Sie sind auf Seite 1von 192

Winter School in Language and Speech

Technologies, 2012
Rovira i Virgili University, Tarragona

Geoffrey K. Pullum

University of Edinburgh

January 2012
Tarragona, Spain

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 1 / 163


The English language: preliminaries

What we mean by English: grammar, style, dialects, etc.


What English is like: brief typology
Structure of The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language
Categories and functions
Lexical categorization: V, N, D, Adj, Adv, P, Sbr, Cdr, Intj
Syntactic features: [auxiliary], [definite], [number], [pronoun], ...
Projection to phrases: heads and dependents.
Complements and adjuncts
Subjects and objects
Canonical clauses

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 2 / 163


The Cambridge Grammar

The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language


by Rodney Huddleston and Geoffrey K. Pullum
is abbreviated here as CGEL.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 3 / 163


The Cambridge Grammar

The Cambridge Grammar of the English Language


by Rodney Huddleston and Geoffrey K. Pullum
is abbreviated here as CGEL.

Useful elementary textbook based on CGEL:


A Students Introduction to English
Grammar a guide to CGEL in 300 pages.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 3 / 163


The Cambridge Grammar

Structure of CGEL:

Chapter 1: introduction
Chapter 2: overview of the content of the entire book
Chapters 37: lexical categorization (N, V, Adj, Adv, Prep)
Chapter 8: adjuncts
Chapters 916: non-canonical clauses (negation, subordinate
clauses, non-declarative clauses, etc.)
Chapter 17: anaphora and ellipsis
Chapter 18: inflectional morphology
Chapter 19: derivational morphology (word formation)
Chapter 20: punctuation

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 4 / 163


First topic: verbs and auxiliaries

Verbs and the AUXILIARY/LEXICAL distinction

The verbal inflectional system

The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 5 / 163


Lexical and auxiliary verbs

Two syntactic classes of verbs (they are not semantic!):

A special subsets, the auxiliary verbs

The rest, called the lexical verbs

Warning: The traditional definition of auxiliary verbs


as helping verbs is toxic! Stay away from it!
(In CGEL terms: it overlooks the non-core uses of auxiliaries.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 6 / 163


English verb inflection

The unique paradigm of be:

PRIMARY FORMS
NEUTRAL NEGATIVE
1st sg 3rd sg other 1st sg 3rd sg other
present am is are arent isnt arent
preterite was were wasnt werent
irrealis were werent

SECONDARY FORMS
plain form past participle gerund-participle
be been being

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 7 / 163


English verb inflection

The wrong wrong wrong way to describe regular verbs:

PRIMARY FORMS
NEUTRAL NEGATIVE
1st sg 3rd sg other 1st sg 3rd sg other
present fill fills fill
preterite filled filled filled
irrealis filled filled filled

SECONDARY FORMS
plain form past participle gerund-participle
fill filled filling

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 8 / 163


English verb inflection

The disastrous threesome lie/lied/lied (tell untruths), lie/lay /lain (be


recumbent), and lay /laid/laid (deposit):

plain present lie lie lay


PRIMARY 3rd sg present lies lies lays
preterite lied lay laid
plain form lie lie lay
SECONDARY gerund-participle lying lying laying
past participle lied lain laid

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 9 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

The six paradigmatic forms that have to be recognized


for a regular lexical verb like fill:

filled preterite
PRIMARY fills 3rd singular present
fill plain present
fill plain form
SECONDARY filling gerund-participle
filled past participle

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 10 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

The distinction between finite and non-finite clauses ALMOST BUT


NOT QUITE aligns with the distinction between primary and secondary
verb inflectional forms:

VERB FORM CONSTRUCTION CLAUSE


PRIMARY I am kind.
IMPERATIVE Be kind. FINITE
PLAIN FORM SUBJUNCTIVE that I be kind
INFINITIVAL for me to be kind
GERUND - PPL . being kind NON - FINITE
PAST- PPL . been kind

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 11 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

The distinction between finite and non-finite clauses ALMOST BUT


NOT QUITE aligns with the distinction between primary and secondary
verb inflectional forms:

VERB FORM CONSTRUCTION CLAUSE


PRIMARY I am kind.
IMPERATIVE Be kind. FINITE
PLAIN FORM SUBJUNCTIVE that I be kind
INFINITIVAL for me to be kind
GERUND - PPL . being kind NON - FINITE
PAST- PPL . been kind

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 12 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

But not all forms have different shapes:

fill ed preterite
PRIMARY fill s 3rd singular present
fill plain present
fill plain form
SECONDARY fill ing gerund-participle
fill ed past participle

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 13 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

There are actually no verbs with exactly 6 shapes.

Some irregular verbs (with past participle identical to plain form)


have just 3 shapes for the 6 paradigm forms:

3rd sing present gerund-participle

hits hitting
plain present plain form

hit
preterite past participle

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 14 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

Regular verbs, like bake, have 4 shapes


for the 6 paradigm forms:

3rd sing present gerund-participle

bakes baking
plain present plain form

bake

baked
preterite past participle

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 15 / 163


English verb inflection: LEXICAL VERBS

Several dozen verbs with irregular past participle suffixes,


like take, have 5 shapes for 6 paradigm forms:

3rd sing present gerund-participle

takes taking
plain present plain form

take

took taken
preterite past participle

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 16 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

And now for the auxiliary verbs. As we saw, be


overcrowds the chart with extra forms:

3rd sing present gerund-participle

is(nt) being
plain present plain form

am / are(nt) be

was(nt) / were(nt) been


preterite past participle

The negative forms really need a separate column.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 17 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

The negative forms really are words, not word sequences

(Zwicky & Pullum, Cliticization versus inflection: English nt,


Language 59 [1983], 502-513)

Key syntactic evidence: single word inversion in interrogatives

We should go. Should we go?


We shouldnt go. Shouldnt we go?
We shouldve gone. *Shouldve we gone?
We oughta go. *Oughta we go?

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 18 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

For the non-modal auxiliary verb have (the one that expresses perfect
tense), the paradigm is the same as its transitive lexical verb
counterpart, except for the additional negative primary forms, and the
fact that it has no past participle:
PRIMARY SECONDARY
3rd sg pres neutral 3rd sg pres negative gerund-participle

have havent having


plain present neutral plain present negative plain form

have havent have


preterite neutral preterite negative past participle

had hadnt *

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 19 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

Auxiliary do is similar, except there are no grounds for saying it has a


gerund-participle or a plain form, so it has no secondary forms:

PRIMARY SECONDARY
3rd sg pres neutral 3rd sg pres negative gerund-participle

does doesnt *
plain present neutral plain present negative plain form

do dont *
preterite neutral preterite negative past participle

did didnt *

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 20 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

The modal auxiliary verb will has one less distinction than auxiliary do
there is no distinct 3rd singular present; moreover, all secondary
forms are missing:

PRIMARY SECONDARY
present neutral present negative gerund-participle

*
will wont
plain form

preterite neutral preterite negative *


past participle
would wouldnt
*

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 21 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

The modal may is defective in one more form (present negative):

PRIMARY SECONDARY
present neutral present negative gerund-participle

*
may *
plain form

preterite neutral preterite negative *


past participle
might mightnt
*

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 22 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

Must is even more defective (no preterite), but still has an inflectional
paradigm:

PRIMARY SECONDARY
present neutral present negative gerund-participle

*
must mustnt
plain form

preterite neutral preterite negative *


past participle
* *
*

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 23 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

Such defectiveness seems to be genuinely morphological.


Consider the data for the modal dare:

No one dare tell him. [present neutral]


We darent tell him. [present negative]
No one dared tell him before. [preterite neutral]
We darednt tell him before. [no preterite negative]
Not daring tell him, we left. [no gerund-participle]
I thought no one would dare tell him. [plain form]
No one has dared tell him yet. [past participle]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 24 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

So the paradigm seems to be this:

PRIMARY SECONDARY
present neutral present negative gerund-participle

*
dare darent
plain form

preterite neutral preterite negative dare


past participle
dared *
dared

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 25 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

The modal need is different again. The data seem to be:

No one need tell him. [present neutral]


We neednt tell him. [present negative]
No one needed tell him before. [no preterite negative]
We needednt tell him before. [no preterite negative]
Not needing tell him, we left. [no gerund-participle]
I thought no one would need tell him. [plain form]
No one has needed tell him yet. [no past participle]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 26 / 163


English verb inflection: AUXILIARY VERBS

So the paradigm seems to be this:

PRIMARY SECONDARY
present neutral present negative gerund-participle

*
need neednt
plain form

preterite neutral preterite negative need


past participle
* *
*

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 27 / 163


Lexical and auxiliary verbs

Certain special properties, the NICE properties, distinguish lexical


from auxiliary verbs:

N Special Negation syntax, preceding clause-negating not


(He is not in), and special negation morphology with the nt suffix
(He isnt in).

I Special Initial (Inverted) position in independent polar


interrogatives (etc.): Do you love me?

C Special Code interpretation: Complement Omission Denotes


Ellipsis (Yes, you are [ ])

E Special Emphasis phonology heavy stress signals polarity


emphasis (But you cn help!)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 28 / 163


Lexical and auxiliary verbs

The NICE properties are found with certain non-core uses of


auxiliaries. Illustrating just with inversion:

Is he [PP in? ]
Have you [NP any idea? ]
Would you rather [Clause I didnt come? ]

The underlined verb is not helping any main-clause lexical verb.

These items invert, but take PP or NP or full tensed Clause


complements (bracketed).

If the underlined words are in Aux, what is head of VP?

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 29 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis
What is a catenative complement?

VP-internal
subjectless
non-finite
clausal complement
not an object
not predicative
not ascriptive
not specificational
allows arbitrary chaining

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 30 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

VP
PPP
 P
V VP
PPP
 P
might V VP
PPP
 P
have V VP
PP

 P
P
helped V VP
HH
 H
avoid V AdjP
ZZ
seeming foolish

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 31 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

VP VP
 
  
 
V VP V VP
 
   
ought to be qualified thought to be qualified

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 32 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

As with lexical verbs, some auxiliary verbs take a bare infinitival


complement and some take a to-infinitival:

taking bare infinitival taking to-infinitival


lexical have; hear ; help; let; dare; hope; like; need;
make; see . . . seem; try ; want . . .
auxiliary can; dare; do; may ; is (modal use); ought
must; need; shall; will

Note also these idiomatic combinations:

be + going and BrE have + got: to-infinitival


had + better and would + rather / sooner / as soon: bare infinitival

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 33 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

The catenative-auxiliary analysis claims the auxiliaries are all verbs


and there is one clause per verb. Each clause can be separately
negated:

NEGATED :
I have always taken bribes from lobbyists. Neither.
I have not always taken bribes from lobbyists. Have.
I have always not taken bribes from lobbyists. Take.
I have not always not taken bribes from lobbyists. Both.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 34 / 163


The Catenative-Auxiliary analysis

The old dependent-auxiliary analysis, where auxiliaries are little


non-verbal markers prefixed to the verb in a clause, has no explanation
for negation facts such as those just illustrated.

Nor can it handle various other facts to do with temporal specification


and constituent structure.

On this topic, read CGEL Ch 3, pp. 12141220.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 35 / 163


Nouns, Determinatives, and NPs

Plan for this part of the lecture:

Nouns and their definition

The category of Determinatives

The Determiner function

Prenominal attributive modifiers

Pronouns, and why they are really nouns

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 36 / 163


Defining nouns
The thing-word caricature

Lowth, A Short Introduction to English Grammar (1762): A noun is


the name of any thing conceived to subsist, or of which we have
any notion

Murray, English Grammar (1795): A noun is the name of any


thing that exists, or of which we have any notion

Curme, English Grammar (1925): A noun . . . is the name of a


living being or lifeless thing

Garner, in The Chicago Manual of Style, 15th edition (2003): A


noun is a word that names something

250 years of saying the same old same old!

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 37 / 163


Defining nouns
What the general public thinks today

I got through 12 years of state funded schooling with the sum total of
my grammatical knowledge being Nouns are thing words, verbs are
doing words, and adjectives are describing words. I suspect we never
covered adverbs.
John Wilkins, on his blog
Evolving Thoughts (14 June 2008)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 38 / 163


Defining nouns: history without evolution

We declared war on terror. We declared war on terror its not even a


noun, so, good luck. After we defeat it, Im sure well take on that
bastard ennui.
Jon Stewart, in a graduation address
at the College of William and Mary

I think uh the con th... the phrase the war on terror uh as...
as if there could be a war on an adjective, I mean its its just or an
adverb it doesnt really work.
Stefan Halper, Senior Fellow at the Carnegie Council on Ethics and
International Affairs in New York, interviewed on radio WHYY

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 39 / 163


Defining nouns
They dont all denote things

fire: process of combustion (rapid oxidation)


absence: not being there
emptiness: nothing being there
failure: not managing to
lack : failing to be provided when needed
method: how (by what means) something is done
assistance: being there with supportive actions

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 40 / 163


Defining nouns
They dont all denote things

fire: process of combustion (rapid oxidation)


absence: not being there
emptiness: nothing being there
failure: not managing to
lack : failing to be provided when needed
method: how (by what means) something is done
assistance: being there with supportive actions

We dont get our definition of Noun from metaphysics;


we get our metaphysics from the use of our nouns.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 40 / 163


Nouns
What they do have in common

Four inflectional forms: singular and plural plain case singular


and plural genitive case

Serve as heads of NPs with functions like Subject, Object,


Predicative Complement, Complement of Preposition

Preceded by determinatives like the or a(n)

Modified by (preceding) adjectives like big

Modified by (following) relative clause modifiers like


who I didnt recognize

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 41 / 163


Nouns
An irregular lexeme with full paradigm

Inflectional forms of child


PLAIN GENITIVE
SINGULAR child childs
PLURAL children childrens

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 42 / 163


Nouns
An irregular lexeme with full paradigm

Inflectional forms of child


PLAIN GENITIVE
SINGULAR child childs
PLURAL children childrens

Phonologically, regular nouns are only half as complex:

Inflectional forms of dog

PLAIN GENITIVE
SINGULAR /dag/
PLURAL /dagz/

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 42 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

The qualifies a noun definition of Adjective leads all dictionaries to


include among the adjectives:

(i) both the articles (the, a(n)

(ii) both demonstratives (this, that)

(iii) all quantifiers (all, some, most, several, . . . )

(iv) all numerals (one, two, . . . , 243, . . . )

(v) the dependent genitive forms of pronouns (my , your , . . . )

Treating these as Adjectives makes a complete hash of the syntactic


properties of that category.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 43 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

The proposal defended here (and in CGEL):

Determinative is a category of words (like Noun or Preposition),


distinct (but not disjoint) from Adjective, containing about 35 basic
items plus all the numerals.

Determiner is a function (like Subject or Head).

Determinatives often (but not always) serve as Determiner.

The Determiner function is often (but not always) filled by a


Determinative.

Genitive NPs can also serve in Determiner function.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 44 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

A Grammar of Spoken English (Harold Palmer and F. G. Blandford,


1939) cites some criteria for distinguishing adjectives from a class of
determinatives (Fr. adjectifs dterminatifs) from the class of
adjectives:

(a) Determinatives cannot be used predicatively.

Alert residents objected. The residents were alert.

All residents objected. 6 *The residents were all.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 45 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

(b) Determinatives only rarely express grade (comparison).

Those who succeeded were more motivated than the others.

*Those who succeeded were more most than the others.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 46 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

(b) Determinatives only rarely express grade (comparison).

Those who succeeded were more motivated than the others.

*Those who succeeded were more most than the others.

(c) Determinatives only rarely take modifiers, and in particular do not


take intensifying modifiers.

[Very alert] residents objected.

*[Very all] residents objected.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 46 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

Four more reliable criteria also distinguish Adjectives from


Determinatives:

(d) Determinatives do not stack, or even (for the most part) co-occur
in NP structure.

Responsible, alert, intelligent residents helped out.

*These, the, all residents helped out.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 47 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

(e) Adding a Determinative can make a singular count noun into a


grammatical NP but adding an adjective cannot:

I heard [NP this guy] was asking about me.

*I heard [NP thin guy] was asking about me.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 48 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

(f) Most Determinatives occur in the fused determiner-head


construction, where a Determinative serves as Determiner and
Head simultaneously and thus constitutes a whole NP. No
adjective does this.

Id like to hear more about [NP this].

*Id like to hear more about [NP thin].

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 49 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

One further minor point is that there is a phonological condition


sufficient to guarantee non-adjectivehood:

(h) Adjectives can never begin with phonological //, but


determinatives can, and some do (that, the, this).

As a result of a historical accident, initial // is never found in Nouns,


Verbs, or Adjectives.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 50 / 163


Determinatives as a distinct category

There are about 35 basic Determinatives:

a(n) a few a little all + another


any both certain+ each either
enough every few + little + many
much neither no one + said +
several some such+ sufficient + that
the this various+ we + whatever +
whatsoever + what + whichever which+ you +

Words with superscript + belong to other categories as well.


Words in boldface italics have varying inflectional forms.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 51 / 163


The Determiner function

The Determiner of an NP is intuitively an initial subconstituent that


fixes certain properties like definiteness and quantification and make it
fit for use semantically as an argument.

In semantic terms, a Determiner combines with the property


denotation of a nominal expression to form a full NP meaning (a
generalized quantifier, under many accounts).

The Determiner function in English is filled by either a Determinative


(this house) or an NP in the genitive case (the presidents house).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 52 / 163


The Determiner function

The Determiner of an NP is intuitively an initial subconstituent that


fixes certain properties like definiteness and quantification and make it
fit for use semantically as an argument.

In semantic terms, a Determiner combines with the property


denotation of a nominal expression to form a full NP meaning (a
generalized quantifier, under many accounts).

The Determiner function in English is filled by either a Determinative


(this house) or an NP in the genitive case (the presidents house).

What does Specifier mean in post-1970 transformational grammar?


Not clear. But probably Determiner i.e., its regarded as a function,
not a category, and certainly not a lexical category.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 52 / 163


The DP Hypothesis
The DP Hypothesis is not merely that some phrases have D as Head.
CGEL agrees that there are phrases with D as Head such as hardly
any , just about all, almost every :

NP

 
Det: Head:
DP Nom

 
Mod: Head: Head:
AdvP D N

Head: any onions


Adv

hardly

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 53 / 163


The DP Hypothesis
The DP Hypothesis is not merely that some phrases have D as Head.
CGEL agrees that there are phrases with D as Head such as hardly
any , just about all, almost every :
NP

 
Det: Head:
DP Nom
 
   
Mod: Head: Mod: Head:
AdvP D AdjP Nom

 
Mod: Head: all Head: Head:
AdvP Adv Adj N

Head: about civilized societies


Adv

just
Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 54 / 163
The DP Hypothesis

But the DP hypothesis is not that some phrases have D as Head; it is


that phrases like the archbishop and this bicycle have the D as
Head.

In a phrase like the king of France, it is claimed that the is the Head.
The rest of the phrase, king of France, is a dependent, specifically a
Complement.

Once informally proposed by John Lyons, the DP Hypothesis was


revived in 1987 in the MIT doctoral dissertation of Steven Abney.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 55 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

English allows pre-head modification of nouns by adjuncts of various


categorial types:

Adjective Phrase (AdjP):


those nice new green sandals you bought

Nominal (Nom, i.e. N): a labor union organizer

Gerund-participial Verb Phrase (VPGPL ):


several quietly sleeping children

Past-participial Verb Phrase (VPPPL ):


the universitys hastily developed pay reduction plan

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 56 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

With the ordering of attributive modifiers we find a phenomenon that


appears to be syntactic at first but is, I think, truly semantic through
and through or at least, sensitive to both semantic and syntactic
properties.

For example, in nice new green sandals it seems hard to reorder any
of the adjectives:

nice new green sandals


?? nice green new sandals
?? new nice green sandals
?? new green nice sandals
?? green nice new sandals
?? green new nice sandals

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 57 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

One suggested operational semantics for the ?? prefix would be


profoundly unlikely to get more than a tiny handful of non-spurious
Google hits.

For example: 100 instances of friendly little white + Noun can be found
using Google; but for ?? little white friendly , only 10 hits, most spurious.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 58 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

The conditions on sequencing of attributive modifiers are not strict like


the condition that says the Determiner precedes the Head. They are
labile constraints: violating them creates special effects, or lowers
acceptability, but does not clearly mark the result as not being English.

Early modifiers (determinatives such as numerals; superlative


adjectives; ordinal adjectives; primacy adjectives) have a strong
tendency to precede residual modifiers (all others):

the two vital facts [D + residual]


the largest known meteorite [sup + residual]
the second abortive attempt [ord + residual]
a key new proposal [prim + residual]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 59 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

And within the residual modifiers, there is a weaker tendency to adhere


to an order like this:
evaluative modifiers before
general modifiers before
age modifiers before
color modifiers before
provenance modifiers before
manufacture modifiers before
type modifiers
CGEL cites this NP:

an attractive tight-fitting new pink Italian lycra womens swimsuit

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 60 / 163


Attributive Modifiers

Shifting any modifier leftward in its sequence tends to suggest it is


being used contrastively with the following constituent presupposed:

pink Italian swimsuit if Italian swimsuits are under discussion;

Italian pink swimsuit if pink swimsuits are under discussion.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 61 / 163


Pronouns and determinatives

The inflectional paradigms of the personal pronoun lexemes

NOM ACC DEP GEN IND GEN REFL


I me my mine myself
you your yours yourself
he him his himself
she her hers herself
it its itself
we us our ours ourselves
you your yours ourselves
they them their theirs themselves

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 62 / 163


Pronouns and determinatives

A small overlap: there are two personal determinatives.

PRONOUN USES DETERMINATIVE USES


I do all right. *I man do all right.
You do all right. *You man do all right.
He does all right. *He man does all right.
She does all right. *She woman does all right.
It does all right. *It puppy does all right.
We do all right. We men do all right. both OK
You do all right. You men do all right. both OK
They do all right. *They men do all right.
*The do all right. The women do all right.
*A does all right. A linguist does all right.
*Every do all right. Every puppy does all right.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 63 / 163


Adjectives, Adverbs, their phrases, and their functions

Plan for this part of the lecture

The disastrous function / category confusion

The functions served by adjective phrases

Criteria for identifying adjectives

Criteria for identifying adverbs

A note on zero-derived adverbs in non-standard dialects

The Categorial Exclusivity assumption

The Adjective-Adverb Identity thesis

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 64 / 163


The function / category confusion

For two hundred years or more the following two notions have been
persistently confused in discussions of English grammar:

What kind of constituent is this? category

What role does this constituent play? function

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 65 / 163


The function / category confusion

For two hundred years or more the following two notions have been
persistently confused in discussions of English grammar:

What kind of constituent is this? category

What role does this constituent play? function

Category can be listed (for words) in a dictionary: it is independent of


the syntax of any particular sentence.

Function is not, and cannot be, a lexical property. It is entirely relative


to the syntax of some particular expression.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 65 / 163


The function / category confusion

Just to make sure the disastrous confusion continues for another


hundred years or so, the Merriam-Webster dictionaries actually use
the term function for (lexical) category!

Main Entry: 1 pig

Pronunciation: pig
Function: noun
Inflected Form: -s
Usage: often attributive
Etymology: Middle English pigge
1 : a young swine of either sex that has not
reached sexual maturity; broadly : a wild or
domestic swine see HOG 1a . . .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 66 / 163


The function / category confusion

Just to make sure the disastrous confusion continues for another


hundred years or so, the Merriam-Webster dictionaries actually use
the term function for (lexical) category!

Main Entry: 1 pig

Pronunciation: pig
Function:Category!! noun
Inflected Form: -s
Usage: often attributive
Etymology: Middle English pigge
1 : a young swine of either sex that has not
reached sexual maturity; broadly : a wild or
domestic swine see HOG 1a . . .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 67 / 163


The functions of adjectives and AdjPs

Adj serves, of course, as Head of AdjP. (When nothing hangs on it we


often say adjective when strictly we mean AdjP.)

The two most important functions in which AdjPs serve are:

1. Attributive Modifier in the structure of NP (n.b.: stackable):

[NP those [Nom totally stupid [Nom red [Nom pants ] ] ] ]

2. Predicative Complement in the structure of VP:

Those pants [VP look really stupid ]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 68 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases and AdjPs

There are a few less significant functions of AdjP:

Postpositive Modifier in the structure of NP:

Id never seen [NP anything so stupid ]

External Modifier in the structure of indefinite NP:

Id never seen [NP so stupid a [Nom pair of pants ]]

(Marginally, perhaps also Subject function: Totally stupid was my main


impression.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 69 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases

Traditional grammar crucially fails to recognize that

occurrence as Attributive 6= membership in Adj

In the same spirit as the thing word definition of Noun, traditional


grammarians define adjective as a word that modifies or qualifies or
adds to the meaning of a noun.
This is vague, semantically-tinged function talk. As a definition, it is
hopeless.
Consider: The good die young.
Two adjectives, no nouns. Modifying a noun is not necessary.
But as we shall see, it is also not sufficient.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 70 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases
Dictionaries often list various nouns with Adj as a second category.
Merriam-Webster is typical:

Main Entry: 2 head

Pronunciation: hed
Function:Category!! adjective
Etymology: Middle English heved, hed, from
heved, hed, n.
1 : of, relating to, or for a head or the head
2 : PRINCIPAL, CHIEF, LEADING, FIRST hhead choristeri
hhead cooki
3 : situated at the head hhead wall* hhead sailsi
4 : coming from in front : meeting the head as it is
moved forward hhead seai hhead tidei

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 71 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases

Consider the modifiers in NPs like Alaska residents, Beatles


recordings, California girls, Dell laptops, Edinburgh weather . . .

If serving in Attributive Modifier function is sufficient to determine


adjectivehood, then the Adjective category will have to include
all place names in the world (Sheffield steel)
every company name (IBM stock , Toyota truck )
every number name (their prestigious 10025 zipcode)
every name of a chemical element or other substance (aluminium
foil, gold ring, oil painting, plutonium bomb)
every plant name (mahogany table, grass verge) . . .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 72 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases

Under the traditional view the list of adjectives will never end.

Adjective will be an open category, even larger than Noun.

And there will be no distinction in grammatical properties between the


two.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 73 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases
M-W is cautious in defining adjective, claiming only typicality, not
criteriality:

. . . typically used as a modifier of a noun to denote a


quality of the thing named . . .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 74 / 163


The functions of adjective phrases
M-W is cautious in defining adjective, claiming only typicality, not
criteriality:

. . . typically used as a modifier of a noun to denote a


quality of the thing named . . .

But amusingly, M-W also has an entry for adjective as an adjective!


The primary sense given is:

being an adjective han adjective wordi : functioning as an ad-


jective han adjective clausei : fitting or suitable to an adjective
hadjective uses of nounsi hadjective inflectionsi

A classic confusion over what adjective means, in a dictionary entry


where adjective is wrongly analysed as an adjective!

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 74 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

How do we define adjective, if not by reference to the function


Attributive Modifier?

In any language, the adjectives (if there are any) are a grammatically
distinct class of words including the simplest and most direct ways of
denoting one-dimensional and stative properties such as being
good, bad, large, small, new, old, black, white, etc.

But that is applicable only in universal grammar.

In English we can, and must, be more specific.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 75 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

Adjectives usually denote static and gradable properties, and


many basic ones inflect for grade (old, older , oldest).

Uninflectable adjectives, if gradable, express grade with pre-Head


more and most.

No adjectives show agreement for person or number.

Adverbs function as pre-head Modifiers of Adjectives (unusually


intelligent, insanely great).

Typical AdjPs can serve as both Attributive Modifier (big boy ) and
Predicative Complement (looks big).

The Complements that Adjectives select are typically PP or


Clause almost never NP.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 76 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

AdjP can serve as Adjuncts (i.e., Modifiers or Supplements).

When such an Adjunct is fronted, it requires a target of predication.

If no such target is available, we get the dangling modifier effect


useful for diagnosing adjectives:

Away is a Preposition but afraid is an Adjective:

Away from home, John behaved properly. [no target needed]


Afraid of us, John behaved properly. [target is John]
Away from home, there was just work. [target unneeded]
Afraid of us, there was just work. [BAD NO TARGET]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 77 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

The predicativity test is also useful in distinguishing adjectives from


adverbs. The general principle is: Prepositions and Adverbs always
have some uses as non-predicative modifiers; adjectives never
do.

Again is an Adverb. Awake is an Adjective.

Again, we scarcely knew what to do. [no target needed]


Awake, we scarcely knew what to do. [target is we]
Again, it snowed heavily. [target unneeded]
Awake, it snowed heavily. [BAD NO TARGET]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 78 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

The strange adjective worth

Does not inflect for grade (despite being short).

Can never be used attributively.

Selects an NP complement, not PP.

The complement is obligatory.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 79 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

The strange adjective worth

Compare with the typical adjective worthy :

The lexeme worth The lexeme worthy

worth, *worther , *worthest worthy , worthier , worthiest

*Its a worth project. Its a worthy project.


It was worth my time. *It was worthy my time.
*It was worth of my time. It was worthy of my time.

*It is certainly worth. It is certainly worthy.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 80 / 163


Criteria for adjectivehood

The words due, like, near , opposite, and unlike are also puzzling, with
a complex mix of Adjective and Preposition properties. But arguments
can be given that

due and opposite were adjectives but have evolved into


prepositions;

like and unlike are sometimes prepositions and sometimes


adjectives with NP or Clause complements;

near may be dually categorized, but is probably prepositional


(though it inflects for grade!).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 81 / 163


And now...

Adverbs

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 82 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

VP modification may be expressed by NP, PP, or AdvP:

Modifier type NP PP AdvP


L OCATIVE next door in the USA locally
T EMPORAL (next) Monday on Monday soon
D URATIVE a long time for ages lengthily
M ANNER the same way in haste hastily

Modifying a verb is therefore virtually useless as a criterion for


membership in the Adverb category. Yet it is the sole criterion
traditional grammars generally give.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 83 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

Adverb is a heterogeneous category in the languages that have it. The


adverbs include expressions for
additive and restrictive focusing (also, even, only ),
degree (very , really , nearly ),
aspectuality (still, already , yet),
seriality (again),
connection (however , therefore, thus),
frequency (always, never , often),
modality (perhaps, probably , certainly ),
time (later , soon, recently ),
manner (quickly , easily , better ),
and other semantic categories.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 84 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

English has a modest number of basic, underived adverbs:

again, almost, already , also, always, anyway , as, even, ever ,


how, however , indeed, just, long, maybe, never , often, only ,
otherwise, perhaps, please, quite, rather , sometimes, soon, still,
therefore, though, thus, too, very , well, yet

A few (early , hard, ill, late, right, well, . . . ) are formed from adjectives
by zero derivation (sometimes with a meaning change). But the vast
majority are derived by suffixation of ly .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 85 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

But being derived by the ly suffix is not a criterion for adverbhood.


Many adjectives are derived from nouns by means of the same suffix:

beastly , brother ly , cowardly , curmudgeonly , deathly ,


father ly , friendly , kingly , mother ly , musicianly , painter ly ,
princely , queenly , sister ly , sprightly

And there are other ly adjectives like kindly and lively .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 86 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

Jackendoff, in X Syntax (1977), suggested a key distinction between


adjectives and adverbs:

Jackendoffs complementability criterion


Adjectives take complements; adverbs do not.

Jackendoffs claim is not true.

Jackendoff may have been misled by the small size of the classes of
complement-taking adverbs.

There are several of such classes. They take the same complements
as the related adjectives.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 87 / 163


Criteria for adverbhood

A few examples of complement-taking adverbs (from the WSJ corpus)


operates [AdvP quite [Adv separately ] [PP from the rest of the
company ] ]

the lower portion could move [AdvP [Adv independently ]


[PP of the upper part ] ]

[AdvP [Adv luckily ] [PP for them, ] ] Mr. Keswick decided not to call
their bluff

it will be treated [AdvP no [Adv differently ] [PP from more permanent


trade developments ] ]

an unregulated concern that operated [AdvP [Adv similarly to a bank


trust department ] ]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 88 / 163


A note on non-standard zero-derived adverbs

It is well known that many non-standard dialects use words with


adjectival form in adverb roles. Some song lines:

! Love me tender [Ken Darby; attributed to Presley & Matson]

! Treat me nice [Leiber & Stoller]

! Hurts so bad [Randazzo, Wilding & Hart]

! my love does it good [McCartney]

It is commonly thought that this indicates confusion of adjectives and


adverbs. Not true, I believe.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 89 / 163


A note on non-standard zero-derived adverbs

What is involved seems to be merely a slight broadening of the class of


zero-derived adverbs in English mentioned above: early , hard, right,
etc.

And (I believe) even in the dialects that have a broader class of such
adverbs, the zero-derived ones are not used as pre-head modifiers:

! Drive real carefully now! ! Drive real careful now!


! She carefully drug it outside. *! She careful drug it outside.

(Sociolinguists: Is this claim correct? Can it be verified from actual


records of non-standard English conversation?)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 90 / 163


The categorial exclusivity claim

There is a long history of traditional grammarians and modern linguists


stating this generalization for Standard English:

The categorial exclusivity claim


Adjectives modify nouns; adverbs modify non-nouns.

Almost any reference work at random any English grammar,


dictionary, or terminology guide will repeat this statement.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 91 / 163


The categorial exclusivity claim

On this view, adjectives and adverbs (in Standard English) do not


overlap in function:

adjective modifier adverb modifier


modifying a noun a nice man *a nicely man
modifying a verb *she sings nice she sings nicely

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 92 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Given the exclusivity claim, an obvious hypothesis arises.

John Lyons proposed it in 1966: that adverbs are merely


positional variants of the corresponding adjectives.

A decade later Joseph Emonds (1976, 1213) suggested the same


thing: that the adverbs formed with ly are simply adjectives in a
verb-modifying rather than a noun-modifying function.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 93 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Andrew Radford (1988) suggests the term advective for the A


category.

And Ingo Plag (2003, p. 196) explicitly asserts that ly is an inflectional


suffix occurring on just those occurrences of adjectives that do not
modify nouns.

Mark Baker (2003, 230257) makes the radical proposal that there are
only three universal categories: N, V, and A. N must refer; V must
assign thematic roles to N; and A must occur only where neither N or V
can.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 94 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

But it is not in fact true that an adverb can act as Modifier of a category
if and only if an adjective cannot.

We begin by setting aside two distractors.

First, ignore the sky above, the weather outside, the room
downstairs.

Traditionally these would be adverbs modifying nouns. (Henry Sweet


noted this.)

But in fact overwhelming evidence shows that the underlined words


are prepositions (claim to be justified later).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 95 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Second, ignore hardly anyone, precisely nothing, almost everybody .

These would appear to have adverbs modifying nouns if


(i) pronouns are a special kind of noun, and
(ii) anyone, nothing, and everybody are pronouns.

But CGEL rejects (ii).

CGEL holds that anyone, nothing, everybody , etc., are compound


determinatives.

And it is normal for determinatives to take adverbs as modifiers.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 96 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Harder to set aside are cases that appear to have adjectives


modifying other adjectives, where modification by the related
adverbs either expresses a different sense or is unacceptable.

ADJECTIVE MODIFIER SEMANTICALLY DISTINCT ADVERB


cold sober 6= coldly sober
plain stupid 6 = plainly stupid
bloody good 6= bloodily good
silky smooth 6= silkily smooth

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 97 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

And here the adverb versions seem outright unacceptable:

ADJECTIVE MODIFIER UNACCEPTABLE ADVERB


blind drunk 6= ?blindly drunk
filthy rich 6 = ?filthily rich
pretty cruel 6 = ?prettily cruel
black British 6 = ?blackly British

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 98 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Another context in which both adjectives and adverbs occur is in the


complement of the copula:

ASCRIPTIVE COMPLEMENT :
The way she dressed was elegant.
( She elegantly performed the act of dressing herself.)

SPECIFYING COMPLEMENT
The way she dressed was elegantly.
( Her dress was elegant in style.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 99 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

ASCRIPTIVE COMPLEMENT
It was rude that she spoke to me.
( The fact of her speaking to me constituted rudeness.)

SPECIFYING COMPLEMENT
It was rudely that she spoke to me.
( She spoke to me in a rude manner.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 100 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

ASCRIPTIVE COMPLEMENT
It was rude that she spoke to me.
( The fact of her speaking to me constituted rudeness.)

SPECIFYING COMPLEMENT
It was rudely that she spoke to me.
( She spoke to me in a rude manner.)

ASCRIPTIVE COMPLEMENT
It was clever that they used flashbacks.
( Using flashbacks was a clever idea.)

SPECIFYING COMPLEMENT
It was cleverly that they used flashbacks.
( They used flashbacks in a clever way.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 100 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

But the really convincing evidence comes from a construction


mentioned briefly in Huddleston & Pullum, A Students Introduction to
English Grammar (2005, 123n not covered in CGEL).

Adverbs (or AdvPs) can postmodify nouns in NPs:

I express my profound disappointment at [NP the governments


refusal yet again to take the high road and bring forth a motion to
allow parliament to sit in committee of the whole.]

Yet again isnt modifying take the high road; its modifying the noun
refusal: the government has yet again refused. This is an AdvP
modifying a noun.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 101 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Other examples:

[NP The NHS and other health organisations internationally] clearly


need methodologies to support benefit analysis of merging healthcare
organisations.

[NP The unique role globally of the Australian Health Promoting Schools
Association, as a non-government organization specifically established
to promote the concept of the health promoting school,] is described.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 102 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

Other attested examples:

the winner recently of both a Gramophone award and the Royal


Philharmonic Society Award for Best Chamber Ensemble

the people locally

the weather recently

the centerpiece visually of the film

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 103 / 163


The AdjectiveAdverb identity thesis

The bottom line:

AdjectiveAdverb Identity is false


It is impossible to sustain the categorial identity claim for the
Adjective and Adverb categories.

Categorial Exclusivity is false


Not even the claim that the sets of modified constituents are
mutually exclusive for Adjective and Adverb can be sustained.

Whatever the facts may be for some other languages, Adj and Adv are
two quite distinct categories in Standard English.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 104 / 163


Prepositions, Particles, and Subordinators

Plan for this part of the lecture

Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles:


The Jespersen/Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments

Subordinating conjunctions as prepositions:


The Hunter/Jespersen/Geis thesis

The CGEL category of Subordinators

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 105 / 163


Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles

What is the lexical category of words such as in, up, and down ?

Every dictionary of English gives the wrong answer.

All say Preposition (prep) and Adverb (adv), and give them separate
entries despite copious semantic overlap.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 106 / 163


Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles

The relevant dictionary entries for down (ignoring the noun meaning
soft feathers and the verb meaning defeat, drink, etc.) tend to say
this sort of thing:

down adv 1 a from a higher point to or toward the ground or base; b


from a higher to a lower position; 2 in a direction conventionally the
opposite of up . . .

down prep 1 a in a descending direction along; b from a higher to a


lower position upon or within; 2 in a direction conventionally the
opposite of up . . .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 107 / 163


Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles

CGEL claims that in, on, off , up, down, round, through, etc., are never
adverbs.

Consider how implausible the traditional claim actually is.

It says that these words are adverbs, despite the fact that

(i) they are not derived from adjective stems like most adverbs;

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 108 / 163


Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles

CGEL claims that in, on, off , up, down, round, through, etc., are never
adverbs.

Consider how implausible the traditional claim actually is.

It says that these words are adverbs, despite the fact that

(i) they are not derived from adjective stems like most adverbs;

(ii) they are all homophonous with specific prepositions; and

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 108 / 163


Prepositions, Adverbs, and Particles

CGEL claims that in, on, off , up, down, round, through, etc., are never
adverbs.

Consider how implausible the traditional claim actually is.

It says that these words are adverbs, despite the fact that

(i) they are not derived from adjective stems like most adverbs;

(ii) they are all homophonous with specific prepositions; and

(iii) they are synonymous with those homophonous prepositions.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 108 / 163


A syntactic argument against the traditonal view

What is more, these words do not perform the usual modifying


functions of adverbs:
He was bleeding internally.
*He was bleeding in.

She was upwardly mobile.


*She was up mobile.

Mike fell immediately.


Mike fell down.
Mike immediately fell.
*Mike down fell.

These are adverbs without the properties of adverbs!

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 109 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments

Several relevant syntactic arguments were given in a classic article of


the classical transformational era (citing earlier observations by
Edward Klima and Bruce Fraser):

Joseph E. Emonds (1972), Evidence that indirect object


movement is a structure-preserving rule.
Foundations of Language 8: 546561.
Reprinted 1973 in Gross, Halle & Schtzenberger (eds.),
The Formal Analysis of Natural Languages (Mouton).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 110 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments

1. Subcategorization of intransitives
Some intransitive verbs like glance and dart syntactically select a
directional phrase as an obligatory complement:

The lizard darted into that hole.


The lizard darted.

These so-called adverbs can fill that complement role:

The lizard darted in.

But in general adverbs cannot:


The lizard darted immediately.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 111 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments

2. Subcategorization of transitives
Certain transitive verbs like put and sneak select a directional phrase
as obligatory second complement:

Well have to sneak some beer into the dorm.


Well have to sneak some beer.

These so-called adverbs can fill in that complement role:

Well have to sneak some beer in.

But in general adverbs cannot:

Well have to sneak the beer quietly.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 112 / 163


Interim conclusion

Conclusion from arguments 1 and 2:

in and similar words are not adverbs.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 113 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments

3. Into the bin with it etc. These constructions involve a directional


PP (underlined) followed by a with-headed PP:

Into the bin with it!


Up the stairs with you!

Some so-called adverbs can also occur as the directional, but


adverbs in general cannot:

Down with capitalist greed!


Out with the old, in with the new.
*Fiercely with capitalist greed!
*Slowly with the old, immediately with the new.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 114 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments
4. Fronted directional PPs with verbs of motion
Directional PPs switch with subjects of verbs of motion:

The terrified townspeople ran into the church.

Into the church ran the terrified townspeople.

The same alternation is found with the so-called adverbs, but not with
adverbs in general:

The terrified townspeople ran in.

In ran the terrified townspeople.

The terrified townspeople ran immediately.


Immediately ran the terrified townspeople.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 115 / 163


The Klima/Fraser/Emonds arguments
5. Modification with right
Certain items such as right, straight, and bang occur in modern
Standard English as pre-head modifiers only with prepositions:
There is a McDonalds right dominating the square.
There is a McDonalds right the same place.
There is a McDonalds right local.
There is a McDonalds right locally.

There is a McDonalds right on our doorstep.

Yet sentences like these are fine:

She leaned over and fell right in.


The price went right down the next day.
Does this road go right through?

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 116 / 163


Interim conclusion

Conclusion from arguments 3, 4, and 5:

in and similar words head preposition phrases (PPs).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 117 / 163


An additional argument

6. In and out
The traditional analysis has to put in and out, counterintuitively, in
entirely different categories:

It looks like were in luck. [in + NP]


It looks like were out luck. [*out + NP]
It looks like were out of luck. [out + PP]

I keep my diamonds in the safe. [in + NP]


I left my diamonds out the safe. [*out + NP]
I left my diamonds out of the safe. [out + PP]

Well be in trouble if he leaves. [in + NP]


Well be out trouble if he leaves. [*out + NP]
Well be out of trouble if he leaves. [out + PP]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 118 / 163


Prepositions that never have NP complements

We can now see that many items are best categorized as prepositions
even though they are strictly intransitive, i.e., they never take NP
complements:

The lizard darted [PP away. ]

Well have to sneak some beer [PP back. ]

Lets hold the meeting [PP right here. ]

Make sure you come [PP straight home. ]

It went [PP right outside. ]

Dear Lord, grant me your precious gift of patience preferably


[PP right now. ]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 119 / 163


Prepositions that never have NP complements

Words like ahead and abroad are prepositions that never take NP
complements, whereas again is an adverb. And it is easy to
demonstrate this:

In 2008 he got arrested again. [Adv at end of VP]


In 2008 he again got arrested. [Adv OK before V]

In 2008 he got arrested abroad. [PP at end of VP]


*In 2008 he abroad got arrested. [PP bad before V]

Conclusion: abroad is not an Adverb.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 120 / 163


Particles

And what of particles, in the sense of the verb-particle construction?

They are light intransitive PPs with special linear positioning


privileges.

PARTICLES NOT PARTICLES


away at (strictly transitive)
back between
down downstream
in indoors
out outside
up upstairs

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 121 / 163


Particles

Plausible structures for a simple verb-particle construction:

VP VP
 
     
V PP NP V NP PP
 

  
 
take P+ the trash take the trash P+

out out

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 122 / 163


The traditional category subordinating conjunction

Traditional grammar recognizes a category of conjunctions divided


into subordinating conjunctions and coordinating conjunctions.

Cogent arguments were presented against the composition of the


former category at least 225 years ago.

John Hunter argued before the Royal Society of Edinburgh in 1784 that
it was not sensible for after to be placed in different categories in these
two examples:

I came after he departed.


I came after his departure.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 123 / 163


The Hunter/Jespersen/Geis thesis

The idea Hunter advocated was argued again by Jespersen 140 years
later (The Philosophy of Grammar, 1924) and again half a century
after that by Michael Geis (MIT Ph.D. dissertation, 1970):

Different verbs take different kinds of complement


(NP complement, Clause complement, no complement, etc.), yet,
Jespersen observes, no one thinks of assigning them to different
parts of speech.

Prepositions should be treated analogously, as subcategorized for


complements of different types.

Dual categorization should be resorted to only when the


grammatical facts require it.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 124 / 163


The Hunter/Jespersen/Geis thesis

Jespersen even finds a sentence in Thackeray where after has a


complement consisting of an NP coordinated with a content clause:
After [ the Baden business and he had dragged off his wife to
Champagne ], the Duke became greatly broken.

CGEL (1327, [15iiib]) cites a better-sounding and more recent attested


case, where the clause comes first:
After [their rubber plantation failed, and
her husbands death on the Upper Rewa in 1885 ], she maintained
her three young children with a tiny store.

Given such examples, dividing after into preposition and conjunction


instances becomes actually impossible.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 125 / 163


Genuine multiple categorization

A word like cosy really does have three lexical entries:

a tea cosy (N) SINGULAR PLURAL


PLAIN cosy cosies
GENITIVE cosys cosies

keep us cosy (Adj) PLAIN COMPARATIVE SUPERLATIVE


cosy cosier cosiest

cosy up to her (V) PLAIN FORM cosy


3 RD SING . PRESENT cosies
PRETERITE , PAST PARTICIPLE cosied
GERUND - PARTICIPLE cosying

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 126 / 163


Spurious multiple categorization

But it is syntactic madness to claim that since belongs to three different


categories, which is what the traditional account does.

Ive loved her ever since [adv ]

Ive loved her ever since our first meeting [prep]

Ive loved her ever since we first met [conj]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 127 / 163


Spurious multiple categorization

Typical dictionary information for since:

since adv
1 : continuously from a time in the past until the present . . .
2 : before the present time
3 : after a time in the past
since prep
1 : in the period after a specified time in the past
2 : continuously from a specified time in the past
since conj
1 : after the time in the past when
2 : up to the present time from the time in the past when
3 : for the reason that; because of the fact that special

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 128 / 163


A better account of since

Rough draft of a more sensible dictionary entry:

since prep
1 continuously from a certain time in the past until the present, the time
being specified by NP complement (empty since March) or Clause
complement (empty since they left) or the context (empty ever since
empty ever since that time).
In older usage, may modify a verb (a wall, since removed), or (espe-
cially if modified by long) may mean simply earlier than the present
(abandoned long since).
2 (with Clause complement only) for the reason that, or because of
the fact that (We must assume it, since there is no other explanation).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 129 / 163


The category of Subordinators

Not all traditional subordinating conjunctions are prepositions.


CGEL posits a small class of subordinators.

a small class (half a dozen items)

markers of syntactic subordination

no independent meaning

often optional or substitutable

never function as Head

(Complementizer is a bad name for these. They dont always form


Complements. Modifiers such as relative clauses are also introduced
by Subordinators.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 130 / 163


Recapitulation

Notice that in these lectures I am rejecting both


the DP hypothesis (that the determinative rather than the nominal
body is Head in the king of France) and
the CP hypothesis (that the subordinator rather than the clausal
body in that nobody cares).

Nouns, Verbs, Adjectives, Adverbs, Prepositions, and Determinatives


head NPs, VPs, AdjPs, AdvPs, PPs, and DPs, respectively (though
the king of France is not a DP).

Subordinators and Coordinators never head phrases at all.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 131 / 163


The category of Subordinators

Declarative clause subordinator: that

default marker of a declarative content clause

has no meaning at all

normally unaccented

usually optional when marking an internal complement, but not


when marking a Subject clause

obligatory in that-relative before Subject gap

never functions as Head (lexical items select tensed or plain form


verbs, but not simply that as subordinator)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 132 / 163


The category of Subordinators

Interrogative clause subordinator: whether

marks a clause as an interrogative content clause

no clear meaning independently of clause interrogativity (?)

can be replaced by if when marking an internal complement, but


not when marking a Subject clause or in the whether or not
exhaustive conditional construction

never functions as Head

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 133 / 163


The category of Subordinators

Other subordinators:

for when initial in infinitival clauses that have subjects for you to do
a thing like that (the word is also a preposition, of course, in other
contexts)

if in extraposed irrealis declarative content clauses, e.g. It would


be great if he were able to join us (compare *If he were able to join
us would be great) but note that conditional if is a preposition

possibly infinitival to also fits in this category (but would be an


anomalous member)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 134 / 163


The category of Subordinators

Nothing is gained by forcing all Subordinators into the P category (as


Emonds 1985 proposes).

But the prepositions traditionally called subordinating conjunctions


(although, because, conditional if , lest, since, though, unless, etc.) are
different from Subordinators:

independent lexical meaning

cannot be omitted or replaced without altering meaning

select complements the way Heads of phrases do

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 135 / 163


The category of Subordinators

These prepositions all differ in complement selection:

OBJECT of - BARE that- PRED NO


NP PP CLAUSE CLAUSE COMP COMP
although + +
at +
because + +
down + +
given + +
lest +
out (+) + +
provided + +
since + + +

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 136 / 163


The category of Subordinators

The difference with Subordinators, if CGEL has it right, is that they


dont select anything. They have no subcategorizational properties,
and take no complements.

They are meaningless markers of subordinate clause status, often


optional, quite idiosyncratic in syntactic behavior.

In X-bar theory terms, they are exceptions to the general principle for
categories in the lexicon: they do not found bar-level projections, they
are never heads.

In The staff were sure that the students were happy, the head of the
underlined complement clause is not that; it is the students were
happy .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 137 / 163


Relative Constructions and Unbounded Dependencies

Plan for this part of the lecture

The typology of subordinate clauses

Types of relative clause

The diversity of wh-phrase uses

Unbounded dependencies

The implausibility of movement

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 138 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

The traditional view (shown here in green to remind you that it is


completely wrong) is that subordinate clauses are of three types:
Nominal or noun clauses: act like nouns can be subjects
and objects
Adjectival or adjective clauses: act like adjectives they
modify nouns
Adverbial or adverb clauses: act like adverbs they modify
verbs

This whole classification is a mistake.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 139 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

First, this is another classification based on function.

As such, it does not separate clauses appropriately.

A clause like that he was guilty can belong either to the nominal
clauses or the adverbial ones:

That he was guilty seemed obvious. [nominal]

I was disappointed that he was guilty. [adverbial]

Why posit two kinds of clause, here rather than two functions
(external complement [= Subject] and internal Complement)?

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 140 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Notice also:

Caroline was late, as she so often is. [adverbial]

Caroline was late, as her car wouldnt start. [adverbial]

Here there are two kinds of clause:


she so often is (structurally incomplete)
her car wouldnt start (structurally complete)

They are traditionally classified the same as adverbial because the


intuitively conceived function is modifying the adjective late.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 141 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Nominal or noun clauses arent like nouns.

They can be subjects, though there are limits:


*Is that he doesnt like you a problem?

They are not (normally) direct objects:


*He denied categorically responsibility.
He denied categorically that he was responsible.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 142 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Nominal or noun clauses arent like nouns.

They are never objects of prepositions:


*I dont approve of that you smoke.

Some verbs take nominal clauses but not nouns:


I used to marvel that he could remember all our names.
*I used to marvel his memory for names.
I wonder whether anyone cares.
*I wonder peoples apathy.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 143 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Adjectival clauses arent like adjectives:

They are never allowed prenominally (*a that I like car ).

They dont take adjective modifiers (*very that I like).

and so on.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 144 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Adjectival clauses arent like adjectives:

They are never allowed prenominally (*a that I like car ).

They dont take adjective modifiers (*very that I like).

and so on.

And adverbial clauses arent clauses at all, but PPs.

Nothing about the traditional classification really works.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 144 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

The right classification of English subordinate clauses:

FINITE SUBORDINATE CLAUSES


content clauses
relative clauses
comparative clauses

NON - FINITE SUBORDINATE CLAUSES


infinitival clauses
participial clauses

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 145 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

FINITE SUBORDINATE CLAUSES


content clauses
declarative interrogative exclamative

relative clauses
wh-relatives th-relatives bare relatives

comparative clauses
scalar inequality scalar equality
non-scalar inequality non-scalar equality

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 146 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

FINITE SUBORDINATE CLAUSES


content clauses
declarative interrogative exclamative

relative clauses
wh-relatives th-relatives bare relatives

comparative clauses
scalar inequality scalar equality
non-scalar inequality non-scalar equality

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 147 / 163


The typology of subordinate clauses

Content clauses illustrated:

declarative content clause


(that) no one had ever told me

interrogative content clause


closed interrogative:
whether anyone could ever survive a trip to Mars
open interrogative:
what surviving a trip to Mars would call for

exclamative content clause


what a great accomplishment it has been

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 148 / 163


The classification of relative clauses

Formal types of relative clauses illustrated:

wh-relative clause:
which they had been invited to [NP ]
to which they had been invited [PP ]

th-relative clause:
that they had been invited to [NP ]

bare relative clause:


they had been invited to [NP ]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 149 / 163


The classification of relative clauses

Relational types of relative clauses

integrated relative clause:


a party which we had been invited to [NP ]
a party to which we had been invited [PP ]

supplementary relative clause:


their party, which we had been invited to [NP ]

cleft relative clause:


It was the anthropology department
whose party we had been invited to [NP ]

fused relative construction:


I protested against what we had been invited to [NP ]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 150 / 163


The classification of relative clauses

Which formal types can instantiate which relational types?

INTEGRATED SUPPLEMENTARY CLEFT FUSED

wh- yes yes yes yes

th- yes (very rare) yes no

bare yes no yes no

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 151 / 163


The diversity of wh-phrase uses

OPEN INTEGR . SUPPL . FUSED


INTERROG . RELATIVE RELATIVE RELATIVE
who X X X ?*
whom X X X
[+hum] whose X X X
[hum] whose X ?
what X X
which X X X
where X X X X
when X X X ?X
how X ?X
why X X ?
while X

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 152 / 163


The diversity of wh-phrase uses

Whose with non-human reference:


open interrogative: I asked whose hinges squeaked.
integrated relative: Oil any door whose hinges squeak.
supplementary relative: ? that door, whose hinges squeaked

fused relative: Oil whose hinges squeak.

What:
open interrogative: I didnt know what he was doing.
integrated relative: the things what he was doing
supplementary relative: his idea, what he had not tested
fused relative: I was suspicious about what he was doing.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 153 / 163


The diversity of wh-phrase uses

Why :
open interrogative: I didnt know why he was yelling.
integrated relative: the reason why he was yelling
supplementary relative: my painful foot, why I was yelling
fused relative: I was suspicious about why he did it.

How:
open interrogative: I didnt know how he would respond.
integrated relative: the way how he would respond
supplementary relative: the usual way, how I do it
fused relative: I was suspicious about how he did it.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 154 / 163


Unbounded dependencies: syntactic structure

The structure of We are deeply indebted to him:


Clause


 

Subj: Head:
NP VP

 
we Head: Comp:
V AdjP


 

are Adjunct: Head:
Adv AdjP


 

deeply Head: Comp:
Adj PP

 
indebted Head: Comp:
P NP

to him

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 155 / 163


Representing grammatical structure
The structure of Him, we are deeply indebted to :
Clause

 
Prenucleus: Nucleus:
NP Clause


 

him Subj: Head:
NP VP

 
we Head: Comp:
V AdjP


 

are Adjunct: Head:
Adv AdjP


 

deeply Head: Comp:
Adj PP


 

indebted Head: Comp:
P NP

to

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 156 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

A hypothesis about plain vanilla unbounded dependencies:

When the path is all Head and Comp links, unbounded dependencies
are always entirely grammatical.

When Adjunct interrupts the path, the result is always somewhat


ungrammatical.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 157 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine the FBI looked at .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks the FBI looked at .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks shell say the FBI
looked at .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks shell say the FBI
looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks shell say we told them
the FBI looked at .

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Unbounded dependencies

How many paths are there to describe?


How far from the fronted complement (e.g., what)
can the stranded preposition be, in grammatical sentences?
I dont know what the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks the FBI looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks shell say the FBI
looked at .
I dont know what you imagine he thinks shell say we told them
the FBI looked at .
Clearly there is no grammatically fixed limit.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 158 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

We can use a description language based on symbolic logic to express


statements about the structure of trees directly.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 159 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

We can use a description language based on symbolic logic to express


statements about the structure of trees directly.

(x, y )[Clause(x) VP(y )]


There is a point labeled Clause and a point labeled VP in the tree.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 159 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

We can use a description language based on symbolic logic to express


statements about the structure of trees directly.

(x, y )[Clause(x) VP(y )]


There is a point labeled Clause and a point labeled VP in the tree.

(x)[Clause(x) (y )[(y < x)]]


There is a point labeled Clause right at the top of the tree.
(Note: y < x means that y is immediately above x and linked to it.)

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 159 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

We can use a description language based on symbolic logic to express


statements about the structure of trees directly.

(x, y )[Clause(x) VP(y )]


There is a point labeled Clause and a point labeled VP in the tree.

(x)[Clause(x) (y )[(y < x)]]


There is a point labeled Clause right at the top of the tree.
(Note: y < x means that y is immediately above x and linked to it.)

(x, y , z)[((z < x) (z < y ) (x 6= y ) (NP(x)) (VP(y ))) (x y )]]

An NP node (x) precedes a VP node (y ) if they are both immediately


under some third node (z).

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 159 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

In a more expressive type of language known as monadic


second-order logic (MSO) we can also say things like this:

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 160 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

In a more expressive type of language known as monadic


second-order logic (MSO) we can also say things like this:

there is a set of points Z that are all on one branch

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 160 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

In a more expressive type of language known as monadic


second-order logic (MSO) we can also say things like this:

there is a set of points Z that are all on one branch


(Z )(x, y )[(Z (x) Z (y )) ((x < y ) (y < x))]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 160 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Z is a continuous chain of points

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 161 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Z is a continuous chain of points


(x, y , z)[((Z (x)) (Z (z)) (x < y ) (y < z)) Z (y )]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 161 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Z is a continuous chain of points


(x, y , z)[((Z (x)) (Z (z)) (x < y ) (y < z)) Z (y )]

Z is a chain of Comp and Head links

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 161 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Z is a continuous chain of points


(x, y , z)[((Z (x)) (Z (z)) (x < y ) (y < z)) Z (y )]

Z is a chain of Comp and Head links


(x, y )[(Z (x) Z (y ) x < y ) (Head(x, y ) Comp(x, y ))]

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 161 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

So in MSO we can give a very precise definition of the following notion


of a properly located vacancy:
A vacancy is properly located in a clause if and only if there is a
continuous chain of Comp and Head links leading down to it from the
top of the clause.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 162 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

So in MSO we can give a very precise definition of the following notion


of a properly located vacancy:
A vacancy is properly located in a clause if and only if there is a
continuous chain of Comp and Head links leading down to it from the
top of the clause.
For non-standard dialects (which allow Wheres it at?):
Prenucleus where can accompany a clause with a properly
located noun phrase vacancy that immediately follows at.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 162 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

So in MSO we can give a very precise definition of the following notion


of a properly located vacancy:
A vacancy is properly located in a clause if and only if there is a
continuous chain of Comp and Head links leading down to it from the
top of the clause.
For non-standard dialects (which allow Wheres it at?):
Prenucleus where can accompany a clause with a properly
located noun phrase vacancy that immediately follows at.
For all dialects:
a Prenucleus noun phrase can accompany a clause with any
properly located noun phrase vacancy.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 162 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Three pieces of computational good news about MSO:

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 163 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Three pieces of computational good news about MSO:


1 D ECIDABLE SATISFIABILITY
For any description in an MSO language, a computer program can
figure out whether it is consistent whether there could be a tree
that conforms to that description.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 163 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Three pieces of computational good news about MSO:


1 D ECIDABLE SATISFIABILITY
For any description in an MSO language, a computer program can
figure out whether it is consistent whether there could be a tree
that conforms to that description.
2 T REE RECOGNIZABILITY
A property of trees is describable in MSO if and only if a
tree-crawling bug with finite memory could recognize that property.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 163 / 163


Model-theoretic syntax

Three pieces of computational good news about MSO:


1 D ECIDABLE SATISFIABILITY
For any description in an MSO language, a computer program can
figure out whether it is consistent whether there could be a tree
that conforms to that description.
2 T REE RECOGNIZABILITY
A property of trees is describable in MSO if and only if a
tree-crawling bug with finite memory could recognize that property.
3 S TRING RECOGNIZABILITY
If a grammar describing some set of sentences can be given as
an MSO description of a set of trees, then for any string of words it
can be determined by a computer program (quite rapidly) whether
it is grammatical or not.

Geoffrey K. Pullum (Edinburgh) WSLST 2012 Jan 2012 163 / 163

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen