Sie sind auf Seite 1von 16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

BetterLateThanNever:RaymondAronsTheoryof
InternationalRelationsAndItsProspectsinthe21st
Century
BryanPaulFrost

29|Setembro|2005

It would be genuinely exciting to say that Raymond Arons theory or understanding of


international relations exercisesor ever did exercisea broad, general influence on the
field. Malheureusement, this is not, and really never has been, the case, at least in AngloAmerican scholarship. Certainly Arons PeaceandWar:ATheoryofInternational
Relations is often cited in perfunctory footnotes listing the classic works of realism; but for

all intents and purposes, John Halls comment concerning this magisterial book remains as
true today as it did when he wrote it some quarter century ago: one suspects that [Peace
andWar] is more quoted than read.

[1]

Although there are likely many reasons that

account for this neglect, Stanley Hoffmann captured a large portion of the truth when he
compared PeaceandWar to a book that has, and still does (if only negatively), exercise an
enormous influence on the field.
One of the many reasons why Raymond Arons monumental Peace and Wara book far
more ambitious in its scope and far more sophisticated in its analyses than PoliticsAmong
Nationsincited no comparable reaction from scholarly readers may well have been the
greater judiciousness and modesty of Arons normative conclusions. Humane skeptics
invite nods and sighs, not sound and fury; and sound and fury are good for creative
scholarship. Moreover, Arons own scholarship was overwhelming enough to be
[2]
discouraging; Morgenthaus was just shaky enough to inspire improvements.
One could add to Hoffmanns incisive assessment by noting that Aron never started what
might be called an Aronian school of thought.Aron assiduously avoided predetermined
and prepackaged conclusions: each situation had to be examined on its own terms, and
from the perspective of those in power, before any concrete evaluation or decision could be
made. The same can be said of his theory or understanding of international relations. Aron
did not set out to explain the totality of international politics through a single concept such
as power or the configuration of forces, and he was never persuaded by the behaviorist
or positivistic revolution in the social sciences that became so fashionable in the 1950s.
Instead of a doctrine, Aron offers his readers a way of thinking about, or a general approach
to, political phenomena, the hallmarks of which are modest expectations, tentative
conclusions, and (at best) probabilistic causal relations. Even if one agrees that Arons
sober procedure remains closer to the actual texture of international politics than more
grandiose theorizing, it is by that same token easy to see how the latter could capture and
[3]
excite the imagination of future social scientists.
Although students of Aron might rightly bemoan the fact that he has had relatively little
impact on international relations theory as a whole, one can certainly wonder whether Aron
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

1/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

has anything significant to contribute to the field today. After all, Aron is often seen as first
and foremost a Cold War theoretician: is he really the best person to turn toward in order to
make sense of events like Islamic fundamentalism, global terrorism, and the apparent
importance of transnational organizations and treaties, to name just a few pertinent issues?
Indeed, one prominent Aron scholar may have unwittingly lent support to the foregoing
appraisal when he stated that the one event Aron might have ignored in his long career was
the Iranian revolution of 1979, which with the benefit of hindsight was the point of
departure for the rise of Islamic fundamentalism.

[4]

It would seem that the post-

September 11th world differs in too many fundamental ways for Aron to offer us any
constructive, concrete guidance today.
This is not the first time such sentiments have been expressed; it is doubtful they will be the
last. In their Introduction to Arons Peace and War, Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C.
Anderson rightly remind us about the plethora of prognostications that followed the
collapse of the Berlin Wall, and how many a scholar was heralding the emergence of a
world order of such a vastly different character that old ways of thinking about
international politics would be rendered obsolete. But they continue:
The atrocities of September 11, the U.S. defeat of the Taliban in Afghanistan, imminent
conflict in Iraq, internal national conflicts within NATO, nuclear brinkmanship between
India and Pakistan, the collapse of the dot-com boom, and rising economic protectionism
how different the world appears today. Politics has returned vengefully, making the liberal
optimism of the 1990s appear nave.
The great French liberal Raymond Aron would not have been surprised at the stubborn
[5]
persistence of politics.
If Aron would likely have doubted that the end of the Cold War signified the end of power
politics, then why should we doubt that he might not have something vital to say about
international politics post-September 11th? Is global terrorism a phenomenon so wholly
unprecedented that we need an entirely new theory of international relations to
comprehend it; or is it the case that Arons conceptual framework might not offer us the
best tools to isolate its character and pinpoint its uniqueness? Indeed, I would contend that
if scholars had paid more attention to Arons understanding of international relations, far
fewer scholars would have been surprised by such events as George W. Bushs doctrine of
preemption, the utter impotence of the U.N. in respect to the invasion of Iraq, and the
vehement condemnation of both by old Europe, in general, and Jacques Chiracs France,
[6]
in particular.
It is the purpose of this essay to demonstrate that Aron is a theorist from
whom we can learn a great dealindeed, a great deal more than many contemporary
scholarsand that far from being deficient, Arons theoretical framework serves as perhaps
the best starting point in conceptualizing international politicsincluding currentpolitics
in the most comprehensive fashion possible. In arguing these points, I will sketch out some
of Arons distinctive contributions to international relations theory as well as suggest some
fruitful ways scholars can pursue and contribute to his legacy.

WhatAronStoodAgainst
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

2/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

In discussing Arons contribution to international relations theory, it is perhaps best to


begin by briefly articulating what Aron stood against: what does he caution the prospective
theorist against expecting or hoping from theory?
Aron sounds one of his massive warnings about international relations theory from the
opening pages of Peace and War: the limits of our knowledge (4/16). The limits to
which Aron is referring are not so much a lack of historical evidence or information
(although he certainly means this as well) but rather the inherent limits of theoretical
knowledge itself. Aron argues that there is no single goal or objective which all states
pursue, and attempts to argue that there is some such overarching end (e.g., national
interest or power and security) are either hopelessly vague or distorting simplifications
(16/28). This is not to say that efforts at conceptualizing international relations are fruitless
on the contrary, Aron is at pains to point out that all political units must be mindful of the
alternatives of war and peace, and that the risk of war obliges [states] to calculate forces or
means (16/29). But the alternatives of war and peace do not and cannot tell the theorist
what specific goals political units will pursue, and absent this, the theorist is relatively
constrained in what he can say or predict: lacking a single goal of diplomatic behavior, the
rational analysis of international relations cannot be developed into an inclusive theory
(17/29). These early cautionary remarks reach a crescendo at the end of chapter three. Here
Aron most fully develops the difference between economic behavior and diplomaticstrategic behavior, and in so doing he clarifies why the former has had (and will continue to
have) far more success when it comes to theory.
Of course, homoeconomicus exists only in our rationalizing reconstruction, but the relation
between homoeconomicus and the concrete economic subject differs fundamentally from
the relation between the idealtypediplomat (defined by the search for the maximization of
resources, of force, or of power), and the historical diplomat. The two economic men
one of theory and the other of practiceresemble each other as a retouched photograph
resembles a snapshot. The theoretical economicus is more true to himself than the practical
one; he has perfect information and makes no errors in calculation. But if either seeks the
maximization of the same quantity (monetary income, production, long- or short-term
profit), the formers perfect calculations help us to understand, and sometimes to correct,
the latters imperfect calculations. The diplomaticus of theory, who would have as his goal
the maximization of resources, of actual forces, or of power, would not be an idealized
portrait of the diplomats of all ages; he would be the caricatured simplification of certain
diplomatic personages at certain periods. (91/100)
He concludes the chapter with the following observation:
If diplomatic behavior is never determined by the relation of forces alone, if power does not
serve the same function in diplomacy as utility in economics, then we may legitimately
conclude that there is no general theory of international relations comparable to the
general theory of economics. The theory we are sketching out here tends to analyze the
meaning of diplomatic behavior, to trace its fundamental notions, to specify the variables
that must be reviewed in order to understand any one constellation. But it does not suggest
an eternal diplomacy; it does not claim to be the reconstruction of a closed system. (93;
cf. 285/102; cf. 288)
Given these inherent limitations, Aron repeatedly cautions theorists against the attempt of
transforming international relations into an operational or predictable science. At the end
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

3/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

of Peace and War, he engages in an extended analysis of game theory (76787/75170).


While not denying its potential usefulness in helping to clarify certain aspects of
diplomatic-strategic conduct, Aron emphasizes that it is not possible to quantify
mathematically a concrete situation. Moreover, the very attempt at mathematical
quantification is likely to lead theorists to ignore or distort a whole range of critical
variables that are notoriously impossible or difficult to quantify (e.g., glory, justice,
prestige, or religion [48, 91/59, 100101]), and yet which are so often decisive in
understanding a given event. What gives these criticisms their urgency is Arons keen
awareness that diplomats will inevitably use and be influenced by theoretical knowledge,
and that such mathematically inspired or oriented models will likely result in
misunderstanding and misguided policies: diplomats may become prisoners of a certain
theoretical outlook, unable to comprehend the genuine motivations of allies and enemies,
and to propose innovative solutions in times of crisis.
Theory and theoretical models might be useful in helping to clarify or pinpoint the unique
character of a particular event or historical epoch, but no theorist should foist upon the
diplomat the dangerous illusion that theoretical knowledge and quantification can sharply
reduce uncertainty, ambiguity, and risk. One might say that theorists who engage in or
encourage such hopes are not only poor theorists but they also fail in their civic duty as
political educators. To approach human affairs in the spirit of geometry is catastrophic.

[7]

In sum, Arons oeuvreserves as a steady reminder of the limits of theory in international


relationsof the necessity of drawing modest conclusions, and of exercising restraint.
Despite the best of intentions, international relations scholars will never discover a grand
theory that enables them to predict diplomatic-strategic behavior, and the effort to do so is
itself potentially irresponsible: it is not a lack of historical knowledge that thwarts scholars
but the inherent limitations of theory itself. Aron stood squarely against the dominant
trends in international relations, and this, in part, helps to explain why he had such a
[8]
limited impact on Anglo-American social science.
AronsDistinctiveMoralContributiontoInternationalRelationsTheory
Aron is most often classified as a classical realistand to a certain extent, this is quite true.
[9]

One readily finds throughout his writings, in general, and PeaceandWar, in particular,

terminology and concepts most often associated with classical realism, e.g., the anarchical
nature of international politics, the state as the principal actor, war as the distinguishing
characteristic of interstate relations, and the configuration of the relation of forces. But if
Aron can to some extent be described as a realist, one must stress with equal vigor and
validity the important differences he has with this school of thought, especially when it
comes to the enormous weight he places on moralconcerns. Indeed, it would not be an
exaggeration to say that Arons theoretical understanding is an attempt (in part) to rescue
morality or moral concerns and to return them to the hands of theoristsnot in the sense of
a doctrine or course of action (as a typical idealist might desire) but as a set of vital
conceptsfor correctly comprehending international politics.
Although it is often overlooked, it is initially worth noting how Aron identifies and
describes the proper focus of interest or specific characteristic of international relations:
they take place within the shadow of war, or, to use a more rigorous expression, relations
among states involve, in essence, the alternatives of war and peace (46/1618). But when
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

4/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

he reformulates this definition a few pages later, he stresses the fact that these alternatives
often (if not always) involve a claim to justice: international relations deals with the
relationsbetweenpoliticalunits,eachofwhichclaimstherighttotakejusticeintoitsown
handsandtobethesolearbiterofthedecisiontofightornottofight (8/20). States have
always understood that they had the legitimate right to resort to force if they felt compelled
or obligated to do so, and classical jurists like Grotius and Vattel concurred in this
assessment. Of course, the fact that states claimed they were engaging in a just and proper
use of force did not at all guarantee that they were doing so; nevertheless, until perhaps
more recent times at least, no state that believed it had been denied justice was required to
endure that situation indefinitely, and no state believed that it needed to receive moral
or juridical permission to use force from some sort of third party, whether it be a religious
institution or an international tribunal or court (11124/11932). In sum, wars between
political units cannot be explained by or reduced to mere self-interest or the accumulation
of power because the human beings that represent their political units do not always act in
this fashion, and a theorist must therefore recognize and weigh the moral arguments the
participants put forth to justify their actions.
Arons acute appreciation of the moral dimensions of international politics resonates
throughout PeaceandWar, especially in his discussion of the goals or ends states seek. At
the most general level of abstraction or conceptualization, he argues that states have sought
three historical objectives: security (either by increasing their own force or weakening a
rivals), power (the ability of imposing ones will on another), and glory (to be recognized by
others in a certain way or for a certain quality). Aron nicely distinguishes these three goals
from one another (the first of which he calls a material objective, the latter two moral
ones) by contrasting three famous French leaders.
Clemenceau sought the security, Napoleon the power, Louis XIV the glory of France. . . . In
1918 any rational chief of state would have proposed the same goal: to spare France the
recurrence of a war as cruel as the one that an immense alliance had just brought to a
favorable conclusion. Napoleon, at least after a certain date, dreamed of ruling Europe: he
was not content with the honor of being universally celebrated as a great war leader. . . . He
was ambitious for reality, not for appearances, and he knew that in the long run no state
commands others if it does not possess the means of constraining them. Louis XIV
probably loved glory as much as power. He wanted to be recognized as the first among
monarchs. . . . He did not conceive of a disproportionately enlarged France, furnished with
resources superior to those of her allied rivals. He dreamed that the names of Louis XIV
and of France would be transfigured by the admiration of nations. (7374/84)
As the chapter proceeds, Aron then recategorizes these objectives as he deepens his analysis
of them. The ternary series security, power, and glory could also be reformulated as space
(to conquer more territory), men (to conquer more subjects), and souls (to convert others
to a political, social, or religious idea), or again as body (to accumulate material objectives
such as space or resources or force), heart (to satisfy a states amourpropre by prevailing
over its rivals), and mind (to spread an idea of which the state represents a unique
incarnation). Aron poignantly and succinctly encapsulates his appreciation of the diversity
of human motivations and objectives much later in the book:
States, like individuals, desire not only life but honor, not only security but dignity. Often
they prefer danger in autonomy to peace under the protection of a stronger power. Are they
irrational? Was the captain who went down with his ship irrational? If so, let us hope that
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

5/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

humanity does not cease being irrational! (629/615)


Arons recognition of the dynamics of morality enriches his theoretical analysis in several
ways. He takes seriously the fact that there have been (and will be) individuals and states
which have seriously believed in their religious or ideological or civilizing mission, and
which have been willing to go to unparalleled lengths to see their goals realized. In other
words, Aron does not fall prey to a ubiquitous cynicism, one which ascribes to all such overt
professions of faith or ideology as nothing more than a camouflage for imperialism. One
must always begin with the viewpoint of the actors involved, even and especially when
these individuals are making stringent moral claims and demands. To do otherwise is to
misunderstandperhaps fatally sothe motivations and ultimate purpose of an adversary,
dismissing as little more than a hypocritical excuse something the adversary takes as the
very core of his being. And this is all the more important for political leaders to avoid doing
because Aron sees that wars fought for glory or an idea (whether religious or ideological)
are often the most inhumane and pitiless; theoretical reasoning must not discount or
distort the moral element in politics precisely because the cost of miscalculation here can be
[10]
so great (7576/8586).
Admittedly, Arons rich, detailed discussion here and
elsewhere means that he must take into account a wide-ranging number of variables if he
hopes to formulate any causal relations; but by the same token, of what use is a theory of
international relations if it so abstracts from the complexities of the human soul that it can
say nothing genuinely meaningful about politics? Aron might be described as a realist, but
he was one whose philosophical education and temperament made him highly cognizant of
the significance of the moral dimension of politics.
When Aron states that the alternatives of war and peace also imply a sense of justice, he
thereby suggests that it is not possible to theorize about international relations without also
examining a particular states conception of justice: in other words, one must look at the
domestic regimes of the major powers as well as the conception(s) of justice and legitimacy
that prevail in the international system. Aron therefore pays great attention to what he
describes as homogenous and heterogenous systems: the former obtains when the
major powers share similar regimes and conceptions of policy, the latter when the regimes
are organized according to different principles and appeal to contradictory values
(100/108). Because states in an homogenous international system share the same general
principles of legitimacy, such systems tend to display greater stability; to limit violence
when it does occur; to be more predictable in their political traditions and diplomatic codes
of conduct; and to engage in competitive and even hostile behavior that does not
degenerate into hatred of the rival or adversary. Heterogeneity of the system produces the
opposite: instability, an increase in violence, uncertainty, and hatred between the enemy
states (100101/10810). The configuration of the relation of forces, while certainly an
essential variable in understanding any international system, cannot be divorced from the
ends or goals sought by the major powers, and these latter depend decisively on the
character of the states regime (14749/15456). By focusing on the unit level of analysis,
Aron is able to avoid three related errors that theorists who focus predominantly on
systemic factors tend to commit. First, states are far more influential in affecting the
dynamics of the system than the system is in affecting their behavior. As Aron notes
(perhaps thinking of Germany in 1933), In each period the principal actors have
determined the system more than they have been determined by it. A change of regime
within one of the chief powers suffices to change the style and sometimes the course of
international relations (95; cf. 9599, 140ff./104; cf. 104108, 148ff.). Second,
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

6/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

maintenance of the system or the systemss equilibrium is not the exclusive or primary
goal of the powers within that system. This may be a prudential consideration; but except
for perhaps the case of Great Britain, the goal of the maintenance or safeguarding or
functioning of the system is to return, by a devious route, to the error of certain
theoreticians of power politics: to confuse the calculation of means or the context of the
decision with the goal itself (13031; cf. 12836, 14649/13940; cf. 13744, 15456).
And finally, third, regardless of the systemwhether bipolar or multipolarboth can lead
to hostilities and war, and both are capable of equilibrium. Aron does not deny that each
system tends to display specific characteristics, and he discusses them throughout chapter
5; but neither system is inherently more bellicose or peaceful than another, and therefore
the dynamics of a particular system cannot be rigidly determined by a theorist in advance
(14649/15456).
The critical importance of the regime (or the unit level of analysis) makes Arons theory of
international relations much more akin to the classical political thought of someone like
Aristotle than it does to many contemporary theorists. As Daniel Mahoney has rightly
observed, Aron, like Aristotle and the classical philosophers in general, sees a necessary
connectedness between the two supposedly distinct political science sub-fields of
international relations and comparative politics. The thought of statesmen about
international relations and the forms of each regime affect the way statesmen operate
within an albeit anarchic international environment.

[11]

This indissoluble link between

comparative politics and international relations is further revealed, if not necessitated by,
Arons methodological approach: historical sociology. According to Aron, the distinguishing
characteristic of historical sociology is its emphasis on comparative study, by which he
means an investigatory method that attempts to isolate and highlight probabilistic causal
relations through a rigorous comparison within and across different historical periods. In
this respect, the historical sociologist is continuously required to glide back and forth
between an analysis of the structural determinants of behavior (i.e., the macro or
sociological or systemic causes that exert an influence on international politics) and the
concrete study of a given diplomatic constellation (i.e., the micro or historical or unit level
causes that influence decision making). Aron notes that theorists who focus primarily on
the former factors to the neglect of the latter are likely to commit two related errors: they
tend to establish causes where, at most, there are trends, and they do not take account of
all the factors involved but exaggerate the influence of those that are considered. One
might say that one of the great virtues of historical sociology is that it compels a theorist to
give due consideration and weight to the authentic political perspective of those actors
whose decisions are the object of theoretical or scientific investigation. Certainly theorists
must avoid privileging the micro level of analysis to the exclusion of everything else, for
then they are likely to deny that there are any recurrent, systemic patterns of behavior.
Nevertheless, the greater problem or temptation that Aron saw in his day was that theorists
tended to ignore or discount what the historical actors themselves said influenced them to
act in a certain way; and one of the most important keys to unlocking in their full
complexity these influences is often embedded in an understanding of the regime which the
actors themselves have self-consciously chosen to serve and defend.
The policy-makers do their thinking with reference to a certain system of values, a
conception of their community and of the world which reflects the special individuality of
the nation. It is perfectly legitimateindeed it is necessaryto determine, in each set of
circumstances and in each country, the ideological system to which the policy-makers
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

7/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

subscribe and the influences, in the form of tradition and public opinion, to which they are
[12]
subjected.
Much more can and ought to be said about other distinctive contributions Aron made to
international relations theorythey are literally bursting forth on every page of Peaceand
War. Let us, however, briefly conclude with the following. Aron was aware that whether a
theorist admitted it or not, every theoretical enterprise carried within it certain normative
conclusions(575/563). Aron was honest and diligent enough to declare forthrightly what
his were in Part IV of his book, entitled Praxeology. Arons normative conclusionsor
morality of prudenceemerge from his attempt to transcend and thereafter to moderate
what he sees as the two praxeological problems confronting leaders: the Machiavellian
problem of the legitimate recourse to force (what he later christens a morality of
struggle) and the Kantian problem of collective security and universal peace (or a
morality of law) (577, 6089/565, 59596). Neither a morality of struggle nor a morality
of law can, on its own, provide a leader with a consistent and responsible principle of
diplomatic-strategic conduct. On the one hand, even though states share certain norms of
behavior and principles of legitimacy, they continue to reserve the right to use force as they
see fit, and the diplomat who neglects to calculate the balance of power in the hopes of
upholding international law fails in his duty; on the other hand, states have rarely
considered every recourse to arms legitimate, and they have often sincerely aimed at
promoting and defending higher goals and values. The bellicose character of international
politics cannot be transcended, only moderated, but such moderation can come neither
from opportunism divorced from reflection upon higher principles and goals nor from the
single-minded pursuit of heartfelt convictions divorced from considerations of the
consequences of those actions. Only a morality of prudence considers and weighs both of
these antinomies as it comes to decide the best course of action:
To be prudent is to act in accordance with the particular situation and the concrete data,
and not in accordance with some system or out of passive obedience to a norm or pseudonorm; it is to prefer the limitation of violence to the punishment of the presumably guilty
party or to a so-called absolute justice; it is to establish concrete accessible objectives
conforming to the secular law of international relations and not to limitless and perhaps
meaningless objectives, such as a world safe for democracy or a world from which power
politics will have disappeared. (585/572)
The morality of prudence is therefore a morality of responsibility, and the prudent diplomat
is the one who, unlike someone acting from Weberian conviction alone, always takes into
consideration the likely consequences of his decisions and acts accordingly (634/620).
Certainly Arons observations on the morality of prudence or responsibility are formal: no
concrete moral evaluation can be made unless one knows the particular event and the
objectives pursued by the states involved. Nonetheless, Arons many political judgments
during the Cold War, and the thoughtful strategy he advocated, give content to that form,
and they begin to suggest how he might evaluate those current conflicts where realists and
idealists alternately decry and praise policy decisions.

Arons Theory in the 21st Century: Conceptualizing, Understanding, and


RespondingtoTerrorism
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

8/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

As was suggested at the beginning of this essay, one can legitimately wonder if Arons socalled Cold War theory of international relations has anything to offer students who wish
to pursue his legacy in the 21st century. And there is no better way to answer this question
than to examine whether, or to what extent, Arons wide-ranging theoretical
conceptualizations offer any guidance in understanding what is undoubtably the most
pressing foreign policy issue facing decision makers today: global terrorism and radical
[13]
Islamic fundamentalism.
These comments do not claim to be strikingly original or new;
rather, my aim is to demonstrate that Arons theoretical framework can fully incorporate
[14]
Islamic terrorism within it as well as suggest prudent responses to it.
Let us begin with
the following observations.
One might claim that the distinguishing characteristic of terrorism is that terrorist
networks do not belong to any state: in the words of Tzvetan Todorov, terrorist violence
has to be committed not by a state or its government but by individuals or groups who have
no legitimate mandate to use violence. . . . Terrorism is an act of war perpetrated by people
without a state.

[15]

It this were correct, then Aron might have very little to say on the

subject of terrorism, for PeaceandWar takes as its starting point and exclusive focus the
alternatives of peace and war between organized, territorial political units (418/1630).
But Aron was fully aware that organized, territorial political units described a Weberian
ideal type and not an entire class of phenomenon, and that there were many situations of
armed conflict in which one or both combatants were not states.
[T]he marginal cases which may or may not involve independent political units or
organized military forces do not invalidate the definition quoted, but are simply fresh
evidence of the gradation always found in social phenomenon. On the borderline, civil war
and international war merge together, as do the clash of armies and guerilla warfare. We
must not overlook this area of doubt on the borderlinewe shall take account of it in the
course of the explanations that followbut it does not make it impossible for us to begin by
[16]
considering the phenomenon in the perfect state.
Arons conceptual framework does not deny the existence of conflict between less organized
and/or non-territorial entities; instead, he constructs a theoretical edifice in the only way
that one can, namely by focusing on the most typical or perfect sorts of armed conflict.
Notwithstanding these initial remarks, the larger question still remains: does statelessness
constitute the distinguishing characteristic of terrorism? I believe that Aron would have
denied this, or at least have severely qualified it. When discussing the various meanings of
the word terror, Aron argues that both states and non-state actors could be terrorists or
use terrorist tactics. An action of violence is labeled terrorist when its psychological effects
are out of proportion to its purely physical result. In this sense, the so-called indiscriminate
acts of revolutionaries are terrorist, as were the Anglo-American zone bombings. The lack
of discrimination helps spread fear, for if no one in particular is a target, no one can be
safe (170/176).According to this definition, the fact that a group is stateless does not mean
that it is necessarily terroristthe group could employ non-violent resistence to achieve its
goal and the state could ruthlessly suppress anyone it thought sympathized with them,
guilty and innocent alike. Nor does it mean that any and all use of violence is necessarily
terrorist, even violence that kills innocent civilians. What Aron identifies as the
distinguishing characteristic of terrorism is a fundamental disjunction or incongruity
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

9/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

between the fearful effects on the psyche of the target population and the actual physical
damage the action wrought. Obviously, actions would be labeled terrorist when the victims
are individuals who have little or nothing to do with the conflict and whose deaths do not
bring the perpetrators of the action significantly closer to what they wish to achievebut
these would not be the only possible cases of terrorism, both theoretically and historically.
Before deciding an action is or was terrorist, Aron first requires the analyst to make a
concrete determination to see if the actions psychological effects are out of proportion to
its purely physical result. Of course, such determinations may differ from analyst to
analyst; nevertheless, Aron does help us to see that terrorism (at least for him) is not so
much an attribute or property of a particular groupbut of a particular sort of action groups
orstates might use.
The preceding remarks suggest that any attempt at determining whether an action or group
is a terrorist will require the analyst to concentrate on two key factors: first, what are the
actual goals that terrorists seek; and second, what are the means that they have at their
disposal. Not surprisingly, these are the very factors Aron uses to understand any and all
diplomatic-strategic conduct, and it is here that we can begin to delineate the unique
features of radical Islamic terrorism (cf. 21, 30, 4748, 7172/33, 42, 5859, 8182). In
respect to the goals of someone like Osama Bin Laden, Arons moral understanding of
international relations plays an extremely useful function: it forces the theorist to highlight
the genuinely religious dimension of this sort of terrorism. Al Qaeda is animated by a
perverse but seemingly genuine form of religious zeal, and their moral principles and
religious ideas must be comprehended in order to understand the goals that they seek,
whether it be the restoration of the ancient caliphate, the expulsion of the United States
from Saudi Arabia, the toppling of corrupt regimes in the Middle East, and/or the
destruction of the West and Israel. In respect to the means, Aron would likely focus on what
he saw as two of the most important revolutions in the post-Cold War era: the worldwide
extension of the diplomatic field and the creation of nuclear weapons (or what he often
simply termed as weapons of mass destruction) (371/369). Modern terrorist networks are
able to utilize international financial institutions and telecommunications, and this allows
them a genuinely global reach when it comes to broadcasting their propaganda, financing
their operations, and communicating internally. In addition, the arsenal of weapons at their
disposal goes far beyond a machine gun and a grenade: for the first time in history,
terrorists have at least the potential to wreak destruction on a truly monstrous scale. In
sum, a terrorist group is one whose violent actions have a terrifying psychological effect on
an enemy which does not at all correspond to the physical damage inflicted, and what is
distinctive about radical Islamic terrorism is the religious goals that they promote and the
[17]
global infrastructure and weapons they now have at their disposal.
By distinguishing Islamic terrorism according to the goals they seek and the means they
use, Aron helps us to draw some important but rather grisly initial conclusions. Consider
the following remarks Aron makes in discussing how political considerations limited
Frances military options against the FLN in Algeria:
Rare in the modern history of Europe are the circumstances in which the leaders have been
free to do everything they regarded as effective and useful on the strictly military level.
That generals must renounce certain actions out of respect for international legality, for
allies or neutrals, is the rule rather than the exception. (38/50)
These remarks would certainly apply to the United States and its allies; they would not
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

10/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

apply to this specific brand of terrorism: whereas the U.S. is clearly constrained in the
weapons it can use and those whom it targets, these same restrictions do not apply to Al
Qaeda. To begin to understand and take seriously Al Qaedas religious and moral ideas is to
confront a profound disregard for any distinction between combatants and noncombatants, soldier and civilian, guilty and innocent, legitimate and illegitimate targets: all
are equally condemned, and all are potential victims, wherever they may be. Therefore, the
means this terrorist group is willing to use includes any and all means that are currently
available to them. In other words, one of the unique characteristics of Al Qaeda is not only
that they have the potential to acquire weapons of mass destruction (this remark would
apply to almost every terrorist network in the world today) but that they would actively seek
to do so (which does not apply to any and all terrorist groups). To put it bluntly, what was
once called the nuclear taboo is no longer considered so by one of the combatants. During
the Cold War, the common interest in preventing nuclear annihilation moderated (to some
extent) the strident ideological battle between the United States and the former Soviet
Union, and this is why Aron called the two antagonists the enemy brothers: enemies to
the extent they were arming for war, brothers to the extent that neither wanted to wage that
war (407, 428, 536ff., 56970, 637, 64849/403, 424, 527ff., 55758, 623, 63334).
Today, the existence of nuclear weapons has exactly the opposite effect, as all sense of
fraternity has been cast aside: one side possess these weapons but is ultimately unable to
use them, and the other side is willing to use them but unable (as yet) to acquire them. In
short, the specific goals of this particular terrorist network allows it to enjoy an enormous
flexibility when it comes to the targets and means at its disposal, targets and means which
will not be at ours. Finding the proper political and military response is all the more
[18]
essential and difficult (cf. 28284/28587).
With these thoughts in mind, we are now in a better position to evaluate to what extent
statelessness is a distinctive characteristic of terrorism. Rather than claiming that
statelessness is the distinguishing characteristic of terrorism, I believe that Aron would
argue that it is statelessness that gives terrorists unique tactical advantages over organized,
territorial political unitsand particularly gruesome ones at that. In the first place, it may
be next to impossible to completely destroy a terrorist group, at least in the short run. If
France was unable to stop the activities of the FLN in Algeria, then in what sense is it
realistic to expect that a group which has terrorist cells everywhere from Germany to
Indonesia to Africa can be eradicated in a matter of months and years, let alone decades?
Second, groups like Al Qaeda have significant advantages when it comes to the public
relations war. Each time that terrorists succeed in carrying out an attack, they can
legitimately claim victory by showing the impotence of those states aligned against them.
As Aron argued in respect to Algeria, all that the FLN had to do in order to win that
conflict was not to lose it. As the FLN had absolutely no chance of destroying France,
their strategy consisted, in part, in preventing themselves from being annihilated; over
time, they rightly saw that France would simply grow weary and exhausted of a protracted
conflict which they (the French) could never hope to win (3036/4248). Similarly, as long
as Al Qaeda can continue to launch successful attacks against any of its enemies, they can
plausibly claim some measure of victory, at least in the sense of demonstrating that those
states cannot guarantee the security of their citizensand this is made all the easier for
them to do precisely because they are a moving target (a stateless group) which is capably
of striking against any number of fixed targets (territorial states). And finally, third, to the
extent that Al Qaeda is able or content to achieve at least some of their goals while
remaining stateless, then it is not clear when or if there will be an end to this sort of
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

11/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

terrorism. Aron notes that terrorism ended in Algeria the moment the FLN had achieved
their objective of an independent state; to the extent that Al Qaedas goals are not simply
nationalistic but are far more comprehensive, destructive, and religiously inspired, then it
is unclear whether terrorism would end unless one of the combatants in this war capitulates
or is destroyed.
Thus far, we have focused on how Aron might begin to conceptualize Islamic terrorism; but
it is also possible to use his theoryand especially his normative conclusionsto discern
some of the unique challenges facing the United States and its allies when it comes to
devising an appropriate political response. Without question, the first task Aron would
stress accomplishing would be the very one which he himself undertook whenever he faced
a new and unfamiliar problem: one must become informed about its true character and
complexities. In this respect, Aron would likely suggest using historical sociology to unearth
the unique moral and religious character of this species of terrorism. Such an analysis
would include, but certainly not be limited to, understanding the philosophical
underpinnings of Al Qaedas writings, beliefs, and pronouncements; the religious and
political leaders whom they admire and after whom they model themselves; the political
and religious history of Islam and the ancient caliphate, as well as the rise and fall of the
former Taliban regime; and finally, the Koran itself. This is not some mere academic
exercise; rather, Aron was acutely aware of the import of being fully cognizant of the way in
which ones adversary sees the world. In commenting on Americas actions after the
conclusion of the First and Second World War, Aron warned:
It is not enough to determine the objective, the ally, the enemy, in order to profit from the
victory. If the intelligence of the state has not clearly determined its goals, and discerned
the true nature of enemy and ally alike, the triumph of weapons will only by accident be an
authentic victory, that is, a political one. (30/42)
Once the true character of this terrorist group is comprehended, Aron would likely
emphasize employing a prudent, judicious rhetoric to combat it. As an editorialist who over
the course of thirty years wrote some 4,000 articles on contemporary politics, Aron was
fully aware of the necessity and power of rhetoric, and he used his prodigious talents to
promote civic harmony by showing France what was in its genuine self-interest, however
unpleasant that might be. In the case of Algeria, for example, Aron argued repeatedly that
independence was inevitable, and that France needed to quit the war as soon as it was
feasible. Algeria was no longer a colonial asset but a burdensome liability, and he called
upon political leaders and the public to recognize this fact and adopt what he called a
heroism of abandonment. Although one cannot be sure what Aron would advise in
respect to terrorism, it does appear as though the opposite situation obtains today: the
necessity of adopting a heroism of commitment. Precisely because terrorists are to some
extent able to win this war simply by not losing it, political leaders have the difficult
task of employing a rhetoric that combines encouragement and hope with a clear
understanding of the unique and protracted character of this conflict. The public must be
made aware that this struggle could likely continue for many years, if not decades, and
those politicians who make sweeping promises of a swift and decisive victory are being both
unrealistic and deeply irresponsible: as Al Qaeda has already demonstrated, they are more
than willing to go into hiding and wait patiently for the enemy to let down its guard before
they renew their attacks. Steadfastness, ardor, resilience: these are some of the qualities of
character that need to be inculcated and practiced today, qualities that are difficult enough
to cultivate let alone to sustain over many years.
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

12/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

The import of employing a proper rhetoric might seem a small thinguntil we see the
relationship between this and Arons understanding of how to evaluate a states power, both
offensively and defensively. At the highest level of generalization, a political units power is
determined by its territory, resources, and collective capacity for action (54/65). Aron notes
that the first two factors can more-or-less be objectively measured, and it is obvious that
the United States far and away exceeds Al Qaeda in economic and military strength. The
problem concerns how one can measure the third, especially over the long term (cf. 48/59).
It is incontestable that U.S. and coalition soldiers in Afghanistan and Iraq have displayed
remarkable courage and self-sacrifice; the question is how long the U.S. and its allies are
willing to prosecute the war on terrorism with an equally tenacious and vigorous
commitment. It is here that rhetoric plays a pivotal role: on the one hand, rhetoric can
summon forth spiritual resources which had hitherto remained untapped, and it can steel a
states resolve as it confronts a dangerous and uncertain future; on the other hand, rhetoric
can just easily conjure up hopes and expectations that are all but impossible to meet, and
which ultimately infect a country with disappointment, defeatism, or complacency. In other
words, rhetoric can help to sustain or undermine the necessary element of self-sacrifice that
every war entails and which so much determines a states collective capacity for action.
Indeed, rhetoric might even be more important in determining this capacity the greater a
states territory and resources: although a more developed country will have greater
resources to mobilize, its wealth might be a hidden liability, especially when it comes to a
protracted war. Aron observes:
In wartime the degree of mobilization is chiefly a function of administrative capacity, but
also, in part, of the peoples acceptance of sacrifice. Beyond a certain point the war effort
cannot be increased except by reducing the level of the standard of living of the civilian
population. How far can this reduction go without affecting the level of morale? This
question cannot be answered in any general way. It would seem, however, that peoples
accustomed to a low standard of living accept privations more easily than those accustomed
to a higher standard of living, which tends to reverse the purely theoretical proposition: the
margin of mobilization is directly proportional to the standard of living. In the abstract, the
gap between the actual condition of the people and the incompressible minimum is greater
in rich countries than in poor countries, but the former cannot always do without what the
latter classify as superfluous. (63/73)
The foregoing remarks have attempted to limn an Aronian-inspired analysis in the postSeptember 11th world. Obviously, we cannot turn to Arons corpus directly for answers to
political problems that plague our century. And yet, it is nevertheless the case that Peace
and War continues to speak to our times by offering us both the basic parameters and
conceptual tools that any rigorous analysis of the twenty-first century would have to
include: how the risk of war necessitates the calculation of means and ends; the power of
ideas, whether political or religious, in shaping the dialectic of international relations; a
regime-based study of the major actors in the international system; historical sociology to
identify the distinguishing characteristics and relevant variables of the system under
investigation; and lastly, the normative implications of the analysis. Certainly Arons
magisterial study of international politics did all of this and much more, and it was this
theoretical framework that helped to shape his prudent political advice throughout the Cold
War. At the end of the day, Aron might also provide us with the pithiest formulation of the
political dynamics we will be witnessing in the twenty-first century. In LeGrandSchisme,
Aron describing the emerging dialectics of the Cold War world as: paiximpossible,guerre
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

13/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

improbable. Given the goals and means available to Islamic terrorists, we would be forced
to conclude: paiximpossible,guerregarantie.

[1]. John Hall, Diagnoses of Our Time: Six Views on Our Social Condition (London: Heinemann
Educational Books, 1981), 164. Despite the overwhelmingly positive response it received upon
publication in France in 1962, it met with decidedly more mixed reviews in North America. For a
summary of both the French and American responses, see Robert Colquhoun, Raymond Aron: The
Sociologist in Society, 19551983, vol. 2 (London: SAGE Publications, 1986), 19197. For Arons
own estimation of the merits of the book, see his Mmoires: 50 ans de rflexion politique (Paris:
Julliard, 1983), recently reissued with a new preface by Tzvetan Todorov (Paris: Robert Laffont,
2003), 45159. [CUT: The abridged English translation is Memoirs: Fifty Years of Political
Reflection, trans. George Holoch (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1990), 3015.]
[2]. Stanley Hoffmann, An American Social Science: International Relations, Daedalus 106, no. 3
(Summer 1977): 45.
[3]. See Raymond Aron, Thinking Politically: A Liberal in the Age of Ideology, trans. James and
Marie McIntosh, intro. Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction
Publishers, 1997), 25354. Perhaps surprisingly, it should be noted that most other parts of Arons
voluminous corpus continue to enjoy a wide readership, both in North America, England, Western
Europe, and most recently in Central and Eastern Europe, where many of his works are being
translated.
[4]. Nicolas Baverez and Pierre Manent (interview), Raymond Aron: Political Liberalism, Civic
Passion, and Impartial Judgement, Society 41, no. 3 (March/April 2004): 17. It must be emphasized
that Baverez would not admit that Aron has nothing to teach us today, as the interview amply
confirms. [CUT: In the sentence immediately following the one quoted above, Baverez
continues: Otherwise, he comprehended everything: the rise of Nazism and of Stalinismin
short, the rise of totalitarianismsand he drew on both the personal and intellectual planes all
the requisite conclusions. A bit later in the interview, Baverez adds: To be sure, todays
world differs from Arons. But the fundamental questions that he posedthe contradictions
within modern liberty, the fragility of democratic institutions, the regulation of market
systems, the combination of war and peacethese are ever present.]
[5]. Daniel J. Mahoney and Brian C. Anderson, Introduction to the Transaction edition of
Raymond Aron, Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations, trans. Richard Howard and
Annette Baker Fox (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2003), xi. [CUT: The authors
refer to such scholars as Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York:
Free Press, 1993), Kenichi Ohmae, The Borderless World: Power and Strategy in the Interlinked
Economy (New York: HarperCollins, 1991), and John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, in On
Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, 1993, eds. Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley
(New York: Basic Books, 1993), 4182. (On this same theme, albeit written some twenty-five
years earlier, see Arons epilogue, Goodbye to Arms, or the Great Illusion, in Clausewitz:
Philosopher of War, trans. Christine Booker and Norman Stone [London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1983], 400412.)] All page citations to Peace and War in the text of this essay will be to the
Transaction edition followed by page citations to the French edition, Paix et Guerre entre les
nations, 5th ed. (Paris: Calmann-Lvy, 1962). [CUT: In general, I have followed the English
translation throughout, although I have sometimes altered it to make it more strictly literal.]
All emphasized words in quotations are contained in the original.
[6]. See, for example, Peace and War, 8384, 11124, 55472, 70336, 74349/9293, 11932,
54459, 691722, 72934, as well as [ADD:Mmoires, 298.]
[7]. Raymond Aron, On War, trans. Terence Kilmartin (New York: W. W. Norton, 1968), 11718.
[8]. For a relatively recent appreciation of Arons understanding of the limits of theory, see Jean
Bethke Elshtain, International Politics and Political Theory, in International Relations Theory
Today, eds. Ken Booth and Steve Smith (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press,
1995), 27478.
[9]. He certainly has much more in common with classical realism than he does with so-called
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

14/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

neorealismand the most well-known neorealist would certainly agree. In Theory of International
Politics (New York: Random House, 1979), 4349, as well as in Realist Thought and Neorealist
Theory, Journal of International Affairs 44, no. 1 (Spring 1990): 2137, Kenneth Waltz sharply
contrasts his understanding of theory with Arons. To be sure, both Waltz and Aron see the
international system as anarchic and that the distribution of capabilities or forces is an important
variable. But after this the similarities end, with Aron focusing on a host of other factors (perhaps
most notably, the character of the regimes of the most important powers).
[10]. It should be emphasized, however, that this appreciation of the role morality plays in
international relations never leads Aron to become a vapid moralizer, whether it be a Wilsonian
internationalist who insists that states act according to international law or an anti-globalization
activist who demands the elimination of capitalism and corporatism. There is no doubt that Aron
deplored lawlessness and oppression, violence and duplicity; but he also understood that, human
beings and states being what they are by nature, violence and duplicity often had to be employed to
prevent even greater evils from occurring. In fact, Aron recognized that such moralizing often had
the unintended consequence of bringing about the very event the moralizer decries (see
111ff./119ff.). One might say that Aron was enough of a realist not to become a moralizer but
enough of a moralist to see the realistic part morality played in international relations.
[11]. [ADD: Daniel J. Mahoney, The Liberal Political Science of Raymond Aron (Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield, 1992), 9396.]
[12]. [ADD: Aron, Conflict and War from the Viewpoint of Historical Sociology, in The
Nature of Conflict: Studies on the Sociological Aspects of International Relations (Paris:
UNESCO, 1957), 185, 19294.] It should be noted that historical sociology is enjoying something
of a renaissance in recent years, at least according to Stephen Hobden and John M. Hobson, eds.,
Historical Sociology of International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), ix,
whose volume of essays is an effort to take stock of this new development and to offer a sort of
historical-sociological manifesto for future research. But while this is certainly encouraging news
for international relations theory, it is very perplexing to see that one of the most persistent
champions of historical sociology is more or less ignored. Although Fred Halliday, For an
International Sociology, 24448, is clearly aware of and impressed by Arons early contributions in
this field, the only other time he is mentioned in the book (I believe) is in a footnote discussing
transnational society (Andrew Linklater, Towards a Critical Historical Sociology of Transnational
Harm, 169n8). If one were to hazard a guess as to why this is so, it might be related to the fact that
the editors wish to use historical sociology as a means to rethink theories and problematise the
analysis of the present, and thereby to reconfigure the international relations research agenda (5). In
this sense, the editors seem interested in problematising many of the common assumptions
underlying international relations theory as it has been generally understood and taught, and this
would seem to mean questioning the key assumptions and beliefs of classical realism, in general,
and therefore of Aron, in particular (1320, 26571). In other words, the conclusions Aron drew by
using historical sociology might be the very ones the editors and others wish to problematise or
reinterpret from whatever perspective in historical sociology they happen to come (2041, 27985).
But again, one can only hazard a guess: in other places, the editors show a discontent with current
approaches to international relations theory that is remarkably similar to Arons (e.g., 4345ff., 58,
27576).
[13]. In what follows, I will focus almost exclusively on Osama Bin Laden and Al Qaeda, and the
threat they pose to the United States, in particular, and the West, in general. It should go without
saying that other terrorist organizations will have very different goals and strategies.
[14]. Although Aron never offered (as far as I am aware) a detailed and schematic conceptualization
of terrorism as such, and although he may not have foreseen the rise of Islamic fundamentalism, he
was certainly familiar with both terrorism and Islam through his long meditations on the Algerian
War and the Front de Libration nationale (FLN) in such books as La Tragdie algrienne (Paris:
Plon,1957) and LAlgrie et la Rpublique (Paris: Plon, 1958). [CUT: Selections from both of
these pamphlets have been translated and published in The Dawn of Universal History:
Selected Essays from a Witness to the Twentieth Century, trans. Barbara Bray, ed. Yair Reiner,
intro. Tony Judt (New York: Basic Books, 2002), 40560.]
[15]. Tzvetan Todorov, Hope and Memory: Lessons from the Twentieth Century, trans. David Bellos
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003), xvi.
[16]. Aron, Conflict and War, 181. The definition referred to in the quote was that war was
Armed conflict between two independent political units, by means of organized military forces, in
http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

15/16

9/2/2015

IPRIInstituto Portugus de Relaes Internacionais

the pursuit of a tribal or national policy.


[17]. [ADD: Cf. Aron, The Anarchical Order of Power, in History, Truth, Liberty: Selected
Writings of Raymond Aron, ed. Franciszek Draus (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985),
25761.]
[18]. Of course, it should go without saying that if the United States believed its very existence was
in jeopardy from terrorism, then leaders and the public would certainly be willing to use much more
extreme means to eradicate this threat.

http://www.ipri.pt/artigos/artigo.php?ida=84

16/16

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen