Sie sind auf Seite 1von 9

Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.

12000

Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor


Ryan Muldoon*
University of Pennyslvania

Abstract
In epistemology and the philosophy of science, there has been an increasing interest in the social
aspects of belief acquisition. In particular, there has been a focus on the division of cognitive labor
in science. This essay explores several different models of the division of cognitive labor, with
particular focus on Kitcher, Strevens, Weisberg and Muldoon, and Zollman. The essay then shows
how many of the benefits of the division of cognitive labor flow from leveraging agent diversity.
The essay concludes by examining the benefits and burdens of diversity, particularly in the evalua-
tive diversity that can be found in interdisicplinary science.

1. Introduction
In both epistemology and the philosophy of science, there has been a growing interest in
the social aspect of belief acquisition. Rather than conceiving of scientists as Robinson
Crusoes, only relying on their own beliefs and talents for developing a research program,
carrying it out, and justifying their conclusions, we can more accurately conceive of sci-
entists as embedded in a larger social structure. Scientists, after all, read journals, go to
conferences, establish collaborations, seek out grant money, win acclaim and prestige, and
operate within a labor market.
In light of this, we might wish to ask ourselves how these social aspects of the scientific
enterprise influence the practice of science. Perhaps the most striking feature of the social
structure of science is that it encourages a division of cognitive labor. The most obvious divi-
sion appears in how scientists sort themselves into different disciplines and sub-disciplines.
By and large, chemists work on chemistry, biologists work on biology, and geologists
work on geology. This macro-level division of cognitive labor hides another division of
cognitive labor that operates within sub-disciplines.
When we consider this more fine-grained account of the division of cognitive labor,
our focus turns toward how individual scientists and labs take the decisions of others into
account. Perhaps most in line with traditional questions found in epistemology of science,
we can investigate how scientists update their beliefs based on evidence produced by
other scientists. Here we can consider how consensus might emerge in a scientific com-
munity, and ask whether or not the emergent consensus is likely to be true.
While questions of consensus in science focus on the context of justification, much of
the interest in the division of cognitive labor comes from the context of discovery. In
particular, how does a division of cognitive labor effect scientists choices about what
projects to pursue in the first place? This was the question that launched much of the
recent interest in the division of cognitive labor.
In what follows, we will examine different social features of science brought on by the
division of cognitive labor. First, we will investigate Philip Kitchers landmark discussion
of the division of cognitive labor, and Strevens elaborations on that model. We will

2013 The Author


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
118 Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor

briefly consider some critiques of this approach. We will then turn to Weisberg and
Muldoons epistemic landscapes model of the division of labor. We will then consider
how this division of cognitive labor can fit into models of scientific consensus. Finally,
we will consider the role that diversity plays in the various models of the division of
cognitive labor.

2. An Economic Approach to the Division of Cognitive Labor


Thomas Kuhn, in his Objectivity, Value Judgment and Theory Choice (Kuhn 1977)
raised the question of whether there was a tension between individual and collective
rationality in science. Kitcher (1990, 1993) picked up on this question. He envisioned a
stylized scenario of some set S of N scientists, each looking to pick between different
projects in the set R to uncover some significant truth (Kitcher supposes discovery of the
structure of a Very Important Molecule, VIM). Each project in the set has a return func-
tion: a function that takes a number of workers as input, and outputs a probability of suc-
cess. It is here that we face a tension between individual and collective rationality: if the
representative scientist is a pure Hempelian, just motivated by doing the best science,
then she will choose to work on the project with the most favorable return function
lets call that P1. But this is not optimal from a collective standpoint: it would be in the
communitys interest to hedge its bets by also having some scientists work on the less-
likely P2. This is just to suppose that P1(n) + P2(N n) Pr(both projects succeed) >
P1(N). That is, distributing cognitive labor across projects would do more to increase the
chance that the significant truth is discovered than if everyone worked on the most
promising project. So, we arrive at a formal articulation of the tension between individual
and collective rationality, as Kuhn suggested. This can manifest itself in a few ways, but
fundamentally it occurs because scientists fail to divide their labor: their choices were not
informed by the choices of others. However, Kitcher points out that we can do much to
alleviate that tension.
If we suppose that scientists, instead of being purely epistemically-minded, are sullied
insofar as they care about rewards. So rather than care about pure epistemic rationality,
scientists instead are economically rational: they seek out the greatest expected returns for
their labor. Now, we can better align collective rationality with individual rationality.
Rather than choosing a project based on its overall characteristics, scientists choose
projects based on their marginal contribution: how much their contribution to the project
would change the output of its return function. Scientists choose projects based on their
marginal contribution because it is based on this marginal contribution that they are
rewarded. Muldoon and Weisberg (2011) refer to this as a Marginal Contribu-
tion Reward model.
Strevens (2003) picked up on Kitchers MCR approach, and extended this model to
look at a series of potential reward schemes and how they might influence project choice.
Strevens argues that since scientific products are fairly unique in that they are only really
valuable the first time they are produced, unlike most normal goods like chairs or cheese-
burgers that are valuable each time they are produced. So, research programs must com-
pete to provide the scientific good first, creating what he calls a benefits race. Following
Kitcher, Strevens also argues that scientists themselves are competing in the rewards race.
Strevens argues that the parallel structure of these two races leads us towards the Priority
rule, which rewards just on actual achievement rather than effort, and rewards only the
first person to achieve. The Priority rule, as Merton (1957) notes, can seem strange: if
two scientists differ only in hours or minutes in achieving success, it is still the first to

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor 119

finish that gets any credit. Strevens seeks to show that it is the Priority rules unique
properties that promote optimal allocation of cognitive labor, and thus ensure that society
maximizes its benefits from the scientific community. Because of this, we can explain
why the Priority rule came to be, and justify its continued existence.
To do this, Strevens relies on Kitchers MCR approach, examining the allocation
properties of three rules: Marge, Goal, and Priority. Marge distributes resources according
to marginal contribution, rewarding scientists for how much their contributions improve
the success prospects of a project regardless of whether that project succeeds. Goal is a
modification of Marge, in which scientists are only rewarded if their project actually suc-
ceeds. This is most compatible with the reward scheme that Kitcher suggests. Finally,
Priority is a further refinement, in which rewards are only distributed to the project that
finishes first. Strevens argues that risk aversion will lead scientists to increasingly favor the
project most likely to succeed when we shift from Marge to Goal, since scientists are not
just rewarded for their efforts, but for successfully picking the correct project. The transi-
tion from Goal to Priority offers us a similar story: now scientists are only rewarded for
finishing first, and so they have reason to further bias their choices toward the most likely
project. Strevens argues that this aligns the benefits race, which only cares about the first
project to succeed, with the rewards race. Under this scheme, the scientific community
hedges its bets, since there remain incentives to work on understaffed projects, but it
skews the distribution of cognitive labor toward those projects that are most likely to
provide social benefits in a timely manner.
The MCR approach adopted by Kitcher and Strevens has numerous strengths: it
clearly illuminates how non-epistemic motives can lead to improved epistemic outcomes,
it shows how the division of cognitive labor is sensitive to the reward structure in sci-
ence, and it provides us with a view of how economic reasoning can inform our philo-
sophical understanding of the division of cognitive labor.
Goldman and Shaked (1991) are even more explicit about the economic aspect of their
modeling of the division of cognitive labor. In this model, scientists receive rewards when
they are able to conduct experiments that lead to altering the prior probability distribu-
tions that other scientists have over the world-state W. Scientists, rather than being in a
race for priority, or choosing between potential projects, are choosing between investiga-
tion and reporting their results. In this model, scientists can continually announce results,
and attempt to support or rebut previous claims. So rather than a single decision like the
MCR approach, scientists are continually engaging with each other, and assigning credit
based on how much each scientist alters the priors of the others. At any given round, a
scientist can choose between several experiments, each with three possible observational
outcomes. Once one has observed the outcome, they can either stay silent, or announce
that it supports one possible world-state over others. Agents can then rely on Bayesian
updating to see how their priors change, and award credit. We find that experiments that
are more able to discriminate between possible world-states are the experiments for
which scientists can receive the most credit. Interestingly, Goldman and Shaked argue
that if we compare credit-motivated agents to truth-motivated agents, credit-motivated
agents do well, but there is a range of cases for which truth-motivated agents will slightly
outperform them.

3. Challenges to the Economic Approach


Though the economic approach has offered several significant insights to our understand-
ing of the division of cognitive labor, it has not been without its critics. Notable among

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
120 Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor

them has been Hands (1995, 1997), who has warned that while economics appears to be
a potential resource for philosophy of science, it should be noted that economics has a
number of methodological challenges that must be taken seriously prior to adopting those
methods wholesale. Hands notes that much of philosophy of economics is about the fail-
ures of economic methodology, which might lead us to wonder whether those same
methods will necessarily be beneficial in our efforts to better understand the practice of
science. Wray (2000) points out that the invisible hand mechanism that is often invoked
in economic philosophy of science, perhaps most notably by Hull (1988), is not an
appropriate form of explanation, as very often the structures that help science operate
were deliberately chosen, rather than being endogenously generated by the choices of sci-
entists. Instead, were left with the hidden hand of our institutions guiding scientific
practice. This is compatible with the MCR model, as neither Kitcher nor Strevens
require that the reward schemes in science be endogenous to scientific practice.
A direct critique of the MCR model is seen in Muldoon and Weisberg (2011). In it,
they point out that the MCR modeling approach rests on two important idealizations:
the distribution assumption and the success function assumption. The distribution
assumption is that each scientist knows what project every other scientist is working on.
The success function assumption is that each scientist knows, prior to investigation, what
the precise success function for a given research project is. Without these two assump-
tions, agents would be unable to calculate their expected marginal utility for working on
a project. Muldoon and Weisberg weaken these idealizations in a series of agent-based
models, and show that if we allow for limited knowledge of what others work on, and a
distribution of beliefs about the nature of success functions, we can see dramatically
different results than those predicted with the idealizations in place. This suggests that the
models are not particularly robust. Given the nature of his project, this poses a larger
challenge for Strevens than it does for Kitcher.

4. Epistemic Landscapes
Weisberg and Muldoon (2009) developed an alternative approach to modeling the divi-
sion of cognitive labor. Rather than rely on an economic methodology, they adopted
something closer to an ecological approach. Scientists are imagined to be hill-climbers
on an unknown landscape.1 The landscape itself is interpreted as a topic of scientific
inquiry. The X and Y dimensions represent potential research approaches. The Z dimen-
sion represents the epistemic significance of any findings to be had given the research
approach indicated by the (X, Y) position. The landscape is broken up into patches of
unit size. At the beginning of inquiry, scientists have no knowledge of the landscape
that is, they do not know anything about the comparative significance of any research
approaches. They discover this only by traversing the landscape. Weisberg and Muldoon
interpret this traversal as a series of research efforts. Each patch visited is equivalent to
doing an experiment, reading the existing literature as it pertains to that research
approach if it exists, or communicating with others who have already tried that approach.
The scientist themselves can have one of three different research strategies, which are
understood as different ways of responding to the research of others.
The simplest approach is simply the control research strategy. The scientists in the
control group simply ignore all of the other scientists, and adopt a classic hill-climbing
strategy. The strategy is simple: the scientist adopts a random heading, and moves forward
one patch. If the new patch is more significant, then the scientist takes another step for-
ward. If not, but the patch is of equivalent significance, then with a 2% probability the

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor 121

scientist moves forward one patch with a random heading. If the patch is of lower signifi-
cance, the scientist moves back her previous patch and chooses a new random heading,
and starts again. With this research strategy, the scientist is sure to find local maxima of
significance on the epistemic landscape. Most importantly, however, this strategy embod-
ies scientists without a concept of the division of cognitive labor. They work on their
own research, but pay no heed to what anyone else is doing. This will find them some
individual success, but it is not socially optimal.
A second approach that Weisberg and Muldoon consider is the follower strategy.
This is strategy is designed to embody the strategy of standing on the shoulder of giants
in ones scientific research. In each round of the model, followers consider the eight
patches in their Moore neighborhood each immediately adjacent space from their cur-
rent position. If any approaches in the neighborhood have been investigated and of
greater significance than the current approach, then the scientist moves towards the
approach of greatest significance (in a tie, she flips a coin). If none of the already-investi-
gated patches are of greater significance, and there are approaches that havent been tried,
then the agents go there. Otherwise, they stop. This strategy does allow for a division of
cognitive labor followers will take the efforts of others into account in their research
strategy, and take it as evidence that nearby already-explored approaches are where good
prospects for future research lie. Perhaps surprisingly, a population of followers does
worse than the control population. They find peaks in the landscape less often, and cover
less significant ground. Followers divide their labor, but do so inefficiently.
The final approach that Muldoon and Weisberg consider is the maverick strategy.
Mavericks, like followers, take information about what others have done into account,
but in an entirely different way. Rather than follow what others have done, mavericks
take that as evidence that they should go in a different direction. In each round, they ask
if their current research approach is at least as significant as the previous approach. If so,
then if any patches in the scientists Moore neighborhood are unvisited, she picks ran-
domly between them. If all have been investigated, then she moves to the patch of high-
est significance, or stops if none is higher than where she is. If her current patch is less
significant than the previous patch, she returns to the previous patch and sets a new ran-
dom heading. This strategy is notable for attempting to maximize cognitive diversity.
Followers, by design, attempt to correlate their research efforts with what has already
been done. Mavericks attempt to anti-correlate. They take what has been done as an
indication that they should do something different. This strategy pays off for them
remarkably well: mavericks vastly outperform both followers and controls. Even small
populations of mavericks almost always find all maxima on the landscape, and have very
good coverage of other significant portions of the landscape.
Perhaps most interestingly, however, is what happens when Weisberg and Muldoon
examine mixed populations of followers and mavericks. These mixed populations do better
than just populations of mavericks, but it is not all the direct effect of mavericks. Mavericks
stimulate followers to cover more fruitful territory, and serve to divide the followers up
more than in a pure follower population. We see that each research strategy has a role:
mavericks are very good at getting a general lay of the land, and efficiently find peaks. But
followers do much of the work involved with filling in details, examining the areas around
the paths blazed by the mavericks. The follower strategy, seemingly foolish by itself,
becomes useful once there are a few mavericks around. If we imagine that the maverick
research strategy to be more costly than the follower strategy, then this model might ade-
quately describe some features of the real division of cognitive labor in science as it is now
practiced: a few mavericks stimulating the efforts of many more followers.

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
122 Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor

This approach affirms a key finding of Kitchers: that a population of Hempelian scien-
tists who just work on the apparently-best projects, regardless of whatever anyone else is
working on, do much worse than populations of scientists who consciously divide their
labor by making research choices informed by the work of others. However, the paper
expands on this point by demonstrating that how one responds to evidence matters a great
deal. A population of followers does worse than a population of controls. But a popula-
tion with mavericks will vastly outperform controls. Whats even more striking, however,
is that the interaction of mavericks and followers further divides cognitive labor: maver-
icks break new ground, while followers do the detailed work of exploring variants on
those original efforts. This diversity of responses to the work of others enables a much
finer analysis of the division of labor than could be discussed in the MCR approach.

5. Models of Scientific Consensus


For a scientific discipline to be a cohesive social enterprise, scientists must seek to estab-
lish some common consensus. Epistemic communities need to share some common
beliefs to ground debates over their differences. Otherwise, we would just have a collec-
tion of strangers who happen to be interested in some of the same things. Biologists
believe in the neo-Darwinian synthesis. Doctors believe in the germ theory of disease.
Physicists agree on the speed of light. Each of these consensus beliefs started out as
research programs. Through a process of evidence-gathering, publishing, and discussion,
scientists slowly converged on a single answer.
A prominent model of this has been the Lehrer-Wagner model of consensus formation.
(Lehrer 1975; Wagner 1978, 1982, 1985; Lehrer and Wagner 1981) This is a repeated-
averaging model, which was seen in earlier work as well (French 1956; DeGroot 1974).
This model represents a simplified rational reconstruction of consensus formation. As peo-
ple discuss their beliefs, they update their personal beliefs based on that discussion.2 It is a
gradual process, and is simply a function of the agents initial estimates of some value,
and their epistemic respect for one another. This model assumes that the process of gath-
ering evidence is complete: the agents have assessed all of the available information and
arrived at their estimates.
Hegselmann and Kraus (2006) extend this averaging model with a more explicit divi-
sion of labor, and a clear anchor of truth to converge on. In their model, which utilizes
both analytic proofs and agent-based simulation, they look at populations wherein only
some are truth seekers, and others have varying cognitive capacities. There is a truth to
be found, and the question that is explored is under what conditions will a population of
scientists reliably converge on it. This breaks a number of the symmetries inherent in the
repeated averaging approach, but builds on the basic principles behind the model.
Surprisingly, they show that relatively few truth-seekers are needed for convergence on
the truth in a wide variety of cases.
Another approach to consensus modeling, perhaps closer to the actual practice of sci-
ence, is one in which we continue to gather evidence until we reach consensus. Scientists
continue to conduct experiments and share their results until they all come to agree about
the question at hand. Zollman (2010) takes this to be one application of the division of
cognitive labor. In particular, Zollman explores how diversity might facilitate ensuring that
scientific consensus ultimately tracks truth, by slowing down consensus until sufficient
investigation has taken place. Zollman focuses on an example taken from medicine, look-
ing at two different treatments for peptic ulcer disease, one relying on the idea that bacteria
cause the ulcers, the second relying on the idea that it is excess acid in the stomach.

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor 123

Zollman models scientists as Bayesians who play two-armed bandits, connected by lines
of communication with other scientists. Each arm of the bandit represents an investiga-
tion into a treatment method one supposes an antibacterial approach, one an acid
reduction approach. If an arm is pulled, the payoff is simply whether the particular treat-
ment method succeeded. As with casino slot machines, the challenge is that each arm has
a payoff distribution, but this distribution is unknown to the agent. Scientists, if they are
connected to each other in a communication structure, can observe what payoffs the
others got from pulling a particular arm. Each agent has prior beliefs about the nature of
each arms payoff distribution. Every time the scientist pulls an arm and receives a payoff,
the scientist updates their priors. Importantly, scientists can also observe anyone who they
are directly connected to in a communication network, and also use that to update their
priors. In every given round, scientists pull the arm that they think is superior, and
update their priors based on their performance, and the performance that they observe
from other scientists that they can communicate with. Zollman examines several different
symmetric network structures, and demonstrates that those structures with fewer connec-
tions less communication between scientists are most correlated with scientists con-
verging on the superior bandit arm. This is due to the fact that less-connected networks
reduce the amount of communication among scientists. This reduced communication
allows greater variety in individual scientists beliefs, until they all start converging on the
right outcome. Too much homogeneity too soon can result in consensus, but consensus
of the wrong kind.
Zollman points to another way of generating this diversity. If we are stuck with
highly-connected scientists, we can instead give some of them extreme priors. Those
individuals who will be less responsive to new evidence from others will be able to con-
tinue to test alternative hypotheses at a rate sufficient to bring others around if they hap-
pen to be right. However, Zollman points out that if we combine these two mechanisms
for generating diversity extreme priors on a more minimal network then diversity
can prove to be too stable, and convergence cannot be achieved.

6. The Benefits and Burdens of Diversity


In several of the models of the division of cognitive labor that we have seen, diversity
plays an important and positive role. Kuhn discusses the risk-hedging value of diversity,
which is explicitly manifested in the MCR models of Kitcher and Strevens. Weisberg
and Muldoon show how diversity matters in two ways: the anti-correlation of maverick
strategies promote fuller scientific exploration, while the difference in cognitive styles
manifested in the information processing differences between mavericks and followers
promote a division of exploration of new scientific frontiers and exploitation of existing
ones amongst scientists. Zollman showed how transient diversity in beliefs, whether
fostered by limited communication or stubborn scientists, can help ensure that scientific
consensus tracks the truth. In all of these examples, diversity helps us. In fact, the division
of cognitive labor promotes diversity in the sense that it encourages differences in agents,
and as more diversity is generated, we can make a finer-grained division of labor.
However, diversity can manifest itself not just in ways we process information, or what
our priors are, or what project we pick. We can also find diversity in our evaluative
judgments. We can disagree about what values we ought to be promoting in our episte-
mic endeavors. We can disagree about what the right standards are for epistemic success.
DAgostino (2009) points out that the division of cognitive labor will generate a diversity
of evaluative standards as a consequence of generating the features that we have shown to

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
124 Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor

be valuable. On this model, we get increasingly high-dimensional spaces to explore, and


not necessarily any agreement on what dimensions matter the most. With this, our goals
of widespread consensus may become more difficult, but the further division of cognitive
labor becomes all the more important. Clusters of researchers can pick areas of this high-
dimensional space to explore with whatever search strategies they see as useful. If they
are sufficiently diverse in their interests and abilities, they might collectively be able to
effectively search the complex search space. But this will not have the character of a cen-
tralized, organized search instead it will be a process of devolution of standards to more
localized judgments about best practices and methods.
If this is the path that the increasing diversity brought on by the division of cognitive
labor leads us down, what are we to do? One answer is to look at those areas of philosophy
of science that already focus on the massively interdisciplinary work that can be found in
Big Science projects, such as radar, particle detectors, or more recently, large colliders.
Galison (1997) developed the trading zone metaphor for scientific collaborations that
involve multiple disciplines of science and engineering. In anthropology, a trading zone is
where two or more communities meet to trade goods, even if they often lack a common
language. Pidgins or creoles develop, enabling people to be able to trade effectively, even if
they do not always understand everything that the other party would like to express. Simi-
larly in science, Galison argues that scientists and engineers develop common symbols and
scientific pidgins that enable information exchange. Given the need for successful coordi-
nation, new kinds of expertise can emerge: the ability to facilitate exchanges between disci-
plines becomes increasingly valuable in these kinds of environments.
With the advent of the study of the division of cognitive labor, epistemology and the
philosophy of science have become more sensitive to the social nature of scientific inquiry.
Great strides have been made in understanding how our collective epistemic goals might
be helped by focusing on our individual interests, and the social structures of science that
can influence them. Diversity can be shown to be a benefit both in the context of discov-
ery and the context of justification. However, there is much work left to do. Developing
new mechanisms for understanding how to mitigate the burdens of increased evaluative
diversity, if not find a way to leverage potential benefits, is essential as the scientific com-
munity attempts to engage in increasingly interdisciplinary work at the same time as scien-
tists become more and more specialized. Epistemic rationality alone does not tell us how to
pick a scheme of evaluation. Nor does it tell us how to negotiate with those who have
different standards than us. Yet, it is essential for many of our collective epistemic goals that
we find ways of navigating these challenges. The world is complex enough that it drives us
to divide our cognitive labor in our attempt at understanding it. We need to be sure that
we can find a way of putting our divided endeavors back together again.

Short Biography
Ryan Muldon is a post-doctoral fellow in the Philosophy, Politics and Economics program
at the University of Pennsylvania. Previously, he was a post-doctoral fellow at the Rotman
Institute of Philosophy at the University of Western Ontario. His research focuses on
diversity in the social contract, norm dynamics, and the division of cognitive labor.

Notes
* Correspondence: Philosophy, Politics and Economics, University of Pennyslvania, 311 Claudia Cohen Hall, 249
S 36th Street, Philadelphia, PA, USA. Email: rmuldoon@sas.upenn.edu.

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd
Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor 125
1
Hill-climbing models are a kind of local optimization technique found in computer science. In these models,
agents try and climb uphill on some landscape that they cannot see in advance. Essentially, they are like blind
hikers who are looking for the top of the mountain. They climb uphill when they can, and avoid going downhill.
The landscape component is a representation of whatever problem for which the modeler would like to find an
optimum.
2
The core idea of the model is that we have N members of a group G that is seeking to come to consensus over
something, whether it be a value of a constant, or the probability of an event, or something else that is similarly
reducible to a numeric value. Each member i of the group has an assessment of each member js expertise on the
question at hand, represented by wij. This assessment provides a measure of the respect an agent has for each of her
peers. Lehrer and Wagner then use these weights to construct an NxN matrix W, representing the total respect
assessments in the group. They constrain the wijs in W such that none of them are negative, and that the values in
each row sum to 1. This matrix W is then multiplied against the vector E, which is simply the vector of everyones
estimates of the value in question. In the resulting product WE the estimates have been modified according to the
respect assessments. Assuming we still lack consensus, this process is repeated k times until WkE has identical com-
ponents. These components are then the consensus estimate.

Works cited
DAgostino, Fred. From the Organization to the Division of Cognitive Labor. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 8.1
(2009): 10129.
DeGroot, M. H. Reaching a Consensus. Journal of the American Statistical Association 69.345 (1974): 11821.
French, J. R. A Formal Theory of Social Power. Psychological Review 63.3 (1956): 18194.
Galison, P. Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Goldman, A. and M. Shaked. An Economic Model of Scientific Activity and Truth Acquisition. Philosophical Stud-
ies 63 (1991): 3155.
Hands, D. Wade. Social Epistemology Meets the Invisible Hand: Kitcher on the Advancement of Science. Dia-
logue 34 (1995): 60521.
. Caveat Emptor: Economics and Contemporary Philosophy of Science. Philosophy of Science 64 (1997): s10716.
Hegselmann, R. and U. Krause. Truth and Cognitive Division of Labour: First Steps Towards a Computer Aided
Social Epistemology. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 9(3)10 (2006). [online]. Retrieved on 29
August 2012 from: http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/9/3/10.html.
Hull, David. Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1988.
Kitcher, Philip. The Division of Cognitive Labor. Philosophy of Science 87 (1990): 522.
. The Advancement of Science. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993.
Kuhn, T. S. The Essential Tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1977.
Lehrer, K. Social Consensus and Rational Agnoiology. Synthese 31 (1975): 14160.
. and C. Wagner. Rational Consensus in Science and Society. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981.
Merton, Robert. Priorities in Scientific Discovery. American Sociological Review 22 (1957): 63959.
Muldoon, R. and Weisberg. M. Robustness and Idealization in Models of Cognitive Labor. Synthese 183.2
(2011): 16174.
Strevens, Michael. The Role of the Priority Rule in Science. Journal of Philosophy 100.2 (2003): 5579.
Wagner, Carl. Consensus Through Respect: A Model of Rational Group Decision-Making. Philosophical Studies
34 (1978): 33549.
. Allocation, Lehrer Models, and the Consensus of Probabilities. Theory and Decision 14 (1982): 20720.
. On the Formal Properties of Weighted Averaging as a Method of Aggregation. Synthese 25 (1985): 23340.
Weisberg, M. and R. Muldoon. Epistemic Landscapes and the Division of Cognitive Labor. Philosophy of Science
76.2 (2009): 22552.
Wray, Brad. Invisible Hands and the Success of Science. Philosophy of Science 67.1 (2000): 16375.
Zollman, Kevin J. S. The Epistemic Benefit of Transient Diversity. Erkenntnis 72 (2010): 1735.

2013 The Author Philosophy Compass 8/2 (2013): 117125, 10.1111/phc3.12000


Philosophy Compass 2013 Blackwell Publishing Ltd

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen