Sie sind auf Seite 1von 17

Access Provided by University of California @ Berkeley at 01/31/13 4:24PM GMT

REPENTANCE AS A BODHISATTVA PRACTICE: WNHYO


ON GUILT AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Eun-su Cho
Department of Philosophy, Seoul National University

The Place of Freedom in a Deterministic Worldview


Determinism and freedom has been a much debated philosophical issue in the
Western philosophical tradition. St. Augustines Confessions, for example, established a long-held Christian theological view on the possession of free will, which
concerns the fate of human beings within a universe ruled by God. Given the specific
context in which the question arosewhy sin and human error occur in a world created by Godmany have held that Asian philosophies, and especially Buddhism, do
not have much relevance to the topic as their doctrines are based on a non-theistic
worldview. It may not even be right to ask the question in the context of the Buddhist
tradition, which denies the existence of a God or a mighty power controlling human
fate. Meanwhile, with the advance of scientific knowledge, the causally determined
nature of the physical and psychological world is becoming known. The question
hasbeen modified in contemporary Western philosophy so that it now concerns the
possibility of freedom when ones psychological states are all causally determined,
and whether freedom can be claimed given the deterministic understanding of our
experience. Even with its atheistic understanding of the existence of the world and
itsevents, it is still not too clear that a Buddhist perspective could engage in this discussion concerning the compatibility or incompatibility of determinism and moral
responsibility. This attitude might explain the scarcity of attempts at engaging the
Buddhist tradition in contemporary discussions of the issue.
In this light, Buddhism is known to hold a deterministic view of our existence.1
Mental states are considered to be caused by prior events, amidst a broader explanation of human existence as the combination of the five elements (skandhas) of body,
sensation, feeling, ideations, and consciousness. Buddhism argues that the world,
including humans, exists in such a way that things come into being and cease dependent on prior causes. The universe and human beings are just a causal series of psychophysical elements.
With this nonself doctrine in place, and physical and mental states understood as
being the result of prior events, are we really responsible for the actions that we perform? This has been a frequently asked question not only in early Buddhist texts such
as the Questions of King Milinda, but also in modern investigations of Buddhist
doctrine. For example, on the recent controversy in Australia over (secular) ethics
education being implemented for school children, which aroused heated criticism
from Christian churches, an Australian Buddhist progressive leader, Bhante Sujato,
commented thus: Our children need to learn ethics, not from any self-appointed

Philosophy East & West Volume 63, Number 1 January 2013 3954
2013 by University of Hawaii Press

39

authority, but by learning to listen to their own voice of conscience, to dialogue


with others, to accept different points of view, and to found ethics on a shared
humanity, not adherence to any religious dogma. He asserts that moral standards
come from the inner voice of conscience, not from an external so-called sacred and
religious authority. He seems to hold a view that Buddhism postulates the moral
conscience as something inherent in sentient beings. However, in light of the no-self
doctrine of Buddhism, namely that there is no soul or permanent self that could be
responsible for the actions that the person performs, could it be argued that moral
conscience universally and permanently exists, operating independently? This raises
a serious question whether the no-self doctrine negates moral responsibility.
However, Buddhists take responsibility seriously, even if they dont think there
are persons who are responsible. Not only are there voluminous Buddhist texts on
moral discipline delineating moral codes in detail, but the early Buddhist community conducted frequent uposatha meetings where they confessed their wrongdoings
in front of the community, and performed repentance ceremonies, pravra, which
took place at the end of summer retreats. Repentance presupposes responsibility. To
feel repentance is to feel bad about something that one acknowledges as ones own
act, and to resolve not to repeat it.
And the no-self doctrine itself has ethical implications of its own. As some Zen
masters put it, one may practice doing without doing, committing actions without
postulating a self or being conscious of ones self. Furthermore, when one is not
driven by selfish motivations with the knowledge of nonself, it makes selflessness and
altruism possible. Thus, these selfless actions are taught and encouraged withoutimplicating the question of who is going to be responsible for the actions committed.2
It is in this context that I would like to bring up the matter of guilt and repentance, by focusing on the writings of a seventh-century Korean Buddhist monk named
Wnhyo, who represents the epitome of East Asian Buddhist scholasticism. His text
will provide a way of investigating moral responsibility from an East Asian Buddhist
perspective.
Wnhyo and His Text on Repentance
Wnhyo (617686) is probably the most seminal Buddhist scholiast in Korea. As a
monk-scholar, he is renowned for not only his scholarly work but also his adventurous
and dramatic life path. He is known to have composed eighty treatises and com
mentaries, among which twenty works are extant, comprising the wide spectrum of
doctrinal development in East Asian Buddhism in the seventh century. This wasthe
most exciting period of Buddhist doctrinal development in East Asia, with Yogcra,
Madhyamaka, Tathgatagarbha, Huayen, Pure Land, and Precepts interpretations all
represented. His writings represent the culmination of a flourishing theoretical and
soteriological understanding of Buddhist thought in India and its adaptation in East
Asia.
The short text that we are analyzing, titled the Mahyna Repentance of the Six
Senses (Taesng yukchng chamhoe),3 composed of 1,073 Chinese characters in

40

Philosophy East & West

seventy verse lines, provides a useful example for our discussion of guilt and moral
responsibility in Buddhist philosophy. The text discusses the non-substantiality of
sentient beings and the actions or offenses they commit. Further, the text deals with
the consequences of wrongdoings: Wnhyo states that if you do not feel remorse or
shame, or repent your actions, even though the crimes you have committed are not
substantial, this will cause you to fall into hell. He calls up the metaphor of an illusory tiger created by magic that in turn swallows the magician. He also states the
need for repentance, and assures that repentance is related to staying mindful of
ones senses. Practicing being mindful of the senses will enable one to realize the
dharma-knti, a state of the non-arising of mental entities. The content of the text
delineates a bodhisattvas practice in terms of repentance.
Metaphysics and ethics are usually considered two separate areas of philosophy.
For Wnhyo, however, the two are deeply intertwined around the central concept
ofthe mind and the world that it creates. His ethics are based on the Madhyamaka
theory of the non-substantiality of entities, a metaphysical foundation and basis of a
theory of knowledge. Wnhyos ethics differs from ethics in the dimension of the
mundane world; his ethics are concerned with the realm of enlightenment, closely
related to metaphysical theories. According to him, metaphysical understanding is
another word for enlightenment and the act of repentance is nothing but the way
of religious practice geared toward enlightenment. The moral responsibility that
Wnhyo expresses in terms of remorse and guilt is to be achieved through understanding the metaphysical outlook on the world that he proposes.
For Wnhyo the practice of morality is not first and foremost a matter of behaving
in a moral manner. His life story, which is full of surprises and adventures, might
provide a backdrop to his differentiation of morality and moral actions. His biographies state that he had an enlightenment experience on his journey to China. He
took refuge from a storm in a sanctuary, but awoke thirsty in the middle of the night
and looked in the dark for water. Finding a bowl of water, he drank from it and, satisfied, went back to sleep. The next morning when he awoke, he found to his disgust
that the place where he had slept was in fact a crypt and that what he had taken to
be a bowl of water was actually stagnant water in a human skull. What he thought
was thirst-quenching the night before was disgusting now.
Wnhyo turned back from his journey to China, proclaiming that there was no
need to search for truth outside ones mind. Later, he was involved in an affair with a
widowed princess; the union produced a son, Sl Chong, one of the most famous
literati in Korean history, and this helped to seal his reputation as someone who transcended such conventional distinctions as secular and sacred. Although a man of
erudition, Wnhyo was notorious in his time for being a monk who frequented brothels and wine shops. After an illustrious career as a writer and Buddhist thinker, he
lived primarily as a mendicant, wandering the cities and markets as a street proselytizer. After the affair just mentioned he withdrew from being a monk and devoted
himself to proselytizing rather than taking on students or finding disciples who would
inherit his teachings. His later life as a mendicant is a performative interpretation of
Buddhist truth.

Eun-su Cho

41

Non-substantiality of Actions
Wnhyo begins the text by stating that sentient beings construct external objects;
with ego-minded thoughts of me and mine, they commit various actions due to
ignorance and erroneous views. Hindered by self-inflicted delusion, they do not see
or hear properly, just like hungry ghosts who, approaching a river, see fire (verses
1016). The actions we commit and the external objects we see are conceptual constructions. They do not really exist. Wnhyo uses Madhyamaka logic to establish the
non-substantiality and non-production of actions in the following verses.
22
Yet these offences do not really exist.
The clusters of conditions occurring together are provisionally named as action.
23
The actions are found neither in the conditions nor apart from the conditions.
Neither within nor outside, there is no third possibility.
24
Anything in the past no longer exists (whatever in the past is already gone).
Things existing in the future have not come forth; the present does not abide (what has
been produced does not abide).
25
Due to its not abiding, there is no production.
If it were existent previously, it cannot be [regarded as] being produced; if it were previously non-existent, what caused it to come forth?
26
If you say it was once non-existent and now became existent,
These two meanings are put together and called production.
27
At the time of non-existence this existence could not have been existing,
At the time of this present existence, there is no original non-existence existing.
28
Before and after cannot reach out to each other, and existence and non-existence cannot
meet.
If the two notions cannot be joined, how could there be production?
29
When the meaning of combining has already been disputed, its disintegration cannot
be established.
[They] cannot be put together or fallen apart, [thus they are] neither existent nor non-
existent.

42

Philosophy East & West

30
At the time of non-existence there is no existence, so in contrast to what could there be
non-existence?
At the time of existence, there is no non-existence, so for whom do we say that there is
existence?
31
Neither before nor after, neither existence nor non-existence can be posited.
32
You should know that actions are by nature originally not produced.
From the beginning, they could not have been produced,
33
Hence on which grounds can production be found?
Both production and non-production cannot be possible.
34
Moreover, saying that they cannot be possible is not possible.
Actions are of such nature, and likewise the Buddhas.

Wnhyo expounds that actions do not really exist: what we call actions are just
provisionally named concepts. Actions are not enduring, actions are not produced
because those events in the past, present, and the future do not abide. There are no
such things that can be called producings; actions are just conceptual constructions built up out of what occurs earlier and later.
He then, in verses 3538, argues that events are created neither from existence
nor from non-existence nor from both; nor do they occur without cause, so there is
no lack of causal production. Therefore, there is no such thing as actions being
committed. In the same manner, there is no such thing as receiving the result of
theactions. At the same time, there is no one who commits the transgressions, no
one to receive the result of the actions. There is no transgressor, no object that was
violated, nor the action of transgression; only by the confluence of the various factors
do the fruits, that is, actions, occur. Both person and action are negated. The persons
and the actions that they had committed are just a causal series of psychophysical
elements. Ones psychological states are all causally determined, commensurate
with a deterministic point of view. However, even though there is no self, when these
elements are arranged in certain ways, it is conventionally true that this is a person
who committed the crime. This is how nonself worksby use of the idea of a
causal series of psychophysical elements. Here Wnhyos argument could be interpreted as allowing a kind of compatibilist positionaccepting the validity of moral
responsibility and guilt while adhering to the nonself of persons and nonself of
elements.
Entities, or, in Buddhist terminology, dharmas, are devoid of inherent nature, or
svabhva in Madhyamaka Buddhism. In the earlier Abhidharma Buddhist develop-

Eun-su Cho

43

ment, the scholiast held that the entities we find in the ordinary world are composed
of parts, and so as wholes are devoid of intrinsic nature; like a chariot that consists of
its parts, a person does not have a self-nature. This was an attempt to explain the
nonself doctrine that the Buddha had expounded. However, the bhidharmakas held
that the atomic parts, the dharmas of which the whole consists and to which the
whole is to be reduced, do have intrinsic nature. For them the dharmas are ultimately
real, even though the whole, such as a chariot or a person, is not real but a mere
conceptual construction. Human existence is no more than a result of the combination of the five skandhas. This theory of the bhidharmakas was to be criticized by
Mdhyamikas, such as Ngrjuna in his Mlamadhyamakakrik.
Here Wnhyo not only negates the actions and substantial essence of persons,
he negates intrinsic nature and causal relations as well. He follows the Mahyna
doctrine of the emptiness of existence understood in the Madhyamaka way, as both
pudgala-nairtmya (selflessness of persons) and dharma-nairtmya (dharmas lack of
intrinsic nature). There is no inherent nature of dharmas: the causal relation lacks
substantiality; it, too, is devoid of self-nature. Wnhyo uses the first kind of emptiness
when he points out that persons are only to be found at the conventional level, notat
the ultimate level, so moral properties such as responsibility cannot be ultimatelyreal.
He goes further, however. The argument at verse 28, for instance, is to the effect
that the causal relation is itself conceptually constructed and so not ultimately real.
The argument is that since cause and effect could only exist at two different
times, they could never come into any kind of relation with one another, which is
what would be needed for a real causal connection. This is what makes what Wnhyo
is doing so radical. He is not just asserting the nonsubstantiality of the persons; he is
asserting the nonsubstantiality of everything whatever. It is mere conceptual construction all the way down. This means that determinism is not ultimately true either.
If it is true at all this is only because it is useful for us to think that way. There arent
any causal connections in the world apart from our ways of thinking about it. But
anaction is something I cause (or these skandhas cause). So there really arent any
actions.
Transgressions are specifically defined as follows.
18
Having been confused by ignorance (), I and other sentient beings committed countless transgressions ().
19
Those five heinous transgressions and the ten evil wrongdoings, there is nothing we
havent done.
Whether doing it oneself, getting someone else to do it, or finding joy in someone else
doing it,
20
Innumerable transgressions such as these, are beyond counting,
Are fully known by all the holy ones.4

44

Philosophy East & West

Thus,
21
Arousing profound shame and remorse for our past transgressions that we have committed,
We dare not repeat them in the future.

To feel guilt or shame is to accept responsibility. As such, for Wnhyo, the feeling of
shame is a reflection of moral consciousness, and why one must repent. Sentient
beings, with profound shame, should arise to the mind of enlightenment (bodhi-citta)
and sincerely practice repentance (kama) for the wrongdoings they had committed
from beginningless time. One should feel profound shame for the actions that had
been committed before, and they should not be repeated in the future.
Non-substantiality of Transgressions or Transgressors
Although transgressions do not have their own substantiality, they can make one
fallen; thus one has to repent. The following verses argue this.
39
If practitioners can contemplate reality in this way with a repentant attitude,
40
It is not possible to commit the four grave offenses and five heinous acts,
Just as empty space cannot be burnt by fire.
41
However, if you are not careful/mindful (, apramda), lack remorse and shame,
and are not able to know the true nature of the actions,
42
Even though transgressions lack the nature (svabhva) of criminality, you will still go to
hell (niraya),
Just like a magical tiger who in turn swallows up the magician who conjured him.
43
Therefore, before the Buddhas in the ten directions,
You should feel profound shame and remorse and perform this repentance.

Having said that there is no one to commit offenses and that no transgressions really
exist, then, would it be justifiable to feel guilty, remorseful, or repentant toward ones
own actions in this regard? Wnhyo says there is still a need to practice repentance.
In his language, repentance is nothing but knowing that the events and actions are
not really produced. Repentance is defined as understanding the absence of selfnature in the things and actions of the universeas understanding their nonsubstantiality or, in other words, their emptiness.
In light of the Buddhist no-self doctrine, is feeling guilty or remorseful justified? His answer would be this: we practice repentance not because I or this

Eun-su Cho

45

person has committed any transgressions; there is really no one who commits the
transgression. There is no one who is a criminal, nor is there a criminal attitude.
However, out of ignorance, one who still does not understand commits transgressions; for that person the transgression exists; the transgressor, the person, exists.
Such transgressions are what one is guilty of, should feel remorse for, for which
repentance should be made.
One has to make sure that that repentance is done in a way that conforms with
nonselfbecause ultimately there is no transgression or transgressor. Wnhyo says:5
44
When you do practice repentance, do it without [ego-involvement].
Just know the very nature of repentance.
45
When the wrongdoings you repent do not really exist,
Where could there exist a repenter?
46
Both repenter and what is to be repented of are not found,
Where can the action of repentance be found?

Based on the nature of non-substantiality of transgressions, the repentance that is


argued for in this section is not about repenting ones own wrongdoings. Wnhyo
argues that repentance should not be just about being remorseful about your past
actions. It requires a more profound understanding of the nature of actions and
the actor. He prescribes a philosophical and religious realization about the nonsubstantiality of persons and events.
Dream-like Existence
With this deluded mind caused by ignorance we misconceive the outer world as
existing, when it is merely a construction of our own mind. The second type of repentance involves seeing things correctly. That correct understanding presupposes the
perspective of ultimate truth.
47
Once you have repented of all these karmic obstructions caused by your past actions,
You should also repent of your lack of mindfulness concerning the six senses.
48
I and other sentient beings, having misunderstood from beginningless time that the elements have never been produced,
49
Deluded and erroneous, I imagine me and mine,
Within, six sense faculties are established, depending on which [six kinds of] consciousness arise respectively.

46

Philosophy East & West

50
The six kinds of sense objects, to which we adhere as existing, are constructed externally.
We do not know these are all creations of our own mind.
51
Like a dream, or an illusion, they have never existed.

Wnhyos views on ultimate truth and conventional truth are illustrated by the
example of dreams. Life experiences are like dreams: while one is in a dream one is
affected by it. Like someone who is terrified by the dream of a flood, deluded we see
ourselves as being carried away in a great river without realizing that it is actually a
dream. Feeling like we are really drowning, we are scared to death. Then, not yet
awake, we have another dream, and say, What I saw was a dream, which was not
real. Because of the minds intelligence, one is aware of the dream within a dream,
and thus is not afraid of drowning. Yet we are still unable to realize that we are lying
in bed. Head shaking and hands trembling, we struggle to really wake up. When we
are finally awake and reflect back on the previous dream, neither the river nor our
drowning selves had a place in existence. We see nothing but ourselves quietly lying
in bed (verses 5460).
The Buddhist account of the path to enlightenment is equated with removing
defilements. Defilements are mental habits that perpetuate the sense of an I.
Wnhyo explains that defilements or deluded thoughts are not real, having no ontological grounds, and only appear due to ignorance. Wnhyo claims that they only
seem to be real, appearing as such only because of a mind shaken by ignorance. Thus
the practitioners task is not to remove or eliminate defilements but rather to know
that the defilements that we experience as reality are in fact nothing but illusion. The
point of the task is to free oneself from ignorance.
This task is realized by grasping the nonsubstantiality of the thought at the moment of inception in which the thought arises. Among the four phases of the evolution of thoughts (arising, sustaining, changing, ceasing), Wnhyo states that the stage
of arising is the subtlest and hardest to grasp. Once the practitioner grasps and
penetrates the moment of inception in which arising occurs and becomes aware of
their nonsubstantiality, these thoughts will thereafter cease to arise. Being aware and
knowing this is being free from ignorance.6 As repentance is defined as understanding the nonsubstantiality of thoughts and actions, this process becomes a way of
meditation, a way of practice.
Repentance as a Means of Bodhisattva Practice
59
The long dream [of sasra] is also thus.
Ignorance covers the mind, falsely creating the six destinies wherein we flow among all
the eight sufferings.

Eun-su Cho

47

60
Internally depending on the inconceivable pervading influence (vsan) of all the
Buddhas,
And externally relying on the great compassion and the power of the vows of all the Buddhas, we come to have some semblance of faith and understanding (raddhdhimoka).
63
That I and all sentient beings are only asleep in a long dream, falsely positing it to be real.
64
The agreeable and disagreeable objects in the six sense fields and the two characteristics
of male and female are also just our dream. They have never been real.
So what is it that makes us unhappy or happy? What is there to crave and hate?

This conceptual framework serves as a unique cognitive tool in East Asian Buddhist
practice. Elsewhere, in a different text, Wnhyo speaks about non-substantiality as
follows:
Sasra itself does not have its own substantiality. Because it is devoid of substantiality,
there are no distinctions in appearance such as changing and evolving. If appearances do
not change, how can substance, that is, the mind itself, change? Thus, I would say that the
four phases in the appearance of thought are actually the same as one mind, and nonenlightenment is the same as original enlightenment; that is how it is said that these
enlightenments are all identical to one enlightenment.7

Wnhyo concludes the text by delineating the way of conducting the practice of
repentance.
66
Repeatedly contemplate it all being a dream,
And gradually you will perfect the cultivation of the samdhi in which everything is like
a dream ().
67
Due to this samdhi, you will gain quiescence in the non-production of dharmas (,
anuttpatikadharmaknti).
68
In a flash you will awaken from this long dream,
And will immediately know that originally you have never flowed back and forth.
But that this has all been just the One Mind lying on the bed of the one suchness.
69
If you leave behind [this dream] and are able to contemplate it repeatedly,
Even though the sensory objects and the six sense fields are not to be regarded as real,
70
With shame for your afflictions, you cannot be mindless ().
This is called the Mahyna Repentance of the Six Senses.
48

Philosophy East & West

Once you awaken from a dream you understand that it is not real. Realizing this is
called obtaining the dharma-knti, and this practice is called meditation based
on the perception of the world as a dream. Repentance is knowing and understanding the true nature of events and the world, by practicing the samdhi that concentrates on the dream-like nature of our cognitive existence. This samdhi will enable
one to realize the dharma-knti or anutpattika-dharma-knti (), literally
patient acceptance based on awareness of the non-arising of phenomena. This is a
distinctive level of enlightenment, a special realization of the non-production of
dharmas, and a doctrinal conception found in certain Mahyna Buddhist texts;
Wnhyo expounds this term with great emphasis in his Treatise on the Vajrasamdhistra. This is a patience, tolerance, or acceptance based on the clear cognition of
theunproduced nature of all existences, to realize that all things are beyond birth
and decay. Because one is removed from the deluded thoughts of objects of the
senses, the mind can be at rest in its awakening to the reality of the non-arising of all
existences.8
Awareness comes out of fundamentally understanding the nature of moral actions, moral agents, the external world, and objects to which ones moral concerns
are directed, which make up the foundation of morality. This awareness involves realizing that there is no such thing as a permanent, independent nature of morality or
immorality, and that understanding this will lead to ones practice of morality. There
is no self-nature (svabhva) in moral actions. There are no actions that are intrinsically good or bad; they are just occurrences at the confluence of bodily and mental
elements. This understanding and insight on actions and wrongdoings make up the
foundation on which morally conscientious action takes place. This knowledge
enables one to become morally responsible and become the foundation for ones
own morality, as well as for the practice of morality toward others.
Wnhyos conclusion is that it is shameful to suffer by your own afflictions, so
one must practice to not be mindless or unthinkingly invested in what ones senses
seem to convey. As the title of this text, Mahyna Repentance of the Six Senses
indicates, Wnhyo specifies repentance as repentance of the six senses, which,
according to what he said above, requires being mindful of ones senses. The six
senses serve as a means for repentance, as it is through ones six senses that one is
going to contemplate the nature of the actions and events one experiences. The
sixsenses are the six sense faculties, which collectively can be called life (). The
six senses originate from ones mind, which rushes to grasp the respective objects of
the senses.9
Being mindful (apramda)10 is a key term worth further investigation here.
Being mindful of the six senses has also been emphasized on many other occasions. The being mindful found in his Commentary on the Awakening of Faith
stretches our understanding of the practice of repentance in an interesting direction:
All the myriad practices from beginning to end are comprised of two types of actionsa
practice according to reality (, yathvad-bhvikat) and being mindful (
). The former corresponds to the vow of producing wisdom; the latter corresponds to
the vow of fulfilling wisdom. The former is like practicing the [virtue] of giving, while the
latter is like not seeking its reward.

Eun-su Cho

49

Thus, by keeping the pure precepts, one does not revert to previous stages of practice.
Bypracticing dharma-knti, the seal of non-arising is attained. While seeking all roots
of goodness tirelessly, all constructed affairs are abandoned. Meditation is practiced
without abiding in meditation. In accomplishing wisdom, the conceptual play (prapca)
of dharmas is not indulged in.11

Wnhyo associates this being mindful (, apramda) with subsequently attained cognition (, pha-labdha-jna), or knowledge attained as a result of
enlightenment, which bodhisattvas use for the task of liberating other sentient beings.
This cognition is also called discerning cognition (). Here Wnhyo distinguishes two levels of moral practice; one is the practicing of moral deeds as ordinarily defined, like giving (dna). The other level is not seeking the reward, an action
committed with the perspective of ultimate truth. The former is seeking to attain wisdom for enlightenment; the latter is seeking to fulfill the cognition or wisdom obtained after the clear understanding of the non-substantiality of the world.
Once the former wisdom is acquired one should move on to apply the wisdom
to be connected with the world, that is, the ordinary world of sentient beings. This
cognition will be used to liberate other sentient beings, and for that purpose one
needs to use the cognition of discernment. Guilt and remorse are necessary moral
qualities in this world for one to move forward along the path to enlightenment. In
this stage, Wnhyos postulating moral ethics can be compared to something Strawson says of what he calls reactive attitudes such as anger and resentment. He says
that parents will deploy a mixture of participatory and objective stances toward their
child as a strategy to deal with reactive attitudes in their children. To fully engage the
reactive attitudes one must fully participate in them. Wnhyo encourages practitioners to be fully engaged in the participant attitude, in which guilt and repentance are
useful tools for the training of sentient beings, while objectively understanding that
no such things really exist nor are necessary for a bodhisattva. Even though there
wasno wrongdoing, one is encouraged repentence over the actions sentient beings
commit. By letting oneself know that one is guilty, one can have the opportunity of
investigating the nature of transgressions and moral responsibility.
In his Mahyna position, not only do persons have no self, but also things have
no independent reality. Nor do causal relations. However, Wnhyo argues further,
because nothing has intrinsic nature, it could not be ultimately true that the psychophysical elements are causally determined. It isnt even true that there are psychophysical elements, let alone that there are ultimately real causal connections.
On the other hand, in spite of the absence of intrinsic nature both in a transgressor and in the transgressions committed by that person, repentance is still useful
when done without ego-involvement. For Wnhyo it is still true that persons are morally responsible for their actions, and it is still true that the wrongdoings you have
committed in the past bring a result, just as the conjured tiger, even though it does
not exist, can inflict injury. The ultimate truth does not negate conventional practice.
They both have currency, because repentance for him is nothing but understanding
the emptiness of existence, and the conventional understanding about the good and

50

Philosophy East & West

the bad is still useful in that regard. Thus, repentance is to be done in both dimensions. Wnhyos position fluctuates between two extremes, playing with the two dimensions. He encourages us not to cling to any so-called accepted truths and instead
transcend such truths. For him truth is not hierarchical. The ultimate is not something
higher or more truthful than the conventional truth.
Compatibilists of the Buddhist Reductionist Paleocompatibilist sort think in terms
of the two truths, with freedom and responsibility being something useful in conventional practice and determinism being the ultimate truth. So conventional truth goes
with the reactive attitudes and participatory stance, while ultimate truth goes with the
objective stance. Wnhyo reverses this. Because fully enlightened beings know the
ultimate truth (not that everything is causally determined, but that everything is
empty), they take up the participant stance. So the situation is this: ordinary people
just have conventional truth and reactive attitudes; arhats have what they think is
ultimate truth (that things like persons or actions are devoid of self [antman] and
causally determined), take the objective stance, and see the participant stance as no
more than a useful device that is less than ultimately true. Wnhyos position here
goes further. He negates both, not wanting to remain in one position, methodologically and ontologically, but wanting instead to keep moving up. Bodhisattvas know
the real ultimate truth (that there is none) and so are able to fully engage those they
try to help, since for them the reactive attitudes are not mere useful fictions. For if
all is conceptually constructed, nothing useful is merely anything. Those bodhisatt
vas who take the participatory stance know not only ultimate truththat the worldly
affairs that they are engaged in fact do not have intrinsic nature, and there is no good
or bad deed, or even helpful deedsbut also that there is no such truth as ultimate
truth. The bodhisattva should be able to desist from thinking that that is ultimate
truth. The notion of emptiness should be empty. Those who are acting based on the
subsequent cognition must know that this world is ultimately empty, acting skillfully enough to follow conventional reality.
Wnhyo is in fact suggesting that we leave both positions in place. He is affirming both, after negating both. As a practitioner, the place one arrives at must be the
same as the place that one had departed after practice; this is in line with the famous
Mahyna saying that nirva is nothing but sasra, but the perspectives must be
different. Wnhyo teaches us to take both a reactive participant attitude and an objective attitude. In fact, what Wnhyo is teaching us is to not take this world too seriously or make a big deal out of this world; playful pretense should be practiced.
While affirming that one is originally free of guilt, he argues that it is still necessary
for people to accept moral responsibility by observing moral behaviors and repenting
of their wrongdoings. Even an attitude of who cares or why bother also implies
that there is an ultimate truth. However, ultimately there is no ultimate truth. Still
the thought that this is the ultimate truth can give rise to a subtle form of clinging that
may prove quite difficult to extirpate. Even though one appreciates the doctrine of
nonself, still this subtle yet insidious form of clingingthat there is ultimate
truthmay thus prove an impediment to complete liberation. Ultimate truth is
another dharma, and it is empty as well. You have to get rid of this idea that there is

Eun-su Cho

51

a substantive ultimate truth out there. Emptiness is meant to cure us of any residual
clinging to ideas of ultimacy, something difficult to extirpate.12 Wnhyo accepts both
levels of perceptionthat there is crime, which needs to be repented, and guilt,
which needs to be removed, and that there is neither crime nor guilt. He delineates
the Mahyna bodhisattvas stance toward moral judgment as part of a strategy for
getting them to stop taking normative ethics so seriously.
Wnhyos Way of Taking Morality Seriously
Wnhyo talks about being responsible, or at least feeling guilty about the actions one
has committed, while seeing and taking the objective stance that these actions arenot
really real and have not been producedthey have arisen through causal powers of
psychophysical elements. Wnhyo seems to say that we can repent without remorse.
We are responsible for our actions but not really responsible, because they havenot
really been produced and we have not really committed them. Then could it be
said that they are caused, that is, in the deterministic sense? What he would sayisthat
nothing is really caused. The notion that everything is determined is not an ultimate
truth that can explain everything. However, this does not mean that it is true thatthings
are not determined. Ultimately, causal relation or causation does not really make any
sense. As we have seen earlier, this is shown by his explanation of the non-production
of the dharmas in the past, present, and future. Moral responsibility can be claimed
when there is an agent and there are consequences, so in the conventional sense
persons are responsible for their actions. However, ultimate view is that bodhisattvas
should be watchful of their actions, so in that way determinism is compatible with
being morally responsible. A bodhisattva would accept moral responsibility while
taking a deterministic worldview, and would even say that they are compatible; but
at the truly ultimate level no view can be maintained. At this point the modern debate over compatibilism is left behind, as no truth is ultimately true either.

Notes
I would like to thank Mark Siderits for his introduction to this issue on determinism
and moral responsibility. However, any shortcomings are mine alone.
1For example, Nicholas F. Gier and Paul Kjellberg assert the position in Buddhism and the Freedom of the Will: Pali and Mahayanist Responses, in
Freedom and Determinism: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy, ed. by J. K.
Campbell, D. Shier, and M. ORourke, (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004),
pp.277304.
2Taking a hard deterministic position, Charles Goodman claims that just as it is
irrational to feel anger at something impersonal such as bile when it causes one
pain, it is equally irrational to feel anger at transgressors, since they are really
just a causal series of impersonal psychophysical elements. Because everything

52

Philosophy East & West

about the person is caused, no one is really responsible for their actions; no one
really deserves praise or blame, reward or punishment, for their good and bad
deeds. Thus, he says that if we take a Buddhist reductionist position seriously,
no one is responsible for the actions that they commit. It is irrational to feel guilt
over ones past. He says that perfected people (i.e., bodhisattvas) do not ascribe
moral responsibility. See his Resentment and Reality: Buddhism on Moral Responsibility, American Philosophical Quarterly 39, no. 4 (October 2002): 359.
3The text Taesng yukchng chamhoe (Mahyna repentance of
the six senses) contained in the Hanguk Pulgyo chns (Collection of Korean
Buddhist writings) (hereafter HPC), vol. 1, 842843, is in prose form, but must
be read as a narrative verse. I have reformatted it as poetry and inserted line
numbers, and the quotations from the text in this article reflect it. It consists of
seventy-one verses, in most cases four lines of four characters apiece. The
theoretical framework of repentance presented in this text resonates much
with the views presented in his Kisillon-so (Commentary to the Awakening of
Mhyana Faith) or Kmgang sammaegyng-ron (Treatise on the Vajrasamdhistra). He composed three works related to Buddhist discipline, proclaiming
moral behavior and discipline, based on the scripture of the Fanwang-jing, an
important East Asian Buddhist book of morality, called either Fanwang-jing precepts or more generally Bodhisattva precepts. The other two are mainly commentarial works on the Fanwang-jing, with a list of the precepts along with
detailed explanations of the individual precepts to observe and the crimes that
are warded off.
4In early Buddhism, transgressions are regarded as ethical matters, immoral actions in violation of socially defined morality. Transgressions or offenses (kama)
are the causes of suffering, klea, or defilements, which is a collective term for
the so-called three poisons, namely greed, anger, and ignorance. These three
poisons were also called avajja, meaning something to be blamed. When these
three poisons are removed, no more transgressions are committed; the mind is
purified to attain enlightenment. In contrast, in Mahyna Buddhism the meaning of transgressions is expanded to take on religious implications. Transgressions do not just violate social Dharma, but are related to the metaphysical
working of karma. In the East Asian Buddhist tradition, for example, the Awakening of Faith preaches an underlying power for the arising of klea called the
fundamental force of karma, the equivalent of the eighth consciousness. The
transgressions are not just performed at the level of sense organs or consciousness, but come into existence due to this beginningless unidentifiable force.
This power is too subtle to be removed; thus, Pure Land Buddhism describes its
removal as requiring blessings or power from the Buddhas, and therefore one
needs to arouse faith in those external powers. See Hynjun Kim, Wnhyo i
chamhoe sasang (Wnhyos theory of repentance), Pulgyo yngu (Buddhist
studies) (Seoul: Hanguk Pulgyo Ynguwn [Korean Institute for Buddhist
Studies]) 2 (1986).

Eun-su Cho

53

5A similar argument about repentance is found in his Commentary on the Awakening of Faith, section on Encouragement of the Practice of Repentance (
) (HPC 731c), and in the Treatise of the Vajrasamdhi-stra, section on
circulation () (HPC 676c677a).
6See Eun-su Cho, Reconciling the Actual with the Potential: Wnhyos Theory
of Buddhahood and Enlightenment, International Journal of Buddhist Thought
and Culture 5 (2005).
7Separate Commentary on the Awakening of Faith, HPC 1763a.
8A similar explanation of dharma-knti is also found in his other work, Treatise
on the Vajrasamdhi-stra.
9Commentary on the Awakening of Faith, HPC 1.735b0102.
10Apramda means non-negligence, carefulness, diligence. It is one of the ten
virtues-producing mental-function dharmas listed in the Abhidharma-koabhya.
11Commentary on the Awakening of Faith, HPC 1.736b0917.
12Mark Siderits, On the Soteriological Significance of Emptiness, Contemporary
Buddhism 4, no. 1 (2003): 17.

54

Philosophy East & West

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen