Sie sind auf Seite 1von 33

the italianist 31 2011 335-366

Dantes New Life and the New Testament:


An Essay on the Hermeneutics of Revelation
William Franke

1 Introduction

The Vita nuova claims to be the story of Dantes encounters with and love for
the woman who became his beatifier, Beatrice. The question of the status of this
woman, whether real or allegorical and in what degrees, has bequeathed to Dante
scholarship a crux for endless debate, but the status of the claim can nevertheless
be determined by reference to a model that, in Dantes own cultural context, would
have been quite inescapable. A person whose presence blesses him and whose
greeting, that is, salute can constitute the very limits of my blessedness (tutti li
termini de la mia beatitudine; iii. 1) is unmistakably Christ-like. Indeed, at least
for Dante, she is salvation and is explicitly identified as such, since in Dantes
Italian salute, in addition to salutation, means also salvation. Dantes phrase
quando questa gentilissima salute salutava (when this most gentle [or kind, or
graceful] salvation saluted, xi. 3) again plays on the double meaning greeting
and salvation of salute.1 Appearing to Dante in the image and in the salvific role
of Christ, Beatrice leads to and even in some sense is the new life la vita nuova
as the title of the book about her says. In this regard, like the one who proclaims
himself the way, the truth, and the life (John 14. 6), she is both protagonist and
propagator of a new and blessed life.
Dante makes the analogy with Christ programmatic in chapter xxiv by
casting Beatrice in a visionary procession as the one who comes after Giovanna
(alias Primavera, Spring, but very also nearly prima verr, or will come first),
whose name he glosses as deriving from that John who preceded the true light
(Quello Giovanni lo quale precedette la verace luce).2 This is what is said in the
Gospel according to John, of John the Baptist as being sent from God in order to
bear witness of the Light, although he himself was not that Light, not the true
Light, which lighteth every man that cometh into the world (1. 6-9; 23).3 Indeed,
at times, the theological intensity of the Vita nuovas affirmations that Beatrice is
Dantes personal saviour and beatifier seems so strong as to approach an idolatrous
heterodoxy.4 But to read understandingly Dantes insertion of certain topoi of

336 the italianist 31 2011

courtly devotion to a beloved lady into his Christian-theological framework


(actually a placing of them back into the matrix whence they derived), it is best
to interpret any virtual identification of Beatrice with Christ not as an idolatrous
worshipping of the creature rather than the Creator (in the terms of Romans
1. 25), but simply as an instance of the one working in and through the other. As in
general Christ works through the individuals who constitute his body, according
to the doctrine of the Christian Church, so he reaches Dante in particular through
the blessed person of Beatrice. This need be no more difficult to account for
theologically than as a common instance of the mystical incorporation of Christ
into the members of his Church those who perform his redemptive work. In this
sense, Beatrice might actually incarnate Christ for Dante, who as a character in a
story of spiritual growth need not always be fully cognizant or theologically precise
in his description of her role as mediator towards increate divinity.5
Not only is Beatrice like Christ in Dantes life, but also Dantes book about
the individual who saves and beatifies him bears a likeness to the Churchs book
about Christ, its Saviour. Both Dantes libello and the Churchs gospel tell stories
of the encounters in life, followed by death and finally by glorification in heaven, of
their respective saviour-beatifiers. The Christian New Testament announces as its
good news the new and greater life in Christ (I have come that ye might have life,
and that ye might have it more abundantly; John 10. 10). Similarly, the Vita nuova,
the story of a new and more abundant life found in relation to Beatrice, is Dantes
good news, and to the extent that his experience may be taken as exemplary, we
could reasonably call it the good news according to Dante.
The fact that it is precisely from the moment of Beatrices appearance to
the nine-year old Dante that he finds written in his memory the rubric Incipit
vita nova suggests that in retrospect Dante sees his life to have been a new life,
which for a Christian cannot but have connotations of being a redeemed and
a blessed life, from the time of Beatrices entry into it and precisely on that
account. Nonetheless, this new life at that point might still have been as yet only
provisional and proleptic. As St. Paul had exclaimed, If any man be in Christ he
is a new creature; old things are passed away, behold all things are become new;
ii Corinthians 5. 17), and nevertheless, the earnest expectation of the creation
waiteth for the revealing of the sons of God; Romans 8. 19. Such ambiguities
aside, Beatrice, too, attains to a new life in the course of the events recounted in
the libello indeed this, if anything, is the event of the book around which all else
revolves and it is unequivocally a glorified life with God, colui qui est per omnia
secula benedictus (xlii. 3).
Thus my contention is that new life in Dantes Vita nuova must be heard
primarily in a Christian evangelical register with its New Testament resonances
of a new and resurrected life. There has, of course, been a great deal of critical
discussion of the meaning of the words vita nuova in the title of the book.6 In

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 337

Purgatorio xxx. 115 (questi fu tal nella sua vita nova), Dante seems to use these
words as synonymous with young life, and in line 7 of his sestina Al poco giorno
e al gran cerchio dombra, the word is evidently used again to mean simply young
in the expression nova donna (young woman). Nevertheless, such a meaning
cannot be taken to fix the sense of the word in the title of the Vita nova nor of the
references to new life within that work. That the Christian connotations of new
life should have been irrelevant for an author such as Dante is not to be believed.
As Vittore Branca observes: Basta del resto scorrere le opere di SantAgostino
per trovare nelle loro pagine ripetuto una decina di volte la vita nova quella
delluomo che conosce Dio; o quelle di Riccardo da San Vittore (che a considerar
fu pi che viro, come lo definisce Dante nel Paradiso x, 132) il quale proprio
alla vita nuova lega anche la poesia nuova; La vita nuova nella giustizia e
nellamore crea la nuova poesia.7
These Christian resonances of new life are perhaps obvious and may
generally be taken for granted (certainly in Dantes cultural context more than
in our own), and yet the comparisons implied in them are far from having been
exploited to the full.8 An enormous amount has been learned about gospel writing
in well over a century of the most intensive, painstaking, and ingenious critical
study of the New Testament.9 Many of the surprising aspects of the process that
have come to light can make puzzling features of Dantes testament of new life
much more understandable. This essay proposes to use the gospels as the model of
a book written in loving memory of a person whose significance is and must remain
central in the life of the author(s). This book witnesses to the miraculousness
of that person realized fully only after the persons death. Yet, in the retelling,
this realization is reflected retrospectively over every episode of the hallowed
individuals existence on earth. This approach through the model of the New
Testament can help to resolve some well-known difficulties in the interpretation of
Dantes New Life, as well as open up new perspectives on possible meanings of
certain of its features heretofore scarcely noticed.
Of particular concern for what follows is the role of those resources of
language and affective imagination customarily called lyrical (in consideration
especially of their nearness to song) in the process by which books like the gospels
and the Vita nuova come to be composed. A principal aim of the ensuing reflections is
to suggest the paramount importance and something of the specific workings of the
lyrical dimension in religious experience and in literary experience generally. This
in itself is a compelling reason for us to study with acute attention Dantes youthful
collection of lyric poems and the hybrid prosimetrum he created out of it. For in
the contemporary cultural climate, the lyrical, along with many other traditional
literary and religious values, runs a risk of extinction. Literature and poetry as
such, not to mention dependent concepts like lyric, can in academic contexts all
too easily be deconstructed as metaphysical idealizations. Yet the rapturous verbal

338 the italianist 31 2011

enchantment and attunement experienced in contact with poetic language, especially


in lyrical forms such as those found in liturgy, must not be allowed completely to
succumb to intellectual, and much less to ideological, critique.
The lyrical will be presented here as a vital constitutive moment of revelation
and as crucial to a poetics of revelation conceived in the terms of hermeneutic
theory. This approach will establish the premises and parameters for a debate
specifically with a remarkable contemporary contribution to Dante studies in just
this area. An arresting and enticing approach to interpreting the Vita nuova was
inaugurated by an original and masterful book by Robert Pogue Harrison, The
Body of Beatrice.10 Guided by the insights and methods of phenomenology in the
manner of Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger, this book raises speculation
on the meaning of Dantes prosimetric masterpiece to a level of reflection where it
can become philosophically and religiously relevant for us today. I find The Body
of Beatrices argumentation profound and compelling, as well as exquisite, yet I
am not persuaded by its conclusions.11
For Harrison, the Vita nuova originates in and from the experience of a
woman, which he would have to be an irreducible reality around which barrages
of hermeneutic assault accumulated only later. This not-to-be-interpreted origin is
complemented, in Harrisons view, by an equally self-transcending and irreducible,
interpretation-resistant destination, for the book issues in an opening towards the
temporality of narrative, and this entails projection into an as yet unrevealed future.
An inviolable mystery is left intact at either end: it is the unaccountable experience
that generates the necessarily indecipherable libello. In the middle that is, across
the whole of the Vita nuova what happens in one way or another constitutes an
overcoming of the lyric obsession that so possessed (and by implication stunted)
Cavalcanti and Petrarch, dubbed cases of lyric stubbornness and set up as foils to
Dante.12 Only the opening to narrative defers disclosure and preserves the mystery
that the lyrics epiphanic insistence is bent rather on making manifest.
I will argue that Harrison has vastly underestimated the absolutely
fundamental and perduring, original and life-affirming, role of the lyric mode in
Dantes inspiration as a writer. The acknowledged lyricism of the Paradiso is read
by Harrison as part of a falling away from the authentic encounter registered
in the Vita nuova into a more conventional, falsifying form of language. But I
maintain that Beatrice, as the phenomenon of transcendence that Harrison so
convincingly shows she was for Dante, was possible only by the instrumentality
of the lyric, specifically by virtue of its powers to express registers of personal
experience where subjective response and feeling are constitutive parts of
objective events, not secondary and less real. Furthermore, I maintain that at
the other end of the Vita nuovas trajectory, at its finis, the narrative dimension
Dante discovers or projects is not the overcoming but the fulfillment of the lyric
mode.13 Whereas Harrison endeavours to chart the trajectory of Dantes career as

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 339

directed not only to the surpassing of the courtly lyric of his time but also of the
lyric mode per se, culminating in the emergence of the epic alternative, I contend
that the narrative poetry of the Commedia, if it exists to tell a story, exists to
tell it in such a way as not to dispense with lyrical sensibility but rather owes
its incomparable visionary power in great measure to the non-chronological,
non-cognitive, musical and emotional qualities of lyric that make things happen
within the souls of readers, as much as to (and inseparably from) what happens
in the story that the poem narrates.
These arguments will constitute a defence, in some respects, of the revelocentric reading of the book which Harrison, in a word, rejects.14 They will also
constitute a certain assessment, informed especially by existential theology, of what
revelation is and of how it is achieved historically and literarily, which may amount
to the rudiments of a hermeneutic theory of revelation.15 This theory, as presented
here, trains attention particularly on the lyrical dimension of religious revelation.
This topic has wide-ranging application in religiously revelatory literature. It
concerns what William Blake in his prophetic poetry calls the Auricular Nerves of
Human Life. Which is the Earth of Eden (Four Zoas, i. 18).16 As the terms of this
statement from a cultural milieu far removed from Dantes confirm, the prophetic
and revelatory powers of poetry are intimately bound up with the rapture created
by the lyrical qualities of poetic language.
The essay begins by observing the power of lyric core texts to generate
narrative in the New Testament as the model of theologically revelatory literature
(2). It then apprehends this same generative logic as it operates in the Vita nuova
(3). This sets up a detailed countering of Harrisons theses (4) and leads finally
to envisaging a poetics of religious revelation as an existential and theological
hermeneutic (5).17
I have said before
That the past experience revived in the meaning
Is not the experience of one life only
But of many generations not forgetting
Something that is probably quite ineffable

(T.S.Eliot, The Dry Salvages, ii)

2 The New Testament model

The most prominent model of autobiographical prosimetrum for Dante was surely
Boethiuss De consolatione philosophiae. But in a deeper way, in his book on
the new life, it is the Bible that Dante is imitating.18 A new life beyond death
can be sought on the basis of the promises of the Christian revelation and, even

340 the italianist 31 2011

more immediately, in the delectation of Christian literature. The New Testament


is the eminent and, for Dante, inevitable model of the relationship between
prose and poetry, narrative and lyric, in the rememoration of an individual in
whom divinity has been revealed and in whom new life is found after an event
of death-glorification. The Magnificat, the Benedictus, Nunc dimittis, and the
Pater Noster are perhaps the most conspicuous examples of poetic compositions
finding narrative settings in the synoptic gospels. Their use in the liturgy also serves
to underscore their independent life as prayers or poems for recitation.19 In the
New Testaments own model, the Old Testament, Moses Song (Exodus 15. 1-21)
can be determined to have preceded the narrative context in which it occurs; it
existed first presumably in a liturgical mode. On the basis of linguistic and stylistic
analysis, it appears to be among the oldest materials of the Pentateuch and likely
the generative source for much of the Exodus narrative. The same could be said
about numerous other passages, for example, about Deborahs Song (Judges 5.
1-31) and the corresponding narrative in the book of Judges.20
Beyond what can be learned through direct historical analysis of documents,
there is a literary logic to this order progressing from poetry to prose in the
evolution of tradition.21 Robert Alter, in his account of the development of biblical
poetry from Line to Story, or in other words, of the narrativization of verse, calls
attention to the narrative development of metaphor. He emphasizes how narrative
can be inherent in and arise from the poetic functions of focusing, heightening, or
concretizing through the form of repetition characteristic of biblical verse, namely,
parallelism. Alter explains that what we very frequently find in biblical verse is
the emergence of the syntagmatic from the paradigmatic: as the poet offers an
approximate equivalent for an image or idea he has just invoked, he also begins, by
the very logic of specification or intensification of the system in which he works, to
push the initial image or idea into action, moving from one image to another that
is temporally subsequent to and implied by the first.22 This dynamic of expansion
and externalization inherent within the poem extends itself into prose accretions
which arise from and accumulate around verse seeds or kernels.
Poetic core texts recording something of the transforming intensity of an
event of the divine generate a plethora of narrative texts that help explain the
sense of the miraculous that poetry is most apt immediately to register and express.
Among the oldest residues preserved within the New Testament are doxologies and
hymns, such as those which critical study employing the instruments of Source and
Form Criticism (Formgeschichte) has been able to isolate embedded within the
earliest extant Christian texts, particularly in certain Pauline (and pseudo-Pauline)
epistles. For example, verses 6 to 11 of Philippians 2 comprise a primitive Christian
canticle that pre-dated and was incorporated into the letter:

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 341

Let this mind be in you, which was also in Christ Jesus:


Who, being in the form of God, (thought not divinity a thing to be
grasped:)
But made himself of no reputation, and took upon him the form of a servant,
and was made in the likeness of men:
And being found in fashion as a man, he humbled, and became obedient
unto death, even the death of the cross.
Wherefore God also hath highly exalted him, and given him a name which
is above every name:
That at the name of Jesus, every knee should bow, of things in heaven, and
things in earth, and things under the earth;
And that every tongue should confess that Jesus Christ is Lord, to the glory
of God the Father.
Such poetic sequences gave the faith community its first capability of verbalizing
the extraordinary, life-transforming experience of the miraculous individual Jesus
of Nazareth, who was the founder of its collective life. The followers who remained
after Jesuss death and who believed that he lived in glory on the right hand of
God the Father believed that they themselves were living a new life made possible
for them because their lives had been touched and transformed by Jesus. The
story of their encounters with Jesus before his death and resurrection/ascension
was evidently elaborated subsequently (the canonical gospel narratives appearing
some 40 to 60 years later) out of an assortment of memories. Composition of the
narratives was guided by controlling images (like the pastoral Good Shepherd
or the apocalyptic Son of Man) and basic symbolic structures, particularly the
binary opposition between high and low, abasement and exaltation, such as are
fixed in the lyrical, liturgical formulas of this canticle. It seems likely that only on
the basis of paradigms such as this trope of kenosis or self-emptying could the
narratives be produced; indeed the narrative sequences or syntagms of the New
Testament should perhaps be seen simply as further developments elaborating on
such lyric paradigms.
Along similar lines, the Resurrection and the Ascension, upon careful formal
analysis, turn out to be readable as two complementary faces or symbolic idioms
for the same event of glorification-exaltation, Jesuss new and glorified life being
imaged convertibly in terms of a rising up or an ascending above, which doubleimage, accordingly, would have generated two different clusters of narratives
expressing this never adequately representable experience of the risen and glorified
Lord. Dante has, in fact, taken over one of these image clusters, when he envisions
Beatrices ascension in a nebuletta bianchissima (whitest of little clouds) and
escorted by a multitude of the heavenly host singing Hosanna in excelsis (xxiii).
Not only do tropes, or what have been called lyric paradigms, seem to have
first enabled the revelation of Jesus as glorified Lord to be verbalized; they also

342 the italianist 31 2011

function as the enabling conditions of the very perception of the event, and in
another way anterior to that concerning binary structures of significance that has
already been suggested. The advent of Jesus as the Christ into the lives of the first
Christians in the Easter experience was prepared for and made possible by an
assortment of figures or types contained in certain verses of the Jewish Scriptures
which suddenly in the light of Easter came to be understood or at least to be
understood in a new way as having been fulfilled by Jesus. This literature lived
in the minds of the faithful through regular public celebration of the liturgy, as
well as in private devotional practices, and it can be seen to have pre-programmed,
pervasively and decisively, the story of Jesus that later came to be told in the
gospels. The weaving of narratives around these prophetic-poetic texts begins
right from the tradition that a Messiah for Israel should come out of Bethlehem,
although the town was otherwise insignificant. Matthew 2. 6 cites this tradition:
And thou, Bethlehem, in the land of Juda, are not least among the princes of Juda:
for out of thee shall come a Governor, that shall rule my people Israel. Matthew
is reproducing verbatim the prophecy in Micah 5. 2 foretelling that Jesus was to
be born in Bethlehem.
The Psalms, from which so many of the prophecies fulfilled by Jesus according
to the gospels are drawn, and of which the twenty-second My God, my God,
Why hast thou foresaken me? is the text on Jesuss lips in the gospel tradition
just before his expiration, were Israels hymnal. Together with them, the often
intensely lyrical (and mnemonic) poetry of the prophets furnished the language of
an expectation within which alone the whole Christ event would be intelligible,
and so could significantly occur.
Following in this tradition, it is not surprising that the earliest formulations
in language on the part of the Christians of what had occurred in the Christ event
should have been cast into lyrical forms like the canticle in Philippians 2 in order
to be recited in the liturgy of the primitive Church. The wonder and exaltation
experienced by the Church at its origin was expressed in poetry, and the poetic,
specifically lyrical dimension would remain indispensable to this experience, even
when it came to be narrativized. This entailed that the narrative of Jesuss life
and ministry would inevitably be at one and the same time a narrativization of
the mystical experience within the Church community of the risen Lord: Jesus is
imagined and sung as present in his glory in the sacraments, as well as in the word
of the liturgy; he is celebrated as working by his Spirit in acts of charity throughout
the Christian body.
Some such posterior reformulation of events in the light shed by Easter
seems to be alluded to and even authorized by Jesuss promises in the gospels to
his disciples that the Holy Spirit would inspire the memory and record of him,
implying that actual memory of the past need not be exclusively relied on, nor even
be privileged: These things have I spoken unto you, being yet present with you. But

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 343

the Comforter, which is the Holy Ghost, whom the Father will send in my name, he
shall teach you all things, and bring all things to your remembrance, whatsoever I
have said unto you (John 14. 25-26).
The narratives of the gospels, then, may be seen as generated in good part out
of lyrical crystallizations which first formulated, linguistically and conceptually,
the extraordinary significance of the person Jesus of Nazareth. Only when the
evangelist (and the evangelical community) had grasped in faith who Jesus is and
this means who Jesus is for them presently, as experienced in the lyrical transports
of poetry performed in liturgy and in the creedal Symbol and in sacraments could
the account of who he was in an historical life lived on earth be worked out in
narrative terms.
The nativity scenes in Luke and Matthew provide a provocative example
of the way in which narrative is prone to spring up around figural cores and
poetic epitomes. Lukes story of the virgin birth seems to have been in part an
accident engendered by translation of the Hebrew word for young girl by the
Greek word for virgin in the Septuagint, which was used by Luke. The word
virgin, in its connotative suggestiveness, contains a poetic universe, what could
be called a myth.23 And Lukes whole story may originate simply as a sort of
Midrash in narrative form expanding upon this mistranslated verse from Isaiah
7. 14.24 Whether or not this is actually the case, its plausibility suggests that prose
narratives can develop from and elaborate on linguistic hints contained in lyrical
hymns and oracles.
This process of a posteriori narrativization of poetic prophecy becomes
almost explicit in a passage such as the following, although a sufficiently ambiguous
veil remains drawn between remembering and inventing:
And Jesus when he had found a young ass, sat thereon; as it is written [in
the book of the prophet Zephaniah], Fear not, daughter of Sion: behold
thy King cometh, sitting upon an asss colt. These things understood not
his disciples at the first: but when Jesus was glorified then remembered they
that these things were written of him, and that they had done these things
unto him. (John 12. 14-16)
Whatever the actual event may or may not have been, clearly its precise significance
was imposed retrospectively under the influence of the prophecy avowedly
recognized as such only later. Thus gospel writing must be sharply distinguished
from historiography because its purpose is not to record facts but to witness to
faith. Even when it invokes the rhetoric of factuality, as in the miracle stories,
the facts are presented always as signs, and their meaning is given only within a
horizon of belief. The gospels are really about a miracle of faith within the lives of
individuals in the Christian community, and only as such is the outward history
they tell susceptible to being comprehended.

344 the italianist 31 2011

Dante, of course, had no such idea of the gospel stories as has been
delineated here with the help of modern synoptic criticism and literary analysis.
Nevertheless, the evangelical model was unavoidable for any Christian author
writing about new life, and Dante himself insists on the association of Beatrice with
Christ, most overtly in Chapter xxiv, but also in xxiii, with the apocalyptic signs
associated with Christs death prefiguring also Beatrices death, and throughout
the book more subtly and incidentally in capillary fashion. My suggestion is that
certain principles of hagiography most apparent in the most intensively studied
hagiographical documents of all, those of the New Testament, are operative in
Dantes hagiographical work as well.25
The basis for such an analogy lies in the common existential conditions
concerning an individual the love of whom miraculously gives ones life new
meaning and who is then no longer accessible in the flesh, at least not as an
individual body, but who is found still to give a new significance to ones life on an
ongoing basis indefinitely into the future. What works recording such experience
need to express is the ecstatic awakening and accession of life communicated by
this persons presence, and for this purpose poetry is paramount. A chronicle
of facts alone about this person could not reveal the persons extraordinary
significance. The biographical narratives subsequently elaborated are keyed to
texts which do not state facts but convey, figuratively and lyrically, the meaning
of a new life. For poetic and especially lyrical heightening of life must first capture
the extraordinary significance of this individual and his or her event in the lives of
witnesses, including the witness who becomes the writer. This existentially verified,
lived miracle, which is the presupposition for beginning the story, is first cast into a
symbolic form lyrically felt to embody and communicate this new and heightened
life. Transposing this figural/lyrical core into a dimension of narrative, the book
begins, then, with a miracle story, such as the annunciation of the angel to Mary
or the apparition of Beatrice to Dante.
History may be servitude,
History may be freedom. See, now they vanish,
The faces and places, with the self which, as it could, loved them,
To become renewed, transfigured, in another pattern.

(T.S.Eliot, Little Gidding, iii)

3 A reading of the Vita nuova

The Vita nuova tells the story of how the lyrics it includes came to be written
as a result of encounters with Beatrice and their aftermath in Dantes life. It
actually presents itself as a prose narrative woven around lyric cores, or even

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 345

as commentary on them, most explicitly in the glossatological sections, notably


the so-called divisioni, which critics since Boccaccio have been at such pains to
explain (or edit) away. The pre-existence of the poems with respect to the prose
text is thus presupposed by the text itself, which specifies the junctures of time in
the past when they came to be written. Taking the book on its own terms, then, the
lyrics would form the first core of verbalization of this miraculous experience. All
the various matters broached in the prose sections cluster around and attend upon
the poems. It is conceivable, and perhaps even likely in certain instances, that the
prose ragioni, which purportedly interpolate the real life situations surrounding
each lyric and leading from one to the next, more than being actual memories
of things that happened as they are said to have happened, are indeed literally
rationalizations and expansions of what the lyrics already imply or project. Such
has been found to be the pattern for the razos on the lives of the troubadours.26
In this case, so far from being rhetorical ornaments for the story, the lyrics would
actually generate it.
The event of Beatrice conveyed in the Vita nuova is something that could
never even in principle be adequately related in mere prose as a sequence of even
quite extraordinary facts. The poetry that Beatrice inspires, or at least the fact
that encountering her is inspirational, which state is betokened by its leading to
the writing of poetry, underlies all that can be recounted about her as Dantes
beatrice, his beatifier, which is indeed the books argument. If she did not
affect Dante, so as to translate him into a new, normally inaccessible, dimension
of existence, she would not be Beatrice. For no mere sequence of external events
without the witness of a subject as expressed in lyrical transports could contain the
miraculous meaning which she manifestly was for Dante.27
We have seen that the revelation of Jesus as the Christ in the gospels could
not be given in the form of objective, historical fact, but is inextricably bound up
with the disciples personal experience in relation to Jesus and with their lyricalpoetic articulation of it. What their testimony witnesses to is a faith which Jesus
inspired in them, and this faith was never compulsory in response to who Jesus
was or what he did: even seeing him resurrected, on the mountain in Galilee,
some doubted (Matthew 28. 17). The stories about Jesus witness not to mere
outward happenings but to the miraculous transformations worked within the
lives and hearts of individuals. Such is the deep significance of the virgin birth
namely, what it says about the miraculous nature of Jesus of Nazareth for those
who experienced him. To make of Jesuss divinity something more objective than
this is to mythologize it in Bultmanns sense of myth. This sense, however, is not
incompatible with C.S.Lewiss dictum that The heart of Christianity is a myth
which is also a fact.28
Dantes experience of Beatrice was an experience of the miraculous and
divine, of that which is beyond all finite experience of objects and which cannot

346 the italianist 31 2011

be adequately expressed in objective terms. This is why Dante had need of a


subjective language, the language of lyric, which, prescinding from any specific
objective referent or content, expresses feeling by form. Like the New Testament
writers, Dante did, of course, express his sense of the miraculous in objectifying
terms, but as his allusion to Homer in the prose of chapter II betrays, he senses
that he is veering into myth when he tries to state the miraculousness of Beatrice
as a simple fact. That she should be the daughter not of a mortal but of god Ella
non parea figliuola duomo mortale, ma di deo (ii. 8) also happens to be the
central claim made about Christ in the New Testament, but it is not a claim that
could be proved objectively or even be interpreted intelligibly in strictly objective
terms. It can only be given a meaning as expressing the marvel Dante felt and
projected onto Beatrice, as the object of that marvel, in the form of an (hyperbolic)
attribute. While it is natural, and fulfills certain needs, that Dante should express
the experience of Beatrice in the hyperboles and wish-fulfilling fantasies of
myth, the truest or most authentic expression, nevertheless, of this emotionally
overwhelming experience, must remain the lyric. Dantes lyrical language about
Beatrice directly embodies his emotional exaltation and the existential reality of
his ecstatic self-transcendence. Lyrical language can do this in and by its formalaesthetic properties, its musical qualities, and its expressiveness in excess of all
representational content or objective reference.29
Just as in the New Testament, the lyric form is indispensable for expressing
what was felt and experienced in relation to the miraculous, divinity-revealing
individual. Without it, there could have been no more than a passing individual
illumination, not a historical revelation, for the transcendent meaning of the event
could not have been communicated or even formulated. The miracle of Beatrice
is what her presence works within the hearts and minds of others, not what is
objectively documentable about her. Actual physical detail of her appearance
is neglected just as is physical description of Christ in the gospels. We are told
only a few symbolic features, principally of her eyes (principio damore) and
her smile (fine damore), and even these features are described not objectively so
much as in terms of their love-inspiring effects on whoever should behold them.
This is clear in probably their most extended description, that in Donne chavete
intelletto damore:
De li occhi suoi, come chella li mova,
escono spirti damore inflammati,
che feron li occhi a qual che allor la guati,
e passan si che l cor ciascun retrova:
voi le vedete Amor pinto nel viso,
la ve non pote alcun mirarla fiso. (xix. 12; my italics)

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 347

That Dantes experience of Beatrice actually steps outside of historical experience


altogether into what is not describable in any prosaic terms is suggested when
he writes that in her he saw all the ends of my beatitude (tutti li termini de la
mia beatitudine; iii. 1). This phrase evokes eschatological time or rather the
eschatons obliteration of historical time. There can be no objective language
objects being given always within the parameters of a given world to describe
what Dante experiences under that condition. But there is lyrical language and
expression, and this is what Dante uses. The subjective and personal dimension
concerning the effect Beatrice had on Dante can only be indirectly and lyrically
conveyed to another, specifically, by suggesting the level of feeling or quality of
existence that was touched in the experience. Without such a lyrical language, all
that could be said would be, We had the experience but we missed the meaning.
Yet thanks to the lyric, another possibility arises, namely, that approach to the
meaning restores the experience | In a different form (The Dry Salvages, ii).
It is remarkable that the same basic scheme as provided a first-order
figuration in lyrical form of Jesus as the Christ in the hymn of Philippians 2 is
operative also throughout the Vita nuovas presentation of Beatrice as glorious yet
humble, precisely coronata [] dumilitade:
Ella si va, sentendosi laudare,
benignamente dumilta vestuta;
e par che sia una cosa venuta
da cielo in terra a miracol mostrare. (xxvi. 6)
This motif of humility accompanies virtually every mention of the gloriosa
donna, from her very first appearance dressed humbly and candidly in a most
noble crimson color (vestita di nobilissimo colore, umile e onesto, sanguigno;
ii. 3). It defines something unmistakable about her significance in no matter
what circumstances she appears. But the humility which constitutes an essential
characteristic of Beatrice turns out to correspond to, or even be convertible with,
something experienced in his own being by Dante in her presence, or by anyone
who sees her: The sight of her makes every being humble (La sua vista fa onne
cosa umile; xxvi. 12).
The Vita nuova and the gospel are both predicated on a common assumption
that there is a subjective dimension of experience in which alone the deep reality
and meaning of history or of a life-history, or even of just an event, can be perceived.
Such meaning, in both cases, declared itself to memory and could be adequately
represented only by a form of witness which projected an inner experience of
miracle into the idiosyncratic diction of poetic language. Dantes acute awareness
of this irreducibly subjective and personal aspect of the advent of divinity and
salvation shows clearly in his constant recourse to categories of dream, vision, and
imagination in relating every one of Beatrices epiphanies.30 From the first occasion,

348 the italianist 31 2011

when he sees her plainly, he uses the rhetoric of appearing apparvemi (ii. 2)
and this rhetoric recurs with insistent redundancy in every one of his visions and
dreams and memorable fancies. Even for an encounter with Beatrice in the public
space of the streets of Florence between two elderly women, Dante employs the
same language with its vaguely psychologizing, subjectivizing implications: this
marvelous lady appeared to me dressed in purest white (questa mirabile donna
apparve a me vestita di colore bianchissimo; iii. 1).
The exceeding marvelousness of this woman seems to make it impossible
to speak of her in objective, matter-of-fact, terms. The state of excitement she
automatically induces evidently renders Dantes perceptions incommensurable
with any common norm, so that he can only speak about how she appeared to him,
his experience of her being abnormal, enhanced and unique. When he discovers
that she has similar effects on others (see Tanto gentile and Vede perfettamente,
xxvi. 5-7 and 10-13), that simply makes them, too, witnesses of what would
not ordinarily be believed, for they too are beside themselves, dumbstruck with
admiration and inwardly shaken and overwhelmed: E quando ella fosse presso
dalcuno, tanta onestade giungea nel cuore di quello, che non ardia di levare li occhi,
n di rispondere a lo suo saluto; e di questo molti, s come esperti, mi potrebbero
testimoniare a chi non lo credesse (xxvi. 1).31
The meaning that Beatrice took on within Dantes experience is constitutive
of what he was able actually to see about her. What he in fact saw is bracketed
within what he believed he saw or seemed to see or perhaps rather thought about
her. Dante expresses this in suggesting that his seeing of Beatrice was a seeing
through love, in an episode which in fact typifies all his encounters with Beatrice,
where Love supplants his visual faculties (spiriti del viso) and takes over their
function, because Love wanted to remain in their most noble place so as to behold
the marvelous lady (per che Amore volea stare nel loro nobilissimo luogo per
vedere la mirabile donna; xiv. 5; see also xi. 2). Thus Dante becomes other than
before (altro che prima), indeed to such an extent as to warrant speaking of his
trasfigurazione, which transfers the supernatural condition of a divine being (since
it recalls Jesuss transfiguration in the gospels) to his own existential condition,
hinting at the intimate connection, the inseparability, of the two.
The rhetoric of appearance consistently evokes a subjective dimension of
experience in all the accounts of his encounters with this miracle; it is so relentless
in its recurrence as to demand to be accounted for itself. Between the various
permutations of pareami, mi parea vedere, mapparve, and mi era apparuto, Dante
manages to repeat these formulaic expressions eleven times in the course of the
description of his dream, not even a page long, in chapter III. 3-7. The same density
of occurrence of this rhetoric characterizes the dream-description of Love as a
young man dressed in white in chapter XIII. 3-8.

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 349

Sometimes such expressions serve to introduce what Dante only felt interiorly,
as in I felt a marvellous tremor begin within my breast (mi parve sentire uno
mirabile tremore incomminciare nel mio petto; xiv. 4). But the appearance-idiom
has a highly labile meaning, as it slides from qualifying a belief, to a perception, to a
look (not an individuated object of perception but an air giving a certain impression),
as in the following phrase about Love: Allora mi parea che io lo conoscesse, per
che mi chiamava cos come assai fiate ne li miei sonni mavea gi chiamato: e
riguardandolo, parvemi che piangesse pietosamente, e parea che attendesse da me
alcuna parola (xii. 4). In each instance, the subjective conditioning of whichever
type of cognition is signaled and the chain of association that is established links
everything reported to the subject and his existential condition.
The same word is used when Dante wants to refer to what exists only in his
imagination. Of Love he writes that in my imagination he appeared as a pilgrim
(ne la mia imaginazione apparve come peregrino; ix. 3). And similarly when
Dante witnesses in dream the series of apocalyptic signs, they are governed by
identical semantics: the darkening of the sun appeared to me (pareami vedere lo
sole oscurare); it seemed to me that the birds flying in the air fell dead (pareami
che li uccelli volando per laria cadessero morti; xxiii. 5). All of these instances
are dismissed by being ascribed to erroneous fantasy (la erronea fantasia), and
yet they prove to be premonitory, revelatory signs.
There is one juncture at which Dante dispenses with the language of
appearance. It occurs where he is speaking not of any sort of presence of Beatrice
or of attendant figures. He tells us that, according to infallible truth (secondo
la infallabile veritade), Beatrice was the number nine (questo numero fue ella
medisima; xxvii). He can be certain about her not as a phenomenon in space
and time but as a mathematical symbol, for this is a question not of facts but of
significance. The certainty he has about her significance, moreover, is an ontological
certainty: it is certain truth for him not because of what he knows objectively
but because of what he is namely, transformed in his own being through his
relation to her. Of course, her being, while it participates in absolute Being and
makes his own being do so likewise, is not itself this absolute Being, and this he
recognizes, saying that he speaks in similitude (per similitudine dico) in arriving
at his conclusion that she was a miracle ontologically rooted in divinity: she was a
nine, that is, a miracle, whose root that is, of the miracle is only the wondrous
Trinity (ella era uno nove, cio uno miracolo, la cui radice, cio del miracolo,
solamente lo mirabile Trinitade; xxix. 3).
All this talk of appearance might induce us to make a distinction, as Robert
Harrison does, between the phenomenal and the noumenal. But against this, I
submit that Dantes language has not an epistemological but rather a hermeneutic
import. The report always of what appears to him does not indicate that Beatrice
has a noumenal being which does not appear, but rather that he is not reporting

350 the italianist 31 2011

an act of perception of an object so much as expressing and completing an episode


of personal involvement which questioned his own being, just as much as he may
have questioned what he saw. Indeed the implication is not that he doubted in
any degree what he saw, but that it was an intensely personal and visionary sort
of seeing. It is this connotation of pareami which has been felt by those readers
in all ages who have expressly recognized the books pervasive visionary quality.
Especially when we consider how this language is used, modulating fluidly from the
domain of perception to that of belief and then to that of decision about meaning,
we begin to sense its value for testifying to a personal susceptibility and a subjective
change experienced in the encounter with the significant individual rather than for
defining epistemologically the status of the phenomena in question.
It is remarkable that, after the disappearance of Beatrice, in the scene where
the gentil donna appears to him, the pareami idiom occurs only rarely and has
not at all the same role as in every account of his encounters with Beatrice or
even with Love that is, in every revelatory experience. It occurs only twice: first
in reference not to the inward quality of Dantes apprehension of the woman
but simply to how he looked on the outside. His sad thoughts, he says, made
me appear externally to be terribly dismayed (mi faceano parere di fore una
vista di terribile sbigottimento; xxxv. 1). Here Dante becomes self-conscious and
concerned lest his consternation be observed by others; he is far from the total
involvement in relation to an Other which makes parere a signal of existential
testimony, as in the encounters with Beatrice. Indeed when Dante encounters the
gentil donna, he is vulnerable precisely because he thinks of Beatrice as belonging
to past time (con ci fosse cosa che io fosse in parte ne la quale mi ricordava del
passato tempo). He allows his true vision of her eternity and of her revelation of
a new life in the present of his personal existence to weaken. He is treating what
Beatrice reveals to him in a visionary present as merely a past fact, which is to miss
its religious significance.
And so, in this instance, he simply sees, as a matter of fact, the compassionate
lady: Then I saw a gentle lady, young and very beautiful, who was looking at me
from a window (Allora vidi una gentile donna giovane e bella molto, la quale da
una finestra mi riguardava; xxxv. 2). The window seems an image for the selfreflexivity that characterizes the scene and that implies a logic of objectification,
even self-objectification, which is the very antithesis of an absorbing relation to
an other in self-oblivion and transcendence. The other occurrence of the tell-tale
idiom of appearing comes in the phrase all pity appeared to be received in her
(tutta la piet parea in lei accolta), which does not serve to suggest anything
unique and indefinable about Dantes personal experience; there is no mi, and
the phrase is as near to stating a fact as a judgment about compassion in another
could be. The contrast could not be more striking than with the re-apparition of
Beatrice four chapters later in an imaginazione where mi parve and parvemi

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 351

reappear. Here we are back in the epiphanic mode, and it emphatically personalizes
and subjectivizes perception.
Alongside the rhetoric of appearance stand other indicators that the
story of Dantes revelation is being told not so much in terms of actual facts as
of a meaningful event grasped figuratively in lyrical forms and then objectified
narratively in retrospect. A figurative or symbolic logic rather than anything like
historical contingency must be discerned in the really quite peculiar sequence of
incidents Dante relates. That Beatrices death should be so closely preceded by
that of her father, as well as by that of a young companion of hers, cannot but
create a configuration of happenings which reciprocally reflect rather than merely
follow one another. The language used to describe the deceased young woman is
indistinguishable from the sort of language Dante uses of Beatrice: it pleased the
Lord of the angels to call to glory a young lady of very noble aspect (fue piacere
del segnore di li angeli di chiamare a la sua gloria una donna giovane e di gentile
aspetto molto; viii. 1). We cannot but think, for example, of Angelo clama in
divino intelletto (xix. 7). The reader might think that Dante is already telling of
Beatrices own death with the sort of circumlocutions he is habitually given to, until
arriving at the mention of quella gentilissima, which can only mean Beatrice; and
even then Dantes great grief is wholly determined by the relation which the early
victim had to his lady: he resolves to write about her in recompense for the several
occasions on which he had seen her in the company of his lady (in guiderdone di
ci che alcuna fiata lavea veduta con la mia donna; viii. 2).
The fact that Beatrice is not the only beautiful young woman who dies
tragically in a little book devoted to her, and although such a death is not to
be taken as common but as catastrophic, exemplifies the numerous structures of
doubling which raise the narrative from the level of facts ingenuously reported to
that of a consciously crafted exposition registering and shaping the meaning of an
event. Everything turns up double or multiple, including the visions of Beatrice and
of Amore. Where the doublings seem gratuitous, as with the two screen ladies, as
if one of these were not already a sufficiently unusual turn of plot, the effect is to
diminish their weight as unique historical realities and turn them into tropes with
a literary function uncanny equivalences and replicas such as history would not
be likely to produce.
The multiple versions which Dante gives of his basic experiences, as for
example the several accounts of his bouts of psychomachia (compare the four
pensamenti of chapter xiii and the quattro cose or reflections on loves effects
in chapter xvi), or even the fact that he anticipates in dream what will happen, or
that he gives both a prose version and a poetic version of each episode, indicate
that the truth is not itself in the facts but that such facts as are related are rather
variations on a theme and illustrations of a deeper meaning. All of the deaths in
the book are somehow or other versions of the books central event Beatrices

352 the italianist 31 2011

death. Similarly, the major figures of women are all, whether positive or negative,
forged in the image of the books one all-important figure Beatrice herself. Where
one central significance is established, everything else becomes subordinated as so
many partial manifestations of it, whether in a positive or negative key.
Unique persons and events become multiple images in memory, or different
episodes become unified, because of the plurality inherent within the sign, which
is not per se a unique occurrence but rather is interchangeable with an infinity
of other possible signs of the same thing. Indeed it is even one and the same
sign only by virtue of its own iterability. Similarly, the gospels (especially as the
Middle Ages read them) turn on a typological linking together of all things as
signs: all become mirrors of the crucial event and person. It is not certain how far
the effect in question is calculated by Dante, but we are in a universe governed
by a central transcendent Signified which turns everything else into signifiers of
itself. Even Beatrice in Dantes book turns into a mosaic of appearances because
no single one of them can render her absolutely. The same must be said of the
gospels multi-perspectival portraiture of Jesus. Perhaps this is also a reason why
the art of mosaic seems so exceptionally endowed for representing the Christ of
Christian spirituality, as the ceiling of SantAppolinare in Classe, reflected in the
Commedia, witnesses.32
Dante figures this structure of the many equivalencies for the one meaning
or Signified geometrically. The god of Love, who, however remotely, can in truth
be nothing but a dim, distorted image of the God who is Love, is himself like
the centre of a circle, the parts of whose circumference are all similar. The god
reproaches Dante in just these terms: Ego tanquam centrum circuli, cui simili
modo se habent circumferentie partes; tu autem non sic (xii. 4). The reproach
is all the more to the point and strikes dead centre, inasmuch as Dante, after the
revelation of Beatrice, is in a uniquely privileged position to be able to comprehend
his own centre. Nevertheless, while castigating Dante for not yet having found
his centre in Beatrice, at the same time the gods cryptic message announces that
Dante is not his own centre but must rather read the signs pointing him to his own
authentic significance, the unifying love of his life.
The similarities which structure the episodes of Dantes life, when written
retrospectively from the standpoint of the centre, that is, as centred on the
glorious lady of my mind (la gloriosa donna de la mia mente), finally become
comprehensible. Viewed retrospectively, all the episodes of Dantes life are
illuminated by the central significance of Beatrice. All, similarly, point to her as
to their deeper meaning. This intrinsic similarity generates a whole constellation
of look-alikes and seeming repeats which outside this perspective appear bizarre
coincidences and pointless redundancies and which, apart from it, would be totally
inimical to Dantes rigorous and wasteless aesthetic.

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 353

Dantes libello symbolizes itself as a testimony to new meaning revealed in


personal existence, rather than as a chronicle of facts, by means of the metaphor of
the book of memory, which governs his book from its very first sentence: In that
part of the book of my memory (In quella parte del libro de la mia memoria; i.
1). We are dealing thus from the start with a reflected image rather than with events
themselves, and the strategy of the book will be to exploit the disparity between
the meaning its events have for Dante as a character encountering them one after
another and the meaning they have for him as the scribe of memory working from
their totalized configuration in the book of memory, with full knowledge of the
final end of the story.
Through the unknown, unremembered gate

(T.S.Eliot, Little Gidding, v)

4 Debate with Harrison

Contrary to my emphasis on the inextricably literary and specifically lyrical


mediation of the religious experience of Beatrice, Harrison asserts the absolute
priority of Dantes experience of Beatrice as a woman rather than as a beatifier: in
its immediacy, stripped of subsequent sublimations and poeticizing interpretations,
it is for him fundamentally an erotic rather than a religious experience. But what is
this an inference from? What are its grounds as an assertion? Does not the poetic
enterprise just as often, or possibly always, co-opt or invent experience that suits
it? And is any experience, once it has been framed in poetic form, without which
articulation it would begin undergoing modification immediately, what it is apart
from poetry?
Harrisons realistic way of construing the relation between Dantes poetry
and its referential content is certainly possible, but not inevitable.33 Indeed one
whole strain of criticism has been built on precisely the contrary assumption that
Beatrice never was a real woman at all. Harrisons assumptions represent a decision
as to what counts as really real for him, or perhaps for everyone in his view. Yet even
he admits that the visionary quality of the experiences Dante recounts blurs the
line between the real and the imaginary: It is difficult to determine the difference
in status between Dantes actual perceptions of Beatrice in the Vita nuova and his
various dreams, visions, and hallucinations (p.172). However, in spite of practical
difficulties, the distinction in principle is not called into question, and Harrisons
aim is to isolate and recover the original perception, thereby going back to the
things themselves as in Edmund Husserls guiding slogan (zurck zu den Sachen
selbst) for the procedure of the phenomenological reduction.

354 the italianist 31 2011

I am not claiming that Harrisons hermeneutic biases are wrong. I simply


want to identify them as hermeneutic biases, so that it will be clear that his
conclusions are not yielded simply by the text on its own terms. I think Harrisons
biases are likely to be shared more generally among American Dante scholars and
literary critics than my own. Nevertheless, the hermeneutics of faith should not
be lost sight of in the interpretation of an author for whom a religious faith was
paramount, as it ostensibly was for Dante and even if this were only ostensibly
so. Much of the truly exceptional experience and insight made accessible by Dante
would be lost together with these hermeneutic practices, which Dante himself
initiated with regard to his own works.
An important advantage to a hermeneutic approach embracing the
hermeneutics of existence as well as of the text is that it makes Dantes faith not
an encumbrance to his vision of reality, but its very essence. We do not need to
discount what was important to Dante in order to carry out our own reading of
the effectual meaning of his perceptions, as if the perception and its meaning were
isolable from each other. To try to interpret Dante on the basis of his Catholic faith
is an interpretive gamble, but so is any critical methodology, whether declared
or implicit.34
Taking Harrisons own approach, we should ask, what is the status of
inferences about the genesis of a poem? Evidently genesis as such, the origin, is
epistemologically beyond our grasp as readers. Still, our engagement with a poem
may lead to constructions referring to its hypothetical origins. And yet this inevitably
entails a hermeneutic process of entering into relation with a work, not a detached
scientific analysis or perception of an object. Harrison has brought contemporary
philosophical methodologies into contact with the thirteenth-century text. He is
engaged in philosophical hermeneutics, where questioning a work must involve
also questioning ones own being in relation to the work. Harrison would like to
get at the work itself, but in actual fact he is dealing with the work as acted upon by
certain select instruments, notwithstanding his statement in the preface: In what
follows I try to confront the Vita nuova on its own terms and at the same time to
avoid the hermeneutic trap of Dantology (p.ix).
I agree with Harrison that we must understand Dantes representations
ontologically, but this is not because of what they represent, purportedly a real
woman, but rather because of what they are: artifacts of an existential-poetic
act. Dantes experience of a real woman, if that is what it was, comes to light in
literature. It is counterproductive to try to go behind the literary veil, which is the
enabling condition of the experience such as it exists for us (and for Dante too).
What if historical documents regarding Beatrice and even her encounters with
Dante were to be discovered? Could this add to our understanding of Dantes
experience of Beatrice, except by contributing to the ensemble of texts surrounding

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 355

her? It would certainly not give us any privileged knowledge of the real significance
of the Beatrice of the Vita nuova.
In Harrisons view, Beatrice inspires the poems in the sense that the poem
incorporates the animations of her presence into its own new life, and poetic
language becomes in some sense authenticated and substantiated by virtue of its
genesis (p.30). Genesis as such is hermeneutically indigestible, which may be why
Harrison likes it so much even though, in saying genesis, I have named nothing
other than the Christian mytho-poetic interpretation of existence par excellence,
as elaborated beginning from the homonymous book of the Bible. What I object to
is speaking of the genesis of the poem as a known from which inferences about the
poem can be drawn, since such genesis as may be inferred comes to us as readers
filtered through the poem itself or through prose glosses which can hardly be
relied on as independent sources.
Moreover, to assert the primacy of perception is to box reality into the
experience of a subject, an epistemological, a perceiving subject, rather than one
involved in the world, its perceptions being secondary reflections with regard to
the reality it lives. What is perceived is not in the first instance perceptions, I affirm
with Heidegger and Aristotle (implicitly) and against the whole cast of modern
philosophy since Descartes. As Heidegger writes, in overturning the general
epistemological bias of modern philosophy: Much closer to us than all sensations
are things themselves. 35
Whereas Harrison talks about the primacy of perception in Dantes
encounter with Beatrice, Dante insists relentlessly on the symbolic characteristics
of each encounter he relates. Dante presents appearances whose meaning is
mysterious. Harrison begins with the assumption, informed by the Freudian
revolution (which is itself at bottom nothing but a hermeneutic method based
on its own type of revelation from unconscious psychological depths36), that
the true meaning, il verace giudicio, of Dantes poetry is the body of Beatrice.
However, as readers and interpreters we are in any case dealing with visions
written in a book rather than with vision or perception of physical bodies. Dante
does make use of the Platonic criterion of immediate intuitive seeing of truth, yet
he re-inscribes it within a hermeneutic context of a linguistically related event.
What you cannot see about Beatrice (or about Christ, for that matter) is that she is
a miracle. This conclusion is reached through hermeneutic methods, for example,
through the deciphering of the nines. For the meaning of existence (even of any
given individual existence) is not primarily perceived, but is rather interpreted;
it is not given to perception, nor can it just be any sort of given at all, without
belying the freedom which is so fundamentally constitutive of human existence.
For this reason, the meaning of human existence can never simply be perceived; it
must rather be decided and enacted. Understanding revelation in existential terms
need not stop with the primacy of perception, as Harrison would have it, but leads

356 the italianist 31 2011

on to the risk and decision of interpretation, such as it has been lived and relived
by believers in all ages.
The prose ragioni show that the poems are indeed verbalizations of existential
data. Without the ragioni the poems would be contextualized only by a literary and
rhetorical tradition rather than by an individual life story. By virtue of the prose
they become the voice of an individual existence. In the Commedia, Dante will
succeed in making his poetry the story of his personal existence rather than just a
rhetorical performance, and he will do so without recourse to a prose complement
but simply by incorporating the story into the lyric. He will thus succeed in making
the I of his poetry not a conventional lyric subject but a thoroughly individualized,
historicized persona coinciding (at least by the end) with himself as author.
To this extent, the function of the prose is to ground the poems in a personal
history. This is quite different from the function attributed to it by Harrison, who
construes the prose as an overcoming of the poetry in the direction of a narrative
openness, whereas the static closure of lyric synchrony is left to Petrarch to be
played out to its last gasps. And yet poetry remains absolutely essential in Dantes
life-story as he tells it both in the Vita nuova and in the Commedia: the lyric would
seem to be anything but overcome, for example, in Dantes review of his poetic
career in Purgatorio xxiv, where the dolce stil novo is first defined. It is through
poetry that the meaning of Dantes experience is realized and communicated.
Although the prose describes the existential circumstances which purportedly gave
rise to the visions and, consequently, to the poems recording those visions, in some
sense the original event must equally be considered to be writing itself a sort of
incarnation of the Word in Dantes individual existence. This sense of poetry as
the lyrical expression of an individual life originates in and with the Vita nuova as
autobiographical poetic text.
The I which speaks in the pages of the Vita nuova from its opening phrases,
as already implied in la mia memoria and outspoken in io trovo, sets itself into
a hermeneutic relation with the story it tells. The I finds the words of the story
it is going to tell written in the book of its memory. It is perfectly ordinary for the
writer of a story, especially an autobiographical story, to stand in a hermeneutic
relation to his material. Such an author unavoidably interprets what he remembers
in telling his story, whether this interpretation is written directly into his retelling
of his memoires or is stated as a commentary delivered from the distance which
separates a telling of what is remembered from its actual occurrence. But in the case
of the Vita nuova, Dante treats his memory as a book. Thus, as author, he interprets
not only the past but, more immediately, a linguistically formulated memory of the
past: the words written (scritte le parole) in the book of his memory (libro de la
mia memoria). In this sense, words are the source of the story the Vita nuova tells.
In the first instance, those words are the poems Dante transcribes into the pages
of the Vita nuova.

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 357

Are the poems within the book also to be understood as products of


hermeneutic endeavour? They arise out of situations described in the prose,
allegedly. As such, the prose provides a gloss on them. But do they in turn, prior
to their anthologizing and narrativizing, hermeneuticize the situations out of
which they allegedly arise? Interpretation does not necessarily move from the less
to the more plain and prosaic. More fundamentally, it consists in the verbalization
of experience or being.37 And that is exactly what the poems do. By supplying the
experiential situations out of which each speaks, the scribe of the new life enables
us to read and understand them as verbalizations of an individuals experience.
This is perhaps the greatest generic novelty of the Vita nuova. The prosimetric
form has august precedents like Boethiuss Consolationes, but the verse in this
as in other models is less the expression of individual experience than a flower of
conventionalized rhetoric. Its poetry is more philosophical (impersonal and about
universal truths) than confessional and existential.
Harrison might object that such a reading encloses the poet within a solipsistic
circle in which writing feeds only on writing. We agree that what is special about
Dante, relative to Petrarch and Cavalcanti, is his access to transcendence, which
for Harrison means that his writing incorporates his experience of an actual
woman. Yet is that what Dante would want to call access to transcendence? It
is transcendence only of the presumed self-enclosure of the self; as such, it still
constitutes a form of remaining grounded in the immediacy of the empirically given,
which is from another point of view a complete denial of transcendence. Only from
a modern perspective, in which access to otherness has become problematic, if
not impossible, due to a starting position in Cartesian subjectivity, for which the
external world is known only by representations, does the openness to an ordinary
encounter in mundane space-time with the perceived bodily form of a human being
count as the true and authentic form of transcendence (transcendent exteriority
as Harrison terms it; p.96). Accordingly, what is transcended here would seem to
be only a wholly modern notion of self-enclosure.38
In the Middle Ages, transcendence was typically thought to pass rather
by an inward channel, and writing as a tool of inward search and a record of
inward contemplative experience might be a more important means of access
than sighting a beloved person, or more exactly the body of a beloved person,
in external space. Harrisons point of view remains circumscribed within an
epistemological framework, wherein consciousness is hemmed in by its own
representations, as indeed his language about Beatrices body as a noumenon
betrays. Everything of which one is immediately conscious, on epistemological
analysis, turns into a perception or representation, and the problem thus becomes
that of access to otherness.
The epistemological point of view has become particularly exacerbated in
the West since Descartes and the rise of a scientific world-view. Of course, there

358 the italianist 31 2011

were forms of epistemological entrapment in the Middle Ages, and Cavalcanti, as


Harrison shows, seems a case in point. Nevertheless, Dante represents a crucial
alternative, and it is hermeneutic in character. Not knowing the other as an object
of perception but relating through the word to an otherness that cannot be directly
perceived is the way of transcendence proper to Dantes Christian medieval culture
based especially on the technique of lectio divinis the meditative and interpretive
reading of sacred texts.
Dantes access to transcendence concerns the revelation of a meaning in his
personal experience, one centred on an absolutely meaningful event the advent
within it of an extraordinary woman who is actually much more than just a woman
to him: she redefines the whole nature of his experience. He need not strive to
know her body as a noumenon, for the body is in any case but a sign to be read (the
more so for being so erotically charged), and noumena are philosophical fictions
standing for epistemologys self-enclosure against revelation, which passes rather
via relations and their hermeneusis.39 Thus, on the basis of perception and its
alleged primacy, Harrison can only reach the conclusion that revelation does not
take place within the Vita nuova, but is deferred into the future.
What this approach misses is that revelation actually has taken place
and it has occurred, moreover, by the instrumentality of the lyric rather than by
overcoming the lyrical impulse. Moreover, after the Vita nuova, Dante will continue
to witness to the revelation personally conferred on him in the person of Beatrice,
and his witness will be his poetry. Granted, the end of the Vita nuova announces
an interval, a temporary suspension of his activity of writing, in order that he may
come into more adequate means of poetic expression. But this suspension is not a
surrender to an indefinitely hypothetical future. The future in which he will be able
to speak more worthily of her (parlare pi degnamente di lei) becomes concretely
actual in the Commedia; and a more abundant fulfillment of the promise tendered
at the end of the Vita nuova could hardly be imagined. But even without looking
ahead to Dantes magnum opus, there is still no reason to think that the language
promised at the end of the Vita nuova is likely to be prose rather than a new and
perhaps an eminently lyrical type of poetry.
By removing revelation outside the bounds and placing it after the end of the
Vita nuova, thus projecting it into a hypothetical future, Harrison acutely analyses
one aspect, the not yet, of the eschatological temporality that Dante lives by virtue
of his personal revelation.40 This is simply a particular enactment of the general
Christian revelation, which in turn is personal for every Christian. But Harrison
loses the other aspect of Dantes witness, the already, the revelation of divinity in
Beatrice, enshrined in the Vita nuovas lyrics just as the New Testament hymns
celebrate Christ as having lived and died and risen to new life.
Now this loss may be counted as gain by Harrison, for it may be that he
does not believe that such revelation of divinity has actually occurred. And hence

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 359

the limiting of the revelation to future hypothesis and hyperbole would be a most
welcome demystification. But let us be clear that here a decision has been made as
to what is or is not possible to be revealed to humans by God. Harrison has declined
to believe (or at least to suspend disbelief) in something that Dante, together with
the evangelists, invites us to believe.41 The different understandings of this literary
text of Dantes that Harrison and I respectively propose are predicated on different
decisions of faith or of non-faith.
Harrisons reading reflects a particular hermeneutic decision vis--vis the
text; it is not simply confronting the text on its own terms. What we read in the
text of the Vita nuova is what we have chosen to believe about the possibilities
for ourselves, as for Dante, of really attaining to a new life. This is to suggest that
the text has been not only freed from Dantes hermeneutic guidelines by Harrison
but has, at the same time, been subjected to Harrisons own. We need to recognize
that there is no access to the text on its own terms that would be immune to our
personal hermeneutic biases, and that the text cannot be understood neutrally.
We can decide to believe what the text witnesses to and thereby risk losing our
scholarly objectivity or we can decide to bracket such religious conviction and
decision. But in either case our decision will radically determine the text as we
encounter it and the possibilities of understanding and self-understanding that the
text holds out to us.
What makes Dantes story so perennially compelling is surely his reenactment of the founding event of the Christian revelation in his own life. That
transcendent divinity should condescend to reveal itself in incarnate form was
the germ and genius of the religion for which Dante became an ideologue and
propagandist not to say a prophet, which would be to espouse his biases and
my own. Dante apprehended the event of incarnate revelation of divinity not just
through apostolic testimony, as had been the norm for thirteen centuries, but also
in the presence in the flesh of a person who became his lifes centre and saviour.
Such was the essence of revelation as Christianity conceived it, and Dante realized
this essence in arguably the most concrete imaginative form possible. The fact that
this incarnational revelation took the shape of a woman reflects the fact that the
relation to woman had come to represent practically the highest possibility of loving
in the culture to which Dante was heir, at least within the literary conventions of
poetry about love, perhaps as a result of the influence of that very Christianity onto
which this courtly love tradition had been grafted. Under these circumstances, a
personal revelation in the flesh, which was the way of Christian revelation, could
be most convincingly realized in the figure of a beloved woman.42
In my beginning is my end.

(T.S.Eliot, East Coker, i)

360 the italianist 31 2011

5 An objection and conclusion

It might be objected to my argument for poetry as the generative source of narrative


that Dante himself explicitly asserts the contrary, in chapter xxv, when he declares
that poetic figuration is justified only on the basis of an independently demonstrable
prose sense (intendimento), of which the figure is merely the garment (vesta):
since it would be a great shame for anyone who made rhymes with poetic figures if,
later, when asked, he did not know how to strip his words of their figurative dress,
so that they had their true meaning (per che grande vergogna sarebbe a colui
che rimasse cose sotto vesta di figura o di colore rettorico, e poscia, domandato,
non sapesse denudare le sue parole da cotale vesta, in guisa che avessero verace
intendimento; xxv. 10).
However, it is crucial to observe that Dante actually conceives of the poetic
figure as being offered first. Only later (poscia), if asked, must the poet be able
to deliver the true meaning of the figure in terms which Dante presumes would be
non-figurative but which a more modern literary theory might well consider to be
necessarily figurative as well especially if, after Vico and Nietzsche, we no longer
necessarily assume that language can be anything but figurative.43
In any case, on Dantes own account, the prose version of poetic (or figural)
meaning in fact comes after, even though Dante here seems to assert its priority.
His own rhetoric assumes that in actual fact the poetry comes first, and then its
sense is drawn out later in prose. This is implied again in the phrase: worthy is the
[vernacular] rhymer to do the same [i.e. to use personification, like the Latin poets],
yet not without a reason but only with some reason that afterwards it is possible
to open up in prose (degno lo dicitore per rima di fare lo somigliante [i. e. use
personification, like li poete], ma non sanza ragione alcuna, ma con ragione la
quale poi sia possibile daprire per prosa).
Thus Dantes statement disguises an acknowledgement that poetry and figural
language are originary articulations of reality and direct expressions of experience,
even while conceding that it must be possible to interpret them subsequently in
prose. Indeed, the ragioni which Dante offers to denude the sense of his poems
hardly render the figures in the poems superfluous adornment, vesta. In practice,
his poetry is inextricably entrenched in figural modes of expression. His literary
theory at this point is somewhat constricted with respect to his manifest creation
as a poet. One can see the spectrous rationalism of a Scholastic philosophy trying
inadequately to account for the prodigious creations of a live poetic imagination.
Dante also gives another more profound account of the ground of poetic
figuration than this rather Scholastic notion of its being the dress or vestment of
a literal meaning. He suggests that figuration has an existential ground, when he
notes that the figure of Love was absorbed into him, Dante, the poet: Then I took
so great a part of him | that he disappeared, and I could not tell how (Allora presi

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 361

di lui s gran parte, | chelli disparve, e non maccorsi come; ix. 12). Or if the less
suspect (though also less clear) prose version should be preferred, in the context of
answering this objection, so as to avoid the petitio principi of arguing for poetrys
originariness from poetry: this imagination of mine suddenly disappeared due to
the very great portion of himself that Love seemed to give me (disparve questa mia
imaginazione tutta subitamente per la grandissima parte che mi parve che Amore
mi desse di s; ix. 7).
Dante implicitly acknowledges here that the figure of Love, under whose
sign he labours as a love-poet, in fact derives from his own existential reality and
disappears back into it. But this (new) existence of Dante itself depends on that
of Beatrice, and accordingly on Love, who comes to be incorporated also into her.
Beatrice is later called Love on account of her great similarity with him (E chi
volesse sottilmente considerare, quella Beatrice chiamerebbe Amore, per molta
somiglianza che ha meco; xxiv. 5).
Clearly, then, poetic figuration derives from existential reality rather than
being strictly a function of prose sense. Dante embraces this view of language as
manifestation of reality rather than just a sign that is meaningless apart from a
convention assigning it true meaning (verace intendimento) also in his espousal
of the principle: Nomina sunt consequentia rerum (xiii. 4). That Names are
consequences of things is turned from a conventional juridical dictum into a theory
of ontological revelation in Dantes appropriation of it. The key example of this is
Beatrices name, which we learn at the very outset is a consequence of the effect of
her presence upon others, namely, that she blesses them and was called Beatrice
even by many who did not know her name (fu chiamata da molti Beatrice li quali
non sapeano che si chiamare; ii. 1). If names and language follow from things,
they are not just arbitrary signs. The intention which their user could be held liable
to make explicit would be an existential testimony of ontological experience of
being blessed through a relation to this woman.
The inherent logic of Dantes whole libello is to ground poetry in existence.
Having supplied an account of the life situation out of which the poems arise, Dante
has already disclosed their true meaning. This is why he can declare that the verace
giudicio or true meaning of his dream is now manifest to all (ora manifestissimo
a li pi semplici), even though the dreams symbolism remains notoriously obscure
to interpreters, since he has indeed made manifest the circumstances in his personal
life which gave rise to the dream.
The great breakthrough of the Vita nuova, I submit, is not so much breaking
out of the lyric circle into narrative linearity but rather grounding the lyric in life.
By contextualizing his lyric poems with prose descriptions of all that led up to
their being written, Dante makes us understand his poems as personal expressions
of his real-life experience. How much more existentially dynamic this is than the
troubadour chanson can be appreciated from Paul Zumthors description of the

362 the italianist 31 2011

latter as un mode de dire entirement et exclusivement rfr un je qui, pour


navoir souvent dautre existence que grammaticale, nen fixe pas moins le plan et
les modalits du discours, hors de toute narration.44 The new life may indeed be
as Italian interpreters like Sanguineti and De Robertis like to suggest a new life for
the lyric.45 I feel it must certainly be that also. Still, the lyric as it occurs in the Vita
nuova is inscribed into the life-story of Dante, and its newness is a participation in
the total renewal of Dantes life. Thus the lyric is renovated within the movement
of an existential transformation or renaissance. And the prosaic account of the
transformation that the lyrics embody and express does not supersede but rather
serves the lyrics hermeneutically, providing them with an existential interpretation.
The prose makes explicit the interpretation of existence that the poems already
inscribe in the more elusive, musical, and revelatory terms of lyric.
I have counterpointed46 this defence of the permanent centrality of the
lyric mode in Dantes project as poet with verses from Four Quartets (in contrast
with Harrisons frequent evocation of Ezra Pounds Cantos), for right from its
title this poem programmatically signals the essentially musical, lyrical nature of
poetic vision still in modern times. The very title Four Quartets offers two figures
of sameness, one phonic (four rhymes with quar in quar-tets) and the other
arithmetic (the concept of the number four is embedded in both words), which
make this title an epitome of the closed, self-reflexive structure of lyric in general.
But such figural closure does not exist merely unto itself; it articulates and makes
available for application to existence a structure of significance; it provides a
paradigm through which existence can become comprehensible and be consciously
appropriated by an individual subject. It thus enables literary representation
originating in lyrical expression to become the hermeneutic vehicle of a revelation
of transcendent meaning in the existence of an individual, which is exactly what
the Vita nuova claims to be.

Notes
1

Dante, La Vita nuova (Florence: Societ Dantesca Italiana,

Bible quotations throughout are from the Authorized

1960). Roman numerals refer to chapter numbers in this

Version (1611), checked against and corrected by The

edition, which follows the text, as well as the chapter and

Greek New Testament, 2nd edn (New York: United

paragraph divisions, of the critical edition of Michele Barbi

Bible Societies, 1968) and the Bibliorum Sacrorum iuxta

(Florence: R.Bemporad, 1932). Translations are my own.

Vultagam Clementinam Nova Editio (Vatican: Typis

The analogy between Christ and Beatrice from which this

Polyglottis, 1959), where necessary.

essay begins constitutes a central axis of the influential

interpretation of the Vita nuova proposed by Charles

Heterodoxy of Dante (London: Faber & Faber, 1932).

S.Singleton, An Essay on the Vita nuova (Cambridge,

So Gertrude Leigh, The Passing of Beatrice: A Study in the


The relationship between Beatrice and Christ is pursued

MA: Harvard University Press, 1949). Beatrice becomes,

theologically in terms of Transfiguration and Ascension

moreover, an Advent of Christ in the Earthly Paradise for

by Oliver Davies, Dantes Commedia and the Body of

Singleton in Journey to Beatrice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard

Christ, in Dantes Commedia: Theology as Poetry, ed.

University Press, 1958).

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 363

by Vittorio Montemaggi and Matthew Treherne (Notre

now updated the essay, particularly its scholarship, thanks

Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010), pp.161-79

to the stimulation provided by Zygmunt Baranskis

essays

(especially pp.171-74).

on the Vita nuova and his personal encouragement and

See, for example, Mario Pazzaglio, Vita nuova, in

comments.

Enciclopedia dantesca, ed. by Umberto Bosco, 6 vols

12

(Rome: Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana, 1970-78), v,

about overcoming poetic solipsism, and making reference

1086-96 (especially p.1088), and Guglielmo Gorni, Vita

to Harrisons treatment, is proposed by Mara Rosa

Nova, Libro delle amistadi e della prima etade, in

Menocal, Writing in Dantes Cult of Truth: From Borges to

Dante prima della Commedia (Florence: Cadmo, 2001),

Boccaccio (Durham: Duke University Press, 1991): Above

pp.133-47.

all, the Vita nuova, the story so charmingly called the New

Il sole 24 Ore, 26 March 1995, p.36.

Suggestive remarks on the New Testament model for

figural interpretation in the Vita nuova are made by


Michelangelo Picone, La Vita nuova fra autobiografia
e tipologia, in Dante e le forme dellallegoresi, ed. by
Michelangelo Picone (Ravenna: Longo, 1987), pp.59-69
(p.65). Olivia Holmes, Assembling the Lyric Self: Authorship
from Troubadour Song to Italian Poetry Book (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 2000) highlights in Dantes
libello a figural reading of literary history that he learned
from the Gospels, especially the Gospel of John (p.120)

A kindred reading of the Vita nuova as fundamentally

Life, is in fact the story of the death the purposeful and


necessary death for Dante of the old ways of reading
and writing, the old kind of Literature, that had proved so
disappointing (p.18). What Dante would have rejected by
this account, and what in any case has become a motif of
rejection in our day, is the fact that the greatest obsession
of troubadour poetry is itself (p.22). This self-reflexive,
essentially lyrical structure is what Menocal and Harrison
alike reject, thinking that in doing so they are following
Dantes cues.
13

Teodolinda Barolini, Cominciandomi dal principio

and notes Dantes superimposition of the Gospel story

infino a la fine (V.N., xxiii. 15): Forging Anti-Narrative

onto the conventional love story of the vernacular lyric

in the Vita Nuova, in La gloriosa donna de la mente:

sequence (p.126). Guglielmo Gorni, Il nodo della lingua e

A Commentary on the Vita Nuova, ed. by Vincent

il Verbo dAmore (Florence: Olschki, 1981), pp.39-45 and

Moleta (Florence: Olschki, 1994), pp.119-40, likewise

155-58, documents the books Scriptural and especially

argues for a dialectical contaminatio between lyric and

Johannine echoes, as does also Domenico De Robertis, Il

narrative, resulting in narrativized lyric and lyricized

libro della Vita nuova, 2nd edn (Florence: Sansoni, 1970).

(dechronologized) narrative, from the Vita nuova to the

For an overview of basic results of the critical approach

to the synoptic gospels, see Carl R.Holladay, A Critical

Paradiso.
14

This Singletonian view is advocated very ably also by

Introduction to the New Testament: Interpreting the

Barbara Nolan, The Vita nuova and Richard of St. Victors

Meaning and Message of Jesus (Nashville: Abingdon Press,

Phenomenology of Vision, Dante Studies, 92 (1974), 35-

2005); tienne Charpentier, Pour lire le Nouveau Testament

52: We can also confirm the function of all the visions of

(Paris: Les ditions du Cerf, 1983); and Fredrick C. Grant,

the libello as prophetic inscriptions commenting on the

The Gospels: Their Origin and Their Growth (New York:

narrators historia and predicting its issue in a final blinding

Harper and Brothers, 1957). Some radical perspectives are

revelation of beatitude (p.35).

argued for by Thomas Sheehan, The First Coming: How the

15

Kingdom of God Became Christianity (New York: Random

de lide de Rvlation, in La rvlation (Brussels: Facults

House, 1986).

Universitaires Saint Louis, 1977), pp. 15-53, translated

10

Robert Harrison, The Body of Beatrice (Baltimore: Johns

Hopkins University Press, 1988).


11

My critical Note on the book appears in Rivista di studi

italiani, 6.ii (1988), 78-82. The present essay was originally


written at the same time and for a course with Professor
Harrison, while I was a graduate student at Stanford. I have

Comparable in this regard is Paul Ricoeur, Hrmeutique

as Toward a Hermeneutic of the Idea of Revelation, in


Essays in Biblical Interpretation, ed. by Lewis S.Mudge
(Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1980), pp. 73-118, although
Ricoeurs theoretical inferences are different and are drawn
from analysis of the interaction of literary and legal genres
in the Torah.

364 the italianist 31 2011

16

The Complete Poetry and Prose of William Blake, ed. by

David W.Erdman (Berkeley: University of California Press,


1982).
17

The Vita Nuovas poetry is understood as aiming at a

21

Dante himself, at the outset of Book ii (chapter i) of De

vulgari eloquentia, explicitly stresses the priority of poetry


to prose in the history of literary language.
22

Robert Alter, The Art of Biblical Poetry (New York: Basic

kind of theological revelation also by Harrisons teacher,

Books, 1985) (pp.37 and 39).

Giuseppe Mazzotta, The Language of Poetry in the Vita

23

nuova, Rivista di studi italiani, 1.i (1983), 3-14. The

I use the term myth in a sense informed by the theology

of Rudolph Bultmann, Theologie des Neuen Testaments,

distinctive emphases on the enigmatic nature of the

9th edn (Tbingen: J.C.B.Mohr, 1984 [1948]). In English,

Vita Nuova, or the narratives stubborn refusal to yield

see especially New Testament and Mythology and other

its secret, on the irreducible particularity of the oneiric

Basic Writings, ed. by Schubert Ogden (Philadelphia:

experience, on Beatrices body in its materiality and

Fortress Press, 1984).

mortality, on the fatal rivalry with Cavalcanti, and on the


openness of the Vita Nuovas end, making it the book of
the future, are all to be found already in Mazzottas essay.
Harrisons anti-theological reading shows up in this light as
originating in Mazzottas (and Dantes) theological vision.
18

The fundamental importance of the Bible as prosimetric

model for Dantes youthful literary masterpiece has been


emphasized recently by Zygmunt Baranski.
In Lascio
cotale trattato ad altro chiosatore: Form, Literature,
and Exegesis in Dantes Vita nova, volume in memory
of Amilcare A.Iannucci, ed. by Margaret Kilgour and
Elena Lombardi (Toronto: University of Toronto Press,
forthcoming), Baranski
proposes re-visioning the special
relationship between Gods book and Dantes libro,
maintaining that the Bible is without doubt the Vita

24

See Raymond E.Brown, The Birth of the Messiah: A

Commentary on the Infancy Narratives in the Gospels


of Matthew and Luke, new edn (New York: Doubleday,
1999), pp.143-53. I treat this in greater detail in Gospel
as Personal Knowing: Theological Reflections on not Just a
Literary Genre, forthcoming.
25

In a different way, this is suggested also by Mario

Pazzaglia, La Vita nuova fra agiografia e letteratura,


Letture classensi, vi (Ravenna: Longo, 1977), pp.189210, and by Vittore Branca, Poetica del rinnovamento e
tradizione agiografica nella Vita Nuova, in Studi in onore di
Italo Siciliano (Florence: Olschki, 1966), pp.123-48.
26

Lucia Lazzerini, Letteratura medievale in lingua doc

(Modena: Mucchi, 2001).


Gregory B.Stone emphasizes that the implied

novas primary source. Starting from the phrase the

27

book of memory in the incipit of the Vita nuova, Baranski

hermeneutic theory formulated in the Vita nuova results

finds a key to the libellos fundamental dependence on

in a radical subjectivism (Dantes Averroistic Hermeneutics

Scripture in Augustines De civitate Dei, 18. 35, which

(On Meaning in the Vita Nuova), Dante Studies, 112

interprets Malachis librum memoriae as signifying the

(1994), 133-59 (p.134)).

New Testament. Baranski


develops his theses also in The

28

C.S.Lewis, Myth Become Fact, in God in the Dock, ed.

Roots of Dantes Plurilingualism: Hybridity and Language

by Walter Hooper (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1970): By

in the Vita nova, in Dantes Plurilingualism, Authority,

becoming fact it does not cease to be myth: that is the

Knowledge, Subjectivity, ed. by Sara Fortuna, Manuele

miracle (pp.66-67).

Gragnolati, and Jrgen Trabant (Oxford: Legenda, 2010),


pp.98-121 (especially pp.111 onwards).
19

P.Mauro Lconi, La preghiera di Ges e la Liturgia

29

This dimension of symbolic communication is explored,

for example, by Susanne K.Langer in Feeling and Form: A


Theory of Art (New York: Scribner, 1953). A theory of art as

cristiana, nei vangeli sinottici (Rome: Associazione Biblica

lyric intuition was developed famously also by Benedetto

Italiana, 1985) contains interesting reflections on the re-

Croce.

deployment of lyric traditions in the gospel narratives.


20

Other examples are i Samuel 2. 1-10; Isaiah 38. 10-20;

30

A guide to the vast critical literature on dreams, visions,

imaginings, fantasies, etc., with its fine distinctions

44. 23-28; Jeremiah 15. 15-25, Daniel 2. 20-23; 3. 26-45;

between degrees and kinds of reality and with special

and 52-90; Jonah 2. 2-9; Tobit 13. See Charpentier, Pour

attention to their reflexive properties as all this relates to

lire LAncien Testament.

Dante, is Zygmunt G. Baranski,


Il carattere riflessivo dei tre

Franke Dantes New Life and the New Testament 365

sogni purgatoriali, in Sole nuovo, luce nuova: Saggi sul

Predicament of 17th-Century Tragedy, Romanische

rinnovamento culturale in Dante (Turin: Scriptorium, 1996),

Forschungen, 105 (1993), 315-31.

pp.255-79.

39

31

An allusion to John 20. 29 (blessed are they that have

Hermeneutic phenomenology has in recent decades

opened towards religious revelation, even in a theological

not seen, and yet have believed), which reinforces the New

sense, particularly in the work of Michel Henry, Jean-Luc

Testament framing of Dantes witness concerning Beatrice,

Marion, and Jean-Louis Chrtien. This theological turn of

is detected in this passage by Bernard S.Levy, Beatrices

phenomenology from a rigorous emphasis on immanence

Greeting and Dantes Sigh in the Vita nuova, Dante

to a focus on the transcendent and invisible is delineated

Studies, 92 (1974), 57-58.

by Dominique Janicaud, Le tournant thologique de la

32

An excellent treatment of the subject is Jeffrey T.Schnapp,

phnomnologie franaise (Combas: LEclat, 1991). In

The Transfiguration of History at the Center of Dantes

English, see Janicaud, Chrtien, et al., Phenomenology

Paradiso (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986),

and the Theological Turn: The French Debate (New York:

pp.170-238.

Fordham University Press, 2000).

33

Rainer Warning, Imitatio und Intertextualitt: Zur

40

This peculiar, contradictory temporality of not yet and,

Geschichte lyrischer Dekonstruktion der Amortheologie:

at the same time, already defines the eschatological

Dante, Petrarca, Baudelaire, in sthetischer Schein, ed. by

existence of Christians, especially as it is apprehended by

Willi Oelmller (Paderborn: Schningh, 1983), pp.168-207,

Saint Paul in some of the earliest documents making up the

argues for the love lyrics own deconstruction of any such

New Testament, for example, Philippians 3. 11-14: Not as

direct apprehension of being, with reference specifically to

though I had already attained, either were already perfect:

the Vita nuova on pp.172-79.

but I follow after, if that I may apprehend that for which

34

The vital importance of specifically theological

approaches is strongly vindicated by Vittorio Montemaggi


and Matthew Treherne in the introduction to their edited
volume Dantes Commedia: Theology as Poetry, pp.1-13.
Also in this vein is Antonio Rossini, Il Dante sapienziale:
Dionigi e la bellezza di Beatrice (Pisa: Serra, 2009).
35

Heidegger, The Origin of the Work of Art, in Basic

Writings, ed. by D.Krell (New York: Harper & Rowe, 1977),


p.156.
36

I make this argument in Psychoanalysis as a

Hermeneutics of the Subject: Freud, Ricoeur, Lacan,


Dialogue: The Canadian Philosophical Review, 38 (1998),
65-81.
37

See Aristotle, On Interpretation, for the doctrine that any

also I am apprehended of Christ Jesus. As developed by


Rudolph Bultmann, this existential temporality became
fundamental to Heideggers thinking in Being and Time and
so to what can be called hermeneutic phenomenology
and its critique of classical (Cartesian) epistemology.
Giorgio Agamben applies this Pauline temporality to the
internal eschatology of the troubadour poem in Il tempo
che resta: un commento alla Lettera ai Romani (Turin:
Bollati Boringhieri, 2000), pp.77-84.
41

In Phenomenology of the Vita Nuova, Annali

ditalianistica, 8 (1990), 180-84, Harrison confirms his


choice to believe only in what can be directly perceived and
not in anything unseen, in explaining his phenomenological
approach as grounded in finitude (p.184). Thomas
C.Stillinger, reviewing Harrisons book in Italica 67.iii

signifying of the real, starting from a significant sound, such

(1990), 403-06, astutely identifies this credo as haunted

as a word, is interpretation (hermeneias).

by a vision of unmediated vision and questions the

38

Michel Foucault, Les mots et les choses (Paris: Gallimard,

adequacy of such a vision of truth (p.404). Harrison, in

1966) serves as a guide to delimit historically this

effect, literalizes the trope of unmediated vision, which in

specifically modern form of self-enclosure in a world of

religious revelation stands for a seeing through belief (as

representations: it pertains to the epistemological subject

more immediate and intuitive than chains of reasoning).

newly constructed in the classical age in the seventeenth

Understood religiously, such vision entails perception

century. I deal with precisely this issue, distinguishing

not just of discrete, finite objects but also, and more

a hermeneutic from an epistemological outlook, in

significantly, of their infinite ground or background.

Hermeneutic Catastrophe in Racine: The Epistemological

366 the italianist 31 2011

42

For Singleton, An Essay, the originality of the Vita nuova

45

Edoardo Sanguineti, Per una lettura della Vita nuova,

was its proposing that a woman could be a revelation or,

in La Vita nuova (Milan: Garzanti, 1977). The Vita nuova

in other words, that the experience of courtly love could

remains centred in lyric also for Vincent Moleta, The Vita

lead to God rather than leading inevitably to religiously

nuova as a Lyric Narrative, Forum Italicum, 12.iii (1978):

motivated recantation.

369-90.

43

Persuasively linking such modern theories of language

46

The way in which the prose narrative validates the

with Dante and his humanist heritage is Ernesto Grassis

poems affective expression as authentic witness is subtly

La metafora inaudita (Palermo: Aesthetica, 1990) as well

analyzed by Sara Sturm-Maddox, The Pattern of Witness:

as The Claim of the Word and the Religious Significance

Narrative Design in the Vita Nuova, Forum Italicum, 12.iii

of Poetry: A Humanistic Problem, Dionysius, 8 (1984),

(1978), 216-32.

131-55.
44

Paul Zumthor, De la circularit du chant, Potique, 2

(1970), 129.

William Franke, Vanderbilt University, USA (williampfranke@yahoo.com)


Department of Italian Studies, University of Reading and Departments of Italian, University of Cambridge and University of Leeds

10.1179/026143411X13184933851895

Copyright of Italianist is the property of Maney Publishing and its content may not be copied or emailed to
multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users
may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen