Sie sind auf Seite 1von 12

Part II

Materiality, Mind and History


Chapter 4

42
The Affordances of Things

Chapter 4

The Affordances of Things: a Post-Gibsonian Perspective


on the Relationality of Mind and Matter

Carl Knappett

The aim of this paper is to offer further perspectives that mind precedes matter, the former finding some
and reflections on the idea of engagement as devel- kind of secondary materialization in the latter
oped by Renfrew (2001; this volume). Engagement is (DeMarrais et al. 1996; DeMarrais this volume).
a potentially key concept for archaeologists, not to Pursuing this notion of materialization a little
mention students of material culture more broadly, further, it becomes apparent that a deep-seated sepa-
because it takes a relational stance on cognition. That ration of mind and matter is by no means unique to
is to say, the relationship between mind and matter archaeology. One dominant image of our current
is understood as one of mutual codependency; nei- social setting the information society actually
ther one nor the other is privileged, thereby avoid- implies a fundamental disengagement of mind from
ing both materialist and mentalist reductionism. matter. In her critique of what she dubs post-
Approaches stressing the importance of rela- humanism, Hayles argues that:
tionality in archaeological interpretation are not al- A defining characteristic of the present cultural
together new. One might cite the early work of moment is the belief that information can circulate
Shanks & Tilley (1987), some of the later work of unchanged among different material substrates
each of these authors (e.g. Tilley 1994; Shanks 1998), (Hayles 1999, 1).
as well as Thomas (1998; 2001) and Hodder (2001).
This is just a selection. Yet crucially, none of these When this logic is applied to humans, the suggestion
post-processual archaeologists develop their notions is that a persons essence can be uploaded, stored,
of relationality in connection specifically with mind and then downloaded in some other dimension basi-
or cognition. Their sights are aimed more at the inter- cally unaltered. Human physicality begins to be
dependency of subject and object, of body and thing; viewed as derivative, a mortal presence that is en-
their inspiration the philosophical tradition of phe- tirely secondary to our virtual existence as informa-
nomenology, particularly Heidegger and Merleau- tional patterns. And yet, as Hayles is at pains to
Ponty. point out, this posthumanist perspective (which is
Part of the reason why this important set of not so very different to liberal humanism) fails to
approaches has continued to focus on body rather accord any significance to the fact that information
than on mind may be due to academic divisions; must always be instantiated in order to exist. More
namely the emergence of mind and cognition as is- significantly still, the information thus instantiated
sues under the opposing banner of processual ar- is not unaffected by the medium in which it finds
chaeology (Renfrew 2001, 1234). However, the itself; information cannot be transferred freely be-
processual, or cognitive-processual, approach to tween physical substrates, easily attached and
mind has not, on the whole, seen mind in fully relat- disattached, free at any moment to float off some-
ional terms vis vis materiality. Within this approach where else. The information is itself transformed by
mind and matter are separate, with the former pri- its medium.
mary and the latter secondary. This kind of hierar- This emphasis on the embodiment of informa-
chical schema continues to be present in recent tion holds within it the kind of relational thinking
theoretical formulations that examine the relation- that is central to the idea of engagement. A human
ship between mind and matter. The notion of mate- agent, one might imagine, requires information in
rialization, for example, holds within it the sense order to decide how to act next. But where does this

43
Chapter 4

information reside, what form does it takes, and it is James Gibsons work (1979) on visual perception
how is it specified and processed? Some information that is fundamental. Gibson, in contemplating the
may simply be stored within the agents mind, and ways in which humans perceive objects in their en-
may be accessed regardless of bodily situation or vironment, was not happy with the orthodox view
environmental context. However, a great deal of in- that humans are only able to understand the func-
formation is not immediately accessible and on-line tion or meaning of an object indirectly, through in-
in this way; rather, it is situated and embodied, emer- ternal representations. That is to say, once the
gent in particular contexts of action. Information is, physical structure of an object (e.g. four legs, flat
in this sense, out there in the material world, and is surface, etc.) is perceived, the object is subsequently
immediately accessible to a given agent in a certain fitted into a pre-existing category within the human
situation. mind (chair). Only then, once the category chair
has been accessed, is the human agent able to re-
The contribution of psychology trieve the potential function of the object (for sitting
on). Thus the human perception of function was,
Although one might have imagined that archaeolo- according to scientific orthodoxy, believed to be in-
gists would have embraced this kind of position direct, and mediated by cultural representations (a
long ago, a relational approach to the interface of two-stage process of perception and conceptu-
mind and matter, such that information is deemed alization). In seeking an alternative to this received
to be distributed between them, has not been forth- wisdom, the psychologist James Gibson developed
coming in archaeological theory. There have been the notion of direct perception. For Gibson, the
strongly relational approaches, as discussed above, potential of an object for sitting on, to continue the
and explicit cognitive approaches, but they have rarely chair example, could be directly observed without
overlapped. This is why the notion of engagement first categorizing the object as a chair. This sug-
marks an important new development, and a chance gested that information might reside in the environ-
to confound the aging division between processual ment itself rather than merely as internal mental
and post-processual archaeologies. representations. His idea was that an agent might
In seeking to develop the idea of engagement acquire information directly from the environment
further, however, we need to turn immediately to as a means of assessing what a situation might afford.
other disciplines, and in particular to various The potentialities held by an object for a particular
branches within psychology (see Cowgill this vol- set of actions were termed by Gibson its affordances.
ume). There are indeed a few different strands within The concepts of direct perception and affordance are
psychology exploring the relationality of mind and closely intertwined in Gibsons ecological psychology.
matter (in ways compatible with Renfrews theory There is certainly much to be said for Gibsons
of material engagement). The three strands in ques- approach. It is fundamentally dynamic in nature,
tion are ecological psychology, cultural psychology, working on the plausible assumption that human
and situated cognition. perception is geared towards tracking possibilities
for action in the world. In addition to this ecologi-
ecological psychology cal slant, it does serve as an important counterpoise
to the dominant Cartesian-derived view that human
action inevitably involves reflection and conscious
evaluation. What Gibson succeeds in demonstrating
is the reactive/executive nature of human percep-
tion and cognition in certain material circumstances.
There surely are a number of artefacts in given situa-
tions that serve to prompt sequences of actions al-
cultural situated most unthinkingly. And yet to say this is the be-all
psychology cognition and the end-all of human perception is rather ex-
treme, and Gibson has been much criticized for this.
One example used by Gibson himself that illustrates
Ecological psychology the limitations of his perspective is the post-box.
Gibson argued that the physical characteristics of
As this diagram indicates, it is ecological psychol- the post-box announce its function in a direct and
ogy that lies at the root of this process. In particular, unmediated way. But what of other similar-sized

44
The Affordances of Things

receptacles with letter-sized slots, such as litterbins? 1996; 1997; Kirsh 1995; Norman 1998; Hutchins 1995;
Do not these also afford the posting of letters, in Suchman 1987). A fundamental idea throughout,
purely physical terms? The reason why a human however, is that the connections between mind and
agent posts mail in a post-box and not in a litterbin is matter must be viewed in relational terms. For more
that the agent possesses cultural information rel- on situated cognition, see the contribution of Mala-
evant to the situation and object in question (Noble fouris in this volume.
1991, 2078; Palmer 1999, 409). This knowledge of
the post-boxs function is not accessible from its Cultural psychology
physical form alone, but derives from numerous as-
sociations and internal categorizations. That is to A similarly relational perspective is also apparent
say, its function is, in part, and contra Gibson, indi- within cultural psychology, notably in the work of
rectly perceived. such scholars as Michael Cole (1996), James Wertsch
This does not mean that Gibsons theory is (1998a,b), Dorothy Holland (Holland et al. 1998) and
invalid, but that it is too radical and one-sided (and, Michael Tomasello (1999). An element common to
one might argue, at the time it needed to be, to have all of these is the profound influence exerted by the
any chance of being heard in the face of the domi- Soviet psychologist Lev Vygotsky (1978). One key
nant representationalist approach). What is required, point, as far as materiality is concerned, is that hu-
then, is a modification of Gibsons perspective, and mans use cultural artefacts when engaging in action,
such a move is well underway in psychology the and that these artefacts serve as mediational means.
potential of Gibsons theory continued to be explored Artefacts not only mediate between a human and
through the 1980s and early 1990s, with scholars his/her environment, but between humans. An arte-
such as Reed (1988a,b; 1991), Michaels & Carello fact may act as a common source of what Tomasello
(1981), Noble (1991; 1993), Heft (1989) and Costall calls joint attention (1999, 62), a kind of pivot
(1981; 1995). It was only during the late 1990s, how- around which activities may form. In a similar vein,
ever, that Gibsons admittedly rather radical pro- Wertsch describes such processes in terms of medi-
posal came to be more seriously considered within ated action. It is also interesting to note that Wertsch
the mainstream psychology of visual perception (e.g. expressly links his perspective to the situated cogni-
Bruce et al. 1996; Gordon 1997; Palmer 1999). Some tion approach described above (particularly D. Nor-
scholars in related fields have also identified the man). Moreover, both Wertsch and Norman owe a
need for a compromise solution uniting indirect and considerable debt to ecological psychology (see dia-
direct perception notably within situated cogni- gram above), not least in their use of the Gibsonian
tion, to which we now briefly turn. idea of affordances. It is not only Wertsch among the
cultural psychologists who adopts the affordances
Situated cognition concept the same also holds true for Tomasello
(1999) and Holland et al. (1998). Cole hardly men-
Situated cognition refers to a movement within cog- tions the affordances in his 1996 book, but he did
nitive psychology that seeks to counter the Cartesian collaborate with Holland in writing a paper in which
representationalist view of cognition (that lies at the much more attention is devoted to the concept (Hol-
heart of AI), arguing instead that cognition is an land & Cole 1995).
embodied, situated and distributed process (Clark All three of the strands outlined above eco-
1998). Although cognition, perception and action are logical psychology, situated cognition and cultural
frequently separated, even hierarchically, this school psychology have in common the idea that cogni-
tends to treat the relations between them much more tion and materiality are far more intimately con-
fluidly. Hence situated cognition also implies situ- nected than is often acknowledged. The compatibility
ated perception and situated action. Gibsonian eco- between these three strands is further underlined in
logical psychology has certainly fed into this branch that the idea of affordances is used in each of them.
of cognitive science (see diagram above), as explic- Now we shall give fuller consideration to this potent
itly recognized by Kirsh (1995). Some of the more concept.
radical proponents of this perspective come close to
Gibsons views on direct perception (e.g. Brooks 1991; Affordances
van Gelder & Port 1995), while others have devel-
oped a more balanced approach incorporating ele- The concept of affordances forms a central plank of
ments of both direct and indirect perception (Clark this paper because it can help us understand the

45
Chapter 4

codependency of mind and matter. Taken directly cal properties do set some limits. There is a difficult
from Gibson, the idea has some limitations; fortu- tension between the independent and relational prop-
nately, though, the concept has been attracting in- erties of objects (Heft 1989).
creased attention in a range of disciplines, and as a
result has been subjected to some important modifi- Transparency
cations and revisions. What such work allows us to
do is home in on three key aspects of affordances: Coming back to the principle of situated action es-
their relationality, transparency and sociality. An poused by Kirsh, a second key aspect, besides
important step to be taken subsequently is an assess- relationality, is the transparency of affordances. For
ment of the relationship between affordances and Gibsons theory of direct perception to hold true, the
meanings. Much of the discussion will be aimed at affordance of an artefact should be transparent in its
material culture generally, albeit with an eye on ap- physical form alone. This is perhaps valid for certain
plicability to archaeological contexts. objects in certain situations the affordances of
water bubbling from a spring in the desert to a thirsty
Relationality human are transparent. The affordance of a chair for
sitting may also be transparent (to certain agents in
The affordance of an object is neither solely an inde- given situations). But what an object affords may be
pendent property of the object itself, nor is it exclu- more or less transparent in different situations in-
sively an intentional state within the mind of the volving different agents. An object designed for use
person engaging with it, but a relational property in a specific situation, assuming a certain amount of
shared between object and agent. The situation in knowledge on behalf of the prospective user, may
which object and agent engage is a dynamic one announce quite clearly what it affords. But with a
and the information specifying where the situation change in circumstances, its function may be far from
can lead is not entirely within the agents head, but transparent. Alternatively, some artefacts may be
is in some way also held within the object (itself designed such that their affordances are almost al-
within an environment). This idea that it is a situa- ways transparent, regardless of circumstance (hand-
tion that has affordances, as far as an agent possess- axe, paper cup?). To use the post-box example cited
ing a given action repertoire is concerned, has been above, its use is only transparent to those with the
usefully developed in cognitive science by Kirsh requisite cultural knowledge the post-boxs
(1995). Rather than being constant, an artefacts affordances are not knowable from its shape and
affordances may change according to the situation size alone.
in which they are found. The notion of relationality
is absolutely key to understanding the affordances Sociality
concept, and has been highlighted by others (e.g.
Ingold, Noble, Heft, Palmer). Let us for a moment A third important element of affordances is that in a
return to the chair example used earlier. It may ap- given situation they will invariably entail a social
pear as if the chairs affordance for sitting inheres component. This is an aspect that Gibson barely
within it, independently of the actions of human elaborated, and his formulation of affordances can
agents. Yet the chair does not afford sitting to all certainly be criticized for being asocial. This is not to
humans the very young or the very old, for exam- say that a social dimension is intrinsically incompat-
ple, may be excluded, as they may not be capable of ible with his theory, and some scholars have at-
sitting on objects of certain heights (perhaps too low tempted to socialize affordances (Reed 1988a; Costall
for the very old, too high for the very young). Thus 1995; 1997; Williams & Costall 2000). Yet the social
the chair only affords sitting to those capable of cer- dimension of affordances has barely registered as an
tain actions. Moreover, while a human agent may area of interest in those disciplines more inclined to
have the capacity for sitting, the nature of the situa- engage with issues of sociality, such as sociology or
tion may not allow it; indeed, other affordances of anthropology. One notable exception to this is the
the chair may emerge in some circumstances, such work of anthropologist Tim Ingold (2000). In trying
as its capacity for propping open a door. While ac- to weave together the habitually-separated traditions
knowledging the importance of the mutual relation- of biology, anthropology and psychology, Ingold sees
ship between object, agent and context in establishing Gibsons vein of ecological thinking within psy-
an affordance, one must also admit that the chairs chology as absolutely key (2000, 34). But while
affordances are not boundless its intrinsic physi- Ingold draws directly on Gibson, there is another

46
The Affordances of Things

strand of anthropology in which ecological psychol- by de Fornel concerns a group of punks who have
ogy has recently had an effect, albeit via a rather been taken in for questioning. The members of the
circuitous route. This strand forms part of the French group are asked to empty their pockets and bags
socio-anthropology tradition that concerns itself with onto a table in the middle of the room. Amongst
material culture, and has done so for many years their possessions are a considerable number of knives.
since the pioneering work of Marcel Mauss (1950/ Once on the table, the groups possessions are
1936) and subsequently Leroi-Gourhan. One could recategorized and out of their reach. An inspector
hardly call this tradition a stranger to psychology, enters the room and the police officers present the
but in recent years it has been receiving its psycho- situation to him. While some of the officers intro-
logical input from an unexpected source. The revival duce the punks, one officer is stood at the table and
of the connections between anthropology and psy- picks up one of the confiscated knives, showing quite
chology is represented in the work of scholars such clearly its blade in such a way that it is brought,
as Warnier (1999a,b), Kaufmann (1997), Julien (1999), almost implicitly, to the inspectors attention. It is
Semprini (1995), Lfgren (1996), Conein & Jacopin through such a sequence of interactions that the po-
(1993), and de Fornel (1993). What is noteworthy lice officers and the inspector come to share the same
here is the evident influence of the situated cogni- understandings of both the object and the whole
tion perspective (described earlier), especially the situation. Consequently the police officers go through
work of Norman. It is perhaps no accident that within an extensive shared manipulation of the knives; han-
situated cognition there is a definite anthropological dling them, understanding their particular afford-
orientation, not least in the work of Suchman and ances. They discover that one of the knives is burnt
Hutchins (and that of Norman, for example, is at the blade, prompting them to accuse its owner of
broadly sociological). Yet of the French scholars men- using it for hashish. Another blade is broken the
tioned above, it is only de Fornel who goes back owner claims to have done it opening a tin the
directly to the work of Gibson. Moreover, none seems officers suggest he broke it trying to force open a car
to reference Ingold, despite the obvious and poten- door. The police officers arrive at a shared under-
tially fruitful parallels between their work and his. standing of the affordances of the artefacts through
So what is meant, exactly, by the sociality of joint practical activity. The punks watch this per-
affordances? Quite simply, that any given situation formance but are excluded from participation. The
will very often involve more than one human agent; knives are far from being passive objects, but play a
two or more agents may be engaged in a joint activ- very active role in establishing the situation and the
ity and so may each see the shared affordances that roles of the different protagonists therein.
an object offers each of them. Alternatively, two or
more agents may find themselves in the same con- Direct and indirect: execution and evaluation
text but in different situations, seeking different out-
comes. In this case a single object may be perceived Apart from demonstrating the means by which
to have different affordances according to the per- affordances come to be shared in social interactions,
spective of each agent. The objects affordances may de Fornel succeeds in showing the mediated and
thus be negotiated and contested. An excellent ex- indirect aspects of perception, albeit within a
ample is provided by de Fornel (1993), showing how Gibsonian framework. Although in some circum-
affordances come to be shared in a social situation. stances human agents merely execute tasks by react-
De Fornels case study involves an analysis of ing to objects, de Fornel underlines that often the
the interaction sequences in routine police investiga- affordances of artefacts are actively evaluated within
tions. Objects are frequently submitted for examina- social situations. This dual status of the human agent,
tion and offered as evidence. An important part of as both active and reactive, is commented upon by
the process is to place the object in question (e.g. a Conein & Jacopin (1993). They argue that in Gibsons
knife) before the accused for identification or recog- theory of direct perception humans are effectively
nition. Before doing so, however, the investigating reduced to the role of reactive agents, merely react-
police officers evaluate the objects that have been ing to those affordances that enable the execution of
seized from the persons accused, categorize them, an action. What the theory of direct perception lacks
and decide what they imply for their (ex-) owners. is the ability to cast human agents as active, with the
This occurs within an interaction context of multiple capacity to evaluate as well as react. In this regard,
agents, such that the affordances of the objects are Conein & Jacopin are keen on the concept of situated
explored and shared. One particular case discussed action (they cite Donald Norman as their prime ex-

47
Chapter 4

ample) it allows for both an active agent at the possible actions). One might also cite the work of
level of evaluation and a reactive one at the level of Edwin Hutchins (1995) on navigation systems, and
execution. that of Latour on door-stoppers, speed-bumps and
This differentiation noted by Conein & Jacopin keys (e.g. Latour 2000). In all of the above examples
between active evaluation and reactive execution is a logical distinction can be drawn between physical
akin to that made by Kirsh & Maglio (1994) between and cognitive affordances, although the two may
epistemic action and pragmatic action respectively. very well co-occur in practice (Kirsh 1995). With the
Take the example of a jigsaw puzzle. A pragmatic former, the environment is physically shaped in such
action is one of execution, such as fitting a piece into a way that action is directly affected; in the case of
its correct position. An epistemic action is an act of the latter, information is available in the environ-
evaluation preceding or following execution: this ment but free of actual physical constraints. A speed-
might be the grouping together of all pieces with a bump physically forces a driver to slow down in a
straight edge and a patch of blue sky. In traditional way that a signpost does not. Leaving the car-keys
cognitive science, it would be argued that the proc- on a table next to the front door of the house is a
ess of execution is external and physical, while the means of planting information in the environment
process of evaluation is internal and mental. What (do not forget car-keys), but it does not provide any
Kirsh & Maglio argue, as do Clark, Hutchins, and direct physical constraints (its still possible to walk
others behind the situated/distributed cognition per- out of the front door and forget them).
spective, is that both processes (execution and evalu-
ation) involve the external manipulation of physical Affordances and meanings
objects. Cognition is both an internal and an external
process. Perception in the course of situated action is The affordances of objects cannot always be ascer-
both direct and indirect, unmediated and mediated. tained directly through information available in the
And we essentially find ourselves at a point that can immediate environment. Often an object will have
be described as post-Gibsonian, in which the associations that may not be physically apparent but
affordances of objects are understood simultaneously which the agent recalls a similarity with other
directly and indirectly, through both execution and objects previously encountered, or a recollection that
evaluation, and in terms of embodiment as well as this object had on earlier occasion been juxtaposed
representations. with other kinds of artefacts in a different setting.
I mentioned the jigsaw puzzle as one example Such knowledge is not available in the environment,
of the complexity of the perceptual/cognitive proc- but comes to the agent upon reflection, and may
ess. And yet understanding the affordance of a jig- very well affect the perceived affordances of the ob-
saw piece is relatively straightforward, in that it is ject at hand. In other words, the object has a mean-
only likely to be encountered in a very limited set of ingfulness that can only be indirectly perceived,
contexts, and the actions pursuant in such contexts mediated through the agents existing social repre-
demarcate the jigsaw pieces affordance relatively sentations about the world.
clearly. The same can also be said of other examples A simple example may underline this point.
studied by Kirsh and his collaborators, notably the Let us take an everyday artefact, a coffee cup. It has
games of Scrabble and Tetris (Maglio et al. 1999; certain physical characteristics which afford drink-
Kirsh & Maglio 1994). In more real situations, the ing (to agents with the appropriate action reper-
possibilities for action are usually much more fluid, toires). For example, it is readily manipulable in the
and the interactions between human agents less rule- hand, given its size, shape, weight and texture. It has
bound. As a corollary, the affordances of objects are a suitably wide and regular lip. Although it is easily
more prone to ambivalent interpretation. Not only held, when the vessel is full of hot coffee its walls
Kirsh (1995) but also Conein & Jacopin (1993) tackle conduct heat and become too hot to touch for any
the question of the use of kitchen space and the ways length of time. For this reason the coffee cup is fur-
in which the affordances of a situation are impli- nished with a handle. The vertical form of the han-
cated by the arrangement of artefacts in space. Spa- dle and its placement close to the rim are features
tial layout can help generate a plan of action it can that afford tipping; moreover, the handle is often
prompt evaluation as well as execution. Donald Nor- shaped in such a way that more than one finger can
man (1998) has focused on doors and how their fit through its hole, thereby increasing graspability.
materiality succeeds or fails in announcing whether Other artefacts may also exist which seem, physi-
they should be pushed or pulled (amongst other cally at least, to afford very similar actions. A tea-

48
The Affordances of Things

cup, a beer mug and a polystyrene cup can all fulfil mind and the doing mind (see Schlanger 1994 for
the same functions as a coffee cup, even though in critique). It is as if humans interact with objects us-
actuality they are rarely used in the same way. This ing two enormously different logics simultaneously,
is in part because the cultural associations of these the one linguistic, codified and symbolic, the other
different objects are not the same. And these associa- embodied, uncodified and pragmatic. Yet such a deep
tions cannot be directly apprehended from the situa- cognitive division seems highly improbable, given
tion at hand. They may be a matter of physical the often-seamless interactions between the human
similarity with other artefact types which render them mind and the material world. To return to the theme
more or less suitable for certain kinds of activity of information, it would certainly appear that there
(perhaps different materials and shapes used by are different sources of knowledge informing agents
groups of differing social status). Or it may be that as to how they might proceed in any given situation.
the coffee cup tends to find itself contiguous with Some information is indeed present in the material
certain kinds of object in particular spatial configu- environment in such a form that humans can re-
rations, and that such associations affect its mean- spond to it directly and unreflectively; but at the
ingfulness (even in those instances when the coffee same time information is also internally derived from
cup does not find itself in such circumstances). There cultural representations or schemata within the hu-
may also be symbolic commentaries and narratives man mind (Strauss & Quinn 1997). Yet even though
connected to a certain artefact that affect the way in the sources of information may vary, is it necessarily
which it is perceived (perception mediated through the case that external and internal information
representations). obey different logics, practical and linguistic re-
spectively? How exactly do internal and external
Artworks and artefacts knowledge, and direct and indirect processes (e.g.
execution and evaluation), articulate with one an-
But can this same perspective be applied to all kinds other? Is this where the phenomenon of tuning (see
of objects? Does the same hold true for artworks, or Norman 1998), or what Gell calls structural iso-
are these subject to different dynamics? Artefacts morphy (1998) comes into the picture? Gell uses this
and artworks have certainly often been cast as two term to describe the links between the cognitive
very distinct ontological categories. It is assumed processes we know (from inside) as consciousness
that these two categories are perceived in quite dif- and the spatio-temporal structures of distributed ob-
ferent ways. On the one hand, the everyday artefact jects in the artefactual realm (1998, 222). If this kind
is engaged with sensorily, as the human protagonist of rapprochement between internal and external
embodies it in the course of action. A functional, domains proves ultimately to be sustainable, then it
practical understanding of the object is developed, promises to remove not only the deep division be-
obviating any need for conscious thought on the tween linguistic and practical knowledge, but also
part of the agent. The artwork, on the other hand, the profoundly unhelpful polarization of artworks
signifies rather than acts. The agent engages with and artefacts.
this kind of object visually rather than sensorily. Answers to this and other similar questions need
Moreover, a different kind of knowledge is in play, to be found if we are to make any progress in under-
one that requires a grasp of the relevant symbolic standing the engagement of mind with the material
codes allowing for the interpretation of the mean- world. And fortunately steps have recently been
ings encoded in the artwork. The reading of the taken in this direction, showing the feasibility of
artwork demands a linguistic form of knowledge combining phenomenology and semiotics, and eco-
that has little relationship to the embodied, practical logical psychology and representationalism, in the
knowledge associated with the everyday artefact. various domains of art history (Sonesson 1989; Bryson
Whereas the agents conscious evaluation of the art- 1990) sociology (Gottdiener 1995), anthropology
work is mediated through an internalized set of cul- (Csordas 1994; Parmentier 1997), cognitive anthro-
tural representations, the agents engagement with pology (Strauss & Quinn 1997) and cognitive science
the artefact emerges in practice through a kind of (Clark 1997; Petitot et al. 2000). This baton has also
direct, unmediated process. been taken up within archaeology, albeit only to a
This kind of polarization of artworks and arte- limited degree as yet (e.g. Preucel & Bauer 2001).
facts is exacerbated by the simplistic distinction fre- To conclude, one might well ask why the con-
quently drawn between linguistic knowledge and cept of affordances has by and large failed to attract
practical knowledge (Hodder 1993), or the thinking much attention within archaeology. Traditional aca-

49
Chapter 4

demic boundaries are partly to blame. The idea was Conein, B. & E. Jacopin, 1993. Les objets dans lespace; la
first put forward in psychology, a discipline with planification dans laction, in Conein et al. (eds.),
which archaeology and anthropology have hardly 5984.
enjoyed strong contacts. Moreover, for many years it Conein, B., N. Dodier & L. Thvenot (eds.), 1993. Les objets
dans laction: de la maison au laboratoire. (Raisons
occupied a rather radical position within that disci-
Pratiques 4.) Paris: Ed. des EHESS.
pline. To compound matters further, its principal Costall, A., 1981. On how so much information controls so
protagonist, J.J. Gibson, died quite soon after the much behaviour: James Gibsons theory of direct
publication of his most substantial work (1979). Nev- perception, in Infancy and Epistemology, ed. G.
ertheless, with the important modification that it has Butterworth. Brighton: Harvester Press, 3051.
since undergone, and with the increasing permeabil- Costall, A., 1995. Socialising affordances. Theory and Psy-
ity of the boundaries between certain academic tra- chology 5, 46782.
ditions, the affordances concept has an important Costall, A., 1997. The meaning of things. Social Analysis 41,
role to play in encouraging us to adopt the kind of 7685.
Csordas, T.J. (ed.), 1994. Embodiment and Experience: the
relational stance that is central to the idea of engage-
Existential Ground of Culture and Self. Cambridge:
ment. If as archaeologists we can accept that humans Cambridge University Press.
think through material culture, and that mind and de Fornel, M., 1993. Faire parler les objets. Perception,
matter achieve a significant degree of codependency, manipulation et qualification des objets dans
then perhaps we give ourselves the chance of escap- lenqute policire, in Conein et al. (eds.), 24165.
ing the paradox of being frustrated mentalists con- DeMarrais, E., L.J. Castillo & T. Earle, 1996. Ideology,
demned to materialism. materialization and power ideologies. Current An-
thropology 37, 1531.
Acknowledgements Gell, A., 1998. Art and Agency: Towards a New Anthropologi-
cal Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Gibson, J.J., 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Percep-
I am most grateful to the organizers, Colin Renfrew, Chris
tion. Boston (MA): Houghton Mifflin.
Gosden and Elizabeth De Marrais, for inviting me to con-
Gordon, I.E., 1997. Theories of Visual Perception. 2nd edi-
tribute to the symposium. My thanks also go to Lambros
tion. Chichester: J. Wiley & Sons.
Malafouris for frequent stimulating discussion of
Gottdiener, M., 1995. Postmodern Semiotics: Material Cul-
materiality and cognition. The research for this paper was
ture and the Forms of Postmodern Life. Oxford:
completed while holding a Junior Research Fellowship at
Blackwell.
Christs College, Cambridge. Christs also funded a two
Graves-Brown, P.M. (ed.), 2000. Matter, Materiality and
month stint at the Maison dArchologie et Ethnologie
Modern Culture. London: Routledge.
(Universit de Paris I et X and CNRS), at the invitation of
Hayles, N.K., 1999. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual
Sander van der Leeuw; this was extremely useful to me in
Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chi-
helping to develop some of the ideas expressed in this
cago (IL): University of Chicago Press.
paper. Any errors or oversights remain of course my own.
Heft, H., 1989. Affordances and the body: an intentional
analysis of Gibsons ecological approach to visual
References perception. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour
19(1), 130.
Bechtel, W. & G. Graham (eds.), 1998. A Companion to Hodder, I., 1993. Social cognition, in Viewpoint: What is
Cognitive Science. Oxford: Blackwell. cognitive archaeology?, by C. Renfrew et al. Cam-
Brooks, R., 1991. Intelligence without representation. Arti- bridge Archaeological Journal 3(2), 24770.
ficial Intelligence 47, 13959. Hodder, I. (ed.), 2001. Archaeological Theory Today. Cam-
Bruce, V., P.R. Green & M.A. Georgeson, 1996. Visual bridge: Polity Press.
Perception: Physiology, Psychology and Ecology. Hove: Holland, D. & M. Cole, 1995. Between discourse and
Psychology Press. schema: reformulating a cultural-historical approach
Bryson, N., 1990. Looking at the Overlooked: Four Essays on to culture and mind. Anthropology and Education
Still Life Painting. London: Reaktion Books. Quarterly 26(4), 47889.
Clark, A., 1996. Philosophical foundations, in Artificial Holland, D., W. Lachicotte, D. Skinner & C. Cain, 1998.
Intelligence, ed. M.A. Boden. London: Academic Identity and Agency in Cultural Worlds. Cambridge
Press, 122. (MA): Harvard University Press.
Clark, A., 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Hutchins, E., 1995. Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge (MA):
Together Again. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press. MIT Press.
Clark, A., 1998. Embodied, situated, and distributed cog- Ingold, T., 2000. The Perception of the Environment: Essays in
nition, in Bechtel & Graham (eds.), 50617. Livelihood, Dwelling and Skill. London: Routledge.
Cole, M., 1996. Cultural Psychology: a Once and Future Dis- Julien, M.-P., 1999. Des techniques du corps la synthse
cipline. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. corporelle: mises en objets, in Julien & Warnier (eds.),

50
The Affordances of Things

1527. Costall. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 17197.


Julien, M.-P. & J.-P. Warnier (eds.), 1999. Approches de la Renfrew, C., 2001. Symbol before concept: material en-
culture matrielle: corps corps avec lobjet. Paris: gagement and the early development of society, in
LHarmattan. Hodder (ed.), 12240.
Kaufmann, J.-C., 1997. Le coeur louvrage: thorie de laction Schlanger, N., 1994. Mindful technology: unleashing the
mnagre. Paris: Nathan. chane opratoire for an archaeology of mind, in The
Kirsh, D., 1995. The intelligent use of space. Artificial Intel- Ancient Mind: Elements of Cognitive Archaeology, eds.
ligence 73, 3168. C. Renfrew & E. Zubrow. Cambridge: Cambridge
Kirsh, D. & P. Maglio, 1994. On distinguishing epistemic University Press, 14351.
from pragmatic action. Cognitive Science 18, 51349. Semprini, A., 1995. Lobjet comme procs et comme action de
Latour, B., 2000. The Berlin key or how to do words with la nature et de lusage des objets dans la vie quotidienne.
things, in Graves-Brown (ed.), 1021. Paris: LHarmattan.
Lfgren, O., 1996. Le retour des objets? Ltude de la Shanks, M., 1998. The life of an artefact in an interpretive
culture matrielle dans lethnologie sudoise. Cul- archaeology. Fennoscandia Archaeologica 15, 1530.
ture matrielle et modernit - Ethnologie franaise 26(1), Shanks, M. & C. Tilley, 1987. Social Theory and Archaeology.
14050. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Maglio, P.P., T. Matlock, D. Raphaely, B. Chernicky & D. Sonesson, G., 1989. Pictorial Concepts: Inquiries into the Semi-
Kirsh, 1999. Interactive skill in Scrabble, in Proceed- otic Heritage and Its Relevance for the Analysis of the
ings of the 21st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Visual World. Lund: Lund University Press.
Science Society, eds. M. Hahn & S.C. Stoness. Mahwah Strauss, C. & N. Quinn 1997. A Cognitive Theory of Cultural
(NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum. Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mauss, M., 1950/1936. Les techniques du corps, in Sociologie Suchman, L.A., 1987. Plans and Situated Actions: the Prob-
et anthropologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de lem of HumanMachine Communication. Cambridge:
France, 36386. [1st edition 1936. Journal de Cambridge University Press.
Psychologie 32.] Thomas, J., 1998. Some problems with the notion of exter-
Michaels, C.F. & C. Carello, 1981. Direct Perception. Lon- nal symbolic storage, and the case of Neolithic ma-
don: Prentice-Hall. terial culture in Britain, in Cognition and Material
Noble, W., 1991. Ecological realism and the fallacy of Culture: the Archaeology of Symbolic Storage, eds. C.
objectification, in Against Cognitivism: Alternative Renfrew & C. Scarre. (McDonald Institute Mono-
Foundations for Cognitive Psychology, eds. A. Still & graphs.) Cambridge: McDonald Institute for Ar-
A. Costall. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 199223. chaeological Research, 14956.
Noble, W., 1993. Meaning and the discursive ecology: Thomas, J., 2001. Archaeologies of place and landscape, in
further to the debate on ecological perceptual theory. Hodder (ed.), 16586.
Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 23(4), 37598. Tilley, C., 1994. A Phenomenology of Landscape: Places, Paths
Norman, D., 1993. Les artefacts cognitifs, in Conein et al. and Monuments. Oxford: Berg.
(eds.), 1534. Tomasello, M., 1999. The Cultural Origins of Human Cogni-
Norman, D., 1998. The Design of Everyday Things. London: tion. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.
MIT Press. van Gelder, T. & R.F. Port, 1995. Its about time: an over-
Palmer, S.E., 1999. Vision Science: From Photons to Phenom- view of the dynamical approach to cognition, in
enology. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press. Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cog-
Parmentier, R.J., 1997. The pragmatic semiotics of cul- nition, eds. R.F. Port & T. van Gelder. Cambridge
tures. Semiotica 116, 1115. (MA): MIT Press, 143.
Petitot, J., F.J. Varela, B. Pacoud & J.-M. Roy (eds.), 2000. Vygotsky, L., 1978. Mind in Society: the Development of
Naturalising Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Higher Psychological Processes, ed. M. Cole. Cambridge
Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford (CA): (MA): Harvard University Press.
Stanford University Press. Warnier, J.-P., 1999a. Construire la culture matrielle: lhomme
Preucel, R.W. & A.A. Bauer, 2001. Archaeological prag- qui pensait avec ses doigts. Paris: Presses Universitaires
matics. Norwegian Archaeological Review 34(2), 8596. de France.
Reed, E.S., 1988a. The affordances of the animate environ- Warnier, J.-P., 1999b. Conclusion: le sujet comme roue
ment: social science from the ecological point of dengrenage, in Julien & Warnier (eds.), 13542.
view, in What Is An Animal?, ed. T. Ingold. London: Wertsch, J.V., 1998a. Mind as Action. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Unwin Hyman, 11026. versity Press.
Reed, E.S., 1988b. James J. Gibson and the Psychology of Wertsch, J.V., 1998b. Mediated action, in Bechtel & Graham
Perception. New Haven (CT): Yale University Press. (eds.), 51825.
Reed, E.S., 1991. James Gibsons ecological approach to Williams, E. & A. Costall 2000. Taking things more seri-
cognition, in Against Cognitivism: Alternative Foun- ously: psychological theories of autism and the ma-
dations for Cognitive Psychology, eds. A. Still & A. terial-social divide, in Graves-Brown (ed.), 97111.

51

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen