Sie sind auf Seite 1von 10

Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.

org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

Essentially contested concept


From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In a paper delivered to the Aristotelian Society on 12 March 1956,[1] Walter Bryce Gallie (19121998)
introduced the term essentially contested concept to facilitate an understanding of the different
applications or interpretations of the sorts of abstract, qualitative, and evaluative notions[2] such as
"art" and "social justice" used in the domains of aesthetics, political philosophy, philosophy of
history, and philosophy of religion.

Garver (1978) describes their use as follows:

The term essentially contested concepts gives a name to a problematic situation that many people
recognize: that in certain kinds of talk there is a variety of meanings employed for key terms in an
argument, and there is a feeling that dogmatism (My answer is right and all others are wrong),
skepticism (All answers are equally true (or false); everyone has a right to his own truth), and
eclecticism (Each meaning gives a partial view so the more meanings the better) are none of
them the appropriate attitude towards that variety of meanings.[3]

Essentially contested concepts involve widespread agreement on a concept (e.g., "fairness"), but not on
the best realization thereof.[4]

They are "concepts the proper use of which inevitably involves endless disputes about their proper uses
on the part of their users",[5] and these disputes "cannot be settled by appeal to empirical evidence,
linguistic usage, or the canons of logic alone".[6]

Contents
1 Identifying the presence of a dispute
1.1 Contested versus contestable?
2 Features
3 Concepts and conceptions
4 Not "hotly disputed" concepts
5 See also
6 Notes
7 References

Identifying the presence of a dispute


Although Gallies term is widely used to denote imprecise use of technical terminology, it has a far more
specific application. And, although the notion could be misleadingly and evasively used to justify
"agreeing to disagree",[7] the term offers something more valuable:

Since its introduction by W.B. Gallie in 1956, the expression "essentially contested concept" has
been treated both as a challenge and as an excuse by social theorists. It has been treated as a
challenge in that theorists consider their uses of terms and concepts to be in competition with the
uses advocated by other theorists, each theorist trying to be deemed the champion. It has been
treated as an excuse that, rather than acknowledge that the failure to reach agreement is due to

1 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

such factors as imprecision, ignorance, or belligerence, instead theorists point to the terms and
concepts under dispute and insist that they are always open to contest that they are terms and
concepts about which we can never expect to reach agreement.[8]

The disputes that attend an essentially contested concept are driven by substantive disagreements over a
range of different, entirely reasonable (although, perhaps, mistaken) interpretations of a mutually-
agreed-upon archetypical notion, such as the legal precept "treat like cases alike; and treat different cases
differently", with "each party [continuing] to defend its case with what it claims to be convincing
arguments, evidence and other forms of justification"[9]).

Gallie speaks of how "This picture is painted in oils" can be successfully contested if the work is
actually painted in tempera;[10] while "This picture is a work of art" may meet strong opposition due to
disputes over what "work of art" denotes. He suggests three avenues whereby one might resolve such
disputes:

1. Discovering a new meaning of "work of art" to which all disputants could thenceforward agree.
2. Convincing all the disputants to conform to one meaning.
3. Declaring "work of art" to be a number of different concepts employing the same name.

Otherwise, the dispute probably centres on polysemy.[11] Here, a number of critical questions must be
asked:

Has the term been incorrectly used, as in the case of mistakenly using decimated for devastated
(catachresis)?[12]
Do two or more different concepts share the same word, as in the case of ear, bank, sound, corn,
scale, etc. (homonymy)?[13]
Is there a genuine dispute about the term's correct application that, in fact, can be resolved?
Or, is it really the case that the term is an essentially contested concept?

Contested versus contestable?

Clarke has made a valuable contribution to the overall debate by suggesting that, in order to determine
whether a particular dispute was a consequence of true polysemy or inadvertent homonymy, one
should seek to "locate the source of the dispute".

This source might be "within the concept itself", or "[within] some underlying non-conceptual
disagreement between the contestants".[14]

Clarke then drew attention to the substantial differences between the expressions "essentially contested"
and "essentially contestable", that were being extensively used within the literature as though they were
interchangeable.

Clarke argued that to state that a concept is merely contested, "is to attribute significance to the contest
rather than to the concept". Yet, to state that a concept is contestable is to "attribute some part of any
contest to the concept". In other words, this is "to claim that some feature or property of the concept
makes it polysemantic, and that the concept contains some internal conflict of ideas"; and it is this fact
that provides the "essentially contested concept" with its inherent potential for "generating disputes".[15]

Features
In 1956, Gallie proposed a set of seven conditions for the existence of an essentially contested

2 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

concept.[16] Gallie was very specific about the limits of his enterprise: it dealt exclusively with abstract,
qualitative notions, such as art, religion, science, democracy, and social justice[17] (and, if Gallies
choices are contrasted with negatively regarded concepts such as evil, disease, superstition, etc., it is
clear that the concepts he chose were exclusively positively regarded).

Freeden remarks that "not all essentially contested concepts signify valued achievements; they may
equally signify disapproved and denigrated phenomena",[18] and Gerring[19] asks us to imagine just how
difficult it would be to "[try] to craft definitions of slavery, fascism, terrorism, or genocide without
recourse to "pejorative" attributes".

These features distinguish Gallie's "essentially contested concepts" from others, "which can be shown, as
a result of analysis or experiment, to be radically confused";[20] or, as Gray[21] would have it, they are
the features that relate to the task of distinguishing the "general words, which really denote an
essentially contested concept" from those other "general words, whose uses conceal a diversity of
distinguishable concepts":[22]

(1) Essentially contested concepts are evaluative, and they deliver value-judgements.[23]

(2) Essentially contested concepts denote comprehensively evaluated entities that have an
internally complex character.[24]

(3) The evaluation must be attributed to the internally complex entity as a whole.

(4) The different constituent elements of that internally complex entity are initially variously
describable.

(5) The different users of the concept will often allocate substantially different orders of relative
importance, substantially different "weights", and/or substantially different interpretations to each
of those constituent elements.

(6) Psychological and sociological causes influence the extent to which any particular
consideration is:
(a) salient for a given individual,
(b) regarded as a stronger reason by that individual than by another, and
(c) regarded as a reason by one individual and not by another.[25]

(7) The disputed concepts are open-ended[26] and vague, and are subject to considerable
modification in the light of changing circumstances.[27]

(8) This further modification can neither be predicted nor prescribed in advance.

(9) Whilst, by Gallies express stipulation, there is no best instantiation of an essentially contested
concept -- or, at least, none knowable to be the best -- it is also obvious that some instantiations
will be considerably better than others;[28] and, furthermore, even if one particular instantiation
seems best at the moment, there is always the possibility that a new, better instantiation will
emerge in the future.[29]

(10) Each party knows and recognizes that its own peculiar usage/interpretation of the concept is
disputed by others who, in their turn, hold different and quite incompatible views.[30]

(11) Each party must (at least to a certain extent) understand the criteria upon which the other

3 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

participants (repudiated) views are based.

(12) Disputes centred on essentially contested concepts:


(a) are "perfectly genuine",
(b) "not resolvable by argument",[31] and
(c) "nevertheless sustained by perfectly respectable arguments and evidence".[32]

(13) Each partys use of their own specific usage/interpretation is driven by a need to uphold their
own particular (correct, proper and superior) usage/interpretation against that of all other
(incorrect, improper and irrational) users.

(14) Because the use of an essentially contested concept is always the application of one use
against all other uses, any usage is intentionally aggressive and defensive.

(15) Because it is essentially contested, rather than radically confused, the continued use of the
essentially contested concept is justified by the fact that, despite all of their on-going disputation,
all of the competitors acknowledge that the contested concept is derived from a single common
exemplar.[33]

(16) The continued use of the essentially contested concept also helps to sustain and develop our
understanding of the concepts original exemplar/s.

Concepts and conceptions


Scholars such as Hart, Rawls, Dworkin, and Lukes have variously embellished Gallies proposal by
arguing that certain of the difficulties encountered with Gallies proposition may be due a consequence
of the unintended conflation of two separate domains associated with the term concept:

(a) the concepts (the abstract, ideal notions themselves), and


(b) the conceptions (the particular instantiations, or realizations of those ideal and abstract
notions).[34]

In essence, Hart (1961), Rawls (1971), Dworkin (1972), and Lukes (1974) distinguished between the
"unity" of a notion and the "multiplicity" of its possible instantiations.

From their work it is easy to understand the issue as one of determining whether there is a single notion
that has a number of different instantiations, or whether there is more than one notion, each of which is
reflected in a different usage.

In a section of his 1972 article in The New York Review of Books, Dworkin used the example of
"fairness" to isolate and elaborate the difference between a concept (suum cuique) and its conception
(various instantiations, for example utilitarian ethics).[35]

He supposes that he has instructed his children not to treat others "unfairly" and asks us to recognize
that, whilst he would have undoubtedly had particular "examples" (of the sorts of conduct he was
intending to discourage) in mind at the time he spoke to his children, whatever it was that he meant
when he issued such instructions was not confined to those "examples" alone, for two reasons:

1. "I would expect my children to apply my instructions to situations I had not and could not have
thought about."
2. "I stand ready to admit that some particular act I had thought was fair when I spoke was in fact
unfair, or vice versa, if one of my children is able to convince me of that later."

4 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

Dworkin argues that this admission of error would not entail any "change" to his original instructions,
because the true meaning of his instructions was that "[he] meant the family to be guided by the concept
of fairness, not by any specific conception of fairness [that he] might have had in mind". Therefore, he
argues, his instructions do, in fact, "cover" this new case.

Exploring what he considers to be the "crucial distinction" between the overall concept of "fairness"
and some particular, and specific conception of "fairness", he asks us to imagine a group whose
members share the view that certain acts are unfair.[36]

The members of this group "agree on a great number of standard cases of unfairness and use these as
benchmarks against which to test other, more controversial cases".

In these circumstances, says Dworkin, "the group has a concept of unfairness, and its members may
appeal to that concept in moral instruction or argument."[37]

However, the members may still disagree over many of these "controversial cases"; and differences of
this sort indicate that members have, or act upon, entirely different theories of why and how each of the
"standard cases" are, in fact, genuine acts of "unfairness".

And, because each considers that certain principles "[which] must be relied upon to show that a
particular division or attribution is unfair" are far a more "fundamental" sort of principle than certain
other principles, it can be said that members of the group have different conceptions of "fairness".

Consequently, those responsible for giving "instructions", and those responsible for setting "standards"
of "fairness", in this community may be doing one of two things:

1. Appealing to the concept of "fairness", by demanding that others act "fairly".


In this case, those instructed to act "fairly" are responsible for "developing and applying
their own conception of fairness as controversial cases arise".[38]
Each of those issuing the instructions (or setting the standards) may have quite different
explanations underlying their actions; and, also, they may well change their explanations
from time to time, without ever changing the standards they set.[39]
2. Laying down a particular conception of "fairness"; by, for example, specifying that all hard
cases were to be decided "by applying the utilitarian ethics of Jeremy Bentham".

It is important to recognize that rather than it just being a case of delivering two different instructions; it
is a case of delivering two different kinds of instruction:

1. In the case of the appeal to the concept of "fairness", one invokes the ideal (and, implicitly, the
universally agreed upon) notion of 'fairness"; and whatever one might believe is the best
instantiation of that notion is, by and large, irrelevant.

2. In the case of laying down a conception of "fairness", one specifies what one believes to be the
best instantiation of the notion "fairness"; and, by this action, one specifies what one means by
"fairness"; and whatever one might believe is the ideal notion of "fairness" is, by and large,
irrelevant.

As a consequence, according to Dworkin, whenever an appeal is made to "fairness", a moral issue is


raised; and, whenever a conception of "fairness" is laid down, an attempt is being made to answer that
moral issue.

Not "hotly disputed" concepts

5 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

Whilst Gallie's expression "essentially contested concepts" precisely denotes those "essentially
questionable and corrigible concepts," which "...are permanently and essentially subject to revision and
question,[40] close examination of the wide and varied and imprecise applications of Gallie's term
subsequent to 1956, by those who have ascribed their own literal meaning to Gallie's term without ever
consulting Gallie's work, have led many philosophers to conclude that "essentially disputed concepts"
would have been far better choice for Gallie's meaning, for at least three reasons:

1. Gallies term has led many to the mistaken belief that he spoke of hotly disputed, rather than
essentially disputed concepts.[41]

2. Expressly stipulating that a specific issue can never be resolved, and then calling it a "contest"
seems both absurd and misleading.[42]

3. Any assertion that "essentially contested" concepts are incommensurable made at the same
time as an assertion that "they have any common subject-matter" is incoherent; and, also, it reveals
an "inconsistency in the idea of essential contestability".[43]

Waldron's research has revealed that Gallies notion has run wild in the law review literature over the
ensuing 60 years and is now being used to denote something like "very hotly contested, with no
resolution in sight",[44] due to an entirely mistaken view[45] that the essential in Gallies term is an
"intensifier", when, in fact, "[Gallies] term "essential" refers to the location of the disagreement or
indeterminacy; it is contestation at the core, not just at the borderlines or penumbra of a concept".[46]

Yet is also clear that "if the notion of logical justification can be applied only to such theses and
arguments as can be presumed capable of gaining in the long run universal agreement, the disputes to
which the uses of any essentially contested concept give rise are not genuine or rational disputes at all"
(Gallie, 1956a, p.188).

Thus, Gallie argued:

So long as contestant users of any essentially contested concept believe, however deludedly, that
their own use of it is the only one that can command honest and informed approval, they are likely
to persist in the hope that they will ultimately persuade and convert all their opponents by logical
means. But once [we] let the truth out of the bag i.e., the essential contestedness of the concept
in question then this harmless if deluded hope may well be replaced by a ruthless decision to
cut the cackle, to damn the heretics and to exterminate the unwanted. (Gallie, 1956a, pp.193-194)

See also

Ambiguity Logical argument


Argumentation theory Vagueness
Critical thinking What Is Art?

Notes
deliver some sort of "value-judgement".
1. ^ Published immediately as Gallie (1956a); a 3. ^ Garver (1978), p. 168.
later, slightly altered version appears in Gallie 4. ^ Hart (1961, p.156) speaks of "a uniform or
(1964). constant feature", and "a shifting or varying
2. ^ They are "evaluative" in the sense that they criterion used in determining when, for any given

6 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

purposes, cases are alike or different". concepts".


5. ^ Gallie (1956a), p.169. The dispute is about the 25. ^ Mason (1990), p.96.
proper use of the concept; and all argue that the 26. ^ Gallie cites "democracy" an example of a
concept is being "used inappropriately" by concept being "open" in its character: "Politics
others (Smith, 2002, p.332). being the art of the possible, democratic targets
6. ^ Gray (1977), p.344. will be raised or lowered as circumstances alter,
7. ^ A statement that, in essence, is usually nothing and democratic achievements are always judged
more than a simple observation that the apparent in the light of such alterations" (Gallie, 1956a,
dispute it is simply a consequence of the same p.186, emphasis added).
label being applied to different referents. 27. ^ Because, in the absence of this condition, it is
8. ^ Rhodes (2000), p. 1. possible that experience could establish one
9. ^ Gallie (1956a) p. 168. instantiation as "universally more acceptable
10. ^ Gallie (1956a), p. 167. than another" (Gallie, 1956a, p.174).
11. ^ The embedded meaning of the term polysemy is 28. ^ Swanton (1985), p.815.
that the polysemous words meanings have 29. ^ Mason (1990), p.85.
multiplied over time (in the sense of its original 30. ^ For, otherwise, it would only be, at best, an
meaning being extended). essentially "contestable" concept.
When discussing finance, "bank" is an 31. ^ Connolly (1974, p.40) expressed the view that
essentially contested concept; because the once the participants in a particular political
discussion involves establishing the dispute realized that the concept was an
"correct" application, meaning or essentially contested concept, the ensuing
interpretation of this polysemous term. political discussions would be far more
In a different dispute over banks, where "enlightened" (Connolly, 1974, p.40).
one speaks of financial institutions and the 32. ^ All from Gallie (1956a), p.169.
other of riparian zones, it is obvious that 33. ^ This agreement is a pre-requisite for the
two homonyms have been confused. argument, it is not a consequence of the
12. ^ Which is "a conflict between truth and error" argument. See McKnight (2003), p.261; and
(Garver, 1990, p. 259) Perry (1977), p.25. In an attempt to account for
13. ^ Which is "a disagreement generated because cases where disputants trace their individual
the parties to the conflict are talking past each notions back to entirely different, but mutually
other" (Garver, 1990, p.259) the "talking past compatible exemplars, Connolly (1974, p.14)
each other" is an allusion to the interaction proposes that we think of the shared exemplar as
between Thrasymachus and Socrates over the a "cluster concept ".
question of "justice" in Plato's Republic I, where 34. ^ The concept/conception terminology seems to
neither addressed any of the issues raised by the originate with Gallies (1956a) own comment
other. Gallie (1956a, p.168.) speaks of this as that, whilst they might still continue to employ
being a case in which "two different concepts the contested concept, the "different teams
about whose proper application no none need to [could] come to hold very different
have contested at all" having become "confused". conceptions of how the game should be played"
14. ^ Clarke (1979), p. 123. (p. 176, emphasis added).
15. ^ Clarke (1979), p. 124. 35. ^ Dworkin (1972), pp.27-28 (an almost identical
16. ^ See Gallie (1956a). passage appears at Dworkin, 1972, pp.134-135).
17. ^ Gallie (1956a), passim. Kekes (1977, p.71) The four-paragraph passage is in Section II of the
offers art, morality, logic, the novel, nature, article [1] (http://www.nybooks.com/articles
rationality, democracy, culture, science, and /10204). It commences with "But the theory of
philosophy as another set of examples of " and ends with "I try to answer it ".
"concepts" that are essentially contested. 36. ^ These unfair acts involve either "a wrongful
18. ^ Freeden (1998), p.56. division of benefits and burdens, or a wrongful
19. ^ Gerring (1999), p.385. attribution of praise or blame".
20. ^ Gallie (1956a), p.180. 37. ^ Emphasis added to original.
21. ^ Gray (1977), p.337. 38. ^ He notes that this does not "[grant] them a
22. ^ They are unpackings of, elaborations upon, or discretion to act as they like"; but, from the fact
extensions of Gallie's original seven features that that "it assumes that one conception is superior to
have been made by a very wide range of scholars another", it is clear that "it sets a standard they
spread over a wide range of academic and must try and may fail to meet".
intellectual pursuits over the last 60 years. 39. ^ Thus, we could say, there is a demand for
23. ^ Baldwin stresses that whilst "not all value orthopraxy (the correctness of action), not for
judgements are appraisive", "[any act of] orthodoxy (the correctness of thought).
appraisal presupposes an accepted set of 40. ^ Hampshire (1965), p.230.
criteria" (Baldwin (1997), p.10. 41. ^ See Waldron (2002).
24. ^ For this reason, Benn and Gaus (1983, pp.3-5) 42. ^ There seems to be a radical fault in the very
advocate using the term "complex-structured notion of a contest that can not by its nature be

7 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

won or lost. (Gray, 1999, p.96) pornography, power, privacy, property,


43. ^ Gray (1999), p.96. proportionality, prosperity, prostitution,
44. ^ Waldron (2002, p.149) found that the following public interest, punishment, reasonable
concepts had been labelled as essentially expectations, religion, republicanism,
contested in the Westlaw database: rights, sovereignty, speech, sustainable
alienation, autonomy, author, bankruptcy, development, and textuality.
boycott, citizenship, civil rights, 45. ^ Of course, the equivalent view about the term
coherence, community, competition, the in general is reasonable: it merely uses the
Constitution, corruption, culture, descriptive definition. The descriptive definition
discrimination, diversity, equality, equal is still a definition, even if one may think it less
protection, freedom, harm, justification, interesting than Gallie's definition.
liberalism, merit, motherhood, the national 46. ^ Waldron (2002), pp.148-149.
interest, nature, popular sovereignty,

References
Abbey, R., "Is Liberalism Now an Essentially Contested Concept?", New Political Science, Vol.27, No.4,
(December 2005), pp.461-480.
Baldwin, D.A., "The Concept of Security", Review of International Studies, Vol.23, No.1, (January 1997),
pp.5-26.
Benn, S.I., A Theory of Freedom, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1988.
Benn, S.I. & Gaus, G.F., "The Public and the Private: Concepts and Action", pp.3-27 in Benn, S.I. & Gaus,
G.F., Public and Private in Social Life, Croom Helm, (London), 1983.
Booth, W.C., "Preserving the Exemplar: or, How Not to Dig Our Own Graves", Critical Inquiry, Vol.3,
No.3, (Spring 1977), pp.407-423.
Boulay, H., "Essentially Contested Concepts and the Teaching of Political Science", Teaching Political
Science, Vol.4, No.4, (July 1977), pp.423-433.
Care, N.S., "On Fixing Social Concepts", Ethics, Vol.84, No.1, (October 1973), pp.10-21.
Clarke, B., "Eccentrically Contested Concepts", British Journal of Political Science, Vol.9, No.1, (January
1979), pp.122-126.
Collier, D., Hidalgo, F.D., & Maciuceanu, A.O., "Essentially contested concepts: Debates and applications"
(http://www.polisci.berkeley.edu/Faculty/bio/permanent/Collier,D/articles-n-chapters/Collier%20Gallie.pdf),
Journal of Political Ideologies Vol.11, No.3, (October 2006), pp.211-246.
Collier, D. & Mahon, J.E., "Conceptual Stretching Revisited: Adapting Categories in Comparative
Analysis", The American Political Science Review, Vol.87, No.4, (December 1993), pp.845-855.
Connolly, W.E., "Essentially Contested Concepts in Politics", pp.10-44 in Connolly, W.E., The Terms of
Political Discourse, Heath, (Lexington), 1974.
Cooper, D.E., "Lewis on our Knowledge of Conventions", Mind, Vol.86, No.342, (April 1977), pp.256-261.
Davidson, D., "On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme", Proceedings and Addresses of the American
Philosophical Association, Vol.47, (1974), pp.5-20.
Dworkin, R., Taking Rights Seriously: New Impression with a Reply to Critics, Duckworth, (Oxford), 1978.
Dworkin, R., "The Jurisprudence of Richard Nixon", The New York Review of Books, Vol.18, No.8, (May
1972), pp.27-35.[2] (http://www.nybooks.com/articles/10204)
Freeden, M., Ideologies and Political Theory A Conceptual Approach, Oxford University Press, (Oxford)
1998.
Frohock, F.M., "The Structure of Politics", The American Political Science Review, Vol.72, No.3,
(September 1978), pp. 859-870.
Gallie, W.B. (1956b), "Art as an Essentially Contested Concept", The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol.6, No.23,
(April 1956), pp.97-114.
Gallie, W.B.(1956a), "Essentially Contested Concepts", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol.56,
(1956), pp.167-198.
Gallie, W.B., "Essentially Contested Concepts", pp. 157-191 in Gallie, W.B., Philosophy and the Historical
Understanding, Chatto & Windus, (London), 1964.
Gallie, W.B., "What Makes a Subject Scientific?", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol.8,
No.30, (August 1957), pp.118-139.
Garver, E., "Essentially Contested Concepts: The Ethics and Tactics of Argument", Philosophy and Rhetoric,
Vol.23, No.4, (1990), pp.251-270.
Garver, E., "Paradigms and Princes", Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Vol.17, No.1, (March 1987),
pp.21-47.
Garver, E., "Rhetoric and Essentially Contested Arguments", Philosophy and Rhetoric, Vol.11, No.3,
(Summer 1978), pp.156-172.

8 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

Gellner, E., "The Concept of a Story", Ratio, Vol.9, No.1, (June 1967), pp.49-66.
Gerring, J., "What Makes a Concept Good? A Criterial Framework for Understanding Concept Formation in
the Social Sciences", Polity, Vol.31, No.3, (Spring 1999), pp.357-393.
Gilbert, M., "Notes on the Concept of a Social Convention", New Literary History, Vol.14, No.2, (Winter
1983), pp.225-251.
Gingell, J. & Winch, C., "Essentially Contested Concepts", pp.88-89 in Gingell, J. & Winch, C., Key
Concepts in the Philosophy of Education, Routledge, (London), 1999.
Grafstein, R., "A Realist Foundation for Essentially Contested Political Concepts", The Western Political
Quarterly, Vol.41, No.1, (March 1988), pp.9-28.
Gray, J., "On Liberty, Liberalism and Essential Contestability", British Journal of Political Science, Vol.8,
No.4, (October 1978), pp.385-402.
Gray, J., "Political Power, Social Theory, and Essential Contestability", pp.75-101 in Miller, D. & Siedentop,
L., The Nature of Political Theory, Clarendon Press, (Oxford), 1983.
Gray, J.N., "On the Contestability of Social and Political Concepts", Political Theory, Vol.5, No.3, (August
1977), pp.331-348.
Hampshire, S., Thought and Action, Chatto and Windus, (London), 1965.
Hrlin, M. & Sundberg, P., "Taxonomy and Philosophy of Names", Biology and Philosophy, Vol.13, No.2,
(April 1998), pp.233-244.
Hart, H.L.A., The Concept of Law, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1961.
Jacobs, M., Sustainable Development as a Contested Concept, pp.21-45 in Dobson, A., Fairness and
Futurity: Essays on Environmental Sustainability and Social Justice, Oxford University Press, (Oxford),
2006.
Jamieson, D., David Lewis on Convention, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol.5, No.1, (September
1975), pp.73-81.
Kekes, J., "Essentially Contested Concepts: A Reconsideration", Philosophy and Rhetoric, Vol.10, No.2,
(Spring 1977), pp.71-89.
Khatchadourian, H., "Vagueness", The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol.12, No.47, (April 1962), pp.138-152.
Lewis, D., Convention, Blackwell, (Oxford), 2002 [first published 1969].
Lewis, D., Convention: A Reply to Jamieson, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol.6, No.1, (March 1976),
pp.113-120.
Lucy, W.N.R., "Rights, Values, and Controversy", Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, Vol.5, No.2,
(July 1992), pp.195-213.
Lukes, S., "A Reply to K.I. Macdonald", British Journal of Political Science, Vol.7, No.3, (July 1977),
pp.418-419.
Lukes, S., Power: A Radical View, Macmillan, (London), 1974.
MacIntyre, A., "The Essential Contestability of Some Social Concepts", Ethics, Vol.84, No.1, (October
1973), pp.1-9.
Mason, A., "On Explaining Political Disagreement: The Notion of an Essentially Contested Concept",
Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, Vol.33, No.1, (March 1990), pp.81-98.
Mason, A., "The Notion of an Essentially Contested Concept", pp.47-68 in Mason, A., Explaining Political
Disagreement, Cambridge University Press, (Cambridge), 1993.
McKnight, C., "Medicine as an Essentially Contested Concept", Journal of Medical Ethics, Vol.29, No.4,
(August 2003), pp.261-262.
Miller, D., "Linguistic Philosophy and Political Theory", pp.35-51 in Miller, D. & Siedentop, L., The Nature
of Political Theory, Clarendon Press, (Oxford), 1983.
Nielsen, K., "On Rationality and Essentially Contested Concepts", Communication and Cognition, Vol.16,
No.3, (1983), pp.269-281.
Perry, T.D., "Contested Concepts and Hard Cases", Ethics, Vol.88, No.1, (October 1977), pp.20-35.
Postema, G.J., "Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law", The Journal of Legal Studies,
Vol.11, No.1, (January 1982), pp.165-203.
Rawls, J., A Theory of Justice, Oxford University Press, (Oxford), 1971.
Rhodes, M.R., Coercion: A Nonevaluative Approach, Rodopi, (Amsterdam), 2000.
Rorty, R., Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press, (Princeton), 1979.
Schaper, E, "Symposium: About Taste (I)", British Journal of Aesthetics, Vol.6, No.1, (January 1966),
pp.55-67.
Smith, K., "Mutually Contested Concepts and Their Standard General Use", Journal of Classical Sociology,
Vol.2, No.3, (1 November 2002), pp.329-343.
Swanton, C., "On the Essential Contestedness of Political Concepts", Ethics, Vol.95, No.4, (July 1985),
pp.811-827.
Waldron, J., "Is the Rule of Law an Essentially Contested Concept (in Florida)?", Law and Philosophy,
Vol.21, No.2, (March 2002), pp.137-164.
Waldron, J., "Vagueness in Law and Language: Some Philosophical Issues", California Law Review, Vol.82,

9 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM
Essentially contested concept - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentially_contested_concept

No.3, (May 1994), pp.509-540.

Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Essentially_contested_concept&


oldid=541735165"
Categories: Concepts in aesthetics Philosophical concepts Philosophy of religion Rhetoric
Social concepts

This page was last modified on 13 September 2013 at 06:27.


Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms
may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy.
Wikipedia is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit
organization.

10 of 10 16/09/13 4:49 PM

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen