that you wish to call being, it suits him through intelligizing; cf.
Echardus de Hochheim, Utrum in deo sit idem esse et intelligere n. 24, ed. Mojsisch, 1999, 192,
103105). As the absolute cause, intellect is thought of as absolutely unlimited only if it is
thought of as wholly without being. As such, intellect becomes the principle for absolute as well
as contingent being. The alternative viewthat knowing is simply identical with being (a
position advanced by Sturlese, 1993a and von Perger, 1997 and again, with new argumentation,
by Grotz, 2002)disregards the more sweeping contention in Eckharts thesis that knowing is
presupposed in every case of being. (Later, Nicholas of Cusa maintains accordingly that the
maximum is without being, yet can be contracted to being; cf. Nicholas of Cusa, De docta
ignorantia I, 6, ed. Hoffmann/Klibansky, 1932a, p. 14, 1: Praeterea, contrahamus maximum ad
esse et dicamus : Besides, we might contract the maximum to being and say ) Scholars
such as Klibansky, however, as well as Imbach, 1976 have drawn attention to parallel passages in
the German sermons that make it clear that for Eckhart absolute knowing is without being,
indeed, that intellection is prior to being.

5. Univocal Causality
Between the uncreated and the created the predominant relationship is one of analogy, a
relationship involving as well the disjunction of the two terms. Insofar as Eckhart in 1305 again
takes up the theme of absolute being in its identity with God (esse est deus), he likewise gives
expression to relationships of analogical causality, teaching that being as such, or absolute being
(esse absolute), is what becomes restricted to determinate being (esse hoc et hoc), while
determinate being is what brings it about that a this or a that (hoc et hoc) actually exists. Eckhart
says ever again that the created is of itself pure nothing, indeed, even nothingness or nullity
(nihileitas, nulleitas). The created is only because absolute being communicates itself to it
through determinate beingwhereby determinate being, of course, is not in any position to
communicate being as such, but only determinacy. That all of this is so, of course, is something
that can be easily stated. Indeed, the metaphysics of being has always thrived on describing such
structures, whether this being be absolute or determinate in nature.
Eckhart, however, breaks through that metaphysics of being with its analogical base by thinking
through the relation of causality informing absolute being. We can assume at least hypothetically
that a cause causes not only something dependent on it, but also something equal to it, namely

that the cause causes in such a manner that it causes itself. But if it causes itself, it causes
something which is itself also cause and at the same time cause of its cause. Such a mode of
causality is called univocal causality. Our hypothesis of what could be thought in these terms
turns into a certainty when we explore the structures of intellectual causality, for example, the
relation between the act of thinking and what is thought, or between an ethical principle and an
ethical principiate. Their relation is precisely what Eckhart takes advantage of in developing his
theory of univocal causality. In these cases, it holds that the principle causes its principiate, and
the principiate causes its principle. Even more: The principiate is in its principle nothing other
than its principle. This means that the active (principle) is at the same time active and passive,
being affected in the course of its activity (as principle). In turn, the passive (principiate) is at the
same time passive and active, being active in the course of its passivity (as principiate).
Accordingly, a central proposition of Eckhart reads as follows: [Principium et principiatum]
opponuntur relative: in quantum opponuntur, distinguuntur, sed in quantum relative, mutuo se
ponunt (Echardus, In Ioh. n. 197; LW III, 166, 1012: [The principle and the principiate]
are opposed to one another relatively: Insofar as they are opposed, they are distinguished, but
insofar as they are relative, they reciprocally posit themselves ).
The breakthrough that Eckhart attains through his theory of univocal causality is exemplified by
the relation between thinking and thought. For Eckhart, thinking presupposes no origin because a
presupposed origin could only be thought by thinking and hence would be a thought of thinking,
that is, itself thinking. Thinking is, then, for itself a presuppositionless origin, that is, it is its own
principle: principium (Echardus, In Ioh. n. 38; LW III, 32, 11: ipsum principium semper est
intellectus purus : The principle itself is always pure intellect ). Any thinking without act,
however, is no thinking at all. Consequently, its own originative activity accrues to thinking, that
is, insofar as it is a principle, the dynamics of its principiating: principiare. In this activity,
however, thinking directs itself towards a thought that it has originated, that is, towards the
product that is its principiate: principiatum. But since this thought is a thought of thinking, it is
itself nothing other than thinking. The act of this thinking that has been thought is, then,
retrograde. This thought, as thinking, is in turn principle, principiating and principiate, whereby
this last is the original thinking. In this way, thinking thinks itself as thought and is therewith
active thinking, while thought, insofar as it thinks its thinking, is itself thinking, and its thinking
now thought. Consequently, both thinking and thought are at the same time active and passive.
Another example of univocal causality as conceived by Eckhart is found in the relation between
justice and the just man. In the same vein as that sketched out with regard to the dynamics of
thinking, justice is in the just man, and the just man is in justice. The just man is his just action,
and this just action is likewise justice. Between the just man and justice, there is difference on
account of the opposition between them, but because of their relationality they reciprocally
include each other. Just as thought is the thought of thinking and therewith itself thinking, so,
too, is what is just for Eckhart what is just of justice and therewith justice itself. From this we
can draw, following Eckhart, a number of important conclusions.
A. For the just man, there is no why to his just action, no purpose or goal of this action. For the
action of the just man has justice as its goal, and this goal is identical with the just man.
Therefore, the just man has no goal external to himself. Instead, as justice, he is his own goal.

B. With the just man and with justice, there is no multiplicity. Justice is one, and the just man is
one; thus, justice and the just man are one. Even if there are many just men: As just men, the
many just men are one (Echardus, In Sap. n. 44; LW II, 366, 67: omnes iusti, in quantum
iusti, unum sunt ), indeed, they are even justice itself.
C. Justice, which is the just man, knows neither where nor when, that is, it knows neither space
nor time, neither size nor quality, neither inside nor outside, neither over nor under, neither this
side nor that side, neither above nor below, neither the activity of effecting nor the passivity of
being effected. Hence, justice is indeterminate and does not accrue to anything else as an
accident. Justice is something whose purpose lies in itself.
D. Consequently, the just man is in justice, which means: The just man is justice. This implies a
reversal of the usual way of looking at things. Normally, a quality (qualitas) is what is found in
an underlying subject (subiectum). With the spiritual perfections (perfectiones spirituales),
however, the situation is different: The subjects are in the perfections, the just man is in justice.
But in the realm of the spirit, being-in is nothing other than being-one. Hence, the just man, who
is in justice, is justice itself. The just man does not possess justice, but rather is justice. Similarly,
he who is free is freedom itself (Echardus, Predigt 28; DW II, 62, 35; cf. Predigt 10; DW I,
165, 2: und ich diu wsheit selber bin, s bin ich ein wser mensche; what applies in the
cases of freedom and justice also applies in the case of wisdom). If he who is free merely
possessed freedom, then this freedom would be something external to him, and he would never
be freedom itself.
What is key is that by freedom Eckhart understands nothing other than self-consciousness or the
I. It is never the case that the I wants something other, rather it wants only itself; the I never
knows something other, rather it knows only itself; the I is never open for anything other, rather
it is open for itself alone. Thus, the I is both cause of itself and conceives itself alone in itself.
The itself known and wanted by the I, as well as defining its fundamental openness, is the other I
that is, the moment of self-relationality constitutive for the realm of the spirit.
E. In summary, Eckhart can say: in spiritualibus conceptio est ipsa parturitio sive partus
(Echardus, In Exod. n. 207; LW II, 174, 34): In the realm of the spirit, conceiving is bearing or
giving birthand therefore (passive) suffering is (active) production. It should be noted that the
motif of birth is one of Eckharts favorites, for example, when he holds that the divine Father
bears his Son in the soul, more precisely: in the ground of the soul, and in this way he bears me
as himself and himself as me. This motif, however, is not limited to theological contexts. It also
finds application as a philosophical motif. Here, again, it is necessary to become accustomed to
Eckharts usage. Where others speak of causing or principiating, Eckhart speaks of
bearing. This kind of language must be approached carefully, however, and demands close
scrutiny now more than ever. Such a hermeneutical approach is currently favored especially by
Largier, Hasebrink and Kbele.
F. Swer underscheit verstt von gerehticheit und von gerehtem, der verstt allez, daz ich sage
(Echardus, Predigt 6; DW I, 105, 23): Whoever understands the theory of justice and the just
man understands everything that I am saying. With this statement, Eckhart commends to our
attention the paradigm of univocal co-relationality in the just man and justice. On one hand, this

paradigm composes the precondition for that analogical thinking that informs, among other
things, the relation of the uncreated and the created. While Wilde, 2000 asserts, then, that
univocal causality is subsumed in analogical causality, Eckharts theory is exactly the opposite.
On the other hand, however, the paradigm of univocal causality refers to what, in line with
Eckhart, must still be made thematic because, as what is first, it cannot be put into question: the
one as unity.

6. One as Unity
The goal of the rational form of lifeof living in and with the spiritual perfections at the level of
that transcendental being or being (esse, ens) convertible with the termini transcendentes (the
one, the true, and the good)is living in and from the absolute one (in and from the divine
nature as presuppositionless unity). If the ground of the soul, as something uncreated and
uncreatableattributes which Meister Eckharts contemporary Eckhart von Grndig explicitly
ascribes to the ground or little spark of the soul that Meister Eckhart often invokes (cf. Winkler,
1999), thus indicating that he in fact employed these attributesif human reasonnot as human,
but as reasonis one with the divine nature or ground (Echardus, Predigt 5b; DW I, 90, 8: Hie
ist gotes grunt mn grunt und mn grunt gotes grunt: Here, Gods ground is my ground and my
ground Gods ground), then man is no longer simply on the way towards unity (unio). Instead,
unity is something that has always already been achieved. This being-unified is alone what
matters (Echardus, Predigt 12; DW I, 197, 89; Predigt 39; DW II, 265, 6266, 2), because man
as reason has left behind everything that stands in the way of his living in and from unity, and
because the ground of the soul is more interior in this unity than it is in itself (Mojsisch 1983a,
140141; 2001, 163165). This is true equanimityletting-go (Gelzenheit)as the goal of
human life.
Living in and from unity in the manner envisioned by Eckhart as the end of self-discovery
becomes possible through a change (metabole) in intellectual disposition. The possible intellect
which, as defined by Aristotle, can become all things (cf. De anima III 5, 430a1415)is able
to know either as ordinary consciousness (in images, species of things) or as self-consciousness
through self-knowledge (without images, free from images). The conversion in disposition
Plato speaks of a peristrophe of the soul (cf. Res publica VII, 521c5)leads the possible intellect
to the uncreated and uncreatable ground of the soul, whose movement, as a process of reason,
reaches its goal in the absolute one (unialiter unum, a combination suggested by Proclus; Eckhart
speaks of the luter pur clar Ein or indistinctum, the undifferentiated). This goal, however, is itself
nothing other than the ground of the soul. The ground of the soul in the absolute one is its own
goal because self-consciousness is nothing other than one and the one, because freedom is
nothing other than one and the one, because moral responsibility for oneself and othersEckhart
speaks of justiceis nothing other than one and the one. Self-consciousness, freedom and justice
are always and everywhere only themselves, having nothing outside of, additional or foreign to
them.
For Eckhart, this means that whoever is justice is always justice, because the I that would stand
out from justice would no longer be an I. The I always already knows that it is justice, however,
because in knowing itself as just, it knows itself as justice; for the just man is justice. The I
knows that it is just, however, because otherwise it does not know at all and is not even an I at

all. The I is what it is only as rationality, as a knowing which knows that it is and knows what it
is. This I is not only cause of itself (causa sui; Eckhart, deepening the tradition of this concept,
says sache mn selbes: cause of myself; cf. Summerell, 2002). It is moreover the cause for
God, insofar as God stands in relation to his creatures. For only the uncreated and uncreateable
ground of the soul stands not in relation to creatures, but instead only in relation to itself (cf.
Echardus, Predigt 52). The I that knows itself, wills itself, and is its own abode, and therewith
the I that is, in univocal causality, cause of itself and yet, in this unity, the one rationality, is,
according to Eckhart, what man ought to become and what man can become in taking on the true
poverty of spirit. This is so since man has always been this I, is now this I, and always will be
this I, even if he knows nothing of himself as this I.
Consequently, the movement of reason, as Eckhart presents it, takes its point of departure from
absolute unity and, as a principle, takes on being. This principle knows itself and wills itself,
thinking thought in this way as its principiate, the ground of the soul in its uncreatedness and
uncreatability. Since this thought is a thought of thinking, however, and thus itself thinking, this
thinking that has been thought principiates its own principle in retrograde fashion. (As Eckhart
puts it, the Son is reborn in the Father.) This movement of reason, as one of self-discovery and
self-cultivation, ends there, where it began, in presuppositionless unity, where it might begin
anew. This is the fundamental processtaking place in and from unityinherent to the selfknowing and self-willing I. Insofar as it knows itself and wills itself, this I is nothing other than
what man is when he has transcended himself as a creature fraught with nothingness and
entrusted himself to the movement of the ground of the soul, acknowledging this movement as
the sole form of life: that of self-consciousness, freedom, and moral responsibility.

7. Conclusion
Nicholas of Cusa, when asked what he had to say about Eckhart, remarked that he had never read
in Eckhart that the creature was identical with the creator. At the same time, he praised Eckharts
talent (ingenium) as well as his ardor (studium). Yet Nicholas also suggested that Eckharts books
should be removed from the public sphere, since they contained much that was astute and useful
(subtilita et utilia) for those who understood them, but the people were not ready for what, in
Eckhart, contradicted the traditional doctrines of the learned world.
Aiebat tamen praeceptor se numquam legisse ipsum sensisse creaturam esse creatorem, laudans
ingenium et studium ipsius; sed optavit, quod libri sui amoverentur de locis publicis, quia vulgus
non est aptus ad ea, quae praeter consuetudinem aliorum doctorum ipse saepe intermiscet, licet
per intelligentes multa subtilia et utilia in ipsis reperiantur. (Nicholas of Cusa, Apologia doctae
ignorantiae, ed. Klibansky, 1932b, p. 25, 712)
Still, the teacher said that he had never read that he [Eckhart] thought that the creature was the
creator, and praised his [Eckhart's] talent and ardor. Yet he wished that his [Eckhart's] books
would be removed from public places; for the people are not ready for what he [Eckhart] often
intersperses, contrary to the custom of other learned men, even though the intelligent find in
them many astute and useful things.

What Nicholas gave voice to is not simply the divide between medieval and modern thought, as
well as that between orthodoxy and unconventionality, that he himself most remarkably
straddled. In fact, it remains a challenge even today to properly understand the Eckhartian
thought that man is free only if he (not merely possesses but instead) is freedom. This is so, in
part, because even scholarly language runs up against its limits in Eckhart. For we still cannot
give adequate expression to the real meaning of the statement: The free man is, if he is really
free, freedom itself, yet only insofar as he is free. For this very reason, however, it is all the
more necessary to engage ourselves in Eckharts thinking instead of banning his writings from
the public sphere. For if our thought counsels it, our language must change, indeed, not only the
language of scholars, but that of the people as well.

Bibliography
A. Works by Meister Eckhart (Echardus de Hochheim)

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke, hrsg. im Auftrage der Deutschen
Forschungsgemeinschaft, Stuttgart 1936 sqq. (DW = Deutsche Werke; LW = Lateinische
Werke).

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die lateinischen Werke, Bd. I,2:
Prologi in Opus tripartitum et Expositio Libri Genesis (Recensio L), hrsg. von Loris
Sturlese, Stuttgart 1987, pp. 1128.

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die lateinischen Werke, Bd. II:
Indices, hrsg. von Loris Sturlese, Stuttgart 1992, pp. 641691.

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die lateinischen Werke, Bd. III:
Indices, hrsg. von Loris Sturlese, Stuttgart 1994, pp. 713763.

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die deutschen Werke, Bd. IV,1:
Meister Eckharts Predigten (Pr. 87105), hrsg. und bers. von Georg Steer unter Mitarb.
von Wolfgang Klimanek und Freimut Lser, Stuttgart 2003.

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die deutschen Werke, Bd. IV,2:
Meister Eckharts Predigten (Pr. 106117), hrsg. und bers. von Georg Steer unter Mitarb.
von Wolfgang Klimanek und Heidemarie Vogl, Stuttgart 2003.

Meister Eckhart, Die deutschen und lateinischen Werke. Die lateinischen Werke, Bd. V:
Sermo Paschalis a. 1294 Parisius habitus. Acta Echardiana, hrsg. von Loris Sturlese,
Stuttgart 1988, pp. 129240; Bd. V: Acta Echardiana. Mag. Echardi Responsio ad
Articulos sibi impositos de Scriptis et Dictis suis, hrsg. von Loris Sturlese, Stuttgart 2000,
pp. 241520.

Meister Eckhart, Werke I: Texte und bersetzungen von Josef Quint, hrsg. und
kommentiert von Niklaus Largier, (Bibliothek des Mittelalters. Texte und bersetzungen,
Bd. 20) Frankfurt a. M. 1993.

Meister Eckhart, Werke II: Texte und bersetzungen von Ernst Benz, Karl Christ, Bruno
Decker, Heribert Fischer, Bernhard Geyer, Josef Koch, Josef Quint, Konrad Wei und
Albert Zimmermann, hrsg. und kommentiert von Niklaus Largier, (Bibliothek des
Mittelalters. Texte und bersetzungen, Bd. 21) Frankfurt a. M. 1993.

Eckhart von Hochheim, Utrum in deo sit idem esse et intelligere? Sind in Gott Sein und
Erkennen miteinander identisch?, hrsg., bersetzt und mit einer Einleitung versehen von
Burkhard Mojsisch, in Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch fr Antike und Mittelalter
4/1999 (2000), pp. 179197.

Deutsche Mystiker des vierzehnten Jahrhunderts, hrsg. von Franz Pfeiffer, Leipzig 1857
(repr. Aalen 1962).

Magistri Eckardi Opera Latina, I: Super oratione dominica, ed. Raymundus Klibansky,
Lipsiae 1934.

Magistri Eckardi Opera Latina, II: Opus tripartitum: Prologi, ed. Hildebrandus Bascour
O.S.B., Lipsiae 1935.

Magistri Eckardi Opera Latina, XIII: Quaestiones Parisienses, ed. Antonius Dondaine
O.P., Commentariolum de Eckardi Magisterio adiunxit Raymundus Klibansky, Lipsiae
1936.

Kaeppeli, Thomas, Praedicator Monoculus. Sermons Parisiens de la Fin du XIIIe Sicle,


in Archivum Fratrum Praedicatorum 27 (1957), pp. 120167.

Meister Eckehart, Deutsche Predigten und Traktate, hrsg. und bersetzt von Josef Quint,
3. Aufl., Mnchen 1969.

Master Eckhart, Parisian Questions and Prologues, transl. with an Introduction and
Notes by Armand A. Maurer, Toronto 1974.

Meister Eckhart, Opere Tedesche, introduzione, traduzione e note di Marco Vannini,


(Classici della Filosofia, Bd. 14) Firenze 1982.

Brunner, Fernand/Libera, Alain de/Wber, douard /Zum Brunn, milie, Luvre latine
de Matre Eckhart, 1: Le Commentaire de la Gense prcd des Prologues, texte latin,
introduction, traduction et notes, Paris 1984.

Zum Brunn, milie/Libera, Alain de/Wber, douard, Luvre latine de Matre Eckhart,
6: Le Commentaire de lvangile selon Jean: Le Prologue (chap. 1, 118), texte latin,
avant-propos, traduction et notes, Paris 1989.

Matre Eckhart, Traits et Sermons, traduction, introduction, notes et index par Alain de
Libera, (Publi avec le concours du Centre national des Lettres) Paris 1993.

Mojster Eckhart, Pridige in traktati, v slovenino prevedli Milica Ka, Gorazd


Kocijani, Vid Snoj, Jani Virk, Janez Zupet, uredil Goradz Kocijani, Celje 1995.

Magistri Echardi, Opera Latina I, ed. and transl. (in Japanese) Yoshiki Nakayama, Tokyo
2005; II, Tokyo 2004; Sermones, Tokyo 1999.

Meister Eckhart, Das Buch der gttlichen Trstung. Vom edlen Menschen,
mittelhochdeutsch/neuhochdeutsch, bers. und mit einem Nachwort von K. Flasch,
Mnchen 2007.

Secondary Sources

Aertsen, J. A., 1992, Ontology and Henology in Medieval Philosophy (Thomas Aquinas,
Master Eckhart and Berthold of Moosburg), in E. P. Bos/P. A. Meijer (eds.), On Proclus
and his Influence in Medieval Philosophy, (Philosophia Antiqua. A Series of Studies on
Ancient Philosophy, Bd. 53) Leiden/New York/Kln, 1992, pp. 120140.

Albert, K., 1976, Meister Eckharts These vom Sein. Untersuchungen zur Metaphysik des
Opus Tripartitum, Saarbrcken/Kastellaun.

Altmeyer, Cl., 2005, Grund und Erkennen in deutschen Predigten von Meister Eckhart,
Wrzburg.

Asmuth, Chr., 1995, Meister Eckharts Buch der gttlichen Trstung, in M. J. F. M.


Hoenen/A. de Libera (eds.), Albertus Magnus und der Albertismus. Deutsche
philosophische Kultur des Mittelalters, Leiden/New York/Kln, 1995, pp. 189205.

, 2011, Bilder ber Bilder, Bilder ohne Bilder. Eine Neue Theorie der Bildlichkeit,
Darmstadt.

Beccarisi, A., 2003, Predigt 1: Intravit Iesus in templum, in Steer/Sturlese, 2003, pp. 1
27.

Beierwaltes, W., 1994, Primum est dives per se. Matre Eckhart et le Liber de
causis, in Zum Brunn, 1994, pp. 285300.

, 1998, Platonismus und Christentum, (Philosophische Abhandlungen, Bd. 73)


Frankfurt a. M.

Beriaschwili, M., 2001, Das einfache Eins-Werden des Menschen und Gottes bei
Meister Eckhart und Hegel, in Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch fr Antike und
Mittelalter 5/2000, pp. 7195.

Bray, N., 2004, Meister Eckhart e Dietrich di Freiberg nell' Opus Ior di Giordano di
Quedlinburg, in Giornale Critico della Filosofia Italiana 24, 1, pp. 3752.

, 2008, Auctoritates bibliche e Quaestiones dottrinali nell' Opus Tripartitum di


Eckhart e nella Summa theologiae di Tommaso d'Aquino, in A. Beccarisi/R. Imbach/P.
Porro (eds.), Per perscrutationem philosophicam. Neue Perspektiven der
mittelalterlichen Forschung, Loris Sturlese zum 60. Geburtstag gewidmet, Hamburg
2008, pp. 156183.

Caputo, J. D., 1975, The Nothingness of the Intellect in Meister Eckharts Parisian
Questions, in The Thomist 39, pp. 85115.

Casteigt, J., 2006, Connaissance et vrit chez Matre Eckhart. Seul le juste connat la
justice, (tudes de philosophie mdivale, Bd. 91) Paris.

Davies, O., 1990, Why were Eckharts Propositions Condemned?, in New Blackfriars
71, pp. 433444.

, 1988, God Within. The Mystical Tradition of Northern Europe, London.

, 1991, Meister Eckhart. Mystical Theologian, London.

Degenhardt, I., 1967, Studien zum Wandel des Eckhartbildes, (Studien zur
Problemgeschichte der antiken und mittelalterlichen Philosophie, Bd. III) Leiden.

Dietrich of Freiberg, 1977, De intellectu et intelligibili, in Opera omnia I, ed. B.


Mojsisch, Hamburg.

Enders, M., 1997, Die Reden der Unterweisung: eine Lehre vom richtigen Leben durch
einen guten und vollkommenen Willen, in Jacobi, 1997, pp. 6992.

Fidora, A. and Niederberger, A., 2001, Von Bagdad nach Toledo. Das Buch der
Ursachen und seine Rezeption im Mittelalter, lat.-deutscher Text, Kommentar und
Wirkungsgeschichte des Liber de causis. Mit einem Geleitwort von M. Lutz-Bachmann,
(excerpta classica 20) Mainz, 2001.

Flasch, K., 1974, Die Intention Meister Eckharts, in H. Rttges/Br. Scheer/J. Simon
(eds.), Sprache und Begriff. Festschrift fr Br. Liebrucks, Meisenheim a. Gl., 1974, pp.
292318.

(ed.), 1984, Von Meister Dietrich zu Meister Eckhart, (Corpus Philosophorum


Teutonicorum Medii Aevi. Beihefte, Bd. 2) Hamburg.

, 1986, Das philosophische Denken im Mittelalter. Von Augustin zu Machiavelli,


Stuttgart.

, 1987, Einfhrung in die Philosophie des Mittelalters, Darmstadt.

, 1988a, Meister Eckhart und die Deutsche Mystik Zur Kritik eines
historiographischen Schemas, in O. Pluta (ed.), Die Philosophie im 14. und 15.
Jahrhundert. In memoriam Konstanty Michalski (18791947), (Bochumer Studien zur
Philosophie, Bd. 10) Amsterdam, 1988, pp. 439463.

, 1988b, Meister Eckhart Versuch, ihn aus dem mystischen Strom zu retten, in P.
Koslowski (ed.), Gnosis und Mystik in der Geschichte der Philosophie, Darmstadt, 1988,
pp. 94110.

, 1998, Predigt 52: Beati pauperes spiritu, in Steer/Sturlese, 1998, pp. 163199.

, 2003, Predigt 6: Iusti vivent in aeternum, in Steer/Sturlese, 2003, pp. 2951.

, 2006, Meister Eckhart. Die Geburt der Deutschen Mystik aus dem Geist der
arabischen Philosophie, Mnchen.

, 2010, Meister Eckhart. Philosoph des Christentums, Mnchen.

Fhrer, M. L., 1999, The Agent Intellect in the Writings of Meister Dietrich of Freiberg
and its Influence on the Cologne School, in Kandler/Mojsisch/Stammktter, 1999, pp.
6988.

Frost, St., 2006, Nikolaus von Kues und Meister Eckhart. Rezeption im Spiegel der
Marginalien zum Opus tripartitum Meister Eckharts, (Beitrge zur Geschichte der
Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters. Neue Folge, Bd. 69) Mnster.

Goris, W., 1997, Einheit als Prinzip und Ziel. Versuch ber die Einheitsmetaphysik des
Opus Tripartitum Meister Eckharts, (Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des
Mittelalters, Bd. LIX) Leiden/New York/Kln.

, 1999, Dietrich von Freiberg und Meister Eckhart ber das Gute, in
Kandler/Mojsisch/Stammktter, 1999, pp. 169188.

, 2002, Der Mensch im Kreislauf des Seins. Vom Neuplatonismus zur


Subjektivitt bei Meister Eckhart, in Th. Kobusch/B. Mojsisch/O. F. Summerell (eds.),
Selbst Singularitt Subjektivitt. Vom Neuplatonismus zum Deutschen Idealismus,
Amsterdam/Philadelphia, 2002, pp. 185201.

, and Pickav, M., 2001, Von der Erkenntnis der Engel. Der Streit um die species
intelligibilis und eine quaestio aus dem anonymen Sentenzenkommentar in ms. Brgge,
Stadsbibliotheek 491, in Miscellanea Mediaevalia 28, pp. 125177.

Grotz, St., 2002, Meister Eckharts Pariser Quaestio I: Sein oder Nichtsein ist das hier
die Frage?, in Freiburger Zeitschrift fr Philosophie und Theologie 49, pp. 370398.

, 2009, Negationen des Absoluten: Meister Eckhart, Cusanus, Hegel, Hamburg.

Guerizoli, R., 2006, Die Verinnerlichung des Gttlichen. Eine Studie ber den
Gottesgeburtszyklus und die Armutspredigt Meister Eckharts, (Studien und Texte zur
Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Bd. 88) Leiden.

Haas, A. M., 1979, Sermo mysticus. Studien zu Theologie und Sprache der deutschen
Mystik, (Dokimion, Bd. 4) Freiburg/Schweiz.

, 2010, Der wise meister Eckhart. Zum 750. Geburtsjahr Meister Eckharts, in
Philotheos 10, pp. 170179.

Hackett, J. M., 1981, Verbum mentalis conceptio, in Miscellanea Mediaevalia 13, pp.
10031011.

Halfwassen, J., 1997, Gibt es eine Philosophie der Subjektivitt im Mittelalter? Zur
Theorie des Intellekts bei Meister Eckhart und Dietrich von Freiberg, in Theologie und
Philosophie 72, pp. 338360.

Hart, R. L., 1998, God and Creature in the Eternity and Time of Nonbeing (or Nothing):
Afterthinking Meister Eckhart, in O. F. Summerell (ed.), The Otherness of God, (Studies
in Religion and Culture) Charlottesville/London, 1998, pp. 3559.

Hasebrink, B., 1992a, Formen inzitativer Rede bei Meister Eckhart. Untersuchungen zur
literarischen Konzeption der deutschen Predigt, (Texte und Textgeschichte, Bd. 32)
Tbingen.

, 1992b, Grenzverschiebung. Zu Kongruenz und Differenz von Latein und Deutsch


bei Meister Eckhart, in Zeitschrift fr Deutsches Altertum 121, pp. 369398.

, 1994, Der Rebdorfer Eckhartkommentar. berlieferung und Kommentierung der


Armutspredigt Meister Eckharts in der Rebdorfer Handschrift Cgm 455, in Zeitschrift
fr Deutsche Philologie 113, pp. 207222.

, 1997, Meister Eckhart. Eine Skizze zu Leben und Werk, Mnchen.

Haug, W., 2004, Das platonische Erbe bei Meister Eckhart, in O. Hildebrand/Th. Pittrof
(eds.), auf klassischem Boden begeistert. Antike-Rezeptionen in der deutschen
Literatur. Festschrift fr J. Schmidt zum 65. Geburtstag, (Rombach Wissenschaften
Reihe Paradeigmata, Bd. 1) Freiburg i. Br., 2004, pp. 1735.

Hauke, R., 1986, Trinitt und Denken. Die Unterscheidung der Einheit von Gott und
Mensch bei Meister Eckhart, (Kontexte. Neue Beitrge zur Historischen und
Systematischen Theologie, Bd. 3) Frankfurt a. M./Bern/New York.

Imbach, R., 1976, DEUS EST INTELLIGERE. Das Verhltnis von Sein und Denken in
seiner Bedeutung fr das Gottesverstndnis bei Thomas von Aquin und in den Pariser
Quaestionen Meister Eckharts, (Studia Friburgensia, Neue Folge, Bd. 53)
Freiburg/Schweiz.

Ivnka, E. von, 1950, Apex mentis. Wanderung und Wandlung eines stoischen
Terminus, in Zeitschrift fr Katholische Theologie 72, pp. 129176.

Jacobi, Kl. (ed.), 1997, Meister Eckhart: Lebensstationen Redesituationen, (Quellen


und Forschungen zur Geschichte des Dominikanerordens. Neue Folge, Bd. 7) Berlin.

Kampmann, I., 1996, Ihr sollt der Sohn selber sein! Eine fundamentaltheologische
Studie zur Soteriologie Meister Eckharts, (Europische Hochschulschriften: Reihe 23,
Theologie, Bd. 579) Frankfurt a. M./Berlin/Bern/New York/Paris/Wien.

Kandler, K.-H., Mojsisch, B., and Stammktter, Fr.-B. (eds.), 1999, Dietrich von
Freiberg. Neue Perspektiven seiner Philosophie, Theologie und Naturwissenschaft,
(Bochumer Studien zur Philosophie, Bd. 28) Amsterdam/Philadelphia.

Kern, U., 2003, Gottes Sein ist mein Leben. Philosophische Brocken bei Meister
Eckhart, (Theologische Bibliothek Tpelmann, Bd. 121) Berlin/New York.

Kobusch, Th., 1986, Mystik als Metaphysik des moralischen Seins. Bemerkungen zur
spekulativen Ethik Meister Eckharts, in Ruh, 1986, pp. 4962.

Koch, J., 1973a, Kritische Studien zum Leben Meister Eckharts, in J. Koch, Kleine
Schriften, Bd. I, (Storia e Letteratura. Raccolta di Studi e Testi, Bd. 127) Roma, pp. 247
347.

, 1973b, Zur Analogielehre Meister Eckharts, in Koch, 1973a, pp. 367397.

Kbele, S., 1994, Bwort sn. Absolute Grammatik bei Meister Eckhart, in Zeitschrift
fr Deutsche Philologie 123, pp. 190206.

, 1998, Predigt 16b: Quasi vas auri solidum, in Steer/Sturlese, 1998, pp. 4374.

Langer, O., 1987, Mystische Erfahrung und spirituelle Theologie. Zu Meister Eckharts
Auseinandersetzung mit der Frauenfrmmigkeit seiner Zeit, (Mnchener Texte und
Untersuchungen zur Deutschen Literatur des Mittelalters, Bd. 91) Mnchen/Zrich.

Largier, N., 1989a, Bibliographie zu Meister Eckhart, Freiburg/Schweiz.

, 1989b, Zeit, Zeitlichkeit, Ewigkeit. Ein Aufriss des Zeitproblems bei Dietrich von
Freiberg und Meister Eckhart, (Deutsche Literatur von den Anfngen bis 1700)
Bern/Frankfurt a. M./New York/Paris.

, 1995a, intellectus in deum ascensus. Intellekttheoretische Auseinandersetzungen in


Texten der deutschen Mystik, in Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift fr Literaturwissenschaft
und Geistesgeschichte 69, pp. 423471.

, 1995b, Meister Eckhart. Perspektiven der Forschung, 19801993, in Zeitschrift


fr Deutsche Philologie 114, pp. 2998.

, 1997, Figurata Locutio. Hermeneutik und Philosophie bei Eckhart von Hochheim
und Heinrich Seuse, in Jacobi, 1997, pp. 303332.

, 1998a, Intellekttheorie, Hermeneutik und Allegorie. Subjekt und Subjektivitt bei


Meister Eckhart, in R. L. Fetz/R. Hagenbchle/P. Schulz (eds.), Geschichte und
Vorgeschichte der modernen Subjektivitt, Berlin/New York, 1998, pp. 460486.

, 1998b, Recent Work on Meister Eckhart. Positions, Problems, New Perspectives,


19901997, in Recherches de thologie et philosophie mdivales 65, 1, pp. 147167.

, 2003, Sermo XXV: Gratia dei sum id quod sum, in Steer/Sturlese, 2003, pp. 177
203.

Leppin, V., and Schiewer, H.-J. (eds.), 2007, Meister Eckhart aus theologischer Sicht,
(Meister-Eckhart-Jahrbuch, Bd. 1) Stuttgart.

Lerner, R. E., 1997, New Evidence for the Condemnation of Meister Eckhart, in
Speculum. A Journal of Medieval Studies 72, pp. 347366.

Libera, A. de, 1984, Introduction la Mystique Rhnane. DAlbert le Grand Matre


Eckhart, Paris.

, 1993, La philosophie mdivale, Paris.

, 1998, On some Philosophical Aspects of Master Eckharts Theology, in


Freiburger Zeitschrift fr Philosophie und Theologie 45, pp. 151168.

Lser, Fr., 1995, Der niht enwil und niht enweiz und niht enht. Drei bersehene Texte
Meister Eckharts zur Armutslehre, in Cl. Brinker/U. Herzog/N. Largier/P. Michel (eds.),
Contemplata aliis tradere. Studien zum Verhltnis von Literatur und Spiritualitt.
Festschrift fr A. M. Haas, Bern/Berlin/Frankfurt a. M./New York, 1995, pp. 391440.

, 1998, Predigt 19: Sta in porta domus domini, in Steer/Sturlese, 1998, pp. 117149.

Lser, Fr., 1999, Meister Eckhart in Melk. Studien zum Redaktor Lienhart Peuger. Mit
einer Edition des Traktats Von der sel wirdichait vnd aigenschafft, (Texte und
Textgeschichte, Bd. 48) Tbingen.

Manstetten, R., 1993, Esse est Deus. Meister Eckharts christologische Vershnung von
Philosophie und Religion und ihre Ursprnge in der Tradition des Abendlandes,
Freiburg/Mnchen.

Margreiter, R., 1997, Mystik zwischen Literalitt und Oralitt. Meister Eckhart und die
Theorie medialer Noetik, in Jacobi, 1997, pp. 1542.

McGinn, B., 1994, Meister Eckhart and the Beguine Mystics: Hadewijch of Brabant,
Mechthild of Magdeburg and Marguerite Porete, New York.

, 2001, The Mystical Thought of Meister Eckhart. The Man from Whom God Hid
Nothing, New York.

, 2003, Sermo XXIX: Deus unus est, in Steer/Sturlese, 2003, pp. 205232.

Mieth, D., 1969, Die Einheit von Vita activa und Vita contemplativa in den deutschen
Predigten und Traktaten Meister Eckharts und bei Johannes Tauler. Untersuchungen zur
Struktur christlichen Lebens, (Studien zur Geschichte der katholischen Moraltheologie,
Bd. 15) Regensburg.

, 2004, Meister Eckhart Mystik und Lebenskunst, Dsseldorf.

Miethke, J., 2009, Der Eckhartprozess in Kln und Avignon, in A. Rigon/F. Veronese
(eds.), L'et dei processi, inchieste e condanne tra politica e ideologia nel '300 , Roma,
2009, pp. 119143.

Mojsisch, B., 1983a, Meister Eckhart. Analogie, Univozitt und Einheit, Hamburg.

, 1983b, Meister Eckharts Kritik der teleologisch-theokratischen Ethik Augustins,


in Medioevo. Rivista di storia della filosofia medievale 9, pp. 4359.

, 1986, Dynamik der Vernunft bei Dietrich von Freiberg und Meister Eckhart, in
Ruh, 1986, pp. 135144.

, 1987, Causa essentialis bei Dietrich von Freiberg und Meister Eckhart, in
Flasch, 1987, pp. 106114.

, 1991, Nichts und Negation. Meister Eckhart und Nikolaus von Kues, in B.
Mojsisch/O. Pluta (eds.), Historia Philosophiae Medii Aevi. Studien zur Geschichte der
Philosophie des Mittelalters. Festschrift fr K. Flasch zum 60. Geburtstag, Bd. II,
Amsterdam/Philadelphia, 1991, pp. 675693.

, 1996, Ce moi: la conception du moi de matre Eckhart. Une contribution aux


Lumires du Moyen-Age, in Revue des sciences religieuses 70, pp. 1830.

, 1997, Die neuplatonische Theorie der Selbstverurschlichung (causa sui) in der


Philosophie des Mittelalters, in L. G. Benakis (ed.), Noplatonisme et philosophie
mdivale, Turnhout, 1997, pp. 2533.

, 2001a, Meister Eckhart. Analogy, Univocity and Unity, transl. with a preface and an
appendix by O. F. Summerell, Amsterdam/Philadelphia.

, 2001b, Notiz Eckhart von Hochheim, in Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch


fr Antike und Mittelalter 6/2000, p. 239.

, 2003a, Der Grund der Seele. Das Ich als Ursache seiner selbst und Gottes in der
Philosophie Meister Eckharts, in G. Binder/B. Effe/R. F. Glei (eds.), Gottmenschen.
Konzepte existentieller Grenzberschreitung im Altertum, (Bochumer
Altertumswissenschaftliches Colloquium, Bd. 55) Trier, 2003, pp. 181203.

, 2003b, Perfectiones spirituales Meister Eckharts Theorie der geistigen


Vollkommenheiten. Mit possibilittsphilosophischen Reflexionen, in M. Pickav (ed.),
Die Logik des Transzendentalen, Festschrift fr Jan A. Aertsen zum 65. Geburtstag,
(Miscellanea Mediaevalia, Bd. 30) Berlin/New York, 2003, pp. 511524.

, 2009, Nulla e negazione. Meister Eckhart e Niccol Cusano, in M. Lenzi/A. Maier


(eds.), Discussioni sul nulla tra medioevo ed et moderna, (Lessico Intellettuale Europeo,
Bd. CIV) Firenze 2009, pp. 195210.

, 2010, Meister Eckhart. Analogie, Univozitt und Einheit, transl. (in Korean) by
Sang-Sup Lee, Seoul.

Nicholas of Cusa, 1932a, De docta ignorantia, ed. E. Hoffmann/R. Klibansky, Leipzig.

, 1932b, Apologia doctae ignorantiae, ed. R. Klibansky, Leipzig.

Panzig, E. A., 2005, Gelzenheit und abegescheidenheit. Eine Einfhrung in das


theologische Denken des Meister Eckhart, Leipzig.

Pekta, V., 2006, Mystique et Philosophie. Grunt, abgrunt et Ungrund chez Matre
Eckhart et Jacob Bhme, (Bochumer Studien zur Philosophie, Bd. 45)
Amsterdam/Philadelphia.

Perger, M. von, 1997, Disputatio in Eckharts frhen Pariser Qustionen und als
Predigtmotiv, in Jacobi, 1997, pp. 115148.

Quero-Snchez, A., 2004, Sein als Freiheit: Die idealistische Metaphysik Meister
Eckharts und Johann Gottlieb Fichtes, (Symposion. Philosophische Schriftenreihe, Bd.
121) Freiburg/Mnchen.

, and Steer, G. (eds.), 2008, Meister Eckharts Straburger Jahrzehnt, (MeisterEckhart-Jahrbuch, Bd. 2) Stuttgart.

Reiter, P., 1993, Der Seele Grund. Meister Eckhart und die Tradition der Seelenlehre,
Wrzburg.

Ruh, K. (ed.), 1985, Meister Eckhart. Theologe, Prediger, Mystiker, Mnchen.

, 1986, Abendlndische Mystik im Mittelalter. Symposion Kloster Engelberg 1984,


(Germanistische Symposien. Berichtsbnde, Bd. VII) Stuttgart.

, 1996, Geschichte der abendlndischen Mystik, Bd. III: Die Mystik des deutschen
Predigerordens und ihre Grundlegung durch die Hochscholastik, Mnchen.

Schirpenbach, M. P., 2004, Wirklichkeit als Beziehung. Das strukturontologische Schema


der Termini generales im Opus Tripartitum Meister Eckharts, (Beitrge zur Geschichte
der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters. Neue Folge, Bd. 66) Mnster.

Schoeller, D., 1992, Gottesgeburt und Selbstbewusstsein. Denken der Einheit bei Meister
Eckhart und G. W. F. Hegel, (Philosophie und Religion. Schriftenreihe des
Forschungsinstituts fr Philosophie Hannover, Bd. 4) Hildesheim/Berlin.

Schnberger, R., 2000, Meister Eckhart. Denken und Innewerden des Einen, in Th.
Kobusch (ed.), Philosophen des Mittelalters. Eine Einfhrung, Darmstadt, pp. 202219.

Schrmann, R., 1978, Meister Eckhart. Mystic and Philosopher, Bloomington/London.

Schwaetzer, H., and Steer, G. (eds.), 2011, Meister Eckhart und Nikolaus von Kues,
(Meister-Eckhart-Jahrbuch, Bd. 4) Stuttgart.

Schweitzer, Fr.-J., 1981, Der Freiheitsbegriff der deutschen Mystik. Seine Beziehung zur
Ketzerei der Brder und Schwestern vom Freien Geist, mit besonderer Bercksichtigung
des pseudoeckartischen Traktates Schwester Katrei (Edition), (Arbeiten zur Mittleren
deutschen Literatur und Sprache, Bd. 10) Frankfurt a. M./Berlin.

, 1997, Meister Eckhart und der Laie. Ein antihierarchischer Dialog des 14.
Jahrhunderts aus den Niederlanden, (Quellen und Forschungen zur Geschichte des
Dominikanerordens. Neue Folge, Bd. 6) Berlin.

Senner, W., 1997, Eckhart in Kln, in Jacobi, 1997, pp. 207237.

Spamer, A. (ed.), 1912, Texte aus der deutschen Mystik des 14. und 15. Jahrhunderts,
Jena.

Speer, A., and Wegener, L. (eds.), 2005, Meister Eckhart in Erfurt, Berlin/New York.

Steer, G., 1992, Zur Authentizitt der deutschen Predigten Meister Eckharts, in
Stirnimann/Imbach, 1992, pp. 127168.

, 1998, Meister Eckhart. Beitrge zur Diskussion seiner Mystik, Wrzburg.

, 2008, Die Interpretation der deutschen und lateinischen Predigten Meister Eckharts
eine unendliche Aufgabe, in Beccarisi/Imbach/Porro, 2008, pp. 184203.

, 2010, Der Aufbruch Meister Eckharts ins 21. Jahrhundert, in Theologische Revue
106, pp. 9099.

, and Sturlese, L. (eds.), 1998, 2003, 2008, Lectura Eckhardi. Predigten Meister
Eckharts, von Fachgelehrten gelesen und gedeutet, Bd. I: Stuttgart/Berlin/Kln; Bd. II:
Stuttgart/Berlin/Kln; Bd. III: Stuttgart.

Stirnimann, H., and Imbach, R. (eds.), 1992, Eckardus Theutonicus, homo doctus et
sanctus. Nachweise und Berichte zum Prozess gegen Meister Eckhart, (Dokimion, Bd.
11) Freiburg/Schweiz.

Sturlese, L., 1989, Die Klner Eckhartisten. Das Studium generale der deutschen
Dominikaner und die Verurteilung der Thesen Meister Eckharts, in Miscellanea
Mediaevalia 20, pp. 192211.

, 1992, Meister Eckharts Weiterwirken. Versuch einer Bilanz, in


Stirnimann/Imbach, 1992, pp. 169183.

, 1993a, Meister Eckhart. Ein Portrt, (Eichsttter Hochschulreden, Bd. 90)


Regensburg.

, 1993b, Mysticism and Theology in Meister Eckharts Theory of the Image, in


Eckhart Review 2, pp. 1831.

, 1995, Meister Eckhart in der Bibliotheca Amploniana. Neues zur Datierung des
Opus Tripartitum, in Miscellanea Mediaevalia 23, pp. 434446.

, 2007, Homo divinus. Philosophische Projekte in Deutschland zwischen Meister


Eckhart und Heinrich Seuse, Stuttgart.

(ed.), 2008, Studi sulle fonti di Meister Eckhart, (Dokimion, Bd. 34)
Freiburg/Schweiz.

, 2009, Hat Meister Eckhart Dietrich von Freiberg gelesen? Die Lehre vom Bild und
von den gttlichen Vollkommenheiten in Eckharts Expositio libri Genesis und Dietrichs
De visione beatifica, in J. Biard/Dr. Calma/R. Imbach (eds.), Recherches sur Dietrich de
Freiberg, (Studia Artistarum, Bd. 19) Turnhout, 2009, pp. 193219.

, 2010, Eckhart, Tauler, Suso. Filosofi e mistici nella Germania medievale, (Giornale
Critico della Filosofia Italiana. Quaderni, Bd. 17) Firenze.

Summerell, O. F., 2002, Self-causality from Plotinus to Eckhart and from Descartes to
Kant, in Quaestio. Annuario di storia della metafisica 2, pp. 493518.

Tobin, Fr. J., 1986, Meister Eckhart. Thought and Language, Philadelphia.

Trusen, W., 1988, Der Proze gegen Meister Eckhart. Vorgeschichte, Verlauf und Folgen,
(Rechts- und Staatswissenschaftliche Verffentlichungen der Grres-Gesellschaft. Neue
Folge, Heft 54) Paderborn/Mnchen/Wien/Zrich.

Ueda, Sh., 1965, Die Gottesgeburt in der Seele und der Durchbruch zur Gottheit. Die
mystische Anthropologie Meister Eckharts und ihre Konfrontation mit der Mystik des
Zen-Buddhismus, (Studien zur Religion, Geschichte und Geisteswissenschaft, Bd. 3)
Gtersloh.

Vannier, M.-A., 1996, Dconstruction de lindividualit ou assomption de la personne


chez Eckhart?, in Miscellanea Mediaevalia 24, pp. 622641.

Wackernagel, W., 1991, Ymagine denudari. thique de limage et mtaphysique de


labstraction chez Matre Eckhart, (tudes de philosophie mdivale, Bd. 68) Paris.

Wackerzapp, H., 1962, Der Einflu Meister Eckharts auf die ersten philosophischen
Schriften des Nikolaus von Kues (14401450), ed. J. Koch, (Beitrge zur Geschichte der
Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters. Texte und Untersuchungen, Bd. 39, Heft 3)
Mnster/Westf.

Waldschtz, E., 1978, Meister Eckhart. Eine philosophische Interpretation der Traktate,
(Studien zur Germanistik, Anglistik und Komparatistik, Bd. 71) Bonn.

, 1989, Denken und Erfahren des Grundes. Zur philosophischen Deutung Meister
Eckharts, Wien.

Weber, R. K., 1978, The Search for Identity and Community in the Fourteenth Century,
in The Thomist 42, pp. 182196.

Weigand, R. K., and Schiewer, R. D. (eds.), 2011, Meister Eckhart und Augustinus,
(Meister-Eckhart-Jahrbuch, Bd. 3) Stuttgart.

Welte, B., 1979, Meister Eckhart. Gedanken zu seinen Gedanken, Freiburg i.


Br./Basel/Wien.

Wendel, S., 2002, Affektiv und inkarniert. Anstze Deutscher Mystik als
subjekttheoretische Herausforderung, (ratio fidei. Beitrge zur philosophischen
Rechenschaft der Theologie, Bd. 15) Regensburg.

Wilde, M., 2000, Das neue Bild vom Gottesbild. Bild und Theologie bei Meister Eckhart,
(Dokimion 24) Freiburg/Schweiz.

Winkler, E., 1965, Exegetische Methoden bei Meister Eckhart, (Beitrge zur Geschichte
der biblischen Hermeneutik, Bd. 6) Tbingen.

Winkler, N., 1993, Normativitt und Reflexion. Meister Eckharts Metaphysik des
entobjektivierten Guten, in Deutsche Zeitschrift fr Philosophie 41, pp. 217235.

, 1996, Zwischen strukturalistischer und intentionalistischer Interpretation


Fallbeispiel: Meister Eckharts Quaestio Parisiensis I, in V. Caysa/K.-D. Eichler (eds.),
Philosophiegeschichte und Hermeneutik, (Leipziger Schriften zur Philosophie, Bd. 5)
Leipzig, 1996, pp. 218237.

, 1997, Meister Eckhart zur Einfhrung, Hamburg.

, 1999, Dietrich von Freiberg und Meister Eckhart in der Kontroverse mit Thomas
von Aquin. Intellektnatur und Gnade in der Schrift Von der wirkenden und der
vermgenden Vernunft, die Eckhart von Grndig zugeschrieben wird, in
Kandler/Mojsisch/Stammktter, 1999, pp. 189266.

Woods, R., 1990, Meister Eckhart and the Neoplatonic Heritage: The Thinkers Way to
God, in The Thomist 54, pp. 609639.

Witte, E., 2003, Bilder an den Grenzen der Philosophie: Selbstthematisierung


Absolutes Als ob, in D. Rustemeyer (ed.), Bildlichkeit. Aspekte einer Theorie der
Darstellung, (Wittener Kulturwissenschaftliche Studien, Bd. 2) Wrzburg, 2003, pp.
225257.

Wulf, E., 1972, Das Aufkommen neuzeitlicher Subjektivitt im Vernunftbegriff Meister


Eckharts, Tbingen.

Zum Brunn, E. (ed.), 1994, Voici Matre Eckhart. Textes et tudes runis, Grenoble (repr.
1998).

, and Libera, A. de, 1984, Matre Eckhart. Mtaphysique du Verbe et thologie


ngative, Paris.

, Kaluza, Z., Libera, A. de, Vignaux, P., and Wber, E., 1984, Matre Eckhart Paris.
Une critique mdivale de lontothologie. Les Questions parisiennes n 1 et n 2
dEckhart, tudes, textes et traductions, (Bibliothque de lcole des Hautes tudes.
Section des Sciences religieuses, Bd. 86) Paris.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen