Sie sind auf Seite 1von 9

American Economic Association

Experimental Economics: Reply


Author(s): Vernon L. Smith
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 75, No. 1 (Mar., 1985), pp. 265-272
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1812727
Accessed: 05-05-2017 07:23 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
American Economic Review

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Experimental Economics: Reply

By VERNON L. SMITH*

More than in any particular method of mental are the concepts and assumptions of
inquiry, I think the hallmark of science is to a science, the easier it is to take them for
be found in a constructively skeptical atti- granted and to abandon this skepticism. In
tude toward knowledge.' The more funda- this spirit, Ronald Heiner (1985) is correct in
emphasizing that the "knowledge" obtained
from the study of the performance of experi-
*Department of Economics, University of Arizona, mental markets is only as secure as the
Tucson, AZ 85721. classical preference model used to induce
1 The principal contribution of Popper's falsifi- prespecified value structures on the agents
cationist methodology is, I believe, the influential at-
in such markets. If the purpose of an ex-
tempt to develop a formal logic of skeptical inquiry.
That the attempt has failed, in the sense that it has periment is to test a theory (for example,
produced no defensible codified set of procedures that supply and demand), and the theory is not
yield a science of scientific method (happily it would "falsified" by the test, this in no way sup-
appear that all such attempts will fail), should not ports any premise of the theory which was
detract from the disciplinary value of the falsificationist
also a premise of the experimental design.
perspective in approaching scientific questions. Its value
to the experimentalist is to force him to ask "How can I When we falsify a theory, the implication is
design an experiment with the property that the set of that one or more of its assumptions about
potentially observable outcomes can be partitioned into the behavior of economic agents (maximiza-
those that are consistent with one (or a given) theory
tion of expected utility, commonly shared
and those that are consistent with other theory(ies) (or
inconsistent with the given theory)?" That experimental
(homogeneous) expectations, risk aversion,
life is such that his effort is about as likely to fail as to zero subjective costs of transacting, etc.) is in
succeed by no means detracts from the value of the question, and the immediate task is to mod-
exercise. Its value to the theorist (if he will just forgo the ify the suspected behavioral assumptions of
career-advancing primeval incentive to publish yet
the original theory. Other assumptions-such
another technically tractable extension of the existing
theory literature) is to force him to ask "How can I as that agents have well-defined preferences,
model this question so as to suggest (as Martin Shubik or know the probability distribution from
would say) a do-able experiment, and so as to yield which other agent values were drawn-are
observable implications that do not exhaust the set of
not brought into question by the experiment
possible outcomes?" That this effort will often fail does
not detract from the value of the exercise. Having said because the experimental design reproduced
this I would not want to leave the impression that (or should have) the environment posited by
experiments that are fishing expeditions in the labora- the theory being tested. When testing formal
tory to see what will happen are of no value; seeing market theories in this way, we should al-
what happens can be essential in defining an analytical-
ways be aware of the fact that we are study-
empirical research program. Similarly, when a theorist
builds (as Buz Brock would say) castles in the air, this is ing behavior within the context of our repre-
not necessarily useless, for it may lead to more oper- sentations of the economic environment. If any
ational forms of theory. We should impute some non- of these representations is wrong, then our
zero probability to the proposition that Feyerabend's
studies have only increased our self-knowl-
"anything goes" posture is right. But at this stage I
think it has become pretty obvious where our profes-
edge, not our knowledge of things (natural
sional weaknesses are concentrated. Economists, while economic processes).
spouting the rhetoric (Donald McClosky, 1983) of the If we are to increase our knowledge of
falsificationist, are in fact verificationist to the core. We things, then our ultimate aim should aspire
all do it. We take a proposition, conjecture, or theory,
to more than discovering that the behavioral
then search for supportive historical or empirical exam-
ples. As everyone ought to know, seek and ye are likely
to find, whether one is a "Keynesian" or a "supply
sider." What is not sufficiently appreciated is that this how difficult it is to find; if there is none or if it is pretty
verificationist grubbing is a prescientific exercise in which hard to uncover, it suggests abandonment in the presci-
one asks whether there is any supporting evidence, and entific womb.

265

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
266 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 1985

properties of our own creations are con- ments "depends critically on the fact that
sistent with controlled experimental evi- subjects behave in a way which is consistent
dence, although the attempt to falsify these with utility-maximizing principles underlying
creations may be a necessary step in acquir- consumer demand theory and that negatively
ing the conditional knowledge that can sloped demand curves have been induced in
improve our theorizing ability. This is why the market" (p. 13). I do not wish to suggest
empirical investigations of all aspects of that these studies have put to rest the issues
parallelism between laboratory and field raised by Heiner whose emphasis is on the
behavior are important. Similarly, our ex- inadequacy of standard theory when prefer-
perimental and other investigations should ences are uncertain. Indeed, both the animal
not be confined to testing formal theory (for and especially the human preference studies
example, nomothetic experiments) since this of Kagel et al. exhibit "dynamic" effects or
objective requires us to impose more struc- lagged responses that are not even supposed
ture on the free play of decision making than to exist in received preference theory, and
ultimately may be justified. Finally, our re- which may reflect the "insecure preference
search methodology should not be too rigid beliefs" suggested by Heiner (1983). It would
in testing only the market implications of a seem that lagged responses are inconsistent
theory (or in testing only the assumptions of with a cognitive, calculating interpretation of
a theory). preference theory, but consistent with some
Thus, John Kagel et al. (1981) have ad- sort of adaptive response interpretation. Even
dressed direct tests of the observable impli- if preference theory accounts for many
cations of preference theory. This literature agents' stationary state choices in certain
reports results consistent with standard pref- experimental situations, it tells us nothing
erence theory (i.e., with Hicks-Slutzky in- about the processes that yield these "good"
come-compensated demand theory), but also predictions or why some agents' behavior is
with the ad hoc widely assumed law of de- not consistent with the theory. The failure of
mand, which Heiner (1983) is able to deduce animal studies to falsify demand theory can
from his model of adaptive uncertain choice.2 be interpreted as lending support to Heiner's
As noted by Kagel et al., the convergence (1983) emphasis on rule-governed behavior
tendency reported in auction market experi- although here the "rules" are apparently
programmed into the instincts (genes), unless
we are prepared to accept the proposition
2Since it seems that no one has ever produced any
rigorous evidence for the existence of a price inferior that species other than ours have cognitive
good (Sir Giffen was just speculating, and had no con- decision-making powers.
trols on his "experiment"), its prediction by textbook Furthermore, the numerous direct studies
theory is a curiosity (which was recognized as such by of individual decision making under uncer-
Alfred Marshall who started it all), that should have
tainty, over the past 25 years (see the recent
counted against the theory, just as the failure to find a
planet "Vulcan" between Mercury and the sun (there papers by David Grether, 1980; Grether and
was no shortage of claimed sightings), that would accountCharles Plott, 1979; and especially the survey
for the advance of Mercury's perihelion, ultimately and evaluation by Paul Slovic and Sarah
counted against Newtonian theory (David DeVorkin,
Lichtenstein, 1983), suggest that our theories
1983, p. 1058). In more mature sciences this might have
sparked analytical interest in producing a theory con-
of decision under uncertainty are in several
sistent with the law of demand, but having other falsifi- respects inconsistent with controlled evi-
able implications. Contrarily, in economics such a the- dence. The results of these experiments are
ory might even be considered unpublishable because of robust under replication, and various arti-
its "lack of generality," and the Giffen good curiosity
factual explanations of the results (that might
has sparked an endless preoccupation with examples of
" multiple" and " unstable" equilibria based on the have rescued the theory) have been sys-
Walrasian adjustment mechanism, which is itself devoid tematically eliminated. The results are not to
of any institutional evidence. These have been good be idly dismissed by anyone with the slight-
analytical exercises, but so far as I can see all this
est interest in evidence. What I want to
self-knowledge is good only for teaching the defenseless
and uninitiated students who will form the next genera- suggest is that (so far as we are able to tell)
tion of automata. experimental methods are entirely competent

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 75 NO. I SMITH: EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS 267

to examine these important issues. New the- greater " rationality" in behavior because they
ory, such as that proposed by Heiner (1983) force or promote a response to, or discovery
and Soo Hong Chew (1983) (also see Don of, opportunity cost conditions, that need
Coursey, 1982) are particularly welcome at not be readily forthcoming when agents
this stage in research programs using, or merely think about the choices they make.
directly concerned with testing, preference What I have in mind may be close to Armen
theory under uncertainty. Alchian's (1977, pp. 27-32) imitative and
However, among those who take these ex- trial-and-error forms of conscious adaptive
perimental results as a serious challenge to behavior, except that I would deemphasize
existing theory, not all may interpret them the "conscious" element.3
in
the same way. In the following I will try to Different forms of market organization
state some of my interpretations, and relate have been found to differ in their power to
them, where it seems appropriate, to Heiner's induce or extract neoclassical rational behav-
work. ior. Thus the English auction is slightly more
1) The state of experimental research on efficient (97 percent of the allocations are
decision under uncertainty has produced Pareto optimal), and prices are consistently
many unresolved anomalies. Experimental closer to the predicted second highest value
tests of market theories, which explicitly among the bidders, than is the Second price
assume expected utility (or value) maximiza- sealed-bid auction (94 percent Pareto opti-
tion, have not falsified many of these theo- mal allocations) (see Cox, Mark Isaac, and
ries (for example, James Cox, Bruce Rober- myself, 1983, pp. 73-75). An explanation is
son and myself, 1982; Plott and Louis Wilde, simple. In the English auction it is a domi-
1982). Yet, as indicated above, the results of nant strategy to raise the standing bid if it is
direct tests are inconsistent with the expected less than your value, and to never raise your
utility hypothesis (EUH). Some, but not own bid. Behaviorally, the temptation to use
all (for example, violation of simple domi- this strategy is irresistable, and made trans-
nance), of these anomalies are resolved by parent (without thinking) by the sequential
Chew's weighted expected utility hypothesis complete bid information properties of the
(WEUH). Although at this stage I think it process. In terms of Heiner's model (1983),
would be premature to abandon EUH, and subjects easily (I would say at low cost)
especially its extensions, it is not premature
to work on the resolution of these anomalies.
(One did not reject Newton's inverse square 3In writing this reply, I found myself reminiscing that
law of attraction because the planets failed Adam Smith did not begin his economic analysis, as
does mainstream economics, with preferences as the
to move in perfect ellipses, nor because of
primeval cause of the phenomena we study. He began
the highly inconsistent observed advance in with a deeply insightful observation qua axiom, which
the perihelion of Mercury.) states that man is unique among all animal species in
2) One route to such a resolution may exhibiting " the propensity to truck, barter and exchange
be to recognize, and to elaborate more for- one thing for another." (Man is not unique in revealing
preferences.) After some speculation that this might be a
mally, the hypothesis that subjects are more
consequence of man's ability to use language (I would
rational (in the sense of received decision speculate that man's development of language may have
theory under uncertainty) in the context of been in part due to the specialization and affluence
laboratory markets, than when responding made possible by markets), Smith deduced the im-
portant result that it is this power of exchanging that
to questionnaire choices among prospects,
gives rise to wealth creating specialization, which in turn
because of Heiner's conjecture that " Ex- is limited by the extent of the market. Markets thus lead
change environments also enable agents to agents to promote ends which are no part of their
interact with each other in an organized and intention. Except for modern scholars such as Hayek,
often repeated fashion. Markets thus provide the idea that we are studying processes that contain
major elements that are not consciously or cognitively
agents with additional feedback that may
purposive has been lost in the pyrotechnics of straight-
help guide their behavior" (1985, p. 263). ening out Smith's little paradoxes of value. No wonder
From the study of experimental markets, I that Kenneth Boulding will tell you flat out that Smith
have long thought that markets may induce was the first great post-Newtonian scientist.

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
268 THE A MERICA N ECONOMIC RE VIE W MA RCH 1985

perceive, perhaps quite unconsciously, the 3) The wide variety of different experi-
opportunity cost of "nonoptimal" behavior. mental studies of decision making under un-
In the Second price sealed-bid auction it is a certainty, yielding results inconsistent with
dominant strategy to submit a bid equal to EUH, are subject to different interpretations
your value. But this requires reasoning which in terms of the damage they inflict on EUH.
is in fact very subtle, although, as with all I think a key element in these interpretations
puzzles, it is obvious or "trivial" once you is what Jacob Marschak (1968) long ago
understand it.4 One must perceive that if called the cost of thinking, calculating, decid-
one's own bid is the highest, the price paid is ing, and acting, which are all part of what I
the amount of the next highest bid, and have called the subjective cost of transacting
therefore one's surplus to be gained is inde- (SCT) (see my 1982 article, p. 934 and pas-
pendent of the amount bid. So the "rational" sim). Of course, one could argue that EUH
bid is to maximize your chance of winning and its Chew-Machina-type extensions are
by bidding your value. About a third of the on the face of it inadequate theories because
subjects recruited out of campus classrooms they leave SCT out of the formal apparatus.
to participate in a sequence of Second price But this is much too harsh. Considerations of
auctions (with values assigned independently SCT are hard to formalize within a frame-
from a distribution to all bidders in each work as general as that attempted in EUH
auction), bid "as if" they perceive the im- and WEUH, that allow the latter to be de-
plied dominant strategy from the beginning. duced as limiting cases when SCT goes to
About one-third appear to "learn" asymptot- zero, or when outcome values get large rela-
ically from their success-failure experience tive to a fixed SCT. But the modification of
that this is the "best" strategy. Another third standard EUH theory by introducing SCT
do not clearly converge to the dominant elements in particular decision-making con-
strategy- some hit it irratically, some rarely, texts (Sydney Siegel, 1961), or in illustrative
if ever, and some bid just below value. An examples (my 1982 article, p. 934), point to
examination of the bids that are less than the untapped potential of imbedding stan-
value reveals that many occur at values so dard theories in larger (and more "rational")
low that the prospect of having the winning frameworks. How important are the SCT
bid is remote. These can be interpreted as elements in the various decision contexts
"throw-away" bids, and if in the strict sense which yield violations of EUH?
they are "irrational," at least they are only (a) I think the class of violations which
marginally so.5 are due to Kahneman-Tversky framing effects
(see Slovic and Lichtenstein, and the refer-
ences therein), do relatively low level damage
4Richard Thaler once reported in a seminar that,
informally, he had gone around polling economists as to to EUH. The typical case here is that the
how they would bid, after describing the Second price options are identical in two situations except
auction procedure. This was before William Vickrey's that in one the outcomes are stated in terms
discussion of this auction had become so well-known.
of what will be lost (deaths), the other in
He reported that very few got it "right." Most thought
one should bid at least a "little" under value. The early
terms of what will be gained (lives saved). It
polling of economists on Allais, Ellsberg, Second price, seems to me that these are like elementary
and other such " paradoxes" makes it clear that optimal illusions, which the individual, at
economists will get it "wrong" about as often as the
comparatively low cost, can learn to recog-
sophomore subject (who of course we pay a monetary
reward) until he or she has had considerable time to
think and analyze. Incidentally, this observation pro-
vides an answer for that somewhat mythical business- so regularly that it has become a permanent way of life.
man who asks, " If you're so smart why ain't you rich?" They reveal two things: 1) how quickly, easily and
My classmate, Otto Eckstein, didn't get rich by equating matter of factly as economists we are prepared to be-
price to marginal cost. lieve our own propaganda (theorems), and to use these
'An outstanding young economist once asked me beliefs to insulate ourselves from evidence; and 2) how
why I was bothering to do Second price sealed-bid the use of experimental methods leads one to think
auction experiments since the dominant strategy prop- about the world of economic knowledge in a fundamen-
erty was so trivial. I encounter statements in this spirit tally different way.

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 75 NO. 1 SMITH: EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS 269

nize as such (for example, the individual can cal" illusions, and may require rather more
be taught that the death rate is one minus SCT to yield consistency of choice. How-
the survival rate. If it is hard to teach this, as ever, the fact that they seem to be moderated
it may be, then I am wrong in interpreting it (although they do not disappear) when the
as a low-cost recognition problem). We all motivation is increased (Werner Pom-
learn that when the sun is low, the pond in merehne et al., 1982) is consistent with the
the highway ahead is just a reflection, and we hypothesis that subjects do seek to increase
do not risk a rear-end collision by jamming benefits net of SCT, even where the latter are
on the brakes. In saying this, I do not mean relatively large. A preference reverser is of
to suggest that the study of framing effects is course vulnerable to a con game (money
of no interest. On the contrary, these exam- pump) in which a sequence of decisions will
ples show how bad we can be at intuitive produce a loss in assets. Will a person dis-
problem solving, and why it is important to cover his decision inconsistencies and learn
examine a decision from alternative perspec- the appropriate corrections in a money pump
tives. Also, these examples vary in trans- sequence? In this context EUH is being
parency. I find the second example cited by tested in a more market-like framework. J. E.
Slovic and Lichtenstein (p. 597) to involve Berg et al. (1984) report results showing that
more SCT than the first. I think the equiv- although the frequency of preference rever-
alence of the two situations in the first exam- sals is not reduced, the total value (dollar
ple could be conveyed to the uninitiated magnitude) of preference reversals is re-
much more easily than the second. So some duced. Apparently, there is positive interac-
of these "optical" illusions may be more tion between the stakes, and the money pump
costly to expose than others.6 Note that this treatment. They also report that the prefer-
SCT interpretation blurs the distinction ence reversal phenomena tends to decline
often made between positive and normative across experiments with the same subjects.
economic theory, but I have never been 4) The results of direct laboratory tests
convinced that such a distinction was very of EUH have been used to explain the ap-
helpful. parent failure of EUH in insurance, securi-
(b) The preference reversal examples ties and futures markets (see Kenneth Arrow,
may represent still more sophisticated "opti- 1982; Heiner, 1983). Although this appears
to be evidence of parallelism in behavior
between laboratory and field, I think we have
to be particularly careful in drawing this
6In studies of science learning it is found that bothparallel. There is first a question of the com-
weak and strong learners come to their first science parability of the quality of the evidence in
classes with extensive "naive" theories about how the the two environments, and second a question
world works. They use these naive theories to explain
physical events and tend, even after instruction in the
of whether EUH is failing for the same
new concepts and the scientific support for them, to reason in the two environments. In the
resort to their prior theories to solve problems that differ laboratory experiments, the situations are
from the textbook examples (Lauren Resnik, 1983). Of carefully controlled and structured, the states
course with EUH we have the difficult problem of
of nature are well-defined, and so are the
deciding when the subject is making a "mistake" (an
"optical" illusion) which she can at more-or-less cost outcomes. Consequently, the results are much
recognize as such, and when the theory is a mistake, or more clearly interpretable as inconsistent
not relevant to the actual problem faced by the subject with EUH, even if the cause of the incon-
(which, for example, might be better represented by
sistency is an inappropriate carryover to the
WEUH than EUH). The fact that about one-third of
the subjects in sequential Second price sealed-bid auc-
laboratory of Heiner's rule-governed agent
tions "learn" to make dominant strategy choices has whose habits have been developed in the
been interpreted as analogous to learning that a certain more unstructured uncertainty environments
mirage is an optimal illusion and the self-interest is not of the field; or if, as I have suggested, the
served by taking such a phenomenon at its face value
results can be interpreted in terms of SCT,
(Vicki Coppinger et al., 1980, p. 20). Also see Thaler
(1983) for a discussion of cognitive illusions and mirages and EUH is considered to be just a limiting
in decision making. case of a more general economic problem.

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
270 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 1985

An example may help to clarify one type it is standard political procedure for the
of ambiguity in interpreting field observa- governor to declare it a disaster area, and the
tions in terms of EUH. Suppose you have federal government to respond with relief
had a sore rib for many weeks that hasn't when a flood occurs, then I might not buy
healed. Your doctor sends you to the lab for insurance even at rates below actuarial value.
an x-ray to "see if it is fractured." It is not (This need not be a conscious decision with
fractured, and she tells you, "Well, a hairline people able to state that the failure to buy
fracture might not show, but it doesn't much insurance was due to the expectation of
matter since the treatment is the same government relief.) Without better controls
whether it is a fracture or a contusion." You on the experimental treatment variable, I
think, "This violates the Savage axioms!" don't know how to interpret the observa-
Does it? How do you (or does she) know that tions. This problem does not reflect on the
there are only two states of nature, rib frac- quality of these excellent studies cited by
tured or rib bruised, given that it is sore? Arrow, but on the difficulty of doing field
Could a carcinoma behind the rib make it experiments with the most desirable controls.
sore? There may be hundreds of causes of Similar considerations apply when asking
sore ribs, and it may not be worth anyone's whether interest rates or stock prices vary
trouble to list them all, or even to invest time "too much" (see the studies by Cagan and
in thinking about any significant fraction of Shiller cited in Arrow). It is unclear what is
them. A host of past experiences may have to be concluded when the falsifying "facts"
programmed your doctor to acquire informa- are no more than "an impression which many
tion that appears to be redundant in this students of these markets and practitioners
particular case, and she may be unable to in them seem to have" (Arrow, p. 4).
organize these experiences into an articulate But Stewart's finding that unprofessional
case for her actions because such a detailed speculators lose money in grain futures is
cognitive treatment of every decision is cited by Arrow as "especially surprising,"
neither a necessary nor a desirable feature of and he asks "why did they enter the market
her modus operandi. at all?" (p. 3). I would suggest that they do it
As a second example, take the reported for the same reason that people go to Las
reluctance of people to insure against rare Vegas to play roulette, buy tickets in the
disasters even though, since 1969, the Arizona Lottery, and play bingo at the local
government has offered subsidized flood in- church on Thursdays. I don't see any way to
surance rates that are below actuarial value. understand these phenomena with EUH (it
Is it a fact that this violates EUH? If it is a is well known that convex, risk-preferring,
fact, then I like Heiner's explanation that utility doesn't explain repetitive small stakes
there is a tradeoff between the greater setup wagering) nor any way to understand them
costs (these are part of what I call SCT) of with Heiner's theory. I find it necessary, if
insuring against more events of small prob- not entirely satisfactory in terms of seeking a
ability, and the expected loss from failing to universal theory, to accept the idea that some
insure, and it is hardly economical to insure people just simply like to gamble (ancient
against everything. Hence, in the field situa- hunter cultures did it) and that it has com-
tion EUH is failing because it formulates the modity value, or perhaps that some people
wrong economic choice problem, by leaving have "pathological" expectations, whether it
out SCT. But it is not clear from the evi- is roulette, grain futures or stock investment.
dence that this is an example of the violation (See my 1971 article.)7
of EUH. Arrow tells us that the reason the
government offered the subsidized insurance
"was to relieve the pressure for the govern-
ment to offer relief when floods occurred"
71f in all markets with uncertainty there is a subclass
(p. 2). If I have built a house on a flood of participants with these "irrational" characteristics,
plane, if flood planes sometimes flood (we this lowers the insurance cost of hedging and lowers the
call them 100-year floods in Arizona), and if cost of capital to firms. The gamblers lose money volun-

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. 75 NO. 1 SMITH: EXPERIMENTAL ECONOMICS 271

I have no disagreement with Heiner's cri- REFERENCES


tique of classical preference theory, which is
among the roots that should be reexamined. Alchian, Armen, "Uncertainty, Evolution and
However, I would register disagreement with Economic Theory," in Economic Forces at
Heiner's interpretation of "privacy" as an Work, Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1977.
experimental condition. As noted in my Arrow, Kenneth, "Risk Perception in Psy-
article (1982, p. 933, fn. 13; p. 935) the chology and Economics," Economic In-
purpose of privacy is to maintain control quiry, January 1982, 20, 1-9.
over preferences. Privacy does not deny the Berg, J. E., Dickhaut, J. W. and O'Brien, J. R.,
existence of interpersonal externalities. The "Preference Reversal and Arbitrage," in
latter is achieved under controlled conditions V. Smith, ed., Research in Experimental
by simply inducing the appropriate interde- Economics, Vol. 3, Greenwich: JAI Press,
pendent preferences if that is the topic of 1984.
investigation. If one wishes to study the effect Chew, Soo Hong, "A Generalization of the
of " utility information" on behavior, one Quasilinear Mean with Applications to the
publicizes information on commodity alloca- Measurement of Income Inequality and
tions, or token earnings (which is analogous Decision Theory Resolving the Allais
to income in the field), but not subject cash Paradox," Econometrica, July 1983, 51,
payoffs since these are to induce utility on 1065-92.
allocations and indirectly on token income. Coppinger, Vicki, Smith, Vernon and Titus, John,
The idea is to preserve the natural uncer- "Incentives and Behavior in English,
tainty about other's subjective value of allo- Dutch and Sealed-Bid Auctions," Eco-
cations, and of the exchange medium. nomic Inquiry, January 1980, 18, 1-22.
Coursey, Don L., "Hierarchical Preferences
and Consumer Choice," unpublished doc-
toral dissertation, University of Arizona,
1982.
tarily, the economy benefits and perhaps only EUH Cox, James, Roberson, Bruce and Smith, Vernon,
suffers as a predictive theory for some types of agents. "Theory and Behavior of Single Object
But the existence of such agents in futures, stock, and Auctions," in V. Smith, ed., Research in
option markets will cause such markets to appear to be
Experimental Economics, Vol. 2, Green-
irrational by our definitions, whereas actually these
markets may be performing with high allocative wich: JAI Press, 1982.
efficiency, given the environment, by taking wealth away , Isaac, Mark and Smith Vernon,' "OCS
from the gamblers and giving it to the hedgers, inves- Leasing and Auctions: Incentives and the
tors, and rational expectationists. Isn't Las Vegas an
Performance of Alternative Bidding In-
exchange market between gamblers (customers) and ra-
stitutions," Supreme Court Economic Re-
tional expectationists (casinos)? The question may be
not "Why are certain markets inefficient?," but "What view, July 1983, 2, 43-87.
is wrong with our interpretation of markets?" An im- DeVorkin, David H., "Review of N. T.
portant technical difference between casinos and finan- Roseveare, Mercury's Perihelion from Le
cial markets is that in the former the agent learns
Verrier to Einstein," Science, March 4,
immediately the outcome of her investment. But the
more variable are the prices of financial instruments, the 1983, 219, 1058.
more will they have this casino characteristic, and the Grether, David, "Bayes Rule as a Descriptive
more attractive they will be to this type of investor. Model: The Representativeness Heuristic,"
Hence, the alleged "fact" that security prices vary " too
Quarterly Journal of Economics, November
much" may be both the effect and the cause of its
1980, 95, 537-57.
appeal to these kinds of investors.
I suspect that Adam Smith would wonder why there and Plott, Charles, "Economic Theory
is so much modem professional interest in the internal of Choice and the Preference Reversal
efficiency or "perfection" of particular markets, and so Phenomenon," American Economic Re-
little interest in what determines the extent of markets,
view, September 1979, 69, 623-38.
and how this in turn may create social gains that are
more important and significant than the " imperfections" Heiner, Ronald A., "The Origin of Predictable
in particular markets that are suggested by our theory of Behavior," American Economic Review,
" rational" preferences. September 1983, 73, 560-95.

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
272 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC RE VIEW MARCH 1985

, "Experimental Economics: Com- nomenon: A Reexamination," American


ment," American Economic Review, March Economic Review, June 1982, 72, 569-74.
1985, 75, 260-63. Resnik, Lauren, B., "Mathematics and Science
Kagel et al., John H., " Demand Curves for Learning: A New Conception," Science,
Animal Consumers," Quarterly Journal of April 29, 1983, 220, 477-78.
Economics, February 1981, 96, 1-16. Siegel, Sydney, "Decision Making and Learn-
Marschak, Jacob, " Economics of Inquiring, ing Under Varying Conditions of Rein-
Communicating, Deciding," American forcement," Annals of the New York
Economic Review Proceedings, May 1968, Academy of Science, 1961, 89, 766-83.
58,1-18. Slovic, Paul and Lichtenstein, Sarah, "Prefer-
McClosky, Donald N., "The Rhetoric of Eco- ence Reversals: A Broader Perspective,"
nomics," Journal of Economic Literature, American Economic Review, September
June 1983, 21, 481-517. 1983, 73, 596-605.
Plott, Charles and Wilde, Louis, "Professional Smith, Vernon L., " Economic Theory of Wager
Diagnosis vs. Self-Diagnosis: An Experi- Markets," Western Economic Journal, Sep-
mental Examination of Some Special Fea- tember 1971, 9, 242-55.
tures of Market With Uncertainty," in Re- __ "Microeconomic Systems as an
search in Experimental Economics, Vol. 2, Experimental Science," American Eco-
Greenwich: JAI Press, 1982, 63-112. nomic Review, December 1982, 72, 923-55.
Pommerehne, Werner W., Schnieder, Frederick Thaler, Richard H., "Illusions and Mirages in
and Zweifel, Peter, "Economic Theory of Public Policy," Public Interest, Fall 1983,
Choice and the Preference Reversal Phe- 73, 60-74.

This content downloaded from 193.226.34.228 on Fri, 05 May 2017 07:23:37 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen