Sie sind auf Seite 1von 14

World Development Vol. 35, No. 2, pp.

183196, 2007
2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved
0305-750X/$ - see front matter
www.elsevier.com/locate/worlddev
doi:10.1016/j.worlddev.2005.10.016

Epistemology, Normative Theory and Poverty


Analysis: Implications for Q-Squared in Practice
RAVI KANBUR
Cornell University, USA

and

PAUL SHAFFER *
University of Toronto and Trent University, Canada
Summary. The turn to the use of mixed qualitative and quantitative (Q-Squared) methods in the
analysis of poverty is a welcome development with large potential payos. While the benets of
mixing are not in doubt, the tensions involved in so doing have not received adequate attention.
The aim of this paper is to address this gap in the Q-Squared literature. It argues that there
are important dierences between approaches to poverty which operate at the levels of epistemol-
ogy and normative theory. These dierences have implications for the numerical transformation of
data, the selection of validity criteria, the conception/dimension of poverty adopted and interper-
sonal comparisons of well-being.
2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Key words poverty, methods, philosophy, ethics, social welfare, welfare measures

1. INTRODUCTION ing found in the contributions to this Sympo-


sium, such as the use of qualitative
In recent years, increasing attention has been information to improve household survey de-
focused on using mixed qualitative and quanti- sign (Parker and Kozel, Jha et al.); interpret
tative (Q-Squared) methods in the analysis of counterintuitive or surprising ndings from
poverty. A number of conferences 1 have been household surveys (Parker and Kozel, Sharp);
devoted to this issue and a growing body of explain the reasons behind observed outcomes
work has accumulated. 2 The articles in this (London et al., Adato et al.); probe motivations
Symposium are examples. They were among a
dozen or so empirical examples of Best Practice
* Introduction to a Symposium, Q-Squared in Prac-
in combining approaches to poverty analysis
selected for a conference held at the University tice, in World Development. Contributions to this Sym-
of Toronto in May 2004 entitled Q-Squared in posium were initially presented at a conference at the
Practice: Combining Qualitative and Quanti- Centre for International Studies, University of Toronto,
tative Approaches to Poverty Analysis. The May 1516, 2004 entitled Q-Squared in Practice: Expe-
conference is the second in a series of the riences of Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Ap-
Q-Squared initiative, which aims to promote proaches in Poverty Analysis. We are grateful to the
a better integration of qualitative and quan- International Development Research Centre (IDRC),
titative approaches to the analysis of poverty. Canada, the Department for International Development
This recent rediscovery of mixed methods in (DFID), United Kingdom, the USAID-funded Strate-
poverty analysis is a welcome development with gies for Growth and Access (SAGA) project and the P-
large potential payos in terms of understand- overty, Inequality and Development Initiative at Cornell
ing and explaining poverty. There are many University for nancial support. Final revision accepted:
examples of value-added associated with mix- October 20, 2005.
183
184 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

underlying observed behavior (Place et al., Rew Quantitative Poverty Appraisal: Complementa-
et al.); suggest the direction of causality (Place rities, Tensions and the Way Forward, consider-
et al.); assess the validity of quantitative results able attention was devoted to denitional and
(Barahona and Levy); better understand con- conceptual issues relating the qualitative/quan-
ceptual categories such as labor and the house- titative distinction. Conference participants had
hold (Adato et al.); facilitate analysis of locally dierent views on how the qual/quant divide
meaningful categories of social dierentiation should be conceptualized though all agreed that
(Howe and McKay, Hargreaves et al., Rew a ner set of categories was required to capture
et al.); provide a dynamic dimension to one- its many dimensions. One such typology of dif-
o household survey data (Howe and McKay), ferences was proposed by Kanbur (2003) build-
etc. ing upon, and adding to, a number of the
In our view, the benets of mixing are not in schemas presented. It is based on the following
doubt. It does seem, however, that the tensions ve dimensions:
involved in so doing have not received ade- 1. Type of information on population: non-
quate attention. There is a tendency to under- numerical to numerical.
play dierences between approaches and 2. Type of population coverage: specic to
consequent diculties in fruitfully combining general.
them. 3 As Appadurai (1989) argued in the con- 3. Type of population involvement: active to
text of a similar debate 15 years ago, a certain passive.
ecumenism has characterized the Q-Squared 4. Type of inference methodology: inductive
debate with dierences between approaches to deductive.
viewed in technical terms, amenable to techni- 5. Type of disciplinary framework: broad
cal solutions. social sciences to neo-classical economics.
The aim of this paper is to address this gap in This typology helps by clarifying terminol-
the Q-Squared literature. It argues that there ogy and spelling out exactly what is being dis-
are important dierences between approaches tinguished. As such, it has served the purpose
to poverty which operate at the levels of episte- for which it was developed. Nevertheless, the
mology and normative theory. 4 These dier- schema does raise a number of issues concern-
ences have implications for the numerical ing both the distinctions themselves and their
transformation of data, the selection of validity derivation from foundational categories. A
criteria, the conception/dimension of poverty review of the ve distinctions illustrates the
adopted and interpersonal comparisons of point.
well-being. The Q-Squared initiative ends up First, the numerical/nonnumerical distinc-
embroiled in these issues because the quest of tion has cutting power. While it is possible to
broadening the methodological framework numerically transform almost any type of
tends to bring out contrasting perspectives information by counting, scaling, ranking,
which go well beyond dierences of method. etc., there are important dierences in the
The format of the paper is as follows: Section numerical transformation process between
2 presents a critical assessment of an initial at- types of data (see Section 3). Further, as dis-
tempt to unpack the qualitative/quantitative cussed below, the distinction between data
distinction into ve dimensions of dierence. types is likely related to epistemological dier-
Section 3 directs attention to epistemological ences between traditions of inquiry in the social
dierences between approaches to poverty with sciences.
implications for numerical transformation of The second distinction, between specic and
data and validity criteria. Section 4 addresses general population coverage, is arguably more
contrasting traditions of normative theory with incidental than essential to the qual/quant di-
implications for the conception of poverty vide. Just about any research technique, quali-
adopted. Throughout, the contributions in this tative or quantitative, may be conducted in
Symposium, as well as other materials, are used few or many sites. Fixed-response question-
to illustrate the above issues. 5 naires may be applied in a single site and de-
tailed ethnographies may be conducted over a
range of sites to attempt to draw conclusions
2. A TYPOLOGY over a broader population. 6 Further, the con-
tent of household surveys and focus group or
At the rst Q-Squared Conference at Cornell interview guides can be modied to be more
University in 2001, entitled Qualitative and or less context specic. This issue of scale
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 185

depends primarily on three considerations: (i) 3. EPISTEMOLOGY


the purpose of the research, that is, whether
results are required to be representative of Arguably, some of the elements of the typol-
a broader population, say to inform decision ogy put forward by Kanbur (2003), as well as
making at regional or national levels; (ii) the other dierences between approaches to pov-
nature of the extrapolation exercise, that is, erty analysis, derive from epistemology. Episte-
whether statistical inference is being used to mology is the branch of philosophy which
extrapolate results, which implies some type studies the nature and claims of knowledge.
of probabilistic sampling and a minimum sam- Dierences in epistemological approach under-
ple size; (iii) practical considerations related to lie a standard distinction in the philosophy of
cost and standardization, which tend to favor social science between empiricism/positivism,
xed-response questionnaires for large n hermeneutics/interpretive approaches and criti-
studies. cal theory/critical hermeneutics (Braybrooke,
Third, the active/passive distinction is deriva- 1987; Fay, 1975).
tive of a standard distinction in the philosophy These programs may be dened in dierent
of social science between critical and other ways. We dene empiricism as a research ap-
traditions of inquiry. Critical traditions of so- proach predicated on an observation-based
cial science argue for an essential link between model for determining the truth or validity of
theory and practice and maintain that emanci- knowledge claims in which brute data are as-
pation, enlightenment or empowerment is a signed a special role. The meaning of brute
central feature of the research exercise (Fay, data will be explained below. It should be
1987). There is a wide disagreement, however, noted that the term empiricism is used in a par-
about the alleged empowering import of dier- ticular sense which diers from its more general
ent approaches to poverty, in particular the sense of being based on experience or experien-
participatory poverty approach. Its claims tial knowledge.
to empowerment have been vigorously con- Hermeneutics is generally dened as the
tested (see Rew et al., this issue). This distinc- interpretative understanding of intersubjective
tion will not be pursued below. meanings. Critical hermeneutics adds two
Fourth, the inductive/deductive dichotomy dimensions to this central thesis: (i) rst, under-
hinges on what exactly is meant by these terms. standing entails critical assessment of given be-
All poverty approaches rely heavily on theoret- liefs and perceptions involving some underlying
ical frameworks whether implicit or explicit. conception of truth or validity; (ii) second,
Further, understanding social phenomena is emancipation, enlightenment or empowerment
always a process of moving back and forth is an essential part of the process of inquiry.
between theoretical concepts and empirical We will dene the critical hermeneutic tradi-
information. The distinction correctly directs tion as one predicated on a discourse-based
attention to the fact that qualitative approaches model for establishing the truth or validity of
tend to be less axiomatic and more reliant on knowledge claims, which assigns a special role
contextually generated categories than quanti- to intersubjective meanings. As discussed
tative approaches. As such, they are closer to above, we omit the emancipatory/empowering
the grounded theory tradition of theory con- component from this denition because the po-
struction advocated by some (Glaser & Strauss, tential empowering role of dierent poverty
1967). Typically, however, induction is not de- approaches is widely contested.
ned in this way (Miller, 2003). We argue that there are important links be-
Fifth, the disciplinary distinction between tween empiricism and the consumption poverty
neo-classical economics and the rest seems approach, the gold standard in applied pov-
to underplay important quantitative traditions erty analysis in the developing world (e.g., Rav-
within the various social science disciplines. allion, 1994). This approach is an amalgam of
There are arguably greater methodic anities two variants of utility theory, revealed prefer-
than dierences between neo-classical econo- ence theory and money metric utility, and
mists and rational choice political scientists, nutrition science. More specically, poverty is
sociologists schooled in the Lazarsfeld tradition conceived as the nonfullment of basic prefer-
of surveying and model-building, 7 cliomet- ences. The preference part is due to the fact
ric historians, etc. (Abbott, 2001). It is likely that consumer preferences over goods and ser-
that this disciplinary distinction requires fur- vices, known by observing consumer behavior
ther unpacking. or asking about consumer choices (revealed
186 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

preference theory), are the building blocks from tion: such things as colors, sounds, smells,
which levels of well-being and poverty are de- hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on (Russell,
rived. Nutrition science is used to distinguish [1912] 1952, p. 12). Sense data began to lose
between basic and nonbasic preferences, their central importance in empiricist circles
as the poverty line is usually anchored on min- following the sustained critiques of Popper
imal levels of dietary energy, or caloric, intake and some of the 20th century logical positivists,
(Ravallion, 1994). Poverty is given a numeric primarily Neurath and Carnap (Ayer, 1959, pp.
representation in that preferences are repre- 13, 1721). Three key factors led to their de-
sented by consumption expenditure (money mise: (1) the realization that sense data were
metric utility), which facilitates the aggregation far from infallible or incorrigible (Ayer,
of persons or households below the poverty line 1959, p. 20); (2) the rejection of the view that
and comparisons of well-being across persons all objects could be translated into actual or
or households. All of these aspects of consump- possible sensations (Nagel, 1961, pp. 121
tion poverty are closely related to empiricism. 125); and critically, (3) the recognition that pub-
Important linkages are also found between lic, intersubjective knowledge claims cannot be
the critical hermeneutic tradition, as dened based on private sensations (Putnam, 1981, p.
above, and those approaches to poverty which 181). As a result, intersubjective observability
rely heavily on dialogic techniques, such as became a dening characteristic of brute data.
focus group discussions, semi-structured Intersubjective observability meets the last
interviews and life histories to come to an objection to sense data by establishing the sub-
understanding of poverty. One example is the ject invariance of properties or qualities of
participatory approach to poverty, which has objects. Harre (1985, p. 159) paraphrases this
been increasingly applied for empirical poverty requirement: many qualities [of objects] vary
analysis in the developing world since the mid- with the state of the subject, the perceiver, while
1990s through the use of participatory pov- for scientic purposes we should choose those
erty assessments (e.g., Narayan et al., 2002). 8 qualities which are subject invariant. In this
Some social anthropological approaches to revised sense then, brute data are physical,
poverty also exemplify this tradition, though intersubjectively observable and subject invari-
to a lesser extent. 9 In both cases, poverty anal- ant. An authoritative statement of the new con-
ysis involves interpreting perceptions of the ception of brute data is provided by Popper
meaning and causes of poverty as revealed by (1959, p. 103) in his discussion of basic state-
participants in dialog. ments . . . a basic statement must also satisfy
The discussion which follows addresses epis- a material requirement . . . this event must be an
temological dierences between empiricism observable event; that is to say, basic state-
and critical hermeneutics which relate to (i) ments must be testable, intersubjectively, by
units of knowledge and (ii) truth or validity observation.
criteria. The rst dierence, which contrasts What are the implications for poverty analy-
brute data with intersubjective meanings, sis? A major preoccupation of the consumption
is applied to the distinction between numerical approach to poverty has been to base its core
and nonnumerical data and illustrated using elements on intersubjectively observable data.
the contribution by Hargreaves et al. in the Nutrition science aimed to set a minimal level
Symposium. The second distinction, which con- of basic human needs in an intersubjectively
trasts observation-based validity criteria and observable way (based on the calorie content
discursive validity criteria, is illustrated by of dierent foods and calorie use in dierent
views presented in the referee reports on contri- types of activities by dierent categories of
butions to the Symposium. persons). 10 Revealed preference theory was
expressly intended to make preferences inter-
(a) Units of knowledge and numerical subjectively observable, whereas money metric
transformation utility sought to facilitate intersubjectively ob-
servable comparisons of welfare. In other
Brute data have played a critically important words, the derivation of the poverty line, inter-
role in both empiricism and the consumption personal comparisons of well-being, and the
approach to poverty as the bedrock of knowl- revelation of preferences are all conducted in
edge and arbiter of validity claims. Originally, intersubjectively observable fashion.
they were conceived of as sense data, the In the critical hermeneutic tradition, the core
things that are immediately known in sensa- unit of knowledge shifts from brute data to
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 187

intersubjective meanings. We dene intersub- about well-being, what types of social relation-
jective meanings as the core categories, beliefs ships are important when analyzing social
and values which give sense to social pheno- change, etc. Typically, inquiry of this sort in-
mena and meaning to social action. Putnam volves dialogic processes such as focus groups
(1981, pp. 201202) provides a good example: and semi-structured interviews. These ap-
proaches to poverty are not only about inter-
Take the sentence the cat is on the mat. We have subjective meanings generated in dialog but
the category cat because we regard the division they are also predicated on an understanding
of the world into animals and nonanimals as signi- of such, which is at the core of all subsequent
cant, and we are further interested in what species analysis.
a given animal belongs to. . . We have the category There is a particular anity between brute
mat because we regard the division of inanimate data and numeric information. Brute data are
things into artifacts and nonartifacts as signicant,
quantities of some sort for which there is often
and we are further interested in the purpose and nat-
ure a particular artifact has . . . We have the category a close mapping onto a numeric scale. For
on because we are interested in spatial relations . . . example, consumption can be viewed in terms
Notice what we have: we took the most banal state- of quantities of goods purchased or consumed,
ment imaginable, the cat is on the mat, and we or money, all of which are already represented
found that the presuppositions which make this numerically. In these cases, a close mapping
statement a relevant [or meaningful] one in certain exists between the social phenomenon in ques-
contexts include the signicance of the categories ani- tion, consumption, and a numeric scale
mate/inanimate, purpose and space.
(grams/kilos, kilo-calories or money). Intersub-
This concept of intersubjective meanings is jective meanings may be numerically trans-
central to the fundamental claim of hermeneu- formed through scaling, ranking or other
tics and critical hermeneutics that social phe- techniques. The properties of the ensuing
nomena are intrinsically meaningful. That numerical data, however, are dierent as is
is, social phenomena depend for their existence, their policy relevance. An example from the
and/or signicance, on the meanings ascribed Symposium illustrates this point.
to them by members of society. Phenomena In the consumption poverty approach, util-
such as poverty are constituted, in part, by ity is the chosen dimension of well-being. It is
the intersubjective meanings given to them equated with preference fulllment and ren-
and interpreted by social actors, including dered observable by restricting preferences to
researchers. Accordingly, explaining the social consumer preferences revealed by choice (re-
world is to undertake a double hermeneutic corded in consumption modules in household
analysis, that is, to interpret a world which is surveys). These are subsequently transformed
preinterpreted by social agents (Giddens, into consumption expenditure, or money. This
1976, p. 162). Failure to do so imposes severe process facilitates subject invariance in that
restrictions on social inquiry: we interpret all any two competent persons should be able
other societies in the categories of our own to rank individuals in the same way once this
(Taylor, 1985, p. 42). money metric criterion has been adopted.
For the hermeneutic and critical hermeneutic Money becomes a representation of well-being
traditions, accessing this preinterpreted world or poverty, which subsequently facilitates the
fundamentally requires participation in a pro- aggregation of those below the poverty line
cess of reaching understanding (Habermas, as well as consistent interpersonal comparisons
1984, p. 112). Participation is necessary because of well-being. 11 The key point is that the well-
it is the only way to come to an understanding being metric itself, utility, is transformed into
of intersubjective meanings. Interpreting indi- an intersubjectively observable datum, revealed
vidual responses to say, attitudinal question- preferences, to which an empirical scale,
naire surveys, without a prior understanding money, is applied.
of their intersubjective meaning referents sim- In the participatory approach, well-being
ply imposes our conceptual categories on every- rankings are often used to generate numbers
one else (Sayer, 1984, pp. 3335). of the poor, which are sometimes compared
A core objective of the participatory poverty across sites. An innovative example is the con-
approach and much of applied social anthro- tribution by Hargreaves et al. in this Sympo-
pological analysis of poverty is to better sium. To simplify, the methodology is to
understand what is meant by poverty, what cat- assign a numerical score to characteristics of
egories are considered relevant when thinking poor and nonpoor households (pile statements),
188 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

such as lack of clothing and lack of food, and to of reference: the relationship between the rep-
use this value to rank and compare households. resentations in our minds [of brute data] and
The score itself is calculated by the number of the external objects [either ideal or real] that
times the pile statements are associated with they refer to is literally a similarity (Putnam,
households in dierent well-being categories 1981, p. 57). The immediacy of sense data
(poor, nonpoor, etc.), determined in the course served as guarantor of this similarity: we are
of prior well-being ranking exercises. able to have ideas that refer to our own sensa-
While both of these approaches generate tions and this is the primary case of reference
numbers, the process of numerical transfor- from an epistemological point of view (Put-
mation is dierent, as is the policy relevance nam, 1981, p. 64).
of the numerical data produced. The key dier- The rejection of metaphysics as meaning-
ence is that the well-being metric is an intersub- less by many logical positivists and logical
jectively observable brute datum in the rst empiricists leads to a shift in emphasis to the
case, but not so in the second. Specically, the nonmetaphysical truth, or validity, of state-
ranking of piles is derived from a prior ranking ments (Ayer, 1959, pp. 116, 118119). The ef-
of households into well-being categories based fect was to closely link truth/validity criteria
on the perceptions of participants in the well- to intersubjective observability. Truth no
being ranking exercise. Unlike the ranking of longer relied on a mysterious relation of corre-
households on the basis of consumption expen- spondence to an external reality, nor on a sub-
diture, this household ranking does not satisfy jective sense of certainty about the validity of
subject invariance in that dierent persons immediate sense impressions. It was founded
may rank identical households dierently for on the intersubjectively observable and sub-
a variety of reasons. For example, the house- ject-invariant properties of brute data them-
hold ranked poorest in an auent commu- selves: Since the properties ascribed to things
nity could very well be ranked best o in a are observable properties, physicalist language
richer community. Consequently, scores gener- thus is intersubjective, and there is no problem
ated by the Hargreaves techniques will not lead in determining the truth [validity] of assertions
to consistent interpersonal comparisons of well- in physicalist languageone merely observes
being unless there is a high degree of homo- and sees whether the thing has the claimed
geneity in the perceived relationship between property (Suppe, 1974, p. 13).
household characteristics and well-being across Accordingly, determination of the validity of
the domain of the comparison. 12 To summa- theoretical statements became a process of
rize, then, epistemological dierences relating establishing their correspondence to intersub-
to the privileged unit of knowledge, brute data jectively observable, subject invariant, physical
vs. intersubjective meanings, have consequences data. The particular correspondence criteria
for the properties of numbers generated in or rules of choice have been the subject of con-
the numerical transformation process, subject siderable debate over the years (Caldwell,
invariant or not, with implications for policy- 1984). Proposals include strict veriability (log-
related applications, that is, making consistent ical positivists), whereby all theoretical terms
interpersonal comparisons. had to be dened in terms of an observation
vocabulary and individual tested, conrmabil-
(b) Validity criteria ity (logical empiricists), which allows for partial
denition of theoretical terms and testing of
The second dierence between empiricism theoretical systems as a whole, and falsiability
and critical hermeneutics concerns truth and (Popper), whereby the derivative hypothesizes
validity criteria. Empiricism relies on an obser- of theories are subject to critical tests set up
vation-based model to establish the truth or to falsify them. While these correspondence cri-
validity of statements in which brute data play teria dier in important respects, they all con-
a special role. The key issue for our purposes verge in that brute data are the referents to
concerns the exact nature of this role. which testing is applied.
For many of the early empiricists, brute data Brute data have played a critical role in
represented an external reality, whether ideal establishing validity in the consumption pov-
or real. Many held a metaphysical conception erty approach. At the level of data collection,
of truth, closely tied to ontological questions consumption expenditure and actual food con-
about the nature of reality. Central to his sumption can be observed and questionnaire
conception of truth was a similitude theory responses checked for reporting biases (Scott
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 189

& Amenuvegbe, 1990). 13 At the level of analy- you really want us to go back to basics on
sis, data on consumption expenditure and the this?!!
poverty line determination may be reviewed Both of these comments relate to issues
and reanalyzed to assess say, the validity of where there is in principle, an intersubjectively
empirical statements about poverty levels and observable and physical referent, for example,
trends. 14 In addition, the validity of theoretical HIV status, anti-social behavior, and food
claims about say, the causal importance of security status. The tension becomes more
dierent variables may be assessed econo- acute where there is no such obvious referent.
metrically through formal hypothesis testing. The point was made clearly by one referee
The critical hermeneutic tradition generally who distinguished between: dierences with
rejects this central role of intersubjective respect to fact . . .and cases where dierent per-
observability in establishing validity. The main ceptions are not necessarily a sign of mis-
reason is that narrative information generated reporting, for example, diering judgments . . .
by dialogic processes plays a much more central perceptions or interpretations. The latter
role in the analysis. There are a number of at- arises in the context of questions about levels
tempts to formulate truth or validity criteria or changes in satisfaction or happiness as dis-
within critical hermeneutics in ways which do cussed in the contribution by London et al.
not rely on the intersubjective observability Many proponents of empiricism express grave
requirement. For example, one version, pro- concerns with these types of data, on grounds
pounded by Jurgen Habermas, relies on a con- that psychological states . . . are not veriable
sensus theory of truth that rests on the premise even in principle, since states or attitudes exist
that truth is the property of a statement which only in the minds of the individuals (Bradburn
has been argumentatively, or discursively, vali- et al., 2004, p. 28).
dated (Habermas, 1991b). This notion of truth Epistemology is deeply relevant to Q-
is further discussed in the following section Squared poverty analysis because it bears on
when it is applied in the context of normative the types of knowledge which are favored
theory. The key point for our purposes is that and the types of validity criteria adopted. Be-
the coexistence of dierent validity criteria neath the conicting perspectives on particular
ends up raising tensions for Q-Squared-type contributions to the Symposium lie debates
work. about the relative merits of intersubjective
A number of the referee reports for this Sym- observability and discourse-based validity crite-
posium, and responses by the contributors, ria. Reconciling these viewpoints entails philo-
serve to illustrate this tension. Much of the con- sophical, not technical analysis.
troversy hinged on the validity of narrative
information generated in focus groups and
semi-structured interviews concerning ones 4. NORMATIVE THEORY
own poverty condition and/or that of others.
Some were skeptical about the validity of these The Q-Squared project cannot avoid address-
types of data. 15 For example, on the issue of ing normative theory at some point. The reason
taboo or dicult subjects one referee main- is that poverty is value laden in a direct and
tained: A second interesting claim is that case immediate way. As such, questions arise about
studies are able to get honest answers to di- the underpinnings of dierent conceptions of
cult questions concerning illegal activities, poverty and/or the processes of determining
HIV, anti-social behavior. This, too, is an their constituent elements. This is the domain
important advantage if it is true. But is it? of normative theory.
(Remember Margaret Mead in Samoa!). The consumption and participatory ap-
Another comment of this type concerns the proaches to poverty draw on dierent tradi-
validity of information generated by key infor- tions of normative theory to arrive at their
mants on the food security situation of house- objects of value, that is, the conceptions of pov-
holds within a given area. The referee erty which they use. There is a historical link be-
maintained that, there is no good evidence tween consumption poverty and what is known
that they [the key informants] are either objec- as naturalist normative theory. In addition,
tive, knowledgeable or capable of making the there are parallels between the participa-
appropriate judgments and assessments. The tory poverty approach and discursive norma-
authors counter that the above view chal- tive theory, also known as the discourse
lenges 30 years of work on participation. Do ethics. The following discussion presents the
190 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

two traditions and spells out their links with the ory without recourse to nonempirical entities.
two approaches to poverty. Bentham ([1823] 1948, p. 18) argued in favor
Naturalist normative theory attempts to of the Greatest Happiness Principle because it
ground evaluative claims in empirical fact. is clearer, as referring more explicitly to pain
There are a number of ways to do this, referred and pleasure. Further, he maintained that
to as naturalizing stratagems (Harman, 1977). pleasure and pain are directly measurable so
Following the terminology in Section 3, we that evaluative judgments could be made
refer to the main naturalizing stratagem used according to an intersubjectively observable
in the bodies of theory underlying the con- felicic calculus (Bentham, 1948, p. 29).
sumption poverty approach as the brute data Modern utility theory drops the mental state
grounding. of happiness or pleasure in favor of the ob-
The brute data grounding aims to derive of servable state of preference fulllment. Paul
the object of moral or prudential value from Samuelson is the central gure. He developed
sensory experience or observation. Historically, revealed preference theory and was an advocate
there have been two main variants, which cor- of money metric utility (Samuelson, 1966).
respond to the two conceptions of brute data Samuelson (1974, p. 1262) maintained that
discussed in Section 3. Originally, the object money metric utility is objectively measur-
of value was a sense datum, known either able and dened behavioristically by virtue
by introspection, observation, or everyday of revealed preference theory. Revealed prefer-
experience. Subsequently, it became an inter- ence theory rendered preferences intersubjec-
subjectively observable physical datum. tively observable and money metric utility
The main historical gure in the development allegedly restored interpersonal comparability
of naturalist normative theory is David Hume. to utility following its earlier rejection as un-
There is a clear historical link between Hume scientic (Robbins, 1962, pp. 138139).
and the consumption poverty approach, which As discussed in the previous section, the
runs through Bentham (1823) and some of the brute data grounding is quite integral to the
founders of utility theory (Shaer, 2002). Hume consumption poverty approach. The derivation
attempted to derive the object of moral value of the poverty line, revelation of preferences,
(virtue) from sensory experience. In his discus- and interpersonal comparisons of well-being
sion of virtue and vice (Hume, 1888, pp. 468 are all conducted in an intersubjectively obser-
469) writes: . . . see if you can nd the matter vable fashion. In addition, the ensuing frame-
of fact or real existence which you call vice . . . work facilitates intersubjectively observable
you will never nd it till you turn your reexion assessment of the validity of consumption data,
into your own breast, and nd a sentiment of simple empirical statements about the level and
disapprobation, which arises in you towards trends of poverty and theoretical claims about
this action. Here is a matter of fact; but tis say, the causes of poverty.
the object of feeling, not reason. Discursive normative theory arose in close
Humes empiricist epistemology and method- association with the works of Jurgen Habermas
ology greatly inuenced his normative think- and Karl-Otto Apel. There is no direct histori-
ing. Brute data provided the informational cal link between discursive normative theory
base for the experimental method that he and the participatory approach though paral-
sought to introduce to the study of ethics: lels exist between the two. Specically, they
. . . we can only expect success by following both require that an actual dialog be conducted
the experimental method, and deducing general to arrive at normative conclusions, such as the
maxims from a comparison of particular in- relevant conception of poverty to adopt. Fur-
stances . . . It is full time . . . [to] reject every sys- ther, there is growing acceptance of the impor-
tem of ethics, however subtle or ingenious, tance of using something akin to the idea of an
which is not founded on fact and observation ideal speech community to validate discursive
(Hume, 1902, pp. 174175). 16 outcomes.
Bentham paid glowing tribute to Hume as an This tradition of normative theory nds its
important intellectual source of his moral the- grounding in discourse, that is, an actual dis-
ory (Baumgardt, 1966, pp. 4243). Bentham cussion among participants in dialog. It rejects
followed Hume in grounding his core evalua- the monological identication of particular
tive standard, the principle of utility or the objects of value such as happiness or preference
Greatest Happiness Principle, in human senti- fulllment, which tend to ontologically favor
ment. Both sought to construct normative the- some particular type of ethical life (Habermas,
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 191

1991a, 1991b, p. 121). Instead, it lays out a pro- more likely than men to be poor at consump-
cedural metanorm about how normative dis- tion or to suer greater consumption poverty.
putes are to be adjudicated without specifying The incidence, intensity, and severity of poverty
the contents of any ensuing agreements. is lower in female-headed households than in
There is an elaborate theoretical edice male-headed households. Sensitivity analysis
underpinning Habermass version of discursive using dierent adult equivalence scales and dif-
normative theory. 17 To simplify, it combines ferent poverty lines (stochastic dominance
the principles of universalization and discourse tests) arms this result. In addition, both
both of which are supported by a transcenden- women and all females are under-represented,
tal pragmatic theory of argumentation. The relative to their share in the population, in poor
central feature of the transcendental pragmatic and ultra-poor households. Further, most indi-
argument is its attempt to derive the rules of cators of intra-household distribution of food
normative discourse from the properties of or health care (nutritional outcome and mortal-
speech. The universalization principle main- ity indicators, aggregate femalemale ratio) re-
tains that for a norm to be valid: all aected veal that men or boys are worse o than girls
can accept the consequences and the side eects or women. 19 PPA data from the village of
its general observance can be anticipated to Kamatiguia in Upper Guinea, however, suggest
have for the satisfaction of everyones interests that women as a group are worse o than men
(Habermas, 1991a, p. 65). It requires that an as a group. In group discussions, a substantial
actual dialog take place, whose idealized re- majority of men and women maintained that
ferent is the idea of ideal role taking or an women were worse o than men, and a larger
ideal speech situation whereby everyone has majority held that in a second life they would
the competence, opportunity and freedom to fully prefer to be born male than female. Further,
participate in dialog. The discourse principle in well-being ranking exercises, groups of both
makes the additional claim that dialog is a men and women separately ranked all but two
necessary means of arriving at normative con- married village women below all male house-
clusions: Only those norms can claim to be va- hold heads in terms of their own criteria of
lid that meet (or could meet) with the approval well-/ill-being. According to participants this
of all aected in their capacity as participants in nding has to do with two dimensions of depri-
practical discourse (Habermas, 1991a, p. 66). vation that disproportionately aect women,
The key point is that the discourse ethics has and are not well captured in consumption
parallels with aspects of the participatory ap- poverty: excessive work load and restricted
proach to poverty. 18 An actual dialog is re- decision-making authority.
quired to determine the dimensions of poverty The tension that arises for Q-Squared type
in which viewpoints are subject to critical re- analyses is that as more and more dimensions
view by participants. Further, there has been of poverty arise, it becomes increasingly di-
increasing recognition of the elusiveness of cult to determine their relative importance for
true participation given asymmetries of policy-related purposes, such as targeting or re-
power, knowledge, ability, etc. among partici- source allocation. While there are statistical
pants (Mosse, 1994). As a result, a number of techniques to perform multidimensional pov-
techniques have been developed to facilitate erty analysis, such as factorial analysis (Asselin,
greater participation, that is, to approximate 2002), statistical valuation is dierent from the
an ideal speech situation, including improved normative valuation which underlies well-being
identication procedures of invisible groups, rankings. The problem is compounded when
separate and/or smaller discussions with mar- dealing with aspects of poverty, such as lack
ginal groups, role plays where issues of power of respect or dignity, which are dicult to oper-
are subtly addressed through the exchange of ationalize in the same way as say, consumption.
social roles (Brock & McGee, 2002). A related set of problems, already alluded to,
What is the relevance for Q-Squared? The concerns interpersonal comparisons of well-
reliance on dierent traditions of normative being and aggregation of persons below the
theory poses tensions for the Q-Squared initia- poverty line when using conceptions of poverty
tive because dierent approaches to poverty are generated by participants in dialog. If dierent
likely to favor dierent dimensions of poverty. conceptions of poverty are favored in dierent
One example is Shaers (1998) study from sites, the basis for interpersonal comparisons
the Republic of Guinea. According to standard and aggregation is not obvious. It is interesting
national household survey data, women are not to note how this issue is handled by those
192 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

contributions in the Symposium which at- comparisons of well-being, on the other. The
tempted to compare and aggregate peoples tensions are at root philosophical and not ame-
perceptions of poverty. nable to an easy technical x.
A rst approach, adopted by Barahona and
Levy, is simply to take one dimension of well-
being which gured prominently in previously 5. CONCLUSION
conducted well-being rankings, food security,
standardize its denition and include it in a The turn toward the use of mixed qualitative
subsequent community census. While the and quantitative (Q-Squared) methods in the
authors argue that poverty denitions should analysis of poverty is long overdue. We believe
be developed through discussion with commu- that the contributions to this Symposium make
nities about how they see poverty, they opted a strong case for the value-added in opting for a
for a proxy of poverty in order to meet Q-Squared approach. We also believe that the
requirements of standardization. A second process of mixing is not seamless but that, at
approach, adopted by Sharp, is to impose a bottom, tensions remain. Two sources of ten-
multidimensional conception of deprivation, sion relating to epistemology and normative
comprising elements such as access to liveli- theory have been identied, with implications
hood resources and household independence, for the numerical transformation of data, the
and to include this within a self-assessment selection of validity criteria, the conception/
module with standardized categories in a dimension of poverty adopted and interper-
household survey. As above, the approach is sonal comparisons of well-being.
designed to be as far as possible, comparable The objective here is not simply to make the
across sites rather than a relative ranking with point that philosophical assumptions matter
the community. A third approach by Harg- for practice. It is to improve practice by teasing
reaves assigns a numerical value to characteris- out a number of implications for applied
tics of the poor generated from well-being poverty analysis. Two issues seem particularly
rankings and uses this information to construct germane.
household wealth and poverty indices and to First, concerning validity criteria, there is
make interpersonal comparisons. As discussed scope to incorporate some of the features of
in Section 3, the Hargreaves approach will only validity criteria based on intersubjective ob-
allow for consistent interpersonal comparisons servability into dialogic/qualitative inquiry.
if there is a great deal of homogeneity across To recall, intersubjective observability was an
sites in the perceived relationship between attempt to facilitate subject invariance, so
household characteristics and well-being or that research results should not depend on
wealth. A nal approach is that of Howe and whoever happened to be undertaking the
McKay who maintain that there is enough research exercise. Otherwise stated, validity is
homogeneity across well-being rankings to closely linked to concerns of reliability and rep-
identify certain meaningful characteristics of licability in the empiricist tradition. One way to
poverty groups, which can then be mapped bring these same considerations into dialogic
onto standard household survey data for analyses is presented in the contribution by
purposes of aggregation and comparison. As Hargreaves et al. In their study, all well-being
the authors note, however, the resulting analy- rankings were conducted on three occasions
sis is an approximation in that only some of the by dierent facilitators and the average score
characteristics of the poor from the PRA rank- of the three exercises used to rank households.
ings can be used and the categories themselves In this way, the undue inuence of any one
represent fairly broad generalizations across facilitator is reduced and the statistical agree-
many dierent regions and groups. ment between the rankings of dierent facilita-
Normative theory matters for Q-Squared tors can be assessed using an intra-cluster
poverty analysis because dierent theoretical correlation coecient. 20 The eect is to pro-
traditions tend to favor dierent conceptions vide a clearer basis for determining the validity
or dimensions of poverty. While there are ways of results by assessing their reliability.
to deal with this, all involve tradeos between A second related point concerns standardiza-
retaining the comprehensiveness and richness tion as a means of ensuring validity. The stan-
of peoples perceptions of well-being on the dardization of questions was already discussed
one hand and meeting the requirements of stan- in the previous section as a means of ensuring
dardization to make consistent interpersonal the comparability of ndings across population
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 193

groups. In the cases of xed response question- dard instructions about the importance of read-
naires, considerable attention has also been ing each question exactly as it appeared, in the
given to standardizing questionnaire adminis- same sequence, with the same emphasis, etc. It
tration so that all questions are asked exactly soon became apparent that this would not
in the same way. This is near impossible to do work for the open-ended questions as it was
in say, focus groups or semi-structured inter- impossible to predict the follow-up probes in
views because responses are not known in advance. As a result, it was decided to draft
advance. In these cases, it is useful to standard- lists of positive and negative probes in-
ize at the level of the dialogic encounter to en- tended to identify processes leading to positive
hance validity, relying on some notion of an and negative impact, respectively. While it was
ideal speech situation. An example, involving impossible to specify the exact probes to use,
an integrated impact assessment of a major as this would depend on how the discussion
anti-poverty program in Vietnam, illustrates evolved, it was possible to ensure a balance of
the point (Shaer/IDEA Intl., 2003). negative and positive probes for all questions.
One component of the impact assessment was As a practical matter, more attention should fo-
a nationally representative qualitative sur- cus on the requirements of approximating an
vey, which combined open-ended and xed re- ideal speech situation through the standardiza-
sponse questions about project impact. The tion and replication of techniques designed to
rst draft of the survey guide contained stan- generate balanced and wide ranging dialog.

NOTES

1. The Q-Squared Conferences at Cornell, March 15 statistical analysis in sociology, he was a consistent
16, 2001 and the University of Toronto, May 1516, advocate of the combined use of qualitative and quan-
2004 as well as the Conference on Combining Confer- titative approaches (see Boudon, 1993).
ence on Combining Quantitative and Qualitative Meth-
ods in Development Research, University of Wales, 8. The participatory approach to poverty had drawn
Swansea, July 12, 2002. heavily on the seminal work of Robert Chambers (1983)
among others.
2. Appleton and Booth (2001), Bevan and Joireman
(1997), Booth et al. (1998), Carvalho and White (1997), 9. The major dierence, for the present purposes, is
Harriss (2002), White (2002). that social anthropology has emphasized both the
observation of behavior (the etic) and the understanding
3. Exceptions include Booth (2002) and Campbell of meanings and beliefs (the emic). A major preoccupa-
(2005). tion is to analyze the often conicting information
coming from each (Booth et al., 1999; Rew et al.,. this
issue). This emphasis on intersubjective observability,
4. Some argue that there are important ontological
through techniques of participant observation, is one
dierences, about the nature of reality, between quali-
reason that some of the founders of anthropology
tative and quantitative approaches, though linkages
considered the new discipline to be empiricist in the
between epistemology and ontology are not straightfor-
sense used in this paper (Wright & Nelson, 1995, pp. 43
ward. It should be recalled that one of the most famous
51). Other dierences between the two traditions are
ontological idealists, Bishop Berkeley, was also an
discussed in Green (2004).
epistemological empiricist.

10. The use of techniques of nutrition science was


5. Sections 24 of this article draw on Shaer (2002,
brought into the modern analysis of consumption
2005).
poverty by Rowntree (1980) who relied upon estimates
derived by the nutritionist Atwater to calculate the
6. One such example is the Village Studies Program, minimal caloric requirements of male adult equivalents
197075, directed by Michael Lipton at the Institute of as well as the caloric value of dierent foodstus in order
Development Studies, University of Sussex (Lipton, to determine minimal food costs. Nutrition science
1992). provides an intersubjectively observable way of dening
an adequacy level of well-being, the poverty line, a fact
7. It should be noted that though Lazarsfeld is often which has been explicitly invoked by its proponents such
associated with the introduction of surveying and as Orshanksy (1965, p. 5), though it appears that
194 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

political considerations were quite integral to the latters and Mullainathan (2001) and more generally, Elster
choice of methods (Fisher, 1992). (1987).

11. There are many technical issues involved here, such 16. In practice Humes experiments were really
as adjusting for price, consumption and household thought exercises that relied heavily on introspective
composition dierences, which can lead to dierent evidence or ordinary experience (Noxon, 1973, pp. 116
results depending on how they are tackled (e.g., Raval- 123).
lion, 1996). Further, to guarantee consistency across
persons a number of assumptions are required which 17. See Habermas (1991a) and Rehg (1994).
may be violated in practice (Ravallion, 2003).
18. It should be noted that the idea of an idea speech
12. Hargreaves et al. acknowledge this point when they situation rests on many assumptions which are never
note that intercommunity comparability hinges on an achieved in practice. Nevertheless, it serves as a regula-
intrinsic link between wealth/well-being and house- tive ideal or standard against which the validity of
hold characteristics. discursive outcomes may be assessed (Forester, 1985). In
addition, following Benhabib (1992, pp. 3031, 7475),
the present argument drops Habermas (1991b, pp. 177
13. It should be explicitly acknowledged that the 182) insistence that the discourse ethics applies only to
reliance on self-reports of consumption from household
moral issues of justice and not to evaluative issues of the
surveys, rather than observations of actual consump- good or bad life, that is, poverty.
tion, marks a departure from the empiricist tradition.
This is second best option adopted for practical
19. The one exception relates to infant mortality
purposes within an empiricist theoretic framework. As
indicators when using relative-dierence or model life
such, it diers from the discussion below.
table norms.

14. Though see note 11. 20. This is analogous to techniques used in anthropol-
ogy for estimating intercoder reliability and determining
15. For this critique applied to subjective questions if the agreement between coders is due to chance, such as
in surveys, see Sudman et al. (1996) and Bertrand Cohens kappa (Bernard, 2002, pp. 480483).

REFERENCES

Abbott, A. (2001). Chaos of disciplines. Chicago: The Bertrand, M., & Mullainathan, S. (2001). Do people
University of Chicago Press. mean what they say? Implications for subjective
Appadurai, A. (1989). Small-scale techniques and large- survey data. MIT Dept. of Economics working paper
scale objectives. In P. Bardhan (Ed.), Conversations 01-04, Cambridge, MA.
between economists and anthropologists (pp. 250 Bevan, P., & Joireman, F. (1997). The perils of measur-
278). Delhi: Oxford University Press. ing poverty. Identifying the poor in Rural Ethio-
Appleton, S., & Booth, D. (2001). Combining partici- pia. Oxford Development Studies, 25(3), 124.
patory and survey-based approaches to poverty Booth, D. (2002). Toward a better combination of the
monitoring and analysis. Paper for workshop at quantitative and the qualitative. In R. Kanbur (Ed.),
Entebbe, Uganda. May 30June 1. Q-Squared. Qualitative and quantitative methods of
Asselin, L. M. (2002). Multidimensional poverty theory. poverty appraisal (pp. 97102). Delhi: Permanent
Mimeo: IDRC/MIMAP. Black.
Ayer, A. J. (1959). Language, truth, and logic. Har- Booth, D., Holland, J., Hentschel, J., Lanjouw, P., &
mondsworth, England: Penguin Books (original Herbert, A. (1998). Participation and combined
work published 1936). methods in African poverty assessment: Renewing
Baumgardt, D. (1966). Bentham and the ethics of today. the agenda. Report commissioned by DFID.
New York: Octagon Books, Inc. Booth, D. et al. (1999). Experiencing poverty in Africa:
Benhabib, S. (1992). Situating the self: Gender, commu- Perspectives from anthropology. Background paper
nity, and postmodernism in contemporary ethics. New no. 1(b) for the World Bank Poverty Status Report
York: Routledge. 1999.
Bentham, J. (1948). The principles of morals and legis- Boudon, R. (1993). Introduction. In R. Boudon (Ed.),
lation. New York: Haner Press (original work On social research and its language (pp. 129).
published 1823). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bernard, H. R. (2002). Research methods in anthropology Bradburn, N. et al. (2004). Asking questions. San
(2nd ed.). Walnut Creek, CA: Altamira Press. Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
EPISTEMOLOGY, NORMATIVE THEORY AND POVERTY ANALYSIS 195

Braybrooke, D. (1987). Philosophy of social science. New Kanbur, R. (2003). Q-squared? A commentary on
Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc. qualitative and quantitative poverty appraisal. In
Brock, K., & McGee, R. (2002). Knowing poverty: R. Kanbur (Ed.), Q-squared: qualitative and quanti-
Critical reections on participatory research and tative poverty appraisal (pp. 121). Delhi: Permanent
policy. London: Earthscan Publications. Black.
Caldwell, B. J. (1984). Beyond positivism. Economic Lipton, M. (1992). Economics and anthropology:
methodology in the twentieth century. London and Grounding models in relationships. World Develop-
New York: Routledge. ment, 20(10), 15411546.
Campbell, J. (2005). Theory and method in the study of Miller, S. (2003). Impact of mixed methods and design
poverty in East Africa. FocaalEuropean Journal of on inference quality. In A. Tashakkori, & C. Teddle
Anthropology, 45(1), 5668. (Eds.), Handbook of mixed methods in social and
Carvalho, S., & White, H. (1997) Combining the behavioral research (pp. 423456). Thousand Oaks,
quantitative and qualitative approaches to poverty CA: Sage Publications.
measurement and analysis. World Bank technical Mosse, D. (1994). Authority, gender and knowledge:
paper 366. The World Bank, Washington, DC. Theoretical reections on the practice of participa-
Chambers, R. (1983). Rural development. Putting the last tory rural appraisal. Development and Change, 25,
rst. New York: Longman Scientic and Technical. 497526.
Elster, J. (1987). Sour grapes, studies in the subversion of Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. New York and
rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Burlingame: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.
Fay, B. (1975). Social theory and political practice. Narayan, D. et al. (2002). Voices of the poor. Oxford:
London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. Oxford University Press.
Fay, B. (1987). Critical social science: Liberation and its Noxon, J. (1973). Humes philosophical development:
limits. Cambridge: Polity Press. A study of his methods. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Fisher, G. (1992). The development and history of the Orshanksy, M. (1965). Counting the poor: another look
poverty thresholds. Social Security Bulletin, 55(4), at the poverty prole. Social Security Bulletin, 28,
314. 129.
Forester, J. (1985). Introduction: the applied turn in Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientic discovery.
contemporary critical theory. In J. Forester (Ed.), London: Hutchinson.
Critical theory and public life (pp. ixxix). Cam- Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Giddens, A. (1976). New rules of sociological method: A Ravallion, M. (1994). Poverty comparisons. Fundamen-
positive critique of interpretative sociologies. London: tals of pure and applied economics. Chur, Switzerland:
Hutchison and Co. Harwood Academic Publishers.
Glaser, B. G., & Strauss, A. (1967). The discovery of Ravallion, M. (1996). Issues in measuring and modeling
grounded theory: Strategies for qualitative research. poverty. The Economic Journal, 106, 13281343.
New York: Aldine. Ravallion, M. (2003). On the utility consistency of
Green, M. (2004). Representing poverty: Attacking poverty lines. World Bank Policy Research work-
representations: Anthropological perspectives on ing paper no. 3157. The World Bank, Washington,
poverty in development. Mimeo. DC.
Habermas, J. (1984). Reason and the rationalization of Rehg, P. (1994). Insight and solidarity. A study in the
society. The theory of communicative action (Vol. 1). discourse ethics of Jurgen Habermas. Berkeley: Uni-
Cambridge: Polity. versity of California Press.
Habermas, J. (1991a). Discourse ethics: Notes on a Robbins, L. (1962). An essay on the nature and signif-
program of philosophical justication. In Moral icance of economic science (second ed.). London:
consciousness and communicative action (pp. 43 MacMillan and Co. Ltd, original work published
115). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 1936.
Habermas, J. (1991b). Moral consciousness and com- Rowntree, S. (1980). Poverty: A study of town life. New
municative action. In Moral consciousness and com- York and London: Garland (original work published
municative action (pp. 116194). Cambridge, MA: 1901).
MIT Press. Russell, B. (1952). The problems of philosophy. London:
Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality: An introduc- Oxford University Press (original work published
tion to ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. 1912).
Harre, R. (1985). The philosophies of science (2nd ed). Samuelson, P. (1966). A note on the pure theory of
Oxford: Oxford University Press. consumers behavior. In J. Stiglitz (Ed.). The
Harriss, J. (2002). The case for cross-disciplinary collected scientic papers of Paul A. Samuelson
approaches in international development. World (Vol. 1, pp. 313). Cambridge: MIT Press (original
Development, 30(3), 487496. work published 1938).
Hume, D. (1888). In L. A. Selby-Bigge (Ed.), A treatise Samuelson, P. (1974). Complementarity: an essay on the
of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press (original 40th anniversary of the HicksAllen revolution in
work published 1740). demand theory. Journal of Economic Literature, 12,
Hume, D. (1902). In L. A. Selby-Bigge (Ed.), Enquiry 12551289.
concerning the principles of morals (2nd ed.). Oxford: Sayer, A. (1984). Method in social science. A realist
Clarendon Press, original work published 1777. approach. London: Hutchinson.
196 WORLD DEVELOPMENT

Scott, C., & Amenuvegbe, B. (1990). Eect of recall Sudman et al. (1996). Thinking about answers: The
duration on reporting of household expenditure: an application of cognitive processes to survey methodol-
experimental study in Ghana. Social Dimensions of ogies. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Adjustment (SDA) working paper no. 6. The World Suppe, F. (Ed.) (1974). The structure of scientic
Bank, Washington, DC. theories. Urbana: The University of Illinois Press.
Shaer, P. (1998). Gender, poverty, and deprivation: Taylor, C. (1985). Interpretation and the science of man.
evidence from the Republic of Guinea. World In C. Taylor (Ed.), Philosophy and the human sciences
Development, 26(12), 21192135. (pp. 1557). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Shaer, P. (2002). Poverty naturalised: implications for (original work published 1971).
gender. Feminist Economics, 8(3), 5575. White, H. (2002). Combining quantitative and qualita-
Shaer, P./IDEA Intl. (2003). Impact assessment of the tive approaches in poverty analysis. World Develop-
Hunger Eradication and Poverty Reduction (HEPR) ment, 30(3), 511522.
program: Concept note. Ministry of Labor and Wright, S., & Nelson, N. (1995). Participatory research
Social Aairs (MOLISA)/United Nations Develop- and participant observation. In N. Nelson, & S.
ment Program (UNDP), Hanoi. Wright (Eds.), Power and participatory development
Shaer, P. (2005). Assumptions matter: reections on (pp. 4359). London: Intermediate Technology Pub-
the Kanbur typology. FocaalEuropean Journal of lications.
Anthropology, 45(1), 1832.

PAPERS PRESENTED IN THE WORLD DEVELOPMENT SYMPOSIUM

Adato, M., et al. Methodological Innovations in London, A., et al. Combining Quantitative and Qual-
Research on the Dynamics of Poverty: A Longitu- itative Data in Welfare Policy Evaluations in the
dinal Study in KwaZulu-Natal, South Africa. United States.
Barahona, C., Levy, S., The Best of Both Worlds: Parker, B., Kozel, V., Understanding Poverty and
Producing National Statistics using Participatory Vulnerability in Indias Uttar Pradesh and Bihar:
Methods. A Q-Squared Approach.
Hargreaves, J., et al. Hearing the voices of the poor: Place, F., et al. Understanding Rural Poverty and
Assigning poverty lines on the basis of local percep- Investment in Agriculture: An Assessment of Inte-
tions of poverty; a quantitative analysis of qualitative grated Quantitative and Qualitative Research in
data from participatory wealth ranking in rural Western Kenya. 0
South Africa. Rew, A., et al. P3 > Q2 In Northern Orissa; an
Howe, G., McKay, A., Combining Quantitative and example of integrating Combined Methods (Q2)
Qualitative methods in Assessing Chronic Poverty: through a Platform for Probing Poverties (P3).
The Case of Rwanda. Sharp, K., Squaring the Qs? Methodological Reec-
Jha, S., et al. Governance in the Gullies: Democratic tions on a Study of Destitution in Ethiopia.
Responsiveness and Leadership in Delhis Slums.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen