Sie sind auf Seite 1von 16

Peace, War, and the Balance of Power

Author(s): R. Harrison Wagner


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 593-607
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944797
Accessed: 26-02-2017 19:14 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The American Political Science Review

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3 September 1994

PEACE, WAR, AND THE BALANCE OF POWE


R. HARRISON WAGNER University of Texas, Austin

E very possible relation between the distribution of power and the likelihood of war has been
defended somewhere in the literature on international politics: war is least likely if power is
distributed equally, war is least likely if power is distributed unequally, and the distribution
of power has no effect on the likelihood of war. I try to settle this dispute by examining the effect o
expectations about the outcome of war on the choice between war and negotiation. I argue that each
of these mutually contradictory propositions can be derived from some plausible set of premises and
thus that which one is correct depends on which set of premises best describes a situation. The most
important factors affecting the relation between the distribution of power and the likelihood of war are
(1) whether the terms of a compromise agreement that might be accepted in lieu of war affect the
distribution of power between the antagonists and therefore the probability that the agreement will b
enforced and (2) how many states' interests will be affected by the outcome.

T he change in the distribution of power caused could provide the basis for the construction of formal
by the collapse of the Soviet Union has led to models, referring the reader to examples in the liter-
renewed interest in the relation between the ature whenever possible. Formal theorists will find
global distribution of power and the likelihood of this insufficiently rigorous. My excuse is that in this
war. More recently, there has been controversy about case one must choose between generality and rigor,
whether increasing the military strength of the and some rigorous models in the literature have
Bosnian forces in the Yugoslavian civil war would made unwarranted claims to generality.
make a settlement of that conflict more likely. Unfor- First, I shall summarize the reasons that scholars
tunately, the literature on international politics is not have given in support of each of the various possible
much help in thinking about questions such as these, relations between the distribution of power and the
since every possible relation between the distribution likelihood of war. I will argue that the sources of their
of power and the likelihood of war has been de- disagreement lie in the degree to which they treat
fended somewhere in it: war is least likely if power is attackers and defenders symmetrically, the assump-
distributed equally (Claude 1962, 56-66); war is least tions they make about the relation between the
likely if power is distributed unequally (Blainey 1988, balance of forces and the expectations of decision
108-24; Organski 1958, 292-93); and the distribution makers, and the assumptions they make about the
of power has no effect on the likelihood of war (Witt- alternative to war. While they differ in these respects,
man 1979, 749-51). Moreover, the empirical literature however, all writers on this subject tend to assume
on this subject is equally divided.' that any conclusions that one might draw about the
Because the arguments that have been offered in effects of the distribution of power in a world of two
support of these contradictory propositions have of- states also hold true in a world of more than two
ten been incomplete and intuitive, it seems plausible states. Subsequently, I shall consider what justifica-
that the cause of this disagreement has been sloppy tion there is for any of the assumptions these writers
reasoning and that the right answer can be found by have made. I will begin by examining the relation
being more careful about what conclusions follow between fighting and negotiating in a world of two
from what premises. One might therefore be tempted states and then examine the effect of adding more
to believe that if one of these propositions can be states.
derived from a formal model it must be true and the The main conclusion is that the most important
others false. I will argue that such an inference would factor affecting the relation between the distribution
be wrong. I will show how each of these contradic- of power and the likelihood of war is whether the
tory propositions can be derived from some plausible terms of a compromise agreement that might be
set of premises and therefore argue that the answer to accepted in lieu of war affect the relative power of the
the question depends on which premises best de- antagonists and therefore the probability that the
scribe a situation. agreement will be enforced. If they do, then a second
Any formal model supporting one or another of important factor is the number of states whose inter-
these contradictory propositions would be complex. I ests will be affected by the outcome. Thus the answer
cannot here fully develop several formal models to to the question of what relation one should expect
illustrate the implications of various alternative sets between the distribution of power and the likelihood
of assumptions and then compare them. I shall of war is, "It depends." The point of the analysis is to
therefore merely sketch several lines of argument that try to make clear what it depends on.

593

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

THE SOURCES OF DISAGREEMENT less the probability of war. This reasoning implies
that if the likelihood of war is to be minimized, not
The idea that war is least likely if power is distributed every state can expect to be able to defend its inter-
equally seems so obvious to many people that it is ests.
rare that anyone feels the need to justify it. However, However, this argument only implies that given an
it is clearly based in part on two assumptions: (1) the attack, the probability that it will lead to war is less,
less likely a state is to be successful, the less likely it the greater the superiority of the attacker. But the
is to start a war; and (2) the smaller a state's military previous argument implies that the probability of an
forces are relative to its adversary's, the less likely it is attack is least, the more nearly equal the two side's
to be successful. If one state is known to have no forces are. Thus the two together imply that the
incentive to use force even if it expected to be probability of war is greatest for distributions some-
successful, these assumptions imply that the likeli- where between equality and great inequality. To get
hood of war could be minimized by making that state the conclusion that the probability of war is mini-
as powerful as possible relative to its potential adver- mized by inequality, one must show that there is
saries. But since there is no reliable way of knowing some degree of inequality such that the probability
which states, if any, will never be tempted to use that the victim of an attack will resist is smaller than
force, most writers assume that all states are equally the probability that a state will choose to attack when
likely to contemplate the use of force if the prospects their forces are equal. But if defenders must choose
of success are favorable. Many people infer from between fighting against a superior force and capitu-
these assumptions that the probability that either of lation, they may be willing to fight even if the chances
two potential adversaries will start a war must be of success are very small. Therefore, the degree of
least when their forces are equal (see, e.g., Claude inequality that would be necessary to minimize the
1962, 56; Mearsheimer 1991, 154).2 probability of war might have to be very great indeed.
However, if we assume (as is commonly done) that However, because war is costly and its outcome
there are only two possible outcomes of war (i.e., one uncertain, there ought to be some negotiated settle-
state wins or the other does), then this conclusion ment that both sides would prefer to the costly lottery
does not follow from these premises. Since the dis- associated with war-in which case, the alternative to
tribution of power between two potential combatants war will be not capitulation but a negotiated settle-
affects the probability of success for both and the ment. But then, since the value of any proposed
probabilities of success must sum to one, decreasing agreement must be compared to the expected value
one state's probability of success must increase the of going to war, the minimum terms that each side
other's by the same amount. Thus it is not clear why will accept will be influenced by how optimistic it is
any decrease in the first state's incentive to use force about the outcome of war. Since the balance of power
should not increase the other's by the same amount, (i.e., the relative size of each side's military forces)
leaving the probability of war unchanged. If so, the influences the expected outcome of war, it influences
distribution of power would be unrelated to the the minimum terms that each will accept. But if a
probability of war. change in the balance of power makes one state more
The simplest (but not the only possible) answer to optimistic about the outcome of war and therefore
this objection is that there are three possible out- leads it to increase its demands, it must make the
comes of war, not just two: one or the other side other more pessimistic and therefore willing to accept
wins, or there is a stalemate. The probability that the a less favorable settlement. This is the basis for the
war will end in stalemate is greatest when the forces claim that a change in the balance of power affects the
of the two sides are equal. In that case the sum of the terms of the settlement that states would accept as an
probabilities that each state will win is least when alternative to war but not the probability that war will
their forces are equal. Note, however, that while the occur (Fearon 1992; Wittman 1979, 749-51).
probability that either state will use force may, as a But this reasoning assumes that decision makers'
result, be least in this situation, both states may still expectations about the outcome of war are consistent.
have an incentive to use force that is uncomfortably If they are not and both sides are optimistic about the
large. outcome, then there may be no negotiated settlement
This reasoning assumes that wars are caused by the that they both prefer to war (Wittman 1979, 755-57).
states that initiate them, so that one has only to This provides another justification for the view that
examine the incentives of aggressors to estimate the war is least likely when power is distributed un-
probability of war. One justification for the claim that equally: Blainey (1988) claims that it is more likely
inequality of power minimizes the probability of war that both antagonists will be optimistic when power
is based on the fact that it takes at least two states to is distributed equally than when it is distributed
make a war and assumes that the reasoning just unequally and therefore that states are most likely to
applied to attackers also applies to defenders. If states be able to agree on a negotiated settlement as an
that are unlikely to be successful are unlikely to use alternative to war when power is distributed un-
force, then weak defenders are least likely to resist an equally. According to Blainey, this explains why wars
attack. And if defenders do not resist the demands of can be ended by negotiations even though negotia-
aggressors, then wars will not occur (Organski 1958, tions failed to prevent them.4 However, Blainey does
292-93). Thus the greater the inequality of power, the not make clear why there should be a relation be-

594

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

tween the distribution of power and the consistency Suppose after they have been deadlocked for a while
of two states' expectations concerning the outcome of one of them considers whether to give in. After all,
a possible war between them. deadlock could last forever, and it seems reasonable
These conflicting lines of argument raise two fun- that both bargainers would prefer to accept some-
damental questions: (1) Is a negotiated settlement thing now to getting some larger sum later. But
always available as an alternative to war? and (2) If a precisely because this is true of both, it is as good a
negotiated settlement is available, how does the reason for either to decide to wait for the other to give
relative military power of the adversaries affect their in as it is a reason to give in oneself. And this remains
choice between war and negotiation? I shall focus on true no matter how long they have been deadlocked:
the second question first. To answer it we must exam- if the other is about to give in, it is better to wait for
ine the relation between fighting and negotiating. his concession than to give in to him unnecessarily,
no matter how much time has already passed.
Consider now the possibility of offering to accept a
FIGHTING AND NEGOTIATING compromise instead. By conceding some of what the
other is demanding, one reduces the potential gain to
Although war and negotiation are usually presented him of holding out for more: the difference between
as alternatives to each other, I shall claim that war is 90% and 50%, for example, is much less than the
best understood as part of a process of negotiation. difference between 90% and 10%. Perhaps, then, a
Thus, while adversaries can certainly choose to ne- concession will lead to agreement. However, if the
gotiate rather than fight, if they fight it is because other expects the first concession to be followed
each sees fighting as a way to influence the outcome
quickly by another, then he may reason that while
of negotiations. The place to begin, therefore, is not
the potential reward to stubbornness has diminished,
with an examination of war but with an examination
the probability of getting the reward has increased.
of bargaining.
Thus a concession may simply make the other more
recalcitrant rather than less. But instead of offering
Bargaining further concessions, the bargainer who made the first
one may decide that it had the wrong effect and offer
The essential feature of bargaining is that two or more
no more.
actors will be better off if they coordinate their actions
The reason it is difficult to say what individuals
than if they do not but that they have conflicting
should do in an unstructured face-to-face bargaining
preferences as to which actions are to be selected
situation such as this is that every possible division of
from some larger feasible set. The paradigmatic ex-
the money is supported not just by an equilibrium
ample is two people who can divide a sum of money
between them if and only if they agree on how it is to combination of strategies but by a sequentially ration-
be divided. If each of them is interested only in al equilibrium. There are two ways of circumventing
receiving the largest possible amount of money, then this indeterminacy: one can extend the definition of
what each will be willing to accept will depend on his rational behavior to include a variety of intuitions as
expectation of what the other is willing to accept. This to how a rational person should respond to it, or one
is the sort of problem that game theory is supposed to can impose some further structure on the situation,
help us analyze. It has proved, however, to be (e.g., by requiring the bargainers to communicate
extraordinarily resistant to analysis. The purpose of offers to each other only in a certain order and at
most discussions of bargaining is to defend one or certain fixed intervals).5 However, any solution that
another solution to this problem. However, the ques- is based on understanding the independent choices
tion of what agreement rational bargainers will accept of the two bargainers must specify a bargaining
is less relevant to understanding why states prefer strategy for both such that given the behavior speci-
fighting to negotiating than the question of how long fied by the strategy, at the time of the predicted
it will take them to accept it, a question that most agreement neither bargainer could expect to gain by
bargaining theory has little to say about. Thus it may waiting instead of accepting the prescribed agree-
be more relevant to emphasize why what is com- ment. But since the effect of waiting depends on how
monly called "the bargaining problem" is such a hard the other bargainer responds to it, it must be common
problem. knowledge that the prescribed solution is sequen-
Consider, then, two people in a room discussing tially rational and therefore the value the bargainers
what agreement they will sign, and suppose one of place on agreements now relative to agreements later
them demands 90% of the money. This may seem must also be common knowledge. Thus it is not
outrageous to the other, but if that is the only surprising that two bargainers will often both be
agreement the person making this demand is willing optimistic about the effect of holding out for better
to accept, then the only rational choice is for the other terms, and it seems entirely possible that even ration-
to accept it, since 10% of the money is better than al bargainers with a good understanding of the prob-
nothing. But this reasoning applies to either bar- lem might take so long to reach an agreement that,
gainer. Suppose, then, both demand 90% of the had they anticipated the outcome, they both would
money. Then they will get nothing unless one or the have preferred to accept the other's offer at the
other changes his demand. But which should it be? outset.6

595

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

Bargaining and Fighting and that one offers a compromise based on his
expectation of the consequences of continuing the
Now suppose that one bargainer grabs the other's struggle. If he releases his grip in response to the
arm and twists it painfully behind him while de- other's apparent agreement, this may allow the other
manding that he give in. Because this has the effect ofbargainer to grab him in a hold he would be unable to
increasing the cost of disagreement for the victim, break and compel him to accept a much worse
standard solutions to the bargaining problem imply agreement than the one he offered. Thus, because no
that this ought to worsen the terms of the bargain one can compel a bargainer not to renege on an offer
that he ultimately accepts. Note, however, that while he has made, once the struggle has begun, neither
this assault may mean that the victim is willing to bargainer may be willing to consider a compromise
surrender all the money to the other bargainer, it until its outcome has been decided.
does not necessarily mean that. While the costs of This rather fanciful story about a wrestling match
disagreement are now much greater for the victim began with one bargainer trying to seize the other in
than for the attacker, the attacker presumably still (as a painful grip in order to force him to agree to a deal
before) prefers an agreement now to an agreement that was less favorable to him (and therefore more
later and might therefore be willing to agree to less favorable to the attacker). Before attacking his fellow
than everything in order to shorten the time to bargainer, however, he could merely threaten to do
agreement. In other words, this assault may not it, and the other could then threaten to retaliate in
deprive the victim of all bargaining power. This is kind. They could then make demands and counter-
because the one who is twisting the other's arm stilldemands of each other based on those threats. Since
requires the cooperation of his victim. If not (e.g., if no one would have tackled anyone at that point,
he can simply take the other's money once he is no however, it is possible to doubt that anyone would or
longer able to resist), then by disabling the other he that if one did, the other would actually resist.
can take everything. Moreover, even if he did resist and were successful in
Perhaps, however, the victim of this maneuver can avoiding being pinned down, he might quickly offer
evade the other's grip and retaliate. If he succeeds in a compromise settlement. Thus each bargainer must
twisting the arm of the first, then the bargaining choose between accepting some proposed agreement
advantage shifts to him. If not, then a struggle may and using force to try to extract a better one. If they
ensue. At every moment during this struggle there both decide to use force, this is not because they have
are three possibilities: either bargainer may succeed decided not to bargain but because they believe
in pinning the other down, or the struggle may fighting will improve their bargaining position.
continue. The struggle itself is unpleasant, however,Each bargainer's expectations of the consequences
and therefore either bargainer may decide he prefers of rejecting any particular proposal can be divided
to offer a compromise in hope that the other will into two categories: expectations about the outcome
agree and they can quit. Perhaps they might pause in of bargaining in various possible circumstances (in-
their struggle to consider further offers and counter- cluding the outright victory of one or the other
offers, or perhaps they might continue to communi- bargainer) and expectations about the outcome of a
cate while struggling. Either way, they must, as fight. How many possible outcomes of a fight are
before, evaluate the terms of any possible offer rela- there? One plausible answer is that there are three:
tive to the possibility of doing better by holding out. one or the other loses, or there is a stalemate. Thus
However, the value of holding out has now become expectations should take the form of a probability
rather complex. It must include an evaluation of the distribution over these three possibilities. However,
unpleasantness associated with the struggle, an esti- one could argue that no stalemate could last forever-
mate of how long it might last, an estimate of the that one or the other would eventually tire and have
probability that either might ultimately emerge as to submit, though this might take a long time. In that
victor, an estimate of the value of each of the possible case, one might want to say that there are only two
agreements that might be accepted in the event that possible outcomes: one wins, or the other does. But if
either won the struggle, along with the probability they care about how long it takes for one to win (as
associated with each, and an estimate of the range of surely they would), then we would have to say that
possible agreements that the other might accept later there are infinitely many possible outcomes: a victory
in the struggle along with the probability associated for one or the other at every possible time at which it
with each and how long it would take before the might occur.
other was willing to accept them. Therefore there are In thinking of their expectations concerning the
now two reasons why bargaining may take so long as outcome of fighting, one must distinguish between
to be self-defeating: each can continue to be optimis- how uncertain they are and how consistent their
expectations are. They are maximally uncertain if
tic that the other will soon tire of the contest and offer
a concession, and each can continue to be optimistic they believe all possible outcomes are equally likely.
that he will soon defeat the other and gain an Their expectations are consistent, however, only if
important bargaining advantage. the probability they each assign to every outcome is
Moreover, the use of force adds a qualitatively the same. If they are both maximally uncertain, then
different element to this situation. Suppose our two their expectations must necessarily be consistent. If
bargainers have struggled inconclusively for a while not and if each has private information relevant to

596

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

estimating the probability of the outcome, then their ous, and therefore that each might believe that the
expectations may be inconsistent. other is likely to make a concession long before it is
We began by assuming that these two people were over. Thus, as long as fighting can be interspersed
bargaining over the division of a sum of money. with negotiations, private information about each
Before force was introduced into the story, this other's evaluation of the struggle itself can lead both
money would have to be a potential addition to the of them to be optimistic about the outcome of fight-
wealth of each bargainer, so that the cost of failing to ing, even though it is common knowledge that a
agree was simply that they would fail to gain any- struggle fought to a decision would be long and
thing. Once force is introduced, however, this is no costly for both sides. Therefore anyone who reasons
longer true, since either might be willing to surrender that simply because they were evenly matched phys-
money he already possessed to avoid further physical ically the prospect of a long and costly struggle would
punishment, and the cost of failing to agree is con- deter them from fighting must implicitly assume that
tinuation of this punishment (if bargaining takes once the fight began it could not be interrupted until
place after fighting begins) or the possibility that one one or the other had been defeated.
may be subjected to this punishment (if bargaining
takes place before fighting begins). The distribution
War and Negotiation
that exists prior to bargaining is one possible outcome
of bargaining but not the only one, even if an agree- Since wars are fought by collectivities, a war's costs
ment is reached without fighting. Thus whether and benefits will fall differently on different individ-
these people can avoid fighting and whether they can uals, who will therefore have different interests even
both protect the assets they had at the outset are two if they have identical expectations-and they are very
different questions. unlikely to have identical expectations. Thus wars
Suppose now that it is common knowledge that in give rise to intense internal conflicts whose pursuit
the event force is used, one would quickly subdue the can influence the course of the war. If we ignore this
other (perhaps because he is a muscular athlete while complication (as the literature on the balance of
the other is an uncoordinated wimp). Should they power does), then I shall claim there is a very close
then be able to reach an agreement without the need parallel between the story just told and interstate war.
to use force? If so, they must both prefer the expected Conventional interstate war is a contest in which
value of bargaining prior to the use of force to the each side tries to disarm the other in order to acquire
expected value of first fighting and then bargaining. the bargaining advantage to be derived from the
If they have sufficiently conflicting expectations of the unopposed use of force. In the limit, of course, force
outcome of bargaining after fighting this may not be can be used to destroy one's adversary completely.
true, since by resisting when he has no chance of Usually, however, the winner of a military contest
success one bargainer might be able to influence the requires the cooperation of its defeated enemy in
other's expectation of how stubborn he would be order to accomplish its aims.8 Thus "victory" and
once the struggle was over.7 Thus their ability to "defeat" refer to the outcome of the clash between
reach agreement without fighting depends on how armed forces, not to the political objectives that
consistent their expectations are of the outcome of motivated the conflict.9
bargaining after the fighting is over. Military contests may lead not to the defeat of one
Now suppose that they appear to be very evenly side or the other, however, but to stalemate. Fighting
matched physically but that one has a black belt in may last for a long time before it becomes common
karate. If this were commonly known, it would give knowledge that a stalemate exists. But even if stale-
that person a bargaining advantage. Precisely for this mate is commonly expected at the outset, the fact that
reason, however, if it is not commonly known then fighting is costly means that it may be possible to
the other has good reason not to believe any claims to derive a bargaining advantage from imposing those
this effect. Thus, because the factors that are com- costs on the enemy, even though doing so requires
monly known are evenly balanced, private informa- subjecting oneself to costs as well. Thus one cannot
tion may lead to inconsistent estimates of the proba- assume (as many do) that a simple probability distri-
bility that each will win. But their ability to reach bution over the two outcomes of victory and defeat is
agreement without fighting depends on their having an adequate way of representing states' incentives to
consistent expectations of the outcome of the bargain- use force or that a belief that stalemate is the most
ing that will take place once the fight is over, and this likely outcome is sufficient to deter its use.'0
will be impossible if they have inconsistent expecta- Wars, therefore, are contests in the use of force that
tions of the outcome of fighting. Thus, even if they are meant to induce one's opponent to agree to
have consistent expectations of the outcome of bar- something. If the adversaries have inconsistent ex-
gaining in the event that either won, inconsistent pectations of the outcome of bargaining after fight-
estimates of the probability that either will win may ing, they are unlikely to be able to reach an agree-
imply that there is no agreement prior to the use of ment without fighting. And if they have inconsistent
force that they both prefer to fighting. expectations of the outcome of fighting, they are
Even without introducing karate into the story, it is unlikely to have consistent expectations of the out-
possible that because the two are evenly matched come of the bargaining that will follow.
they expect that a struggle would be long and ardu- There are a variety of factors that are relevant to

597

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

estimating the outcome of fighting, including the Moreover, states may prefer fighting to negotiating
relative sizes of the opposing forces, the nature of the in these circumstances even if their expectations of
weapons systems available, the ability of the antago- the outcome of both fighting and negotiating are
nists to mobilize resources to replace those which are consistent. Blainey wrote: "When nations prepare to
lost in combat, the skill of the opposing forces, the fight one another, they have contradictory expecta-
strategies to be employed, and so on. The state of tions of the likely duration and outcome of the war.
some of these factors (e.g., the size of the opposing When those predictions, however, cease to be con-
forces and the economic base that supports them) is tradictory, the war is almost certain to end" (1988,
public knowledge. However, information about other 293-94). If compromise agreements are not enforce-
factors (e.g., the strategy to be employed) is not able, however, states may fight not because their
public, either because states try to keep them secret expectations are inconsistent but because they are
or because they have an incentive to mislead their both sufficiently uncertain of the outcome of war to
adversaries when they publicize them. The greater prefer it to defeat or the status quo. The war ends,
the role of factors that decision makers have private therefore, not when the adversaries' expectations
information about, the greater the likelihood that become consistent (since they may have been consis-
their estimates of the outcome of war will be incon- tent at the outset) but when the ultimate outcome
sistent. And the more nearly equal the publicly becomes nearly certain.
known factors are, the greater the role of factors We have identified, then, two plausible lines of
about which the antagonists have private informa- reasoning about the relation between the distribution
tion. Hence it is most likely that both sides will feel of power and the likelihood of war. One leads to the
optimistic when the balance of power is approxi- conclusion that (other things being equal) there is an
mately equal and that their expectations will be inverse linear relationship between inequality of
consistent when their power is unequal. This reason- power and the probability of war, since the more
ing therefore supports Blainey's claim that conven- unequal the balance of forces, the more consistent
tional war is least likely when power is distributed adversaries' expectations of the outcome of a military
unequally between the potential combatants." contest will be and therefore (other things being
However, in comparing the choice between war equal) the more likely it is that they will be able to
and negotiation with a situation in which two indi- agree on the terms of a settlement as an alternative to
viduals were struggling over the division of a sum of war. The other leads to the conclusion that the
money, I implicitly assumed that agreements were relation between the distribution of power and the
enforceable (even if offers made while struggling probability of war is nonlinear, since the probability
were not). I also assumed that there was no relation of war is greatest for distributions somewhere be-
between wealth and bargaining power. But agree- tween equality and great inequality; however, power
ments between states must be self-enforcing, and the has to be very unequal for the probability of war to be
correlation between wealth and power is an impor- lower than it is when it is distributed equally. The
tant feature of international conflict. This means not crucial difference between these two arguments con-
only that the wealthiest states are likely to be the cerns the enforceability of agreements: the first as-
strongest states but also that states can become stron- sumes that all possible compromise agreements are
ger by defeating other states and acquiring their enforceable, and the second assumes that compro-
resources. Thus, the outcome of one contest can mise agreements are not enforceable and that there-
influence the expected outcome of subsequent con- fore adversaries must choose between the status quo
tests, so that compromise agreements may not be and negotiating after one side or the other has been
enforceable. defeated on the battlefield.
To see why, suppose that two states are consider- Note that both arguments are ceteris paribus argu-
ing an agreement to redistribute resources as an ments, and thus in practice any effect of a change in
alternative to fighting. The range of agreements they the distribution of power on the probability of war
both would prefer to fighting depends on their ex- could be swamped by the influence of other factors.
pectations of the outcome of the fight. But if redis- Note also that both assume (implausibly) that any
tributing resources from one to the other worsens the two potential adversaries are equally likely to decide
expectations of the first and improves the expecta- to use force to upset the status quo when faced with
tions of the second, then after the redistribution the the same probability of military success. If instead
one who benefited from it may be able to enforce a one state prefers the status quo to any alternative
demand for more. If so, the first agreement is not regardless of the distribution of power, both lines of
enforceable and therefore not really available.'2 In argument imply that the probability of war is least
that case war can be avoided only if each side prefers when that state's relative power is maximized.
the existing distribution to the present value of the Both these arguments also assume that only two
distribution that it expects would be agreed to after states are in conflict with each other. However, wars
one or the other was defeated or if one side is are fought not just by individual states but by coali-
sufficiently pessimistic about the outcome of tions, fighting
so that the distribution of power between
that it prefers to accept defeat in advance.' This military antagonists depends not just on the power of
implies, as we have seen, that war is most likely if the individual states but also on which states decide to
balance is neither equal nor very unequal. fight. We must therefore consider how this affects the

598

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

relation between the distribution of power and the models have also made a very simple and unrealistic
likelihood of war. assumption about the relation between the distribu-
tion of power and the outcomes of wars: if ri > r1,
then it is common knowledge that the probability that
i will win a war with j is 1.0, and winning the war will
ALLIANCES, THE DISTRIBUTION give i control over all of j's resources; whereas if ri =
OF POWER, AND WAR rj, it is common knowledge that the probability of
stalemate is 1.0, and a stalemate implies that no
Let us continue to assume, following the previous resources are redistributed (Niou and Ordeshook
discussion, that states have resources such as wealth, 1990; Niou, Ordeshook, and Rose 1989; Wagner
territory, population, and technology that are assets 1986). With these assumptions, of course, states may
in fighting wars. Using their knowledge of the assets or may not be eliminated (which is the question of
of potential adversaries, statesmen estimate the like- system stability) but wars will occur only if negotia-
lihood of the outcomes of wars between them. Be- tion is impossible, since there is neither uncertainty
cause the outcomes of wars are also affected by nor private information.
factors that are not common knowledge, their prob- Nonetheless, these models are relevant to our
ability estimates may not be consistent. However, problem, since one of the possible consequences of
given any two potential military antagonists, the wars is the elimination of the defeated state or states
more unequal they are with respect to their publicly and the absorption of their resources by the victors
known assets, the more consistent everyone's expec- and since this fact will affect the incentive of states to
tations will be. But now let us also assume that there participate in wars. Suppose, for example, that two
are more than two states and that the assets of states states absorb all the resources of a third. This transfer
can be combined, so that wars can be fought between will not be permanent if, as a result of it, one of the
coalitions as well as individual states. victors is then able to force its former ally to surrender
We have seen that because assets such as wealth, its resources. Consider, then, a system of three states
territory, and population lead to military power, in which the resources are distributed 150, 100, 50.
gains derived from either the actual or threatened use Then the assumptions just stated imply that if the
of force may be cumulative, so that any particular pair largest state acquires any more resources it will be
of adversaries must consider the effect of some pro- able subsequently to defeat both the other two. Thus
posed redistribution of these assets on the expected neither of the other states will ally with it, and each
outcome of subsequent conflicts between them. will come to the aid of the other if it is attacked by it.
When there are more than two states, this fact also Moreover, neither of the smaller states will attack
implies that even allies must consider the effect of any the other, since doing so would allow the largest state
redistribution on the expected outcome of subse- to join the attack and gain resources. Therefore no
quent conflicts in which they may be adversaries, and transfers can take place in this situation, and the
states that do not participate in a conflict must con- system is stable.'4
sider the effect of its outcome on some subsequent Suppose, on the other hand, that resources are
conflict they might have with one or another of the distributed 100, 100, 100. Then a coalition of any two
participants. Controversies about the implications of states can defeat the third, but will it absorb all its
these facts are the central focus of the literature on the resources? Perhaps it will, if the resources of the
balance of power. defeated state are divided equally between them,
In examining their implications for the relation leading to the distribution (150, 150). In that case, the
between the distribution of power and the probability system is not stable. However, such an agreement
of war, it will be convenient to assume that all the would not be enforceable, and nothing prevents
commonly known assets of a state that are relevant to either ally from trying to cheat and acquire more. If i
predicting the military outcomes of wars it might does, then the other can only protect itself from this
engage in can be summarized in a single index defection by switching to the side of the victim before
represented by a real number, r (for "resources"). it is eliminated.'5 And even if this fails to occur, the
Using their knowledge of the distribution of these enemy is defeated, and the distribution (150, 150) is
resources, together with any private information they implemented, any exogenous change in either side's
may have, statesmen estimate the likelihood of the resource endowment (perhaps by economic growth)
outcomes of wars fought between various possible would leave the other unable to avoid defeat. Thus
combinations of states. (When states form alliances, neither of the victorious states would want to elimi-
the military resources available to the alliance are nate the defeated state entirely. Either or both these
simply the sum of the resources of the member possibilities would imply that the victim, while it
states.) Let us also assume that wars lead to one of might lose resources, would not be eliminated, which
three possible military outcomes: one or the other provides a justification for a "hidden hand" interpre-
side's armed forces win, or there is a military stale- tation of the idea of the balance of power: in a system
mate. of more than two states, the balance of power will
Some recent game-theoretic models designed to protect the independence of states even if all states
investigate the stability of international systems have seek to expand at the expense of others.'6
been based on such assumptions. However, these With this conclusion in mind, consider again the

599

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

distribution (100, 100, 100). In this situation each state quently pose. However, there is nothing to guarantee
is exposed to the possibility that the other two will that the other states would agree either with its
form a coalition and attack it. On the other hand, any probability estimates or with its attitude toward risk.
two of them can secure themselves from attack by Suppose that war led to a distribution such as (140,
attacking the third and absorbing its resources until 140, 20). Then, instead of being supported by the
one of them has 150 units, which freezes the system third state in an alliance against the first with a
and makes further transfers impossible. Thus there is comfortable margin of superiority, the second state
a strong incentive for expansion even for states that might find itself faced with a hostile alliance between
have no interest in acquiring more resources. the first and third states. In order to avoid this
This reasoning implies that three-member interna- outcome, it might therefore agree to allow the first
tional systems are stable. But this conclusion implies state to make greater gains at the expense of the
in turn that five-member systems may not be, for if enemy. This would increase the likelihood of postwar
two states in a five-member system are strong assistance from the third state in any military conflict
enough to defeat any combination of other states, with the former ally, but at the price of a smaller
then they can eliminate two other actors and stabilize chance of winning in case such a conflict occurs.
their winnings in a three-actor system. The tradi- Thus uncertainty implies that states face a dilemma
tional literature on the balance of power focuses on in trying to secure the fruits of military victory.
the need for states to ally against a potential hege- Maximizing security requires maximizing the power
mon, that is, a state that is on the verge of being able of whatever postwar coalition a state expects to
to defeat any combination of other states. In systems belong to, as well as maximizing the incentives of the
with more than three states, however, this reasoning other members of this expected coalition to partici-
implies that hegemonic coalitions are also a danger. pate in it. But with uncertainty these objectives are
These conclusions rest on the assumption that the inconsistent, since the incentive of states to partici-
outcome of wars can be anticipated with certainty pate in a coalition for the defense of the status quo is
and that they are common knowledge. It we assume, inversely related to its power relative to a potentially
more plausibly, that knowledge of the distribution of dominant state. One paradoxical implication of this
resources between potential adversaries leads to non- fact is that while in a two-state world the fact that
zero probability estimates for all the possible out- gains are cumulative implies that compromise agree-
comes of war and that these probability estimates ments are not enforceable, in a world of three or more
may not be consistent, then the incentive for coali- states the reverse is true: a state threatened by an-
tions to form in opposition to potentially hegemonic other state can increase the incentive of a third state
states or coalitions remains, but much else is al- to help defend it by conceding some of its resources
tered.'7 Uncertainty about outcomes implies that in to the threatening state and thereby weakening it-
every military conflict, each side faces some probabil- self.'8
ity of defeat, though this probability can be dimin- What does all this tell us about the relation between
ished by increasing the resources on one's own side. the distribution of power and the likelihood of war?
In a world of two states, of course, each side can In a two-state world one could minimize the likeli-
increase the quantity of resources available for mili- hood of war by maximizing the power of states that
tary use by reallocating them from other uses; but a are satisfied with the status quo. However, it is not
state's initial resource endowment (and its capacity clear how to identify such states or to guarantee that
for mobilization) implies that there is some upper they would always remain satisfied. Thus if compro-
limit to the quantity of resources it can devote to mise agreements are not enforceable, only equality of
conflict. Alliances enable states to circumvent this power will minimize the probability that either state
limitation if other countries are willing to cooperate. will choose to use force against the other. In a world
Uncertainty about what other states will do, how- of three or more states, however, one must distin-
ever, will lead to uncertainty about the strength of guish between the distribution of power among
each side, and thus add to the uncertainty that states and the distribution of power between some
already exists about the outcome of war. pair of coalitions that might fight each other. And if
Consider again the distribution (100, 100, 100), for settlements are not enforceable, then even dissatis-
example, and suppose the first two states combine to fied states must be concerned about how to protect
attack the third. With no uncertainty about the out- what they already have. As a result, it is at least
come of war, if their attack led to a distribution such possible that threats to upset the status quo would
as (150, 140, 10) then their gains would be secure, always be met by an overwhelmingly powerful coa-
since the largest state could not defeat the other two lition, a possibility that would paradoxically require
combined and neither of the other two would allow an equal distribution of power among states.
the other to be attacked without coming to its assis- To see why, bear in mind that (other things being
tance. With uncertainty, however, the second-biggest equal) the probability of one side's success in war
state may decide that such a distribution would lead varies directly with the ratio between its resources
to too great a risk of defeat by the most powerful and those of its opponent and that the more unequal
state. Therefore the second state may want to leave this ratio the less likely "other things" (i.e., assets
the third stronger than it otherwise would, in order to that states have private information about) will mat-
reduce the threat that its own ally would subse- ter. Thus states that wanted to deter an attack by all

600

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

possible antagonists would want to maximize the defend the status quo but not to alter it by supporting
resources available to prevent every other state from another in an attack. It is not clear what actions
upsetting the status quo.19 Consider again, then, the would serve to discriminate between these two sets
distribution (100, 100, 100), and assume that no state of preferences.22
wanted to diminish the power available to oppose Moreover, if one state does attack another, this
some other state's expansion. Then, even if every could be either because it does not share the prefer-
state would prefer to have more resources, this ences necessary to support a collective security policy
distribution would have the same effect as the (150, or because it doubts that the others do. Should the
100, 50) distribution in the world without uncertainty others therefore seek to reestablish their credibility by
earlier discussed; that is, no state would want to jointly defending the status quo, or should they infer
assist any other in expanding (since even if it ex- that the attacking state will not cooperate in a collec-
panded as well, the relative power of any coalition tive security system and therefore seek to make it less
subsequently available to oppose the other expan- of a threat by reducing its power? And if they choose
sionist state would be diminished), and any state that the latter alternative, how are they to protect them-
sought to expand on its own would be opposed by selves from each other after this is done?23
both the other two. Because distributions must be Thus, while an equal distribution of power mini-
self-enforcing, in other words, even expansionist mizes the role of private information in estimating the
states would follow a collective security policy. power of the community as a whole relative to the
If this sort of symmetrical policy of deterrence is to power of a single state that challenges the status quo,
succeed, however, any state contemplating expan- private information about the willingness of states to
sion would have to be confident that all the resources join in the defense of the status quo means that there
that might potentially oppose it would in fact be used may nonetheless be inconsistent expectations about
against it. Consider again the distribution (100, 100, whether a challenger would be successful. Consider,
100) and suppose the first state believes that it has a on the other hand, a distribution such as (140, 130,
strategy that will enable it quickly to defeat the 30) and suppose that the two smaller states agree that
second state at an acceptable cost (in spite of the any further increase in the power of the largest would
equality of their military resources). If it is to be be unacceptable and declare that they would cooper-
deterred from trying, it must believe that the third ate to prevent it. If so, then the distribution itself
state will oppose it. But will it?20 This depends not would lend credibility to this claim, and this credibil-
only on the third state's evaluation of the risks of not ity could be reinforced by the formation of an alli-
opposing it relative to the costs of doing so but also ance, the commitment of troops, and all the other
on what the third state believes about the second actions that states customarily use to signal their
state's preferences; for it would be self-defeating for intentions to each other. Thus this distribution less-
the third state to protect the second and then find ens the role of private information in influencing
itself facing a coalition between the second state and states' expectations about who will defend whom
the first state-that is, in order for all states to follow against what. And the near equality of the two
a policy of collective security, it is necessary not only opposing coalitions reduces the incentive of either to
that they all prefer to follow a policy of maximizing use force against the other.
deterrence but that it be common knowledge that Thus, if wars affect the distribution of power, then
they do. But precisely because military resources are (other things being equal) in a world of more than
distributed so equally, each state has reason to doubt two states the distribution of power that minimizes
that this is true of the others.21 the likelihood of war is one in which power is
Now that we have seen a connection between the distributed sufficiently unequally among states that at
idea of collective security and military deterrence, we least one state (or, if there are four or more states, a
can use the literature on deterrence theory to explore coalition of two states) is considered unacceptably
this problem further. The deterrence problem is to close to dominance by the other states in the system,
make one's threats credible when there is reason to a distribution that will then lead to the formation of
doubt one's willingness to carry them out. This a stable opposing coalition which will nonetheless
problem arises because the person or state making not be strong enough to have an incentive to use
the threat has private information about his willing- force to weaken the near-dominant state or states.
ness to carry out the threat and has an incentive to The likelihood of war is minimized, in other words,
misrepresent that information to the person or state when power is distributed sufficiently unequally
being threatened. When modeled as a game with among states that two stable but nearly equal oppos-
incomplete information, the standard conclusion is ing coalitions form.24
that to increase the credibility of its threat a state must This conclusion can be used to illuminate post-
take some action that it would be less likely to take if World War II controversies among students of inter-
it were prepared to carry out its threat than if it were national relations about the relation between the
not (Wagner 1992). Doing this is much more difficult distribution of power and the likelihood of war.
in the three-actor system I have described, however, Traditionally, when people have said that power was
than in the two-actor context in which the problem is "balanced,"' they have meant that it was approxi-
normally discussed. For example, each state must try mately equally distributed, so that any individual
to show that it is prepared to join with another to state that might contemplate expansion could be

601

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

opposed by another state of approximately equal tation has mistakenly been identified with one in
power. In a world of more than two states, this also which the two largest countries can defend them-
implied a multiplicity of possible coalitions of states- selves without allies against any combination of ad-
hence the connection between "balanced power" and versaries (one of the common definitions of bipolari-
the shifting alliances of a "balance-of-power system." ty).28 This has made it difficult to explain the fact that
The conventional wisdom was that this distribution "more than anything else, the Cold War between the
was the most stable one. This wisdom did not clearly United States and the Soviet Union has been a
distinguish, however, between stability in the sense competition for allies" (Walt 1987, 3). However, this
of the preservation of the independence of the mem- behavior can easily be understood in light of the
bers of the system and stability in the sense of peace. argument presented here. It is precisely because it
This confusion was encouraged by the tendency to seemed so plausible that U.S. security did not de-
ignore the fact that while individual states could be pend on allies that so many resources were expended
opposed by other individual states with equal power, by the American government during the Cold War to
overwhelmingly powerful coalitions of states could demonstrate that it considered the defense of its allies
form. This helped secure the stability of the system, to be a vital interest. This is consistent with the thesis
since it meant that individual states had a long way that what is commonly known about the distribution
to go before they were stronger than any possible of military capabilities is not enough to determine
countercoalition, and therefore hegemony could al- with certainty the vital interests of states, but a
ways be prevented. For precisely that reason, how- distribution of capabilities such as this one facilitates
ever, states could be uncertain about how far they the exchange of private information about what those
might expand before they encountered effective op- interests are. Thus the emphasis of the U.S. govern-
position, and the fear that if they did not expand they ment on deterrence during the Cold War was not
might be defeated by superior coalitions gave them a simply the result of the development of nuclear
strong incentive to do so. These facts help explain the weapons-a fact that illustrates the close connection
two world wars of the twentieth century.25 between my theme and deterrence.29
After World War II, three competing ideas about Consider, on the other hand, the problem of deter-
how to secure the peace were influential in Great ring Iraq from its recent conquest of Kuwait. Even if
Britain and the United States: to restore the old it had been common knowledge that the U.S. gov-
system of "balanced power," to create a permanent ernment was committed to preventing any state in
alliance among the victors that would control the the Middle East from becoming unacceptably power-
defeated countries, and to use international institu- ful, no one could have been certain that the United
tions to create a collective security system. There was States would use force to liberate Kuwait if it were
instead a conflict among the members of the victori- conquered by Iraq. And uncertainty about U.S. pref-
ous coalition over how to secure their gains, which erences gave the government of Saudi Arabia an
led to the Cold War, a development that can easily be incentive to avoid provoking the government of Iraq
understood in the context of the analysis offered. The and thus to avoid stating clearly that Saudi Arabia
leaders of the Soviet Union, fearing that their former would cooperate in opposing it. Moreover, because
allies would turn against them and join forces with the United States had wanted the cooperation of Iraq
the countries defeated in World War II, preferred a in opposition to Iran, it had helped Iraq acquire
settlement that left Germany sufficiently weaker- sufficient military power that Saddam Hussein could
and the USSR sufficiently stronger-that their allies believe that Saudi Arabia would not dare oppose it.
formed a counteralliance to deter the Soviets from But without the cooperation of Saudi Arabia, the
any further expansion.26 The result was a distribution liberation of Kuwait would have been impossible.
of power similar to the one described. Thus if, prior to the invasion of Kuwait, the United
Because this conflict led to the division of Europe States had succeeded in convincing the government
into East and West, it seemed to imply no possibility of Iraq that it had turned against it without convinc-
of a return to a system of shifting alliances among ing Saddam Hussein that the government of Saudi
more or less equal states. For those who believed that Arabia was prepared to oppose it as well, this would
such a system was the most stable one, this implied a only have given Saddam Hussein an added incentive
pessimistic conclusion about the future. This inter- to absorb Kuwait. This, on a small scale, is an
pretation was reinforced by the common view that it illustration of how shifting coalitions make deter-
was such a polarization that had helped cause World rence more difficult.30
War I. Instead of war, however, the polarization that
accompanied the Cold War led to what John Gaddis
has dubbed "the long peace" (Gaddis 1991). This fact SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
supports an alternative view, based on the analysis
offered here, that the polarization of the international
It is often said that war represents the failure of
system did not cause World War I but that its incom-diplomacy. As Blainey pointed out, one could just as
plete polarization helped make it possible and that it
easily say that diplomacy represents the failure of
was the prolonged confrontation between East and war: the problem is to understand why states some-
West that helped keep the peace after World War JJ.27
times choose one and sometimes the other (1988,
The distribution of power underlying this confron- 292). And to understand the relation between the

602

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

distribution of power and the likelihood of war, we agreements accepted in lieu of war may not be
must understand how the distribution of power af- enforceable.
fects this choice. This is a much more complicated If agreements are enforceable, it is most likely that
question than it is commonly made out to be, for two there will be an agreement that both antagonists
reasons. First, war and diplomacy are not just alter- prefer to war if their expectations concerning the
natives: the point of war is to influence the outcome likely outcome of war are consistent. This is the main
of negotiations, so war can be a way of conducting reason for believing that the likelihood of war be-
diplomacy. Thus to understand the relation between tween two antagonists varies inversely with the de-
war and diplomacy, one must understand the rela- gree of inequality in the distribution of power be-
tion between the use of force and bargaining. Second, tween them, because, for the reasons given, it seems
conclusions about the effect of the distribution of plausible that inequality of power makes consistent
power on the probability of war that may seem expectations of the outcome of war more likely.31
plausible in a world of two states do not necessarily However, much of the literature on international
apply to historical international systems in which politics assumes not only that war is influenced by
there have always been more than two states. the distribution of power but also that war affects the
The primary function of force in bargaining is to distribution of power-and therefore that the out-
improve one's bargaining position by increasing the come of one war will affect the expected outcome of
costs of disagreement for one's adversary. Force can subsequent wars. This implies that compromise
serve this function even if both sides can employ it agreements are not enforceable, so that if one state
against each other, as long as one expects to suffer prefers the expected outcome of fighting to the status
proportionally less than the other (Pillar 1983, 144- quo, war can be avoided only if the other prefers to
95). However, force is much more effective if it can be
surrender without fighting.?2 Therefore in a two-
country world if both sides are equally likely to use
used unilaterally, so that another function of force is
force when faced with the same probability of win-
to disarm one's enemy, thereby preventing him from
ning, the likelihood of war is least if power is distrib-
using force against one while one uses force against
uted equally (so that the likelihood that either will
him. All wars are to some extent contests in punish-
prefer war to the status quo is least) or if power is
ment, since all wars are to some degree costly and
distributed very unequally (so that, for the weaker
unpleasant. Interstate wars have primarily been con-
side, the probability of winning is outweighed by the
tests in disarmament, however, in which each side
expected costs of fighting).33
seeks to acquire the ability to punish the other uni-
When there are more than two states, expectations
laterally by first destroying its military forces.
of the outcome of wars depend on who will partici-
Counterforce contests, if fought to the finish, must pate in them as well as on the distribution of power,
end in the disarmament of one side or the other, or in and expectations about who will participate will be
stalemate. "Victory" and "defeat" in this context, influenced by private information about how states
then, refer to the outcome of a counterforce military define their interests. All states can be expected to
contest and not to the achievement of the political have an incentive to defend their independence,
objectives that may have motivated it, and "power" however, so that the more a state's independence is
means whatever assets states have that affect the threatened by another state or coalition of states, the
probability that they will win such a contest. The more consistent should be everyone's estimates of
fruits of victory in this sense may be disappointing, the probability that it will join an opposing coalition.
and so power in this sense may be worth much or This leads to the conclusion that in a world of three or
little. Wars, however, need not be fought to the more states the likelihood of war is minimized when
finish, so that another possible outcome of war is that power is distributed sufficiently unequally that at
it may lead to a negotiated settlement before either least one state (or, if there are more than three states,
side wins (or before it becomes certain who the a coalition of two states) is considered unacceptably
eventual winner will be). Thus states may choose to close to dominance by the other states in the system,
fight even if the expected outcome of fighting is a who therefore form a stable opposing coalition with
military stalemate, if each is optimistic about the nearly equal power.34 This conclusion clarifies the
effect of a stalemate on the willingness of the other to relation between controversies about whether equal
compromise. or unequal power distributions reduce the probability
States must choose, then, between negotiating of war and controversies about whether bipolar or
without fighting and fighting followed by negotia- multipolar international systems are more stable.
tions. Any agreements that states reach must be The relation between the distribution of power and
self-enforcing, however, in the sense that implement- the likelihood of war depends, then, on whether the
ing an agreement cannot be expected to enable one of terms of possible compromise agreements that might
the parties to overturn it and enforce a still more be accepted in lieu of war influence the balance of
favorable agreement. Thus if the terms of an agree- power between the antagonists and therefore influ-
ment affect the relative power of the parties to it (e.g.,
ence the probability that the agreement will be en-
if what is in dispute is the distribution of territoryforced-and if they do, it depends on how many
and the military power of each is positively related to states' interests will be affected by the outcome. Thus
the amount of territory it controls), then compromise there can be no general answer to the question of

603

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

what relation one should expect between the distri- 1. For a recent discussion with citations to the literature,
bution of power and the likelihood of war, and see Fearon 1992.
2. It is sometimes suggested that this conclusion requires
reasoning that may be appropriate for understanding
the assumption that all states are in fact interested in territo-
conflicts among the great powers during certain his- rial expansion. However, this assumption is clearly stronger
torical periods may not be relevant to conflicts that than necessary.
have only local or regional significance or to other 3. Both these arguments assume that it is impossible to
decrease one state's likelihood of success in attacking without
periods. Note that this conclusion would hold even if
increasing the other's. Obviously this need not be true. In
the only factor affecting the likelihood of war were medieval times building a castle diminished the likelihood
the distribution of power, and power (i.e., all the that one's enemies would be successful in attacking without
publicly known attributes of states that affect the increasing one's own chances of success in attacking one's
probability of their success in counterforce military enemies. Natural geographical barriers as well as great dis-
tances can have the same effect. This is one basis for the view
contests) could be unambiguously measured.
that whether technology favors the defense over the offense is
In fact, of course, many other factors besides the more important in influencing the likelihood of war than the
distribution of power affect the likelihood of war, and balance of power. One cannot count on the appropriate
their effect may be much greater. Moreover, the way technology, however, and given some prevailing technology,
in which decision makers translate the distribution of the relative size of military forces may still be important.
4. A similar idea can be found in Timasheff 1965.
such commonly known assets of states as population
5. The latter method is the basis for the Rubinstein model
and wealth into probability estimates of the outcomes of bargaining. For an accessible recent discussion of the
of various possible wars may be difficult to discern relevant theoretical issues, see Kreps 1990. For an attempt to
and quite variable.35 Thus it is not surprising that apply this model to the choice between fighting and bargain-
empirical tests of competing claims about the effect of ing, see Powell 1992.
6. One of the difficulties even with formal models of
the distribution of power on the probability of war
bargaining that assume incomplete information is that they
have been inconclusive. predict that bargainers will reach agreement much sooner
Finally, this discussion has two important implica- than they often do in fact (Powell 1992).
tions for the use of formal models in investigating 7. Consider Saddam Hussein's current reputation for
compromise.
theoretical issues in the study of international poli-
8. Because wars are contests between collectivities, there
tics: (1) the issues discussed here are more compli- is a difference between postwar negotiations in which the
cated than they are often made out to be and are defeated country retains a government and negotiates as a
therefore difficult to explore without the aid of formal single political entity and a situation in which the victor
models, but (2) in constructing such models one must occupies the defeated country and deals directly with the
population. For discussions of bargaining between victor and
be careful about the assumptions one makes. If the
vanquished, see Albert and Luck 1980; Kecskemeti 1958;
role of a formal model is to provide a counterexample Sharp 1990. For a discussion of negotiated settlements of wars
to some general assertion in the literature, the realism using cooperative bargaining theory, see Pillar 1983. For a
of its assumptions is not very important.36 But if a discussion of negotiated settlements of civil wars, see Wagner
1993a.
model is to tell us something we did not already
9. One must distinguish between victory/defeat on one
know about some historical situation, it is important battlefield or in one theater and strategic victory/defeat. The
that its conclusions not require that states in that Japanese defeated the U.S. forces at Pearl Harbor. Had the
situation either be able to do things they could not in United States not retaliated and acquiesced in Japanese ex-
fact do or unable to do things that they could in fact pansion in the Far East, this would have been because it chose
not to, not because it was unable to, and in that case, it would
do. Many models assume that prior to war, any
have been considered a negotiated settlement between the
agreements states might make are enforceable but United States and Japan influenced by a military engagement,
that once war begins no further negotiation is possi- not simply a military victory by Japan. One could say the
ble-and then proceed to analyze the implications of same about a decision by the United States and England not
to invade the European continent after the defeat of France by
these propositions in a world of two states.37 As the
Hitler's Germany or a decision by the United States and its
current civil war in Yugoslavia graphically illustrates, allies to acquiesce in the conquest of Kuwait by Iraq. This is
these assumptions are not as innocuous as they relevant to understanding what Mearsheimer calls a "limited
appear.38 And even scholars who are likely to notice aims strategy" (1983, 23-66; see also Clausewitz 1976, 69,
the significance of assuming that agreements be- 90-99).
10. This is important to bear in mind in thinking about the
tween states are enforceable (e.g., those who identify impact of nuclear weapons on the likelihood of war. The
themselves as "realists") tend to overlook the fact combination of nuclear weapons technology and ballistic
that the nonenforceability of agreements does not missiles changes the relation between the counterforce and
have the same significance in a world of more than punishment uses of organized military force and therefore the
significance of the balance of power in the sense of that term
two states that it has when there are only two.39
employed here: because of ballistic missiles, it is difficult to
disarm one's opponent completely, but adversaries are still
able to do massive amounts of damage to each other (Schell-
ing 1966, v-vii, 1-34). However, conventional wars have
always been costly when neither side was able to disarm the
Notes
other; and one cannot be certain that states with nuclear
weapons will be dissuaded from engaging in the sort of
An earlier version of this article was presented at the annual contest in punishment that military stalemates have always
meeting of the American Political Science Association, 1992. I made possible.
would like to thank James Fearon and Robert Powell for 11. Blainey actually seems to defend a stronger thesis-that
helpful conversations and correspondence on the subject. inconsistent expectations of the outcome of war are a neces-

604

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

sary condition for fighting. Fearon (1992) analyzes a model ally who would be frozen out by such a transfer could be no
illustrating the falseness of this claim, since even with consis- worse off if he made it. Thus it appears that in any plausible
tent probability estimates of the outcome of war bargainers noncooperative model of this situation in which counteroffers
may not be able to reach an agreement they both prefer to are not prohibited, all states desire more resources, and there
fighting if their evaluations of the costs of fighting are not is no uncertainty about the outcomes of wars, the preemptive
common knowledge. The same point is made more informally transfers assumed by Niou and Ordeshook would not be
in Wagner 1993a. Because Fearon assumes consistent proba- equilibrium outcomes.
bility estimates, in his model the probability of war is com- 17. I shall continue to assume that military victory gives the
pletely unrelated of the balance of power. winning side control over all the resources of the losing side
Although Mearsheimer (1991) asserts that war is least likely and therefore that uncertainty only characterizes expectations
when power is equal, his book, Conventional Deterrence, pro- of the outcome of combat. However, it is important to bear in
vides evidence that supports this version of the opposite view mind that military victory only gives the victor the ability to
(idem 1983). In this book Mearsheimer presents several case use force unopposed and does not deprive the vanquished of
studies supporting the thesis that war is most likely when all bargaining power. Thus victory does not necessarily mean
decision makers believe they have a strategy that will enable that the winner can exploit all the resources of the loser or
them to win quickly without much cost-a blitzkrieg strategy even that it will be strengthened by winning. Therefore there
(pp. 23-66). But he points out that "when a potential attacker may be uncertainty about the effects of military victory as well
enjoys an overwhelming force advantage, the importance of as about whether to expect it. For a fuller and more rigorous
discovering and successfully implementing the optimum mil- analysis, see Wagner 1994.
itary strategy is not as great as when the forces are essentially 18. Thus the unilateral transfers assumed by Niou and
balanced" (p. 65). This is consistent with the idea that when Ordeshook become more relevant when not all states desire
forces are equal, estimates of the likelihood of success are to expand and there is uncertainty about the distribution of
most likely to be influenced by factors whose status is private power.
information. 19. Stephen Walt (1987) assumes that balance-of-power
12. For an example of this sort of problem, consider the theory is inconsistent with the formation of defensive coali-
worries of many Israelis about the effect of territorial compro- tions that are much more powerful than their adversaries and
mises with the Palestinians on the ability of Israel to resist that such indexes as size, population, and gross national
subsequent Palestinian demands. This may be what people product are adequate measures of the power of states. Thus
have in mind when they say that because international he concludes that the sizes of the alliances that formed against
conflict is a struggle for power, it is a zero-sum game. This is Germany and Japan and against the USSR are inconsistent
not a zero-sum game, however, since both adversaries would with traditional balance-of-power theory. Neither assumption
be better off if they could agree without fighting; the problem is warranted, however. See, e.g., the sections entitled "The
is that no agreement is an equilibrium. Uncertainty of the Balance of Power" and "The Unreality of
13. For this to be true, any redistribution must reduce the the Balance of Power" in Morgenthau 1967, 196-205.
beneficiary's probability of losing or its expected costs of war 20. Walt (1987) distinguishes between balancing and band-
enough to compensate for the fact that the redistribution also wagoning. If this distinction is as general as he claims, it ought
reduces the beneficiary's net gains from winning. But it is to be applicable here, but in fact its implications are not clear.
unlikely to be common knowledge whether this is true or not, If the third state joins with the first, is that bandwagoning?
so that inconsistent beliefs about these effects may serve to We have seen that it is one way of trying to make itself more
inhibit compromise even if it is in principle possible. James secure. Similarly, a concession by the second state to the first
Fearon has pointed out to me that if delays are expected would increase the third state's incentive to defend it: Would
between rounds of negotiation then with sufficient discount- it then be balancing or bandwagoning? These questions
ing of future benefits states might agree to settlements that led illustrate the fact that the distinction between balancing and
to piecemeal surrenders to territory. This provides a possible bandwagoning is unclear unless one state is on the verge of
interpretation for what are called "salami tactics." I shall dominance. This helps explain the motivation for Walt's ad
assume that states will not behave in this way. hoc distinction between balancing against "power" and bal-
14. One might object that this admittedly highly simplified ancing against "threats."
depiction of the relation between the distribution of power 21. Niou and Ordeshook (1990) discuss collective security
before and after wars overlooks the fact that military resources as a nonstationary equilibrium in a noncooperative model of
are destroyed by war. However, as the examples of Japan and balance-of-power system. However, their model assumes the
Germany illustrate, a war may destroy a country's current possibility of preemptive unilateral resource transfers, no
military capabilities without destroying its military poten- uncertainty about the outcomes of wars, perfect information
tial-hence the significance of territorial expansion for the (so that it is always known which state deviated from the
postwar balance of power. equilibrium), and a preference for expansion on the part of all
15. Thus the victim has an incentive to make cheating states. Without these assumptions it is doubtful that the
easier by not resisting every member of the enemy coalition punishment strategies necessary to sustain a nonstationary
equally (Wagner 1986). For a historical example of this, see equilibrium of this sort could be supported.
Kecskemeti's account of the debate among German leaders 22. Consider, for example, how England might have
about what strategy to follow once they became certain of shown, prior to World War I, that it would ally with Russia to
Germany's ultimate defeat in World War 11 (1958, 127-54). See prevent the expansion of Germany in case of a general war on
also Koerner and Goemans 1990. the continent but would not support Russia if it tried to make
16. For a fuller discussion, see Wagner 1986. Niou and gains at the expense of Germany and Austria.
Ordeshook arrive at the same conclusion by assuming that the 23. Consider the question in the context of U.S.-Soviet
victim can protect itself from elimination by preemptively cooperation in the war against Hitler's Germany and the
transferring enough resources to one of the members of the U.S.-Soviet conflict over the future of Germany that followed.
attacking coalition to give it 150 units and thus prevent any 24. For a fuller discussion, see Wagner 1994.
further transfers (Niou and Ordeshook 1990; Niou, Orde- 25. Kenneth Waltz was perhaps the first to point out this
shook, and Rose 1989). This is an extremely implausible problem with international systems in which power was
assumption, however, not because voluntary transfers are distributed more or less equally. However, he mistakenly
impossible (they clearly are not) but because the assumption identified it with the problem of securing contributions to-
implicitly forbids any possible counteroffer to such a transfer. ward the supply of a collective good (Waltz 1979, 164-65). The
If counteroffers are possible, one must show why an ally real difficulty is instead the fact that until a state is close to
could not prevent its partner from accepting such a transfer by dominance, opposing its expansion may not be a collective
threatening to ally with the victim instead. Clearly the victim good. Therefore the problem diminishes not when multiactor
would prefer such an offer to making the transfer, and the international systems are replaced by two-actor systems

605

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Peace, War, and the Balance of Power September 1994

(which has never happened) but when states are powerful an exogenous change that would strengthen them can pro-
enough to attract organized opposition before they attempt to vide a motivation for the other states to wage a preventive
expand (Wagner 1993b; see also Koerner and Goemans 1990). war, since even a 50% chance of defeating the near-dominant
26. This interpretation of the Cold War implies that ideol- state or states before they become stronger may be preferable
ogy was important not because it influenced the objectives of to a much smaller chance of defeating them later.
Soviet leaders but because it affected their expectations of the 35. In particular, there is no reason to believe that if the
future behavior of their allies and because of the effect of the power estimates of the Correlates of War Project are con-
Stalinist system on the confidence of Soviet leaders in their verted into percentages they can be used to represent the
ability to control large amounts of territory. probability estimates of historical decision makers.
27. With respect to World War I, compare the coalition that 36. See, e.g., Fearon's (1992) use of a formal model to
won the war with the alliances that preceded it. Moreover, provide a counterexample to a claim in Blainey 1988.
while Britain's commitments (which reflected its interests) 37. See, e.g., the model analyzed in Bueno de Mesquita
turned a continental war into a world war, uncertainty about and Lalman 1992. There are other, stronger, assumptions also
what Britain would do helped make the war more likely (Levy embedded in the Bueno de Mesquita and Lalman model,
1990/91). Of course, during the Cold War not every state among which is the assumption that the state making a
joined in opposition first to the Sino-Soviet alliance and then demand has a first-strike advantage if it chooses to fight but
to the Soviet Union alone, and there was a great deal of debate surrenders that advantage to the victim if it chooses to
negotiate.
about how large an opposing coalition was necessary. This is
38. The argument presented here is relevant to one of the
not surprising, given the uncertainty involved in estimating
the distribution of power.
issues in the current debate about how outsiders might help
end the war in Yugoslavia-whether offering to enforce a
28. Many writers assume that since the United States and
settlement or increasing the power of the Bosnian forces
the USSR did not need allies there were only two "great
would make a settlement more likely. Suppose outside inter-
powers", and therefore that the international system during
vention is expected to prevent the Serbs from defeating the
the Cold War was equivalent to one with only two states. This
Bosnians and therefore lead to a military stalemate. If both
has led to further confusion by mingling together controversy
sides were confident that any settlement they reached would
about the significance of the number of actors with contro-
be enforced, then outside involvement leading to a stalemate
versy about the effect of the distribution of power among
might lengthen the war if each side were optimistic about the
them. For a fuller discussion of the various meanings of the
other's willingness to compromise on the terms of such a
word bipolarity and their relation to the analysis offered here,
settlement in order to avoid continuation of the conflict. On
see Wagner 1993b.
the other hand, if (as seems more likely) neither side is
29. In explaining the behavior of the American government
confident of outside enforcement and any territorial settle-
during the Cold War, it is important to bear in mind that
ment will influence the balance of power between the com-
having to defend Europe from even very small military
batants in subsequent conflicts, then expectation of a stale-
encroachments was considered almost as big a disaster as
mate might lead the Serbs to accept an armistice that
trying to defend it and failing. Thus the objective of policy
preserves the existing distribution of territory. However, any
was not simply to be able to defend one's interests with some
subsequent change in the distribution of power between the
acceptable probability of success, but to minimize the proba- two sides might lead to a reopening of the conflict. In the
bility of having to do so. This was a much more ambitious
meantime, the war continues because the Serbs are too
objective than states had pursued prior to World War II.
confident of winning and the Bosnians not sufficiently certain
30. I do not mean to suggest that the U.S. government
of losing to stop fighting. Thus, if the war cannot be ended by
made no mistakes in dealing with Iraq but only that criticisms
diminishing the expectations of the Serbs, it can only be
of its behavior after the fact have understated the difficulty of ended by diminishing the expectations of the Bosnians.
the problem, in part because they assume that the United
39. On this point, see also Snidal 1991.
States alone, by acting differently, could have deterred the
invasion of Kuwait. For a fuller discussion, see Stein 1992.
31. Bear in mind that "power" in this context means all the
resources of states that influence the probability of their
success in a counterforce military contest and that are matters
References
of common knowledge.
32. See, however, the qualifications in n. 13. Albert, Stuart, and Edward C. Luck, eds. 1980. On the Endings
33. However, since one side can become nearly certain of of Wars. Port Washington, NY: Kennikat.
its eventual defeat before a war is fought to the finish, wars Blainey, Geoffrey. 1988. The Causes of War. 3d ed. New V rk:
can still be ended by negotiation even though they could not Free Press.
be prevented by them. Moreover, when power is distributed Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and David Lalman. 1992. War and
equally, the role of private information in influencing expec- Reason: Domestic and International Imperatives. New Haven:
tations of the outcome of war is increased, so that if war Yale University Press.
occurs the two sides are likely in fact to have inconsistent Claude, Inis L. 1962. Power and International Relations. New
expectations of its outcome. Blainey (1988) confused uncer- York: Random House.
tainty with inconsistent expectations and thus falsely inferred Clausewitz, Carl von. 1976. On War. Ed. and trans. Michael
that because wars can lead to negotiations and because prior Howard and Peter Paret. Princeton: Princeton University
to war both sides tend to be optimistic about its income, wars Press.
are always caused by inconsistent expectations and thus that Fearon, James D. 1992. "War, Relative Power, and Private
inequality of power always reduces the likelihood of war. Information." Presented at the annual meeting of the
34. In evaluating the significance of this conclusion, one Midwest Political Science Association, Chicago.
must bear in mind the fact that it does not tell us how likely Gaddis, John L. 1991. "The Long Peace: Elements of Stability
war is when its likelihood is minimized. Moreover, I have in the Postwar International System." In The Cold War and
throughout assumed that the distribution of power could be After, ed. Sean M. Lynn-Jones. Cambridge: Massachusetts
changed only by wars and alliances. As a result first of the Institute of Technology Press.
democratization and then of the industrialization of war, Kecskemeti, Paul. 1958. Strategic Surrender: The Politics of
however, since the French Revolution the distribution of Victory and Defeat. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
power has been subject to very large exogenous changes. Koerner, Craig, and Hein E. Goemans. 1990. "Bipolar Stabil-
When no state or pair of states is close to dominance, such ity: The Carthaginian Perspective." University of Chicago.
changes magnify the difficulty states experience in developing Typescript.
consistent expectations of each other's behavior. When one or Kreps. David M. 1990. Game Theory and Economic Modelling.
two states are close to dominance, however, an expectation of Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

606

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 88, No. 3

Levy, Jack S. 1990/91. "Preferences, Constraints, and Choices Snidal, Duncan. 1991. "Relative Gains and the Pattern of
in July 1914." International Security 15:151-86. International Cooperation." American Political Science Review
Mearsheimer, John J. 1983. Conventional Deterrence. Ithaca: 85:701-26.
Cornell University Press. Stein, Janice G. 1992. "Deterrence and Compellence in the
Mearsheimer, John J. 1991. "Back to the Future: Instability in Gulf, 1990-91: A Failed or Impossible Task?" International
Europe after the Cold War." In The Cold War and After, ed. Security 17:147-79.
Sean M. Lynn-Jones. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute Timasheff, Nicholas S. 1965. War and Revolution. New York:
of Technology Press. Sheed & Ward.
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1967. Politics among Nations: The Struggle Wagner, R. Harrison. 1986. "The Theory of Games and the
for Power and Peace. New York: Knopf. Balance of Power." World Politics 38:546-76.
Niou, Emerson M.S., and Peter C. Ordeshook. 1990. "Stabil- Wagner, R. Harrison. 1992. "Rationality and Misperception in
ity in Anarchic International Systems." American Political Deterrence Theory." Journal of Theoretical Politics 4:115-41.
Science Review 84:1207-34. Wagner, R. Harrison. 1993a. "The Causes of Peace." In
Niou, Emerson M.S., Peter C. Ordeshook, Gregory F. Rose. Stopping the Killing, ed. Roy Licklider. New York: New York
1989. The Balance of Power. New York: Cambridge University University Press.
Press. Wagner, R. Harrison. 1993b. "What Was Bipolarity?" Interna-
Organski, A.K.F. 1958. World Politics. New York: Alfred A. tional Organization 47:77-106.
Knopf. Wagner, R. Harrison. 1994. "Peace and the Balance of Power
Pillar, Paul R. 1983. Negotiating Peace: War Termination as a in a Three-State World." Presented at the annual meeting of
Bargaining Process. Princeton: Princeton University Press. the American Political Science Association, New York.
Powell, Robert. 1992. "Bargaining in the Shadow of Force." Walt, Stephen M. 1987. The Origins of Alliances. Ithaca: Cornell
University of California, Berkeley. Typescript. University Press.
Schelling, Thomas C. 1966. Arms and Influence. New Haven: Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New
Yale University Press. York: Addison-Wesley.
Sharp, Gene. 1990. Civilian-based Defense: A Post-Military Weap- Wittman, Donald. 1979. "How a War Ends: A Rational Model
ons System. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Approach." Journal of Conflict Resolution 23:743-63.

R. Harrison Wagner is Professor of Government, University of Texas at Austin,


Austin, TX 78712-1087.

607

This content downloaded from 195.49.216.244 on Sun, 26 Feb 2017 19:14:01 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen