Sie sind auf Seite 1von 12

Axiomatic heresy

The non-philosophy of Franois Laruelle

Ray Brassier

There are at least two ways of evaluating philosophical detailed concrete analyses in a way that cannot be
originality. The most obvious is in terms of what a mapped back onto this clumsy form/content schema.
philosopher thinks. As well as proposing novel philo Notwithstanding this clumsiness, however, and the
sophical theses concerning the nature of being or truth ease with which exceptions and counter-examples
or knowledge, a philosopher may produce new sorts of can be summoned, this admittedly simplistic schema
claim bearing on history, art, morality, politics, and so remains useful if only because it provides us with
on. Another way of evaluating originality is in terms a basic frame in terms of which to begin gauging
of how a philosopher thinks. There are philosophers the originality of a thinker who has a serious claim
whose most conspicuous claim to innovation resides to being the most important unknown philosopher
not so much in what they think but rather in how they working in Europe today: Franois Laruelle.1
think. They propose a fundamental change in the way What makes Laruelle so singular is that he may
philosophy is done a revolutionary break, a new well be the rst European philosopher in whose work
beginning. Descartes, Kant, Hegel and Husserl are substantive innovation has been wholeheartedly sacri
perhaps the most celebrated examples, but gures such ced in the name of total formal invention. This is a
as Frege or Russell also deserve a mention. That their polite way of saying that, unlike his more illustrious
putative innovation may, on closer inspection, turn out peers,2 not only does Laruelle not make novel philo
to be pseudo-revolutionary or essentially conservative sophical claims about being or truth or knowledge; he
is irrelevant here. What is relevant is their avowed also has nothing much to say about history, ethics, art
ambition to effect a total transformation in philo or politics or at least nothing that would make any
sophical method, to have recongured both the formal kind of sense outside the parameters of his own sev
means and the substantive aims of philosophizing. erely abstract theoretical apparatus. Those deliciously
Thus, the novelty of what they think is less important substantial titbits with which it is customary for the
than the newness of how they think. Which is to say philosopher to placate the publics appetite for con
that any substantive claims philosophers like this make cretion are entirely lacking in his work. Show me
about history or nature or art or politics can only be an example of an example, and I renounce this book,
appraised in light of the revolutionary innovation they Laruelle once quipped.3
purport to have brought about at the level of the form The truth is that his thought operates at a level of
of philosophical thinking. abstraction which some will nd debilitating, others
It will be objected that this is an entirely supercial exhilarating. Those who believe formal invention
distinction and that the canonical philosophers in should be subordinated to substantive innovation will
the European tradition combine both dimensions of undoubtedly nd Laruelles work rebarbative. Those
originality in varying proportions: their work marries who believe that untethering formal invention from
a greater or lesser degree of formal inventiveness to the constraints of substantive innovation and thereby
a greater or lesser degree of substantive innovation. transforming the latter remains a philosophically
And of course Hegelians or Deleuzeans will be quick worthy challenge, may well nd Laruelles work invigor
to point out that in Hegel or Deleuze we have formal ating. Regardless of the response whether it be one of
invention and substantive innovation bound together repulsion or fascination Laruelle remains indifferent.
in perfect equipoise. Heideggerians or Derrideans Abstraction is a price he is more than willing to pay
will be equally quick to point out that Heidegger in exchange for a methodological innovation which
or Derrida wed formidable abstract inventiveness to promises to enlarge the possibilities of conceptual

24 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


invention far beyond the resources of philosophical unintelligible to Euclidian geometers.4 Thus, Laruelle
novelty. suggests that the non in the expression non-phil
Thus, Laruelles importance can be encapsulated osophy be understood as akin to the non in the
in a single claim: the claim to have discovered a new expression non-Euclidian geometry: not as a negation
way of thinking. By new, of course, Laruelle means or denial of philosophy, but as suspending a specic
philosophically unprecedented. But what Laruelle structure (the philosophical equivalent of Euclids fth
means by philosophically unprecedented is not what axiom concerning parallels) which Laruelle sees as
philosophical revolutionaries like Descartes, Kant, constitutive of the traditional practice of philosophy.
Hegel or Husserl meant by it. Laruelle prefers heresy New possibilities of thought become available once
to revolution. Where philosophical revolution involves that structure has been suspended and non-philosophy
a reformation of philosophy for the ultimate benet of is an index of those philosophically unenvisageable
philosophy itself and a philosophical stake in what possibilities.
philosophy should be doing heresy involves a use Consequently, if non-philosophy can be contrasted
of philosophy in the absence of any philosophically to the postmodern pragmatists supermarket trolley
vested interest in providing a normative denition of approach to philosophy, where the philosophical con
philosophy. This is not to say that Laruelles heretical sumers personal predilections provide the sole crite
use of philosophy is anchored in a refusal to dene rion for choosing between competing philosophies, and
philosophy; were that the case, there would be nothing where the academy now gures as a sort of intellectual
to distinguish it from cynical Rortian pragmatism. superstore, it is not as yet another theoretical novelty
On the contrary, what makes the Laruellean heresy the latest fad, the next big thing but as a means
interesting is the way it provides a philosophically dis of turning the practice of philosophy itself into an
interested which is to say non-normative denition exercise in perpetual invention.
of the essence of philosophy. How is such a practice possible? Why should it be
Like the revolutionary, the heretic refuses to accept necessary? And what worth does this enlargement of
any denition of philosophy rooted in an appeal to possibility for thought have? These are the questions
the authority of philosophical tradition. But unlike we propose to examine in what follows.
the revolutionary, who more often than not overturns
tradition in order to reactivate philosophys supposedly Philosophy as decision
originary but occluded essence, the heretic proceeds We must begin by considering the rst of several of
on the basis of an indifference which suspends tradi Laruelles controversial claims: that there is a single,
tion and establishes a philosophically disinterested transhistorical invariant operative in every attempt to
denition of philosophys essence, or, as Laruelle philosophize, whether it be by Hume or Heidegger,
prefers to say, identity. This disinterested identication Descartes or Derrida. Laruelle calls this invariant the
of philosophy results in what Laruelle calls a non- philosophical decision. The structure of decision is a
philosophical use of philosophy: a use of philosophy formal syntax governing the possibilities of philoso
that remains constitutively foreign to the norms and phizing. Yet it remains unrecognized by philosophers
aims governing the properly philosophical practice of themselves; not through a lack of reexive scrupulous
philosophy. And in fact, non-philosophy is Laruelles ness on their part but precisely because of it. It is
name for the philosophically unprecedented or hereti philosophys hyper-reexivity that prevents it from
cal practice of philosophy he has invented. identifying its own decisional form. Decision cannot
Yet despite its name, this is neither an anti-phil be grasped reexively because it is the constitutively
osophy nor yet another variant on the well-worn reexive element of philosophizing. The identication
end of philosophy theme. It is not the latest variety of decision as essence of philosophizing presupposes a
of deconstruction or one more manifestation of post- non-reexive or (in Laruellese) non-thetic perspective
philosophical pragmatism. Non-philosophy is a theor on the thetic reexivity which is the very element of
etical practice of philosophy proceeding by way of philosophy.
transcendental axioms and producing theorems which This is why non-philosophy is not metaphilosophical
are philosophically uninterpretable. Uninterpretable philosophy is already metaphilosophical through its
because Laruelle insists and reactions to his work constitutive reexivity or specularity: every philosophy
certainly seem to bear him out non-philosophy is worthy of the name harbours (whether implicitly or
constitutively unintelligible to philosophers, in the same explicitly) a philosophy of philosophy. Non-philosophy
way that non-Euclidian geometries are constitutively is not a philosophy of philosophy but a heterogeneous

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 25


practice of philosophy; one shorn of the dimension (Deleuze) a (dis)joining that remains co-constituted
of specular reexivity which is intrinsic to decision. by the two terms it is supposed to condition and so
And once again, since philosophical specularity is a implicitly contained within both. Because it is posited
function of the structure of decision, the identication as given in and through the immediate distinction
of the decisional structure which conditions that specu between conditioned datum and conditioning faktum
larity is only possible from a non-specular, which is the very distinction which it is supposed to constitute
to say non-decisional, perspective on philosophy. But this structure presupposes itself as given in and
in order to understand how this non-philosophical through the datum which it constitutes, and posits itself
perspective is not only possible but already operative as a priori condition, or givenness, in and through the
for the non-philosopher, we have to understand how faktum which conditions that datum.
decision operates. Thus, because the disjoining of condition and
Decision minimally consists in an act of scis conditioned is simultaneously extrinsic and intrinsic
sion or separation dividing two terms: a conditioned to their joining, all the moments of a philosophical
(but not necessarily perceptual or empirical) datum decision are self-positing (or auto-positional) and
and its condition as an a priori (but not necessarily self-presupposing (or auto-donational): a conditioned
rational) faktum, both of which are posited as given datum is given by being posited a priori through some
in and through a synthetic unity wherein condition conditioning faktum which is in turn only articulated
and conditioned, datum and faktum, are conjoined. as conditioning in so far as it has already been pre
Thus the philosopher posits a structure of articula supposed through that datum, and so on. There is a
tion which immediately binds and distinguishes the sense in which the structure of decision is circular in
conditioned datum that which is given whether that it already presupposes itself in whatever phenom
it be perceptual, phenomenological, linguistic, social enon or set of phenomena it articulates. Hence the
or historical, and its condition its givenness as an suspicion that philosophy manages to interpret every
a priori faktum through which that datum is given: thing while explaining nothing, because the structure
for example, sensibility, subjectivity, language, society, of the explanans, decision, is already presupposed in
history. the explanandum, the phenomenon or phenomena to
What is crucial here is the way in which such a be explained. Yet strictly speaking the structure of
structure is immediately independent of, yet inseparable decision is not so much that of a circle as that of a
from, the two terms which it simultaneously connects Moebius strip but one where the twist that joins the
and differentiates. It is a basically fractional structure inner and outer faces of the strip and allows them to
comprising two differentiated terms and their differ ow smoothly into one another is also a fracture, scis
ence as a third term that is simultaneously intrinsic sion or split whose dimensionality is simultaneously
and extrinsic, immanent and transcendent to those two more and less than, both in excess of and subtracted
terms. Thus, for any philosophical distinction or dyad, from, the immanent dimensions of the strips opposing
such as transcendental/empirical, subject/substance, surfaces.
being/beings, diffrance/presence, the distinction is This fractional loop, this auto-positional and
simultaneously intrinsic and immanent to the dis auto-donational structure, constitutes philosophys
tinguished terms and extrinsic and transcendent in inherently reexive or specular character. It guar
so far as it is supposed to remain constitutive of antees that everything is potentially philosophizable,
the difference between the terms themselves. For the which is to say, possible grist for the decisional mill.
division is inseparable from a moment of immanent Thus, if philosophizing (especially in the continen
indivision guaranteeing the unity-in-differentiation of tal manner) remains a loose-knit grouping of inter
the dyadic coupling. pretative strategies rather than a rigorous theoretical
The result is a structure wherein the coupling of praxis, it is because decisional specularity ensures
related terms is also their disjoining for example: the world remains philosophys mirror. Philosophiz
pure synthesis as that which (dis)joins transcendental ing the world becomes a pretext for philosophys own
and empirical (Kant); self-relating negativity as that interminable self-interpretation. And since interpreta
which (dis)joins subject and substance (Hegel); hori tion is a function of talent rather than rigour, the
zonal ekstasis as that which (dis)joins being and beings plurality of mutually incompatible yet unfalsiable
(Heidegger); diffrance as that which (dis)joins archi- interpretations merely perpetuates the uncircum
text and signied presence (Derrida); indi-differ scribable ubiquity of philosophys auto-encompass
ent/ciation as that which (dis)joins virtual and actual ing specularity. Absolute specularity breeds innite

26 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


interpretation such is the norm for the philosophical (what Laruelle calls the Stranger-subject) who now
practice of thought. effectuates the unilateralizing identity of the term Y
while philosophy instantiates the unilateralized differ
Unilateral duality ence of the term X as it distinguishes itself from Y. Con
Moreover, if everything is philosophizable, that sequently, it is not non-philosophy that distinguishes
which most urgently needs to be philosophized for itself unilaterally from philosophy but philosophy that
post-Kantian European philosophy is the difference distinguishes itself unilaterally from non-philosophy.
between philosophy and its other(s); which is to say, But in non-philosophical thought, the supplementary
the difference between the philosophical and the extra- dimension of specular reexivity through which the
philosophical. Continental philosophy lives off this philosopher is able to oversee the relation between X
difference between itself and its specular, imaginary and Y is effectively reduced, rendered inoperative, so
other(s): science, religion, the mystical, the ethical, the that the unilateral relation between X and Y has itself
political, the aesthetic or even surely a symptom of become unilateralized, deprived of its transcendent,
terminal desperation the ordinary. It is because bilateral circumscription via the subject of philosophy
philosophy enjoys a constitutive relation to the extra- and leaving only the unilateralizing identity of Y
philosophical, however characterized, that the non qua subject of non-philosophy and the unilateralized
in Laruelles non-philosophy indexes a suspension of difference between X and Y qua philosophy. Y, the
philosophys all-encompassing specularity, rather than subject of non-philosophy, is now radically indifferent
a naive attempt to demarcate or delimit it which to the difference between X and Y, philosophy and
would merely reiterate the decisional gesture. non-philosophy.
Thus, whereas the relation between the philosophical This total structure is what Laruelle means by
and the extra-philosophical is constitutively dialectical unilateral duality: a structure comprising non-rela
(where dialectical is taken to mean differential in tion (the subject of non-philosophy as unilateralizing
the broadest possible sense), and since the dialectical identity) and the relation of relation and non-relation
relationality championed by philosophy is invariably (philosophy as unilateralized difference between X and
one of bilateral reciprocity (following the circular Y). Unlike philosophical unilaterality, which always
logic of decision), the relation between philosophy ultimately has two sides, the unilateral duality which
and non-philosophy is one of what Laruelle calls lies at the heart of non-philosophy is a duality with
unilateral duality unilateral duality rather than only one side: the side of philosophy as difference
just unilaterality. This is a crucial technical nuance. (relation) between X (relation) and Y (non-relation).
The concept of unilateral duality lies at the very Accordingly, if the apex of decisions dialectical specu
heart of Laruelles non-philosophical enterprise and larity consists in articulating the relation between the
it is important to distinguish it from the notion of philosophical and extra-philosophical as relation of
unilateral relation, which is well known in philosophy: relation and non-relation, then the unilateral duality
X distinguishes itself unilaterally from Y without Y as non-dialectical relation between philosophy and
distinguishing itself from X in return. Various Neo- non-philosophy has to be understood in terms of the
Platonists, Hegel, Heidegger, Derrida and Deleuze all non-relation of relation and non-relation. Once again,
make (implicit) use of this logic of unilaterality in unlike the philosophical dialectic, non-philosophy
different ways. But in philosophy, the unilaterality of effectuates a unilateral duality with only one side
X is always reinscribed in a bilateral relation with Y at the side of philosophy as all-encompassing relation
the supplementary meta-level available to the subject ality. Since every philosophical decision is always
of philosophy, who enjoys a position of overview vis-- two-sided that is, dialectical the non-philosophical
vis X and Y and continues to see both terms in relation unilateralization of decision cannot be dialectically
to one another at the same time. Thus, Xs unilaterality reinscribed.
relative to Y is only operative at the level of X and
Y, not for the philosopher who exempts himself from The axiomatic suspension of decision
this immanent relation through transcendence. The What is innovative about twentieth-century European
philosopher is always a spectator who views everything philosophys preoccupation with alterity or difference,5
(terms and relations) from above. This is what Laruelle Laruelle suggests, is its attempt to use the latter as
means by specularity. a way of acknowledging and mobilizing the struc
By way of contrast, in the non-philosophical logic tural blind spot in decision, the moment of absolute
of unilateral duality, it is the subject of non-philosophy division as absolute indivision, the fractional surplus

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 27


or indivisible remainder that (dis)joins decision and thinking for which philosophical decision qua innite
enables philosophical reexivity while disabling phil reexivity encompassing and integrating its own limits
osophys attempt to grasp the non-specular root of has already been suspended through an act of axi-
its own specularity. If twentieth-century European omatic positing. But what prevents this axiomatic
philosophy has consistently characterized that condi suspension of decisional specularity from amounting
tion as an aporia, caesura or unobjectiable excess to yet another decisional scission between the philo
(e.g. diffrance, non-identity, Unterschied, event, other, sophical and the extra-philosophical is the fact that it
real, and so on), it is because it has tried to grasp is effected on the basis of an immanence which has
the non-reexive root of reexivity using reexive not itself been decided about: an immanence which has
means. Hence the latters aporetic or intra-decisional not been posited and presupposed as given through a
characterization as condition of (im)possibility for transcendent act of decision, but axiomatically posited
philosophy; as an unnameable traumatic kernel that as already given, independently of every perceptual or
resists or shatters conceptualization. intentional presupposition, as well as every gesture of
For Laruelle, philosophys assumption that deci ontological or phenomenological position. It is posited
sional reexivity is the only available paradigm for as already given and as already determining its own
abstract thought, and that specular abstraction is positing.
the only possible kind of abstraction, results in this Thus, this non-decisional immanence, which allows
aporetic characterization of the non-thetic root of itself to be posited as already given without decisional
decision. Yet a non-specular paradigm of theoretical positing, is an immanence that does not even need
abstraction already exists, Laruelle insists. Moreover, to be liberated from decisional transcendence: it is
it exists precisely in that form of thinking which precisely as that which is already separated (without-
continental philosophy has consistently belittled separation) from the decisional co-constitution of given
and demeaned as un-thinking: the axiomatic. Since and givenness, immanence and transcendence, that
philosophy cannot conceive of a thought operating it conditions its own positing as already given. Con
without recourse to the fractured mirror of decision, sequently, this non-decisional immanence is not the
since it equates thinking with innite specularity and Deleuzean plane of immanence, which is at once pre
interminable interpretation, it cannot imagine any supposed as pre-philosophically given and constructed
thought worthy of the name that would be neither or posited as given through the philosophical concept,6
specular nor interpretative. Yet axiomatic abstraction in accordance with the decisional co-constitution of
provides the paradigm for precisely such a thought: given and givenness, positing and presupposition.
one which is non-specular, non-reexive. This non- Where decision renders positing and presupposition
thetic or immanently performative thought anchors co-constitutive the positing of a presupposition and
itself in the non-reexive root of decision by positing the presupposition of the posited (as in Hegels exem
it axiomatically as its own enabling condition, rather plary analysis of the logic of reection in the Science
than trying to grasp it decisionally and failing (it of Logic) the non-decisional axiom separates them in
is this failure which results in the aporetic charac such a way as to render the immanence it has posited
terization of decisions non-thetic root as unthink determining for its own description as already posited
able caesura or obstacle to conceptualization). What (without-presupposition). By the same token, the axiom
is an obstacle for decisional conceptualization an renders the immanence it has presupposed determin-
obstacle whose quasi-insurmountable status fuels the ing for its own description as already presupposed
postmodern pathos of terminal exhaustion provides (without-positing).
a new basis for axiomatic invention. It is a question of Consequently, unlike Michel Henrys phenomen
positing the non-thetic root of decision axiomatically, ologized version of radical immanence,7 which has to
without presupposing it via decision. Or (which comes absolve itself from reexive specularity in order to count
to the same thing) of presupposing it via an axiom as non-thetic, Laruelles non-decisional immanence
rather than positing it via a decision. is not co-constituted by decision. Non-philosophical
For Laruelle, a thinking of this sort axiomatic or immanence is foreclosed rather than opposed to deci
non-philosophical thinking is not merely possible but sion which is to say: radically indifferent to the
real, which is to say radically performative (we will dyadic distinction between positing and presupposing,
have more to say about this performativity below). immanence and transcendence, given and givenness, as
Thus, if the non in non-philosophy is not a negation well as to every other decisional dyad. In other words,
of philosophical reexivity it is because it indexes a it is radically indifferent to all dyadic couplings of the

28 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


form: thinkable/unthinkable, decidable/undecidable, non-decisional thinking operates on the basis of an
determinable/undeterminable. irreversible duality between them, so that immanence
It should now be easier to see why a certain obvious unilaterally determines its own transcendent concep
philosophical objection to the non-philosophical pos tual description, without being determined by it in
iting of radical immanence misses the point. This return.
objection, which tries to argue that the axiomatic Third, the separation between the decisional and
positing of immanence as non-decisional reinscribes non-decisional is not itself dyadic, which is to say
it in the dyad decision/non-decision, thereby allowing decisional. To maintain that is to fail to acknowledge
it to become co-constituted by decision, is mistaken that for non-philosophy that separation is axiomatically
on three counts. posited as already in effect without recourse to deci
First, whereas philosophical specularity operates sion, in accordance with the nature of radical imma
by assuming a fundamental reciprocity or revers nence as separate-without-separation and determining
ibility between conceptual description and ontological its own description as already-separate. Accordingly, it
constitution, non-specular or non-philosophical think is imperative that we appreciate the peculiar radicality
ing does not. It operates on the basis of a radically of the manner in which Laruelles non separates
irreversible or unilateral duality between the axiomatic the decisional from the non-decisional. It is not two
positing of immanence and its description as already distinct things that are being separated. If it were, the
posited. Thus, the non-philosophical characterization non-philosopher would indeed still be operating within
the ambit of decision. What this non separates is the
of radical immanence as already given does not con
realm of separability in its entirety (decision) from
stitute it as given. Radical immanence is ontolog
the inseparable (immanence) as that which is posited
ically foreclosed. It remains non-constitutable, not
as already separated prior to the need for a separat
because it opposes or resists constitution, but because
ing decision. In other words, the non-philosophical
it is indifferent to the dyadic distinction between des
positing of immanence as already given axiomatically
cription and constitution. It is the already constituted
separates decisional separation (scission, distinction,
determining its own description as constituted. Thus,
differentiation, division, dialectic) from the inseparable
there is no dyadic distinction between the axiomatic
as that which is already separated, independently of
positing of immanence as given and its description as
any separating decision.
posited. Instead, there is a unilateral duality, which is
Of course, it is intrinsic to the character of decisional
to say a duality with only one side: that of the des
thinking that it cannot acknowledge this axiomatic
cription which is determined by the positing without
separation between the decisional and the non-deci
determining that positing in return. This unilateral or
sional as something which is already realized, already
non-decisional duality, whereby what is axiomatically
achieved for non-philosophy. Decisional specularity
given determines its own description as given, guaran cannot countenance the axiomatic positing of a radi
tees that the non-philosophical description of radical cally autonomous, non-specular immanence. However,
immanence as already posited is adequate to it in the for Laruelle, far from indicating confusion on the part
last instance, without being constitutive of it. Adequa- of philosophers, this incapacity is symptomatic of
tion without correspondence: such is the hallmark philosophys necessary resistance to non-philosophy.
of truth for a non-philosophical axiomatic shorn of Far from being an unfortunate, arbitrary expression of
the specularity that envelops truth as correspondence, philosophical prejudice, this resistance is wholly and
coherence or unveiling (aletheia). legitimately necessary. It is structurally intrinsic to
Second, that radical immanence is foreclosed to decision rather than empirically contingent. In other
constitution does not mean that it is unconceptual words, it is de jure rather than de facto. Decisional
izable. On the contrary, it becomes limitlessly con thinking is programmed to insist that the axiomatic
ceptualizable on the basis of any given conceptual positing of immanence amounts to yet another instance
material precisely in so far as it already determines its of decisional division. It is obliged to reduce the axi
own description as adequate to it in the last instance, omatic suspension of decision according to immanence
without any of these conceptual characterizations or to an intra-decisional opposition to decision, or an
descriptions becoming co-constitutive or co-determin anti-decisional annihilation of decision. And rather
ing for it. Thus, where decisional thinking posits and than being a problem or obstacle for non-philosophy,
presupposes a reversible equivalence between imma this philosophical resistance is precisely what non-
nence and its transcendent conceptual characterization, philosophy requires in order to operate. The decisional

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 29


resistance to radical immanence provides non-phil tion. In Althusser, the philosophical dyad infrastruc
osophy with the occasional cause which it needs in ture/superstructure entails that the last instance remains
order to begin working. It is what initiates non-philo reciprocally co-constituted by what it determines, in
sophical thinking in the rst place. There would be accordance with the bilateral logic of decision. For
no non-philosophy without it. Non-philosophy is the Laruelle, however, the last instance is separate-without-
conversion of philosophys specular resistance to non- separation from the decisional logic which it unilat
thetic immanence into a form of non-specular thinking erally determines. Determination-in-the-last-instance
determined according to that immanence. consists in the non-philosophical transformation of
the unitary syntax of decision qua transcendental syn
Determination in the last instance thesis or One-of-the-dyad into a unilateral duality
Thus, non-philosophy works with philosophical whereby the One (i.e. identity or immanence) now
decision. It does not seek to replace or supplant it. unilateralizes the philosophical dyad (i.e. difference
Philosophical decision is the object of non-phil or transcendence) not directly, since it is indifferent
osophy better still, its material. But it is a matter to decision, but through the intermediary of the non-
of using decision non-philosophically. Consequently, philosophical subject who has posited immanence as
besides positing immanence as ultimately determining determining and decision as determinable. The struc
instance for non-decisional thought, the non-philo ture of the non-philosophical subject is simply that
sophical axiom posits decisional resistance to that of the unilateral duality: a duality with only one side
positing as something which is also already given that of decision as transcendent difference between
non-decisionally as a determinable material; a contin the decisional and the non-decisional. The other,
gent occasion that can be determined in accordance non-side of this duality is not immanence, whose
with immanences foreclosure to decision. Following radical indifference precludes any direct determination
an axiomatically given immanence as determining of philosophy on its part, but the non-philosophical
instance, the second axiomatically given factor for subject itself as unilateralizing instance effectuating
non-philosophy is decisional resistance to immanence immanences indifference. Since philosophical resist
as determinable occasion. ance to non-philosophy occasions non-philosophy, the
Accordingly, non-philosophy is the coordination of non-philosophical subject effectively unilateralizes (or
two causes: immanence as necessary cause in-the- dualyses) its own dyadic inscription at the hands of
last-instance and decisional resistance as occasional philosophical resistance. Non-philosophical thinking
cause. Non-philosophy is simply the determination consists in converting philosophys bilateral resistance
of the latter by the former: it is the taking into con to non-philosophy into a unilateral duality: not the
sideration of decisional resistance to immanence as unilateral duality of immanence and decision, which
an occasional material to be determined in accord does not exist since the former is radically indifferent
ance with immanence as cause in-the-last-instance. to decision, but rather the unilateral duality effectuated
Thus, the minimal but denitive coordinates for the by the subject of non-philosophy in so far as it is
non-philosophical axiomatic are: immanence qua now the organon for determining decisional resistance
radically necessary condition; decisional resistance according to immanence.
qua occasional cause; and immanences determina Obviously, the role played by this non-philosophical
tion of decision as transcendental effectuation of that subject bears little resemblance to that played by the
necessary determining condition for that determinable philosophical subject. It is no longer the phenomeno
material. logical subject, whether the latter be construed in terms
We are now in a position to understand in what of intentional consciousness or being-in-the-world. But
sense the new way of thinking initiated by Laruelle nor is it the subject as caesura, self-relating negativity.
is supposed to be philosophically unprecedented. The It is neither the explicitly reexive, self-conscious
syntax of non-philosophical thought is that of determi subject, nor the pre-reexive, unconscious subject,
nation-in-the-last-instance as unilateral duality whereby who is merely the obverse of the latter and therefore
the non-philosophical subject determines philosophical implicitly enveloped by decisional reexivity. It is
decision. Like much in Laruelle, determination in the simply a function: the transcendental function which
last instance is an expression with an explicit philo non-philosophy effectuates for philosophy on the basis
sophical lineage in this case, Althusserian. But like of immanence as real invariant and decision as occa
every other philosophical expression used by Laruelle, sional variable. The subject as transcendental function
it has been subjected to non-philosophical transforma is a radically disembodied, excarnate, non-conscious

30 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


subject performing a set of quasi-algorithmic opera again). More exactly, the syntax of decision enacts or
tions upon a philosophical material by determining-it- performs its own hallucinatory reality in what effec
in-the-last-instance. These operations involve neither tively amounts to an operation of auto-deduction with
interpretation nor reection: they are blind, automatic, a tripartite structure: decision is at once an empirically
mechanical, which is to say non-thetic. Consequently, conditioned enunciation; an enunciated faktum condi
the non-philosophical subject is simply an axiomatiz tioning that enunciation; and nally the transcendental
ing organon, a transcendental computer, but one which synthesis of enunciated condition and condition of
Laruelle prefers to characterize as a uni-maton rather enunciation as event of thought. This is the complex
than as an auto-maton.8 This is a subject which has been internal architecture proper to the decisional autos
denitively purged of all its philosophical privileges as as self-positing/self-donating circle or doublet.9
locus of reection and reduced to the unilateralizing For Laruelle, the trouble with this performative
structure of determination-in-the-last-instance. Thus, dimension of philosophical activity, this decisional
for non-philosophy unilateralization is subjectivation auto-enactment, lies not in its performativity (far
and subjectivation is determination: the non-philo from it) but in the way in which the latter invariably
sophical subject determines decision by converting operates on the basis of an unstated set of constative
the philosophical dyad which provides its material assumptions which themselves only ever become per
support into a theorem that is at least temporarily formatively legitimated. In other words, philosophy
philosophically uninterpretable because it cannot
consists in the co-constitution of theory and prac
be dyadically circumscribed or decided. However,
tice: it is a theory whose cognitive possibilities are
unlike deconstruction, where aporia or undecidability
compromised through an extraneous set of practical
is unleashed merely in order to effect a destabilization
exigencies, and a practice whose performative capaci
of metaphysical conceptuality, the non-philosophical
ties are hindered by a needlessly restrictive system of
subjects unilateralization of decision has a positive
theoretical assumptions.10 The philosopher, in effect,
and expansive rather than negative and delimiting
never says what he/she is really doing, nor does what
effect on philosophy: a non-philosophical theorem
he/she is really saying.
ultimately forces philosophy to expand its available
Laruelle objects to this co-constitution of theory
decisional resources by obliging it to invent a new
and practice, constative and performative, on the
dyad in order to decide reintegrate the unilateral
grounds that it needlessly constricts both the possi
duality encapsulated in that theorem.
bilities of saying and of doing, of theory and of
practice. Moreover, simply to afrm the diffrance
The non-philosophical identity of theory between theory and practice, constative and perfor
and practice mative, is complacently to reafrm philosophical
Determination or unilateralization is not just what decisions embroilment in its own self-presupposing,
the subject of non-philosophy does, it is what he/ self-perpetuating structure.
she is. Performativity is the hallmark of thinking By positing radical immanence as already-per-
in accordance with immanence. It provides the cri formed, as performed-without-performance, the non-
terion for an important contrast between the self- philosophical subject operationalizes the non-decisional
sufcient or philosophical practice of philosophy and essence of performativity.11 It releases the identity
its non-philosophical practice. Philosophys specular (without synthesis or unity) of theory and practice
self-sufciency means that the philosophical practice by converting their decisional co-constitution into a
of philosophy is not really a theoretical practice but unilateral duality whereby the subject performatively
rather an empirical activity whose claim to theoretical unilateralizes the dyadic synthesis of saying and
legitimacy is only ever assured through its perform doing. Thus, the non-philosophical subject unleashes
ance. Thus, philosophy is a game, the rules of which the radically performative character of theory as well
are always effectively guaranteed by virtue of the as the rigorously cognitive character of practice. Non-
operation through which their stipulation is enacted. philosophy is at once a theoretical practice and a
Moreover, the philosopher reinscribes his/her own performative theory. Moreover, it is precisely in so far
philosophical activity within the decisional mirroring as the non-philosopher is already operating accord
which renders that activity co-constitutive of the real ing to immanence as already-performed that he or
at a level that is simultaneously ontic-empirical and she cannot help but say what he/she does and do as
ontological-transcendental (the decisional hybrid once he/she says.

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 31


The reality and contingency of non- Yet since non-philosophy only exists as immanent
philosophy axiomatic determination of philosophys resistance to
Consequently, for Laruelle, non-philosophy is more immanent determination, does this de-speculariza
than just a possibility. It is real more radically real tion have any binding force for philosophy as such?
than any positivity or effectivity gauged philosophic Could something like a non-philosophical injunction
ally in terms of empirical concretion or actuality. The to change how one thinks become imperative for
question of its possibility is a philosophical one: it philosophers?
continues to assume the validity of the philosophical Laruelle himself would be the rst to admit that
problematization of something that is no longer a there is nothing necessary about non-philosophy.
problem for non-philosophy; something that is simply There is no obligation for the philosopher to switch
out of the question for it radical immanence as from the philosophical to the non-philosophical
the real root of decision and hence as the answer to posture. Unlike philosophical revolution, whose
every philosophical question. More specically, radical raison dtre stems from a vision of the true tasks
immanence is the solution that precedes the possibility of philosophy, Laruelles axiomatic heresy cannot be
of decisional problematization. philosophically legitimated by invoking an intolerable
Clearly, however, if radical immanence is the shortfall between what philosophy has been doing and
non-philosophical real, it is no longer the real as what it should be doing. While the conceptual preoc
philosophically characterized in terms of percep cupations which after long and arduous detours
tion, consciousness, materiality, production, power, led Laruelle to his discovery have a venerable
the social, and so on. Nor is it the real as being, philosophical pedigree, they cannot be used to lend
diffrance, Ur-grund, noumenon, thing-in-itself, will- it an aura of necessity. Thus, from a philosophical
to-power, self-relating negativity, Unterschied, non- perspective, the non-philosophical practice of phil
identity, absolute deterritorialization. Instead, it is osophy is neither necessary nor inevitable. Unlike
simply real immanence as utterly empty invariant=X. Heideggerian/Derridean deconstruction, which lays
This is an invariant that does not resist philosophy claims to an irrecusable historial necessity for itself
but is indifferent to it, and hence can be rendered the uncircumventable necessity of deconstructing
axiomatically determining for thought on the basis of the history of metaphysics non-philosophy simply
any philosophical occasion. It is an invariant whose remains an aberrant possibility for the philosopher;
empty transparency does not render it refractory to one whose sole criterion of legitimation resides in an
cognition but on the contrary can be axiomatically efcacy which can only be judged according to the
specied using any philosophical material.
parameters of the practice itself. Since that practice
Thus, the specically Laruellean discovery that
suspends the teleological considerations in terms of
makes non-philosophy effective is that the real is not
which the necessity of a move in the space of con
a philosophical problem: it is positively nothing at all.
ceptual possibilities is usually appraised, Laruelle is
And the fact that the real is no longer a problem for
obliged to deny that philosophers are under any kind
non-philosophy allows for a change in the way one
of obligation to accept the pertinence of his discovery
thinks. Instead of proceeding philosophically from
and begin practising philosophy non-philosophically.
thought to the real, or using philosophy to think the
Interestingly, the very considerations which render
real as difference, or as differing from some other
non-philosophy unproblematically real and immedi
philosophical term, one proceeds non-philosophically
ately operational for the non-philosopher also ensure
from the reals immanent identity to philosophy as
that it remains at a safe remove, safely ensconced in
specular transcendence which strives to split, dis
tinguish or differentiate between the real and some the realm of possibility for the philosopher. Yet the
other term, and then mirror the world through that question remains: what is non-philosophy for? This
difference. Instead of using the mirror of philosophy is a philosophical question, but perhaps one non-phil
to think the transcendence of real objects in the osophy cannot entirely obviate by simply referring
world, non-philosophy uses the immanence of the the questioner to the efciency of non-philosophical
real to de-specularize those objects which philosophy practice. Since the only philosophical legitimacy non-
cocoons in its reexive transcendence. It follows that philosophy can muster is as an arbitrary possibility,
the object of non-philosophy is not the real, which is and since its non-philosophical validity is out of the
never an object, not even an unthinkable one, but the question being a simple matter of efciency is it
philosophical specularization of real objects. possible to frame the question of the worth of Laru

32 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


elles axiomatic heresy without reinscribing the latter constructive? Has Laruelle not retreated from phil
within a philosophical teleology? osophy into something like a mathematized theology
Laruelle himself invokes the desirability of of radical immanence?
enlarging the possibilities of thought as one way The answer to the latter question must, I believe, be
of legitimating non-philosophy. And he also suggests an emphatic No. Unlike philosophers of immanence
that, despite appearances, philosophys privileging of such as Spinoza and Deleuze, Laruelle does not decide
thought has always involved subordinating it to some in favour of immanence (which means against trans
extraneous end (ethical, political, aesthetic, and so cendence) through a philosophical decision which has
on) while simultaneously reappropriating that end for an ethical telos as its ultimate horizon: liberation,
thought, in conformity with the logic of decisional the achievement of beatitude, the intellectual love
co-constitution. Thus, Laruelle seems to imply, thought of God. Although ethics is a philosophical material
has never been an end in itself for philosophy. Non- which can be treated non-philosophically, there can
philosophy, by way of contrast, frees thought from be no ethics of radical immanence and consequently
every end. By curtailing philosophys specular narcis no ethics of non-philosophy.13 The very notion of an
sism, non-philosophy untethers thought from every ethics of immanence is another instance of the way in
decisional telos. which philosophical decision invariably subordinates
Consequently, despite its apparent arbitrariness, immanence to a transcendent teleological horizon. But
Laruelles axiomatic heresy can lay claim to a valid Laruelle is no more interested in subordinating radical
ity for philosophy: the validity of an emancipatory immanence to philosophy than he is in subordinating
gesture as far as the form of thinking itself is con philosophy to radical immanence. Radical immanence
cerned.12 Emancipation, of course, is an eminently is simply not the object of non-philosophy. It is not
philosophical motif. But Laruelle invests it with a even interesting: it is utterly banal, radically trans
non-philosophical valence: philosophical specularity is parent. This is what separates Laruelle from Michel
constrictive because the possibilities of philosophical Henry, whose phenomenology of radical immanence
invention, whether formal or substantive, are already entails an ultimately theological disavowal of phil
delimited in advance by philosophys decisional syntax. osophy. Yet the point, as Laruelle tirelessly repeats,
But only from a non-philosophical vantage point does is not to abandon philosophy in favour of a thought
this constriction become perceptible. Philosophers of immanence, but to use immanence to think phil
themselves are entirely oblivious to it and more than osophy. It is the consequences of thinking philosophy
happy to keep spinning variations on the decisional immanently that are interesting, not thinking imma
theme for centuries to come. If non-specular thinking nence philosophically. Thus, unlike philosophies of
does have a certain binding force for the philosopher absolute immanence such as those of Spinoza, Deleuze
willing to explore its possibility, it simply consists in or Michel Henry, non-philosophy has nothing to say
the impossibility of returning to the circuitous ambit about radical immanence in itself. What it does have
of decisional mirroring having once frequented the something to say about is how immanence provides a
horizonless expanses of mirrorless immanence. new basis for practising philosophy.
Conversely, and in spite of the fact that Laruelle
The price of abstraction has certainly been guilty of encouraging such mis
Nevertheless, there will be many for whom the puni interpretations in the past,14 it would be a mistake to
tive abstraction of Laruelles thought is too high a price see in non-philosophy nothing more than an attempt
to pay for such scanty rewards. Non-philosophy strikes to extend the Kantian critique of metaphysics to the
its more generous detractors that is, those who do whole of philosophy. Unlike Kantian critique, the
not simply dismiss it out of hand as incomprehensible non-philosophical suspension of decision is not guided
gobbledegook as interesting but thoroughly incon by a normative, ethico-juridical telos. Nor can it be
sequential. Unlike Adorno, Heidegger or Derrida, reduced to some sort of post-Derridean variant on
Laruelle does not set out to dismantle metaphysics deconstruction. Unlike deconstruction, the unilateraliz
in a way that could be co-opted for the purposes of ation of decision involves a positive enlargement of
ideological critique. And, unlike Deleuze or Badiou, he the ambit of decision, rather than just an aporetic
does not elaborate a new philosophical system capable interruption.
of incorporating a broad spectrum of contemporary Thus, before hastily dismissing Laruelles work as a
artistic, scientic and social phenomena. But what crypto-theological renunciation of philosophy, a hyper-
is the worth of something that is neither critical nor deconstruction, or even a sterile exercise in meta-philo

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 33


sophical narcissism, it is important to remember that Seuil, Paris, 1976.
although non-philosophy does not have a goal, it does Nietzsche contre Heidegger. Thses pour une politique ni-
etzschenne [Nietzsche contra Heidegger: Theses for a
have a function. And although it cannot be legitimated Nietzschean Politics], Payot, Paris, 1977.
in terms of some transcendent teleological horizon, Le dclin de lcriture [The Decline of Writing], Aubier
non-philosophical practice is for something: it is for Flammarion, Paris, 1977.
Au dela du principe de pouvoir [Beyond the Power Principle],
philosophical decision. Anyone interested in practising
Payot, Paris, 1978.
philosophy should be interested in Laruelles incisive
Philosophie II
exposure of what he calls the theoreticist idealism
Le Prinipe de minorit [The Minority Principle], Aubier,
inherent in the spontaneous philosophical practice of
Paris, 1981.
philosophical decision. Philosophers, Laruelle insists, Une biographie de lhomme ordinaire. Des autorits et des
do not know what they are doing. They are never doing minorities [A Biography of the Ordinary Man: Of Authori-
what they say or saying what they are doing even and ties and Minorities], Aubier, Paris, 1985.
Les Philosophies de la diffrence. Introduction critique [The
especially when they purport to be able to legitimate
Philosophies of Difference: A Critical Introduction], PUF,
their philosophical decisions in terms of some ethical, Paris, 1986.
political or juridical end. The theoreticist idealism Philosophie et non-philosophie [Philosophy and Non-Phil-
inherent in decision is never so subtle and pernicious osophy], Mardaga, Lige/Brussels, 1989.
En tant quun. La non-philosophie xplique au philosophes
as when it invokes the putative materiality of some [As One: Non-Philosophy Explained to Philosophers],
extra-philosophical instance in order to demonstrate its Aubier, Paris, 1991.
pragmatic worth. To condemn Laruelle for excessive Thorie des Identits. Fractalit gnralise et philosophie
articielle [Theory of Identities: Generalized Fractality
abstraction on the grounds that the worth of a phil
and Articial Philosophy], PUF, Paris, 1992.
osophy can only be gauged in terms of its concrete,
Philosophie III
extra-philosophical (e.g. ethical, political or juridical)
Thorie des trangers. Science des hommes, dmocratie,
effects is to ignore the way in which extra-philo
non-psychanalyse [Theory of Strangers: Science of Men,
sophical concretion invariably involves an idealized Democracy, Non-Psychoanalysis], Kim, Paris, 1995.
abstraction that has already been circumscribed by Principes de la non-philosophie [The Principles of Non-Phil-
decision. osophy], PUF, Paris, 1996.
Dictionnaire de la non-philosophie [Dictionary of Non-Phil-
It may be that Laruelles crisp, sharply delineated
osophy], Franois Laruelle et Collaborateurs, Kim, Paris,
mode of abstraction turns out to be far more concrete 1998.
than those nebulous abstractions which philosophers thique de ltranger. Du crime contre lhumanit [Ethics
try to pass off as instances of concretion. In other of the Stranger: Of the Crime Against Humanity], Kim,
Paris, 2000.
words, the criteria for evaluating the worth of non- Introduction au non-marxisme [Introduction to Non-Marx-
philosophys function for philosophy are not available ism], PUF, Paris, 2000.
to philosophers, who know not what they do. In non- Le Christ futur. Une leon dhrsie [The Future Christ: A
Lesson in Heresy], Exils, Paris, 2002.
philosophy, radical axiomatic abstraction gives rise,
not to a system or doctrine inviting assent or dissent,
Notes
but to an immanent methodology whose function for
1. Born in 1937, Laruelle is Professor of Philosophy at the
philosophy no one is in a position to evaluate as yet. University of Paris XNanterre, where he has taught
Ultimately, then, non-philosophy can only be gauged since 1967.
in terms of what it can do. And no one yet knows 2. For instance: Althusser, Badiou, Derrida, Deleuze,
Foucault, Lacan, Lyotard, Serres.
what non-philosophy can or cannot do.
3. Au-del du principe de pouvoir, Payot, Paris, 1978,
p.7.
Bibliography of works by Laruelle 4. The radically heterodox character of Laruelles thought,
Laruelle divides his work into three periods: Philosophy I, its sheer unclassiable strangeness, has consistently
Philosophy II and Philosophy III. Philosophy I (197181) managed to provoke hostility and bewilderment not
could be called Laruelles formative period, his philosophical only among the guardians of philosophical orthodoxy
apprenticeship. The shift toward non-philosophy is initiated within the French academy but also among his relatively
with Philosophy II (198195). However, as far as Laruelle unorthodox philosophical peers. The unfortunate result,
himself is concerned, it is not until Philosophy III (1995 after a certain degree of intellectual notoriety among the
present) that non-philosophy truly begins. Parisian avant-garde of the 1970s, has been a position
Philosophie I of almost total intellectual isolation. Laruelle continues
to inspire a peculiar mixture of derision and fear among
Phnomne et diffrence. ssai sur lontologie de Ravaisson his fellow philosophers. Derision, because his work is
[Phenomenon and Difference: An Essay on Ravaissons
deemed utterly incomprehensible. Fear, because those
Ontology], Klinskieck, Paris, 1971.
same philosophers, who are used to bafing the un
Machines textuelles. Dconstruction et libido dcriture [Tex-
initiated, nd their own inability to understand Laruelle
tual Machines: Deconstruction and Libido of Writing],

34 Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03)


unsettling. Yet, contrary to what these philosophers main from dispersion in average everydayness to the properly
tain, there is nothing obscurantist or wilfully esoteric meta-physical appropriation of being-unto-death as its
about Laruelles work. Understanding it is not a matter ownmost potentiality for being. Since it is via the lat
of initiation: it does not entail exhaustive familiarity with ter that Daseins own being comes into question for it,
a corpus of sacred texts replete with all manner of lexical fundamental ontology as theoretical project is ultimately
trickery or obscure wordplay. The difculty presented supervenient on the existential ur-project delineated in
by Laruelles work is entirely objective: it is a matter of being-unto-death.
learning to think in a way that is radically unlike the way 10. Once [philosophy] begins to be used as a material and
one has been trained to think if one is a philosopher. And occasion, it becomes shorn of its traditional nalities, all
having learnt to think non-philosophically, the point is to of which are based upon a spontaneous philosophical
put this technique into practice to see what it is capable faith. The latter forms a circle: it obliges one to practise
of producing. Laruelles work presents the reader with philosophy for reasons that are extrinsic to it, whether
an organon, an instrument which one needs to learn how these be ethical, juridical, scientic, aesthetic, etc. But
to use so as to be in a position to gauge its potential, not philosophy then uses these nalities the better to triumph
a system or world-view whose doctrines invite assent or and afrm itself on the basis of their subordination as
dissent. the only activity which is genuinely excellent, uncir
5. For example Heidegger, Derrida, Deleuze. Laruelle
cumventable or absolute. All this prescriptive activity
analyses this problematic in Les philosophies de la dif-
whether it be ethical or pedagogical, etc. , all this
frence, PUF, Paris, 1986.
normative or auto-normative use of philosophy with a
6. Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari, What is Philosophy?,
view to experience; every latent or explicit teleology
trans. G. Burchell and H. Tomlinson, Verso, London,
concomitant with the spontaneous practice of philosophy
1994.
must be abandoned, which does not mean destroyed
7. Michel Henry, The Essence of Manifestation, trans. G.
Etskorn, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1973. but treated as a mere material and practised henceforth
8. Laruelle sketches a non-philosophical treatment of the within these limits (Laruelle, Philosophie et non-phi-
issue of thinking machines in two recent but as yet losophie, Mardaga, Lige, 1989, p. 27).
unpublished papers: Thorie uni de la pense et du 11. It is this Performed, shorn of the fetishes of per
calcul [Unied Theory of Thought and Computation] formativity and of activity and the causa sui in gen
and Performance et Perform [Performance and Per eral, which invests thinking itself as identity (within its
formed]. I should mention here that Laruelle himself relatively autonomous order of thought) of science and
would probably not endorse what he would see as my philosophy, and more generally, of the theoretical and
excessively machinic characterization of the non-philo the pragmatic. We shall not say too hastily confusing
sophical subject. once again thinking with the Real that this identity is
9. This decisional structure is at work in Deleuze and performed directly in-One, but that it is performed only
Guattaris machinic constructivism: the philosophical in the last instance by the One as the Performed itself
concepts counter-effectuation of intensive materiality (Laruelle, Principes de la non-philosophie, PUF, Paris,
is at once extracted from an empirical state of affairs 1996, p. 215).
through which the philosopher is forced to think and 12. A point made by Hughes Choplin in his admirable little
transcendentally productive of being qua event. But monograph La non-philosophie de Franois Laruelle
perhaps it is best exemplied by Heidegger, who re (Kim, Paris 2000).
inscribes the conditions for the genesis of the project 13. See, for example, Laruelles thique de ltranger
of fundamental ontology within the structure of funda (Kim, Paris, 1999) for precisely such a treatment.
mental ontology itself. Thus, the philosophical project 14. Especially in certain works from Philosophie II such
delineated in Being and Time encompasses its own as Philosophie et non-philosophie, and En tant quun
conditions of possibility, as explicated in Daseins shift (Aubier, Paris, 1991).

Centre for Research in Keynote speaker

Modern European Philosophy Franois Laruelle

Topics
Non-Philosophy Now: Theory and Practices
Media and Inter-Media
Saturday 15 November, 2003 10am6pm
Ethics and Politics of the Real
Non-philosophy is not anti-philosophy or post-philosophy but a new way
of using and practising philosophy: an autonomous theoretical discipline Religion and Non-Religion
for which philosophy functions as a material. This conference brings to-
gether researchers from Canada, France, San Salvador and Venezuela Aesthetics and Non-Aesthetics
to explore ways in which non-philosophy, inaugurated by Franois Laru-
elle, might be developed beyond the confines of Laruelles own writings.
Radical Translation
Science and Non-Philosophy

20 waged, 10 unwaged. Contact: Ray Brassier (r.brassier@mdx.ac.uk), Centre for Research in Modern European
Philosophy, Middlesex University, White Hart Lane, London N17 8HR, Tel. 020-8411-6220

Radical Philosophy 121 (September/October 20 03) 35

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen