Sie sind auf Seite 1von 466

ilfiflifimili1rfilil1mi

02000000002503
~r
ADVANCED TEXTBOOKS GENERAL COMPETITIVE
IN ECONOMICS ANALYSIS

VOLUME 12 KENNETH J. ARROW


Stanford University, CA, USA

Editors:
FRANK H. HAHN
C. J. BLISS
University of Cambridge, England

M. D. INTRILIGATOR
(i) S
Advisory Editors:
W.A.BROCK
D. W. JORGENSON
M.C.KEMP
J.-J. LAFFONT
J.-F. RICHARD

NH
CJ!~C
~
~
NORTH-HOLLAND NORTH-HOLLAND
AMSTERDAM NEWYORK OXFORD TOKYO AMSTERDAM NEWYORK OXFORD TOKYO
ADVANCED TEXTBOOKS GENERAL COMPETITIVE
IN ECONOMICS ANALYSIS

VOLUME 12 KENNETH J. ARROW


Stanford University, CA, USA

Editors:
FRANK H. HAHN
C. J. BLISS
University of Cambridge, England

M. D. INTRILIGATOR
(i) S
Advisory Editors:
W.A.BROCK
D. W. JORGENSON
M.C.KEMP
J.-J. LAFFONT
J.-F. RICHARD

NH
CJ!~C
~
~
NORTH-HOLLAND NORTH-HOLLAND
AMSTERDAM NEWYORK OXFORD TOKYO AMSTERDAM NEWYORK OXFORD TOKYO
ELSEVIER SCIENCE PUBLISHERS B. V.
Sara Burgerhat'tstraat 25 PREFACE
P.O. Box 211, 1000 AE Amsterdam, The Nether1ands

Distributors for the United S tates and Canada:


ELSEVIER S CIEN CE PUBLISHING COMPANY INC.
655, Avenue of the Americas
Tradition is a matter of much wider
New York, N. Y. 10010, U.S.A. significance. lt cannot be inherited,
and ij you want it you must obtain
First cdition: 1971 it by great labour.
Second printing: 1980 -T.S. Eliot, Tradition and the
Third printing: 1983 Individual Talent
Fourth printing: 1986
Fifth printing: 1988
Sixth printing: 1991

Much of this book is concerned with the analysis of an idealized,


decentralized economy. In particular, it is supposed, in the main, that
there is perfect competition and that the choices of economic agents
can be deduced from certain axioms of rationality. Only recently has
a fairly complete and rigorous examination of this long-developing con-
struction become possible.
It is our intent to give a systematic exposition of the subject. In the
course of doing so, it became clear that a considerable amount of unex-
plored intellectual territory could be traversed without sacrificing the
basically expository aims of the work; indeed, in many cases, the
filling-in of gaps gives a more systematic feel to the whole. Also, in
most cases, we have offered new proofs of the known results in com-
petitive equilibrium theory.
Acknowledgments of priority are to be found in the Notes at the end
ISBN: O444 85497 5
of each chapter; we have not tried to give detailed histories there, only
Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. 1991 the first significant statement of each result. Theorems in the .text not
cited in the Notes are either so well known at this stage that reference
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
would be pedantic or are, to the best of our knowledge, original with
transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V./ the authors.
Academic Publishing Division, P.O. Box 1991, 1000 BZ Amsterdam, The Netherlands. The book is strictly a joint effort, and both authors are responsible
for all errors. In the actual writing, one author had the initial responsi-
Special regulations for readers in the U.S.A.- This publication has been registered with the Copyright
bility for each chapter, which was then subject to repeated criticism and
Clearance Center Inc. (CCC), Salem, Massachusetts. Information can be obtained from the CCC about
conditions under which photocopies of parts of this publication may be made in the U.S.A. All other emendation by the other; in severa! cases, the ttonnement went through
copyright questions, including photocopying outside of the U.S.A., should be referred to the publisher. severa! more steps. Doubtless, this process would have gone still further
if the authors had not learned by bitter experience that the time in
No responsibility is assumed by the publisher for any injury and/or damage to persons or property as a
which recontract takes place is in fact coincident with real time. Arrow
matter of products liability, negligence or otherwise, or from any use or operation of any methods,
instructions or ideas contained in the material herein. wrote the initial drafts of Chapters 1 and 3-8 and Mathematical Ap-
pendices B and C, Hahn those of Chapters 9-14 and Mathematical
Printed in The Netherlands
V
ELSEVIER SCIENCE PUBLISHERS B. V.
Sara Burgerhat'tstraat 25 PREFACE
P.O. Box 211, 1000 AE Amsterdam, The Nether1ands

Distributors for the United S tates and Canada:


ELSEVIER S CIEN CE PUBLISHING COMPANY INC.
655, Avenue of the Americas
Tradition is a matter of much wider
New York, N. Y. 10010, U.S.A. significance. lt cannot be inherited,
and ij you want it you must obtain
First cdition: 1971 it by great labour.
Second printing: 1980 -T.S. Eliot, Tradition and the
Third printing: 1983 Individual Talent
Fourth printing: 1986
Fifth printing: 1988
Sixth printing: 1991

Much of this book is concerned with the analysis of an idealized,


decentralized economy. In particular, it is supposed, in the main, that
there is perfect competition and that the choices of economic agents
can be deduced from certain axioms of rationality. Only recently has
a fairly complete and rigorous examination of this long-developing con-
struction become possible.
It is our intent to give a systematic exposition of the subject. In the
course of doing so, it became clear that a considerable amount of unex-
plored intellectual territory could be traversed without sacrificing the
basically expository aims of the work; indeed, in many cases, the
filling-in of gaps gives a more systematic feel to the whole. Also, in
most cases, we have offered new proofs of the known results in com-
petitive equilibrium theory.
Acknowledgments of priority are to be found in the Notes at the end
ISBN: O444 85497 5
of each chapter; we have not tried to give detailed histories there, only
Elsevier Science Publishers B.V. 1991 the first significant statement of each result. Theorems in the .text not
cited in the Notes are either so well known at this stage that reference
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
would be pedantic or are, to the best of our knowledge, original with
transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher, Elsevier Science Publishers B.V./ the authors.
Academic Publishing Division, P.O. Box 1991, 1000 BZ Amsterdam, The Netherlands. The book is strictly a joint effort, and both authors are responsible
for all errors. In the actual writing, one author had the initial responsi-
Special regulations for readers in the U.S.A.- This publication has been registered with the Copyright
bility for each chapter, which was then subject to repeated criticism and
Clearance Center Inc. (CCC), Salem, Massachusetts. Information can be obtained from the CCC about
conditions under which photocopies of parts of this publication may be made in the U.S.A. All other emendation by the other; in severa! cases, the ttonnement went through
copyright questions, including photocopying outside of the U.S.A., should be referred to the publisher. severa! more steps. Doubtless, this process would have gone still further
if the authors had not learned by bitter experience that the time in
No responsibility is assumed by the publisher for any injury and/or damage to persons or property as a
which recontract takes place is in fact coincident with real time. Arrow
matter of products liability, negligence or otherwise, or from any use or operation of any methods,
instructions or ideas contained in the material herein. wrote the initial drafts of Chapters 1 and 3-8 and Mathematical Ap-
pendices B and C, Hahn those of Chapters 9-14 and Mathematical
Printed in The Netherlands
V
'i

vi PREFACE PREFACE vii

Appendix A. Both authors wrote sections of Chapter 2. and guided by price signals would be compatible with a coherent dis-
Note should be made that certain tapies that some readers might position of economic resources that could be regarded, in a well-defined
expect to find here are not covered; they were omitted to hold the sense, as superior to a large class of possible alternative dispositions.
physical and intellectual compass of the book within reasonable bounds Moreover, the price signals would operate in a way to establish this
and to preserve some semblance of unity of approach. ( 1) We have degree of coherence. It is important to understand how surprising this
omitted all discussion of markets with a continuum of traders, a study claim must be to anyone not exposed to this tradition. The immediate
of great potential importance in our judgment introduced in recent "common sense" answer to the question "What will an economy moti-
years by Aumann and pursued by Debreu, Hildenbrand, Vind, and vated by individual greed and controlled by a very large number of
the younger Belgian and Israel schools. This work requires the use of different agents look like?" is probably: There will be chaos. That quite
measure theory, which would have been a formidable addition to the a different answer has long been claimed true and has indeed perme-
advanced mathematical prerequisites we already demand of our read- ated the economic thinking of a large number of people who are in
ers. In Chapters 7 and 8, however, we have attempted to go as far as no way economists is itself sufficient grounds for investigating it seri-
we can in this direction without the use of measure theory. (2) Since our ously. The proposition having been put forward and very seriously
emphasis is on the general equilibrium of the economy, we have not entertained, it is important to know not only whether it is true, but also
covered in detail specific theorems on the theories of the firm and the whether it could be true. A good deal of what follows is concerned with
household; only such results as are needed for general equilibrium this last question, which seems to us to have considerable claims on
analysis are discussed. This means also that we have been satisfied to the attention of economists.
base the theory of the household on the assumption of a preference If confirmation of the proposition we have been discussing has been
ordering and have not examined the growing literature that bases this found in a particular formalization of the economy, it then becomes
theory on some form of revealed preference assumption. (3) We have interesting to see how robust this result is. Will it survive a change in
refrained also from a development of welfare economics, except for assumption from a perfectly competitive to an imperfectly competitivc
sorne theorems that also play a role in the descriptive theory of general economy? Will it be overturned by externa! economics, by apparent
equilibrium. It is expected that other volumes in this series of texts on irrationalities such as "judging quality by price" or by lack of suffi.cient
mathematical economics and econometrics will deal with the theories "future markets" and the special role that might be taken by the
of the firm and the household and with welfare economics. ( 4) The medium of exchange? Some answers to these questions have been sug-
extension of general equilibrium theory to the case of uncertainty is gested in what follows. Other questions, of course, remain. But the
given only the most cursory treatment in Chapter 5. On the one hand, point is this: It is.not sufficient to assert that, while it is possible to
the economics of uncertainty is a large topic that cannot be given ade- invent a world in which the claims made on behalf of the "invisible
quate treatment here; on the other hand, the general equilibrium theory hand" are true, these claims fail in the actual world. It must be shown
is still in an early stage of development. just how the features of the world regarded as essential in any descrip-
It is natural and proper to ask whether this enquiry into an economy, tion of it also make it impossible to substantiate the claims. In attempt-
apparently so abstracted from the world, is worthwhile. We may answer ing to answer the question "Could it be true?", we learn a good deal
in the usual way by drawing attention to the enormously complex about why it might not be true.
nature of the material that economists study and the accordingly urgent Our view, therefore, is that an intellectually challenging theol'y of.
need for simplification and so abstraction. This, however, leaves open decentralized economics exists, has and is being taken seriously, and s0
the question of why the particular simplifications here used should be deserves the most careful logical scrutiny.
the appropriate ones. We have paid some attention here also to the possibility of using
Our answer is somewhat different. There is by now a long and fairly the idealized constructions in comparing different economies. On the
imposing line of economists from Adam Smith to the present who have whole, our conclusion is that the postulates are too weak to allow one
sought to show that a decentralized economy motivated by self-interest to make much headway. This can be taken as evidence of the defi-
'i

vi PREFACE PREFACE vii

Appendix A. Both authors wrote sections of Chapter 2. and guided by price signals would be compatible with a coherent dis-
Note should be made that certain tapies that some readers might position of economic resources that could be regarded, in a well-defined
expect to find here are not covered; they were omitted to hold the sense, as superior to a large class of possible alternative dispositions.
physical and intellectual compass of the book within reasonable bounds Moreover, the price signals would operate in a way to establish this
and to preserve some semblance of unity of approach. ( 1) We have degree of coherence. It is important to understand how surprising this
omitted all discussion of markets with a continuum of traders, a study claim must be to anyone not exposed to this tradition. The immediate
of great potential importance in our judgment introduced in recent "common sense" answer to the question "What will an economy moti-
years by Aumann and pursued by Debreu, Hildenbrand, Vind, and vated by individual greed and controlled by a very large number of
the younger Belgian and Israel schools. This work requires the use of different agents look like?" is probably: There will be chaos. That quite
measure theory, which would have been a formidable addition to the a different answer has long been claimed true and has indeed perme-
advanced mathematical prerequisites we already demand of our read- ated the economic thinking of a large number of people who are in
ers. In Chapters 7 and 8, however, we have attempted to go as far as no way economists is itself sufficient grounds for investigating it seri-
we can in this direction without the use of measure theory. (2) Since our ously. The proposition having been put forward and very seriously
emphasis is on the general equilibrium of the economy, we have not entertained, it is important to know not only whether it is true, but also
covered in detail specific theorems on the theories of the firm and the whether it could be true. A good deal of what follows is concerned with
household; only such results as are needed for general equilibrium this last question, which seems to us to have considerable claims on
analysis are discussed. This means also that we have been satisfied to the attention of economists.
base the theory of the household on the assumption of a preference If confirmation of the proposition we have been discussing has been
ordering and have not examined the growing literature that bases this found in a particular formalization of the economy, it then becomes
theory on some form of revealed preference assumption. (3) We have interesting to see how robust this result is. Will it survive a change in
refrained also from a development of welfare economics, except for assumption from a perfectly competitive to an imperfectly competitivc
sorne theorems that also play a role in the descriptive theory of general economy? Will it be overturned by externa! economics, by apparent
equilibrium. It is expected that other volumes in this series of texts on irrationalities such as "judging quality by price" or by lack of suffi.cient
mathematical economics and econometrics will deal with the theories "future markets" and the special role that might be taken by the
of the firm and the household and with welfare economics. ( 4) The medium of exchange? Some answers to these questions have been sug-
extension of general equilibrium theory to the case of uncertainty is gested in what follows. Other questions, of course, remain. But the
given only the most cursory treatment in Chapter 5. On the one hand, point is this: It is.not sufficient to assert that, while it is possible to
the economics of uncertainty is a large topic that cannot be given ade- invent a world in which the claims made on behalf of the "invisible
quate treatment here; on the other hand, the general equilibrium theory hand" are true, these claims fail in the actual world. It must be shown
is still in an early stage of development. just how the features of the world regarded as essential in any descrip-
It is natural and proper to ask whether this enquiry into an economy, tion of it also make it impossible to substantiate the claims. In attempt-
apparently so abstracted from the world, is worthwhile. We may answer ing to answer the question "Could it be true?", we learn a good deal
in the usual way by drawing attention to the enormously complex about why it might not be true.
nature of the material that economists study and the accordingly urgent Our view, therefore, is that an intellectually challenging theol'y of.
need for simplification and so abstraction. This, however, leaves open decentralized economics exists, has and is being taken seriously, and s0
the question of why the particular simplifications here used should be deserves the most careful logical scrutiny.
the appropriate ones. We have paid some attention here also to the possibility of using
Our answer is somewhat different. There is by now a long and fairly the idealized constructions in comparing different economies. On the
imposing line of economists from Adam Smith to the present who have whole, our conclusion is that the postulates are too weak to allow one
sought to show that a decentralized economy motivated by self-interest to make much headway. This can be taken as evidence of the defi-
viii PREFACE PREFACE ix

ciency of the theory. It can also be taken to show its strength, however, denoted by a prime.
for it suggests that sufficient degrees of freedom have been left for Detailed notation will be found in each chapter.
emprica! information to make a difference to prediction; it is not a In any chapter or appendix, assumptioris, lemmas, theorems, defi-
totally a priori construction. nitions, and displayed expressions are numbered consecutively. As-
sumptions, theorems, and definitions are referred to by their respective
initialletters capitalized; for example, A.3.1 is the first assumption in
Note on Conventions of Notations and Cross References
1
Chapter 3, T.3.1 the first theorem, and Lemma 3.1 the first lemma.
All vectors are in boldface; components of a vector have the same A corollary is given the number of its main theorem. If there is more
'li
,
symbol as the vector, but in italic and are distinguished from one an- than one corollary to a given theorem, a prime is placed after the num-
other by subscripts. For example, if x is a vector, x 1 is its ith com- ber of the second; for example, Corollary 2 is the corollary to, say,
11
ponent. Where the context makes it clear, no special notation is em- T.3.2 and Corollary 2' is its second corollary.
ployed to distinguish row from column vectors. For example, in the
inner product xy, it is taken for granted that here x is a row vector and
11

y a column vector. Acknowledgments


The notation for vector inequalities is as follows: x :2: y means The work reported on in this book has been developed in the last
x1 :2: y 1 , all i; x > y means X; :2: Y1 , all i, x 1 > y 1 for at least 20 years, and our indebtedness to a few of our contemporaries is very
one i; and x : y means x 1 > y 1 for all i. great. The influence of the splendid work of Debreu and his brilliant
A set is usually indicated by a capital italic letter. A vector sum expository volume, Theory of Values 1 will be obvious everywhere in
of sets of vectors is indicated by an ordinary summation sign, 2: . A what follows. We have attempted to answer some questions he did not
cartesian product of sets of vectors is indicated by X ; for both, run- pose and our methods of proof are in a number of instances quite
ning ndices indicate the range of summation. Thus, if, for each index different, but the theory in its present form would not have existed
f, Y1 is a set of possible production vectors, then their vector sum, the without him. Our debt to McKenzie and to Hurwicz is also sufficiently
social production possibility set, is indicated by L1 Y1 , while their great to call for special attention here. All of us in turn are indebted
cartesian product, which is the set of possible production allocations, to the seminal work of Wald, who gave the first rigorous treatment
is denoted by X1 Y1 . A set defined as a cartesian product of an indexed of general equilibrium analysis in the literature, and to Koopmans'
family of sets with an italic letter is designated with the correspond- activity analysis of production, which shaped the basic nature of the
ing capital script letter, thus, qy = X 1 Y1 , and any element of it with models we are dealing with.
the corresponding small script letter, thus, 11 is a typical member of qy. James Mirrlees read much of the manuscript, and we have bene-
If a set is defined by sorne property of its members, it is written with fited from a number of his suggestions, but most especially the treat-
curly brackets in which the typical element of the set is written first, ment of utility functions in Chapter 4, Section 2, is due to him.
succeeded, after a verticalline, by the property in question. For exam- We are greatly indebted to the United States Office of Naval Re-
ple, A = {x x >O}
1 is the set of all vectors x with the property search, which has supported the preparation of this book under con-
that all its elements are non-negative and at least one is positive. tracts successively with Stanford University and Harvard University.
A pair of curly brackets enclosing a single vector denotes the set At various stages, we enjoyed the stimulating environments and facili-
consisting of that vector alone, for example, {x 0 } If A and B are ties of the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavorial Sciences and
sets, A"' B denotes the set-theoretic difference of A and B, that is, the of Churchill College.
set of all elements of A that are not also in B. We are grateful also to Dan Christiansen and Masahiro Okuna for
Matrices usually are denoted with capital italic letters or are repre- their careful preparation of the indexes.
sented by parentheses surrounding the typical element. For example, Finally, we are glad to acknowledge the indispensable aid of Laura
(x!J) is the matrix X with typical element xij. Transposition is Staggers at Stanford University, Dorothy Brothers at the Center for
viii PREFACE PREFACE ix

ciency of the theory. It can also be taken to show its strength, however, denoted by a prime.
for it suggests that sufficient degrees of freedom have been left for Detailed notation will be found in each chapter.
emprica! information to make a difference to prediction; it is not a In any chapter or appendix, assumptioris, lemmas, theorems, defi-
totally a priori construction. nitions, and displayed expressions are numbered consecutively. As-
sumptions, theorems, and definitions are referred to by their respective
initialletters capitalized; for example, A.3.1 is the first assumption in
Note on Conventions of Notations and Cross References
1
Chapter 3, T.3.1 the first theorem, and Lemma 3.1 the first lemma.
All vectors are in boldface; components of a vector have the same A corollary is given the number of its main theorem. If there is more
'li
,
symbol as the vector, but in italic and are distinguished from one an- than one corollary to a given theorem, a prime is placed after the num-
other by subscripts. For example, if x is a vector, x 1 is its ith com- ber of the second; for example, Corollary 2 is the corollary to, say,
11
ponent. Where the context makes it clear, no special notation is em- T.3.2 and Corollary 2' is its second corollary.
ployed to distinguish row from column vectors. For example, in the
inner product xy, it is taken for granted that here x is a row vector and
11

y a column vector. Acknowledgments


The notation for vector inequalities is as follows: x :2: y means The work reported on in this book has been developed in the last
x1 :2: y 1 , all i; x > y means X; :2: Y1 , all i, x 1 > y 1 for at least 20 years, and our indebtedness to a few of our contemporaries is very
one i; and x : y means x 1 > y 1 for all i. great. The influence of the splendid work of Debreu and his brilliant
A set is usually indicated by a capital italic letter. A vector sum expository volume, Theory of Values 1 will be obvious everywhere in
of sets of vectors is indicated by an ordinary summation sign, 2: . A what follows. We have attempted to answer some questions he did not
cartesian product of sets of vectors is indicated by X ; for both, run- pose and our methods of proof are in a number of instances quite
ning ndices indicate the range of summation. Thus, if, for each index different, but the theory in its present form would not have existed
f, Y1 is a set of possible production vectors, then their vector sum, the without him. Our debt to McKenzie and to Hurwicz is also sufficiently
social production possibility set, is indicated by L1 Y1 , while their great to call for special attention here. All of us in turn are indebted
cartesian product, which is the set of possible production allocations, to the seminal work of Wald, who gave the first rigorous treatment
is denoted by X1 Y1 . A set defined as a cartesian product of an indexed of general equilibrium analysis in the literature, and to Koopmans'
family of sets with an italic letter is designated with the correspond- activity analysis of production, which shaped the basic nature of the
ing capital script letter, thus, qy = X 1 Y1 , and any element of it with models we are dealing with.
the corresponding small script letter, thus, 11 is a typical member of qy. James Mirrlees read much of the manuscript, and we have bene-
If a set is defined by sorne property of its members, it is written with fited from a number of his suggestions, but most especially the treat-
curly brackets in which the typical element of the set is written first, ment of utility functions in Chapter 4, Section 2, is due to him.
succeeded, after a verticalline, by the property in question. For exam- We are greatly indebted to the United States Office of Naval Re-
ple, A = {x x >O}
1 is the set of all vectors x with the property search, which has supported the preparation of this book under con-
that all its elements are non-negative and at least one is positive. tracts successively with Stanford University and Harvard University.
A pair of curly brackets enclosing a single vector denotes the set At various stages, we enjoyed the stimulating environments and facili-
consisting of that vector alone, for example, {x 0 } If A and B are ties of the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavorial Sciences and
sets, A"' B denotes the set-theoretic difference of A and B, that is, the of Churchill College.
set of all elements of A that are not also in B. We are grateful also to Dan Christiansen and Masahiro Okuna for
Matrices usually are denoted with capital italic letters or are repre- their careful preparation of the indexes.
sented by parentheses surrounding the typical element. For example, Finally, we are glad to acknowledge the indispensable aid of Laura
(x!J) is the matrix X with typical element xij. Transposition is Staggers at Stanford University, Dorothy Brothers at the Center for
,,
111
'1'
::
!
X PREFACE CONTENTS
Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences and Sheila V. Conroy at
Harvard University, who contributed not only their great abilities as
typists, but also unlimited patience in incorporating our innumerable
revisions, persistence in deciphering our incomprehensible handwrit-
ing, and sympathy on the numerous occasions when it was needed.

Kenneth J. Arrow
F. H. Hahn
August 1971

PREFACE V

CHAPTER 1
HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION

CHAPTER 2
MARKET EQUILIBRIUM: A FIRST APPROACH 16

CHAPTER 3
PRODUCTON DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE
ECONOMY 52

CHAPTER 4
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 75

CHAPTER 5
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 107

CHAPTER 6
GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE
ASSUMPTIONS 129

CHAPTER 7
MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES 169

CHAPTER 8
THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 183

CHAPTER 9
THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 207

CHAPTER 10
COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 245

xi
,,
111
'1'
::
!
X PREFACE CONTENTS
Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences and Sheila V. Conroy at
Harvard University, who contributed not only their great abilities as
typists, but also unlimited patience in incorporating our innumerable
revisions, persistence in deciphering our incomprehensible handwrit-
ing, and sympathy on the numerous occasions when it was needed.

Kenneth J. Arrow
F. H. Hahn
August 1971

PREFACE V

CHAPTER 1
HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION

CHAPTER 2
MARKET EQUILIBRIUM: A FIRST APPROACH 16

CHAPTER 3
PRODUCTON DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE
ECONOMY 52

CHAPTER 4
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 75

CHAPTER 5
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 107

CHAPTER 6
GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE
ASSUMPTIONS 129

CHAPTER 7
MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES 169

CHAPTER 8
THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 183

CHAPTER 9
THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 207

CHAPTER 10
COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 245

xi
xii CONTENTS Chapter One

CHAPTER 11 HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION


INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 263

CHAPTER 12 This is the use of memory


STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 282 For liberation ...
CHAPTER 13 History may be servitude,
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE History may be freedom . ...
ECONOMY 324
-T. S. Eliot, Little Gidding
CHAPTER 14
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 347 l. The Classical Economists
MATHEMA TI CAL APPENDIX A There are two basic, incompletely separable, aspects of the notion
POSITIVE MATRICES 370 of general equilibrium as it has been u sed in economics: the simple
notion of determinateness, that the relations describing the economic
MATHEMATCAL APPENDIX B system must be sufficiently complete to determine the values of its
CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 375 variables, and the more specific notion that each relation represents
a balance of forces. The last usually, though not always, is taken to
MATHEMATICAL APPENDIX C
FIXED POINT THEOREMS AND RELATED COMBINATORIAL mean that a violation of any one relation sets in motion forces tend-
ALGORITHMS 402 ing to restore it (it has been shown (see Section 12.6) that this
hypothesis does not imply the stability of the entire system). In a
BIBLIOGRAPHY 428 sense, almost any attempt to give a theory of the whole economic
system implies the acceptance of the first part of the equilibrium
AUTHORINDEX 438 notion; and Adam Smith's "invisible hand" is a poetic expression of
the most fundamental of economic balance relations, the equalization
SUBJECT INDEX 440 1

1. of rates of return, as enforced by the tendency of factors to move


from low to high returns.
The notion of equilibrium ("equal weight," referring to the con-
dition for balancing a lever pivoted at its center) was familiar to
mechanics long before the publication of The Wealth of Nations in
1776, and with it the notion that the effects of a force may annihilate
it (e.g., water finding its own level), but there is no obvious evidence
that Smith drew his ideas from any analogy with mechanics. What-
ever the so urce of the concept, the notion that a social system
moved by independent actions in pursuit of different values is
consistent with a final coherent state of balance, and one in which
the outcomes may be quite different from those intended by the
agents, is surely the most important intellectual contribution that
economi<; thought has made to the general understanding of social
processes.

1
xii CONTENTS Chapter One

CHAPTER 11 HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION


INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 263

CHAPTER 12 This is the use of memory


STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 282 For liberation ...
CHAPTER 13 History may be servitude,
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE History may be freedom . ...
ECONOMY 324
-T. S. Eliot, Little Gidding
CHAPTER 14
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 347 l. The Classical Economists
MATHEMA TI CAL APPENDIX A There are two basic, incompletely separable, aspects of the notion
POSITIVE MATRICES 370 of general equilibrium as it has been u sed in economics: the simple
notion of determinateness, that the relations describing the economic
MATHEMATCAL APPENDIX B system must be sufficiently complete to determine the values of its
CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 375 variables, and the more specific notion that each relation represents
a balance of forces. The last usually, though not always, is taken to
MATHEMATICAL APPENDIX C
FIXED POINT THEOREMS AND RELATED COMBINATORIAL mean that a violation of any one relation sets in motion forces tend-
ALGORITHMS 402 ing to restore it (it has been shown (see Section 12.6) that this
hypothesis does not imply the stability of the entire system). In a
BIBLIOGRAPHY 428 sense, almost any attempt to give a theory of the whole economic
system implies the acceptance of the first part of the equilibrium
AUTHORINDEX 438 notion; and Adam Smith's "invisible hand" is a poetic expression of
the most fundamental of economic balance relations, the equalization
SUBJECT INDEX 440 1

1. of rates of return, as enforced by the tendency of factors to move


from low to high returns.
The notion of equilibrium ("equal weight," referring to the con-
dition for balancing a lever pivoted at its center) was familiar to
mechanics long before the publication of The Wealth of Nations in
1776, and with it the notion that the effects of a force may annihilate
it (e.g., water finding its own level), but there is no obvious evidence
that Smith drew his ideas from any analogy with mechanics. What-
ever the so urce of the concept, the notion that a social system
moved by independent actions in pursuit of different values is
consistent with a final coherent state of balance, and one in which
the outcomes may be quite different from those intended by the
agents, is surely the most important intellectual contribution that
economi<; thought has made to the general understanding of social
processes.

1
2 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 3

Smith also perceived the most important implication of general it remains to sorne extent today); indeed, with the Malthusian
equilibrium theory, the ability of a competitive system to achieve an assumption, the model again hada single primary factor, land.
allocation of resources that is efficient in sorne sense. Nothing Thus, in a certain definite sense, the classical economists had no
resembling a rigorous argument for, or even a careful statement of true theory of resource allocation, since the influence of prices on
the efficiency proposition can be found in Smith, however. quantities was not studied and the reciproca! influence denied. 1
Thus it can be maintained that Smith was a creator of general But the classical theory could survive neither the logical problem of
equilibrium theory, though the coherence and consistency of bis explaining relative wages of heterogeneous types of labor nor the
work may be questioned. A fortiori, later systematic expositors of empirical problem of accounting for wages that were rising steadily
the classical system, such as Ricardo, Mill, and Marx, whose work above the subsistence level. It is in this context that the neoclassical
filled in sorne of Smith's logical gaps, can all be regarded as early - theories emerged about 1870, with all priinary resources in the role
expositors of general equilibrium theory. In sorne ways, Marx that land alone had had before.
carne closer in form to modern theory in his scheme of simple (In all fairness to the classical writers, it should be remarked that
reproduction (Capital, Vol. 11), studied in combination with bis the theory of foreign trade in the form given to it by Mill was a
development of relative price theory (Vols. 1 and 111), than any other genuine general equilibrium theory. Of cotlfSe, the assumptions
classical economist, though he confuses everything by his attempt to made, particularly factor immobility, were very restrictive.)
maintain simultaneously a pure labor theory of value and an
equalization of rates of return on capital. 1
There is, however, a very important sense in which nne of the 2. The Contributions of Walras
classical economists had a true general equilibrium theory: None The full recognition of the general equilibrium concept can be
gave an explicit role to demand conditions. No 'doubt the more attributed unmistakably to Walras [1874, 1877], though many
systematic thinkers among them, most particularly J. S. Mill, gave elements of the neoclassical system had been worked out independ-
verbal homage to the role of demand and the influence of prices on ently by W. Stanley Jevons and by Carl Menger. 2 The economic
it, but there was no genuine integration of demand with the essen- system is made up of households and firms. Each household owns
tially supply-oriented nature of classical theory. The neglect of a set of resources, commodities useful in production or consumption,
demand was facilitated by the special simplifying assumptions made including different kinds of labor. For any given set of prices, then,
about supply. A general equilibrium theory is a theory about both a household has an income from the sale of its resources and, with
the quantities and the prices of all commodities. The classical this income, it can choose among all alternative bundles of con-
authors found, however, that prices appeared to be determined by sumer goods whose cost, at the given prices, does not exceed the
a system of relations, derived from the equal-rate-of-profit condition, household's income. Thus, the demand by households for any
- into which quantities did not enter. This is clear enough with fixed consumer good is a function of the prices of both consumer goods
production coefficients and a single primary factor, labor, as in and resources. The firms were assumed (at least in the earlier
Smith's famous exchange of deer and heavers; and it was the great
1 The classical failure to see clearly the allocational nature of the economic
accomplishment of Malthus and Ricardo to show that land could be
problem has been most forcefully argued by F. H. Knight [1935].
brought into the system. lf, finally, Malthusian assumptions about 2 Schumpeter and others have called attention to Isnard [1781] as a creator of

population implied that the supply price of labor was fixed in terms general equilibrium theory. According to the account given by Theocharis
of goods, then even the rate of return on capital could be determined [1961, 1966-70], Isnard's model for the pure exchange case amounts to assuming
that no individual holds more than one asset and that all demand functions are
(though the presence of capital as a productive factor and recipient of unit elasticity in income ahd in own price. Under these conditions, relative
of rewards was clearly an embarrassment to the classical authors, as prices are shown to be the solution of a system of simultaneous linear equa-
tions. Production is also introduced, with the usual fixed-coeffi.cient assump-
1
For sorne modern reconstructions of classical theories as general equilibrium tions. The spirit of the model is very much closer to the later neoclassical
models, see Samuelson [1957, 1959]. writers than to the contemporary classicists.

l.
2 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 3

Smith also perceived the most important implication of general it remains to sorne extent today); indeed, with the Malthusian
equilibrium theory, the ability of a competitive system to achieve an assumption, the model again hada single primary factor, land.
allocation of resources that is efficient in sorne sense. Nothing Thus, in a certain definite sense, the classical economists had no
resembling a rigorous argument for, or even a careful statement of true theory of resource allocation, since the influence of prices on
the efficiency proposition can be found in Smith, however. quantities was not studied and the reciproca! influence denied. 1
Thus it can be maintained that Smith was a creator of general But the classical theory could survive neither the logical problem of
equilibrium theory, though the coherence and consistency of bis explaining relative wages of heterogeneous types of labor nor the
work may be questioned. A fortiori, later systematic expositors of empirical problem of accounting for wages that were rising steadily
the classical system, such as Ricardo, Mill, and Marx, whose work above the subsistence level. It is in this context that the neoclassical
filled in sorne of Smith's logical gaps, can all be regarded as early - theories emerged about 1870, with all priinary resources in the role
expositors of general equilibrium theory. In sorne ways, Marx that land alone had had before.
carne closer in form to modern theory in his scheme of simple (In all fairness to the classical writers, it should be remarked that
reproduction (Capital, Vol. 11), studied in combination with bis the theory of foreign trade in the form given to it by Mill was a
development of relative price theory (Vols. 1 and 111), than any other genuine general equilibrium theory. Of cotlfSe, the assumptions
classical economist, though he confuses everything by his attempt to made, particularly factor immobility, were very restrictive.)
maintain simultaneously a pure labor theory of value and an
equalization of rates of return on capital. 1
There is, however, a very important sense in which nne of the 2. The Contributions of Walras
classical economists had a true general equilibrium theory: None The full recognition of the general equilibrium concept can be
gave an explicit role to demand conditions. No 'doubt the more attributed unmistakably to Walras [1874, 1877], though many
systematic thinkers among them, most particularly J. S. Mill, gave elements of the neoclassical system had been worked out independ-
verbal homage to the role of demand and the influence of prices on ently by W. Stanley Jevons and by Carl Menger. 2 The economic
it, but there was no genuine integration of demand with the essen- system is made up of households and firms. Each household owns
tially supply-oriented nature of classical theory. The neglect of a set of resources, commodities useful in production or consumption,
demand was facilitated by the special simplifying assumptions made including different kinds of labor. For any given set of prices, then,
about supply. A general equilibrium theory is a theory about both a household has an income from the sale of its resources and, with
the quantities and the prices of all commodities. The classical this income, it can choose among all alternative bundles of con-
authors found, however, that prices appeared to be determined by sumer goods whose cost, at the given prices, does not exceed the
a system of relations, derived from the equal-rate-of-profit condition, household's income. Thus, the demand by households for any
- into which quantities did not enter. This is clear enough with fixed consumer good is a function of the prices of both consumer goods
production coefficients and a single primary factor, labor, as in and resources. The firms were assumed (at least in the earlier
Smith's famous exchange of deer and heavers; and it was the great
1 The classical failure to see clearly the allocational nature of the economic
accomplishment of Malthus and Ricardo to show that land could be
problem has been most forcefully argued by F. H. Knight [1935].
brought into the system. lf, finally, Malthusian assumptions about 2 Schumpeter and others have called attention to Isnard [1781] as a creator of

population implied that the supply price of labor was fixed in terms general equilibrium theory. According to the account given by Theocharis
of goods, then even the rate of return on capital could be determined [1961, 1966-70], Isnard's model for the pure exchange case amounts to assuming
that no individual holds more than one asset and that all demand functions are
(though the presence of capital as a productive factor and recipient of unit elasticity in income ahd in own price. Under these conditions, relative
of rewards was clearly an embarrassment to the classical authors, as prices are shown to be the solution of a system of simultaneous linear equa-
tions. Production is also introduced, with the usual fixed-coeffi.cient assump-
1
For sorne modern reconstructions of classical theories as general equilibrium tions. The spirit of the model is very much closer to the later neoclassical
models, see Samuelson [1957, 1959]. writers than to the contemporary classicists.

l.
4 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 5
i'
versions) to be operating under fixed coefficients. Then the demand all other prices; this will normally require raising the price if demand
for consumer goods determined the demand for resources, and the initially exceeded supply, decreasing it in the opposite case. The
combined assumptions of fixed coefficients and zero profits for a change in the first price will change supply and demand on all other
competitive system implied relations between the prices of consumer markets. Repeat the process with the second and subsequent
goods and resources. An equilibrium set of prices, then, was a set markets. At the end of one round the last market will be in equi-
such that supply and demand were equated on each market; under librium, but none of the others need be because the adjustments on
the assumption of fixed coefficients of production, or more generally, subsequent markets will destroy the equilibrium achieved on any
of constant returns to scale, this amounted to equating supply and one. However, Walras argued, the supply and demand functions
demand on the resource markets, with prices constrained to satisfy for any given commodity will be more affected by the changes in its
the zero-profit condition for firms. Subsequent work of Walras, own price than by changes in other prices ;. hence, after one round the
J. B. Clark, Wicksteed, and others generalized the assumptions about markets should be more nearly in equilibrium than they were to
production to include alternative methods, as expressed in a produc- begin with, and with successive rounds the supply and demand on
tion function. The marginal productivity considerations helped to each market will tend to equality.
determine the prices of resources. Jt seems clear that Walras did not literally suppose that markets
That there exists an equilibrium set of prices was argued from the come into equilibrium in sorne definite order. Rather, the story is
equality of the number of prices to be determined with the number a convenient way of showing how the market system in fact could
of equations expressing the equality of supply and demand on all solve the system of equilibrium relations. The dynamic system,
markets. Both'are equal to the number of commodities, say n. In more properly expressed, asserted that the price on any market rises
this counting, Walras recognized that there are two offsetting com- when demand exceeds supply and falls in the opposite case; the price
plications. (a) Only relative prices affect the behavior of households changes on the different markets were to be thought of as occurring
and firms, hence te system of equations ha ve only n - 1 variables, simultaneously.
a point that Walras expressed by selecting one commodity to serve as Finally, Walras had a still higher aim for general equilibrium
numeraire, with the prices of all commodities being measured relative analysis: to study what is now called comparative statics, in other
to its price. (b) The budgetary balance of each household between words, the laws by which the equilibrium prices and quantities vary
income and the value of consumption and the zero-profit condition with the underlying data (resources, production conditions, or utility
for firms together imply what has cometo be known as Walras' law: functions). But little was actually done in this direction.
The market value of supply equals that of demand for any set of
prices, not merely the equilibrium set; hence, the supply-demand
3. Edgeworth and Pareto: Group Rationality ami Allocation
relations are not independent. If supply equals demand on n - 1
markets, then the equality must hold on the nth. From Adam Smith's invisible hand on, the classical economists
Walras went further and discussed the stability of equilibrium, held that competitive equilibrium yielded what was in sorne none-
essentially for the first time (that is, apart from sorne brief discussions too-well-defined sense an optimal allocation of resources. Edge-
by Mili in the context of foreign trade) in his famous but rather worth [1881] and Pareto [1909, p. 534] clarified considerably the
clumsy theory of ttonnements (lite rally "gropings" or "tentative relation between competitive equilibria and optimal allocations by
proceedings "). Suppose, as Walras did, a set of prices arbitrarily starting from the latter.
given; then supply may exceed demand on so me markets and fall Edgeworth considered a pair of individuals, with initial resources
below on others (unless the initial set is in fact the equilibrium set, of two con:modities, who were trying to arrange a trade between
there must be at least one case of each, by Walras' law). Suppose them. He did not assume that they were operating under the rules
the markets are considered in some definite order. On the first of the competitive game, but rather that they could make any trades
market, adjust the price so that supply and demand are equal, given they wished. He assumed that (a) they would not make a trade if
4 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 5
i'
versions) to be operating under fixed coefficients. Then the demand all other prices; this will normally require raising the price if demand
for consumer goods determined the demand for resources, and the initially exceeded supply, decreasing it in the opposite case. The
combined assumptions of fixed coefficients and zero profits for a change in the first price will change supply and demand on all other
competitive system implied relations between the prices of consumer markets. Repeat the process with the second and subsequent
goods and resources. An equilibrium set of prices, then, was a set markets. At the end of one round the last market will be in equi-
such that supply and demand were equated on each market; under librium, but none of the others need be because the adjustments on
the assumption of fixed coefficients of production, or more generally, subsequent markets will destroy the equilibrium achieved on any
of constant returns to scale, this amounted to equating supply and one. However, Walras argued, the supply and demand functions
demand on the resource markets, with prices constrained to satisfy for any given commodity will be more affected by the changes in its
the zero-profit condition for firms. Subsequent work of Walras, own price than by changes in other prices ;. hence, after one round the
J. B. Clark, Wicksteed, and others generalized the assumptions about markets should be more nearly in equilibrium than they were to
production to include alternative methods, as expressed in a produc- begin with, and with successive rounds the supply and demand on
tion function. The marginal productivity considerations helped to each market will tend to equality.
determine the prices of resources. Jt seems clear that Walras did not literally suppose that markets
That there exists an equilibrium set of prices was argued from the come into equilibrium in sorne definite order. Rather, the story is
equality of the number of prices to be determined with the number a convenient way of showing how the market system in fact could
of equations expressing the equality of supply and demand on all solve the system of equilibrium relations. The dynamic system,
markets. Both'are equal to the number of commodities, say n. In more properly expressed, asserted that the price on any market rises
this counting, Walras recognized that there are two offsetting com- when demand exceeds supply and falls in the opposite case; the price
plications. (a) Only relative prices affect the behavior of households changes on the different markets were to be thought of as occurring
and firms, hence te system of equations ha ve only n - 1 variables, simultaneously.
a point that Walras expressed by selecting one commodity to serve as Finally, Walras had a still higher aim for general equilibrium
numeraire, with the prices of all commodities being measured relative analysis: to study what is now called comparative statics, in other
to its price. (b) The budgetary balance of each household between words, the laws by which the equilibrium prices and quantities vary
income and the value of consumption and the zero-profit condition with the underlying data (resources, production conditions, or utility
for firms together imply what has cometo be known as Walras' law: functions). But little was actually done in this direction.
The market value of supply equals that of demand for any set of
prices, not merely the equilibrium set; hence, the supply-demand
3. Edgeworth and Pareto: Group Rationality ami Allocation
relations are not independent. If supply equals demand on n - 1
markets, then the equality must hold on the nth. From Adam Smith's invisible hand on, the classical economists
Walras went further and discussed the stability of equilibrium, held that competitive equilibrium yielded what was in sorne none-
essentially for the first time (that is, apart from sorne brief discussions too-well-defined sense an optimal allocation of resources. Edge-
by Mili in the context of foreign trade) in his famous but rather worth [1881] and Pareto [1909, p. 534] clarified considerably the
clumsy theory of ttonnements (lite rally "gropings" or "tentative relation between competitive equilibria and optimal allocations by
proceedings "). Suppose, as Walras did, a set of prices arbitrarily starting from the latter.
given; then supply may exceed demand on so me markets and fall Edgeworth considered a pair of individuals, with initial resources
below on others (unless the initial set is in fact the equilibrium set, of two con:modities, who were trying to arrange a trade between
there must be at least one case of each, by Walras' law). Suppose them. He did not assume that they were operating under the rules
the markets are considered in some definite order. On the first of the competitive game, but rather that they could make any trades
market, adjust the price so that supply and demand are equal, given they wished. He assumed that (a) they would not make a trade if
6 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 7

there was another that would be more beneficia! for both and (b) an individual gives up something for the commodity in question.
neither would make a trade that would make him worse off than in If there was really only one commodity in the world, there would be
the absence of trade. He showed that there was a whole set of no exchange and no market.
allocations, which he called the contract curve, satisfying these con- Suppose for the moment that there are only two commodities, say
ditions, of which the competitive equilibrium was one. He went on 1 and 2. Because of homogeneity, demand and supply are deter-
to suppose that, instead of two individuals, there were two types of mined by the ratio of the price of commodity 1 to that of commodity
individua1s, all individuals of the same type having the same utility 2, that is, the price of commodity 1 with commodity 2 as numeraire.
function and the same endowment of initial resources. He general- From Walras' law, equilibrium on market 1 ensures equilibrium on
ized the previous assumptions about the conditions for satisfactory market 2. Partial equilibrium analysis of market 1 is, in the case of
trade; no multilateral trade among the participants would be com- two commodities, fully equivalent to general equilibrium analysis.
pleted if there was sorne subset of them that could make another Analysis of a two-commodity world may have considerable
trade among themselves, using only their own resources, that would didactic usefulness as a way of studying general equilibrium through
benefit them more than the initially proposed trade. This condition a special case admitting of simple diagrammatic representation, but
generalizes both (a) and (b) above. He then carne to the remarkable it may be asked if partial equilibrium analysis has any empirical
conclusion that as the number of individuals of each type became interest for a world of many commodities. An answer is provided
large, the range of possible trades shrank toward the competitive by the following theorem, due independently to Hicks [1939] and
equilibrium. Thus, a general bargaining process turns out to have Leontief [1936]: If the relative prices of sorne set of commodities
a close relation to general competitive equilibrium. remain constant, then for all analytical purposes the set can be
Pareto's special contribution is a suitable definition of optimal regarded as a single composite commodity, the price of which can be
resource allocation, essentially the satisfaction of condition (a) of regarded as proportional to the price of any member of the set and
Edgeworth's contract curve. He recognized, but did not rigorously the quantity of which is then defined so that expenditure (price times
show that an optimum in his sense could always be achieved as a quantity) on the composite commodity is equal to the sum of the
competitive equilibrium starting from sorne suitable initial allocation expenditures on the individual commodities in the set. In symbols,
of endowments. if the prices p 1 , . . , Pm of a set of commodities l, ... , m satisfy the
conditions Pt = pft1 (p1 a constant for each i while p may vary), then
we can take p to be the price of the composite commodity, and
4. Partial Equilibrium Analysis
Cournot [1838] and later Jenkin [1870] and the neoclassical
economists employed extensively the partial equilibrium analysis of
a single market. The demand and supply of a single commodity to be the quantity, where q1 is the quantity of the ith good.
are conceived of as functions of the price of that commodity alone; , The Hicks-Leontief aggregation theorem can be used to justify
the equilibrium price is that for which demand and supply are equal. partial equilibrium analysis. Suppose that a change in the price of
This form of analysis must be viewed either as a pedagogical device commodity 1 leaves the relative prices of all others unchanged.
to take advantage of the ease of graphical representation of one- Then insofar as we are considering only disturbances to equilibrium
variable relations or as a first approximation to general equilibrium from causes peculiar to the market for commodity 1, the remaining
analysis in which repercussions through other inarkets are neglected. commodities can be regarded as a single composite commodity, and
Partial equilibrium analysis is to be regarded as a special case of partial equilibrium analysis is valid.
general equilibrium analysis. The existence of one market pre- The assumption of strict constancy of relative prices of the other
supposes that there must be at least one commodity beyond that commodities will not usually be valid, of course, but it may hold
traded on that market, for a price must be stated as the rate at which approX:imately in many cases of practica! interest. It is sufficient for
6 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 7

there was another that would be more beneficia! for both and (b) an individual gives up something for the commodity in question.
neither would make a trade that would make him worse off than in If there was really only one commodity in the world, there would be
the absence of trade. He showed that there was a whole set of no exchange and no market.
allocations, which he called the contract curve, satisfying these con- Suppose for the moment that there are only two commodities, say
ditions, of which the competitive equilibrium was one. He went on 1 and 2. Because of homogeneity, demand and supply are deter-
to suppose that, instead of two individuals, there were two types of mined by the ratio of the price of commodity 1 to that of commodity
individua1s, all individuals of the same type having the same utility 2, that is, the price of commodity 1 with commodity 2 as numeraire.
function and the same endowment of initial resources. He general- From Walras' law, equilibrium on market 1 ensures equilibrium on
ized the previous assumptions about the conditions for satisfactory market 2. Partial equilibrium analysis of market 1 is, in the case of
trade; no multilateral trade among the participants would be com- two commodities, fully equivalent to general equilibrium analysis.
pleted if there was sorne subset of them that could make another Analysis of a two-commodity world may have considerable
trade among themselves, using only their own resources, that would didactic usefulness as a way of studying general equilibrium through
benefit them more than the initially proposed trade. This condition a special case admitting of simple diagrammatic representation, but
generalizes both (a) and (b) above. He then carne to the remarkable it may be asked if partial equilibrium analysis has any empirical
conclusion that as the number of individuals of each type became interest for a world of many commodities. An answer is provided
large, the range of possible trades shrank toward the competitive by the following theorem, due independently to Hicks [1939] and
equilibrium. Thus, a general bargaining process turns out to have Leontief [1936]: If the relative prices of sorne set of commodities
a close relation to general competitive equilibrium. remain constant, then for all analytical purposes the set can be
Pareto's special contribution is a suitable definition of optimal regarded as a single composite commodity, the price of which can be
resource allocation, essentially the satisfaction of condition (a) of regarded as proportional to the price of any member of the set and
Edgeworth's contract curve. He recognized, but did not rigorously the quantity of which is then defined so that expenditure (price times
show that an optimum in his sense could always be achieved as a quantity) on the composite commodity is equal to the sum of the
competitive equilibrium starting from sorne suitable initial allocation expenditures on the individual commodities in the set. In symbols,
of endowments. if the prices p 1 , . . , Pm of a set of commodities l, ... , m satisfy the
conditions Pt = pft1 (p1 a constant for each i while p may vary), then
we can take p to be the price of the composite commodity, and
4. Partial Equilibrium Analysis
Cournot [1838] and later Jenkin [1870] and the neoclassical
economists employed extensively the partial equilibrium analysis of
a single market. The demand and supply of a single commodity to be the quantity, where q1 is the quantity of the ith good.
are conceived of as functions of the price of that commodity alone; , The Hicks-Leontief aggregation theorem can be used to justify
the equilibrium price is that for which demand and supply are equal. partial equilibrium analysis. Suppose that a change in the price of
This form of analysis must be viewed either as a pedagogical device commodity 1 leaves the relative prices of all others unchanged.
to take advantage of the ease of graphical representation of one- Then insofar as we are considering only disturbances to equilibrium
variable relations or as a first approximation to general equilibrium from causes peculiar to the market for commodity 1, the remaining
analysis in which repercussions through other inarkets are neglected. commodities can be regarded as a single composite commodity, and
Partial equilibrium analysis is to be regarded as a special case of partial equilibrium analysis is valid.
general equilibrium analysis. The existence of one market pre- The assumption of strict constancy of relative prices of the other
supposes that there must be at least one commodity beyond that commodities will not usually be valid, of course, but it may hold
traded on that market, for a price must be stated as the rate at which approX:imately in many cases of practica! interest. It is sufficient for
8 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 9
the purpose that the changes in the relative prices of other com-
modities induced by a change in the price of the commodity being perfectly plausible values of the input-output coefficients, a1h the
prices or quantities that satisfy (1) and (2) might well be negative.
studied do not in turn induce a significant shift in supply or demand
conditions on the market for that commodity. Von Stacke1berg noted that (1) constitutes a complete system of
equations in the outputs xi, since the factor supplies, V;, are data, but
nothing had been assumed about the numbers of distinct factors or
5. Developments During and After the 1930's: Existence ancl distinct commodities. If, in particular, the number of commodities
Uniqueness was less than that of factors, equation (1), in general, would have
no solution.
The next truly major advances did not come until the 1930's. Zeuthen reconsidered the meaning of equation (1). He noted
There were two distinct streams ofthought, one beginning in German- that economists, at least since Carl Menger, had recognized that
language literature and dealing primarily with the existence and sorne factors (e.g., air) are so abundant that there would be no price
uniqueness of equilibrium, the other, primarily in English, dealing charged for them. These would not enter into the list of factors in
with stability and comparative statics. The former started with a Cassel's system. But, Zeuthen argued, the division of factors into
thorough examination of Cassel's simplification [1924] of Walras' free and scarce should not be taken as given a priori. Hence, all
system, an interesting case of work that had no significance in itself, that can be said is that the use of a factor should not exceed its
but whose study turned out to be extraordinarily fruitful. Cassel supply, but if it falls short, then the factor is free. In symbols, (1)
assumed two kinds of goods: commodities that en ter into the
is replaced by
demand functions of consumers and factors that are used to produce
commodities (intermediate goods were not considered). Each com-
modity is produced from factors with constant input-output coef-
2:
j
aijXj. ,:S; V;; if the strict inequality ho1ds, then r 1 = O. (!')

ficients. Factor supplies are supposed totally inelastic. Let aii be Toa la ter generation of economists to whom linear programming and
the amount of factor i used in the production of one unit of com- its generalizations are familiar, the meaning of this step needs no
modity j, xi the total output of commodity j, V; the total initial supply elaboration; equalities are replaced by inequalities and the vital
of factor i, Pi the price of commodity j, and r; the price of factor i. notion of the complementary slackness of quantities and prices
Then the condition that demand equal supply for all factors reads
introduced.
Independently of Zeuthen, Schlesinger, a Viennese banker and
for all i, (1)
amateur economist, came to the same conclusion. He went much
further, however, and intuitively grasped the crucial point that
while the condition that each commodity be produced with zero
replacement of equalities by inequalities also resolves the problems
profits reads
raised by Neisser and von Stackelberg. Schlesinger [1933-34]
for all j. (2) realized the mathematical complexity of a rigorous treatment and,
at his request, Oskar Morgenstern put him in touch with a young
The system is completed by the equations relating the demand for mathematkian, Abraham Wald. The result of their collaboration
commodities to their prices a.d to total income from the sale of was the first rigorous analysis of general competitive equilibrium.
factors. In total there are as many equations as unknowns. But In a series ofpapers [1933-34, 1934-35] (see Wald [1936, 1951] for a
three virtually simultaneous papers by Zeuthen [1932], Neisser summary), Wald demonstrated the existence of competitive equi-
[1932], and von Stackelberg [1933] showed in different ways that the librium in a series of alternative models, including the Cassel model
problem of existence of meaningful equilibrium is deeper than and a model of pure exchange. Competitive equilibrium was
equality of equations and unknowns. Neisser noted that even with defined in the Zeuthen sense, and the essential role of that definition
in the justification of existence is made clear in the mathematics.
8 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 9
the purpose that the changes in the relative prices of other com-
modities induced by a change in the price of the commodity being perfectly plausible values of the input-output coefficients, a1h the
prices or quantities that satisfy (1) and (2) might well be negative.
studied do not in turn induce a significant shift in supply or demand
conditions on the market for that commodity. Von Stacke1berg noted that (1) constitutes a complete system of
equations in the outputs xi, since the factor supplies, V;, are data, but
nothing had been assumed about the numbers of distinct factors or
5. Developments During and After the 1930's: Existence ancl distinct commodities. If, in particular, the number of commodities
Uniqueness was less than that of factors, equation (1), in general, would have
no solution.
The next truly major advances did not come until the 1930's. Zeuthen reconsidered the meaning of equation (1). He noted
There were two distinct streams ofthought, one beginning in German- that economists, at least since Carl Menger, had recognized that
language literature and dealing primarily with the existence and sorne factors (e.g., air) are so abundant that there would be no price
uniqueness of equilibrium, the other, primarily in English, dealing charged for them. These would not enter into the list of factors in
with stability and comparative statics. The former started with a Cassel's system. But, Zeuthen argued, the division of factors into
thorough examination of Cassel's simplification [1924] of Walras' free and scarce should not be taken as given a priori. Hence, all
system, an interesting case of work that had no significance in itself, that can be said is that the use of a factor should not exceed its
but whose study turned out to be extraordinarily fruitful. Cassel supply, but if it falls short, then the factor is free. In symbols, (1)
assumed two kinds of goods: commodities that en ter into the
is replaced by
demand functions of consumers and factors that are used to produce
commodities (intermediate goods were not considered). Each com-
modity is produced from factors with constant input-output coef-
2:
j
aijXj. ,:S; V;; if the strict inequality ho1ds, then r 1 = O. (!')

ficients. Factor supplies are supposed totally inelastic. Let aii be Toa la ter generation of economists to whom linear programming and
the amount of factor i used in the production of one unit of com- its generalizations are familiar, the meaning of this step needs no
modity j, xi the total output of commodity j, V; the total initial supply elaboration; equalities are replaced by inequalities and the vital
of factor i, Pi the price of commodity j, and r; the price of factor i. notion of the complementary slackness of quantities and prices
Then the condition that demand equal supply for all factors reads
introduced.
Independently of Zeuthen, Schlesinger, a Viennese banker and
for all i, (1)
amateur economist, came to the same conclusion. He went much
further, however, and intuitively grasped the crucial point that
while the condition that each commodity be produced with zero
replacement of equalities by inequalities also resolves the problems
profits reads
raised by Neisser and von Stackelberg. Schlesinger [1933-34]
for all j. (2) realized the mathematical complexity of a rigorous treatment and,
at his request, Oskar Morgenstern put him in touch with a young
The system is completed by the equations relating the demand for mathematkian, Abraham Wald. The result of their collaboration
commodities to their prices a.d to total income from the sale of was the first rigorous analysis of general competitive equilibrium.
factors. In total there are as many equations as unknowns. But In a series ofpapers [1933-34, 1934-35] (see Wald [1936, 1951] for a
three virtually simultaneous papers by Zeuthen [1932], Neisser summary), Wald demonstrated the existence of competitive equi-
[1932], and von Stackelberg [1933] showed in different ways that the librium in a series of alternative models, including the Cassel model
problem of existence of meaningful equilibrium is deeper than and a model of pure exchange. Competitive equilibrium was
equality of equations and unknowns. Neisser noted that even with defined in the Zeuthen sense, and the essential role of that definition
in the justification of existence is made clear in the mathematics.
r,

10 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 11

Wald's papers were of forbidding mathematical depth, not only in theorems are found in Mathematical Appendix C.) With these
the use of sophisticated tools, but also in the complexity of the foundations, plus the influence of the rapid development of linear
argument. As they gradually carne to be known among mathe- programming on both the mathematical (again closely related to
matical economists, they probably served as much to inhibit further saddle-point theorems) and economic 1 sides, it was perceived
research by their difficulty as to stimulate it. independently by a number of scholars that existence theorems of
Help finally carne from development of a related line of research, greater simplicity and generality than Wald's were now possible.
John von Neumann's theory of games (first basic paper published in The first papers were those of McKenzie [1954] and Arrow and
1928; see von Neumann and Morgenstern [1944]). This historical bebreu [1954]. Subsequent developments were due to Hukukane
relation between game theory and economic equilibrium has Nikaido [1956] and Hirofumi Uzawa, Debreu, and McKenzie [1959,
paradoxical elements. Game theory has developed severa! very 1961]. The most complete systematic account of the existence con-
general notions of equilibrium, which, in principie, should either ditions is in Debreu [1959]; the most general version is also in
replace the notion of competitive equilibrium or include it as a Debreu [1962].
special case. Indeed, one such equilibrium notion, that of the core,
is identical with Edgeworth's contract curve; it was introduced by 6. Developments During and After the 1930's: Stability-and
Gillies [1953] and applied to specifically market situations by Shubik Comparative StatiCs
[1959] and, in a manner much closer to standard economic thought,
by Scarf [1962] (see Chapter 8). The principal stimulation of game Independently of this development of the existence conditions for
theory to equilibrium theory has been through the use of mathe- equilibrium, the Anglo-American literature contained an intensive
matical tools developed in the former and used in the latter with study of the comparative statics and stability of general competitive
entirely different interpretations. Von Neumann himself made the equilibrium. Historically, it was closely related to analyses of the
first such application in his celebrated paper on balanced economic second-order conditions for maximization of profits by firms and of
growth [1937, 1945]. In this model, there were no demand functions, utility by consumers; the most important contributors were John R.
only production. The markets in each period had to be in equi- Hicks, Harold Hotelling, Paul Samuelson, and R. G. D. Allen. In
librium in the Zeuthen sense, but beyond this was equilibrium in a particular, Hicks [1939] introduced the argument that the stability
second sense, which may be termed stationary equilibrium. The of equilibrium carried with it sorne implications for the shapes of the
equilibrium configuration had to be the same from period to period. supply and demand functions in the neighborhood of equilibrium;
To prove the existence of equilibrium, von Neumann demonstrated hence, the effects of small shifts in any one behavior relation may be
that a certain ratio of bilinear forms had a saddle point, a generaliza- predicted, at least as to sign. Hicks' definition of stability has been
tion of the theorem that showed the existence of equilibrium in two- rep1aced in subsequent work by Samuelson's [1941, 1942]; however,
person zero-sum games. In game theory, however, the variables of Hicks showed that (locally) stability in his sense was equivalent to a
the problem were probabilities (of choosing alternative strategies), condition that has played a considerable role in subsequent research.
while in the application to equilibtium theory one set of variables Let Z be the excess demand (demand less supply) for the ith com-
was prices and the other the levels at which productive activities were modity; it is in general a function of Pl, ... , Pno the prices of all n
carried on. commodities. Then Hicks' definition of stability was equivalent to
Von Neumann deduced his saddle-point theorem from a general- the condition that the principal minors of the matrix whose elements
ization of,Brouwer's fixed-point theorem, a famous proposition in were zfpj had determinants that were positive or negative accord-
topology. A simplified version of von Neumann's theorem was ing as the number of rows or columns included was even or odd.
presented a few years later by the mathematician Shizuo Kakutani, 1 See Koopmans [1951a] for a collection of the work of George B. Dantzig,
and Kakutani's theorem has been the basic tool in virtually all sub- Albert W. Tucker, Harold W. Kuhn, Tjal!ing C. Koopmans and others, and
sequent work. (Statements and proofs of Brouwer's and Kakutani's John F. Nash, Jr. [1950].
r,

10 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 11

Wald's papers were of forbidding mathematical depth, not only in theorems are found in Mathematical Appendix C.) With these
the use of sophisticated tools, but also in the complexity of the foundations, plus the influence of the rapid development of linear
argument. As they gradually carne to be known among mathe- programming on both the mathematical (again closely related to
matical economists, they probably served as much to inhibit further saddle-point theorems) and economic 1 sides, it was perceived
research by their difficulty as to stimulate it. independently by a number of scholars that existence theorems of
Help finally carne from development of a related line of research, greater simplicity and generality than Wald's were now possible.
John von Neumann's theory of games (first basic paper published in The first papers were those of McKenzie [1954] and Arrow and
1928; see von Neumann and Morgenstern [1944]). This historical bebreu [1954]. Subsequent developments were due to Hukukane
relation between game theory and economic equilibrium has Nikaido [1956] and Hirofumi Uzawa, Debreu, and McKenzie [1959,
paradoxical elements. Game theory has developed severa! very 1961]. The most complete systematic account of the existence con-
general notions of equilibrium, which, in principie, should either ditions is in Debreu [1959]; the most general version is also in
replace the notion of competitive equilibrium or include it as a Debreu [1962].
special case. Indeed, one such equilibrium notion, that of the core,
is identical with Edgeworth's contract curve; it was introduced by 6. Developments During and After the 1930's: Stability-and
Gillies [1953] and applied to specifically market situations by Shubik Comparative StatiCs
[1959] and, in a manner much closer to standard economic thought,
by Scarf [1962] (see Chapter 8). The principal stimulation of game Independently of this development of the existence conditions for
theory to equilibrium theory has been through the use of mathe- equilibrium, the Anglo-American literature contained an intensive
matical tools developed in the former and used in the latter with study of the comparative statics and stability of general competitive
entirely different interpretations. Von Neumann himself made the equilibrium. Historically, it was closely related to analyses of the
first such application in his celebrated paper on balanced economic second-order conditions for maximization of profits by firms and of
growth [1937, 1945]. In this model, there were no demand functions, utility by consumers; the most important contributors were John R.
only production. The markets in each period had to be in equi- Hicks, Harold Hotelling, Paul Samuelson, and R. G. D. Allen. In
librium in the Zeuthen sense, but beyond this was equilibrium in a particular, Hicks [1939] introduced the argument that the stability
second sense, which may be termed stationary equilibrium. The of equilibrium carried with it sorne implications for the shapes of the
equilibrium configuration had to be the same from period to period. supply and demand functions in the neighborhood of equilibrium;
To prove the existence of equilibrium, von Neumann demonstrated hence, the effects of small shifts in any one behavior relation may be
that a certain ratio of bilinear forms had a saddle point, a generaliza- predicted, at least as to sign. Hicks' definition of stability has been
tion of the theorem that showed the existence of equilibrium in two- rep1aced in subsequent work by Samuelson's [1941, 1942]; however,
person zero-sum games. In game theory, however, the variables of Hicks showed that (locally) stability in his sense was equivalent to a
the problem were probabilities (of choosing alternative strategies), condition that has played a considerable role in subsequent research.
while in the application to equilibtium theory one set of variables Let Z be the excess demand (demand less supply) for the ith com-
was prices and the other the levels at which productive activities were modity; it is in general a function of Pl, ... , Pno the prices of all n
carried on. commodities. Then Hicks' definition of stability was equivalent to
Von Neumann deduced his saddle-point theorem from a general- the condition that the principal minors of the matrix whose elements
ization of,Brouwer's fixed-point theorem, a famous proposition in were zfpj had determinants that were positive or negative accord-
topology. A simplified version of von Neumann's theorem was ing as the number of rows or columns included was even or odd.
presented a few years later by the mathematician Shizuo Kakutani, 1 See Koopmans [1951a] for a collection of the work of George B. Dantzig,
and Kakutani's theorem has been the basic tool in virtually all sub- Albert W. Tucker, Harold W. Kuhn, Tjal!ing C. Koopmans and others, and
sequent work. (Statements and proofs of Brouwer's and Kakutani's John F. Nash, Jr. [1950].
12 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 13

Hicks also sought to derive comparative-statistics conclusions about analysis. The condition of zero profit for all processes leads to a
the response of prices to changes in demand functions. Presently system of linear equations. In the simple case in which all inputs
accepted theorems derive the same conclusions, from somewhat are original factors, prices of commodities that are produced in any
different premises, however (see Chapter 10). positive amount are related to factor prices by equations (2) (Section
Samuelson formulated the presently accepted definition of stability. 1.5). Note that if there is only one primary commodity, then the
It must be based, he argued, on an explicit dynamic model concerning relative prices of all commodities are determined by the technological
the behavior of prices when the system is out of equilibrium. He coefficients. On the other hand, if the number of factors does not
formalized the implicit assumption of Walras and most of his suc- exceed the number of commodities produced and if the matrix (a 1)
cessors: The price of each commodity in creases at a rate propor- has a rank equal to the number of factors (equals number of rows),
tional to excess demand for that commodity. This assumption then the factor prices are uniquely determined by the commodity
defines a system of differential eq uations; if every path satisfying the prices.
system and starting sufficiently close to equilibrium converges to it, These obvious conclusions turn out to generalize very con-
then the system is stable. Samuelson was able to demonstrate that siderably. The first extensions were to the case in which there are
Hicks' definition is neither necessary nor sufficient for his and that intermediate commodities, that is, produced goods used as inputs
the economic system is stable if the income effects on consumption into the production of goods (Leontief [1941]). Consider again only
are sufficiently small. He proposed a general correspondence prin- commodities produced in sorne positive amount so that the zero-
cipie that all meaningful theorems in comparative statics derive either profit condition holds for each production process. Now Iet au be
from the second-order conditions on maximization of profits by the amount of produced good i used in the production of one unit
firms or of utility by consumers or from the assumption that the of commodity j and let b1, 1 be the amount of original factor k used in
observed equilibrium was stable. In fact, very few useful proposi- the production of one unit of commodity j. As befo re, let p1 be the
tions are derivable from this principie. price of produced commodity j and let V~c be the price of original
The current trend in comparative statics and stability dates from factor k. Then the zero-profit conditions are written:
the work of Mosak [1944] and.Metzler [1945]. The emphasis has
tended to be a little different from Samuelson's correspondence
P1 = '5_. pa 1 + '5_. v,,b/CJ
i le
principie; rather, the tendency has been to formulate hypotheses
or, in matrix and vector notation,
about the excess-demand functions that imply both stability and
certain results in comparative statics. p = pA + vB, (3)
where p and vare the vectors with components p 1 and v1" respectively,
7. The Structure of Price Determination and the Uniqueness of and A and B re the matrices with elements a 1, b~c 1 , respectively.
Equilibrium Then (3) can be written
p(/- A)= vB, (4)
A development of the period since 1948 has been a more detailed
analysis of the relations between prices of factors and prices of and, if 1 - A is non-singular,
produced goods. It is typically assumed in these analyses that (a)
p = vB(/- A)- 1 (5)
each commodity is either an original factor or a produced good, but
never both, and (b) there is no joint production; that is, each Hence, commodity prices are determined by factor prices; in par-
production process has exactly one output, though it may have ticular, if there is only one original factor, it remains true that
severa! inputs. relative prices of produced goods are completely determined by the
The case in which it is assumed, in addition, that production takes technical coefficients, independent of demand. Also, if the rank of
place under conditions of fixed coefficients leads to relatively simple the matrix B equals the number of factors (rows), then it can be seen
12 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 13

Hicks also sought to derive comparative-statistics conclusions about analysis. The condition of zero profit for all processes leads to a
the response of prices to changes in demand functions. Presently system of linear equations. In the simple case in which all inputs
accepted theorems derive the same conclusions, from somewhat are original factors, prices of commodities that are produced in any
different premises, however (see Chapter 10). positive amount are related to factor prices by equations (2) (Section
Samuelson formulated the presently accepted definition of stability. 1.5). Note that if there is only one primary commodity, then the
It must be based, he argued, on an explicit dynamic model concerning relative prices of all commodities are determined by the technological
the behavior of prices when the system is out of equilibrium. He coefficients. On the other hand, if the number of factors does not
formalized the implicit assumption of Walras and most of his suc- exceed the number of commodities produced and if the matrix (a 1)
cessors: The price of each commodity in creases at a rate propor- has a rank equal to the number of factors (equals number of rows),
tional to excess demand for that commodity. This assumption then the factor prices are uniquely determined by the commodity
defines a system of differential eq uations; if every path satisfying the prices.
system and starting sufficiently close to equilibrium converges to it, These obvious conclusions turn out to generalize very con-
then the system is stable. Samuelson was able to demonstrate that siderably. The first extensions were to the case in which there are
Hicks' definition is neither necessary nor sufficient for his and that intermediate commodities, that is, produced goods used as inputs
the economic system is stable if the income effects on consumption into the production of goods (Leontief [1941]). Consider again only
are sufficiently small. He proposed a general correspondence prin- commodities produced in sorne positive amount so that the zero-
cipie that all meaningful theorems in comparative statics derive either profit condition holds for each production process. Now Iet au be
from the second-order conditions on maximization of profits by the amount of produced good i used in the production of one unit
firms or of utility by consumers or from the assumption that the of commodity j and let b1, 1 be the amount of original factor k used in
observed equilibrium was stable. In fact, very few useful proposi- the production of one unit of commodity j. As befo re, let p1 be the
tions are derivable from this principie. price of produced commodity j and let V~c be the price of original
The current trend in comparative statics and stability dates from factor k. Then the zero-profit conditions are written:
the work of Mosak [1944] and.Metzler [1945]. The emphasis has
tended to be a little different from Samuelson's correspondence
P1 = '5_. pa 1 + '5_. v,,b/CJ
i le
principie; rather, the tendency has been to formulate hypotheses
or, in matrix and vector notation,
about the excess-demand functions that imply both stability and
certain results in comparative statics. p = pA + vB, (3)
where p and vare the vectors with components p 1 and v1" respectively,
7. The Structure of Price Determination and the Uniqueness of and A and B re the matrices with elements a 1, b~c 1 , respectively.
Equilibrium Then (3) can be written
p(/- A)= vB, (4)
A development of the period since 1948 has been a more detailed
analysis of the relations between prices of factors and prices of and, if 1 - A is non-singular,
produced goods. It is typically assumed in these analyses that (a)
p = vB(/- A)- 1 (5)
each commodity is either an original factor or a produced good, but
never both, and (b) there is no joint production; that is, each Hence, commodity prices are determined by factor prices; in par-
production process has exactly one output, though it may have ticular, if there is only one original factor, it remains true that
severa! inputs. relative prices of produced goods are completely determined by the
The case in which it is assumed, in addition, that production takes technical coefficients, independent of demand. Also, if the rank of
place under conditions of fixed coefficients leads to relatively simple the matrix B equals the number of factors (rows), then it can be seen
14 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS 1-IISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 15

from (4) that factor prices are uniquely determined by the prices of In general, there is no need that equilibrium be unique, and ex-
commodities. amples of non-uniqueness have been known since Marshall. Wald
It should be remarked that the commodity prices determined by [1936] initiated the study of sufficient conditions for the uniqueness
(4) are necessarily non-negative if factor prices are, and if a natural of competitive equilibrium. Both of his alternative sufficient
condition on A is satis:fied. Specifically, it follows from the defini- conditions have sin ce beco me major themes of the literature: The
tions of A and B and the assumption that there is no joint production weak axiom of revealed preference holds for the market-demand
that the e1ements of A and B are non-ncgative. Now assume that functions or all commodities are gross subsiitutes (for the definition,
the system is productive in the sense that it is possible to produce a see D.9.5).
positive amount of every produced good if we ignore limitations due An error in Samuelson's conditions for factor price determination
to factor scarcities; in symbols, there exists a non-negative vector x was corrected by Gale and Nikaido [1965], who supplied the mathe-
such that Ax x (i.e., every component of Ax is less than the matical basis for a fairly general uniqueness theorem, which
corresponding component of x). Then it follows from a well-known generalizes, in particular, Wald's condition of gross substitutability
mathematical theory of Perron and Frobenius that the matfix 1 - A (see Sections 9.2-9.3) .
.is non-singular and that the elements of (! - A) are non-negative.
For v non-negative, vB is non-negative, and hence p = vB(l- A)- 1
Note
is non-negative. (For an exposition, see Karlin [1959, Vol. I,
pp. 245-246 and 256-258]; for the mathematical theory, see Karlin The material of this chapter is drawn from Arrow [1968].
[1959, Vol. I, 246-256] or Mathematical Appendix A.)
Work since 1948 has den:onstrated t~at these relations. betw~en
commodity and factor pnces generahze to the case mvolvmg
alternative methods of production (but the hypothesis of no joint
production is maintained). Samuelson [1951] and Georgescu-
Roegen [1951] showed that with one primary factor it is still true
that relative prices of produced goods are determined by the tech-
nology, independent of demand conditions. This is, in a certain
sense, a surprising resuscitation of the classical theory in which
prices are determined by supply conditions alone. Since com-
petitive production always minimizes costs, it follows that the
technique actually chosen for the production for any commodity is
also independent of demand conditions, though it will depend, in
general, on technological conditions in other industries. For more
extended discussion, see Section 2.11.
The conditions for the determination of factor prices by com-
modity prices were studied ~y Samuelson [1948, 1953-54]; the
problem arose in the context of foreign trade, which is assumed to
equalize commodity prices across countries. In fact, the question
of the conditions under which commodity prices determine factor
prices is a special case of the conditions for the uniqueness of general
equilibrium prices, specifically the case in which demand for com-
modities is perfectly elastic.
14 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS 1-IISTORICAL INTRODUCTION 15

from (4) that factor prices are uniquely determined by the prices of In general, there is no need that equilibrium be unique, and ex-
commodities. amples of non-uniqueness have been known since Marshall. Wald
It should be remarked that the commodity prices determined by [1936] initiated the study of sufficient conditions for the uniqueness
(4) are necessarily non-negative if factor prices are, and if a natural of competitive equilibrium. Both of his alternative sufficient
condition on A is satis:fied. Specifically, it follows from the defini- conditions have sin ce beco me major themes of the literature: The
tions of A and B and the assumption that there is no joint production weak axiom of revealed preference holds for the market-demand
that the e1ements of A and B are non-ncgative. Now assume that functions or all commodities are gross subsiitutes (for the definition,
the system is productive in the sense that it is possible to produce a see D.9.5).
positive amount of every produced good if we ignore limitations due An error in Samuelson's conditions for factor price determination
to factor scarcities; in symbols, there exists a non-negative vector x was corrected by Gale and Nikaido [1965], who supplied the mathe-
such that Ax x (i.e., every component of Ax is less than the matical basis for a fairly general uniqueness theorem, which
corresponding component of x). Then it follows from a well-known generalizes, in particular, Wald's condition of gross substitutability
mathematical theory of Perron and Frobenius that the matfix 1 - A (see Sections 9.2-9.3) .
.is non-singular and that the elements of (! - A) are non-negative.
For v non-negative, vB is non-negative, and hence p = vB(l- A)- 1
Note
is non-negative. (For an exposition, see Karlin [1959, Vol. I,
pp. 245-246 and 256-258]; for the mathematical theory, see Karlin The material of this chapter is drawn from Arrow [1968].
[1959, Vol. I, 246-256] or Mathematical Appendix A.)
Work since 1948 has den:onstrated t~at these relations. betw~en
commodity and factor pnces generahze to the case mvolvmg
alternative methods of production (but the hypothesis of no joint
production is maintained). Samuelson [1951] and Georgescu-
Roegen [1951] showed that with one primary factor it is still true
that relative prices of produced goods are determined by the tech-
nology, independent of demand conditions. This is, in a certain
sense, a surprising resuscitation of the classical theory in which
prices are determined by supply conditions alone. Since com-
petitive production always minimizes costs, it follows that the
technique actually chosen for the production for any commodity is
also independent of demand conditions, though it will depend, in
general, on technological conditions in other industries. For more
extended discussion, see Section 2.11.
The conditions for the determination of factor prices by com-
modity prices were studied ~y Samuelson [1948, 1953-54]; the
problem arose in the context of foreign trade, which is assumed to
equalize commodity prices across countries. In fact, the question
of the conditions under which commodity prices determine factor
prices is a special case of the conditions for the uniqueness of general
equilibrium prices, specifically the case in which demand for com-
modities is perfectly elastic.
r,
1'

Chapter Two MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 17

We start our discussion with a consideration of a very abstract


MARKET EQUILIBRIUM: kind of economy and then proceed to analyze a number of more
A FIRST APPROACH restricted situations.

To be or not to be, that is the 2. Goods and Prices


question. A good may be defined by its physical characteristics, its location
-W. Shakespeare, Hamlet
in space, and the date of its delivery. Goods differing in any of
these characteristics will be regarded as different. Services are
regarded as goods. We shall suppose here that the number of
different goods is finite.
1. The Problem
We shall write p 1 as the price of the ith good and we define p as
We shaJI be considering a number of constructions r'epresenting the n-dimensional row vector with components p 1 (i = 1, ... , n).
economies in which agents take the terms at which they may transact All prices are expressed in fictional unit of account-say "bancors"
as independently given. This, of cotme, is a feature of a perfectly -and aJI prices are viewed from the present. Thus if "i" is a given
competitive economy. A consequence of this is that part of the good to be delivered at sorne location "A" in" T" periods from now,
environment relevant to the decisions of economic agents consists of then p 1 is the price that must be paid now for delivery of that good
the prices of various goods that they take as given. Our main at that place at that time. This supposes the existen ce of aJI possible
concern will be the description of situations in which the desired futures markets, a highly unrealistic assumption with which we shaJI
actions of economic agents are all mutuaJly compatible and can dispense at a later stage.
all be carried out simultaneously, and for which w~ can prove that
for the various economies discussed, there exists a set of prices that
will cause agents to make mutuaJly compatible decisions. 3. The Excess-Demand Functions
In carrying out this program we have imposed a number of Demand and supply decisions are taken by two kinds of agents:
restrictions on the matters covered and the degree of generality households andjirms. The two are distinguished by the property that
aimed at. Many of these restrictions are removed in the foJlowing firms do, and households do not, take production decisions. This
chapters. Our first omission will be the rigorous discussion of the distinction is convenient.
eh oices of economic agents; this will be found in Chapters 3 and 4. Let xhi be the decision of household h with respect to good i.
Our basic, and often implied, hypothesis is that agents have a com- Then, if xh 1 < O, we shall say that i is a service supplied by household
plete ordering of points in the space of their possible choices and
h; when xhi is non-negative, then i will be a good demanded by
that, of the choices they can actually make in a given market situa- h, where this concept includes zero demand. We Jet x" repr'esent
tion, none is taken if there exists one that is preferred. These ideas the n-dimensional column vector with components xh!. Summation
are sufficiently familiar to justify invoking them informally before over households 1s indicated by omitting the subscript h. Thus,
establishing them thoroughly. Our second omission, to be put
we have
formally presently, is that we 'shall be exclusively concerned with
situations in which, for each set of prices, there is only one "best"
choice for each agent. This will allow us to deal with demand and
x1 = xht x = L x".
h

supply functions rather than with "correspondences" (i.e., situations


"
We write y 11 as the decision of firm f with respect to good i.
in which the demand for a good, say at a given set of prices, must be We regard Yn < O as denoting that i is an input demanded by J,
represented by a set rather than by a number). The omission is while Y!i non-negative means that i is supplied by fwhere this concept
rectified in Chapters 3-5 and further discussed below. includes zero supply. Also, y1 is the n-dimensional column vector

16
r,
1'

Chapter Two MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 17

We start our discussion with a consideration of a very abstract


MARKET EQUILIBRIUM: kind of economy and then proceed to analyze a number of more
A FIRST APPROACH restricted situations.

To be or not to be, that is the 2. Goods and Prices


question. A good may be defined by its physical characteristics, its location
-W. Shakespeare, Hamlet
in space, and the date of its delivery. Goods differing in any of
these characteristics will be regarded as different. Services are
regarded as goods. We shall suppose here that the number of
different goods is finite.
1. The Problem
We shall write p 1 as the price of the ith good and we define p as
We shaJI be considering a number of constructions r'epresenting the n-dimensional row vector with components p 1 (i = 1, ... , n).
economies in which agents take the terms at which they may transact All prices are expressed in fictional unit of account-say "bancors"
as independently given. This, of cotme, is a feature of a perfectly -and aJI prices are viewed from the present. Thus if "i" is a given
competitive economy. A consequence of this is that part of the good to be delivered at sorne location "A" in" T" periods from now,
environment relevant to the decisions of economic agents consists of then p 1 is the price that must be paid now for delivery of that good
the prices of various goods that they take as given. Our main at that place at that time. This supposes the existen ce of aJI possible
concern will be the description of situations in which the desired futures markets, a highly unrealistic assumption with which we shaJI
actions of economic agents are all mutuaJly compatible and can dispense at a later stage.
all be carried out simultaneously, and for which w~ can prove that
for the various economies discussed, there exists a set of prices that
will cause agents to make mutuaJly compatible decisions. 3. The Excess-Demand Functions
In carrying out this program we have imposed a number of Demand and supply decisions are taken by two kinds of agents:
restrictions on the matters covered and the degree of generality households andjirms. The two are distinguished by the property that
aimed at. Many of these restrictions are removed in the foJlowing firms do, and households do not, take production decisions. This
chapters. Our first omission will be the rigorous discussion of the distinction is convenient.
eh oices of economic agents; this will be found in Chapters 3 and 4. Let xhi be the decision of household h with respect to good i.
Our basic, and often implied, hypothesis is that agents have a com- Then, if xh 1 < O, we shall say that i is a service supplied by household
plete ordering of points in the space of their possible choices and
h; when xhi is non-negative, then i will be a good demanded by
that, of the choices they can actually make in a given market situa- h, where this concept includes zero demand. We Jet x" repr'esent
tion, none is taken if there exists one that is preferred. These ideas the n-dimensional column vector with components xh!. Summation
are sufficiently familiar to justify invoking them informally before over households 1s indicated by omitting the subscript h. Thus,
establishing them thoroughly. Our second omission, to be put
we have
formally presently, is that we 'shall be exclusively concerned with
situations in which, for each set of prices, there is only one "best"
choice for each agent. This will allow us to deal with demand and
x1 = xht x = L x".
h

supply functions rather than with "correspondences" (i.e., situations


"
We write y 11 as the decision of firm f with respect to good i.
in which the demand for a good, say at a given set of prices, must be We regard Yn < O as denoting that i is an input demanded by J,
represented by a set rather than by a number). The omission is while Y!i non-negative means that i is supplied by fwhere this concept
rectified in Chapters 3-5 and further discussed below. includes zero supply. Also, y1 is the n-dimensional column vector

16
18 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A. FIRST APPROACH 19

with components Yn Summation over firms is indicated by omitting but that the firm produces under constant returns to scale. Then
the subscriptf. Thus, we have evidently for k > O, ky1 will also maximize profits and so p does not
determine the total supply of good i uniquely and F does not hold.
Y1 = .2;Yti Y= _2; Yt Other examples are possible, none of which _relies on unrealistic
f f
postulates. It is clear, therefore, that we shall have to regard F as
If there are any quantities of goods available in the economy an assumption that, at sorne stage, we must do without.
before there is any production or market exchange, then we shall There is one other important point that requires emphasis. The
take it that these goods are owned by households. We write X as number z(p) willlater be derived from a proper theory of the actions
the amount of good i owned by household h, and note that for good of economic agents, households, and firms. It tells us what the
sense this must be a non-negative quantity. As before, x1, is the excess demand for i will be if all attempted to carry out their preferred
n-dimensional column vector with components Xn~ and summation actions at p. The excess-demand function is thus an ex ante
over households is indicated by omitting the subscript h. concept; it is hypothetical in the sense that the actual purchases and
Market equilibrium is concerned with the compatibility of the sales may differ from those that the theory of the decisions of agents
decisions of the different firms and households, and therefore we are tells us would be the purchases and sales regarded as proper by the
interested in the difference between the demand for a good and its agents at p. 1 Indeed, at z(p) positive, for instance, it clearly would
total supply. The latter is the sum of the production of the good not be possible for all the agents to complete the transactions with
and the quantities of it available before production. Thus, the respect to i that they regard as desirable at p.
rl
total supply of good i is y 1 + x 1 We define the excess demand for
l;.11 good i (written z1) by
il, 4. The Main Assumptions
!!
Z = X - y1 - X i=1, ... ,n.
In this section we introduce the main assumptions to be used in
We write z for the n-dimensional column vector with components z1 this chapter. Many of these will be deduced as propositions from
and refer to it as the excess-demand vector. Taking x and X as more basic postulates later in this book (Sections 3.4 and 4.5).
given, we regard z as a function of p. We shall sometimes refer to The first assumption asserts that the actions of agents depend on
z 1 < O asan excess supply of good i. We put this formally: the rates at which goods exchange one against another and not at all
on the rate at which goods exchange against the (fictional) unit of
AssUMPTION 1 (F). To any p there corresponds a unique number
account, in this case, bancors. This assumption should not be
z(p) called the excess-demandfunction for i and so a unique vector
misunderstood. lf one of the goods acts as a medium of exchange,
of excess-demand functions z(p). We have z1(p) = x 1(p) - y1(p) -
for instance, then it too will have a price in terms of unit of account,
x1 and call x1(p) the demand function and y1(p) the supply function. 1 and it is not asserted that the rate at which goods exchange against
It is quite important to understand why this assumption is indeed this particular good, the medium of exchange, is of no consequence
restrictive, and we consider a simple example by way of illustration to the decisions of economic agents. We write this assumption
for which F will not hold. Suppose that, given p, there is a formally:
unique household response x1(p). Suppose further that good i is
produced by firmj, which produces no other kind of good,_while no ASSUMPTION 2 (H). z(p) = z(kp) for all p > 0 and k > 0; the
;1

other firm produces i. Let the firm choose y1 , among all the choices excess-demand functions are homogeneous of degree zero in p.
illr, of y1 open to it, so as to maximize py, its profits. Assume that p A consequence of H is that we may fix the level of p arbitrarily
is such that this maximization is possible and is achieved for py1 = O, i'l without restricting our analysis in any way. For our purposes, this
1
Of coLirSe y(p) is a vector and contains negative components so that this use
1
of the notion "supply function" is not that of the textbook. See Sections 13.6 and 14.4 for detailed discussions.
18 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A. FIRST APPROACH 19

with components Yn Summation over firms is indicated by omitting but that the firm produces under constant returns to scale. Then
the subscriptf. Thus, we have evidently for k > O, ky1 will also maximize profits and so p does not
determine the total supply of good i uniquely and F does not hold.
Y1 = .2;Yti Y= _2; Yt Other examples are possible, none of which _relies on unrealistic
f f
postulates. It is clear, therefore, that we shall have to regard F as
If there are any quantities of goods available in the economy an assumption that, at sorne stage, we must do without.
before there is any production or market exchange, then we shall There is one other important point that requires emphasis. The
take it that these goods are owned by households. We write X as number z(p) willlater be derived from a proper theory of the actions
the amount of good i owned by household h, and note that for good of economic agents, households, and firms. It tells us what the
sense this must be a non-negative quantity. As before, x1, is the excess demand for i will be if all attempted to carry out their preferred
n-dimensional column vector with components Xn~ and summation actions at p. The excess-demand function is thus an ex ante
over households is indicated by omitting the subscript h. concept; it is hypothetical in the sense that the actual purchases and
Market equilibrium is concerned with the compatibility of the sales may differ from those that the theory of the decisions of agents
decisions of the different firms and households, and therefore we are tells us would be the purchases and sales regarded as proper by the
interested in the difference between the demand for a good and its agents at p. 1 Indeed, at z(p) positive, for instance, it clearly would
total supply. The latter is the sum of the production of the good not be possible for all the agents to complete the transactions with
and the quantities of it available before production. Thus, the respect to i that they regard as desirable at p.
rl
total supply of good i is y 1 + x 1 We define the excess demand for
l;.11 good i (written z1) by
il, 4. The Main Assumptions
!!
Z = X - y1 - X i=1, ... ,n.
In this section we introduce the main assumptions to be used in
We write z for the n-dimensional column vector with components z1 this chapter. Many of these will be deduced as propositions from
and refer to it as the excess-demand vector. Taking x and X as more basic postulates later in this book (Sections 3.4 and 4.5).
given, we regard z as a function of p. We shall sometimes refer to The first assumption asserts that the actions of agents depend on
z 1 < O asan excess supply of good i. We put this formally: the rates at which goods exchange one against another and not at all
on the rate at which goods exchange against the (fictional) unit of
AssUMPTION 1 (F). To any p there corresponds a unique number
account, in this case, bancors. This assumption should not be
z(p) called the excess-demandfunction for i and so a unique vector
misunderstood. lf one of the goods acts as a medium of exchange,
of excess-demand functions z(p). We have z1(p) = x 1(p) - y1(p) -
for instance, then it too will have a price in terms of unit of account,
x1 and call x1(p) the demand function and y1(p) the supply function. 1 and it is not asserted that the rate at which goods exchange against
It is quite important to understand why this assumption is indeed this particular good, the medium of exchange, is of no consequence
restrictive, and we consider a simple example by way of illustration to the decisions of economic agents. We write this assumption
for which F will not hold. Suppose that, given p, there is a formally:
unique household response x1(p). Suppose further that good i is
produced by firmj, which produces no other kind of good,_while no ASSUMPTION 2 (H). z(p) = z(kp) for all p > 0 and k > 0; the
;1

other firm produces i. Let the firm choose y1 , among all the choices excess-demand functions are homogeneous of degree zero in p.
illr, of y1 open to it, so as to maximize py, its profits. Assume that p A consequence of H is that we may fix the level of p arbitrarily
is such that this maximization is possible and is achieved for py1 = O, i'l without restricting our analysis in any way. For our purposes, this
1
Of coLirSe y(p) is a vector and contains negative components so that this use
1
of the notion "supply function" is not that of the textbook. See Sections 13.6 and 14.4 for detailed discussions.
20 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 21

is most conveniently done by considering only those prices that By our definition of goods (Section 2.2), this "accounting restraint"
belong to the ndimensional simplex Sn. which is defined by includes borrowing and lending. The individual borrows by selling
goods now for future delivery and he lends by buying goods now for
future delivery.
The difference between the total value of all purchases planned by
It may be objected that this procedure is rather drastic because it households and firms and the total value of sales planned by them is
precludes from consideration situations in which all prices are zero evidently pz. We shall now give reasons for taking this number to
and also situations in which sorne price is negative. be nonpositive. Suppose that all firms aim to maximize their
First we note that if we wished to examine an economy from which profits and that they all have the choice of not engaging in any
the "economic problem" of scarcity is absent, we could do so by productive activity. Clearly, since py is the profits of all firms taken
supposing everyone to own sorne quantities of a good, the price of together, we roay take it that py is always nonnegative. Next sup
which we set equal to unity so that all the other goods have a zero pose that every household h receives a given fraction, dh ::::: O, of the
price. This we can do while restricting al! p to be in Sn., The total profits of firms and that
proper representation of such an economy could not be achieved by
'J..dh=l.
setting p = O. h
There is also a technical reason for excluding p = O from con Then h may choose any xh that satisfies
sideration. Suppose H holds for k ::::: O and not just for k > O.
Now consider two price vectors, p and p', with z(p) -. z(p'). Then pxh - pxh - dhpy :s; O. (1)
by H, z(kp) = z(p) and z(kp') = z(p') for k > O. Evidently, if we
If we can suppose further that a household always prefers x" to
allow k to approach zero, the two vectors of the excess-demand
x~ if xh > x;, and that it will never choose an action if a preferred one
functions must approach different limits, from which we conclude is available, then the reader can verify that xh will always be such as
that z(p) is not continuous at p.= O. But we certainly wbuld find it to make the expression in (1) equal to zero. Summing (1) over h
very inconvenient to ha ve todo without the continuity of the excess then gives pz = O.
demand function at any point of the price domain we consider, and These are the underlying rationalizations of the assumption that
in this instance nothing of economic interest would be gained. we now put formally.
The reason. for excluding negative prices is less cogent and also
less necessary for the subsequent analysis, though we shall maintain AsSUMPTION 3 (W). For all pE Sn. pz(p) =O (Walras' law). ln
it for simplicity. If a good has a negative price, then the individual what follows we shall need another, rather technical assumption.
selling that good has to give up units ofsome other good or goods AssUMPTION 4 (C). The vector excess-demand function, z(p), is
with positive price as well. If he also has the option of disposing continuous over its domain of definition, Sn.
'i of the good without giving up any other good with a positive price,
'1
1: it is reasonable to suppose that he will prefer this option. Thus the Assumption C implies that z(p) is bounded everywhere, since Sn
11' exclusion of negative prices from consideration is justified if we is a compact set, which here means that it is closed and bounded.
l i!
1 suppose that there always exists the option of free disposal, for then In particular, this means that the demand for a free good is bounded;
no one would be wiing to transact at a negative price and so a every individual beco mes satiated with respect to any particular good.
negative price could not arise. In this chapter and elsewhere in the Unfortunately this assumption comes close to being inconsistent
book, free disposal is postulated. with the reasoning underlying W, which requires that at any point
The second assumption derives from the fact that, stealing apart, the household is unsatiated with respect to at least one good. A
no agent can plan a greater expenditure on goods and services than weaker continuity assumption that permits unlimited demand for
the receipts he plans to obtain from the sale of goods and services. ! ; free goods will be introduced in Section 2.8.
1

1
1

!
20 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 21

is most conveniently done by considering only those prices that By our definition of goods (Section 2.2), this "accounting restraint"
belong to the ndimensional simplex Sn. which is defined by includes borrowing and lending. The individual borrows by selling
goods now for future delivery and he lends by buying goods now for
future delivery.
The difference between the total value of all purchases planned by
It may be objected that this procedure is rather drastic because it households and firms and the total value of sales planned by them is
precludes from consideration situations in which all prices are zero evidently pz. We shall now give reasons for taking this number to
and also situations in which sorne price is negative. be nonpositive. Suppose that all firms aim to maximize their
First we note that if we wished to examine an economy from which profits and that they all have the choice of not engaging in any
the "economic problem" of scarcity is absent, we could do so by productive activity. Clearly, since py is the profits of all firms taken
supposing everyone to own sorne quantities of a good, the price of together, we roay take it that py is always nonnegative. Next sup
which we set equal to unity so that all the other goods have a zero pose that every household h receives a given fraction, dh ::::: O, of the
price. This we can do while restricting al! p to be in Sn., The total profits of firms and that
proper representation of such an economy could not be achieved by
'J..dh=l.
setting p = O. h
There is also a technical reason for excluding p = O from con Then h may choose any xh that satisfies
sideration. Suppose H holds for k ::::: O and not just for k > O.
Now consider two price vectors, p and p', with z(p) -. z(p'). Then pxh - pxh - dhpy :s; O. (1)
by H, z(kp) = z(p) and z(kp') = z(p') for k > O. Evidently, if we
If we can suppose further that a household always prefers x" to
allow k to approach zero, the two vectors of the excess-demand
x~ if xh > x;, and that it will never choose an action if a preferred one
functions must approach different limits, from which we conclude is available, then the reader can verify that xh will always be such as
that z(p) is not continuous at p.= O. But we certainly wbuld find it to make the expression in (1) equal to zero. Summing (1) over h
very inconvenient to ha ve todo without the continuity of the excess then gives pz = O.
demand function at any point of the price domain we consider, and These are the underlying rationalizations of the assumption that
in this instance nothing of economic interest would be gained. we now put formally.
The reason. for excluding negative prices is less cogent and also
less necessary for the subsequent analysis, though we shall maintain AsSUMPTION 3 (W). For all pE Sn. pz(p) =O (Walras' law). ln
it for simplicity. If a good has a negative price, then the individual what follows we shall need another, rather technical assumption.
selling that good has to give up units ofsome other good or goods AssUMPTION 4 (C). The vector excess-demand function, z(p), is
with positive price as well. If he also has the option of disposing continuous over its domain of definition, Sn.
'i of the good without giving up any other good with a positive price,
'1
1: it is reasonable to suppose that he will prefer this option. Thus the Assumption C implies that z(p) is bounded everywhere, since Sn
11' exclusion of negative prices from consideration is justified if we is a compact set, which here means that it is closed and bounded.
l i!
1 suppose that there always exists the option of free disposal, for then In particular, this means that the demand for a free good is bounded;
no one would be wiing to transact at a negative price and so a every individual beco mes satiated with respect to any particular good.
negative price could not arise. In this chapter and elsewhere in the Unfortunately this assumption comes close to being inconsistent
book, free disposal is postulated. with the reasoning underlying W, which requires that at any point
The second assumption derives from the fact that, stealing apart, the household is unsatiated with respect to at least one good. A
no agent can plan a greater expenditure on goods and services than weaker continuity assumption that permits unlimited demand for
the receipts he plans to obtain from the sale of goods and services. ! ; free goods will be introduced in Section 2.8.
1

1
1

!
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 23
22

It may help the reader to have an example of the violation of C. Before we formalize this idea we must take note of a special point.
Suppose again that good i is produced only by firmf, which produces The decision to supply a good in a perfectly competitive economy is
no other goods. Given the prices of all goods other than i, assume nota decision to supply so-and-so much to such-and-such agents, but
the average cost curve off to be U shaped. 1 Let pX" be the lowest simply to exchange so-and-so much of the good for othergoods. If
price at which the firrri can cover average costs. Then by the usual the price ruling for a good is zero and agents planto supply sorne of it,
assumptions, the firm's output will be zero for all Pi < PT, while we then by the assumption of free disposal (see discussion of H in
stipulate that there is a positive output at p{. It can be left to the Section 2.4), we may simply say that agents decide to dispose of a
reader to verify that C will be violated. Since this example is not certain amount of the good. Clearly this decision can be carried out
fanciful, we must conclude that C indeed may be a serious restric- by our assumption, whatever the demand of other agents for that
tion on our analysis. Although this assumption can be somewhat good may be. If this demand were greater than the amount
relaxed after F is abandoned, we cannot do without something very offered, however, then the decisions of the demanding agents could
close to it in many of the results to be given both in this chapter not be carried to fruition. From this we conclude that while we
and in this book. However, we hope to draw sorne conclusions for would never be willing to regard a situation with positive excess
the working of an economic system in certain of the cases in which demand in sorne market as an equilibrium, an excess supply in a
market where the price is zero is quite consistent with our notion of
e is violated.
an equilibrium. All this seems agreeable to common sense and it
remains to put it more formally.
5. Equilibrium
DEFINITION 1 (E). p* in Sn is called an equilibrium if z(p*) =::; O,
Economic agents may be taken to reach their decisions in the light
where z(p) is derived from the "preferred" actions of agents.
of what they want and what they can get. If tastes and technology
are given, and if the goods owned by individuals and households That this formal definition indeed corresponds to our discussion
are also given, then the variables influencing their decisions are the of the equilibrium concept can be seen with the aid of the following
prices prevailing in the various markets. If at sorne set of admissible theorem.
prices (i.e., for us sorne p in Sn) all these decisions can be carried out
THEOREM l. If W and z(p*) =::; O, then z;(p*) < O implies that
simultaneously, then we may say that these decisions are compatible
and that the prices are equilibrium prices. There are really two PT =O.
sets of ideas involved in this notion of equilibrium. On the one Proof Since p* is in Sn, it follows from the assumptions of T.2.1
hand, in such a situation every agent can achieve what he wishes to that every element in the sum p*z(p*) is non-positive. Then, if,
achieve. On the other hand, if tastes, technology, and the ownership contrary to whaf is asserted, PT > O, it must be that p*z(p*) < O,
of goods remain given, there will be no mechanism to bring about which contradicts W. Since no price can be negative, this com-
a change in p. Under the conditions postulated, it is argued that a pletes the proof.
change in prices is a signa!, the consequence of incompatibility in
the decisions of agents. This is a familiar notion, the "law of In severa! respects D.2.1 is incomplete because it does not specify
demand and supply," which is discussed more extensively in Chapters the conditions that must hold for each agent if his decision is to be
11, 12, and 13. the "best" open to him at p*. This, however, must be postponed
until Chapters 3 and 4. Here we must be satisfied with our rather
1 Since we have taken pE Sn, the curve must be thought of as constructed .as
follows: Take any p E Sn, and suppose that at this p there is at least one pomt informal treatment.
on i's average cost curve equal to p 1 Now, say, raise p, to p{ and multiply all It should also be noted that there is no reason to suppose that
other prices by k < 1 so that the new p' E Sn. Again find a point on the there is only one equilibrium price vector. The question of the
average cost curve at p' that is equal to p. Proceed in this way to trace the
"uniqueness" of an equilibrium will be fully explored in Chapter 9.
whole curve.
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 23
22

It may help the reader to have an example of the violation of C. Before we formalize this idea we must take note of a special point.
Suppose again that good i is produced only by firmf, which produces The decision to supply a good in a perfectly competitive economy is
no other goods. Given the prices of all goods other than i, assume nota decision to supply so-and-so much to such-and-such agents, but
the average cost curve off to be U shaped. 1 Let pX" be the lowest simply to exchange so-and-so much of the good for othergoods. If
price at which the firrri can cover average costs. Then by the usual the price ruling for a good is zero and agents planto supply sorne of it,
assumptions, the firm's output will be zero for all Pi < PT, while we then by the assumption of free disposal (see discussion of H in
stipulate that there is a positive output at p{. It can be left to the Section 2.4), we may simply say that agents decide to dispose of a
reader to verify that C will be violated. Since this example is not certain amount of the good. Clearly this decision can be carried out
fanciful, we must conclude that C indeed may be a serious restric- by our assumption, whatever the demand of other agents for that
tion on our analysis. Although this assumption can be somewhat good may be. If this demand were greater than the amount
relaxed after F is abandoned, we cannot do without something very offered, however, then the decisions of the demanding agents could
close to it in many of the results to be given both in this chapter not be carried to fruition. From this we conclude that while we
and in this book. However, we hope to draw sorne conclusions for would never be willing to regard a situation with positive excess
the working of an economic system in certain of the cases in which demand in sorne market as an equilibrium, an excess supply in a
market where the price is zero is quite consistent with our notion of
e is violated.
an equilibrium. All this seems agreeable to common sense and it
remains to put it more formally.
5. Equilibrium
DEFINITION 1 (E). p* in Sn is called an equilibrium if z(p*) =::; O,
Economic agents may be taken to reach their decisions in the light
where z(p) is derived from the "preferred" actions of agents.
of what they want and what they can get. If tastes and technology
are given, and if the goods owned by individuals and households That this formal definition indeed corresponds to our discussion
are also given, then the variables influencing their decisions are the of the equilibrium concept can be seen with the aid of the following
prices prevailing in the various markets. If at sorne set of admissible theorem.
prices (i.e., for us sorne p in Sn) all these decisions can be carried out
THEOREM l. If W and z(p*) =::; O, then z;(p*) < O implies that
simultaneously, then we may say that these decisions are compatible
and that the prices are equilibrium prices. There are really two PT =O.
sets of ideas involved in this notion of equilibrium. On the one Proof Since p* is in Sn, it follows from the assumptions of T.2.1
hand, in such a situation every agent can achieve what he wishes to that every element in the sum p*z(p*) is non-positive. Then, if,
achieve. On the other hand, if tastes, technology, and the ownership contrary to whaf is asserted, PT > O, it must be that p*z(p*) < O,
of goods remain given, there will be no mechanism to bring about which contradicts W. Since no price can be negative, this com-
a change in p. Under the conditions postulated, it is argued that a pletes the proof.
change in prices is a signa!, the consequence of incompatibility in
the decisions of agents. This is a familiar notion, the "law of In severa! respects D.2.1 is incomplete because it does not specify
demand and supply," which is discussed more extensively in Chapters the conditions that must hold for each agent if his decision is to be
11, 12, and 13. the "best" open to him at p*. This, however, must be postponed
until Chapters 3 and 4. Here we must be satisfied with our rather
1 Since we have taken pE Sn, the curve must be thought of as constructed .as
follows: Take any p E Sn, and suppose that at this p there is at least one pomt informal treatment.
on i's average cost curve equal to p 1 Now, say, raise p, to p{ and multiply all It should also be noted that there is no reason to suppose that
other prices by k < 1 so that the new p' E Sn. Again find a point on the there is only one equilibrium price vector. The question of the
average cost curve at p' that is equal to p. Proceed in this way to trace the
"uniqueness" of an equilibrium will be fully explored in Chapter 9.
whole curve.
24 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 25
Here we simply introduce a piece of notation: We write E for the sorne judgment as to the Iikelihood that the coherence of decisions
set of equilibrium price vectors, implied by equillbrium is attainable by actual economies. In this,
E = {p z(p) ::; O; pE Sn}
J
however, due care will ha veto be taken not to confuse the statement
"an equilibrium cannot be shown to exist" with the statement "no
equilibrium is possible."
6. The Existence of Equilibrium-the Case of Two Goods In Figure 2-1 we illustrate the propositiqn just established for a
two-good economy. In the diagram the horizontal axis is of unit
This section is to serve as an introduction to the proof that in
1ength.
general, given our assumptions, the set E is not empty. It is hoped
that it will facilitate a proper appreciation of the roles of the various
assumptions in the proof. In what follows we take all p to be in Sn. 7. The Existence of an Equilibrium: Many Goods
eonsider, in a two-goocl-economy, the two price vectors
When we turn to the economy with many goods, it is clear that the
p' = (0,1) and p" = (1,0). simple procedure of Section 2.6 will not serve, although the lessons
we have.learned will continue to be of interest, as we shall see.
We suppose that neither p' nor p" is in E, else there is nothing to Indeed, the best introduction to the general case is probably achieved
prove. But then it must be that z1 (p') > O and z 2(p") > O. eon- by staying with the two-good case a Iittle longer.
sider the fi.rst of these. By W we have Oz 1 (p') + 1z2(p') = O. If, Take any arbitrary point pon the horizontal axis of Figure 2-1 so
contrary to our assertion, we had z 1 (p') ::; O, then the fi.rst term that p is in Sn. At the point chosen in the figure, z 1 (p) is positive
1
would ~ertainly be zero and so also z 2(p') = O, which contradicts and z 2(p) is negative. Let us adopt the following rules:
,il' the supposition that p' is not in E. The same argument establishes
1
li,
the inequality for z 2(p"). (1) Raise the price of the good in positive excess demand.
'1'
1'
1
1
Now Iet (2) Lower or at least do not raise the price of the good in
excess supply, but never lower the price below zero.
p(m) = mp' + (1 - m)p" with 1 2m2 O.
By W, one oJ the numbers z 1 (p(m)) and z 2 (p(m)) is positive and
the other negative when m ,, 0,1, unless p(m) E E. Suppose then,
without loss of generality, that z 1 (p(m 0 )) < O for sorne m 0 # 0,1.
Now Iet m increase from m 0 to l. We already know that z 1 (p(O)) is
positive, and therefore, as m approaches zero, somewhere z 1 (p(m))
must change sign. But, by e, it cannot change sign without
becoming zero. Suppose this happens at m*. Then p(m*) is in E,
for, by W, it must be that z 2 (p(m*)) = O.
We note the important role of e in this demonstration. Without
it we could not exclude the possibility of a change in the sign of z 1 , p"
as m approaches zero, without its ever becoming equal to zero. Of
course we also relied heavily on W, but this assumption does not
appear to be very restrictive. As was indicated in the discussion of
e, however, the Iatter will certainly exclude a number of perfectly
possible situations from consideration. Later in the book, an
investigation of sorne of these possibilities should help us to form Figure 2-I
24 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 25
Here we simply introduce a piece of notation: We write E for the sorne judgment as to the Iikelihood that the coherence of decisions
set of equilibrium price vectors, implied by equillbrium is attainable by actual economies. In this,
E = {p z(p) ::; O; pE Sn}
J
however, due care will ha veto be taken not to confuse the statement
"an equilibrium cannot be shown to exist" with the statement "no
equilibrium is possible."
6. The Existence of Equilibrium-the Case of Two Goods In Figure 2-1 we illustrate the propositiqn just established for a
two-good economy. In the diagram the horizontal axis is of unit
This section is to serve as an introduction to the proof that in
1ength.
general, given our assumptions, the set E is not empty. It is hoped
that it will facilitate a proper appreciation of the roles of the various
assumptions in the proof. In what follows we take all p to be in Sn. 7. The Existence of an Equilibrium: Many Goods
eonsider, in a two-goocl-economy, the two price vectors
When we turn to the economy with many goods, it is clear that the
p' = (0,1) and p" = (1,0). simple procedure of Section 2.6 will not serve, although the lessons
we have.learned will continue to be of interest, as we shall see.
We suppose that neither p' nor p" is in E, else there is nothing to Indeed, the best introduction to the general case is probably achieved
prove. But then it must be that z1 (p') > O and z 2(p") > O. eon- by staying with the two-good case a Iittle longer.
sider the fi.rst of these. By W we have Oz 1 (p') + 1z2(p') = O. If, Take any arbitrary point pon the horizontal axis of Figure 2-1 so
contrary to our assertion, we had z 1 (p') ::; O, then the fi.rst term that p is in Sn. At the point chosen in the figure, z 1 (p) is positive
1
would ~ertainly be zero and so also z 2(p') = O, which contradicts and z 2(p) is negative. Let us adopt the following rules:
,il' the supposition that p' is not in E. The same argument establishes
1
li,
the inequality for z 2(p"). (1) Raise the price of the good in positive excess demand.
'1'
1'
1
1
Now Iet (2) Lower or at least do not raise the price of the good in
excess supply, but never lower the price below zero.
p(m) = mp' + (1 - m)p" with 1 2m2 O.
By W, one oJ the numbers z 1 (p(m)) and z 2 (p(m)) is positive and
the other negative when m ,, 0,1, unless p(m) E E. Suppose then,
without loss of generality, that z 1 (p(m 0 )) < O for sorne m 0 # 0,1.
Now Iet m increase from m 0 to l. We already know that z 1 (p(O)) is
positive, and therefore, as m approaches zero, somewhere z 1 (p(m))
must change sign. But, by e, it cannot change sign without
becoming zero. Suppose this happens at m*. Then p(m*) is in E,
for, by W, it must be that z 2 (p(m*)) = O.
We note the important role of e in this demonstration. Without
it we could not exclude the possibility of a change in the sign of z 1 , p"
as m approaches zero, without its ever becoming equal to zero. Of
course we also relied heavily on W, but this assumption does not
appear to be very restrictive. As was indicated in the discussion of
e, however, the Iatter will certainly exclude a number of perfectly
possible situations from consideration. Later in the book, an
investigation of sorne of these possibilities should help us to form Figure 2-I
26 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 27

(3) Do not change the price of a good in zero excess demand. It is intended that M 1(p) representan adjustment toan existing price
(4) Multiply the resulting price vector by a scalar, leaving so that a price vector p is transformed into a new price vector with
relative prices unchanged, so that the new price vector you components p 1 + M(p).
obtain is in Sn. Functions satisfying (2) exist; for cone example, let M{p) =
max(- p, k1z1(p)), where k1 > O. Since M 1(p) is a continuous trans-
If we are successful in carrying out these rules we can say: Given formation of p 1 and Z, it is certainly continuous by C.
any p in Sn, we have a routine for finding another point in Sn To verify (2a), first suppose z1(p) > O. Sincep1 ;::: O, k1z;(p) >
Another way of putting this is to say that our procedure gives us a -p1, so that M 1(p) = k 1z1(p) > O. Conversely, if z1(p) ::;; O, then
mapping of Sn into itself. We note that if p is an equilibrium, then either M 1(p) = k 1z1(p) ::;; O or M 1(p) = - p 1 ::;; O. It is easy to verify
the mapping will give us p again. The converse will al so be true: that (2b) and (2c) hold.
If the mapping takes us from p back to p, then equilibrium exists. An even simpler, though less intuitive, example of a function
The question then is: Does at least one such point exist? In our satisfying (2) is M 1(p) = max(O, k 1z1(p)), k 1 > O.
two-good example the answer is clearly "yes." Suppose that neither For functions satisfying (2), we easily deduce
p' nor p" is the point we seek. We know that at p' the rules tell us
to raise the price of good 1 and at p" they tell us to raise the price of M 1(p)z1(p) ;::: O all i. (3)
good 2. By W, though, we can never be asked to raise the prices It will be seen that if we interpret p 1 + M 1(p) as the ith component
of both goods at any p. Hence, at p(m) with 1 =1= m. =1= O, the rules of the new price vector that the mapping produces, given p, the
instruct us to lower the price of sorne good, say the first. But then procedure for finding these new price~ satisfies rules discussed earlier.
by C at sorne p(m*), the rules tell us not to change the price of the However, while all p 1 + M;(p) are certainly non-negative, there is
first good (because z1 (p(m*)) = 0), and then by W it follows also nothing to ensure that they will add up to one. In other words, if
that we must not change the price of the second good. Hence, we write p + M(p) as the row.vector of the new prices (components
p(m*) is a point of the kind we seek. p1 + M(p)), then there is no reason to suppose that p + M(p) is in
All this is really a repetition ofthe argument ofthe previous section Sn when p is in Sn. Since we seek a mapping of Sn into itself, we
in slightly different terms. When we come to the case of many must modify the mapping.
goods, our method will have to be somewhat different. As much as An obvious way of doing this is as follows: Let e be the n-dimen-
possible, we shall use the economics of our problem to construct a sional column vector with all components unity. Then [p + M(p)]e
procedure that satisfies the rules we have given. We can use C to is certainly non-negative. If we are certain that this number is
establish that the rules give a continuous mapping. Then we will strictly positive, then we may take the mapping given by
appeal to a mathematicaltheorem that assures us that there will be
at least one point in Sn that the mapping returns to itself. W e then p + M(p) (4)
will appeal again to our economics to show that this point is the
T(p) = [p + M(p)]e.
equilibrium we seek. The reader can now verify that (4) obeys all ofthe four rules we have
laid down, in particular, that the vector T(p) is in Sn.
Step 1: Construction of mapping. We first seek a continuous We now show that (4) is indeed a possible mapping by proving
function with the following three properties: that for all pE Sn, [p + M(p)]e > O. If not, then for sorne pE Sn.
p + M(p) = O by 2(c). But then
M1(p) > O if and only if z(p) > O, (2a)
O = [p + M(p)]z(p) = pz(p) + M(p)z(p) = M(p)z(p)
M 1(p) =O if Z(p) = 0, (2b)
by W. But then by (3), M(p)z1(p) = O, all i. Since pE Sn, it
Pt + M1(p) 2: O. (2c) must be that p 1 > O, so me i, so for that i, M 1(p) = - Pt < O. This,
26 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 27

(3) Do not change the price of a good in zero excess demand. It is intended that M 1(p) representan adjustment toan existing price
(4) Multiply the resulting price vector by a scalar, leaving so that a price vector p is transformed into a new price vector with
relative prices unchanged, so that the new price vector you components p 1 + M(p).
obtain is in Sn. Functions satisfying (2) exist; for cone example, let M{p) =
max(- p, k1z1(p)), where k1 > O. Since M 1(p) is a continuous trans-
If we are successful in carrying out these rules we can say: Given formation of p 1 and Z, it is certainly continuous by C.
any p in Sn, we have a routine for finding another point in Sn To verify (2a), first suppose z1(p) > O. Sincep1 ;::: O, k1z;(p) >
Another way of putting this is to say that our procedure gives us a -p1, so that M 1(p) = k 1z1(p) > O. Conversely, if z1(p) ::;; O, then
mapping of Sn into itself. We note that if p is an equilibrium, then either M 1(p) = k 1z1(p) ::;; O or M 1(p) = - p 1 ::;; O. It is easy to verify
the mapping will give us p again. The converse will al so be true: that (2b) and (2c) hold.
If the mapping takes us from p back to p, then equilibrium exists. An even simpler, though less intuitive, example of a function
The question then is: Does at least one such point exist? In our satisfying (2) is M 1(p) = max(O, k 1z1(p)), k 1 > O.
two-good example the answer is clearly "yes." Suppose that neither For functions satisfying (2), we easily deduce
p' nor p" is the point we seek. We know that at p' the rules tell us
to raise the price of good 1 and at p" they tell us to raise the price of M 1(p)z1(p) ;::: O all i. (3)
good 2. By W, though, we can never be asked to raise the prices It will be seen that if we interpret p 1 + M 1(p) as the ith component
of both goods at any p. Hence, at p(m) with 1 =1= m. =1= O, the rules of the new price vector that the mapping produces, given p, the
instruct us to lower the price of sorne good, say the first. But then procedure for finding these new price~ satisfies rules discussed earlier.
by C at sorne p(m*), the rules tell us not to change the price of the However, while all p 1 + M;(p) are certainly non-negative, there is
first good (because z1 (p(m*)) = 0), and then by W it follows also nothing to ensure that they will add up to one. In other words, if
that we must not change the price of the second good. Hence, we write p + M(p) as the row.vector of the new prices (components
p(m*) is a point of the kind we seek. p1 + M(p)), then there is no reason to suppose that p + M(p) is in
All this is really a repetition ofthe argument ofthe previous section Sn when p is in Sn. Since we seek a mapping of Sn into itself, we
in slightly different terms. When we come to the case of many must modify the mapping.
goods, our method will have to be somewhat different. As much as An obvious way of doing this is as follows: Let e be the n-dimen-
possible, we shall use the economics of our problem to construct a sional column vector with all components unity. Then [p + M(p)]e
procedure that satisfies the rules we have given. We can use C to is certainly non-negative. If we are certain that this number is
establish that the rules give a continuous mapping. Then we will strictly positive, then we may take the mapping given by
appeal to a mathematicaltheorem that assures us that there will be
at least one point in Sn that the mapping returns to itself. W e then p + M(p) (4)
will appeal again to our economics to show that this point is the
T(p) = [p + M(p)]e.
equilibrium we seek. The reader can now verify that (4) obeys all ofthe four rules we have
laid down, in particular, that the vector T(p) is in Sn.
Step 1: Construction of mapping. We first seek a continuous We now show that (4) is indeed a possible mapping by proving
function with the following three properties: that for all pE Sn, [p + M(p)]e > O. If not, then for sorne pE Sn.
p + M(p) = O by 2(c). But then
M1(p) > O if and only if z(p) > O, (2a)
O = [p + M(p)]z(p) = pz(p) + M(p)z(p) = M(p)z(p)
M 1(p) =O if Z(p) = 0, (2b)
by W. But then by (3), M(p)z1(p) = O, all i. Since pE Sn, it
Pt + M1(p) 2: O. (2c) must be that p 1 > O, so me i, so for that i, M 1(p) = - Pt < O. This,
28 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 29

however, must mean z1(p) = O, which in turn by (2b) implies that We have thus been able to establish that for the economy here
M 1(p) = O, a contradiction. Hence, [p + M(p)]e > O for all pE Sn. described there exists a set of "signals "-market prices-that will
'i
lead agents to make decisions that are mutually compatible. This
,l li is by no means a trivial result, and we repeat that careful reflection
. !1 Step 2: The mathematical result. W e first define sorne 9f the
notions of our introductory remarks more formally. on the roles of the various assumptions in establishing it is very
desirable because there are certainly economies that interest us in
DEFINI'TION 2. (a) If T(p) is a mapping that takes points in Sn into which coherence in decentralized decisions may not be possible, or
points in Sn, then the mapping is said to map Sn into itself. at least for which it cannot be proved possible. Thus important
(b) lf for sorne p* we have p* = T(p*), then p* is called afixed issues in the judgment of decentralized systems are at stake.
point of T(p).
The theorem we use in this chapter is called Brouwer's fixed-point 8. Equilibrium under a Weakened Continuity Condition
theorem, and it is stated as follows: Every continuous mapping of a
compact convex set into itself has a fixed point. The proof of this As noted in Section 2.4, e implies in its present forro that the
result will be found in T.e.I; convexity is defined in D.B.7. Here demand for free goods is bounded. We shall want to weaken this
we need confirm only that the set Sn that we are interested in satisfies restriction for severa! reasons: It is not unreasonable that demand
th!:l requirements of the theorem. for at least sorne goods might approach infinity as the price
eertainly if p and p' are in Sn. then for any m with 1 ;::: m ;::: O, approaches zero; as airead y noted, the non-satiation hypothesis that
the vector p(m) = mp + (1 - m)p' is in Sn. since p(m) is non- underlies Walras' law is at least partly inconsistent with satiation in
negative and p(m)e = l. Hence, Sn is convex. Since Sn is clearly any single good; the assumption that all goods are gross substitutes,
bounded and since the limit point of any sequence of price vectors an assumption frequently made in the literature on stability and
in Sn is itself in S.,., Sn is compact. uniqueness and repeatedly used by us in later chapters of this book,
implies that demands may approach infinity as prices go to zero.
We must be careful, however, in stating the weakened continuity
Step 3: The fixed point of T(p) is an equilibrium. At the fixed
assumption. A simple possibility might be to admit that an excess
point, we have p* = T(p*), that is,
demand function z1(p) can take on the value +oo in addition to finite
{[p* + M(p*)]e}p* = p* + M(p*) values and to define continuity in an obvious extension of the usual
definition (i.e., if z1(p) approaches infinity along one converging
or
sequen ce of price vectors, it must do so on every sequen ce converging
M(p*) = .\p*, (5) to the same limit). This assumption indeed implies the existence of
equilibrium, but it cannot be derived from a utility-maximization
where ,\ = [p* + M(p*)]e - l. Take the inner product of (5) on
theory of household behavior. eonsider the following example.
both sides with z(p*), and use W to find There are three goods, and the household has a utility function
M(p*)z(p*) = .\p*z(p*) = O. U(x) = x~ 12 + x' 2 + x!i12 ,
As before, M 1(p*)z1(p*) = O, all i, by (3). Hence, z1(p*) > O would which is in no way pathological. Let the initial endowment be one
imply M 1(p*) = O, which contradicts (2a). Hence, z1(p*) :::; O, all i. unit of commodity 3, and suppose that p 3 = 1, while p and p 2 are
By D.2.1, p* is an equilibrium. both varying and approaching O. The usual calculations for demand
We summarize the result of this section formally: functions show that

THEOREM 2. If F, H, w, and e, then an equilibrium for a


competitive economy with a finite number of goods exists.
28 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 29

however, must mean z1(p) = O, which in turn by (2b) implies that We have thus been able to establish that for the economy here
M 1(p) = O, a contradiction. Hence, [p + M(p)]e > O for all pE Sn. described there exists a set of "signals "-market prices-that will
'i
lead agents to make decisions that are mutually compatible. This
,l li is by no means a trivial result, and we repeat that careful reflection
. !1 Step 2: The mathematical result. W e first define sorne 9f the
notions of our introductory remarks more formally. on the roles of the various assumptions in establishing it is very
desirable because there are certainly economies that interest us in
DEFINI'TION 2. (a) If T(p) is a mapping that takes points in Sn into which coherence in decentralized decisions may not be possible, or
points in Sn, then the mapping is said to map Sn into itself. at least for which it cannot be proved possible. Thus important
(b) lf for sorne p* we have p* = T(p*), then p* is called afixed issues in the judgment of decentralized systems are at stake.
point of T(p).
The theorem we use in this chapter is called Brouwer's fixed-point 8. Equilibrium under a Weakened Continuity Condition
theorem, and it is stated as follows: Every continuous mapping of a
compact convex set into itself has a fixed point. The proof of this As noted in Section 2.4, e implies in its present forro that the
result will be found in T.e.I; convexity is defined in D.B.7. Here demand for free goods is bounded. We shall want to weaken this
we need confirm only that the set Sn that we are interested in satisfies restriction for severa! reasons: It is not unreasonable that demand
th!:l requirements of the theorem. for at least sorne goods might approach infinity as the price
eertainly if p and p' are in Sn. then for any m with 1 ;::: m ;::: O, approaches zero; as airead y noted, the non-satiation hypothesis that
the vector p(m) = mp + (1 - m)p' is in Sn. since p(m) is non- underlies Walras' law is at least partly inconsistent with satiation in
negative and p(m)e = l. Hence, Sn is convex. Since Sn is clearly any single good; the assumption that all goods are gross substitutes,
bounded and since the limit point of any sequence of price vectors an assumption frequently made in the literature on stability and
in Sn is itself in S.,., Sn is compact. uniqueness and repeatedly used by us in later chapters of this book,
implies that demands may approach infinity as prices go to zero.
We must be careful, however, in stating the weakened continuity
Step 3: The fixed point of T(p) is an equilibrium. At the fixed
assumption. A simple possibility might be to admit that an excess
point, we have p* = T(p*), that is,
demand function z1(p) can take on the value +oo in addition to finite
{[p* + M(p*)]e}p* = p* + M(p*) values and to define continuity in an obvious extension of the usual
definition (i.e., if z1(p) approaches infinity along one converging
or
sequen ce of price vectors, it must do so on every sequen ce converging
M(p*) = .\p*, (5) to the same limit). This assumption indeed implies the existence of
equilibrium, but it cannot be derived from a utility-maximization
where ,\ = [p* + M(p*)]e - l. Take the inner product of (5) on
theory of household behavior. eonsider the following example.
both sides with z(p*), and use W to find There are three goods, and the household has a utility function
M(p*)z(p*) = .\p*z(p*) = O. U(x) = x~ 12 + x' 2 + x!i12 ,
As before, M 1(p*)z1(p*) = O, all i, by (3). Hence, z1(p*) > O would which is in no way pathological. Let the initial endowment be one
imply M 1(p*) = O, which contradicts (2a). Hence, z1(p*) :::; O, all i. unit of commodity 3, and suppose that p 3 = 1, while p and p 2 are
By D.2.1, p* is an equilibrium. both varying and approaching O. The usual calculations for demand
We summarize the result of this section formally: functions show that

THEOREM 2. If F, H, w, and e, then an equilibrium for a


competitive economy with a finite number of goods exists.
30 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 31

From the paths along which p 1 and p 2 both approach zero, it is AssuMPTION 5 (B). There exists a positive finite number R such that
possible to choose one for which pifp 2 approaches any given non- for all p in S m Zt(P) > - R, all i; z(p) is bounded from below.
negative real number or indeed +oo. Then x 1 (p) can be made to
approach any given non-negative real number, or +co. Thus no B can be justified by supposing that the amount that can be
definition can be given to x 1 (0,0,1) that is consistent with con- produced of any one good at any one time not infinitely removed
tinuity in any sense. We must therefore regard x(p) as undefined at from the present is finite, that the quantities of goods initially owned
by households also can properly be taken as finite, and that it is not
the point (0,0, 1).
However, it can be seen that x 1 (p) + xip) + x 3 (p) approaches fanciful to suppose that the quantity of any one service a household
is capable of supplying at a moment of time is also not infinite.
+oo. We can calculate that
Assumption B is superfluous if e is postulated, but not if it is
1 relaxed as below.
Xs(P) = (lfp) + (lfp2) + 1
AssuMPTION 6 (e'). The excess-demand function, z(p), is defined
and therefore certainly approaches zero as p 1 and p 2 approach O in for all p O and possibly for other p and is continuous wherever
any direction. Since p 3 = 1, p 3 x 3 (p)--. O. From the budget con- defined. If z(p) is not defined for p = p0 , then
straint,
lim 2 Z(p) = +co.
PtXt(P) + P2X2(p)--. l. p-tpO i

:
W e can calculate also that
1 In view of e', we can define, by convention,
(1 + u v)
2 Ji
l!
Jr
-(u+ u2 v)'
~
where u = p 1/p 2, v = 1 + p 2. For p 2 small, v can be regarded as
: to take on the value +oo for all p for which z(p) is not defined.
1 We now show that the previous equilibrium proof can be modifled
constrained to a right-hand neighborhood of l. Since the right- 1
hand side is negative as u varies over positive values and v over its ' so as to be valid if e is replaced by B and C'.
range and since it approaches -oo as u approaches O and -1 as u We take M(p) to have the properties (2), but now require only
approaches +oo, it is clearly negative and bounded away from O. that it be continuous wherever z(p) is defined and therefore con-
However, tinuous. The previous examples show that this is possible. Then
(3) is still valid, as is the conclusion that [p + M(p)]e > O.
+ X2(p)] = + P2X2(p)-
1

! P2[Xt(P) [PtXt(P) 1]- [(Pt- P2)x1(p)- 1]; For convenience of notation, let,
!1,
since the first term on the right-hand side approaches O and the
1'
'
second is negative and bounded away from O, it follows that
Z(p) = 2 z;(p).
j
'11

P2[x1(p) + x 2(p)] is positive and bounded away from O. Since


11
Now introduce a continuous function, a(Z), defined for all real
p 2 --3>- O, it must be that x 1(p) + x 2(p)--. +co, and, since Xs(P)
numbers Z such that O :::; a(Z) :::; 1, all Z, a(Z) = O for Z :::; O,
approaches O, x 1 (p) + x 2(p) + x 3 (p) approaches +co.
a(Z) = 1 for Z ;:::: Z, where Z 1 > 0. Then define a(p) = a[Z(p)]
It will be shown later (T.4.8) that this result is a general implication
and
of utility maximization. At present, we simply assume that the sum
of excess demands approaches infinity whenever excess demand is N(p) = {~~ - a(p)]M(p) + a(p)e' if z(p) is defined,
(6)
if z(p) is undefined.
undefined.
Before restating the continuity assumption formally, we introduce Here e' is the row vector whose components are all l. N(p) is so
another. chosen that it coincides with M(p) if Z(p) :::; O(a region in which we
30 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 31

From the paths along which p 1 and p 2 both approach zero, it is AssuMPTION 5 (B). There exists a positive finite number R such that
possible to choose one for which pifp 2 approaches any given non- for all p in S m Zt(P) > - R, all i; z(p) is bounded from below.
negative real number or indeed +oo. Then x 1 (p) can be made to
approach any given non-negative real number, or +co. Thus no B can be justified by supposing that the amount that can be
definition can be given to x 1 (0,0,1) that is consistent with con- produced of any one good at any one time not infinitely removed
tinuity in any sense. We must therefore regard x(p) as undefined at from the present is finite, that the quantities of goods initially owned
by households also can properly be taken as finite, and that it is not
the point (0,0, 1).
However, it can be seen that x 1 (p) + xip) + x 3 (p) approaches fanciful to suppose that the quantity of any one service a household
is capable of supplying at a moment of time is also not infinite.
+oo. We can calculate that
Assumption B is superfluous if e is postulated, but not if it is
1 relaxed as below.
Xs(P) = (lfp) + (lfp2) + 1
AssuMPTION 6 (e'). The excess-demand function, z(p), is defined
and therefore certainly approaches zero as p 1 and p 2 approach O in for all p O and possibly for other p and is continuous wherever
any direction. Since p 3 = 1, p 3 x 3 (p)--. O. From the budget con- defined. If z(p) is not defined for p = p0 , then
straint,
lim 2 Z(p) = +co.
PtXt(P) + P2X2(p)--. l. p-tpO i

:
W e can calculate also that
1 In view of e', we can define, by convention,
(1 + u v)
2 Ji
l!
Jr
-(u+ u2 v)'
~
where u = p 1/p 2, v = 1 + p 2. For p 2 small, v can be regarded as
: to take on the value +oo for all p for which z(p) is not defined.
1 We now show that the previous equilibrium proof can be modifled
constrained to a right-hand neighborhood of l. Since the right- 1
hand side is negative as u varies over positive values and v over its ' so as to be valid if e is replaced by B and C'.
range and since it approaches -oo as u approaches O and -1 as u We take M(p) to have the properties (2), but now require only
approaches +oo, it is clearly negative and bounded away from O. that it be continuous wherever z(p) is defined and therefore con-
However, tinuous. The previous examples show that this is possible. Then
(3) is still valid, as is the conclusion that [p + M(p)]e > O.
+ X2(p)] = + P2X2(p)-
1

! P2[Xt(P) [PtXt(P) 1]- [(Pt- P2)x1(p)- 1]; For convenience of notation, let,
!1,
since the first term on the right-hand side approaches O and the
1'
'
second is negative and bounded away from O, it follows that
Z(p) = 2 z;(p).
j
'11

P2[x1(p) + x 2(p)] is positive and bounded away from O. Since


11
Now introduce a continuous function, a(Z), defined for all real
p 2 --3>- O, it must be that x 1(p) + x 2(p)--. +co, and, since Xs(P)
numbers Z such that O :::; a(Z) :::; 1, all Z, a(Z) = O for Z :::; O,
approaches O, x 1 (p) + x 2(p) + x 3 (p) approaches +co.
a(Z) = 1 for Z ;:::: Z, where Z 1 > 0. Then define a(p) = a[Z(p)]
It will be shown later (T.4.8) that this result is a general implication
and
of utility maximization. At present, we simply assume that the sum
of excess demands approaches infinity whenever excess demand is N(p) = {~~ - a(p)]M(p) + a(p)e' if z(p) is defined,
(6)
if z(p) is undefined.
undefined.
Before restating the continuity assumption formally, we introduce Here e' is the row vector whose components are all l. N(p) is so
another. chosen that it coincides with M(p) if Z(p) :::; O(a region in which we
32 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 33
j 1

know any possible equilibrium must Iie) and becomes a strictly THEOREM 3. If F, H, N, B, and C', then an equilibrium for a
positive vector if z(p) is undefined or indeed if Z(p) ;::: Z 1 and there competitive economy with a finite number of goods exists.
fore, by C', in any neighborhood of a point where z(p) is undefined.
Obviously, N(p) is continuous wherever z(p) is defined. Suppose 9. Restricted Futures Markets
z(p) is undefined for p = p 0 By C', we can find a neighborhood
of p 0 such that Z(p) ;::: Z 1 for all p in the neighborhood for which The economy we have been considering is an abstract one in many
z(p) is defined. Then N(p) = e' for all such p; it also equals e' for respects, but perhaps the most serious departure from what we
all p for which z(p) is not defined and in particular p = p 0 , so that expect the world to be "really Iike" is the supposition that there are
N(p) is constant ate' throughout the neighborhood and is certainly enough futures markets to produce "coherence" not only in the
continuous. markets for current goods, but also in the markets for future goods.
Sin ce O ::; o:(p) ::; 1, it follows from (6) that, where z(p) is defined, This hypothesis "telescopes" the future into the present, and
M 1(p) ::; 1 implies N1(p) ;::: M 1(p) and, therefore, p1 + N 1(p) ;::: p 1 + although this occurs at least partially in certain markets, we know
M 1(p) ;::: O, while M 1(p) > O implies N1(p) > O and, therefore, that it does not take place either universally or over the distant
p1 + N(p) > p 1 ;::: O. Hence, certainly p1 + N1(p) ;::: O, all i. Also, future. There are explanations for this, which have a good deal to
if M(p) > O, sorne i, then p + N(p) > O, so that [p + N(p)]e > O, do with the uncertainty agents ha ve regarding the future state of the
while if M(p) ::; O, all i, then p + N(p) ;::: p + M(p), [p + N(p)]e ;::: environment that is relevant to their present decisions. We do not
[p + M(p)]e > O. Thus, if z(p) is defined, [p + N(p)]e > O; if now propase to formally introduce uncertainty into the story and
z(p) is not defined, then [p + N(p)]e = (p + e')e is certainly greater will instead take a route following the signposts that are already
than O. available to us.
It follows that the mapping The first point is this: It is quite possible that when the economy
we have been considering is in equilibrium, there are sorne markets
T()- p + N(p) in which there are no transactions of any kind. For instance, in
p - [p + N(p)]e
parta! equilibrium analysis, where we take the prices of all goods
is a continuous transformation of the fundamental price simplex, Sn, other than the one we are considering as given, the situation is
into itself and, therefore, has a fixed point, p*. In the equation represented by a supply curve that everywhere Iies above the demand
T(p*) = p*, if we substitute the definition of T(p) and solve for curve; both curves intersect the vertical axis. An obvious question
N(p*), we find is "To what extent is a market in which no transactions take place
a market at all ?" This is not our main concern. Instead, suppose
N(p*) = .\p*, that the market for the delivery of shoes next week is of this
where ,\ = [p* + N(p*)]e - l. If z(p*) were undefined, then type. Clearly it is not implied that no one contemplates either
N(p*) = e', from which it follows that p* O, a contradiction since acquiring shoes next week or selling them next week. Instead, it
z(p*) would then be defined. Multiply both sides of the above may be, for instance, that those hoping to get shoes next week on the
equation by z(p*); from (W), N(p*)z(p*) = O, or from (6), whole expect there to be a cost-saving innovation in their manufac
ture, while those who hope to scll thcm cxpcct no such thing.
[1 - o:(p*)]M(p*)z(p~) + o:(p*)Z(p*) = O. Evidently, although markets are formally in equilibrium, the system
Note that, by definition, Z(p) = e'z(p). But from (3), [1 - o:(p*)] x has failed to produce intertemporal coherence since agents have
M(p*)z(p*) ;::: O, so that o:(p*)Z(p*) ::; O. Since o:(p*) > O would made plans on differing views of the terms on which shoes will
imply Z(p*) > O by construction, we must have o:(p*) = O. Hence, exchange against other things, both of which cannot be correct. It
M(p*)z(p*) = O, which implies' that p* is an equilibrium price vector is preferable, therefore, to say that no futures market in shoes exists
as befare. if, when we stipulate such a market, every equilibrium of the system


1
32 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 33
j 1

know any possible equilibrium must Iie) and becomes a strictly THEOREM 3. If F, H, N, B, and C', then an equilibrium for a
positive vector if z(p) is undefined or indeed if Z(p) ;::: Z 1 and there competitive economy with a finite number of goods exists.
fore, by C', in any neighborhood of a point where z(p) is undefined.
Obviously, N(p) is continuous wherever z(p) is defined. Suppose 9. Restricted Futures Markets
z(p) is undefined for p = p 0 By C', we can find a neighborhood
of p 0 such that Z(p) ;::: Z 1 for all p in the neighborhood for which The economy we have been considering is an abstract one in many
z(p) is defined. Then N(p) = e' for all such p; it also equals e' for respects, but perhaps the most serious departure from what we
all p for which z(p) is not defined and in particular p = p 0 , so that expect the world to be "really Iike" is the supposition that there are
N(p) is constant ate' throughout the neighborhood and is certainly enough futures markets to produce "coherence" not only in the
continuous. markets for current goods, but also in the markets for future goods.
Sin ce O ::; o:(p) ::; 1, it follows from (6) that, where z(p) is defined, This hypothesis "telescopes" the future into the present, and
M 1(p) ::; 1 implies N1(p) ;::: M 1(p) and, therefore, p1 + N 1(p) ;::: p 1 + although this occurs at least partially in certain markets, we know
M 1(p) ;::: O, while M 1(p) > O implies N1(p) > O and, therefore, that it does not take place either universally or over the distant
p1 + N(p) > p 1 ;::: O. Hence, certainly p1 + N1(p) ;::: O, all i. Also, future. There are explanations for this, which have a good deal to
if M(p) > O, sorne i, then p + N(p) > O, so that [p + N(p)]e > O, do with the uncertainty agents ha ve regarding the future state of the
while if M(p) ::; O, all i, then p + N(p) ;::: p + M(p), [p + N(p)]e ;::: environment that is relevant to their present decisions. We do not
[p + M(p)]e > O. Thus, if z(p) is defined, [p + N(p)]e > O; if now propase to formally introduce uncertainty into the story and
z(p) is not defined, then [p + N(p)]e = (p + e')e is certainly greater will instead take a route following the signposts that are already
than O. available to us.
It follows that the mapping The first point is this: It is quite possible that when the economy
we have been considering is in equilibrium, there are sorne markets
T()- p + N(p) in which there are no transactions of any kind. For instance, in
p - [p + N(p)]e
parta! equilibrium analysis, where we take the prices of all goods
is a continuous transformation of the fundamental price simplex, Sn, other than the one we are considering as given, the situation is
into itself and, therefore, has a fixed point, p*. In the equation represented by a supply curve that everywhere Iies above the demand
T(p*) = p*, if we substitute the definition of T(p) and solve for curve; both curves intersect the vertical axis. An obvious question
N(p*), we find is "To what extent is a market in which no transactions take place
a market at all ?" This is not our main concern. Instead, suppose
N(p*) = .\p*, that the market for the delivery of shoes next week is of this
where ,\ = [p* + N(p*)]e - l. If z(p*) were undefined, then type. Clearly it is not implied that no one contemplates either
N(p*) = e', from which it follows that p* O, a contradiction since acquiring shoes next week or selling them next week. Instead, it
z(p*) would then be defined. Multiply both sides of the above may be, for instance, that those hoping to get shoes next week on the
equation by z(p*); from (W), N(p*)z(p*) = O, or from (6), whole expect there to be a cost-saving innovation in their manufac
ture, while those who hope to scll thcm cxpcct no such thing.
[1 - o:(p*)]M(p*)z(p~) + o:(p*)Z(p*) = O. Evidently, although markets are formally in equilibrium, the system
Note that, by definition, Z(p) = e'z(p). But from (3), [1 - o:(p*)] x has failed to produce intertemporal coherence since agents have
M(p*)z(p*) ;::: O, so that o:(p*)Z(p*) ::; O. Since o:(p*) > O would made plans on differing views of the terms on which shoes will
imply Z(p*) > O by construction, we must have o:(p*) = O. Hence, exchange against other things, both of which cannot be correct. It
M(p*)z(p*) = O, which implies' that p* is an equilibrium price vector is preferable, therefore, to say that no futures market in shoes exists
as befare. if, when we stipulate such a market, every equilibrium of the system


1
34 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 35

so constructed is found to be one in which no transactions take place


10. Temporary or Short-Period Equilibrium
in that market.
The second point is connected with the first. If the number of The absence of futures markets does not mean that an individual
transactions in a market is small (in the limit zero ), it is hard to cannot engage in the intertemporal transfer of goods. If storage is
continue the assumption that the agents in this market take the price possible, I can plan today to exchange apples for oranges tomorrow
as given. The point is obvious and, insofar as futures markets tend by storing apples for one day. Naturally, this decision will be
to be "narrow" for the reasons of the previous paragraph and al so influenced by current prices, storage and transaction costs, and the
because the proper definition of a good for future delivery may ha ve prices expected to prevail in the future. Here we shall take it that
to be peculiarly fine to allow for intervening technological change, each agent regards bis price expectations as certain, or at any rate
the manner in which we have incorporated futures markets into the that he is unwilling to pay anything to insure bis future transactions
system is likely to be pretty misleading in many instances. We (i.e., to make certain that the transaction can be carried out at the
might do less violence to the facts to stipulate instead that such terms expected). This leads to the following difficulty: Should there
markets do not exist. be no difference between the transaction and storage costs of different
The last point we can make here without a detailed discussion of goods, then the reader can verify that an agent would be indifferent
uncertainty is that our foregoing analysis has postulated that there about which good to store, and this would lead to difficulties with
is only a finite number of markets. Since there is no reason to assumption F. All this is due to the artificial exclusion of the
suppose that "time must have a stop," we have implicitly limited the forces of uncertainty. In addition, we must not forget durable
number of futures markets that exist, and so also the extent in time goods, that is, those goods not annihilated by a current act of
to which we can say that coherence of decisions is possible. The consumption.
reason for this limitation on our analysis is at least partly the desire To overcome all these difficulties with one hand tied behind our
to avoid the analytical and conceptual difficulties of infinite- backs, we shall arbitrarily postulate (a) that all storing is done by
dimensional spaces at this stage. As economists, we recognize, households who may rent such durable production goods as they
however, that the limitation also makes good sense if for no other have to producers and (b) that all households ha ve preferences o ver
reason than the facts of birth and death. To suppose that I now the goods stored such that at any set of current and expected prices
contract for the delivery of a pair of shoes to my grandson, whom I they store one and only one combination of goods. The second
expect to be born twenty years from now, is itself somewhat fanciful. assumption is not as terrible as it seems, sin ce it "mimics" in its
To suppose further that I have correctly foreseen the situation in consequences the forces of uncertainty that are excluded here. The
which my grandson will find himself and that in these circumstances first assumption is pretty hannless at the moment.
he will value the shoes in a way correctly known by me now is So far we have made it possible, through storage, for agents to
certainly dubious. Even if we allow contingent futures contracts plan to exchange present for future goods in the absence of futures
such as, "For a price to be paid now, deliver a pair of shoes to my markets. But the reverse operation cannot be carried out if there
grandson if he exists and is twenty years old in forty years' time, and are no futures markets at all. By assumption, there is no way I can
if not, deliver nothing," we would certainly expect such marketsto be obtain more of a good now by promising to deliver a quantity of
pretty narrow and to become narrower as the future recedes; quite sorne good ata future date. In order not to exclude this possibility,
apart from anything else, it is not clear how far the benevolence of we shall assume that there exists a futures market in at least one
an individual of a given generation extends to future generations. physical good (e.g., the medium of exchange) for all relevant future
For these reasons and others having to do with uncertainty, it is dates.
./ It is now advisable to put all this in more formallanguage before
desirable to have an analysis of a competitive system in which
universal futures markets are not postulated. To this we now we consider the difference the new set of postulated circumstances
turn. will make to the conclusions of earlier sections.
34 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 35

so constructed is found to be one in which no transactions take place


10. Temporary or Short-Period Equilibrium
in that market.
The second point is connected with the first. If the number of The absence of futures markets does not mean that an individual
transactions in a market is small (in the limit zero ), it is hard to cannot engage in the intertemporal transfer of goods. If storage is
continue the assumption that the agents in this market take the price possible, I can plan today to exchange apples for oranges tomorrow
as given. The point is obvious and, insofar as futures markets tend by storing apples for one day. Naturally, this decision will be
to be "narrow" for the reasons of the previous paragraph and al so influenced by current prices, storage and transaction costs, and the
because the proper definition of a good for future delivery may ha ve prices expected to prevail in the future. Here we shall take it that
to be peculiarly fine to allow for intervening technological change, each agent regards bis price expectations as certain, or at any rate
the manner in which we have incorporated futures markets into the that he is unwilling to pay anything to insure bis future transactions
system is likely to be pretty misleading in many instances. We (i.e., to make certain that the transaction can be carried out at the
might do less violence to the facts to stipulate instead that such terms expected). This leads to the following difficulty: Should there
markets do not exist. be no difference between the transaction and storage costs of different
The last point we can make here without a detailed discussion of goods, then the reader can verify that an agent would be indifferent
uncertainty is that our foregoing analysis has postulated that there about which good to store, and this would lead to difficulties with
is only a finite number of markets. Since there is no reason to assumption F. All this is due to the artificial exclusion of the
suppose that "time must have a stop," we have implicitly limited the forces of uncertainty. In addition, we must not forget durable
number of futures markets that exist, and so also the extent in time goods, that is, those goods not annihilated by a current act of
to which we can say that coherence of decisions is possible. The consumption.
reason for this limitation on our analysis is at least partly the desire To overcome all these difficulties with one hand tied behind our
to avoid the analytical and conceptual difficulties of infinite- backs, we shall arbitrarily postulate (a) that all storing is done by
dimensional spaces at this stage. As economists, we recognize, households who may rent such durable production goods as they
however, that the limitation also makes good sense if for no other have to producers and (b) that all households ha ve preferences o ver
reason than the facts of birth and death. To suppose that I now the goods stored such that at any set of current and expected prices
contract for the delivery of a pair of shoes to my grandson, whom I they store one and only one combination of goods. The second
expect to be born twenty years from now, is itself somewhat fanciful. assumption is not as terrible as it seems, sin ce it "mimics" in its
To suppose further that I have correctly foreseen the situation in consequences the forces of uncertainty that are excluded here. The
which my grandson will find himself and that in these circumstances first assumption is pretty hannless at the moment.
he will value the shoes in a way correctly known by me now is So far we have made it possible, through storage, for agents to
certainly dubious. Even if we allow contingent futures contracts plan to exchange present for future goods in the absence of futures
such as, "For a price to be paid now, deliver a pair of shoes to my markets. But the reverse operation cannot be carried out if there
grandson if he exists and is twenty years old in forty years' time, and are no futures markets at all. By assumption, there is no way I can
if not, deliver nothing," we would certainly expect such marketsto be obtain more of a good now by promising to deliver a quantity of
pretty narrow and to become narrower as the future recedes; quite sorne good ata future date. In order not to exclude this possibility,
apart from anything else, it is not clear how far the benevolence of we shall assume that there exists a futures market in at least one
an individual of a given generation extends to future generations. physical good (e.g., the medium of exchange) for all relevant future
For these reasons and others having to do with uncertainty, it is dates.
./ It is now advisable to put all this in more formallanguage before
desirable to have an analysis of a competitive system in which
universal futures markets are not postulated. To this we now we consider the difference the new set of postulated circumstances
turn. will make to the conclusions of earlier sections.
~
~-
.......

l1
36 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 37

It will be convenient to regard the services a given durable excludes a number of matters of great economic interest, for example,
productive good renders as distinct from that good itself. If there investment plans by firms, it is relatively harmless for the rather
are, say, m durable productive goods, there will be m additional formal problem of this section. 1 At the moment, we note that A.2. 7
goods, the services rendered by the durables. All these goods have allows us to suppose that firms do not form any price expectations.
the same date. We write Yr as the production choice offirmfand, for convenience
Let there be N current goods as defined above, and in addition, Jet take it to ha ve N + T components, of which the last Tare certainly
there be one physical good at a fixed location at T intervals into the zero. A negative component again denotes an input, which
future, for which contracts for future delivery and sale can be madt: category now includes the services of productive equipment hired
now. There are then N + T goods altogether. The vector pis now from households. As usual, the omission of the subscriptjindicates
1

1
the N + Y-dimensional row vector of their current prices. In summation over f.
1

addition, agents have expectations as to the prices at future dates for W e define z by
,.
1

the N physical goods currently being traded. We here ignore the


z=x-x-y
1.'!
invention of new goods, regard "location" as inessential, and sup-
1 ,,!1, pose that no good deteriorates through use or storage. Suppose so that z is the vector of excess demands in the N current markets for
'1
that agents are concerned only with the future over T periods. current goods and the T current markets for the future delivery of
il Then we write qh as the NT-dimensional vector of prices expected by the o'n!y physical good with a futures market. Evidently we may
household h, and if there are H households, we write q as the HNT- take z to depend on (p,q). We now introduce
dimensional vector of expected prices.
AssuMPTION .8. (a) z satisfies assumption F: z = z(p,q) is a
1 The price relevant to the current plans of household h is (p, q~).
vector-valued function.
As befare, we suppose that the household owns a stock of goods
1 (b) z satisfies assumption W: pz = O for all (p; q) considered.
[1 represented by the vector x1;. Also as befare, we shall write Xhi as
(e) z satisfies assumption H: z(p,q) = z(kp,kq).
the amount of the good i demanded by h either for storage or con-
(d) z satisfies assumption C over SN+T for fixed q.
sumption. Recall here that goods are still distinguished not only
by their physical characteristics, but also by date. We write xh as These suppositions are neither more nor less restrictive than they
the demand vector of household h and regard a negative component were in our earlier discussion, and we do not explain or justify them
as a plan to supply a service, which category now includes the offer further here.
,'
1:.:
1!1!
of the services of a piece of productive equipment. Summation Since z is the vector of excess demands for current goods and the
1'1'1
11
over households is again shown by the omission of the subscript h. single physical good with futures markets, we cannot deduce from
Lastly, we write x* as the vector consisting of the first N + T com- knowledge of z what the market situations for goods in subsequent
ponents of x and x* as the vector consisting of the first N + T time periods will be. Accordingly, we are justified in the nomen-
components of x. These components represent the N current goods. clature of the following definition:
and the T futures of the single physical good assumed to have a
futures market. DEFINITION 3. (p* ,q) is a temporary equilibrium if z(p* ,q) ::;; O.
We now introduce Once again this definition is justified as in our earlier discussion.
AssuMPTION 7. Firms cannot stock goods of any kind, they cannot It is important to remember, however, that the "coherence of
en ter into "futures" contracts, and the production process of each decisions" we talked about there now refers to the markets repre-
firm can be completed in the current period. sented in z only.

This assumption is highly u nrealistic, of course, beca use it puts all 1 This and other assumptions will be removed in the detailed treatment in

intertemporal transactions in the household sector. But although it Chapter 6.


~
~-
.......

l1
36 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 37

It will be convenient to regard the services a given durable excludes a number of matters of great economic interest, for example,
productive good renders as distinct from that good itself. If there investment plans by firms, it is relatively harmless for the rather
are, say, m durable productive goods, there will be m additional formal problem of this section. 1 At the moment, we note that A.2. 7
goods, the services rendered by the durables. All these goods have allows us to suppose that firms do not form any price expectations.
the same date. We write Yr as the production choice offirmfand, for convenience
Let there be N current goods as defined above, and in addition, Jet take it to ha ve N + T components, of which the last Tare certainly
there be one physical good at a fixed location at T intervals into the zero. A negative component again denotes an input, which
future, for which contracts for future delivery and sale can be madt: category now includes the services of productive equipment hired
now. There are then N + T goods altogether. The vector pis now from households. As usual, the omission of the subscriptjindicates
1

1
the N + Y-dimensional row vector of their current prices. In summation over f.
1

addition, agents have expectations as to the prices at future dates for W e define z by
,.
1

the N physical goods currently being traded. We here ignore the


z=x-x-y
1.'!
invention of new goods, regard "location" as inessential, and sup-
1 ,,!1, pose that no good deteriorates through use or storage. Suppose so that z is the vector of excess demands in the N current markets for
'1
that agents are concerned only with the future over T periods. current goods and the T current markets for the future delivery of
il Then we write qh as the NT-dimensional vector of prices expected by the o'n!y physical good with a futures market. Evidently we may
household h, and if there are H households, we write q as the HNT- take z to depend on (p,q). We now introduce
dimensional vector of expected prices.
AssuMPTION .8. (a) z satisfies assumption F: z = z(p,q) is a
1 The price relevant to the current plans of household h is (p, q~).
vector-valued function.
As befare, we suppose that the household owns a stock of goods
1 (b) z satisfies assumption W: pz = O for all (p; q) considered.
[1 represented by the vector x1;. Also as befare, we shall write Xhi as
(e) z satisfies assumption H: z(p,q) = z(kp,kq).
the amount of the good i demanded by h either for storage or con-
(d) z satisfies assumption C over SN+T for fixed q.
sumption. Recall here that goods are still distinguished not only
by their physical characteristics, but also by date. We write xh as These suppositions are neither more nor less restrictive than they
the demand vector of household h and regard a negative component were in our earlier discussion, and we do not explain or justify them
as a plan to supply a service, which category now includes the offer further here.
,'
1:.:
1!1!
of the services of a piece of productive equipment. Summation Since z is the vector of excess demands for current goods and the
1'1'1
11
over households is again shown by the omission of the subscript h. single physical good with futures markets, we cannot deduce from
Lastly, we write x* as the vector consisting of the first N + T com- knowledge of z what the market situations for goods in subsequent
ponents of x and x* as the vector consisting of the first N + T time periods will be. Accordingly, we are justified in the nomen-
components of x. These components represent the N current goods. clature of the following definition:
and the T futures of the single physical good assumed to have a
futures market. DEFINITION 3. (p* ,q) is a temporary equilibrium if z(p* ,q) ::;; O.
We now introduce Once again this definition is justified as in our earlier discussion.
AssuMPTION 7. Firms cannot stock goods of any kind, they cannot It is important to remember, however, that the "coherence of
en ter into "futures" contracts, and the production process of each decisions" we talked about there now refers to the markets repre-
firm can be completed in the current period. sented in z only.

This assumption is highly u nrealistic, of course, beca use it puts all 1 This and other assumptions will be removed in the detailed treatment in

intertemporal transactions in the household sector. But although it Chapter 6.


38 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 39

The question of interest now is whether a temporary equilibrium upper bound of the amount that can be usefully employed. Thus,
exists. We prove that indeed it does. no equilibrium may exist. If we consider that the physiological
The existence of a competitive equilibrium for fixed q is assured needs of people make it impossible for them to offer labor services
by the following argument: Normalizing p so that pE SN+T also without positive consumption and if we also take note of the
implies by H that the expectation vector q has been normalized. specificity of much productive equipment to particular uses, it is
For fixed q we may write z = z(p,q) = z(p). The vector-valued clear that the example is not farfetched. Of course, the same diffi-
function z(p) has all the properties of z(p) in our previous discussion culty could have arisen in the world with a complete set of futures
of "existence" except H. But H was never invoked in the proof markets. In that case, however, households would have had the
of T.2.2. Hence, we may use the same proof to establish the additional option of selling their services forward and firms may have
existence of a temporary equilibrium. been willing to buy them in conjunction with the future services of
We have shown that, whatever the expectations of agents offuture durable equipment, so that the realism of the postulated conditions
prices might be and however much these expectations may differ of the example would have been less compelling.
among agents, there exists a set of prices in the current markets such So far it has been supposed that, given the normalization of p, the
that all the actions agents plan to undertake in these markets can prices expected by agents may be taken as given. It is more
indeed be carried out. This seems to be a comforting result to have, reasonable, though, to take expected prices as influenced, at least to
but it is not unimportant to bear in mind that the conclusion is sorne extent, by current prices. Our main result, however, will not
limited by the assumptions on which it is based and, in particular, be affected if we stipulate:
that the proof of the existence of equilibrium prices does not
constitute a claim that these prices in fact will be established. AssuMPTION 9. For each household h the expected price vector qh
To understand the limitations imposed by A.2.8, consider the is a continuous function qh(P) of p in
following example. When we consider a system, we take its past
as given, and in particular, we take the stock of durable productive
equipment inherited from the past as given. Suppose that the
production opportunities open to the economy (the production set for Given this assumption, we may again eliminate q from z(p,q) and
the economy) are such that with the inherited equipment (or rather write the vector of excess-demand functions as z(p). In conjunction
with the maximum services the equipment can yield in the current with A.2.8(d), we may take it that z(p) is continuous over SN+T We
period), there is an upper bound on the quantity of certain labor may then use the same mapping as in Section 2.7 to map SN+T into
services that can be "usefully" employed. By "usefully" we mean itself and proceed as we did there to establish the existence of an
that the employment of sorne more of that labor service makes equilibrium.
possible a change in the vector of outputs of the economy. Next,
suppose that the plans of households have the following property: THEOREM 4. Under assumptions A.2.7, A.2.8, and A.2.9, a tem-
If the ith good is the service supplied by households we have just porary equilibrium exists.
discussed, then for all p in SN+T for whichp 1 ;::: p; the amount of the It behooves us to draw attention to the restrictiveness of A.2.9.
service supplied exceeds sorne fixed positive number, while for It is true that in a number of studies it has appeared that agents
Pt < p; none of it will be supplied. Of course, this violates A.2.8.(d) forecast prices they think will rule in the future by extrapolating from
as the supply function of the service is not now continuous over tbe past and present prices. Moreover, such extrapolation procedures
relevant domain. It is now possible, in light of our other supposi- would satisfy the assumption under discussion. Yet we must recall
tions in this example, that for all p in SN+T for whichp1 :=:: p1, the that for the purposes of an existence proof, the postulated con-
demand of firms for this household service is less than the amount tinuity must be over the whole of SN+T and it is harder to claim
offered by households, say, because they always offer more than the that this is the case from the emprical evidence. In particular, it
38 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 39

The question of interest now is whether a temporary equilibrium upper bound of the amount that can be usefully employed. Thus,
exists. We prove that indeed it does. no equilibrium may exist. If we consider that the physiological
The existence of a competitive equilibrium for fixed q is assured needs of people make it impossible for them to offer labor services
by the following argument: Normalizing p so that pE SN+T also without positive consumption and if we also take note of the
implies by H that the expectation vector q has been normalized. specificity of much productive equipment to particular uses, it is
For fixed q we may write z = z(p,q) = z(p). The vector-valued clear that the example is not farfetched. Of course, the same diffi-
function z(p) has all the properties of z(p) in our previous discussion culty could have arisen in the world with a complete set of futures
of "existence" except H. But H was never invoked in the proof markets. In that case, however, households would have had the
of T.2.2. Hence, we may use the same proof to establish the additional option of selling their services forward and firms may have
existence of a temporary equilibrium. been willing to buy them in conjunction with the future services of
We have shown that, whatever the expectations of agents offuture durable equipment, so that the realism of the postulated conditions
prices might be and however much these expectations may differ of the example would have been less compelling.
among agents, there exists a set of prices in the current markets such So far it has been supposed that, given the normalization of p, the
that all the actions agents plan to undertake in these markets can prices expected by agents may be taken as given. It is more
indeed be carried out. This seems to be a comforting result to have, reasonable, though, to take expected prices as influenced, at least to
but it is not unimportant to bear in mind that the conclusion is sorne extent, by current prices. Our main result, however, will not
limited by the assumptions on which it is based and, in particular, be affected if we stipulate:
that the proof of the existence of equilibrium prices does not
constitute a claim that these prices in fact will be established. AssuMPTION 9. For each household h the expected price vector qh
To understand the limitations imposed by A.2.8, consider the is a continuous function qh(P) of p in
following example. When we consider a system, we take its past
as given, and in particular, we take the stock of durable productive
equipment inherited from the past as given. Suppose that the
production opportunities open to the economy (the production set for Given this assumption, we may again eliminate q from z(p,q) and
the economy) are such that with the inherited equipment (or rather write the vector of excess-demand functions as z(p). In conjunction
with the maximum services the equipment can yield in the current with A.2.8(d), we may take it that z(p) is continuous over SN+T We
period), there is an upper bound on the quantity of certain labor may then use the same mapping as in Section 2.7 to map SN+T into
services that can be "usefully" employed. By "usefully" we mean itself and proceed as we did there to establish the existence of an
that the employment of sorne more of that labor service makes equilibrium.
possible a change in the vector of outputs of the economy. Next,
suppose that the plans of households have the following property: THEOREM 4. Under assumptions A.2.7, A.2.8, and A.2.9, a tem-
If the ith good is the service supplied by households we have just porary equilibrium exists.
discussed, then for all p in SN+T for whichp 1 ;::: p; the amount of the It behooves us to draw attention to the restrictiveness of A.2.9.
service supplied exceeds sorne fixed positive number, while for It is true that in a number of studies it has appeared that agents
Pt < p; none of it will be supplied. Of course, this violates A.2.8.(d) forecast prices they think will rule in the future by extrapolating from
as the supply function of the service is not now continuous over tbe past and present prices. Moreover, such extrapolation procedures
relevant domain. It is now possible, in light of our other supposi- would satisfy the assumption under discussion. Yet we must recall
tions in this example, that for all p in SN+T for whichp1 :=:: p1, the that for the purposes of an existence proof, the postulated con-
demand of firms for this household service is less than the amount tinuity must be over the whole of SN+T and it is harder to claim
offered by households, say, because they always offer more than the that this is the case from the emprical evidence. In particular, it
1

i!lli 40 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


41
MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH
'!i:'~l:
'"J,
'1:
may be argued that there are certain p in SN+T so different from any of one non-produced input. All household demand functions satisfy
1 i prices that ruled befare our investigation started that agents will
H.
consider their routinized method of expectation formation inade-
quate should such p occur. If this is so (and no doubt instances in We shall wish to restrict the possible production choices further by
economic history cometo mind in which it certainly appears to ha ve AssuMPTION 12. (a) y~N < O for all y 1 =!= O that f can choose.
been so), then A.2.9 is unlikely to be satisfied. In any event, this is No output without labor input.
an area of economics in which our ignorance is so great that it would (b) For each J, there exists a vector y1 such that
be very unwise to regard our assumption as more than tentative and,
of course, convenient for our purposes. L YiJ >O.
NN
The system is productive. (Note that ~his condition need hold only
11. Short-Period Equilibrium: A Special Case for a suitable choice of units.)

The short-period model we have been considering, although Finally, let us now take p to be an N-dimensional price vector,
restricted by certain assumptions, is of a pretty general sort and SN to be the N-dimensional price simplex, and define C1 by
could be made more general still without too much difficulty (e.g., Cr = p,- py~.
we could easily do without the assumption that firms make no in ter- Evidently C1 is the unit production cost at p when y; is chosen. We
temporal decisions). We have seen that there is a well-defined postula te
meaning for the equilibrium of such an economy, and we have seen
what we must postulate in order to establish that such equilibrium AssuMPTION 13. (a) For every p in SN there is a choice ofy~(p) such

exists. In this section we will examine the short-period equilibrium that Cj(p) = p 1 - py~(p) :S: p1 - py~, all possible y~.
of a somewhat different economy. It is an economy we shall wish (b) CJ(p) is continuous over SN.
to discuss further elsewhere in this book. For brevity, we shall (e) Necessary conditions for the equilibrium of economic agents
refer to it as the Leontief (L) economy beca use it is closely connected in the L-economy at p* are
with the work of that economist. It is described by the following (i) p'j :S: Cj(p*) all J,
set of assumptions: (ii) pjy11(p*) = CJ(p*)Y1r(P*) allf
AssuMPTION 10. (a) If y1 is a possible choice for firm J, then so is No production at negative profit andzero equilibrium profits.
ky 1 with k > O. Constant returns to sea/e (CR). This, with one exception to be introducetllater, completes the specifi-
(b) Every possible y1 for firm f has only one non-negative com- cation of the L-economy. We shall postpone a proper discussion of
ponent, namely y 11 No joint production. the various assumptions until we have established certain properties
(e) There are no durable production goods. of this economy. Here, however, we may note that CR implies a
In view of CR, we may, for all y 11 > O, define situation we took as an example of the violation of F. It is clear,
, _lf_
therefore, that we cannot hope to discuss the L"economy exclusively
Yf - in terms of excess.-demand functions. It is at this stage that A.2.13(e)
Yrr
proves useful. This assumption is based on the Walrasian view that
and be certain that if y1 is a possible choice for J, then so is y~. production as such involves no costs, psychic or otherwise, other
We now suppose that the Nth component of y~ represents the than the mount that has to be paid to inputs required for produc-
input of a labor service and postula te:
tion.1 Hence, if at some p a firm is found to make a profit, there is
AssuMPTION 11. No household can supply a labor service other
1
than that represented by the Iabel N. We call this the assumption A.2.13(a) and (b) can be deduced from the production conditions (see Section
3.4, especially T.3.7).
1

i!lli 40 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


41
MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH
'!i:'~l:
'"J,
'1:
may be argued that there are certain p in SN+T so different from any of one non-produced input. All household demand functions satisfy
1 i prices that ruled befare our investigation started that agents will
H.
consider their routinized method of expectation formation inade-
quate should such p occur. If this is so (and no doubt instances in We shall wish to restrict the possible production choices further by
economic history cometo mind in which it certainly appears to ha ve AssuMPTION 12. (a) y~N < O for all y 1 =!= O that f can choose.
been so), then A.2.9 is unlikely to be satisfied. In any event, this is No output without labor input.
an area of economics in which our ignorance is so great that it would (b) For each J, there exists a vector y1 such that
be very unwise to regard our assumption as more than tentative and,
of course, convenient for our purposes. L YiJ >O.
NN
The system is productive. (Note that ~his condition need hold only
11. Short-Period Equilibrium: A Special Case for a suitable choice of units.)

The short-period model we have been considering, although Finally, let us now take p to be an N-dimensional price vector,
restricted by certain assumptions, is of a pretty general sort and SN to be the N-dimensional price simplex, and define C1 by
could be made more general still without too much difficulty (e.g., Cr = p,- py~.
we could easily do without the assumption that firms make no in ter- Evidently C1 is the unit production cost at p when y; is chosen. We
temporal decisions). We have seen that there is a well-defined postula te
meaning for the equilibrium of such an economy, and we have seen
what we must postulate in order to establish that such equilibrium AssuMPTION 13. (a) For every p in SN there is a choice ofy~(p) such

exists. In this section we will examine the short-period equilibrium that Cj(p) = p 1 - py~(p) :S: p1 - py~, all possible y~.
of a somewhat different economy. It is an economy we shall wish (b) CJ(p) is continuous over SN.
to discuss further elsewhere in this book. For brevity, we shall (e) Necessary conditions for the equilibrium of economic agents
refer to it as the Leontief (L) economy beca use it is closely connected in the L-economy at p* are
with the work of that economist. It is described by the following (i) p'j :S: Cj(p*) all J,
set of assumptions: (ii) pjy11(p*) = CJ(p*)Y1r(P*) allf
AssuMPTION 10. (a) If y1 is a possible choice for firm J, then so is No production at negative profit andzero equilibrium profits.
ky 1 with k > O. Constant returns to sea/e (CR). This, with one exception to be introducetllater, completes the specifi-
(b) Every possible y1 for firm f has only one non-negative com- cation of the L-economy. We shall postpone a proper discussion of
ponent, namely y 11 No joint production. the various assumptions until we have established certain properties
(e) There are no durable production goods. of this economy. Here, however, we may note that CR implies a
In view of CR, we may, for all y 11 > O, define situation we took as an example of the violation of F. It is clear,
, _lf_
therefore, that we cannot hope to discuss the L"economy exclusively
Yf - in terms of excess.-demand functions. It is at this stage that A.2.13(e)
Yrr
proves useful. This assumption is based on the Walrasian view that
and be certain that if y1 is a possible choice for J, then so is y~. production as such involves no costs, psychic or otherwise, other
We now suppose that the Nth component of y~ represents the than the mount that has to be paid to inputs required for produc-
input of a labor service and postula te:
tion.1 Hence, if at some p a firm is found to make a profit, there is
AssuMPTION 11. No household can supply a labor service other
1
than that represented by the Iabel N. We call this the assumption A.2.13(a) and (b) can be deduced from the production conditions (see Section
3.4, especially T.3.7).
;""1

42 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 43

an inducement for sorne agents in the economy not presently engaged Since then O < pt = TN(p*) and k < 1, it must be that pt =
in production to become so engaged. The profit here referred to is 1 - V(p*) or else pt = kpt. So we have
the maximum profit. By the same token, if profits are zero, then
1 - V(p*) > kpt,
the scale of production is a matter of indifference to the firm CR.
Our first task is to show that there exist prices satisfying A.2.13(e). from which it then follows that
Our procedure once again will be to find a mapping of SN into itself pj = T1(p*) = Cj(p*) /=1, ... ,N-1,
and to show that the fixed point of this mapping is the price vector
we seek. so that the fixed point certain1y satisfies A.2.13(e). It remains only
Consider the following mapping: to show that indeed pt > O.
Since p* is in SN, the supposition that pt = O would imply that
T1(p) = min[1; (1 ;(:rN)]Cj(p), f= 1, ... , N- 1; 1 >k> O p~ = maxpj >O m< N. (8)
1
(7a)
Also from (7), pt = O implies that
(7b)
1 - V(p*) ::;; O. (9)
where
Let Ym be the vector described in A.2.12(b), with f = m, y~ =
V(p) = L
NN
Cj(p). (7c) Ym/Ymm; note that

We shall first verify that (7) does indeed take points of SN into points
in SN.
(a) By the definition of Cj(p) and the assumption of no joint From A.2.13(a), C~(p*) ::;; p; - p*y~, so that

production, we have Cj(p) ?:: O, all p and all f Hence, certainly p~ - C~(p*) ?:: p*y~ = L PJY~; ?:: p~ L y~,; > O,
T(p) ?:: O, all f, TN(p) ?:: O, all p. We note that the assumption of NN NN
-[
"no output without labor input" implies that V(p) can be only zero
where use has been made of the facts that pt = O, pj ::;; p~, and
whenpN =O.
Y~; ::;; O for j
# m. From (7) and (9).
(b) Suppose that 1 - V(p) < kpN. Then by (7), T1(p) =
(1 - kPN)Cj(p)/V(p),J = 1, ... , N- 1, and TN(P) = kPN Adding
gives
P = V(~*) Cj(p*) ::;; Cj(p*) /=1, ... ,N-l.

Since not both these inequalities can hold, we conclude that indeed
Pt >O.
(e) If 1 - V(p) ?:: kpN, then by (7), T1(p) = Cj(p), f = 1, ... , We now note that by A.2.12(a) and A.2.13(a), pt > O implies
N- 1, and TN(p) = 1 - V(p). Adding gives C(p*) > O, allf, and so it follows that pj > O, allf Moreover, we
have shown that there exists p* in SN, which satisfies A.13(c). We
L Tl(p) = l.
1
summarize:
THEOREM 5. If A.2.10-A.2.13 inclusive, then there exists a strictly
Since, by A.2.13(b), the functions Cj(p) are continuous over SN,
. . p* m
posttlve . SN such that p 1* = C 1*(p) ,J= 1, ... ,N- 1, and
the mapping in (7) is also continuous and thus has a fixed point p*.
Pt = 1 - V(p*).
We now show that p* satisfies the zero-profit condition. In doing
this we shall first assume that pt > O and then prove that this is This result is pleasant, but it is not yet sufficient to establish the
indeed the case. existence of an equilibrium for the L-economy; it remains to show

i i
; __ ,,t,,lL ______ _
;""1

42 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 43

an inducement for sorne agents in the economy not presently engaged Since then O < pt = TN(p*) and k < 1, it must be that pt =
in production to become so engaged. The profit here referred to is 1 - V(p*) or else pt = kpt. So we have
the maximum profit. By the same token, if profits are zero, then
1 - V(p*) > kpt,
the scale of production is a matter of indifference to the firm CR.
Our first task is to show that there exist prices satisfying A.2.13(e). from which it then follows that
Our procedure once again will be to find a mapping of SN into itself pj = T1(p*) = Cj(p*) /=1, ... ,N-1,
and to show that the fixed point of this mapping is the price vector
we seek. so that the fixed point certain1y satisfies A.2.13(e). It remains only
Consider the following mapping: to show that indeed pt > O.
Since p* is in SN, the supposition that pt = O would imply that
T1(p) = min[1; (1 ;(:rN)]Cj(p), f= 1, ... , N- 1; 1 >k> O p~ = maxpj >O m< N. (8)
1
(7a)
Also from (7), pt = O implies that
(7b)
1 - V(p*) ::;; O. (9)
where
Let Ym be the vector described in A.2.12(b), with f = m, y~ =
V(p) = L
NN
Cj(p). (7c) Ym/Ymm; note that

We shall first verify that (7) does indeed take points of SN into points
in SN.
(a) By the definition of Cj(p) and the assumption of no joint From A.2.13(a), C~(p*) ::;; p; - p*y~, so that

production, we have Cj(p) ?:: O, all p and all f Hence, certainly p~ - C~(p*) ?:: p*y~ = L PJY~; ?:: p~ L y~,; > O,
T(p) ?:: O, all f, TN(p) ?:: O, all p. We note that the assumption of NN NN
-[
"no output without labor input" implies that V(p) can be only zero
where use has been made of the facts that pt = O, pj ::;; p~, and
whenpN =O.
Y~; ::;; O for j
# m. From (7) and (9).
(b) Suppose that 1 - V(p) < kpN. Then by (7), T1(p) =
(1 - kPN)Cj(p)/V(p),J = 1, ... , N- 1, and TN(P) = kPN Adding
gives
P = V(~*) Cj(p*) ::;; Cj(p*) /=1, ... ,N-l.

Since not both these inequalities can hold, we conclude that indeed
Pt >O.
(e) If 1 - V(p) ?:: kpN, then by (7), T1(p) = Cj(p), f = 1, ... , We now note that by A.2.12(a) and A.2.13(a), pt > O implies
N- 1, and TN(p) = 1 - V(p). Adding gives C(p*) > O, allf, and so it follows that pj > O, allf Moreover, we
have shown that there exists p* in SN, which satisfies A.13(c). We
L Tl(p) = l.
1
summarize:
THEOREM 5. If A.2.10-A.2.13 inclusive, then there exists a strictly
Since, by A.2.13(b), the functions Cj(p) are continuous over SN,
. . p* m
posttlve . SN such that p 1* = C 1*(p) ,J= 1, ... ,N- 1, and
the mapping in (7) is also continuous and thus has a fixed point p*.
Pt = 1 - V(p*).
We now show that p* satisfies the zero-profit condition. In doing
this we shall first assume that pt > O and then prove that this is This result is pleasant, but it is not yet sufficient to establish the
indeed the case. existence of an equilibrium for the L-economy; it remains to show

i i
; __ ,,t,,lL ______ _
11

44 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 45

that all markets can be cleared at p*. (Recall that p* O, so that which is the value of the labor services supplied by households.
excess supplies are inconsistent with equilibrium.) To do so, we i 1 Hence, multiplication of both si des of (!O) by p*, since we know that
l,
unfortunately require another assumption: pt > O, shows that the labor market is also in equilibrium at p*.
AssUMPTION 14. Let x'(p*) be the N - !-dimensional vector of We summarize:
,u

,:11 household demand at p* for all goods other than the Nth. 1 Then THEOREM 6. If A.2.10-A.2.14 then a strictly positive equilibrium
if x' is the N- !-dimensional vector of the goods owned by house-
1

for the L-economy exists.


holds, x'(p*) - x' > o.
Let us discuss sorne of the features of this economy and, in
We note that for x' = O, this assumption will always hold provided particular, examine the role of the various assumptions we have
households supply sorne of the labor service. However, with made.
x' =6 O, the assumption is evidently quite restrictive; we will com- We note that if an equilibrium exists, we are able to determine p*
ment on this again. without reference to the forces of demand at all. This is one of the
Now if all markets for non-labor services are cleared, we require most striking properties of the L-economy. Moreover, we ha ve, by
that T.2.5,
y[(p*)y11(p*) = x;(p*) -
f
x; j= !, ... ,N-l. p* H(p*) = - pty~(p*), (11)
where y~(p*) is the N - 1 vector with components YN(p*). There-
On writing h(p*) for the N- !-dimensional vector with components
fore,
y 11 (p*) and H(p*) for the (N- 1) x (N - 1) matrix with typical
element y[(p*), we have to solve p* = - p,~y~(p*) [H(p*)]- 1.
H(p*)h(p*) = x'(p*) - x' (10) As the example in the footnote 1 makes clear, this means that we
may express the equilibrium price of every produced commodity as
for h'(p*) > O. From A.2.10(b), H(p*) is a matrix with n~n-positive
made up of the direct and indirect labor costs of producing one unit
off-diagonal elements and positive diagonal elements. Also, of that commodity.
pfy[iP*) = - PtY[N(p*) > 0
NN
1
Consider the case in which H(p*) is 2 x 2 and so y~ is 2-dimensional.
Omitting the argument p*, we may write
by T.2.5 and A.2.12(a). Hence (see Appendix A, Remark 2), H(p*)
has a non-negative inverse. This, together with A.2.14, then leads H(p*) = [ ~ YF] + 1= say, -A+ 1,
to h(p*) > O. YF! O
We are now left only with the market for labor services. By the where 1 is the diagonal unit matrix. Evidently, A is non-negative, and by the
postulate A.2.12(b), we have
definition of p*, we ha ve, writing jj* for the N.- 1 vector of prices
excluding pt, [H(p*)]- 1 = 1 + A + A 2 + .
p* H(p*)h(p*) = - Pt YrN(p*)yrr(p*), So
f p* = pJ{y~(l + A + A + ),
2

which is the value of the total demand for labor by firms. By W from which, for instance, p~ is given by
we have also
P~ = [Y~N + YPYN + YFY~rY~N + ]pJ{.
p*(x'(p*) - x') = - ptxN(p*), The first term in the bracket measures the direct labor input required per unit
of output of firm F, the second term measures the labor input required to
1 We take the expected price vector q to be a continuous function of p and
produce the output of firm f required to produce one unit of output of firm F,
have eliminated it from the excess-demand function. and so on.
11

44 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 45

that all markets can be cleared at p*. (Recall that p* O, so that which is the value of the labor services supplied by households.
excess supplies are inconsistent with equilibrium.) To do so, we i 1 Hence, multiplication of both si des of (!O) by p*, since we know that
l,
unfortunately require another assumption: pt > O, shows that the labor market is also in equilibrium at p*.
AssUMPTION 14. Let x'(p*) be the N - !-dimensional vector of We summarize:
,u

,:11 household demand at p* for all goods other than the Nth. 1 Then THEOREM 6. If A.2.10-A.2.14 then a strictly positive equilibrium
if x' is the N- !-dimensional vector of the goods owned by house-
1

for the L-economy exists.


holds, x'(p*) - x' > o.
Let us discuss sorne of the features of this economy and, in
We note that for x' = O, this assumption will always hold provided particular, examine the role of the various assumptions we have
households supply sorne of the labor service. However, with made.
x' =6 O, the assumption is evidently quite restrictive; we will com- We note that if an equilibrium exists, we are able to determine p*
ment on this again. without reference to the forces of demand at all. This is one of the
Now if all markets for non-labor services are cleared, we require most striking properties of the L-economy. Moreover, we ha ve, by
that T.2.5,
y[(p*)y11(p*) = x;(p*) -
f
x; j= !, ... ,N-l. p* H(p*) = - pty~(p*), (11)
where y~(p*) is the N - 1 vector with components YN(p*). There-
On writing h(p*) for the N- !-dimensional vector with components
fore,
y 11 (p*) and H(p*) for the (N- 1) x (N - 1) matrix with typical
element y[(p*), we have to solve p* = - p,~y~(p*) [H(p*)]- 1.
H(p*)h(p*) = x'(p*) - x' (10) As the example in the footnote 1 makes clear, this means that we
may express the equilibrium price of every produced commodity as
for h'(p*) > O. From A.2.10(b), H(p*) is a matrix with n~n-positive
made up of the direct and indirect labor costs of producing one unit
off-diagonal elements and positive diagonal elements. Also, of that commodity.
pfy[iP*) = - PtY[N(p*) > 0
NN
1
Consider the case in which H(p*) is 2 x 2 and so y~ is 2-dimensional.
Omitting the argument p*, we may write
by T.2.5 and A.2.12(a). Hence (see Appendix A, Remark 2), H(p*)
has a non-negative inverse. This, together with A.2.14, then leads H(p*) = [ ~ YF] + 1= say, -A+ 1,
to h(p*) > O. YF! O
We are now left only with the market for labor services. By the where 1 is the diagonal unit matrix. Evidently, A is non-negative, and by the
postulate A.2.12(b), we have
definition of p*, we ha ve, writing jj* for the N.- 1 vector of prices
excluding pt, [H(p*)]- 1 = 1 + A + A 2 + .
p* H(p*)h(p*) = - Pt YrN(p*)yrr(p*), So
f p* = pJ{y~(l + A + A + ),
2

which is the value of the total demand for labor by firms. By W from which, for instance, p~ is given by
we have also
P~ = [Y~N + YPYN + YFY~rY~N + ]pJ{.
p*(x'(p*) - x') = - ptxN(p*), The first term in the bracket measures the direct labor input required per unit
of output of firm F, the second term measures the labor input required to
1 We take the expected price vector q to be a continuous function of p and
produce the output of firm f required to produce one unit of output of firm F,
have eliminated it from the excess-demand function. and so on.
,;
1

lil
. il

111

11 46 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST A;PPROACH 47


11

Since p* is determined without reference to demand conditions, it The assumption that the system is productive is one we probably
follows also that we now do not need any elaborate assumptions to should want to impose on models other than the L-economy, and it
ensure that all demand functions are continuous over SN. Indeed, seems quite agreeable to casual experience. Matters are rather
the theory of household behavior can be left in a most rudimen- different when it comes to the postulate that households are net
tary state. All we need is H and W, the most innocuous of demanders of sorne produced goods and net suppliers of none
the assumptions. Por all these reasons, the L-economy has proved (A.2.14). Without this assumption, there might be transactions in
attractive to many economists. But 1he number of assumptions we a good that can be, but is not, produced. Indeed, the equilibrium
have made suggests that this simplicity is achieved at certain costs. market price of that good, that is, the situation in which the excess
The role of constant returns to scale in achieving our results is demand for that good is non-positive, might then be below the
clear. If we did not make the assumption, we could not determine mnimum unit cost of producing it. Evidently the forces of demand
the prices that do not exceed unit costs without reference to the scale will be in volved ii1 the determination of prices. The assumption has
of production, and so to the forces of demand. If certain durable no immediate appeal unless it is argued that we may take households
goods (their services) were used in production and the quantity of not to hold any quantities of the producible goods. Without this
these goods available arbitrarily specified, then once again prices postulate, then not only might we lose the special features of the
could not be determined independently of demand conditions. As L-economy, but we will also have to proceed along different lines to
the services of durable goods used currently are not produced prove the existence of an equilibrium, in order to deal with excess
currently, the price of these services cannot be determined from the demands not satisfying F (see Chapter 5).
conditions of production, but must be found from the conditions of There remains A.2.13. In part (a) of this assumption we ensured
market equilibrium, which, in turn, involve the forces of demand. the existence of a unique cost-minimizing choice y~ for all p. This
Moreover, we cannot determine the prices of goods currently pro- allowed us without further argument to treat the market clearing
duced until we know the prices of the services of durables. If we do problem as we did in (10). The same point is involved here as in
not take the amount of durables as arbitrarily given, and make sorne assumption F and is not at all important in a general treatment.
further assumptions, these consequences can be avoided. Exactly Part (b) is explained on the same grounds as those invoked in the
the same reasoning explains why we found it necessary to postulate discussion of C. Both assumptions can be deduced as conse-
that there is only one kind of labor service. When we consider the quences of somewhat more fundamental restrictions on the set of
variety of such services in practice, it is clear that not too much possible production choices of firms. This is done in Chapter 3,
reliance should be placed on the L-model. where the realism of this procedure is also considered.
The assumption of "no output without labor input" is somewhat After all this, we may judge that the L-economy is an interesting
stronger than is strictly required. . Its consequence is, of course, to construction, if for no other reason than that it helps us to under-
ensure that all equilibrium prices are strictly positive. Had we stand earlier theories, such as the labor theory of value, but it seems
postulated instead that for sorne particular good only, we could get somewhat unlikely that a pure "cost of production theory" of prices
no output without labor input, you can verify that all our arguments is capable of reflecting adequately the complexiti~s of the real world.
and conclusions would continue to hold, except the proposition that There are severa! directions, however, in which the analysis can be
p* is strictly positive. Had we dropped the assumption altogether, extended. We note only one of these here.
we would have had an equilibrium situation in which all produced Suppose that inputs precede output by "one period"; production
goods might have a zero price-an uninteresting case. In any case, takes time. We are interested in situations in which the price
this particular assumption is not particularly unpalatable. expected by everyone for the period t + 1 is the same as that at t.
The use we have made of the supposition that the system is However, the price that would actually be paid at t for a good to be
productive is evident. It enabled us to ensure a semi-positive delivered at t + 1 differs from the current price for current delivery
solution for (10). by an arbitrarily given "discount factor." This is a familiar and
,;
1

lil
. il

111

11 46 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST A;PPROACH 47


11

Since p* is determined without reference to demand conditions, it The assumption that the system is productive is one we probably
follows also that we now do not need any elaborate assumptions to should want to impose on models other than the L-economy, and it
ensure that all demand functions are continuous over SN. Indeed, seems quite agreeable to casual experience. Matters are rather
the theory of household behavior can be left in a most rudimen- different when it comes to the postulate that households are net
tary state. All we need is H and W, the most innocuous of demanders of sorne produced goods and net suppliers of none
the assumptions. Por all these reasons, the L-economy has proved (A.2.14). Without this assumption, there might be transactions in
attractive to many economists. But 1he number of assumptions we a good that can be, but is not, produced. Indeed, the equilibrium
have made suggests that this simplicity is achieved at certain costs. market price of that good, that is, the situation in which the excess
The role of constant returns to scale in achieving our results is demand for that good is non-positive, might then be below the
clear. If we did not make the assumption, we could not determine mnimum unit cost of producing it. Evidently the forces of demand
the prices that do not exceed unit costs without reference to the scale will be in volved ii1 the determination of prices. The assumption has
of production, and so to the forces of demand. If certain durable no immediate appeal unless it is argued that we may take households
goods (their services) were used in production and the quantity of not to hold any quantities of the producible goods. Without this
these goods available arbitrarily specified, then once again prices postulate, then not only might we lose the special features of the
could not be determined independently of demand conditions. As L-economy, but we will also have to proceed along different lines to
the services of durable goods used currently are not produced prove the existence of an equilibrium, in order to deal with excess
currently, the price of these services cannot be determined from the demands not satisfying F (see Chapter 5).
conditions of production, but must be found from the conditions of There remains A.2.13. In part (a) of this assumption we ensured
market equilibrium, which, in turn, involve the forces of demand. the existence of a unique cost-minimizing choice y~ for all p. This
Moreover, we cannot determine the prices of goods currently pro- allowed us without further argument to treat the market clearing
duced until we know the prices of the services of durables. If we do problem as we did in (10). The same point is involved here as in
not take the amount of durables as arbitrarily given, and make sorne assumption F and is not at all important in a general treatment.
further assumptions, these consequences can be avoided. Exactly Part (b) is explained on the same grounds as those invoked in the
the same reasoning explains why we found it necessary to postulate discussion of C. Both assumptions can be deduced as conse-
that there is only one kind of labor service. When we consider the quences of somewhat more fundamental restrictions on the set of
variety of such services in practice, it is clear that not too much possible production choices of firms. This is done in Chapter 3,
reliance should be placed on the L-model. where the realism of this procedure is also considered.
The assumption of "no output without labor input" is somewhat After all this, we may judge that the L-economy is an interesting
stronger than is strictly required. . Its consequence is, of course, to construction, if for no other reason than that it helps us to under-
ensure that all equilibrium prices are strictly positive. Had we stand earlier theories, such as the labor theory of value, but it seems
postulated instead that for sorne particular good only, we could get somewhat unlikely that a pure "cost of production theory" of prices
no output without labor input, you can verify that all our arguments is capable of reflecting adequately the complexiti~s of the real world.
and conclusions would continue to hold, except the proposition that There are severa! directions, however, in which the analysis can be
p* is strictly positive. Had we dropped the assumption altogether, extended. We note only one of these here.
we would have had an equilibrium situation in which all produced Suppose that inputs precede output by "one period"; production
goods might have a zero price-an uninteresting case. In any case, takes time. We are interested in situations in which the price
this particular assumption is not particularly unpalatable. expected by everyone for the period t + 1 is the same as that at t.
The use we have made of the supposition that the system is However, the price that would actually be paid at t for a good to be
productive is evident. It enabled us to ensure a semi-positive delivered at t + 1 differs from the current price for current delivery
solution for (10). by an arbitrarily given "discount factor." This is a familiar and
48 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 49

elementary idea; we do not pro pose to discuss here the determination carrying out the transactions they wish to carry out, it will also be
of the equilibrium discount factor. true that, after these transactions, they will find themselves holding
We <;ontinue to postulate A.2.10-A.2.12, as well as A.2.13(a) and goods (if apy) in just the quantities they had planned. This simply
lli: (b ). In particular, note that there are still no durable inputs. means that if people can carry out the desired change in their stocks
h:l
:::1
A.2.13(e) is modified as follows: -transact so much and so much of the particular good over the
;.:1
given time interval-then they will also find that they hold as much
111
AssuMPTION 13. (e*) A necessary condition of equilibrium is, of the good as desired. In general, however, prices will differ not
1

::!il (i) p'J s RCj(p*) allj, only from one period to the next, but also from what they had been
111!
expected to be. The prices here are those that establish temporary
,'11
* = RC*(
(n.. ) Pr*Yrr *) *
r P Yrr a 11/,,
:.,,1
11111
equilibrium'at each moment in time. This means that the quantities
where R is a scalar, R 2: 1 (R - l is the discount factor). of various goods that agents wish to hold will differ at different
moments of time.
The question is whether for given R, there exists p* satisfying
It is evidently both useful apd legitimate to distinguish between
A.2.13(c*). Now let
an economy in which there is the full complement of futures markets,
Cj*(p) = RCj(p), or that behaves as though there were such a full complement, and
one that is not so fortunate. The equilibrium ofthe former economy
/-#N, might be called a "full" or "long-run" equilibrium, while the latter
V*(p) = _2 Cj*(p), may be analyzed by means of a sequence of short-run equilibria. In
NN the literature we find a further distinction, as is evident in the title of
and Jet T*(p) be the mapping in (7) with the new definitions. It is this section. If we think of the quantity of a good offered for sale,
easy to check that if we just assume pt > Othe mapping d<;>es indeed we must specify, for good sense, the period over which this is so, and
have a fixed point satisfying A.2.13(c*). However, A.2.13(b) does similarly for the quantity demanded. Hence, both quantities have
not now ensure that a time dimension: so-and-so much per unit of time. When we think
of the amount of a gqod an agent wishes to store, we think of the
p; - C**(p*) 2: p*y~, amount he wishes to ha ve at a moment of time, and no time dimen-
sion is involved. The former are called ''flow" variables and the
so our earlier line of proof that pt > O may fail. Indeed, it is clear latter "stock" variables. If we change the units in which we
that the assumption that the system is productive cannot ensure the measure time, then the flow variables are affected, but the stock
above inequality for arbitrarily large R. On the other hand, the variables are not. In the literature, then, a distinction is drawn
argument is clearly safe for R = l. We conclude: between a situation in which all flow markets are cleared, a jlow
The time-using economy has an equilibrium satisfying A.13(c*) equilibrium, and a situation in which all agents find they have the
for any given R not exceeding sorne R. > l. stocks they desire, a stock equilibrium.
The market-clearing equations are now also changed since current In the light of what has already been said, this distinction can
inputs must be provided by the outputs of past production decisions. have force only if we regard as a flow equilibrium a situation in
This is not pursued here. which not all agents are carrying out the transactions they regard as
most satisfactory at the ruling prices, although all flow markets are
cleared. Th,is goes counter to the definition of an equilibrium that
12. Stock and Flow Equilibrium
we have employed throughout this chapter. Consider a typical
If we consider again the short-period equilibrium of the economy example. It may be that ata given set of prices curren ti y ruling and
of Section 2.10, we see that sin ce, at p*, all agents are capable of given expected prices, flow markets are cleared because sorne agents
48 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 49

elementary idea; we do not pro pose to discuss here the determination carrying out the transactions they wish to carry out, it will also be
of the equilibrium discount factor. true that, after these transactions, they will find themselves holding
We <;ontinue to postulate A.2.10-A.2.12, as well as A.2.13(a) and goods (if apy) in just the quantities they had planned. This simply
lli: (b ). In particular, note that there are still no durable inputs. means that if people can carry out the desired change in their stocks
h:l
:::1
A.2.13(e) is modified as follows: -transact so much and so much of the particular good over the
;.:1
given time interval-then they will also find that they hold as much
111
AssuMPTION 13. (e*) A necessary condition of equilibrium is, of the good as desired. In general, however, prices will differ not
1

::!il (i) p'J s RCj(p*) allj, only from one period to the next, but also from what they had been
111!
expected to be. The prices here are those that establish temporary
,'11
* = RC*(
(n.. ) Pr*Yrr *) *
r P Yrr a 11/,,
:.,,1
11111
equilibrium'at each moment in time. This means that the quantities
where R is a scalar, R 2: 1 (R - l is the discount factor). of various goods that agents wish to hold will differ at different
moments of time.
The question is whether for given R, there exists p* satisfying
It is evidently both useful apd legitimate to distinguish between
A.2.13(c*). Now let
an economy in which there is the full complement of futures markets,
Cj*(p) = RCj(p), or that behaves as though there were such a full complement, and
one that is not so fortunate. The equilibrium ofthe former economy
/-#N, might be called a "full" or "long-run" equilibrium, while the latter
V*(p) = _2 Cj*(p), may be analyzed by means of a sequence of short-run equilibria. In
NN the literature we find a further distinction, as is evident in the title of
and Jet T*(p) be the mapping in (7) with the new definitions. It is this section. If we think of the quantity of a good offered for sale,
easy to check that if we just assume pt > Othe mapping d<;>es indeed we must specify, for good sense, the period over which this is so, and
have a fixed point satisfying A.2.13(c*). However, A.2.13(b) does similarly for the quantity demanded. Hence, both quantities have
not now ensure that a time dimension: so-and-so much per unit of time. When we think
of the amount of a gqod an agent wishes to store, we think of the
p; - C**(p*) 2: p*y~, amount he wishes to ha ve at a moment of time, and no time dimen-
sion is involved. The former are called ''flow" variables and the
so our earlier line of proof that pt > O may fail. Indeed, it is clear latter "stock" variables. If we change the units in which we
that the assumption that the system is productive cannot ensure the measure time, then the flow variables are affected, but the stock
above inequality for arbitrarily large R. On the other hand, the variables are not. In the literature, then, a distinction is drawn
argument is clearly safe for R = l. We conclude: between a situation in which all flow markets are cleared, a jlow
The time-using economy has an equilibrium satisfying A.13(c*) equilibrium, and a situation in which all agents find they have the
for any given R not exceeding sorne R. > l. stocks they desire, a stock equilibrium.
The market-clearing equations are now also changed since current In the light of what has already been said, this distinction can
inputs must be provided by the outputs of past production decisions. have force only if we regard as a flow equilibrium a situation in
This is not pursued here. which not all agents are carrying out the transactions they regard as
most satisfactory at the ruling prices, although all flow markets are
cleared. Th,is goes counter to the definition of an equilibrium that
12. Stock and Flow Equilibrium
we have employed throughout this chapter. Consider a typical
If we consider again the short-period equilibrium of the economy example. It may be that ata given set of prices curren ti y ruling and
of Section 2.10, we see that sin ce, at p*, all agents are capable of given expected prices, flow markets are cleared because sorne agents
50 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 51

are prepared to satisfy what would otherwise be an excess flow Notes


demand by holding less of a good than they would like (" unintended" Existence theorems of the general nature ofT.2.2 were first proved by
dishoarding), while others hold more of a good than they would like Wald [1933-34, 1934-35]; for systematic expositions of severa! inter-
and so prevent what otherwise would be a flow excess supply related results, see Wald [1936, 1951]. Wald assumed demand func-
(unintended hoarding). Evidently, in this view we may have flow tions arising from the household sector together with Cassel's system of
equilibrium and stock disequilibrium. But the notion of an fixed coefficient relations for production (see Section 1.5). Iffactors are
identified with final goods so that the production of final good i requires
equilibrium has clearly been widened to include situations in which one unit of factor i and nothing else, then Wald's result is the same as
agents themselves are not in equilibrium in the sense that they do not T.2.2, though his assumptions were considerably stronger; see Wald
carry out the transactions most satisfactory to themselves at the [1951' pp. 372-373].
ruling prices. McKenzie [1954] established an existence theorem that is more
It is not at all clear that the nomenclature of the literature is a general than Wald's with regard to production assumptions; however,
if specialized to the case of exchange, it is identical to Wald's.
good one, simply because it is not helpful to have the same name to Both Wald and McKenzie assumed that the demand for a free good
describe quite different situations. In any case, in this volume the was infinite, more precisely that z,(pv)-->- + ctJ for any sequence {pv} for
distinction between stock and flow equilibrium will become relevant which pv-->- p0 , where pp = O. As the discussion in Section 2.8 shows,
only in the analysis of what, in our d~finition, are disequilibrium this assumption is not compatible, in general, with utility maximization.
situations. Equilibrium in a mo del of no joint production, as discussed in Section
2.11, was discussed extensively by Leontief [1941] for the special case
Connected with the distinction we have been discussing is the in which there are fixed coefficients for the production of each com-
device of "period analysis." This can be helpful in overcoming modity. The crucial role of the productivity assumption, A.2.12(b) in
some of the conceptual problems raised by continuous time, but it our notation, was first stressed by Hawkins and Simon [1949]. The
can also be misleading. For instance, Swedish authors at one time generalization of these results to the case of variable coefficients is due
found it helpful to define the length of the period by the time interval independently to Georgescu-Roegen [1951] and Samuelson [1951].
over which prices could be taken as fixed. Starting with g~ven prices
at the beginning of the period, a flow equilibrium over the period,
then, would involve stock disequilibrium at the end of the period
unless the economy was in full equilibrium. They then traced the
economy from period to period by using certain rules for changing
prices. In an economy with many agents, however, it seems
unnatural to suppose that they all not only adjust their preferred
action at discrete intervals, but they do so at the same moment. If
that is not so, then such adjustments will be taking place more or
less continuously. To this must be added the fact that period
analysis leads to a formulation in terms of "difference equations,"
which are capable of producing motions for the system that are not
possible if the formulation is in terms of differential equations, so
that what started as an aid to visualization may finish by being
pretty misleading. In any event, it is noticeable that the discus-
sion of this paragraph quite naturally. ran in terms of what, from
the agents' point of view, are plainly disequilibrium processes and
confirms the view that these matters are best treated when we come
to consider such processes.

J'
50 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r MARKET EQUILIBRIUM : A FIRST APPROACH 51

are prepared to satisfy what would otherwise be an excess flow Notes


demand by holding less of a good than they would like (" unintended" Existence theorems of the general nature ofT.2.2 were first proved by
dishoarding), while others hold more of a good than they would like Wald [1933-34, 1934-35]; for systematic expositions of severa! inter-
and so prevent what otherwise would be a flow excess supply related results, see Wald [1936, 1951]. Wald assumed demand func-
(unintended hoarding). Evidently, in this view we may have flow tions arising from the household sector together with Cassel's system of
equilibrium and stock disequilibrium. But the notion of an fixed coefficient relations for production (see Section 1.5). Iffactors are
identified with final goods so that the production of final good i requires
equilibrium has clearly been widened to include situations in which one unit of factor i and nothing else, then Wald's result is the same as
agents themselves are not in equilibrium in the sense that they do not T.2.2, though his assumptions were considerably stronger; see Wald
carry out the transactions most satisfactory to themselves at the [1951' pp. 372-373].
ruling prices. McKenzie [1954] established an existence theorem that is more
It is not at all clear that the nomenclature of the literature is a general than Wald's with regard to production assumptions; however,
if specialized to the case of exchange, it is identical to Wald's.
good one, simply because it is not helpful to have the same name to Both Wald and McKenzie assumed that the demand for a free good
describe quite different situations. In any case, in this volume the was infinite, more precisely that z,(pv)-->- + ctJ for any sequence {pv} for
distinction between stock and flow equilibrium will become relevant which pv-->- p0 , where pp = O. As the discussion in Section 2.8 shows,
only in the analysis of what, in our d~finition, are disequilibrium this assumption is not compatible, in general, with utility maximization.
situations. Equilibrium in a mo del of no joint production, as discussed in Section
2.11, was discussed extensively by Leontief [1941] for the special case
Connected with the distinction we have been discussing is the in which there are fixed coefficients for the production of each com-
device of "period analysis." This can be helpful in overcoming modity. The crucial role of the productivity assumption, A.2.12(b) in
some of the conceptual problems raised by continuous time, but it our notation, was first stressed by Hawkins and Simon [1949]. The
can also be misleading. For instance, Swedish authors at one time generalization of these results to the case of variable coefficients is due
found it helpful to define the length of the period by the time interval independently to Georgescu-Roegen [1951] and Samuelson [1951].
over which prices could be taken as fixed. Starting with g~ven prices
at the beginning of the period, a flow equilibrium over the period,
then, would involve stock disequilibrium at the end of the period
unless the economy was in full equilibrium. They then traced the
economy from period to period by using certain rules for changing
prices. In an economy with many agents, however, it seems
unnatural to suppose that they all not only adjust their preferred
action at discrete intervals, but they do so at the same moment. If
that is not so, then such adjustments will be taking place more or
less continuously. To this must be added the fact that period
analysis leads to a formulation in terms of "difference equations,"
which are capable of producing motions for the system that are not
possible if the formulation is in terms of differential equations, so
that what started as an aid to visualization may finish by being
pretty misleading. In any event, it is noticeable that the discus-
sion of this paragraph quite naturally. ran in terms of what, from
the agents' point of view, are plainly disequilibrium processes and
confirms the view that these matters are best treated when we come
to consider such processes.

J'
Chapter Three PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 53

inputs, the corresponding outputs could be produced. Thus, the


PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE production possibility set is a description of the state of the firm's
BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY knowledge about the possibilities of transforming commodities.
For simplicity in following the discussion in this and the following
two chapters, it will be convenient to assume that production and all
Specz'alizing is necessary to ejjiciency, other economic activity is timeless; inputs and outputs are con-
which is a form of altruism, and temporaneous, and no consideration is given to the future in any-
however narrow the specialist becomes, one's decisions. It should be made clear, however, that time can be
we ought to pardon him if he does
introduced into the system by a mere reinterpretation ofthe symbols,
good work.
so that the model of general competitive equilibrium has a broad
-B. Russell, The Autobiography of
application.
Bertrand Russell*
The distinction between pure technological possibility and feasi-
bility, that is, possibility plus the availability of resources, cannot
1. General Principies and lllustrative Examples always be maintained strictly. We will find it convenient to con-
The three basic elements of the theory of production under sider sorne commodities as being private to a firm or group of firms
competitive conditions are its organization through separate firms, (e.g., managerial ability or, in the case of foreign trade, domestic
the delimitation of the production possibilities of each firm, and the factor supplies). Theq__,the following two descriptions of reality are
choice among these possibilities by the principie of profit maximiza- equivalent:
tion at given prices. In this section, we will discuss these points (1) including the private commodities with all others among
informally and comment on sorne revisions and extensions of the the components of the activity vectors and adding to the
simple concepts of supply and demand functions made necessary by system a statement prohibiting the f!ow of these com-
a careful analysis. By illustrations, we will show especially the modities out of the firm or group of firms;
possible importance of multi-valued supply and demand relations. (2) deleting the private commodities from the activity vectors
First, we will consider the description of a firm's production and considering among the set of possible vectors in the
possibilities. In general, a firm will use many inputs to produce remaining components only those vectors whose demands
several outputs; there is no need to confine attention to the single- for the private commodities can be satisfied with the
product firm. Any possible state of production of the firm, then, is available supplies.
a statement that outputs of certain commodities in certain amounts
can be achieved by inputs of other commodities in other given Given a set of prices for all commodities, it is possible to calcula te
amounts. We will agree as a convention that positive quantities for each activity its profit, the excess of the values of its outputs o ver
will represent outputs and negative quantities inputs. Any such the val u e of its inputs; for sorne activities, of cotll'Se, profit m ay be
specification of possible relations between inputs and outputs will be negative. The assumptions of perfect competition imply that, at any
termed an activity; the set of all activities available to the firm will be set of prices regarded as given to it, each firm chooses an activity
called its production possibility S(( t. that yields it at least as much profit as any other possible.
The word "possible" in the preceding paragraph refers to tech- Sorne of the possible complexities in a general and rigorous theory
nological knowledge, not to availability of resources; to say that an of production decisions can best be brought out through examples.
activity is possible means only that if the firm possessed the specified We start with perhaps the simplest possible assumption about
possible activities: There is one output that is proportional to the
* Little, Brown and Co., Boston, 1957, p. 246. quantity of the one input.

52
Chapter Three PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 53

inputs, the corresponding outputs could be produced. Thus, the


PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE production possibility set is a description of the state of the firm's
BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY knowledge about the possibilities of transforming commodities.
For simplicity in following the discussion in this and the following
two chapters, it will be convenient to assume that production and all
Specz'alizing is necessary to ejjiciency, other economic activity is timeless; inputs and outputs are con-
which is a form of altruism, and temporaneous, and no consideration is given to the future in any-
however narrow the specialist becomes, one's decisions. It should be made clear, however, that time can be
we ought to pardon him if he does
introduced into the system by a mere reinterpretation ofthe symbols,
good work.
so that the model of general competitive equilibrium has a broad
-B. Russell, The Autobiography of
application.
Bertrand Russell*
The distinction between pure technological possibility and feasi-
bility, that is, possibility plus the availability of resources, cannot
1. General Principies and lllustrative Examples always be maintained strictly. We will find it convenient to con-
The three basic elements of the theory of production under sider sorne commodities as being private to a firm or group of firms
competitive conditions are its organization through separate firms, (e.g., managerial ability or, in the case of foreign trade, domestic
the delimitation of the production possibilities of each firm, and the factor supplies). Theq__,the following two descriptions of reality are
choice among these possibilities by the principie of profit maximiza- equivalent:
tion at given prices. In this section, we will discuss these points (1) including the private commodities with all others among
informally and comment on sorne revisions and extensions of the the components of the activity vectors and adding to the
simple concepts of supply and demand functions made necessary by system a statement prohibiting the f!ow of these com-
a careful analysis. By illustrations, we will show especially the modities out of the firm or group of firms;
possible importance of multi-valued supply and demand relations. (2) deleting the private commodities from the activity vectors
First, we will consider the description of a firm's production and considering among the set of possible vectors in the
possibilities. In general, a firm will use many inputs to produce remaining components only those vectors whose demands
several outputs; there is no need to confine attention to the single- for the private commodities can be satisfied with the
product firm. Any possible state of production of the firm, then, is available supplies.
a statement that outputs of certain commodities in certain amounts
can be achieved by inputs of other commodities in other given Given a set of prices for all commodities, it is possible to calcula te
amounts. We will agree as a convention that positive quantities for each activity its profit, the excess of the values of its outputs o ver
will represent outputs and negative quantities inputs. Any such the val u e of its inputs; for sorne activities, of cotll'Se, profit m ay be
specification of possible relations between inputs and outputs will be negative. The assumptions of perfect competition imply that, at any
termed an activity; the set of all activities available to the firm will be set of prices regarded as given to it, each firm chooses an activity
called its production possibility S(( t. that yields it at least as much profit as any other possible.
The word "possible" in the preceding paragraph refers to tech- Sorne of the possible complexities in a general and rigorous theory
nological knowledge, not to availability of resources; to say that an of production decisions can best be brought out through examples.
activity is possible means only that if the firm possessed the specified We start with perhaps the simplest possible assumption about
possible activities: There is one output that is proportional to the
* Little, Brown and Co., Boston, 1957, p. 246. quantity of the one input.

52
~ '
'

54 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 55

In accordance with our notational principies, we take the input prolonged) is the set of possible activities. For price vectors with
y 1 to be negative and the output y 2 to be positive; then we have slope less than. a, that is, making an obtuse angle with OA, profits
assumed that the activities are those of the form ca~ ~lways be mcreased by a small decrease in scale; hence only the
ongm can be optimal. A price vector with slope a is perpendicular
(1) to OA everywhere; hence no change in scale will change profits so
th.at every point of OA is profit maximizing. Finally, a price ve~tor
where a is sorne positive constant. If p 1 and p 2 are the prices of
WI~h a s~ope grea_t~r than a, making an acute angle with OA at any
input and output, respectively, then the profit is
pomt, ywlds additwnal profits for any .increase in scale and so can
P1Y1 + P2Y2 = (p2 - ap1)Y2' define no profit-maximizing activity. In Figure 3-1 b, the supply
curve for the product implied by Figure 3-Ia is presented. The
as seen by substituting from (1). Now the firm's profit-maximizing quantity supplied depends, of course, only on the price ratio; it is
decision can easily be calculated. If p 2 < ap 1, then profits are zero for price ratios less than a, it can be any value whatever indif-
negative if y 2 > O and O if y 2 = O; thus, the profit-maximizing ferently at a, and it is undefined above a.
decision is to set Y2 = O (and, from (1), also set y 1 = 0), in other This trivial case has been examined in such detail to bring out
words, not to engage in production at all. If p 2 = ap1, a more three points, stated in increasing order of importance: For sorne
curious situation arises; profits are O no matter what level is chosen price vectors, the firm may find it most profitable to engage in the
for y 2 Hence, any value of y 2 can be regarded as profit-maximizing,
activit~ ~f doin~ ~othing; for sorne price vectors, there is no profit-
provided that the appropriate value of y is chosen at the same time. maximizmg achvity; for sorne price vectors, there is a whole set of
Equivalently, we can say that any vector satisfying (1) is profit
~ctivities, each of which is profit maximizing, in the sense that there
maximizing. Finally, if p 2 > ap, an increase in y 2 always increases IS no other activity that yields a higher profit. Thus, for a general
profits. Strictly speaking, there is no profit-maximizing activity,
theor~, we must relax the assumptions of the last chapter, according
since for any pair (y 1 ,y 2 ) satisfying (1), there is another, that yields to wh1ch supply and demand are both defined and single valued for
higher profits. In ordinary terms, the supply and demand functions each price vector.
must be regarded as undefined in this case. Sorne further examples will be useful. Suppose there are two
We note that the classification of cases depended only on the types of activity, of which one is more efficient in the simple sense
price ratio, p 2 fp. The case just studied is represented graphically of more output per unit of input, but can be carried out to a limited
in Figure 3-1. In Figure 3-1a, the line OA (assumed indefinitely scale, beyond which a less efficient type of activity must be used.
(The more efficient activity may require sorne input prvate to the
Output Output firm and limited in quantity.) The case is represented in Figure
3-2.
Clearly, for a price vector with slope less than a, the maximum
profit again is zero, obtainable only at the origin. When the slope
A
equals. a, all activities on the line OA yield equal (zero) profit, while
the_ ~r~ce vec~or makes an obtuse angle with all points representing
actlvities at h1gher scales, which therefore cannot be optimal, so that
the profit-maximizing activities are those on OA. If the slope Iies
a
between a and b, the profit must be increasing with scale up to A
------....::!0> I L . - - - Input an~ decreasing thereafter; hence the profit-maximizing point is
(a) (b)
umquely A as the output-input price ratio increases from a to b
supply of the output anci demand for the input are completely price~
Figure 3-1
~ '
'

54 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 55

In accordance with our notational principies, we take the input prolonged) is the set of possible activities. For price vectors with
y 1 to be negative and the output y 2 to be positive; then we have slope less than. a, that is, making an obtuse angle with OA, profits
assumed that the activities are those of the form ca~ ~lways be mcreased by a small decrease in scale; hence only the
ongm can be optimal. A price vector with slope a is perpendicular
(1) to OA everywhere; hence no change in scale will change profits so
th.at every point of OA is profit maximizing. Finally, a price ve~tor
where a is sorne positive constant. If p 1 and p 2 are the prices of
WI~h a s~ope grea_t~r than a, making an acute angle with OA at any
input and output, respectively, then the profit is
pomt, ywlds additwnal profits for any .increase in scale and so can
P1Y1 + P2Y2 = (p2 - ap1)Y2' define no profit-maximizing activity. In Figure 3-1 b, the supply
curve for the product implied by Figure 3-Ia is presented. The
as seen by substituting from (1). Now the firm's profit-maximizing quantity supplied depends, of course, only on the price ratio; it is
decision can easily be calculated. If p 2 < ap 1, then profits are zero for price ratios less than a, it can be any value whatever indif-
negative if y 2 > O and O if y 2 = O; thus, the profit-maximizing ferently at a, and it is undefined above a.
decision is to set Y2 = O (and, from (1), also set y 1 = 0), in other This trivial case has been examined in such detail to bring out
words, not to engage in production at all. If p 2 = ap1, a more three points, stated in increasing order of importance: For sorne
curious situation arises; profits are O no matter what level is chosen price vectors, the firm may find it most profitable to engage in the
for y 2 Hence, any value of y 2 can be regarded as profit-maximizing,
activit~ ~f doin~ ~othing; for sorne price vectors, there is no profit-
provided that the appropriate value of y is chosen at the same time. maximizmg achvity; for sorne price vectors, there is a whole set of
Equivalently, we can say that any vector satisfying (1) is profit
~ctivities, each of which is profit maximizing, in the sense that there
maximizing. Finally, if p 2 > ap, an increase in y 2 always increases IS no other activity that yields a higher profit. Thus, for a general
profits. Strictly speaking, there is no profit-maximizing activity,
theor~, we must relax the assumptions of the last chapter, according
since for any pair (y 1 ,y 2 ) satisfying (1), there is another, that yields to wh1ch supply and demand are both defined and single valued for
higher profits. In ordinary terms, the supply and demand functions each price vector.
must be regarded as undefined in this case. Sorne further examples will be useful. Suppose there are two
We note that the classification of cases depended only on the types of activity, of which one is more efficient in the simple sense
price ratio, p 2 fp. The case just studied is represented graphically of more output per unit of input, but can be carried out to a limited
in Figure 3-1. In Figure 3-1a, the line OA (assumed indefinitely scale, beyond which a less efficient type of activity must be used.
(The more efficient activity may require sorne input prvate to the
Output Output firm and limited in quantity.) The case is represented in Figure
3-2.
Clearly, for a price vector with slope less than a, the maximum
profit again is zero, obtainable only at the origin. When the slope
A
equals. a, all activities on the line OA yield equal (zero) profit, while
the_ ~r~ce vec~or makes an obtuse angle with all points representing
actlvities at h1gher scales, which therefore cannot be optimal, so that
the profit-maximizing activities are those on OA. If the slope Iies
a
between a and b, the profit must be increasing with scale up to A
------....::!0> I L . - - - Input an~ decreasing thereafter; hence the profit-maximizing point is
(a) (b)
umquely A as the output-input price ratio increases from a to b
supply of the output anci demand for the input are completely price~
Figure 3-1
56 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 57
!;,;,

Output
11:

J.
Output Output

b ~---- ............... -..........


Output

8
Input L -_ __.__ _--+--P2 / ' ,,
a b -----------~'-"-a'~- Input
(b) O B a
(a) (b)
Figure 3-2
Figure 3-3
inelastic in this interval. When the price ratio is b, all points from
A on are equally profitable, since the price vector is perpendicular to
For a final example of considerable general interest, we show in
all ofthem. The amount ofprofit (divided by the price ofthe input)
Figures 3-4a and 3-4b a case of increasing returns followed by
is represented by the intersection B of the perpendicular to the price
diminishing returns. Consider first any price vector with slope less
vector at any given activity leve! with the input axis; therefore, the
than a. It may make an obtuse angle with all possible vectors, so
profit is positive as soon as the price ratio rises above a. For price
that none are optimal. Alternatively, it may be the perpendicular
ratios above b, the profit-maximizing activity is undefined again,
to sorne possible activity, such as B; but then the profit, measured by
since any increase in scale is profitable.
C, is negative, so that B is inferior to the origin. The output-input
This is the first example of diminishing retums to scale. The new
price ratio' a is the smallest value that is perpendicular to the curve
feature is the possibility of positive profits, which can be obtained
of possible production vectors at a point A that yields a zero
whenever the price ratio exceeds a.
profit at the ratio a. Hence, for that ratio, A and O both represent
In Figures 3-3a and 3-3b, we exhibit continuously diminishing
profit-maximizing activities; for higher values of a, the supply curve
returns to scale. In this case, any given price vector with slope
between a and b does define a unique profit~maximizing activity,
since the price vector can be perpendicular to only one point. Consider, for examples, the following possible input-output relations (recall
Profits are necessarily positive for price ratios greater than a, since that Y1 :S: O):
the intercept of the perpendicular to the price vector (which is also Yo = 1 - Yl - e"1 (a)
the tangent to the production possibility curve) clearly cuts the input (b)
axis to the right of the origin, as at B. As the price ratio approaches
b, the optimum scale approaches infinity; for price ratios at or above With p 1 fixed at 1, the optimum scale of production in both cases approaches
infinity (Yl-+ -oo, y 2 -+ +oo) as J12 approaches 1, but the profits at the
b, the profit-maximizing activity is undefined. 1 optimum leve! approach 1 for (a) and +oo for (b). Note al~o that when P2
1
rises beyond 1, we can achieve infinite profit even in case <.a), m the sense that
Note that the leve] of maximum profits at any given price vector may a profit as large as prescribed can be obtained by a suffic1ently large scale of
approach either a finite or an infinite limit as the price ratio approaches b. operations.
56 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 57
!;,;,

Output
11:

J.
Output Output

b ~---- ............... -..........


Output

8
Input L -_ __.__ _--+--P2 / ' ,,
a b -----------~'-"-a'~- Input
(b) O B a
(a) (b)
Figure 3-2
Figure 3-3
inelastic in this interval. When the price ratio is b, all points from
A on are equally profitable, since the price vector is perpendicular to
For a final example of considerable general interest, we show in
all ofthem. The amount ofprofit (divided by the price ofthe input)
Figures 3-4a and 3-4b a case of increasing returns followed by
is represented by the intersection B of the perpendicular to the price
diminishing returns. Consider first any price vector with slope less
vector at any given activity leve! with the input axis; therefore, the
than a. It may make an obtuse angle with all possible vectors, so
profit is positive as soon as the price ratio rises above a. For price
that none are optimal. Alternatively, it may be the perpendicular
ratios above b, the profit-maximizing activity is undefined again,
to sorne possible activity, such as B; but then the profit, measured by
since any increase in scale is profitable.
C, is negative, so that B is inferior to the origin. The output-input
This is the first example of diminishing retums to scale. The new
price ratio' a is the smallest value that is perpendicular to the curve
feature is the possibility of positive profits, which can be obtained
of possible production vectors at a point A that yields a zero
whenever the price ratio exceeds a.
profit at the ratio a. Hence, for that ratio, A and O both represent
In Figures 3-3a and 3-3b, we exhibit continuously diminishing
profit-maximizing activities; for higher values of a, the supply curve
returns to scale. In this case, any given price vector with slope
between a and b does define a unique profit~maximizing activity,
since the price vector can be perpendicular to only one point. Consider, for examples, the following possible input-output relations (recall
Profits are necessarily positive for price ratios greater than a, since that Y1 :S: O):
the intercept of the perpendicular to the price vector (which is also Yo = 1 - Yl - e"1 (a)
the tangent to the production possibility curve) clearly cuts the input (b)
axis to the right of the origin, as at B. As the price ratio approaches
b, the optimum scale approaches infinity; for price ratios at or above With p 1 fixed at 1, the optimum scale of production in both cases approaches
infinity (Yl-+ -oo, y 2 -+ +oo) as J12 approaches 1, but the profits at the
b, the profit-maximizing activity is undefined. 1 optimum leve! approach 1 for (a) and +oo for (b). Note al~o that when P2
1
rises beyond 1, we can achieve infinite profit even in case <.a), m the sense that
Note that the leve] of maximum profits at any given price vector may a profit as large as prescribed can be obtained by a suffic1ently large scale of
approach either a finite or an infinite limit as the price ratio approaches b. operations.
58 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 59

follows as in Figure 3-3. We note again that the profit-maximizing If at a given set of prices one or more of the firms has more than
activity is multi-valued at the price ratio a. one set of profit-maximizing activities, then correspondingly the
Another way of looking at this case is illuminating. Imagine the aggregate supply or demand must be niulti-valued; any aggregate
original production possibility curve modified by replacing the activity vector that can be forrned by choosing a profit-rnaxirnizing
curved section OA by the straight line OA. The case is now exactly vector for each firm and adding thern up is an aggregate supply
like that of Figure 3-2. The s11pply curves are also the same, except vector for that set of prices.
that at the price ratio a the profit-maximizing set of activities con- Finally, we note that if ata given set ofprices the profit-maxirnizing
tains just two points in Figure 3-4, while in Figure 3-2 it contains the vector is undefined for sorne firrn, the aggregate supply vector must
same two points plus all those lying between them. Thus the modi- also be regarded as undefined.
fied production possibility curve, obtained by straightening out the
hollows, yields a supply curve that is a smoothed version of the
2. Production Possibility Sets of Individual Firms
original. This smoothing process will be important in discussing
the extent to which the existence of general equilibrium is affected by DEFiNITION l. The production possibility set for firm J, denoted by
the presence of increasing returns (see Chapter 7). Y1 , is the set of activity vectors possible to the firrn.
Finally, we mention briefty the aggregation of the profit-maxi-
The components of an activity vector include all cornmodities;
mizing decisions of individual firms. First, consider for each firm a
positive cornponents refer to outp\lt, negative ones to inputs, and
single chosen activity vector. Because ofthe convention about signs
zeros to cornrnodities neither purchased nor sold by the firm. An
-positive for outputs and negative for inputs-the net output of any
elernent of Y1 will usually be denoted by y1 .
commodity by the productive sector can be obtained by simple
First we introduce two trivial assurnptions about production
addition ofthe outputs ofthe individual firms; the amount produced
possibilities. The first states that it is always possible for the firm
by one firm and used by another for further production simply
to engage in no activity.
cancels out. The net aggregate "output" will turn 'out to be
1!

'1 negative for sorne commodities; these are net inputs needed from the ASSUMPTION l. 0 E Y1 .
: 1

household sector, such as labor services.


The second is more of a convention than an assurnption.
AssuMPTION 2. Y 1 is closed.

' '' \
Output Output That is, if there are technologically possible activities arbitrarily
close toa given activity, then we include the given activity arnong the
'A
\
possible ones. Clearly, little would be lost by sacrificing this
assurnption; for example, instead of there being a profit-maxirnizing
activity for sorne set of prices, there would be a sequenc of possible
/ activities approaching a given vector such that the profit derived
frorn any given activity is less than that derived from any rnernber
of the sequence beginning sufticiently far out.
A more serious restriction to be irnposed on the production
possibility sets of individual firrns is that they are convex sets. The
1---+a------p2/p
property of convexity can be derived from two, more elernentary
(a) (b)
hypotheses: divisibility and additivity. Production is said to be
Figure 3-4 divisible if, whenever y is an activity, .\y is an activity for O s >. s l.
58 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 59

follows as in Figure 3-3. We note again that the profit-maximizing If at a given set of prices one or more of the firms has more than
activity is multi-valued at the price ratio a. one set of profit-maximizing activities, then correspondingly the
Another way of looking at this case is illuminating. Imagine the aggregate supply or demand must be niulti-valued; any aggregate
original production possibility curve modified by replacing the activity vector that can be forrned by choosing a profit-rnaxirnizing
curved section OA by the straight line OA. The case is now exactly vector for each firm and adding thern up is an aggregate supply
like that of Figure 3-2. The s11pply curves are also the same, except vector for that set of prices.
that at the price ratio a the profit-maximizing set of activities con- Finally, we note that if ata given set ofprices the profit-maxirnizing
tains just two points in Figure 3-4, while in Figure 3-2 it contains the vector is undefined for sorne firrn, the aggregate supply vector must
same two points plus all those lying between them. Thus the modi- also be regarded as undefined.
fied production possibility curve, obtained by straightening out the
hollows, yields a supply curve that is a smoothed version of the
2. Production Possibility Sets of Individual Firms
original. This smoothing process will be important in discussing
the extent to which the existence of general equilibrium is affected by DEFiNITION l. The production possibility set for firm J, denoted by
the presence of increasing returns (see Chapter 7). Y1 , is the set of activity vectors possible to the firrn.
Finally, we mention briefty the aggregation of the profit-maxi-
The components of an activity vector include all cornmodities;
mizing decisions of individual firms. First, consider for each firm a
positive cornponents refer to outp\lt, negative ones to inputs, and
single chosen activity vector. Because ofthe convention about signs
zeros to cornrnodities neither purchased nor sold by the firm. An
-positive for outputs and negative for inputs-the net output of any
elernent of Y1 will usually be denoted by y1 .
commodity by the productive sector can be obtained by simple
First we introduce two trivial assurnptions about production
addition ofthe outputs ofthe individual firms; the amount produced
possibilities. The first states that it is always possible for the firm
by one firm and used by another for further production simply
to engage in no activity.
cancels out. The net aggregate "output" will turn 'out to be
1!

'1 negative for sorne commodities; these are net inputs needed from the ASSUMPTION l. 0 E Y1 .
: 1

household sector, such as labor services.


The second is more of a convention than an assurnption.
AssuMPTION 2. Y 1 is closed.

' '' \
Output Output That is, if there are technologically possible activities arbitrarily
close toa given activity, then we include the given activity arnong the
'A
\
possible ones. Clearly, little would be lost by sacrificing this
assurnption; for example, instead of there being a profit-maxirnizing
activity for sorne set of prices, there would be a sequenc of possible
/ activities approaching a given vector such that the profit derived
frorn any given activity is less than that derived from any rnernber
of the sequence beginning sufticiently far out.
A more serious restriction to be irnposed on the production
possibility sets of individual firrns is that they are convex sets. The
1---+a------p2/p
property of convexity can be derived from two, more elernentary
(a) (b)
hypotheses: divisibility and additivity. Production is said to be
Figure 3-4 divisible if, whenever y is an activity, .\y is an activity for O s >. s l.
60 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 61

Production is said to be additive if, whenever y1 and y 2 are activities, as one of indivisibility; given the geometric shape of the container,
y1 + y 2 is an activity. In this notation, production exhibits constant containers of different size should be regarded as different com-
returns to sea/e if, whenever y is an activity, Ay is an activity for all modities, each of which comes only in integer amounts. (This case
A ;::: O. The mathematical equivalent to the economic property of is possibly of wide economic importance. To a very considerable
constant returns to scale is that of being a cone: a set of vectors that extent, the manufacturing of commodities in continuous-process
contains Ax for all A ;::: O if it contains x. industries, such as chemicals, is the handling of materials in a
sequence of containers. It has been observed empirically that the
LEMMA l. If production is divisible and additive, then thc produc- cost of a chemical plant of fixed type rises less than proportionately
tion possibility set is convex and exhibits constant returns to scale, to the capacity and indeed roughly as the 0.6 power.)
that is, it is a convex cone. Even if the divisibility of commodities is accepted, at least as an
Proof. If y1 and y2 are activities, then, by divisibility, Ay 1 and approximation, that of divisibility of production activities does not
(1 - A)y are activities, for O :::; A :::; 1, and Ay 1 + (1 - A)y 2 is an
2 follow as a logical truth. Rather t is an empirical generalization
activity, by additivity, demonstrating convexity. that, for the great majority of ordinary production processes, a
uniform reduction in scale preserves feasibility.
Let y be an activity, A ;::: O. Let n be the largest integer not The assumption of additivity, on the other hand, can always be
exceeding A, v = A - n. Then O :::; v < 1, and vy is an activity by defended and indeed made essentially tautologous. The usual
.. 'b'l'
d lVISl 1 Ity. Let y1 = y ('1 = 1, ... , n) , yn+l = vy. Th en y1 IS
. an
criticism of additivity is that if all inputs are doubled, it still may not
activity (i = 1, .... , n + 1), and be possible to double outputs because of limiting conditions such as
n+l inability to manage larger organizations. This means merely that
2
i= 1
yi =Ay. sorne relevant input has been omitted. Jf all relevant inputs are
listed, there is no reason why two activities cannot both be carried
From additivity it follows by induction that Ay is an activity. on if their inputs are available.
The realism ofthe two hypotheses may be discussed briefly. First, Sorne care must be taken, however, in the interpretation of the
consider divisibility, to which the more serious objections can be additivity assumption in the context of economic equilibrium. As
raised. In principie, we must distinguish between divisibility of already remarked, not all inputs are, in fact, marketed. For the
commodities and divisibility of activities. There are many com- moment, let y be a possible production vector in which all com-
modities (water, butter) that come in clearly divisible form and sorne modities, marketed or not, are included as components, and Jet Y
(sugar, sand) for which the indivisible units are so small that the be the set of possible production vectors (for a particular firm). If
assumption of divisibility is clearly an excellent approximation. On divisibility and additivity are assumed, then Y is a convex cone.
the other hand, there are many commodities, particularly instru- Suppose that sorne of the components are marketed, while others are
ments of production (shovels, stamping mills) that come in indi- prvate to the firm. For any vector y, Jet yM and yP be the vectors
visible units. Certainly, if commodities are indivisible, activities formed by considering only the marketed and private components,
involving them cannot be divisible. lf it is possible to use one respectively. For the firm, assume that the prvate components are
shovel, it does not follow that there is any process in which half a given: yP = yP. From the viewpoint of the study of markets, only
shovel can be used. A more sophisticated example is that of storage the vector y M is relevant; that is, we are interested in the set of
containers. The usefulness of a storage container is proportional vectors YM = {yM 1 (yM,V) E Y}. It is trivial to observe that the
to the surface area (that is, if the thickness of the walls is constant; convexity of Y implies the convexity of YM, but YM need not exhibit
it may have to increase somewhat with volume to resist the pressure constant returns to scale.
of the contents). Therefore, the input is proportional to the two- From this point on, suppose that the components of y are all
thirds power of the output. This case can be regarded formally marketed. Then the discussion justifies the tentative assumption:
60 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 61

Production is said to be additive if, whenever y1 and y 2 are activities, as one of indivisibility; given the geometric shape of the container,
y1 + y 2 is an activity. In this notation, production exhibits constant containers of different size should be regarded as different com-
returns to sea/e if, whenever y is an activity, Ay is an activity for all modities, each of which comes only in integer amounts. (This case
A ;::: O. The mathematical equivalent to the economic property of is possibly of wide economic importance. To a very considerable
constant returns to scale is that of being a cone: a set of vectors that extent, the manufacturing of commodities in continuous-process
contains Ax for all A ;::: O if it contains x. industries, such as chemicals, is the handling of materials in a
sequence of containers. It has been observed empirically that the
LEMMA l. If production is divisible and additive, then thc produc- cost of a chemical plant of fixed type rises less than proportionately
tion possibility set is convex and exhibits constant returns to scale, to the capacity and indeed roughly as the 0.6 power.)
that is, it is a convex cone. Even if the divisibility of commodities is accepted, at least as an
Proof. If y1 and y2 are activities, then, by divisibility, Ay 1 and approximation, that of divisibility of production activities does not
(1 - A)y are activities, for O :::; A :::; 1, and Ay 1 + (1 - A)y 2 is an
2 follow as a logical truth. Rather t is an empirical generalization
activity, by additivity, demonstrating convexity. that, for the great majority of ordinary production processes, a
uniform reduction in scale preserves feasibility.
Let y be an activity, A ;::: O. Let n be the largest integer not The assumption of additivity, on the other hand, can always be
exceeding A, v = A - n. Then O :::; v < 1, and vy is an activity by defended and indeed made essentially tautologous. The usual
.. 'b'l'
d lVISl 1 Ity. Let y1 = y ('1 = 1, ... , n) , yn+l = vy. Th en y1 IS
. an
criticism of additivity is that if all inputs are doubled, it still may not
activity (i = 1, .... , n + 1), and be possible to double outputs because of limiting conditions such as
n+l inability to manage larger organizations. This means merely that
2
i= 1
yi =Ay. sorne relevant input has been omitted. Jf all relevant inputs are
listed, there is no reason why two activities cannot both be carried
From additivity it follows by induction that Ay is an activity. on if their inputs are available.
The realism ofthe two hypotheses may be discussed briefly. First, Sorne care must be taken, however, in the interpretation of the
consider divisibility, to which the more serious objections can be additivity assumption in the context of economic equilibrium. As
raised. In principie, we must distinguish between divisibility of already remarked, not all inputs are, in fact, marketed. For the
commodities and divisibility of activities. There are many com- moment, let y be a possible production vector in which all com-
modities (water, butter) that come in clearly divisible form and sorne modities, marketed or not, are included as components, and Jet Y
(sugar, sand) for which the indivisible units are so small that the be the set of possible production vectors (for a particular firm). If
assumption of divisibility is clearly an excellent approximation. On divisibility and additivity are assumed, then Y is a convex cone.
the other hand, there are many commodities, particularly instru- Suppose that sorne of the components are marketed, while others are
ments of production (shovels, stamping mills) that come in indi- prvate to the firm. For any vector y, Jet yM and yP be the vectors
visible units. Certainly, if commodities are indivisible, activities formed by considering only the marketed and private components,
involving them cannot be divisible. lf it is possible to use one respectively. For the firm, assume that the prvate components are
shovel, it does not follow that there is any process in which half a given: yP = yP. From the viewpoint of the study of markets, only
shovel can be used. A more sophisticated example is that of storage the vector y M is relevant; that is, we are interested in the set of
containers. The usefulness of a storage container is proportional vectors YM = {yM 1 (yM,V) E Y}. It is trivial to observe that the
to the surface area (that is, if the thickness of the walls is constant; convexity of Y implies the convexity of YM, but YM need not exhibit
it may have to increase somewhat with volume to resist the pressure constant returns to scale.
of the contents). Therefore, the input is proportional to the two- From this point on, suppose that the components of y are all
thirds power of the output. This case can be regarded formally marketed. Then the discussion justifies the tentative assumption:
62 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS ANO THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 63

ASSUMPTION 3. Y is convex. Remark. The firms must be assumed distinct, because we are, in
According to the previous argument, non-convexity arises only effect, assuming additivity across firms, but not necessarily across
because of indivisibility of commodities. Clearly, its economic processes within a firm. It is the assumption of possible limitational
significance is relatively less when the number of units is large. factors to the firm that gives it its individuality.
Thus, the difference between one stamping mill and none is impor- We will also refer to the set of possible production allocations that
tant, but if the relevant choice is between 100 and 101 shovels, the define the production vector for each firm. This is the Cartesian
assumption of divisibility is unlikely to be seriously misleading. pr,oduct of the production possibility sets for the individual firms.
The effects of non-convexity on the existence of equilibrium will be
reconsidered along these lines in Chapter 7. DEFINITION 3. qy = X Y 1 = {y, ... , YF 1 Yr E Y, allf}
f
where F is the number of firms. Note that
3. Production Possibility Set of the Entire Economy
LYr
f
The entire production side of the economy is assumed composed
of a finite number of (potential or actual) firms. The total produc- is a linear mapping of the set of possible production allocations into
tion of the economy is the sum of the productions of the individual commodity space.
firms. Note that if a commodity is an input to one firm and an THEOREM l. O E qy; qy is el o sed and convex.
output from another, the net output for society is the difference
This theorem follows trivially from A.3.1-A.3.3.
between the two. If y1 is the production vector for firm f, then
Corollary l. O E Y; Y is convex.
Y= LYr
f Proof From T.3.1, since Y is the image of qy under the linear
is the production vector for society. mapping
Let Y be the social production possibility set. Then, formally, L Yr.
f

DEFINITION 2. Y= {y = t Yr 1 Yr E Y, allf} = tY 1.
it does not follow from A.3.1-A.3.3 alone that Y is closed; this
property requires A.3.4 below.
A production vector may be regarded as possible for a set of firms If Y1 is unbounded, then at certain p it may be that the firm would
if it is the sum of vectors, each possible for a different firm of the set. ljke to produce on an infinitely large scale. This possibility, as such,
Then, from D.3.2 and A.3.1, it is easy to see that any production .does not make it impossible to conduct an analysis of market
vector possible for a set of firms is possible for society as a whole equilibrium with positive prices; although the firm is taken to suppose
(i.e., for the set of all firms). Let ft. ... ,j[( be distinct firms, and that it can sell and bu y whatever quantities it likes at the going prices,
suppose the economy, in fact, may be incapable of producing outputs and
using inputs in unlimited amounts. Indeed, if we are interested in.
Yr~E Yh (k= 1, ... ,K). a world of scarcity, we ought to exclude the possibility. We will
Set Yr =O ifjis distinct from any ofthe firms.t;,; by A.3.1, Yr E Y1 , examine a fairly weak assumption that ensures this.
allf By D.3.2, AssuMPTION 4. If y E qy and Yr ::::: O, then y = O.
f
LYh = LYrE Y. A.3.4 defines the problem of scarcity when
k f

LEMMA 2. For any set of distinct firms, ft. ... , ;" Te Y1 e Y.


~
LYr >O;
f
62 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS ANO THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 63

ASSUMPTION 3. Y is convex. Remark. The firms must be assumed distinct, because we are, in
According to the previous argument, non-convexity arises only effect, assuming additivity across firms, but not necessarily across
because of indivisibility of commodities. Clearly, its economic processes within a firm. It is the assumption of possible limitational
significance is relatively less when the number of units is large. factors to the firm that gives it its individuality.
Thus, the difference between one stamping mill and none is impor- We will also refer to the set of possible production allocations that
tant, but if the relevant choice is between 100 and 101 shovels, the define the production vector for each firm. This is the Cartesian
assumption of divisibility is unlikely to be seriously misleading. pr,oduct of the production possibility sets for the individual firms.
The effects of non-convexity on the existence of equilibrium will be
reconsidered along these lines in Chapter 7. DEFINITION 3. qy = X Y 1 = {y, ... , YF 1 Yr E Y, allf}
f
where F is the number of firms. Note that
3. Production Possibility Set of the Entire Economy
LYr
f
The entire production side of the economy is assumed composed
of a finite number of (potential or actual) firms. The total produc- is a linear mapping of the set of possible production allocations into
tion of the economy is the sum of the productions of the individual commodity space.
firms. Note that if a commodity is an input to one firm and an THEOREM l. O E qy; qy is el o sed and convex.
output from another, the net output for society is the difference
This theorem follows trivially from A.3.1-A.3.3.
between the two. If y1 is the production vector for firm f, then
Corollary l. O E Y; Y is convex.
Y= LYr
f Proof From T.3.1, since Y is the image of qy under the linear
is the production vector for society. mapping
Let Y be the social production possibility set. Then, formally, L Yr.
f

DEFINITION 2. Y= {y = t Yr 1 Yr E Y, allf} = tY 1.
it does not follow from A.3.1-A.3.3 alone that Y is closed; this
property requires A.3.4 below.
A production vector may be regarded as possible for a set of firms If Y1 is unbounded, then at certain p it may be that the firm would
if it is the sum of vectors, each possible for a different firm of the set. ljke to produce on an infinitely large scale. This possibility, as such,
Then, from D.3.2 and A.3.1, it is easy to see that any production .does not make it impossible to conduct an analysis of market
vector possible for a set of firms is possible for society as a whole equilibrium with positive prices; although the firm is taken to suppose
(i.e., for the set of all firms). Let ft. ... ,j[( be distinct firms, and that it can sell and bu y whatever quantities it likes at the going prices,
suppose the economy, in fact, may be incapable of producing outputs and
using inputs in unlimited amounts. Indeed, if we are interested in.
Yr~E Yh (k= 1, ... ,K). a world of scarcity, we ought to exclude the possibility. We will
Set Yr =O ifjis distinct from any ofthe firms.t;,; by A.3.1, Yr E Y1 , examine a fairly weak assumption that ensures this.
allf By D.3.2, AssuMPTION 4. If y E qy and Yr ::::: O, then y = O.
f
LYh = LYrE Y. A.3.4 defines the problem of scarcity when
k f

LEMMA 2. For any set of distinct firms, ft. ... , ;" Te Y1 e Y.


~
LYr >O;
f
64 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r
1

PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 65

it states that society cannot produce something for nothing by any The set of feasible production allocations is denoted by
organization of its entire production apparatus. It is important to
observe that this basic property of a social production possibility set
cannot be deduced from the corresponding properties of the firm
qp = @'n{y\,'f>r + x~o}
production possibility sets. If, in A.3.4, we let y1 = O for all firms
A feasible vector or allocation is one that society is capable of
but one, then we can deduce the corresponding statement for a firm;
carrying out, given the existing resources.
that is, it cannot be that y1 > O for any possible y1 E Y1 But the
For later reference, it is important to add one more assumption,
converse is not true; from this last statement, A.3.4 cannot be
namely that the resources and technology of society together permit
deduced. For example, if firm A produces 2 units of commodity 2
the supply of a positive amount of all goods.
from 1 unit of commodity 1 and firm B produces 2 units of com-
modity 1 from 1 unit of commodity 2, then neither firm has outputs AssuM:>TION 5. For sorne yE Y, x+ y O.
without inputs, but together they can have a net output of 1 unit of Note that if y is the social production possibility vector, y + x is the
each commodity with no net inputs. net supply, which must be non-negative for feasibility. To insist on
When the possibility of strict positivity means something like the following:
Divide the commodities into produced and non-produced. The
non-produced commodities all must be available initially in positive
A.3.4 says further that no non-trivial, socially possible production amounts (a commodity that is neither produced nor available
process can be completely undone by another. For the validity of initially can surely be disregarded). If the divisibility of production
this irreversibility postulate, it suffices that there exists at least one is assumed, assumption A.3.5 is euivalent to the surely innocuous
non-produced input that is needed, directly or indirectly, for all proposition that if non-produced goods were available in unlimited
production; labor provides an obvious example. Alternatively, if quantities, it would be feasible to produce a positive amount of any
production takes time and differently dated commodities are dis- given produced good. Let P be the set of produced goods, N the
tinguished, then reversa! of a process would require that sorne outputs set of non-produced goods, and for each i E P, let y 1 be a vector with
precede the corresponding inputs. a positive output of commodity i that would be feasible if there were
Assumption A.3.4 implies that the economy must have an initial no restrictions on the availability of non-produced inputs. That is,
endowment of resources in order to produce anything. Let the yi > O yj ~ O forjE P.
initial endowment be denoted by x.
Let n be the number of produced goods,
DEFINITION 4. The social production possibility vector y is feasible
if it is possible and

y+ x ~O. y is a convex combination of vectors in Y, so yE Y. Also,


The set of feasible production possibility vectors is denoted by all iEP,

Y= Yn {y y1 +x ~ 0}. by construction. For iEN, x 1 >O; then choose a, O< a::; 1, so


that
DEFINITION 5. The production allocation !) is feasible if y1 is
all i E N.
possible for each f (i.e., if y E W) and if
Since x1 ~O, i EP,
2 Yr +:X~ O.
f all i E P.
64 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r
1

PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 65

it states that society cannot produce something for nothing by any The set of feasible production allocations is denoted by
organization of its entire production apparatus. It is important to
observe that this basic property of a social production possibility set
cannot be deduced from the corresponding properties of the firm
qp = @'n{y\,'f>r + x~o}
production possibility sets. If, in A.3.4, we let y1 = O for all firms
A feasible vector or allocation is one that society is capable of
but one, then we can deduce the corresponding statement for a firm;
carrying out, given the existing resources.
that is, it cannot be that y1 > O for any possible y1 E Y1 But the
For later reference, it is important to add one more assumption,
converse is not true; from this last statement, A.3.4 cannot be
namely that the resources and technology of society together permit
deduced. For example, if firm A produces 2 units of commodity 2
the supply of a positive amount of all goods.
from 1 unit of commodity 1 and firm B produces 2 units of com-
modity 1 from 1 unit of commodity 2, then neither firm has outputs AssuM:>TION 5. For sorne yE Y, x+ y O.
without inputs, but together they can have a net output of 1 unit of Note that if y is the social production possibility vector, y + x is the
each commodity with no net inputs. net supply, which must be non-negative for feasibility. To insist on
When the possibility of strict positivity means something like the following:
Divide the commodities into produced and non-produced. The
non-produced commodities all must be available initially in positive
A.3.4 says further that no non-trivial, socially possible production amounts (a commodity that is neither produced nor available
process can be completely undone by another. For the validity of initially can surely be disregarded). If the divisibility of production
this irreversibility postulate, it suffices that there exists at least one is assumed, assumption A.3.5 is euivalent to the surely innocuous
non-produced input that is needed, directly or indirectly, for all proposition that if non-produced goods were available in unlimited
production; labor provides an obvious example. Alternatively, if quantities, it would be feasible to produce a positive amount of any
production takes time and differently dated commodities are dis- given produced good. Let P be the set of produced goods, N the
tinguished, then reversa! of a process would require that sorne outputs set of non-produced goods, and for each i E P, let y 1 be a vector with
precede the corresponding inputs. a positive output of commodity i that would be feasible if there were
Assumption A.3.4 implies that the economy must have an initial no restrictions on the availability of non-produced inputs. That is,
endowment of resources in order to produce anything. Let the yi > O yj ~ O forjE P.
initial endowment be denoted by x.
Let n be the number of produced goods,
DEFINITION 4. The social production possibility vector y is feasible
if it is possible and

y+ x ~O. y is a convex combination of vectors in Y, so yE Y. Also,


The set of feasible production possibility vectors is denoted by all iEP,

Y= Yn {y y1 +x ~ 0}. by construction. For iEN, x 1 >O; then choose a, O< a::; 1, so


that
DEFINITION 5. The production allocation !) is feasible if y1 is
all i E N.
possible for each f (i.e., if y E W) and if
Since x1 ~O, i EP,
2 Yr +:X~ O.
f all i E P.
66 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 67

Let y = ay. Since Y is divisible, y E Y, and by construction, is an index of net inputs to society, while L(Jf) and U(!f) are indices
:X + y O, as assumed in A.3.5. of inputs and outputs, respectively, totalled over firms without
Now it is essential to demonstrate that the set of feasible produc- cancelling inputs of one firm against outputs of another.
tion allocations is bounded. Por any real number g, let Let us expand & to include all allocations for 'which the inputs
satisfy (3); that is, define
g+ = max(g,O) g- = max(- g,o),
so that (4)
g = g+ - g- g- ;:::: o.
To prove qfi bounded, it certainly suffices to show that the larger set,
Por a vector, x, define upper and lower bounds, qj*, is bounded. Al so, qy is closed by T.3.1, the set
U(x) =.L: x/
j
L(x) = x
j
1-.

Obviously, a set of vectors, S, is bounded if and only if U(x) and


is closed since it is defined by the continuous function
L(x) are both bounded from above as x varies over S.
THEOREM 2. If A.3.1-A.3.4 hold, then the set of feasible production
allocations, &, is compact and convex.
and the intersection of closed sets is closed, so that Cfl/* is closed.
Proof. Por any lf E qy = X Y1, let y = 2: y1 . Then Prom (2) and the definition of qj*, (4),
f f

L; (yt -y)= L;Yn = Y1 2 -y-, U(!f) + U(x) 2L(Jf) for !fE qj*; (5)
f f
hence, to prove the boundedness of qij*, it suffices to show that U(!f)
or is bounded there, for then the boundedness of L(!f) follows by (5).
If U(!f) ~ 1, alllf E qj*, then there is nothing to pro ve. Suppose
that U(!f) > 1, sorne lf E qj*. Por any such lf let a = 1/ U(!f) < l.
Sum over i. Then By divisibility, ay1 E Y, allj, so that alfE qy. Also,

U(!f) + L(f Yr) 2 L(Jf). (2) L(f ~Yr) = aL(f Yr) ~ aU(x) ~ U(x),
Por lf E qfi, lf is feasible; that is, so that alfE qj*. Also, U(a!f) = aU(!f) = 1, by definition of a.
Let
y, 2
f '
-:X, qj** = qj* n{!f 1 U(!f) = 1}.
so that It has just been shown that
1
for lf E&. (3) if U(Jf) > 1 and a = U(Jf)' then alfE Cfl/**.

L and U may be thought of as indices of inputs and outputs, To pro ve the boundedness of qij*, note that it is sufficient to show
respectively; then that

L(f Yr) bounded away from zero on qij**. (6)


66 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 67

Let y = ay. Since Y is divisible, y E Y, and by construction, is an index of net inputs to society, while L(Jf) and U(!f) are indices
:X + y O, as assumed in A.3.5. of inputs and outputs, respectively, totalled over firms without
Now it is essential to demonstrate that the set of feasible produc- cancelling inputs of one firm against outputs of another.
tion allocations is bounded. Por any real number g, let Let us expand & to include all allocations for 'which the inputs
satisfy (3); that is, define
g+ = max(g,O) g- = max(- g,o),
so that (4)
g = g+ - g- g- ;:::: o.
To prove qfi bounded, it certainly suffices to show that the larger set,
Por a vector, x, define upper and lower bounds, qj*, is bounded. Al so, qy is closed by T.3.1, the set
U(x) =.L: x/
j
L(x) = x
j
1-.

Obviously, a set of vectors, S, is bounded if and only if U(x) and


is closed since it is defined by the continuous function
L(x) are both bounded from above as x varies over S.
THEOREM 2. If A.3.1-A.3.4 hold, then the set of feasible production
allocations, &, is compact and convex.
and the intersection of closed sets is closed, so that Cfl/* is closed.
Proof. Por any lf E qy = X Y1, let y = 2: y1 . Then Prom (2) and the definition of qj*, (4),
f f

L; (yt -y)= L;Yn = Y1 2 -y-, U(!f) + U(x) 2L(Jf) for !fE qj*; (5)
f f
hence, to prove the boundedness of qij*, it suffices to show that U(!f)
or is bounded there, for then the boundedness of L(!f) follows by (5).
If U(!f) ~ 1, alllf E qj*, then there is nothing to pro ve. Suppose
that U(!f) > 1, sorne lf E qj*. Por any such lf let a = 1/ U(!f) < l.
Sum over i. Then By divisibility, ay1 E Y, allj, so that alfE qy. Also,

U(!f) + L(f Yr) 2 L(Jf). (2) L(f ~Yr) = aL(f Yr) ~ aU(x) ~ U(x),
Por lf E qfi, lf is feasible; that is, so that alfE qj*. Also, U(a!f) = aU(!f) = 1, by definition of a.
Let
y, 2
f '
-:X, qj** = qj* n{!f 1 U(!f) = 1}.
so that It has just been shown that
1
for lf E&. (3) if U(Jf) > 1 and a = U(Jf)' then alfE Cfl/**.

L and U may be thought of as indices of inputs and outputs, To pro ve the boundedness of qij*, note that it is sufficient to show
respectively; then that

L(f Yr) bounded away from zero on qij**. (6)


'/

PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND TI-lE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 69


68 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Suppose (6) true. Then for any lf for which U(!f) > 1, Corollary 2. Y is closed.
Proo.f. That x was actually the endowment vector did not enter
L(f rxy) = rxL(f Yr) e> O, the proof of T.3.2; what was shown was that the set

so that wn{vj_'f>r + xo} (7)

1 L(2. Yr) u(-)


U(!f) = - ::::; _ r _ ::::; ~;
is compact for any vector x. Let y0 be a limit point of Y. Then
ex e e there is a sequence, {yv}, yv E Y, yv---+ y0 . By D.3.2, there is, for
each v, a production allocation ij" such that
thus, for !/E qtj*, either U(y) ::::; 1 or U(!J) :i; U(x)je, so that U(!J) is
certainly bounded on qt}*, and qtj* is bounded. 2 yj = yv.
f
It remains to demonstrate (6). The set, qt}**, is clearly closed;
since U(y) is bounded on it by definition, (5) implies that qtj** is Since yv---+ y 0 , we can certainly find a vector x, with -x y 0 , such
bounded and therefore compact. Recall that a continuous function that
actually assumes a minimum value as the argument varies over a 2 yj + x O all v.
r
compact set; that is, if f(x) is continuous for x E S, where S is
compact, then, for sorne x E S, f(x) f(x), all x E S. It follows Then / belongs to the compact set (7) for al! v. Therefore there
that if f(x) > O, for x E S, then f(x) e > O, all x E S, where exists a subsequence converging to so me y 0 belonging to '!!/; hence,
e = f(x). Since yv = 2 yjf
converges to 2 Y7
f '

along the subsequence. But yv---+ y 0 ; hence

is a continuous function of qy on qt}**, it suffices that


yo= 2 Y7 E Y.
f

011 qt}**
4. Costs, Profits, an<l Supply

in order that (6) hold. In this section, we will show how sorne of the assumptions of
Since U(O) = O =!= 1, then lf =!= O for lf E qtj**. By A.3.4, Chapter 2 can be derived as propositions in the theory of production
and establish a few results that will be used later in the book. A
2Yr complete study of profit and supply functions is not intended.
f Suppose first that, in addition to A.3.1-A.3.3, we postulate that
has at least one negative component, so that Yr is bounded above. Clearly this is not an assumption we should
wish to retain indefinitely-it excludes, for instance, the case of
for lf E qt}**, constant returns to scale. When it is made, howover, then for given
pE Sn, the function PYr always attains a maximum on Y1 . Accord-
ingly, we introduce
as required.
Thus, oJJ has been proved bounded. By definition, it is the DEFINITION 6.
intersection of closed convex sets and therefore is closed and convex. 7Tr(P) = max py1 ,
Y E Y
A closed bounded set is compact, so that T.3.2 has been demon-
where 7T1(p) is the profit function of firm.f.
strated.
'/

PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND TI-lE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 69


68 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Suppose (6) true. Then for any lf for which U(!f) > 1, Corollary 2. Y is closed.
Proo.f. That x was actually the endowment vector did not enter
L(f rxy) = rxL(f Yr) e> O, the proof of T.3.2; what was shown was that the set

so that wn{vj_'f>r + xo} (7)

1 L(2. Yr) u(-)


U(!f) = - ::::; _ r _ ::::; ~;
is compact for any vector x. Let y0 be a limit point of Y. Then
ex e e there is a sequence, {yv}, yv E Y, yv---+ y0 . By D.3.2, there is, for
each v, a production allocation ij" such that
thus, for !/E qtj*, either U(y) ::::; 1 or U(!J) :i; U(x)je, so that U(!J) is
certainly bounded on qt}*, and qtj* is bounded. 2 yj = yv.
f
It remains to demonstrate (6). The set, qt}**, is clearly closed;
since U(y) is bounded on it by definition, (5) implies that qtj** is Since yv---+ y 0 , we can certainly find a vector x, with -x y 0 , such
bounded and therefore compact. Recall that a continuous function that
actually assumes a minimum value as the argument varies over a 2 yj + x O all v.
r
compact set; that is, if f(x) is continuous for x E S, where S is
compact, then, for sorne x E S, f(x) f(x), all x E S. It follows Then / belongs to the compact set (7) for al! v. Therefore there
that if f(x) > O, for x E S, then f(x) e > O, all x E S, where exists a subsequence converging to so me y 0 belonging to '!!/; hence,
e = f(x). Since yv = 2 yjf
converges to 2 Y7
f '

along the subsequence. But yv---+ y 0 ; hence

is a continuous function of qy on qt}**, it suffices that


yo= 2 Y7 E Y.
f

011 qt}**
4. Costs, Profits, an<l Supply

in order that (6) hold. In this section, we will show how sorne of the assumptions of
Since U(O) = O =!= 1, then lf =!= O for lf E qtj**. By A.3.4, Chapter 2 can be derived as propositions in the theory of production
and establish a few results that will be used later in the book. A
2Yr complete study of profit and supply functions is not intended.
f Suppose first that, in addition to A.3.1-A.3.3, we postulate that
has at least one negative component, so that Yr is bounded above. Clearly this is not an assumption we should
wish to retain indefinitely-it excludes, for instance, the case of
for lf E qt}**, constant returns to scale. When it is made, howover, then for given
pE Sn, the function PYr always attains a maximum on Y1 . Accord-
ingly, we introduce
as required.
Thus, oJJ has been proved bounded. By definition, it is the DEFINITION 6.
intersection of closed convex sets and therefore is closed and convex. 7Tr(P) = max py1 ,
Y E Y
A closed bounded set is compact, so that T.3.2 has been demon-
where 7T1(p) is the profit function of firm.f.
strated.
70 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

By A.3.1 we have 7T(p) ;::: O, all pE Sn. We rnay also define


r PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 71

that Y 1 admitsfree disposal, in other words, that y1 E Y 1 and y~ ::; y1


DEFINITION 7. Y1(p) = {y 1 1 py1 = 7T(p), y1 E Y1} where Y1(p) is irnply that y~ E Y1 . A set that adrnits free disposal necessarily has
the supply correspondence of firrnf full dimensionality.

Of course, sorne cornponents of rnernbers of Y1(p) will be negative. THEOREM 4. Let Y1 be bounded and strictly convex and adrnit free
disposal. Then (a) 7T(p) is a strictly convex function, and (b) Y1(p)
These denote dernands.
has only one elernent for each p and can be written as a fUnction,
W e now pro ve.
y(p).
THEOREM 3. If Y1 is bounded, then (a) 7T(p) is a continuous convex
Proof Suppose that y 1 and y~ both belong to Y1(p). Then, in
function over Sn; (b) Y1(p) is a convex set for each p.
the previous notation and by the rernarks just rnade, y(a) belongs
Proof (a) Let p, p' E Sn, p(a) = ap' + (1 - a)p, O ::; a ::; 1, and to the interior of Y1 if O < a < l. Then there exists y~ y1(a),
Iet y1 E Y1(p), y~ E Y1(p'), y~ E Y1 [p(a)J. Then by D.3.6 and D.3.7, y'f E Y1 . But then, since p > O, py'f > py(a) = 7T1(p) by T.3.3(b), a
contradiction to D.3.6 and D.3.7. It also follows that, forO < a <
py~ ::; py p'y~ ::; p'y~. 1, the inequalities used in proving T.3.3(a) are all strict, so that 7T(p)
Hence, rnultiplying the first inequality by (1 - a), the second by a, rnust be strictly convex.
and adding yield This theorern shows that the discussion in the previous chapter,
in particular assurnption A.2.1, was based on the implicit supposition
7T[p(a)J ::; (1 - a)7T(p) + tx7T(p'), of diminishing returns to scale. We can also easily prove the other
assurnptions rnade there. Of course, A.2.2, hornogeneity of degree
so that 7T(p) is convex.
zero, follows imrnediately from the nature of the rnaximization
To dernonstrate continuity, let {pv} be a sequence of price vectors
process as far as the production side goes. Walras' law (A.2.3)
converging to p 0 . For each. v, let y[ E Y1(pv). Then, for any
cannot be discussed without considering the consurnption sector, but
y1 E Y, pvyj ;::: pvy1 for all v. Since Y1 is compact, the sequence,
continuity (A.2.4) can now be demonstrated.
{yf}, is bounded. Let y~ be any limit point; then p 0 y~ :2:: P0 Yr for
any y1 E Y1 , so that by D.3.6 and D.3.7, Y? E Y1(p 0) and 7T(p 0) = THEOREM 5. Let Y1 be bounded and strictly convex and admit free
poy7. Since y~ was any lirnit point of the bounded sequence {yf} and disposal. Then y1(p) is continuous over Sn.
since 7T(pv) = pvy, it has been shown that 7T(pv)---'>- 7T(p 0 ), and
therefore, 7T(p) is a continuous function. Proof. Let pv---'>- p0 E Sn, and y[ = y(pv). Since Y 1 is cornpact,
(b) Let y 1 , y~ E Y1(p). Then for O ::; a ::; 1, let y(a) = ay 1 + y[---'>- Y? E Y1 along sorne subsequence. By definition of the supply
(1 - a)Y function, pv[y)! - y1(p 0)] ;::: O, all v, so that, taking limits along the
selected subsequence, p 0 [y7 - y1 (p 0 )] ;::: O. ijowever, frorn the
py1(a) = apy1 + (1 - a)py~ = tx7T(p) + (1 - a)7T(p) = 7T(p). u,niqueness of the profit-rnaxirnizing cornrnodity vector for each p,
asserted in T.3.4(b), y7 = y1(p 0). Since this holds for any limit
But y1(a) E Y 1 by A.3.3 and so belongs to Y1(p) by D.3.4.
If one is willing to assurne Yr to be strictly convcx, the results can point, y7, T.3.5 has been established.
be strengthened. (A set is strictly convex if every proper convex Let us now return to the profit function. Since 7T(p) = py1(p), it
combination of two points of the set belongs to the interior of the is certainly continuous. We will show that 7T is, in fact, differen-
set relative to the srnallest linear space containing it. If the set has tiable and that 8?T1/8p = y1(p). This rneans that, to a linear
full dimensionality then the relative interior is the interior in the approximation, the effect on profits of changing a price is the
usual sense. A proper convex cornbination of x 1 and x 2 is a point sarne whether inputs and outputs are adjusted optimally or left
x = ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 , for sorne a, O < a < 1.) We also assurne unchanged.
70 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

By A.3.1 we have 7T(p) ;::: O, all pE Sn. We rnay also define


r PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 71

that Y 1 admitsfree disposal, in other words, that y1 E Y 1 and y~ ::; y1


DEFINITION 7. Y1(p) = {y 1 1 py1 = 7T(p), y1 E Y1} where Y1(p) is irnply that y~ E Y1 . A set that adrnits free disposal necessarily has
the supply correspondence of firrnf full dimensionality.

Of course, sorne cornponents of rnernbers of Y1(p) will be negative. THEOREM 4. Let Y1 be bounded and strictly convex and adrnit free
disposal. Then (a) 7T(p) is a strictly convex function, and (b) Y1(p)
These denote dernands.
has only one elernent for each p and can be written as a fUnction,
W e now pro ve.
y(p).
THEOREM 3. If Y1 is bounded, then (a) 7T(p) is a continuous convex
Proof Suppose that y 1 and y~ both belong to Y1(p). Then, in
function over Sn; (b) Y1(p) is a convex set for each p.
the previous notation and by the rernarks just rnade, y(a) belongs
Proof (a) Let p, p' E Sn, p(a) = ap' + (1 - a)p, O ::; a ::; 1, and to the interior of Y1 if O < a < l. Then there exists y~ y1(a),
Iet y1 E Y1(p), y~ E Y1(p'), y~ E Y1 [p(a)J. Then by D.3.6 and D.3.7, y'f E Y1 . But then, since p > O, py'f > py(a) = 7T1(p) by T.3.3(b), a
contradiction to D.3.6 and D.3.7. It also follows that, forO < a <
py~ ::; py p'y~ ::; p'y~. 1, the inequalities used in proving T.3.3(a) are all strict, so that 7T(p)
Hence, rnultiplying the first inequality by (1 - a), the second by a, rnust be strictly convex.
and adding yield This theorern shows that the discussion in the previous chapter,
in particular assurnption A.2.1, was based on the implicit supposition
7T[p(a)J ::; (1 - a)7T(p) + tx7T(p'), of diminishing returns to scale. We can also easily prove the other
assurnptions rnade there. Of course, A.2.2, hornogeneity of degree
so that 7T(p) is convex.
zero, follows imrnediately from the nature of the rnaximization
To dernonstrate continuity, let {pv} be a sequence of price vectors
process as far as the production side goes. Walras' law (A.2.3)
converging to p 0 . For each. v, let y[ E Y1(pv). Then, for any
cannot be discussed without considering the consurnption sector, but
y1 E Y, pvyj ;::: pvy1 for all v. Since Y1 is compact, the sequence,
continuity (A.2.4) can now be demonstrated.
{yf}, is bounded. Let y~ be any limit point; then p 0 y~ :2:: P0 Yr for
any y1 E Y1 , so that by D.3.6 and D.3.7, Y? E Y1(p 0) and 7T(p 0) = THEOREM 5. Let Y1 be bounded and strictly convex and admit free
poy7. Since y~ was any lirnit point of the bounded sequence {yf} and disposal. Then y1(p) is continuous over Sn.
since 7T(pv) = pvy, it has been shown that 7T(pv)---'>- 7T(p 0 ), and
therefore, 7T(p) is a continuous function. Proof. Let pv---'>- p0 E Sn, and y[ = y(pv). Since Y 1 is cornpact,
(b) Let y 1 , y~ E Y1(p). Then for O ::; a ::; 1, let y(a) = ay 1 + y[---'>- Y? E Y1 along sorne subsequence. By definition of the supply
(1 - a)Y function, pv[y)! - y1(p 0)] ;::: O, all v, so that, taking limits along the
selected subsequence, p 0 [y7 - y1 (p 0 )] ;::: O. ijowever, frorn the
py1(a) = apy1 + (1 - a)py~ = tx7T(p) + (1 - a)7T(p) = 7T(p). u,niqueness of the profit-rnaxirnizing cornrnodity vector for each p,
asserted in T.3.4(b), y7 = y1(p 0). Since this holds for any limit
But y1(a) E Y 1 by A.3.3 and so belongs to Y1(p) by D.3.4.
If one is willing to assurne Yr to be strictly convcx, the results can point, y7, T.3.5 has been established.
be strengthened. (A set is strictly convex if every proper convex Let us now return to the profit function. Since 7T(p) = py1(p), it
combination of two points of the set belongs to the interior of the is certainly continuous. We will show that 7T is, in fact, differen-
set relative to the srnallest linear space containing it. If the set has tiable and that 8?T1/8p = y1(p). This rneans that, to a linear
full dimensionality then the relative interior is the interior in the approximation, the effect on profits of changing a price is the
usual sense. A proper convex cornbination of x 1 and x 2 is a point sarne whether inputs and outputs are adjusted optimally or left
x = ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 , for sorne a, O < a < 1.) We also assurne unchanged.
72 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 73

By definition of profits and profit maximization, we have, for any Lastly, let us consider the special case discussed in Section 2.1 1
change h in the price vector, under the title, the L-economy. Here Y1 is a convex cone and not
strictly convex. Instead we consider the normalized cone,
7r(p + h) = (p + h)Yr(P + h) ;:;>: (p + h)yr(p) = PYr(P) + hy(p)
i,,
= 7r(p) + hy(p),
Y = {Y Y
J = __!__
Yrr
Yr, Yr E Y, Yrr > o};
7r(p) = PYr(P) ;:;>: PYr(P + h) = (p + h)yr(P + h) - hyr(P + h)
= 7r(p + h) - hy(p + h). recall the "no joint production" assumption, A.2.10(b ). With the
further assumption that positive output requires some input, it is
Hence, easy to sho;v that Y is bounded. We can now define:
h[Yr(P + h) - Yr(P)] > 7rr(P + h) - 7r(p) - hyr(P) > O DEFINITION 8. The unit profit function for a firm having only a
JhJ - Jhl - . single output and constant returns to scale is defined as

From T.3.4, Yr(P + h) - Yr(P) approaches O as h approaches O; 7r(p) = sup PY


YfEY
since h/JhJ is certainly bounded, the left-hand member of the above
inequality approaches O, and therefore,
The mnimum unit cost function of Section 2.11, C1(P), then 1s
Iim 7r(p + h) - 7r(p) - hy(p) =O
defined by
h~o JhJ ' C1(p) = Pr - 7r(p).
It follows at once from T.3.3 that
by definition, 7r1(p) is differentiable for any p E Sno while, by letting
h = tei, where ei is the ith unit row vector, (0, ... , O, 1,0, ... , 0), with THEOREM 7. C1(P) is a continuous concave function over Sn.
1 in the ith place, we see that 87r1)8p = Y!i
Thus the use of the fixed point in establishing the existence of equili-
THEOREM 6. lf Yr is bounded and strictly convex and admits free brium in an L-economy (see A.2.13(b)) is justified.
disposal, then the profit function 7rr(p) is everywhere differentiable Finally, we note a. very simple, but much-used, implication of
and 87rrf8p = Y!i(p). profit maximization.

lf it is assumed, in addition, that the profit function is twice


THEOREM 8. If Y7 E Y(p1'), k = 1,2, then (p 1 - p2)(y} - yJ) ;:;>: 0.
differentiable, certain very familiar propositions of production theory In particular, under the hypotheses of T.3.5,
emerge. By T.3.6,
(pl _ p2)[y(pl) _ y1(p2)] ;::.: o.
Proof Profit maximization implies that y} is at least as profitable
as YJ at prices p1 and vice versa.
But if 7r is twice continuously differentiable, then the matrix
({P7r rf8p8p 1) is symmetric; sin ce 7r1 is convex; it is al so positive
semi-definite. If these inequalities are added and the terms regrouped, the theorem
is established.
Corollary 6. 1f Y 1 is bounded and strictly convex and admits free
disposal and if the profit function, 7r(p), is twice differentiable, then Notes
(a) 8yrdp1 = 8yr 1f8pt for all i and }; (b) the matrix (8y;/8p 1) 1s
The general outlines of production theory in this chapter are common
positive semi-definite; and in particular, (e) 8yfif8p ;:;>: O. to the neoclassical tradition and need no special reference. The
72 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
PRODUCTION DECISIONS AND THE BOUNDEDNESS OF THE ECONOMY 73

By definition of profits and profit maximization, we have, for any Lastly, let us consider the special case discussed in Section 2.1 1
change h in the price vector, under the title, the L-economy. Here Y1 is a convex cone and not
strictly convex. Instead we consider the normalized cone,
7r(p + h) = (p + h)Yr(P + h) ;:;>: (p + h)yr(p) = PYr(P) + hy(p)
i,,
= 7r(p) + hy(p),
Y = {Y Y
J = __!__
Yrr
Yr, Yr E Y, Yrr > o};
7r(p) = PYr(P) ;:;>: PYr(P + h) = (p + h)yr(P + h) - hyr(P + h)
= 7r(p + h) - hy(p + h). recall the "no joint production" assumption, A.2.10(b ). With the
further assumption that positive output requires some input, it is
Hence, easy to sho;v that Y is bounded. We can now define:
h[Yr(P + h) - Yr(P)] > 7rr(P + h) - 7r(p) - hyr(P) > O DEFINITION 8. The unit profit function for a firm having only a
JhJ - Jhl - . single output and constant returns to scale is defined as

From T.3.4, Yr(P + h) - Yr(P) approaches O as h approaches O; 7r(p) = sup PY


YfEY
since h/JhJ is certainly bounded, the left-hand member of the above
inequality approaches O, and therefore,
The mnimum unit cost function of Section 2.11, C1(P), then 1s
Iim 7r(p + h) - 7r(p) - hy(p) =O
defined by
h~o JhJ ' C1(p) = Pr - 7r(p).
It follows at once from T.3.3 that
by definition, 7r1(p) is differentiable for any p E Sno while, by letting
h = tei, where ei is the ith unit row vector, (0, ... , O, 1,0, ... , 0), with THEOREM 7. C1(P) is a continuous concave function over Sn.
1 in the ith place, we see that 87r1)8p = Y!i
Thus the use of the fixed point in establishing the existence of equili-
THEOREM 6. lf Yr is bounded and strictly convex and admits free brium in an L-economy (see A.2.13(b)) is justified.
disposal, then the profit function 7rr(p) is everywhere differentiable Finally, we note a. very simple, but much-used, implication of
and 87rrf8p = Y!i(p). profit maximization.

lf it is assumed, in addition, that the profit function is twice


THEOREM 8. If Y7 E Y(p1'), k = 1,2, then (p 1 - p2)(y} - yJ) ;:;>: 0.
differentiable, certain very familiar propositions of production theory In particular, under the hypotheses of T.3.5,
emerge. By T.3.6,
(pl _ p2)[y(pl) _ y1(p2)] ;::.: o.
Proof Profit maximization implies that y} is at least as profitable
as YJ at prices p1 and vice versa.
But if 7r is twice continuously differentiable, then the matrix
({P7r rf8p8p 1) is symmetric; sin ce 7r1 is convex; it is al so positive
semi-definite. If these inequalities are added and the terms regrouped, the theorem
is established.
Corollary 6. 1f Y 1 is bounded and strictly convex and admits free
disposal and if the profit function, 7r(p), is twice differentiable, then Notes
(a) 8yrdp1 = 8yr 1f8pt for all i and }; (b) the matrix (8y;/8p 1) 1s
The general outlines of production theory in this chapter are common
positive semi-definite; and in particular, (e) 8yfif8p ;:;>: O. to the neoclassical tradition and need no special reference. The
74 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r- i

1
Chapter Four
analysis of production into activities, which underlies the en tire chapter
and which constitutes a synthesis of the earlier "fixed-coefficient" and CONSUMER DECISIONS
"production function" viewpoints, seems to have first appeared in the AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS
classic paper of von Neumann [1937, 1945] on economic growth. A
systematic development of production theory from the activity analysis
viewpoint first appeared in Koopmans [1951b]; the crucial importance
of assumptions of the type of A.3.4 in establishing the boundedness of A levelling rancorous rational sort of
the set of feasible production allocations first appeared there. mind
Section 2. For more extended discussion of the possibilities for and That never looked out of the eye of a
meaning of divisibility in production, see the interchange between saint
Chamberlin [1948, 1949] and Hahn [1949] and also Menger [1954]. Or out of a drunkard' s eye.
Section 3. It has been shown by Debreu [1962] that, in fact, irre- -W. B. Yeats, Seven Sages
versibility is not necessary to the existence theorems to be established in
Chapter 5, but the proofs appear to become more comp!icated. In
view of the high acceptability of the irreversibility assumption, we ha ve
not felt it worthwhile to seek the added generality.
l. Consumer Choice
Section 4. Most of the development of this section is parallel to the
corresponding theorems in consumer demand theory due primarily to It is assumed that there are a finite number of households, indexed
Slutzky [1915]. More specifically, the application to the theory of the by h; X, will represent the consumption vector of household h.
firm and particularly Corollary 6 appears in Hotelling [1932]. The . ~

Each household is also assumed to hold an initial endowment, X,, of


method of proof follows that of McKenzie [1956-57] for the consumer
demand case; see also Karlin [1959, Vol. I, pp. 265-273]. goods; for convenience in exposition, we assume that it sells this
endowment at the going prices and uses the income to purchase
consumption goods. Thus, all consumption can be regarded as
non-negative.
The preferences of the households extend, among other commod-
ities, to choices between labor and leisure and among different kinds
of labor. Similarly, among the endowments of the household, the
most important in practice are the capacities to perforni different
types of labor. To represent labor services, sorne slightly artificial
conventions are needed.
GRESE Let L be the set of labor services. For -a~ lq.Qqf.;:service i EL, let
UN\VERS!rt DE PARIS 1 - PANTHON SORBONNE X,, the endowment, be undefstb6d th' mean tb.e lfWJ.~irnu;t1~;tll1.imnt
90, ruede To!biac of that service that household h is oapble Df.supplying undet' any
75634 PARIS CEDEX 13 71
circumstances. Thus, if i is a slhfl .h<!il(~'l{$s,e~~~d.<-p~ ..~ .xht = O. If
i is an arduous occupation, it may be physically imposs1ble to supply
it at a very high rate; then xlti will be small. We define the indi-
vidual's "demand" for labor service i, xlti, as the extent to which his
supply of that service falls short of the maximum he is capable of
supplying; the amount of labor of type i supplied is then X, - X,.
Thus, if the individual is capable of teaching for 12 hours a day and
also capable of driving a bus for 12 hours a day and if, in fact, he
teaches for eight hours a day and does not drive a bus at all, then
his demand for "teaching leisure" is four hours and that for

75

1i
74 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r- i

1
Chapter Four
analysis of production into activities, which underlies the en tire chapter
and which constitutes a synthesis of the earlier "fixed-coefficient" and CONSUMER DECISIONS
"production function" viewpoints, seems to have first appeared in the AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS
classic paper of von Neumann [1937, 1945] on economic growth. A
systematic development of production theory from the activity analysis
viewpoint first appeared in Koopmans [1951b]; the crucial importance
of assumptions of the type of A.3.4 in establishing the boundedness of A levelling rancorous rational sort of
the set of feasible production allocations first appeared there. mind
Section 2. For more extended discussion of the possibilities for and That never looked out of the eye of a
meaning of divisibility in production, see the interchange between saint
Chamberlin [1948, 1949] and Hahn [1949] and also Menger [1954]. Or out of a drunkard' s eye.
Section 3. It has been shown by Debreu [1962] that, in fact, irre- -W. B. Yeats, Seven Sages
versibility is not necessary to the existence theorems to be established in
Chapter 5, but the proofs appear to become more comp!icated. In
view of the high acceptability of the irreversibility assumption, we ha ve
not felt it worthwhile to seek the added generality.
l. Consumer Choice
Section 4. Most of the development of this section is parallel to the
corresponding theorems in consumer demand theory due primarily to It is assumed that there are a finite number of households, indexed
Slutzky [1915]. More specifically, the application to the theory of the by h; X, will represent the consumption vector of household h.
firm and particularly Corollary 6 appears in Hotelling [1932]. The . ~

Each household is also assumed to hold an initial endowment, X,, of


method of proof follows that of McKenzie [1956-57] for the consumer
demand case; see also Karlin [1959, Vol. I, pp. 265-273]. goods; for convenience in exposition, we assume that it sells this
endowment at the going prices and uses the income to purchase
consumption goods. Thus, all consumption can be regarded as
non-negative.
The preferences of the households extend, among other commod-
ities, to choices between labor and leisure and among different kinds
of labor. Similarly, among the endowments of the household, the
most important in practice are the capacities to perforni different
types of labor. To represent labor services, sorne slightly artificial
conventions are needed.
GRESE Let L be the set of labor services. For -a~ lq.Qqf.;:service i EL, let
UN\VERS!rt DE PARIS 1 - PANTHON SORBONNE X,, the endowment, be undefstb6d th' mean tb.e lfWJ.~irnu;t1~;tll1.imnt
90, ruede To!biac of that service that household h is oapble Df.supplying undet' any
75634 PARIS CEDEX 13 71
circumstances. Thus, if i is a slhfl .h<!il(~'l{$s,e~~~d.<-p~ ..~ .xht = O. If
i is an arduous occupation, it may be physically imposs1ble to supply
it at a very high rate; then xlti will be small. We define the indi-
vidual's "demand" for labor service i, xlti, as the extent to which his
supply of that service falls short of the maximum he is capable of
supplying; the amount of labor of type i supplied is then X, - X,.
Thus, if the individual is capable of teaching for 12 hours a day and
also capable of driving a bus for 12 hours a day and if, in fact, he
teaches for eight hours a day and does not drive a bus at all, then
his demand for "teaching leisure" is four hours and that for

75

1i
76 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
!
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 77

"bus-driving leisure" 12 hours. The conventions u sed imply the AssuMPTION l. The consumption possibility set Xh for individual h
constraints is closed and convex; xlt :::: O for xlt E Xh.
(i EL). Note that the time constraints are satisfied with strict inequality
if Xht = .Xht (i EL), Xht = O (i 1 L). Then we can choose a, O < a <
If xht < .Xht (i EL), then the individual is supplying labor of type i in
1, so that the time constraints are satisfied by the vector x" defined
the amount .Xht - Xht lf Xht > .X", then the individual is a net
by Xht = a.Xht (i EL), Xht = O (i 1 L). Then certainly
demander of labor of type i in the amount Xht - .Xht; the second case
might arise, for example, for domestic or repair services. In the xhi :::; .xht all i,
notation introduced in Chapter 3, the net supply of labor of type i by X~tt < X~tt if Xnt > O.
household h is (xht - .Xht)-, the net demand is (xht - Xnt) +.
This argument justifies the assumption,
The amount of all types of labor that can be supplied is constrained
not merely by capabilities, but also by the scarcity oftime itself. We AssuMPTION 2. There exists a possible consumption vector x" X",
E

have not specified in what units labor is measured, so let Tht be the such that
amount of time that labor activity i requires per unit. (Ordinarily, xhi :::; .x,, all i,
we measure labor by time, so that Tht = 1, but it might be measured Xnt < .X!tt if .Xitt >O,
in terms of tasks performed, for example.) There is sorne limit Ton
the amount of time in the period under analysis (e.g., 24 hours in a
where xlt is the initial endowment for household h.
day), so that the total labor supplied cannot exceed T; The income. of a household is assumed to derive from two sources:
the sale of the initial endowment and the share held by the household
2 Tht(Xht - .x,,;)- :::; T. in the profits of firms. lt is assumed that household h owns a
iEL
fraction, dhf, of firmf and shares to that extent in the profits. Of
It is al so true that at least so me types of consumption of goods (other course, d1, 1 must be non-negative, though it may be zero, and for
than types of leisure) require time. Let Tht be the amount of time each firm the total amount of profits is allocated to different house-
required to consume a unit of good i (i 1 L); Jet T~t be the amount of holds.
time required to consume the services of a unit of labor of type i. AssuMPTION 3. For each household h the total income Mh at any set
Then the time constraint becomes of prices p and any given set of production decisions y1 is given by

M" = px" + 2 dh!(PY) where dlt 1 :::: O, 2 dltf =


h
l.
f

Later on, the general equilibrium model will be reinterpreted to apply As stated, A.4.3 implies that each firm is a partnership, since the
to many time periods simultaneously. The individuals are assumed household shares in losses as well as profits. However, since
to make their labor and consumption choices simltaneously for the O E Y1 , a profit-maximizing firm will always choose y 1 so that
future as well as for the present. Then there is a time constraint for py1 :::: pO = O; therefore, atan equilibrium in which firms maximize
each period. profits, it could have been assumed equally well that the firms are
For subsequent purposes this' detailed description of the consump- incorporated, with limited liability for stockholders.
tion possibility set will be used only as informal justification for The alm of the household is to choose the most preferred point
certain axioms. The set has been characterized as the set of non- among the commodity vectors available to it at a given set of prices
negative vectors that, in addition, satisfy certain inequalities. It is and a given income. Its preferences are, as usual, assumed to be
easy to verify that the set of vectors x,., which satisfy these inequalities, defined by an ordering of al! commodity vectors in its consumption
1s convex. possibility set. The following assumptions will be made:
76 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
!
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 77

"bus-driving leisure" 12 hours. The conventions u sed imply the AssuMPTION l. The consumption possibility set Xh for individual h
constraints is closed and convex; xlt :::: O for xlt E Xh.
(i EL). Note that the time constraints are satisfied with strict inequality
if Xht = .Xht (i EL), Xht = O (i 1 L). Then we can choose a, O < a <
If xht < .Xht (i EL), then the individual is supplying labor of type i in
1, so that the time constraints are satisfied by the vector x" defined
the amount .Xht - Xht lf Xht > .X", then the individual is a net
by Xht = a.Xht (i EL), Xht = O (i 1 L). Then certainly
demander of labor of type i in the amount Xht - .Xht; the second case
might arise, for example, for domestic or repair services. In the xhi :::; .xht all i,
notation introduced in Chapter 3, the net supply of labor of type i by X~tt < X~tt if Xnt > O.
household h is (xht - .Xht)-, the net demand is (xht - Xnt) +.
This argument justifies the assumption,
The amount of all types of labor that can be supplied is constrained
not merely by capabilities, but also by the scarcity oftime itself. We AssuMPTION 2. There exists a possible consumption vector x" X",
E

have not specified in what units labor is measured, so let Tht be the such that
amount of time that labor activity i requires per unit. (Ordinarily, xhi :::; .x,, all i,
we measure labor by time, so that Tht = 1, but it might be measured Xnt < .X!tt if .Xitt >O,
in terms of tasks performed, for example.) There is sorne limit Ton
the amount of time in the period under analysis (e.g., 24 hours in a
where xlt is the initial endowment for household h.
day), so that the total labor supplied cannot exceed T; The income. of a household is assumed to derive from two sources:
the sale of the initial endowment and the share held by the household
2 Tht(Xht - .x,,;)- :::; T. in the profits of firms. lt is assumed that household h owns a
iEL
fraction, dhf, of firmf and shares to that extent in the profits. Of
It is al so true that at least so me types of consumption of goods (other course, d1, 1 must be non-negative, though it may be zero, and for
than types of leisure) require time. Let Tht be the amount of time each firm the total amount of profits is allocated to different house-
required to consume a unit of good i (i 1 L); Jet T~t be the amount of holds.
time required to consume the services of a unit of labor of type i. AssuMPTION 3. For each household h the total income Mh at any set
Then the time constraint becomes of prices p and any given set of production decisions y1 is given by

M" = px" + 2 dh!(PY) where dlt 1 :::: O, 2 dltf =


h
l.
f

Later on, the general equilibrium model will be reinterpreted to apply As stated, A.4.3 implies that each firm is a partnership, since the
to many time periods simultaneously. The individuals are assumed household shares in losses as well as profits. However, since
to make their labor and consumption choices simltaneously for the O E Y1 , a profit-maximizing firm will always choose y 1 so that
future as well as for the present. Then there is a time constraint for py1 :::: pO = O; therefore, atan equilibrium in which firms maximize
each period. profits, it could have been assumed equally well that the firms are
For subsequent purposes this' detailed description of the consump- incorporated, with limited liability for stockholders.
tion possibility set will be used only as informal justification for The alm of the household is to choose the most preferred point
certain axioms. The set has been characterized as the set of non- among the commodity vectors available to it at a given set of prices
negative vectors that, in addition, satisfy certain inequalities. It is and a given income. Its preferences are, as usual, assumed to be
easy to verify that the set of vectors x,., which satisfy these inequalities, defined by an ordering of al! commodity vectors in its consumption
1s convex. possibility set. The following assumptions will be made:
78 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 79
AssUMPTION 4. Por each h, there is a relation, >n (interpreted must contain xk by definition of a closed set; that is, x~ >h xk,
"preferred or indifferent "), for pairs of elements in the consumption contrary to the assumption xli >-" x~.
possibility set, Xn, with the following properties: The assumption (d) of convexity is, as always, something of a
(a) Transitivity: stumbling block; it will be seen in Chapter 7 that it can be relaxed.
The semi-strictness condition is designed to avoid local satiation, as
xk >n x~ and x~ >n x~ imply xk >h x~; shown by the following lemma.
(b) Connexity:
LEMMA l. (a) Local non-satiation: For every xli E X" there exists
Por all xk and x~ in X~, either x~ >h x~ or x~ >n xk; x~ E Xn arbitrarily close to xli for which x~ >-/ x~.
(e) Continuity: (b) Convexity: For any x~, the set {x" 1x" >" x~} is convex.
1
Por any given x~, the sets {xh 1 X~ >h x~} Proof. (a) By A.4.4(e), there exists x~ >- x/i. By (d), x~ =
(1 - a)x~ + exx/i >-" x~ forO :::; ex < l. For ex arbitrarily el ose to 1,
and {xh 1 x~ :P:h X~} are closed;
xr can be made arbitrarily close to xk.
(d) Semi-strict convexity: '(b) Let xli and x~ E {x" 1 x" >" x~}, and let x" = (1 - a)x~ -:
If xk >-n x~ andO .:::;; ex < 1, then (1 - ex)xk + exx~ >-h x~; exx~, O :::; ex :::; l. We seek to prove that x" > 0
X, for all ex. Th1s IS
trivial if ex = O or 1, so assume O < ex < l. From A.4.4(b), assume
(e) Non-satiation: without loss of generality that xk >" x~. Choose x;;' so that
x* >- x 1 x* arbitrarily el ose to xk. Then x~ >-" x~ by transitivity
There is no X~ such that X~ >=h Xn for all X~ E xh. /
and A.4.4(b). Let x;;'* = (1 - ex)x;;' + exx~. By A.4.4(d), x" >-"
h h "' **
x~, and by transitivity, x;;'* >-h x~, and, in particular, x;;'* E {x" 1~"
The notation >- h used in (d) is defined by ;p:" x~}. Since x; is arbitrarily close to xJi, x;;'* can be chosen arb!-
xk >-h x~ means xk:P:n x~ and not x~ >n xk; trarily close to x". Hence, x, is a limit point of the set {xh Xn :P:"
1

x~}; by continuity (A.4.4(c)) Xn belongs to this set.


that is, xk >- x~ means that xk is preferred to x~. In view of
Connexity (b), Analogous to the choice of production vectors in the profit-
xJi >-h x~ if and only if not x~ >n xk. maximizing firm, there is a choice of preferred consumption vectors
by the household. We will speak of a preferred vector for a given
The assumptions of A.4.4 are fairly stanuard. Parts (a) and (b) set S e X" as a vector :X,, such that :X" E S and Xn :P:" X~ for all
state simply that the individual is capable of ranking alternative x" E S. The demand functions or their generalizations are the
commodity vectors in order of preference. Part (e) and the term preferred vectors x" E X" for the set satisfying the budget constraint,
"continuity". attached to it, may be slightly less familiar. The
preference ordering is assumed to be continuous in the sense that a px,:::; Mn.
strict preference between two vectors is not altered if either is As in the case of the firm, no preferred vector need exist; suppose
altered by sufficiently small amounts; in symbols, if xJi >-n xn, then the price of a commodity is zero and the household is never satiated
there are neighborhoods, N 1 and N 2 , of xk and x~, respectively, such with regard to that commodity. Further, it is also possible that
that X~ >- h x~ for all x" E N 1 and xk >- h Xn for all Xn E N 2 there is not a unique preferred point; there may be a set of com-
This statement is equivalent to A.4.4(c). Suppose, for example, modity vectors satisfying the budget constraint, indifferent to each
there was no such neighborhood, N 1 Then in every neighborhood other and preferred to all other bundles in Xn satisfying the budget
of xli there would exist Xn such that x~ :P:h x", that is, a member of constraint. This possibility requires that the indifference surfaces
the set {xa 1 x~ :P:" x,}. Since (e) asserts that this set is closed, it ha ve flat sections, as, for example, when two commodities are perfect '
1'

i:
78 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 79
AssUMPTION 4. Por each h, there is a relation, >n (interpreted must contain xk by definition of a closed set; that is, x~ >h xk,
"preferred or indifferent "), for pairs of elements in the consumption contrary to the assumption xli >-" x~.
possibility set, Xn, with the following properties: The assumption (d) of convexity is, as always, something of a
(a) Transitivity: stumbling block; it will be seen in Chapter 7 that it can be relaxed.
The semi-strictness condition is designed to avoid local satiation, as
xk >n x~ and x~ >n x~ imply xk >h x~; shown by the following lemma.
(b) Connexity:
LEMMA l. (a) Local non-satiation: For every xli E X" there exists
Por all xk and x~ in X~, either x~ >h x~ or x~ >n xk; x~ E Xn arbitrarily close to xli for which x~ >-/ x~.
(e) Continuity: (b) Convexity: For any x~, the set {x" 1x" >" x~} is convex.
1
Por any given x~, the sets {xh 1 X~ >h x~} Proof. (a) By A.4.4(e), there exists x~ >- x/i. By (d), x~ =
(1 - a)x~ + exx/i >-" x~ forO :::; ex < l. For ex arbitrarily el ose to 1,
and {xh 1 x~ :P:h X~} are closed;
xr can be made arbitrarily close to xk.
(d) Semi-strict convexity: '(b) Let xli and x~ E {x" 1 x" >" x~}, and let x" = (1 - a)x~ -:
If xk >-n x~ andO .:::;; ex < 1, then (1 - ex)xk + exx~ >-h x~; exx~, O :::; ex :::; l. We seek to prove that x" > 0
X, for all ex. Th1s IS
trivial if ex = O or 1, so assume O < ex < l. From A.4.4(b), assume
(e) Non-satiation: without loss of generality that xk >" x~. Choose x;;' so that
x* >- x 1 x* arbitrarily el ose to xk. Then x~ >-" x~ by transitivity
There is no X~ such that X~ >=h Xn for all X~ E xh. /
and A.4.4(b). Let x;;'* = (1 - ex)x;;' + exx~. By A.4.4(d), x" >-"
h h "' **
x~, and by transitivity, x;;'* >-h x~, and, in particular, x;;'* E {x" 1~"
The notation >- h used in (d) is defined by ;p:" x~}. Since x; is arbitrarily close to xJi, x;;'* can be chosen arb!-
xk >-h x~ means xk:P:n x~ and not x~ >n xk; trarily close to x". Hence, x, is a limit point of the set {xh Xn :P:"
1

x~}; by continuity (A.4.4(c)) Xn belongs to this set.


that is, xk >- x~ means that xk is preferred to x~. In view of
Connexity (b), Analogous to the choice of production vectors in the profit-
xJi >-h x~ if and only if not x~ >n xk. maximizing firm, there is a choice of preferred consumption vectors
by the household. We will speak of a preferred vector for a given
The assumptions of A.4.4 are fairly stanuard. Parts (a) and (b) set S e X" as a vector :X,, such that :X" E S and Xn :P:" X~ for all
state simply that the individual is capable of ranking alternative x" E S. The demand functions or their generalizations are the
commodity vectors in order of preference. Part (e) and the term preferred vectors x" E X" for the set satisfying the budget constraint,
"continuity". attached to it, may be slightly less familiar. The
preference ordering is assumed to be continuous in the sense that a px,:::; Mn.
strict preference between two vectors is not altered if either is As in the case of the firm, no preferred vector need exist; suppose
altered by sufficiently small amounts; in symbols, if xJi >-n xn, then the price of a commodity is zero and the household is never satiated
there are neighborhoods, N 1 and N 2 , of xk and x~, respectively, such with regard to that commodity. Further, it is also possible that
that X~ >- h x~ for all x" E N 1 and xk >- h Xn for all Xn E N 2 there is not a unique preferred point; there may be a set of com-
This statement is equivalent to A.4.4(c). Suppose, for example, modity vectors satisfying the budget constraint, indifferent to each
there was no such neighborhood, N 1 Then in every neighborhood other and preferred to all other bundles in Xn satisfying the budget
of xli there would exist Xn such that x~ :P:h x", that is, a member of constraint. This possibility requires that the indifference surfaces
the set {xa 1 x~ :P:" x,}. Since (e) asserts that this set is closed, it ha ve flat sections, as, for example, when two commodities are perfect '
1'

i:
80 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

substitutes or when one commodity does not enter into consumption


1
1

1
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 81

1
LEMMA 2. If x;!' is a preferred vector subject to a budget constraint,
at all. px" :s; M, x" E X 1., then x;!' minimizes px" subject to the constraint
Remark. If p > O, as we shall assume, and py1 ;::: O, all j, then x" >" x;!'.
the possible consumption vector, X, whose existence was guaranteed Proof. Suppose the conclusion is false. Then there exists
by A.4.2, obviously satisfies the budget constraint. Thus, in any com- >"
xk x;!', for which pxk < px;!'. By local non-satiation (Lemma
petitive equilibrium, we can as sume that the individual will achieve a 4.1(a)), there exists x~ arbitrarily close to xk, for which x~ xk and,>h
satisfaction (in terms of the ordering about to be introduced) at least therefore, x~ >"
xt. By choosing x~ close enough to xk we can
as high as that achievable fromx. guarantee px~ :s; px;!' :s; M, which contradicts the hypothesis that
x;!' is pref~rred in the budget constraint.
To ensure the existence of equilibrium, the demand for com- The converse of Lemma 4.2 is valid only if expenditures are above
modities should vary continuously with the prices, in sorne appro- the mnimum possible.
priate sense of continuity. The hypotheses made do not ensure this
result. Suppose there are two goods in the economy, and an LEMMA 3. If x;!' minimizes px subject to the constraint X x~ >h
individual has an initial stock of good 1, but none of good 2 and no and if px;!' > pxk for so me xk E X, then x;!' is preferred in the budget
constraint, px :s; px;!'.
share of any firm. Hold the price of good 2 constant, and Jet p 1
approach O. The budget constraint requires that Proof. Consider any x~ E X for which px~ :s; px;!'. Let
X(a) = (1 - a)x~ + axk;
then
so that for p 1 > O, X 1 :s; X 1 . On the other hand, when p 1 = O, the px(a) = (1 - a)px~ + apxk < px;!' forO < a :s; l.
set of commodity vectors compatible with the budget constraint is
the set of all pairs, (X 1 ,0), and the chosen value of X 1 ' may, be If X(a) >h
x~, then by hypothesis, px; :s; px(a). Hence, x~ )>
considerably Iarger than .X 1 This discontinuity will necessarily x"(a) and, therefore, X( a) E {xh x~ >"X}. Since this last set is
1

occur in sorne part of the price space, except in the unrealistic closed, it contains lim X( a) = x~. Since x;!'
a->0
x~, x;!' >h
x~ for any >"
case in which the household has a positive initial holding of all x~ for which px~ :s; px;!'.
goods.
In fact, the failure of the compensated demand functions to agree
On the other hand, there is another optimization problem that is
with the uncompensated functions on the boundary of the price
very similar to choice of the preferred point under a budget con-
domain is useful, for it can be shown that the compensated demand
straint, but for which the chosen point varies, in an appropriate
functions are continuous in an appropriate sense. Since these
sense, continuously with prices. This is the problem of choosing X
functions may be multi-valued, as we have seen, we need a broader
to minimize the cost of achieving a given leve! of satisfaction, or
concept of continuity. A multi-valued function will be called a
formally, minimizing px subject to the constraint that X >h x~ for
correspondence; we define the correspondence <P(x) to be upper semi-
sorne prescribed x~. The chosen bundle is usually known in eco- continuous if for any sequences {xv}, {yv}, the conditions xv-+ x,
nomic Iiterature as the compensated demand function, since real yv-+ y, yv E cp(xv), imply that y E <D(x).
income (leve! of satisfaction) is held constant, we imagine, by
Also, defining the compensated demand correspondence, X(p,x~) =
accompanying each change of price vector with a change of nominal
{x~ x~ minimizes px subject to X E X, X>" x~}.
1

income so that the commodity vector indifferent to the original one


can be achieved. LEMMA 4. X(p,x~) is upper semi-continuous in p for fixed x~.
,,,
The uncompensated and compensated demand functions are Proof. Let {pv} be a sequence with pv-+ p; suppose x); E
'1'"
closely related. X"(pv,x~) and x)'-+ X. Then x)' >h
x~, all v, and by continuity of
.',,,
/'
1
1

1''

11 ,11
11,
80 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

substitutes or when one commodity does not enter into consumption


1
1

1
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 81

1
LEMMA 2. If x;!' is a preferred vector subject to a budget constraint,
at all. px" :s; M, x" E X 1., then x;!' minimizes px" subject to the constraint
Remark. If p > O, as we shall assume, and py1 ;::: O, all j, then x" >" x;!'.
the possible consumption vector, X, whose existence was guaranteed Proof. Suppose the conclusion is false. Then there exists
by A.4.2, obviously satisfies the budget constraint. Thus, in any com- >"
xk x;!', for which pxk < px;!'. By local non-satiation (Lemma
petitive equilibrium, we can as sume that the individual will achieve a 4.1(a)), there exists x~ arbitrarily close to xk, for which x~ xk and,>h
satisfaction (in terms of the ordering about to be introduced) at least therefore, x~ >"
xt. By choosing x~ close enough to xk we can
as high as that achievable fromx. guarantee px~ :s; px;!' :s; M, which contradicts the hypothesis that
x;!' is pref~rred in the budget constraint.
To ensure the existence of equilibrium, the demand for com- The converse of Lemma 4.2 is valid only if expenditures are above
modities should vary continuously with the prices, in sorne appro- the mnimum possible.
priate sense of continuity. The hypotheses made do not ensure this
result. Suppose there are two goods in the economy, and an LEMMA 3. If x;!' minimizes px subject to the constraint X x~ >h
individual has an initial stock of good 1, but none of good 2 and no and if px;!' > pxk for so me xk E X, then x;!' is preferred in the budget
constraint, px :s; px;!'.
share of any firm. Hold the price of good 2 constant, and Jet p 1
approach O. The budget constraint requires that Proof. Consider any x~ E X for which px~ :s; px;!'. Let
X(a) = (1 - a)x~ + axk;
then
so that for p 1 > O, X 1 :s; X 1 . On the other hand, when p 1 = O, the px(a) = (1 - a)px~ + apxk < px;!' forO < a :s; l.
set of commodity vectors compatible with the budget constraint is
the set of all pairs, (X 1 ,0), and the chosen value of X 1 ' may, be If X(a) >h
x~, then by hypothesis, px; :s; px(a). Hence, x~ )>
considerably Iarger than .X 1 This discontinuity will necessarily x"(a) and, therefore, X( a) E {xh x~ >"X}. Since this last set is
1

occur in sorne part of the price space, except in the unrealistic closed, it contains lim X( a) = x~. Since x;!'
a->0
x~, x;!' >h
x~ for any >"
case in which the household has a positive initial holding of all x~ for which px~ :s; px;!'.
goods.
In fact, the failure of the compensated demand functions to agree
On the other hand, there is another optimization problem that is
with the uncompensated functions on the boundary of the price
very similar to choice of the preferred point under a budget con-
domain is useful, for it can be shown that the compensated demand
straint, but for which the chosen point varies, in an appropriate
functions are continuous in an appropriate sense. Since these
sense, continuously with prices. This is the problem of choosing X
functions may be multi-valued, as we have seen, we need a broader
to minimize the cost of achieving a given leve! of satisfaction, or
concept of continuity. A multi-valued function will be called a
formally, minimizing px subject to the constraint that X >h x~ for
correspondence; we define the correspondence <P(x) to be upper semi-
sorne prescribed x~. The chosen bundle is usually known in eco- continuous if for any sequences {xv}, {yv}, the conditions xv-+ x,
nomic Iiterature as the compensated demand function, since real yv-+ y, yv E cp(xv), imply that y E <D(x).
income (leve! of satisfaction) is held constant, we imagine, by
Also, defining the compensated demand correspondence, X(p,x~) =
accompanying each change of price vector with a change of nominal
{x~ x~ minimizes px subject to X E X, X>" x~}.
1

income so that the commodity vector indifferent to the original one


can be achieved. LEMMA 4. X(p,x~) is upper semi-continuous in p for fixed x~.
,,,
The uncompensated and compensated demand functions are Proof. Let {pv} be a sequence with pv-+ p; suppose x); E
'1'"
closely related. X"(pv,x~) and x)'-+ X. Then x)' >h
x~, all v, and by continuity of
.',,,
/'
1
1

1''

11 ,11
11,
,r-;

82 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS


T CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 83
11 . ~ preferences, x, ~" xW. Take any x~ such that x~ ~" xW. Then, by of x, U(x), is taken to be the distance from x 0 to the set of points
definition of X,.(pv,xg), pvx; ::::; pvx~. In the limit, px,. ::::; px~.
1
; 1

ill preferred or indifferent to x. (By the distance from a point to a set


'
Q.E.D. is meant the smallest distance from the given point to any point of
We will not in fact make use of Lemma 4.4 as it stands, but it the set.)
motivates the strategy for proving the existence of competitive Then let
equilibrium used in Chapter 5. It is easier to establish the existence C(x) = {x' J x' ~ x}
of an equilibrium in a compensated sense because the compensated
demand correspondences are continuous; then it has to be shown be the upper contour set through x. By A.4.4(c), this set is closed.
(with the aid of an additional assumption) that the compensated Let p(x) = Jx - x 0 J, the distance from x 0 to x. Since p(x') is a
equilibrium assigns each individual an expenditure above the continuous function bounded from below (it is non-negative) and
minimal possible, so that the individual is in fact achieving a pre- C(x) is closed, p(x') has a mnimum as x' vares over C(x). We
define
ferred point under the budget constraint.
U(x) = min p(x), (1)
X'EG(X)

1 ,,
2. Utility Functions
and we will show that U(x) is indeed a continuous utility function.
It turns out that the assumption A.4.4 made on the preference The mnimum in (1) is taken on at one or more points of C(x); let
relation suffices to permit a continuous numerical representation.
M(x) = C(x) n{x' / p(x') = U(x)}. (2)
DEFINITION l. A real-valued function, uh, defined on x,, is a
utility function if it has the property that xk ~" x~ if and only if Since M(x) e C(x), clearly x' ~ x for all x' E M(x). In fact, it
U11(xk) ;::: U11 (x~). must be that x' "' x. Suppose that x' E M(x), x' >- x. There is,
by Continuity, a neighborhood of x' such that x" ~ x for all x" in
The numerical representation, although it can be d'spehsed with, the neighborhood. Choose a > O, but sufficiently small so that
is extremely useful in simplifying the proofs. (1 - a)x' + ax 0 ~ x; in particular, choose a < l. But
Since we are dealing with a single household in this section, we
will omit the subscript h in all uses in order to lighten the notational p[(1 - a)x' + ax~] = /(1 - a)x' + ax 0 - x 0 J
burden. Also, for the purpose of establishing the existence of a = (1 - a)Jx' - x 0 J = (1 - a)p(x') = (1 - a)U(x).
continuous utility function, we will not need the full force of A.4.4, By definition (1), U(x) ::::; p[(l - a)x' + ax 0 ], so that (1 - a)U(x) ;:::
only assumptions (a), (b), and (e) (transitivity, connexity, and U(x) or U(x) ::::; O. Since U(x) has been defined to be non-negative,
continuity). U(x) = O. Therefore p(x') = O, or x' = x 0 Since we are con-
The two assumptions that play the most important roles in sidering only x ~ x 0 , however, the assumption x' >- x has been
demonstrating the existence of a numerical representation are the contradicted.
continuity ofthe ordering (A.4.4(c)) and the convexity of X (actually,
the latter could be replaced by the much weaker assumption that any If x' E M(x), then x' "' x. (3)
two points in X could be connected by a continuous path entirely To show that U(x) is a utility function, it suffices by D.4.1 and
contained in X; for a convex set, the line segment joining two given Connexity, A.4.4(b), to show that x 1 ~ x 2 implies U(x 1 ) ;::: U(x 2 )
points is such a path). . and that x 1 >- x 2 implies U(x 1 ) > U(x 2 ). The first follows immedi-
First, a utility function is constructed for a subset of X. ~pecfi ately from the definition of U(x), (1), and Transitivity (A.4.4(a));
cally an arbitrary element, x 0 E X, is chosen, and a contmuous Transitivity implies that C(x 1) e C(x 2), the minimization in (1)
utilit~ function is constructed for the subset of X for which x ~. ~ 0 occurs over a subset, and hence the mnimum achieved cannot be
The method is simple: For any x satisfying this condition, the utlhty any lower. Now suppose that x 1 >- x 2 . Then M(x 1) e C(x 1 ) e
,r-;

82 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS


T CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 83
11 . ~ preferences, x, ~" xW. Take any x~ such that x~ ~" xW. Then, by of x, U(x), is taken to be the distance from x 0 to the set of points
definition of X,.(pv,xg), pvx; ::::; pvx~. In the limit, px,. ::::; px~.
1
; 1

ill preferred or indifferent to x. (By the distance from a point to a set


'
Q.E.D. is meant the smallest distance from the given point to any point of
We will not in fact make use of Lemma 4.4 as it stands, but it the set.)
motivates the strategy for proving the existence of competitive Then let
equilibrium used in Chapter 5. It is easier to establish the existence C(x) = {x' J x' ~ x}
of an equilibrium in a compensated sense because the compensated
demand correspondences are continuous; then it has to be shown be the upper contour set through x. By A.4.4(c), this set is closed.
(with the aid of an additional assumption) that the compensated Let p(x) = Jx - x 0 J, the distance from x 0 to x. Since p(x') is a
equilibrium assigns each individual an expenditure above the continuous function bounded from below (it is non-negative) and
minimal possible, so that the individual is in fact achieving a pre- C(x) is closed, p(x') has a mnimum as x' vares over C(x). We
define
ferred point under the budget constraint.
U(x) = min p(x), (1)
X'EG(X)

1 ,,
2. Utility Functions
and we will show that U(x) is indeed a continuous utility function.
It turns out that the assumption A.4.4 made on the preference The mnimum in (1) is taken on at one or more points of C(x); let
relation suffices to permit a continuous numerical representation.
M(x) = C(x) n{x' / p(x') = U(x)}. (2)
DEFINITION l. A real-valued function, uh, defined on x,, is a
utility function if it has the property that xk ~" x~ if and only if Since M(x) e C(x), clearly x' ~ x for all x' E M(x). In fact, it
U11(xk) ;::: U11 (x~). must be that x' "' x. Suppose that x' E M(x), x' >- x. There is,
by Continuity, a neighborhood of x' such that x" ~ x for all x" in
The numerical representation, although it can be d'spehsed with, the neighborhood. Choose a > O, but sufficiently small so that
is extremely useful in simplifying the proofs. (1 - a)x' + ax 0 ~ x; in particular, choose a < l. But
Since we are dealing with a single household in this section, we
will omit the subscript h in all uses in order to lighten the notational p[(1 - a)x' + ax~] = /(1 - a)x' + ax 0 - x 0 J
burden. Also, for the purpose of establishing the existence of a = (1 - a)Jx' - x 0 J = (1 - a)p(x') = (1 - a)U(x).
continuous utility function, we will not need the full force of A.4.4, By definition (1), U(x) ::::; p[(l - a)x' + ax 0 ], so that (1 - a)U(x) ;:::
only assumptions (a), (b), and (e) (transitivity, connexity, and U(x) or U(x) ::::; O. Since U(x) has been defined to be non-negative,
continuity). U(x) = O. Therefore p(x') = O, or x' = x 0 Since we are con-
The two assumptions that play the most important roles in sidering only x ~ x 0 , however, the assumption x' >- x has been
demonstrating the existence of a numerical representation are the contradicted.
continuity ofthe ordering (A.4.4(c)) and the convexity of X (actually,
the latter could be replaced by the much weaker assumption that any If x' E M(x), then x' "' x. (3)
two points in X could be connected by a continuous path entirely To show that U(x) is a utility function, it suffices by D.4.1 and
contained in X; for a convex set, the line segment joining two given Connexity, A.4.4(b), to show that x 1 ~ x 2 implies U(x 1 ) ;::: U(x 2 )
points is such a path). . and that x 1 >- x 2 implies U(x 1 ) > U(x 2 ). The first follows immedi-
First, a utility function is constructed for a subset of X. ~pecfi ately from the definition of U(x), (1), and Transitivity (A.4.4(a));
cally an arbitrary element, x 0 E X, is chosen, and a contmuous Transitivity implies that C(x 1) e C(x 2), the minimization in (1)
utilit~ function is constructed for the subset of X for which x ~. ~ 0 occurs over a subset, and hence the mnimum achieved cannot be
The method is simple: For any x satisfying this condition, the utlhty any lower. Now suppose that x 1 >- x 2 . Then M(x 1) e C(x 1 ) e
84 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 85
C(x 2). If U(x 1) = U(x 2), then M(x 1) e M(x 2), by (2). If x' E
M(x 1), then by (3), x' "' x 1 and also x' "' x 2 , so that x 1 "' x 2 , a con- Now Iet X 1 be any compact subset of X and X" any finite subset of
tradiction. Since we know that U(x 1) ;;:; U(x 2) and ha ve just shown X'. By Transitivity, we see that
that U(x 1 ) #- U(x 2 ), it must be that U(x 1) > U(x 2 ). Therefore U(x) X' n{x' 1 x" :P:: x'} e X' n{x' 1 x :P:: x'} for all x E X 1',
is a utility function for those x E X for which x :p:: x 0
To demonstrate that U(x) is a continuous function, it suffices to or equivalently,
show that for every real number u, the two sets {x J U(x) ;:::: u} and
{x 1 U(x) s u} are closed. Consider the first set. Let {xv} be a X' n{x' 1 x" >== x'} =
XEX"
n [X' n{x' 1 X>== x'}];
sequence such that U(xv) ;:::: u, aii v, xv--. x. Let x'' be any element
of M(x); by Lemma 4.l(a), we can choose x" >- x' and arbitrarily that is, the set of consumption vectors x' in X' not superior to x"
close. Certainly, U(x") ::::; p(x"), by(!). On the other hand, since is the intersection of the sets of consumption vectors not superior to
x" :P:: x' and . x' "' x, by (3), x" >- x. By Continuity, x" :p:: xv for aii the various members of X". Since X 1' belongs to the left-hand set, we
v sufficiently large, U(x") ;:::: U(xv) ;:::: u, so that p(x") ;:::: u. But x" see that the intersection on the right is non-null. The sets
can be chosen as el ose as desired to x'; since p(x) is continuous, we X' n{x' 1 x :P:: x'}
can assert that u ::::; p(x') = U(x), so that the set {x 1 U(x) ;:::: u} has
been shown to be closed. are compact sets. If we consider the entire family of such sets as
, Now let {xv} be any sequence such that U(xv) ::::; u, aii v, xv--. x. x vares over X', it has been shown that the intersection of any
For each v, choose x'v E M(x'). Since p(x'') = U(xv), we have that finite subfamily is non-null. By a well-known theorem of analysis,
p(x'') s u, aii v. Thus, the sequence {x''} is bounded and therefore it follows that the intersection of all such sets is non-null, so that there
has a limit point x', for which p(x') ::::; u. Since x'v "' xv, by (3) and exists x* such that,
xv ->- x, it foilows, by restricting attention to the subsequence of
x* E X' n{x' 1 x :p:: X 1
} for all x in X',
{x'v} that converges to x', that x' "' x, where use is made of the
Continuity of preferences. Then by definition of U(x) and the fact and therefore x :P:: x* for aii x E X', x* E X'.
that it is a utility function, In particular, for any fixed positive integer /1-, the set X n
U(x) = U(x') ::::; p(x') ::::; u,
{x [lxl ::; P-} is compact; it is non-null for aii 11- sufficiently large.
By (4), it has a least preferred point, x 0 ~". Further, since
so that the set {x 1 U(x) ::::; u} is indeed closed, and therefore, U(x)
is a continuous utility function over the set {x 1 x :p:: x 0 }.
Xn {x [lxl : : ; P-} e Xn {x [lxl : : ; 11- + 1},
It remains to extend U(x) in sorne appropriate way to the entire it must be true that x 011 :p:: x 0 11 + 1 for all 11-
consumption possibility set, X. If there is a least preferred point, Since we are now assuming that X has no least preferred point, it
that is, a point x 0 such that x :P:: x 0 for aii x E X, then simply choose is true that for every 11- there exists an x E X such that x 0 ~" >- x. By
0
x in the previous construction. Otherwise, for every x E X, there construction, it must be that /x/ > 11- For any 11-' ;:::: /x/, x 0 ~"' <. x,
exists x' E X such that x >- x', and we consider this case. It will be by construction. Now define 11-(v) recursively as follows:
shown next that
11-(l) = min{P-[ Xn {x [ /xl : : ; P-} is non-null},
Any compact non-null subset of X contains 11-(v + 1) = min{P- / x 0 u(v) >- x 0 ~"}.
a least preferred point.
By the previous discussion, 11-(v + 1) ;:::: 11-(v) + 1, so that 11-(v) ;:::: v;
To see this, consider first any finite subset X" of X. Then by and in particular 11-(v) ->- +oo. Define
Transitivity, there certainly exists a least preferred point x" of X".
84 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 85
C(x 2). If U(x 1) = U(x 2), then M(x 1) e M(x 2), by (2). If x' E
M(x 1), then by (3), x' "' x 1 and also x' "' x 2 , so that x 1 "' x 2 , a con- Now Iet X 1 be any compact subset of X and X" any finite subset of
tradiction. Since we know that U(x 1) ;;:; U(x 2) and ha ve just shown X'. By Transitivity, we see that
that U(x 1 ) #- U(x 2 ), it must be that U(x 1) > U(x 2 ). Therefore U(x) X' n{x' 1 x" :P:: x'} e X' n{x' 1 x :P:: x'} for all x E X 1',
is a utility function for those x E X for which x :p:: x 0
To demonstrate that U(x) is a continuous function, it suffices to or equivalently,
show that for every real number u, the two sets {x J U(x) ;:::: u} and
{x 1 U(x) s u} are closed. Consider the first set. Let {xv} be a X' n{x' 1 x" >== x'} =
XEX"
n [X' n{x' 1 X>== x'}];
sequence such that U(xv) ;:::: u, aii v, xv--. x. Let x'' be any element
of M(x); by Lemma 4.l(a), we can choose x" >- x' and arbitrarily that is, the set of consumption vectors x' in X' not superior to x"
close. Certainly, U(x") ::::; p(x"), by(!). On the other hand, since is the intersection of the sets of consumption vectors not superior to
x" :P:: x' and . x' "' x, by (3), x" >- x. By Continuity, x" :p:: xv for aii the various members of X". Since X 1' belongs to the left-hand set, we
v sufficiently large, U(x") ;:::: U(xv) ;:::: u, so that p(x") ;:::: u. But x" see that the intersection on the right is non-null. The sets
can be chosen as el ose as desired to x'; since p(x) is continuous, we X' n{x' 1 x :P:: x'}
can assert that u ::::; p(x') = U(x), so that the set {x 1 U(x) ;:::: u} has
been shown to be closed. are compact sets. If we consider the entire family of such sets as
, Now let {xv} be any sequence such that U(xv) ::::; u, aii v, xv--. x. x vares over X', it has been shown that the intersection of any
For each v, choose x'v E M(x'). Since p(x'') = U(xv), we have that finite subfamily is non-null. By a well-known theorem of analysis,
p(x'') s u, aii v. Thus, the sequence {x''} is bounded and therefore it follows that the intersection of all such sets is non-null, so that there
has a limit point x', for which p(x') ::::; u. Since x'v "' xv, by (3) and exists x* such that,
xv ->- x, it foilows, by restricting attention to the subsequence of
x* E X' n{x' 1 x :p:: X 1
} for all x in X',
{x'v} that converges to x', that x' "' x, where use is made of the
Continuity of preferences. Then by definition of U(x) and the fact and therefore x :P:: x* for aii x E X', x* E X'.
that it is a utility function, In particular, for any fixed positive integer /1-, the set X n
U(x) = U(x') ::::; p(x') ::::; u,
{x [lxl ::; P-} is compact; it is non-null for aii 11- sufficiently large.
By (4), it has a least preferred point, x 0 ~". Further, since
so that the set {x 1 U(x) ::::; u} is indeed closed, and therefore, U(x)
is a continuous utility function over the set {x 1 x :p:: x 0 }.
Xn {x [lxl : : ; P-} e Xn {x [lxl : : ; 11- + 1},
It remains to extend U(x) in sorne appropriate way to the entire it must be true that x 011 :p:: x 0 11 + 1 for all 11-
consumption possibility set, X. If there is a least preferred point, Since we are now assuming that X has no least preferred point, it
that is, a point x 0 such that x :P:: x 0 for aii x E X, then simply choose is true that for every 11- there exists an x E X such that x 0 ~" >- x. By
0
x in the previous construction. Otherwise, for every x E X, there construction, it must be that /x/ > 11- For any 11-' ;:::: /x/, x 0 ~"' <. x,
exists x' E X such that x >- x', and we consider this case. It will be by construction. Now define 11-(v) recursively as follows:
shown next that
11-(l) = min{P-[ Xn {x [ /xl : : ; P-} is non-null},
Any compact non-null subset of X contains 11-(v + 1) = min{P- / x 0 u(v) >- x 0 ~"}.
a least preferred point.
By the previous discussion, 11-(v + 1) ;:::: 11-(v) + 1, so that 11-(v) ;:::: v;
To see this, consider first any finite subset X" of X. Then by and in particular 11-(v) ->- +oo. Define
Transitivity, there certainly exists a least preferred point x" of X".
86 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 87

then xv >- xv+ 1. Further, for any x E X, x:;:,: x 0 tt for p, :::-: lxl; there- Continuity, so that U(x') = U1(x') or Uv(x') in a neighborhood of x;
fore, for any x E X, x :;:,: xv for all v sufficiently large. since the functions Uv(x) are continuous at x, so is U(x).
The sequence {xv} has two basic properties: It is strictly decreasing Now suppose x "' xv for so me v. Let {xP} be a sequence such that
in preference, xv >- xv+ 1 for all v, and every x E X is preferred or xP ->- x. If xP :;:,: x, all p, then xv - 1 >- xP for p sufficiently large, if
indifferent to xv for all v sufficiently large. v > 1. Hence, U(xP) = Uv(xP) for p large; by continuity of Uv(x),
We can take in turn each xv as the x 0 of our earlier construction Uv(xP) ->- Uv(x) = U(x). Similarly, if x >- xP for all p, xP :;:,: xv +1
and find a continuous utility function for the set {x 1 x :;:,: xv}. Let for p sufficiently large, U(xP) = Uv+ 1 (xP) for p large, and U(xP)--.
U(x;xv) be this utility function. As is well known and obvious, if Uv+l(x) = Uv+ 1(xv) = Uv = U(x). Finally, if the sequence {xP}
U is a utility function and F(u) is a strictly increasing function on contains some members inferior to x and others not inferior, we can
the real numbers, then F[U(x)] is also a utility function in the sense divide it into two sequences, for each of which U(xP) converges to
of D.4.l. If F is continuous, then sois F[U(x)]. In particular, if U(x).
F(u) = a + bu, b > O, then a + bU(x) is a continuous utility func-
THEOREM l. Every preference ordering satisfying A.4.4(a)-(c) and
tion. Further, by suitable choice of a and b, this utility function can
defined over a convex set can be represented by a continuous utility
be made to assume prescribed values at two given points.
We will choose arbitrarily the utility values for the points xv. function.
Then, for each v, a utility function will be chosen, by the procedure To state the implications of A.4.4(d) for the utility function,
just given, to as sume the prescribed val u es at xv - 1 and xv; if v = 1, introduce the definition
only the value at x 1 is prescribed. Finally, the utility function is
defined for any given x as the value of the utility function associated DEFINITION 2. A function f(x) is said to be semi-strictly quasi-
with xv for the smallest v for which x:;:,: xv. concave if
Formally, let {uv} be a strictly decreasing sequence of real f(x 1) ;::.: f(x 2 ) implies f[ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 ] :::-: f(x 2 ),
numbers. For each v, define Uv(x) = av + bvU(x;xv) for x:;:,: xv by
choosing av,bv so that Uv(xv- 1) = Uv_ 1, Uv(xv) = Uv. (For v = 1, and
we require only that U1(x 1) = u1.) Then for each x, there is
f(x 1) > f(x 2 ) implies f[ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 ] > f(x 2 ), O<asl.
precisely one v such that xv- 1 >- x:;:,: xv, or else x:;:,: x 1. Let
U(x) = Uv(x).
As noted earlier, if U(x) is a continuous utility function, then for
The function U(x) is then defined for all x. It remains to show,
any b > O, a + bU(x) is also a continuous utility function. This
first, that U(x) is a utility function, and second, that it is continuous.
freedom of choice will be used here to set a zero utility level. With
It is obvious that if xa "' xb, then U(xa) = U(xb). Suppose xa >- xb,
b = 1, we can always ensure that U(x) = O, where x is the possible
There are three possibilities: (a) xa >- xb:;:,: x 1; (b) xv- 1 >-
consumption vector named in A.4.2.
xa >- xb:;:,: xv for .some v; (e) xa:;:,: xv >- xb for some v. If (a)
Then, with the aid of Lemma 4.1, we state
holds, then U(xa) = U1(xa), U(xb) = U1(xb); since U1 is a utility
function, U(xa) > U(xb). If (b) holds, then similarly, U(xa) = Corollary J. Under A.4.1 and A.4.4, for every household h there
Uv(xa), U(xb) = Uv(xb), and again U(xa) > U(xb). If (e) holds, let is a continuous semi-strictly quasi-concave utility function, U,(x,.),
v' be the smallest v such that xa:;:,: xv, and v" the largest v such that defined on X,., such that for every xh, there exists x~ arbitrarily close,
xv >- xb; clearly, v' ;::.: v", so that Uv ;::.: Uv" Then U(xa) = Uv-(xa) :::-: for which Uh(x~) > U,(xh), and such that U,.(xh) = O for a com-
Uv-(xV') = Uv, and U(xb) = Uv"+1(xb) < Uv"+1(xV") = Uv" S Uv S modity vector, xh E xh, such that xh! S Xh, all i, Xh < xhl if Xh > o.
U(xa). Hence, U(x) is a utility function.
It remains to pro ve continuity. If x >- x 1 or xv - 1 >- x :;:,: x for The airo of the consumer, then, is to maximize Uh(x,.) subject to
some v, then the same relation holds for x' sufficiently close to x, by xh E xh, px S M,., where Mh is defined in A.4.3.

1'

:' 1
111
llu:l!
'1:
,'1 il
'U
86 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 87

then xv >- xv+ 1. Further, for any x E X, x:;:,: x 0 tt for p, :::-: lxl; there- Continuity, so that U(x') = U1(x') or Uv(x') in a neighborhood of x;
fore, for any x E X, x :;:,: xv for all v sufficiently large. since the functions Uv(x) are continuous at x, so is U(x).
The sequence {xv} has two basic properties: It is strictly decreasing Now suppose x "' xv for so me v. Let {xP} be a sequence such that
in preference, xv >- xv+ 1 for all v, and every x E X is preferred or xP ->- x. If xP :;:,: x, all p, then xv - 1 >- xP for p sufficiently large, if
indifferent to xv for all v sufficiently large. v > 1. Hence, U(xP) = Uv(xP) for p large; by continuity of Uv(x),
We can take in turn each xv as the x 0 of our earlier construction Uv(xP) ->- Uv(x) = U(x). Similarly, if x >- xP for all p, xP :;:,: xv +1
and find a continuous utility function for the set {x 1 x :;:,: xv}. Let for p sufficiently large, U(xP) = Uv+ 1 (xP) for p large, and U(xP)--.
U(x;xv) be this utility function. As is well known and obvious, if Uv+l(x) = Uv+ 1(xv) = Uv = U(x). Finally, if the sequence {xP}
U is a utility function and F(u) is a strictly increasing function on contains some members inferior to x and others not inferior, we can
the real numbers, then F[U(x)] is also a utility function in the sense divide it into two sequences, for each of which U(xP) converges to
of D.4.l. If F is continuous, then sois F[U(x)]. In particular, if U(x).
F(u) = a + bu, b > O, then a + bU(x) is a continuous utility func-
THEOREM l. Every preference ordering satisfying A.4.4(a)-(c) and
tion. Further, by suitable choice of a and b, this utility function can
defined over a convex set can be represented by a continuous utility
be made to assume prescribed values at two given points.
We will choose arbitrarily the utility values for the points xv. function.
Then, for each v, a utility function will be chosen, by the procedure To state the implications of A.4.4(d) for the utility function,
just given, to as sume the prescribed val u es at xv - 1 and xv; if v = 1, introduce the definition
only the value at x 1 is prescribed. Finally, the utility function is
defined for any given x as the value of the utility function associated DEFINITION 2. A function f(x) is said to be semi-strictly quasi-
with xv for the smallest v for which x:;:,: xv. concave if
Formally, let {uv} be a strictly decreasing sequence of real f(x 1) ;::.: f(x 2 ) implies f[ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 ] :::-: f(x 2 ),
numbers. For each v, define Uv(x) = av + bvU(x;xv) for x:;:,: xv by
choosing av,bv so that Uv(xv- 1) = Uv_ 1, Uv(xv) = Uv. (For v = 1, and
we require only that U1(x 1) = u1.) Then for each x, there is
f(x 1) > f(x 2 ) implies f[ax 1 + (1 - a)x 2 ] > f(x 2 ), O<asl.
precisely one v such that xv- 1 >- x:;:,: xv, or else x:;:,: x 1. Let
U(x) = Uv(x).
As noted earlier, if U(x) is a continuous utility function, then for
The function U(x) is then defined for all x. It remains to show,
any b > O, a + bU(x) is also a continuous utility function. This
first, that U(x) is a utility function, and second, that it is continuous.
freedom of choice will be used here to set a zero utility level. With
It is obvious that if xa "' xb, then U(xa) = U(xb). Suppose xa >- xb,
b = 1, we can always ensure that U(x) = O, where x is the possible
There are three possibilities: (a) xa >- xb:;:,: x 1; (b) xv- 1 >-
consumption vector named in A.4.2.
xa >- xb:;:,: xv for .some v; (e) xa:;:,: xv >- xb for some v. If (a)
Then, with the aid of Lemma 4.1, we state
holds, then U(xa) = U1(xa), U(xb) = U1(xb); since U1 is a utility
function, U(xa) > U(xb). If (b) holds, then similarly, U(xa) = Corollary J. Under A.4.1 and A.4.4, for every household h there
Uv(xa), U(xb) = Uv(xb), and again U(xa) > U(xb). If (e) holds, let is a continuous semi-strictly quasi-concave utility function, U,(x,.),
v' be the smallest v such that xa:;:,: xv, and v" the largest v such that defined on X,., such that for every xh, there exists x~ arbitrarily close,
xv >- xb; clearly, v' ;::.: v", so that Uv ;::.: Uv" Then U(xa) = Uv-(xa) :::-: for which Uh(x~) > U,(xh), and such that U,.(xh) = O for a com-
Uv-(xV') = Uv, and U(xb) = Uv"+1(xb) < Uv"+1(xV") = Uv" S Uv S modity vector, xh E xh, such that xh! S Xh, all i, Xh < xhl if Xh > o.
U(xa). Hence, U(x) is a utility function.
It remains to pro ve continuity. If x >- x 1 or xv - 1 >- x :;:,: x for The airo of the consumer, then, is to maximize Uh(x,.) subject to
some v, then the same relation holds for x' sufficiently close to x, by xh E xh, px S M,., where Mh is defined in A.4.3.

1'

:' 1
111
llu:l!
'1:
,'1 il
'U
88 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 89

3. Individual- and Market-Excess Demands ponent, for then for each commodity aggregate supply, both from
production and from initial endowment, exceeds or equals aggregate
In the discussion of equilibrium, we are primarily interested in
requirernents of consurners.
excess demands on the rnarket, that is, vectors z of the forrn
~O.
z = L x"- y- x,
h
x" E X", y E Y.
DEFINITION 5. An allocation, w, isfeasible ifz(w)
feasible allocations will be denoted by
The set of

Here, because of our conventions as to signs, if' = irn{w 1 z(w) ~ 0}.

L:x"
h
THEOREM 2. The set of feasible allocations, if', is cornpact and
convex.
is the aggregate vector of demands by households, y the aggregate
vector of goods supplied by firrns, and x the aggregate vector of Proof. Frorn D.4.3., A.4.1., and A.3.3, iris a Cartesian product
supplies initially available before production. The excess-demand of convex sets and, therefore, convex. Since z(w) is a linear
vector is a function of the decisions of all units of the economy, function, by D.4.4, the set {to 1 z(w) ~ O} is convex. By D.4.5,
households and firms: if' is the intersection of convex sets and, therefore, convex.
Let @''be the projection of if' on I!Y, that is,
@' = I!Y n {y 1 z(x,y) ~ O for sorne x E ,q[},
In D.3.3 we introduced the notion of a production allocation, which
is a large vector composed of vectors, each of which is a possible and similarly Jet :f be the projection of if' on ,q[,

production vector for one firm. As noted, it is an element of the :f = ,q[ n{x 1 z(x,y) ~ O for sorne rE I!Y}.
Cartesian product of the production possibility sets of the different
firrns, X Y1 . Analogously, we introduce If y E @', then
r
DEFINITION 3. A consumption allocation is any element, x, of Lr Yr + x;;::: L x";;::: O,
h

,qr =Xh x", for sorne x E ,q[, so that, by D.3.5, @' e @, where qi} is the set of
and an allocation, to = (x,y), is a consumption allocation and a feasible production allocations. Then @ is bounded, as shown in
production allocation, that is, an element of the set T.3.2., and therefore, so is @<
If x E :f, then x ;;::: O and
ir= ,q[ X i!Y.
for sorne y E I!Y.
DEFINITION 4. The excess demand is a linear function over the set
ll!:'lii of allocations,
1

''i'
"
But then y rnust belong to @', by definition, and therefore, is bounded
z(w) = L:xh- LYr- x, above. If x ;::: O,
" r
1

.
,,.
1.1,:,.'

~i
1
where L x,. bounded above for x E :f,
to = (x,y)Eif'. "
11!;.1:.1 then ic rnust be bounded. If the projections of if' on both ,qr and
1
To say that an allocation is feasible is simply to say that the I!Y are bounded, however, then if' itself must be bounded. Since it
.!'1
corresponding excess-demand vector is non-positive in each com- is obviously closed, it must be cornpact.
:;,
' lr 1

,,
1'1
,!:
,'!
'!'i
,iL
88 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 89

3. Individual- and Market-Excess Demands ponent, for then for each commodity aggregate supply, both from
production and from initial endowment, exceeds or equals aggregate
In the discussion of equilibrium, we are primarily interested in
requirernents of consurners.
excess demands on the rnarket, that is, vectors z of the forrn
~O.
z = L x"- y- x,
h
x" E X", y E Y.
DEFINITION 5. An allocation, w, isfeasible ifz(w)
feasible allocations will be denoted by
The set of

Here, because of our conventions as to signs, if' = irn{w 1 z(w) ~ 0}.

L:x"
h
THEOREM 2. The set of feasible allocations, if', is cornpact and
convex.
is the aggregate vector of demands by households, y the aggregate
vector of goods supplied by firrns, and x the aggregate vector of Proof. Frorn D.4.3., A.4.1., and A.3.3, iris a Cartesian product
supplies initially available before production. The excess-demand of convex sets and, therefore, convex. Since z(w) is a linear
vector is a function of the decisions of all units of the economy, function, by D.4.4, the set {to 1 z(w) ~ O} is convex. By D.4.5,
households and firms: if' is the intersection of convex sets and, therefore, convex.
Let @''be the projection of if' on I!Y, that is,
@' = I!Y n {y 1 z(x,y) ~ O for sorne x E ,q[},
In D.3.3 we introduced the notion of a production allocation, which
is a large vector composed of vectors, each of which is a possible and similarly Jet :f be the projection of if' on ,q[,

production vector for one firm. As noted, it is an element of the :f = ,q[ n{x 1 z(x,y) ~ O for sorne rE I!Y}.
Cartesian product of the production possibility sets of the different
firrns, X Y1 . Analogously, we introduce If y E @', then
r
DEFINITION 3. A consumption allocation is any element, x, of Lr Yr + x;;::: L x";;::: O,
h

,qr =Xh x", for sorne x E ,q[, so that, by D.3.5, @' e @, where qi} is the set of
and an allocation, to = (x,y), is a consumption allocation and a feasible production allocations. Then @ is bounded, as shown in
production allocation, that is, an element of the set T.3.2., and therefore, so is @<
If x E :f, then x ;;::: O and
ir= ,q[ X i!Y.
for sorne y E I!Y.
DEFINITION 4. The excess demand is a linear function over the set
ll!:'lii of allocations,
1

''i'
"
But then y rnust belong to @', by definition, and therefore, is bounded
z(w) = L:xh- LYr- x, above. If x ;::: O,
" r
1

.
,,.
1.1,:,.'

~i
1
where L x,. bounded above for x E :f,
to = (x,y)Eif'. "
11!;.1:.1 then ic rnust be bounded. If the projections of if' on both ,qr and
1
To say that an allocation is feasible is simply to say that the I!Y are bounded, however, then if' itself must be bounded. Since it
.!'1
corresponding excess-demand vector is non-positive in each com- is obviously closed, it must be cornpact.
:;,
' lr 1

,,
1'1
,!:
,'!
'!'i
,iL
90 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 91

4. Feasible and Efficient Utility Allocations THEOREM 3. For each u, the set of u-feasible allocations 'if'(u) is
compact and convex.
We will be interested in the possibility that a given household
achieves a certain utility level, and more generally, in the utility T.4.3 is proved exactly the same way as T.4.2, with Xn everywhere
levels achieved by all households. replaced by Xh(uh).
DEFINITION 6. The set of U-possible consumption vectors for house- Corollary 3. For each u, Z(u) is compact and convex.
hold h is
Xn(u) = {xn U(X)
1 ::0: uh}. Proo.f From T.4.3, since Z(u) is the image of 'if'(u) under a linear
and therefore continuous mapping.
By a utility allocation, u, we will mean a vector whose hth
,'' 11 component, u1, is a possible utility for household h. Among the feasible utility allocations, we wish to characterize
those that are efficient in the appropriate sense, that of Pareto.
DEFINITION 7. The set of u-possible consumption allocations is
1'

1'1'
DEFINITION 12. A utility allocation u1 is dominated by u2 if u2 is
feasible and u2 u1 . A utility allocation, u, is Pareto efficient if it
that is, the Cartesian product of the sets of u1t-possible consumption is feasible and not dominated by any other feasible utility allocation.
i 11 vectors for the different households h.
'!!: We use the term "Pareto efficient" instead of the more common
li
DEFINITION 8. The set of u-possible allocations is "Pareto optimal" beca use the latter term conveys more commenda-
il ir(u) = ff(u) x ql/;
tion than the concept should bear, since a Pareto-efficient allocation
1',
might assign extremely low utilities to sorne (indeed, possibly to all
,,

'
1.1'1
that is, a u-possible allocation is a u-possible consumption allocation but one) households and thus not be optimal in any sense in which
!!
:
1

1
and a possible production allocation. distributional ethics are involved., This definition differs somewhat
1 1
' '
We will be interested in the excess demands corresponding to the from the conventional one, in which the statement u2 dominates u1
1

is interpreted to mean u2 > u1 ; that is, everyone is at least as well

~;
u-possible allocations.
off and one person is better off. In our definition, the concept of
DEFINITION 9. The set of u-possible excess demands is the image of efficiency is somewhat wider than usual; an allocation is efficient if
,,
'
ir(u) under the linear mapping z(w ), that is, there is noway of making everyone better off. The present definition
Z(u) = {z 1 z = z(w) for sorne toE "/Y(u)}. leads to simpler results and avoids sorne special, odd cases.
The general plan of the analysis is to note that if z is an excess-
Analogous to the notion of feasibility is that of u-feasibility, the demand vector for which z O, it would appear to correspond to a
ability of the economy to achieve a utility allocation u within the dominated allocation, since everyone can be given more of every
limits of its resources. commodity; hence, if u is efficient, Z(u) is disjoint from the set
{z 1 z 0}. The two sets are convex and the second has an interior;
DEFINITION 10. The set of u~feasible allocations is the set of u-pos- hence, we can find a separating hyperplane, which can be shown to
sible allocations that also are feasible; imply a price system such that the utility allocation u is realized
"V(u) = "/f"(u) n{w 1 z(w) :::; o}. when each firm is maximizing profits and each household is mini-
mizing the cost of achieving its prescribed utility level.
DEFINITION 11. A u~easible excess demand is the excess demand
corresponding toa u-feasible allocation; that is, Z(u) is the image of LEMMA 5. If z E Z(u), there exist z',u', with z' E Z(u'), z' arbitrarily
"V(u) under the linear mapping z(w ). close to z and u' u.
90 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 91

4. Feasible and Efficient Utility Allocations THEOREM 3. For each u, the set of u-feasible allocations 'if'(u) is
compact and convex.
We will be interested in the possibility that a given household
achieves a certain utility level, and more generally, in the utility T.4.3 is proved exactly the same way as T.4.2, with Xn everywhere
levels achieved by all households. replaced by Xh(uh).
DEFINITION 6. The set of U-possible consumption vectors for house- Corollary 3. For each u, Z(u) is compact and convex.
hold h is
Xn(u) = {xn U(X)
1 ::0: uh}. Proo.f From T.4.3, since Z(u) is the image of 'if'(u) under a linear
and therefore continuous mapping.
By a utility allocation, u, we will mean a vector whose hth
,'' 11 component, u1, is a possible utility for household h. Among the feasible utility allocations, we wish to characterize
those that are efficient in the appropriate sense, that of Pareto.
DEFINITION 7. The set of u-possible consumption allocations is
1'

1'1'
DEFINITION 12. A utility allocation u1 is dominated by u2 if u2 is
feasible and u2 u1 . A utility allocation, u, is Pareto efficient if it
that is, the Cartesian product of the sets of u1t-possible consumption is feasible and not dominated by any other feasible utility allocation.
i 11 vectors for the different households h.
'!!: We use the term "Pareto efficient" instead of the more common
li
DEFINITION 8. The set of u-possible allocations is "Pareto optimal" beca use the latter term conveys more commenda-
il ir(u) = ff(u) x ql/;
tion than the concept should bear, since a Pareto-efficient allocation
1',
might assign extremely low utilities to sorne (indeed, possibly to all
,,

'
1.1'1
that is, a u-possible allocation is a u-possible consumption allocation but one) households and thus not be optimal in any sense in which
!!
:
1

1
and a possible production allocation. distributional ethics are involved., This definition differs somewhat
1 1
' '
We will be interested in the excess demands corresponding to the from the conventional one, in which the statement u2 dominates u1
1

is interpreted to mean u2 > u1 ; that is, everyone is at least as well

~;
u-possible allocations.
off and one person is better off. In our definition, the concept of
DEFINITION 9. The set of u-possible excess demands is the image of efficiency is somewhat wider than usual; an allocation is efficient if
,,
'
ir(u) under the linear mapping z(w ), that is, there is noway of making everyone better off. The present definition
Z(u) = {z 1 z = z(w) for sorne toE "/Y(u)}. leads to simpler results and avoids sorne special, odd cases.
The general plan of the analysis is to note that if z is an excess-
Analogous to the notion of feasibility is that of u-feasibility, the demand vector for which z O, it would appear to correspond to a
ability of the economy to achieve a utility allocation u within the dominated allocation, since everyone can be given more of every
limits of its resources. commodity; hence, if u is efficient, Z(u) is disjoint from the set
{z 1 z 0}. The two sets are convex and the second has an interior;
DEFINITION 10. The set of u~feasible allocations is the set of u-pos- hence, we can find a separating hyperplane, which can be shown to
sible allocations that also are feasible; imply a price system such that the utility allocation u is realized
"V(u) = "/f"(u) n{w 1 z(w) :::; o}. when each firm is maximizing profits and each household is mini-
mizing the cost of achieving its prescribed utility level.
DEFINITION 11. A u~easible excess demand is the excess demand
corresponding toa u-feasible allocation; that is, Z(u) is the image of LEMMA 5. If z E Z(u), there exist z',u', with z' E Z(u'), z' arbitrarily
"V(u) under the linear mapping z(w ). close to z and u' u.
92 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 93

Proof. Let Hence, from px ;:::: e, all x E A, it can be concluded that px ;:::: O, all
XEA.
z = L xh - L y1 - :X, where xh E Xh(uh), Yr E Y,.
h f We now combine the disjunction assured by Lemma 4.6 with the 'i
,,, 1

By Corollary 1, x~ can be chosen arbitrarily el ose to xh with Uh(x~) > separation theorem, Lemma 4.8. :.:

Uh(xn) = uh. Let THEOREM 4. If u0 is Pareto efficient, there exists a vector p with the
z' = L x~ - L yr -
h f
X. following properties:
(a) p > O;
Then by D.4.9, z' E Z(u'), where u~ = Uh(x~). (b) pz;::::O,allzEZ(u 0);
LEMMA 6. If u is Pareto efficient, then Z(u) is disjoint from (e) pz =O, all z E Z(u 0); (
'1

(d) if (m\~ 0 ) E i?'(u 0 ), so that the conditions Uh(x~) e: u~, 11'


{z 1 z 0}. 1,
,
,,
y~ E Y,, and 1

Proof. Suppose z E Z(u), z O. By Lemma 4.5 we can find '1

z' O for which z' E Z(u'), u' u. But then i(u') is non-null so
that u' is feasible and dominates u, contrary to the definition D.4.12
are satisfied, then
of Pareto efficiency.
(i) pxh is minimized over Xh(u~) at x~;
We now use the well-known separation theorem for convex sets (ii) py r is maximized o ver Yr at y~;
(see T.B.6). . (iii) the social budget constraint,
:!
LEMMA 7. If A and B are disjoint convex sets in a finite-dimen-
sional space and at least one has an interior, then ther~ exists a
px~ = n [px + r dhf(py~)J,
h
vector p =1= O and a scalar e such that is satisfied.
px ;:::: e for all x E A, Proof. Conclusions (a) and (b) are simple consequences of
px :;:; e for all x E B. Lemmas 4.6 and 4.8; in other words, Pareto efficiency implies that
LEMMA 8. If A is a convex set disjoint from the set {x 1 x 0}, Z(u 0) is disjoint from the set of strictly negative vectors, while Lemma
then there exists a vector p >O for which px e: O for all x E A. 4.8 assures the existence of a vector, p > O, for which (b) is true.
If z E 2(u 0), then z :;:; O so that, from (a) pz :S: O; then (e) follows
Proof. Choose p as in Lemma 7, with B = {x x O}; note 1
from (b). Note that, sin ce u0 is feasible, 2(u 0 ) is non-null.
that B has an interior. Let x 0 O, ei be the vector with 1 in the Statements (b) and (e) can be rephrased as follows: The mnimum
ith component and O elsewhere, and A > O. Then value of pz for z E Z(u 0 ) is O and is attained at any z 0 in 2(u 0 ), that is,
any z 0 E Z(u 0 ) for which z 0 :;:; O.
al! A > O,
The hypothesis of (d) is precisely that z 0 :S: O, where
so that
zo = L.,xh-
"" o L.,Yr-
"" o L.. X.
"" -
all A > O. li f h

Divide through by A and let A approach infinity; then p e: O. Thus, For any z in Z(u 0
), we can, by definition, choose X E Xh(u~), Yr E Y,,
p ;:::: O; sin ce p =1= O, p > O. so that
Also, let e be the vector all of whose components are l. Then
- Ee O, all E > O. Then e ;:::: - Epe; let E approach O, then e e: O.
h
!'li
92 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 93

Proof. Let Hence, from px ;:::: e, all x E A, it can be concluded that px ;:::: O, all
XEA.
z = L xh - L y1 - :X, where xh E Xh(uh), Yr E Y,.
h f We now combine the disjunction assured by Lemma 4.6 with the 'i
,,, 1

By Corollary 1, x~ can be chosen arbitrarily el ose to xh with Uh(x~) > separation theorem, Lemma 4.8. :.:

Uh(xn) = uh. Let THEOREM 4. If u0 is Pareto efficient, there exists a vector p with the
z' = L x~ - L yr -
h f
X. following properties:
(a) p > O;
Then by D.4.9, z' E Z(u'), where u~ = Uh(x~). (b) pz;::::O,allzEZ(u 0);
LEMMA 6. If u is Pareto efficient, then Z(u) is disjoint from (e) pz =O, all z E Z(u 0); (
'1

(d) if (m\~ 0 ) E i?'(u 0 ), so that the conditions Uh(x~) e: u~, 11'


{z 1 z 0}. 1,
,
,,
y~ E Y,, and 1

Proof. Suppose z E Z(u), z O. By Lemma 4.5 we can find '1

z' O for which z' E Z(u'), u' u. But then i(u') is non-null so
that u' is feasible and dominates u, contrary to the definition D.4.12
are satisfied, then
of Pareto efficiency.
(i) pxh is minimized over Xh(u~) at x~;
We now use the well-known separation theorem for convex sets (ii) py r is maximized o ver Yr at y~;
(see T.B.6). . (iii) the social budget constraint,
:!
LEMMA 7. If A and B are disjoint convex sets in a finite-dimen-
sional space and at least one has an interior, then ther~ exists a
px~ = n [px + r dhf(py~)J,
h
vector p =1= O and a scalar e such that is satisfied.
px ;:::: e for all x E A, Proof. Conclusions (a) and (b) are simple consequences of
px :;:; e for all x E B. Lemmas 4.6 and 4.8; in other words, Pareto efficiency implies that
LEMMA 8. If A is a convex set disjoint from the set {x 1 x 0}, Z(u 0) is disjoint from the set of strictly negative vectors, while Lemma
then there exists a vector p >O for which px e: O for all x E A. 4.8 assures the existence of a vector, p > O, for which (b) is true.
If z E 2(u 0), then z :;:; O so that, from (a) pz :S: O; then (e) follows
Proof. Choose p as in Lemma 7, with B = {x x O}; note 1
from (b). Note that, sin ce u0 is feasible, 2(u 0 ) is non-null.
that B has an interior. Let x 0 O, ei be the vector with 1 in the Statements (b) and (e) can be rephrased as follows: The mnimum
ith component and O elsewhere, and A > O. Then value of pz for z E Z(u 0 ) is O and is attained at any z 0 in 2(u 0 ), that is,
any z 0 E Z(u 0 ) for which z 0 :;:; O.
al! A > O,
The hypothesis of (d) is precisely that z 0 :S: O, where
so that
zo = L.,xh-
"" o L.,Yr-
"" o L.. X.
"" -
all A > O. li f h

Divide through by A and let A approach infinity; then p e: O. Thus, For any z in Z(u 0
), we can, by definition, choose X E Xh(u~), Yr E Y,,
p ;:::: O; sin ce p =1= O, p > O. so that
Also, let e be the vector all of whose components are l. Then
- Ee O, all E > O. Then e ;:::: - Epe; let E approach O, then e e: O.
h
!'li
~
1'1
;
1
,'1:
' ',

94 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 95


Then pz ~ pz 0 , or minimize the cost of achieving the given utility leve! at the desired
consumption vector, at the same time spending exactly the value of
P(.Lx"-
h
LYr- _Lx")
f h
~ p(_Lxg-
h
LY~- _Lx")
h f
endowment in goods and shares. Thus, in a certain sense, any
desired efficient allocation can be achiev.ed by redistribution of initial
for all x" E Xh(ug), y1 E Y1.
assets, followed by the achievement of an equilibriUm. However,
Add p(~ x,.) to both si des and rewrite slightly: there are severa! important qualifications that should be kept in
mind.
L pxh - L PY1 ~ L pxg - L pyg,
h f h f
The most obvious and perhaps most important qualification is
that the assumptions made so far have to be satisfied. The most
all x" E Xh(ug), y1 E Y1.
important of these are the convexity of production possibility sets
,,,,,
!he va~iables on the left-hand side are independent so that the and orderings (the first is much more significant, as the discussion
mequahty must hold term-by-term. In more detail let y = y 0 all in Chapter 7 will show). Also implicit so far has been the absence
o 1 ' f ,,
f , x". = x~ for h i= h. Then 1f we cancel all terms in pxg(h i= h') of externalities; preferences and production possibilities are not
and m py1 from both sides, we have affected by the behavior of other economic agents. This problem
will be considered again in Section 6.2.
for all Xh' E Xh'(ug,),
The informational requirements as stated are far beyond the
which is (i). Statement (ii) follows similar! y; statement (iii) is possible. Methods of successive approximations are needed, but
simply a restatement of (e). this, in turn, implies an ability to measure utility levels already
T.4.4 is t~e basic e~ciency theorem of welfare economics. Any achieved.
The equilibrium, as defined, is not precisely the competitive
Par~t.o-~ffictent allocatwn can be realized as a sort of competitive
equilibrium in the usual sense. As already noted in Section 4.1, it
eqmhbnum. If an omniscient state wishes to realize a given
is rather a compensated equilibrium. The relations between these
Pareto-efficient allocation, it computes a price vector, p, satisfying
hypotheses of the theorem. Then it chooses for each individual an concepts are discussed in detail in Section 5.1.
Sorne of the initial endowments reflect labor skills; it is hard to
initial endowment, x", and ownership shares, dhf, in the different
firms, so that imagine that, in fact, they can be redistributed from one individual
to another. The redistribution must take the form of abstract 1'',

pxg = px" + dhf(PY~)


11

each h purchasing power.


f
Por any given distribution of initial assets, the resulting equi-
and, f course, illll
librium might not be unique (see Chapter 9) or stable (see Chapters 1:!'
,d
11-13). Therefore, if the state merely allocates endowments, it ',il
cannot always be sure that the market will achieve the desired
i,,l
'1
Pareto-optimal allocation. Of course, if the state also announces
These equations certainly can be sol ved beca use of (d-iii). Por
example, let each individual h have the proportion the price vector, then competitive forces will maintain tht vector.

pxg A more extended analysis of the welfare implications of T.4.4 is


pxg beyond the scope of this book, which is concerned with the proper-
h
ties of competitive equilibria; T.4.4 has been proved here as a step
of every initially available good and every firm.
in demonstrating the existence of equilibrium.
Then, indeed, at the given prices, each firm will maximize its It has not been implied that the price vector p that will support
profits at the desired production vector and each household will a given Pareto-efficient utility allocation is unique. The essential
~
1'1
;
1
,'1:
' ',

94 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 95


Then pz ~ pz 0 , or minimize the cost of achieving the given utility leve! at the desired
consumption vector, at the same time spending exactly the value of
P(.Lx"-
h
LYr- _Lx")
f h
~ p(_Lxg-
h
LY~- _Lx")
h f
endowment in goods and shares. Thus, in a certain sense, any
desired efficient allocation can be achiev.ed by redistribution of initial
for all x" E Xh(ug), y1 E Y1.
assets, followed by the achievement of an equilibriUm. However,
Add p(~ x,.) to both si des and rewrite slightly: there are severa! important qualifications that should be kept in
mind.
L pxh - L PY1 ~ L pxg - L pyg,
h f h f
The most obvious and perhaps most important qualification is
that the assumptions made so far have to be satisfied. The most
all x" E Xh(ug), y1 E Y1.
important of these are the convexity of production possibility sets
,,,,,
!he va~iables on the left-hand side are independent so that the and orderings (the first is much more significant, as the discussion
mequahty must hold term-by-term. In more detail let y = y 0 all in Chapter 7 will show). Also implicit so far has been the absence
o 1 ' f ,,
f , x". = x~ for h i= h. Then 1f we cancel all terms in pxg(h i= h') of externalities; preferences and production possibilities are not
and m py1 from both sides, we have affected by the behavior of other economic agents. This problem
will be considered again in Section 6.2.
for all Xh' E Xh'(ug,),
The informational requirements as stated are far beyond the
which is (i). Statement (ii) follows similar! y; statement (iii) is possible. Methods of successive approximations are needed, but
simply a restatement of (e). this, in turn, implies an ability to measure utility levels already
T.4.4 is t~e basic e~ciency theorem of welfare economics. Any achieved.
The equilibrium, as defined, is not precisely the competitive
Par~t.o-~ffictent allocatwn can be realized as a sort of competitive
equilibrium in the usual sense. As already noted in Section 4.1, it
eqmhbnum. If an omniscient state wishes to realize a given
is rather a compensated equilibrium. The relations between these
Pareto-efficient allocation, it computes a price vector, p, satisfying
hypotheses of the theorem. Then it chooses for each individual an concepts are discussed in detail in Section 5.1.
Sorne of the initial endowments reflect labor skills; it is hard to
initial endowment, x", and ownership shares, dhf, in the different
firms, so that imagine that, in fact, they can be redistributed from one individual
to another. The redistribution must take the form of abstract 1'',

pxg = px" + dhf(PY~)


11

each h purchasing power.


f
Por any given distribution of initial assets, the resulting equi-
and, f course, illll
librium might not be unique (see Chapter 9) or stable (see Chapters 1:!'
,d
11-13). Therefore, if the state merely allocates endowments, it ',il
cannot always be sure that the market will achieve the desired
i,,l
'1
Pareto-optimal allocation. Of course, if the state also announces
These equations certainly can be sol ved beca use of (d-iii). Por
example, let each individual h have the proportion the price vector, then competitive forces will maintain tht vector.

pxg A more extended analysis of the welfare implications of T.4.4 is


pxg beyond the scope of this book, which is concerned with the proper-
h
ties of competitive equilibria; T.4.4 has been proved here as a step
of every initially available good and every firm.
in demonstrating the existence of equilibrium.
Then, indeed, at the given prices, each firm will maximize its It has not been implied that the price vector p that will support
profits at the desired production vector and each household will a given Pareto-efficient utility allocation is unique. The essential
. 1

111:1
\

CONSUMER DECISJONS AND EFFICIENT .;\LLOCATIONS 97


96 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

properties are (a) and (b) of T.4.4; any price satisfying those con- Thus,
ditions automatically satisfies (e) and (d). It is obvious that if p z = x - ay - x O,
satisfies (a) and (b ), then so does ,\p for any ,\ > O. This is the usual X = : x, x, E X,(o)' aH h,
h
homogeneity property of prices. Then, without loss of essential
generality, we can restrict ourselves to price vectors p for which so that, by Lemma 4.6, O is a dominated utility aHocation.
pe = 1, where, it will be recalled, e = (1, ... , 1). We will confine our attention to non-negative utility aHocations.
Even among these normalized price vectors there may be more Then the Pareto-efficient utility allocations will be semi-positive.
than one satisfying (a) and (b). Let We note
DEFINITION 13. U= {u 1 u Pareto efficient} = Pareto frontier. LEMMA 10. If u and u' are feasible non-negative utility aHocations,
u ::;; u', and u, < u;, for any h for which u~ > O, then u is dominated.
DEFINITION 14. P(u) = {p p > 0, pe= 1, pz
1 ::0: 0 for aH Z EZ(u)}.
Proof. Let toE "F(u), w' E "F(u'). Since, by Lemma 4.9, O is
T.4.4 asserts that P(u) is non-m1ll for u E U. We will consider P(u) dominated there is an allocation toa E if'(ua), with ua O. Now
as a correspondence from U to Sn = {p p > O, pe = 1}, the price
1 consider 'the allocation wb = (1 - a)to' + atoa, O < ex ::;; 1; it is
set, the unit simplex for n-dimensional vectors, where n is the certainly feasible. We will show that by suitable choice of ex we have
number of commodities. ub u, where u~ = u,(xn. First, consider any h for which u~= O;
We conclude this section with some lemmas on domination of then u, = O. Either x~ >-, x~ or x~ >=,
x~. In the first case, by
utility allocations to be used in the next chapter. semi-strict convexity of preferences, A.4.4( d), x~ >-, x~, so that
In A.4.2 and Corollary 1, we introduced a possible consumption u~ > U,(x~) ;:o: u~ =O= u,. In the second case, by Lemma 4.1(b),
vector, xh, for each individual, which was used to define his zero b > u (xa) > ua > 0 = u. Now consider the households for
Uh - h h - h ,..
utility level. which u~ > O; then u~ > u,. Then u~ ;:o: u~ > U, for a = O; b_Y
continuity u~ > U, for a > O and sufficiently smaH. Hence, u IS
1.:1 LEMMA 9. The utility aHocation, O, is dominated.
dominated.
1

Proof. By A.3.5 there is a vector y in the social production Remar k. It is noted, for later reference, that the proof of Lemma
1 '1'
possibility set for which 4.10 depends only on the validity of Lemma 4.9 and on the semi-
x +y O. (6) strict convexity of preferences.

For any commodity i, either X > O or X = O. In the first case,


1

Xni ::0: O, all h, Xni > O, some h. By A.4.2, then, xhi ::0: xhi aH h,
5. Sorne Continuity Theorems
xh > xhi sorne h, so that Some of the sets introduced in the preceding sections are functions
of utility 1evels. For the existence of equilibrium we will need to
show that these set-valued functions or correspondences are con-
tinuous in appropriate senses. In addition to the concept of uppcr
and therefore semi-continuity, already used in Section 4.1, we will need that of
for a > O and sufficiently sma11. lower semi-continuity.
0
<D(x) is lower semi-continuous if xv---+ x 0 , y0 E <D(x ) implies that
0
(Recall that some components of y are negative.) If X = O, then there exists a sequence {yv} for which yv E <D(xv), yv---+ Y A ,11:
X = O, and from (6), ji > O so that correspondence <D(x) is said to be continuous if it is both upper and !' '1
111

lower semi-continuous. ;1
,, 1

1!! 1

'11 :.
. 1
';
. 1

111:1
\

CONSUMER DECISJONS AND EFFICIENT .;\LLOCATIONS 97


96 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

properties are (a) and (b) of T.4.4; any price satisfying those con- Thus,
ditions automatically satisfies (e) and (d). It is obvious that if p z = x - ay - x O,
satisfies (a) and (b ), then so does ,\p for any ,\ > O. This is the usual X = : x, x, E X,(o)' aH h,
h
homogeneity property of prices. Then, without loss of essential
generality, we can restrict ourselves to price vectors p for which so that, by Lemma 4.6, O is a dominated utility aHocation.
pe = 1, where, it will be recalled, e = (1, ... , 1). We will confine our attention to non-negative utility aHocations.
Even among these normalized price vectors there may be more Then the Pareto-efficient utility allocations will be semi-positive.
than one satisfying (a) and (b). Let We note
DEFINITION 13. U= {u 1 u Pareto efficient} = Pareto frontier. LEMMA 10. If u and u' are feasible non-negative utility aHocations,
u ::;; u', and u, < u;, for any h for which u~ > O, then u is dominated.
DEFINITION 14. P(u) = {p p > 0, pe= 1, pz
1 ::0: 0 for aH Z EZ(u)}.
Proof. Let toE "F(u), w' E "F(u'). Since, by Lemma 4.9, O is
T.4.4 asserts that P(u) is non-m1ll for u E U. We will consider P(u) dominated there is an allocation toa E if'(ua), with ua O. Now
as a correspondence from U to Sn = {p p > O, pe = 1}, the price
1 consider 'the allocation wb = (1 - a)to' + atoa, O < ex ::;; 1; it is
set, the unit simplex for n-dimensional vectors, where n is the certainly feasible. We will show that by suitable choice of ex we have
number of commodities. ub u, where u~ = u,(xn. First, consider any h for which u~= O;
We conclude this section with some lemmas on domination of then u, = O. Either x~ >-, x~ or x~ >=,
x~. In the first case, by
utility allocations to be used in the next chapter. semi-strict convexity of preferences, A.4.4( d), x~ >-, x~, so that
In A.4.2 and Corollary 1, we introduced a possible consumption u~ > U,(x~) ;:o: u~ =O= u,. In the second case, by Lemma 4.1(b),
vector, xh, for each individual, which was used to define his zero b > u (xa) > ua > 0 = u. Now consider the households for
Uh - h h - h ,..
utility level. which u~ > O; then u~ > u,. Then u~ ;:o: u~ > U, for a = O; b_Y
continuity u~ > U, for a > O and sufficiently smaH. Hence, u IS
1.:1 LEMMA 9. The utility aHocation, O, is dominated.
dominated.
1

Proof. By A.3.5 there is a vector y in the social production Remar k. It is noted, for later reference, that the proof of Lemma
1 '1'
possibility set for which 4.10 depends only on the validity of Lemma 4.9 and on the semi-
x +y O. (6) strict convexity of preferences.

For any commodity i, either X > O or X = O. In the first case,


1

Xni ::0: O, all h, Xni > O, some h. By A.4.2, then, xhi ::0: xhi aH h,
5. Sorne Continuity Theorems
xh > xhi sorne h, so that Some of the sets introduced in the preceding sections are functions
of utility 1evels. For the existence of equilibrium we will need to
show that these set-valued functions or correspondences are con-
tinuous in appropriate senses. In addition to the concept of uppcr
and therefore semi-continuity, already used in Section 4.1, we will need that of
for a > O and sufficiently sma11. lower semi-continuity.
0
<D(x) is lower semi-continuous if xv---+ x 0 , y0 E <D(x ) implies that
0
(Recall that some components of y are negative.) If X = O, then there exists a sequence {yv} for which yv E <D(xv), yv---+ Y A ,11:
X = O, and from (6), ji > O so that correspondence <D(x) is said to be continuous if it is both upper and !' '1
111

lower semi-continuous. ;1
,, 1

1!! 1

'11 :.
. 1
';
'f
!
1

98 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 99

LEMMA 11. The correspondence Xiu") defined in D.4.6, is convex To prove lower semi-continuity, let uv _,.. u0 , aJ- 0 E if"(u 0). By
for each given u" and is continuous in u". definition, w 0 = (x 0 ,l), xg E X"(ug), :lE 1!!1. Since the corre-
spondence X,.(u") is lower serni-continuous, we can find a sequence,
Proof Convexity has already been noted. Suppose u); _,.. u~,
1

{xh}, for each h, such that,


1' x); E Xh(u];), x); -. X~. By definition, Uh(xh) 2: u;;. Since uh is .
continuous, U"(xg) 2: x~, so that xg E X"(ug) and X"(u") is upper x); E X,.( u;) x); _,.. xg.
serni-continuous. If we let tov = (xv,y 0), then wv E if"(uv), wv _,.. w 0 , so that lower
Now suppose that u);_,.. ug and x~ E X,.( u~). Choose xk so that semi-continuity holds. li
U"(xk) > U,.(xg) 2: u~. Then, for each v, precisely one of the three
following possibilities holds: Corollary 5. The set of u-feasible allocations, it'(u), is upper if
semi-continuous in u. ,,.
.,
(a) u); 2: U,.(xk); i]
Proof From D.4.10, "/i'(u) is the intersection of two sets, one of
(b) U,.(~k) > u;; 2: U"(xg); which is upper semi-continuous in u by T.4.5 and the other of which 'il
!ji
(e) U"(x~) > u;;. is independent of u. lj

Since u;;_,.. u~, (a) can hold only for finitely rnany v by the definition
1

Corollary 5'. The set of u-possible excess demands, Z(u), is lower li


of x 1 ; for those v, choose x)'. to be any element of X"(uh). If (e) k
1
11

serni-continuous in u. "!i
::
holds, let x;; = xg. On this subsequence (if infinite), x)'. ->- x~ ,:
trivially, and x); E X,.(uh). Proof Let uv _,.. u0 , z 0 E Z(u 0). By D.4.9, z 0 = z(uJ- 0 ) for sorne
!i,,l
Now suppose (b) holds. Let x"(a) = (1 - a)xg + axk, O ::::; a ::::; to E "/Y(u0). From T.4.5, then, thre exists a sequence {wv} with
0 .,,

wv ->- to 0 , wv E if"(uv). Let zv = z(wv); then zv _,.. z 0, zv E Z(uv), by '


l. By continuity there exists av, O ::::; av < 1, for which U"[x,.(av)] = :i
D.4.9.
u);. Let x); = x"(av). Certainly, x); E X"(uh). It remains to show
that if (b) holds for infinitely many v, then x); _,.. xg along that THEOREM 6. The set P(u), as defined in D.4.14, is upper semi-
subsequence. continuous in u, compact and convex for each u, and is non-null for
The sequence {av} is bounded and, therefore, has a limit point; let UE U.
a* be any such, and let x~ = x"(a*) .. Then U"(x~) = ug, since by
Proof Convexity and compactness follow trivially from the
assumption, u;;_,.. ug. But since U,. is semi-strictly quasi-concave,
definition of P(u). The non-nullity of the set for u E U is the content
U,,[x"(a)] > U,.(xg) 2: ug for any a > O. Hence, a* = O, and this
ofT.4.4. To see upper semi-continuity, suppose there are sequences
must be the only limit point of the sequence {av}. Therefore,
uv _,.. u0 , pv _,.. p0 , pv E P(uv). Since pv > O, pve = 1, it follows that
x)'. _,.. x~ = xg.
p0 2: O, p0 e = 1, and therefore, p0 > O. Take any z 0 E Z(u 0 ); by
THEOREM 5. The correspondence if"(u) defined in D.4.8 is convex Corollary 5', we can choose a sequen ce {zv}, where zv _,.. z 0, zv E Z(uv),
for each u and continuous in u. all 11. Since pv E P(uv), it follows by definition that pvzv 2: O, artd
hence, by taking limits, p0 z0 2: Q. But then p0 satisfies the definition
Proof Convexity has already been noted. For upper semi- of P(u 0).
continuity, suppose uv _,.. u0 , wv _,.. to 0 , wv E if"(uv). Write

10 v = (xv,yv) where xv E .:r(uv), yv E 1!!1, 6. The Single-Valued Case


100 = (xo,yo).
Analogously to Section 3.4, we will present sorne assumptions that
Then x); _,.. xg, and by Lemma 4.11, xg E X"(u~), each h, or x 0 E .:r(u 0). ensure that the excess-demand correspondences of the household
~ince 1!!/ is a closed set, and yv E 1!!1, all v, y 0 E 1!!/; by the definition of become single-valued functions, and we will then discuss sorne of
u-possible allocations, '#"(u), in D.4.8 to 0 E if"(u 0). their well-known properties.
'f
!
1

98 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 99

LEMMA 11. The correspondence Xiu") defined in D.4.6, is convex To prove lower semi-continuity, let uv _,.. u0 , aJ- 0 E if"(u 0). By
for each given u" and is continuous in u". definition, w 0 = (x 0 ,l), xg E X"(ug), :lE 1!!1. Since the corre-
spondence X,.(u") is lower serni-continuous, we can find a sequence,
Proof Convexity has already been noted. Suppose u); _,.. u~,
1

{xh}, for each h, such that,


1' x); E Xh(u];), x); -. X~. By definition, Uh(xh) 2: u;;. Since uh is .
continuous, U"(xg) 2: x~, so that xg E X"(ug) and X"(u") is upper x); E X,.( u;) x); _,.. xg.
serni-continuous. If we let tov = (xv,y 0), then wv E if"(uv), wv _,.. w 0 , so that lower
Now suppose that u);_,.. ug and x~ E X,.( u~). Choose xk so that semi-continuity holds. li
U"(xk) > U,.(xg) 2: u~. Then, for each v, precisely one of the three
following possibilities holds: Corollary 5. The set of u-feasible allocations, it'(u), is upper if
semi-continuous in u. ,,.
.,
(a) u); 2: U,.(xk); i]
Proof From D.4.10, "/i'(u) is the intersection of two sets, one of
(b) U,.(~k) > u;; 2: U"(xg); which is upper semi-continuous in u by T.4.5 and the other of which 'il
!ji
(e) U"(x~) > u;;. is independent of u. lj

Since u;;_,.. u~, (a) can hold only for finitely rnany v by the definition
1

Corollary 5'. The set of u-possible excess demands, Z(u), is lower li


of x 1 ; for those v, choose x)'. to be any element of X"(uh). If (e) k
1
11

serni-continuous in u. "!i
::
holds, let x;; = xg. On this subsequence (if infinite), x)'. ->- x~ ,:
trivially, and x); E X,.(uh). Proof Let uv _,.. u0 , z 0 E Z(u 0). By D.4.9, z 0 = z(uJ- 0 ) for sorne
!i,,l
Now suppose (b) holds. Let x"(a) = (1 - a)xg + axk, O ::::; a ::::; to E "/Y(u0). From T.4.5, then, thre exists a sequence {wv} with
0 .,,

wv ->- to 0 , wv E if"(uv). Let zv = z(wv); then zv _,.. z 0, zv E Z(uv), by '


l. By continuity there exists av, O ::::; av < 1, for which U"[x,.(av)] = :i
D.4.9.
u);. Let x); = x"(av). Certainly, x); E X"(uh). It remains to show
that if (b) holds for infinitely many v, then x); _,.. xg along that THEOREM 6. The set P(u), as defined in D.4.14, is upper semi-
subsequence. continuous in u, compact and convex for each u, and is non-null for
The sequence {av} is bounded and, therefore, has a limit point; let UE U.
a* be any such, and let x~ = x"(a*) .. Then U"(x~) = ug, since by
Proof Convexity and compactness follow trivially from the
assumption, u;;_,.. ug. But since U,. is semi-strictly quasi-concave,
definition of P(u). The non-nullity of the set for u E U is the content
U,,[x"(a)] > U,.(xg) 2: ug for any a > O. Hence, a* = O, and this
ofT.4.4. To see upper semi-continuity, suppose there are sequences
must be the only limit point of the sequence {av}. Therefore,
uv _,.. u0 , pv _,.. p0 , pv E P(uv). Since pv > O, pve = 1, it follows that
x)'. _,.. x~ = xg.
p0 2: O, p0 e = 1, and therefore, p0 > O. Take any z 0 E Z(u 0 ); by
THEOREM 5. The correspondence if"(u) defined in D.4.8 is convex Corollary 5', we can choose a sequen ce {zv}, where zv _,.. z 0, zv E Z(uv),
for each u and continuous in u. all 11. Since pv E P(uv), it follows by definition that pvzv 2: O, artd
hence, by taking limits, p0 z0 2: Q. But then p0 satisfies the definition
Proof Convexity has already been noted. For upper semi- of P(u 0).
continuity, suppose uv _,.. u0 , wv _,.. to 0 , wv E if"(uv). Write

10 v = (xv,yv) where xv E .:r(uv), yv E 1!!1, 6. The Single-Valued Case


100 = (xo,yo).
Analogously to Section 3.4, we will present sorne assumptions that
Then x); _,.. xg, and by Lemma 4.11, xg E X"(u~), each h, or x 0 E .:r(u 0). ensure that the excess-demand correspondences of the household
~ince 1!!/ is a closed set, and yv E 1!!1, all v, y 0 E 1!!/; by the definition of become single-valued functions, and we will then discuss sorne of
u-possible allocations, '#"(u), in D.4.8 to 0 E if"(u 0). their well-known properties.
'"""Ir
i

100 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFIC!ENT ALLOCATIONS 101
" '
,, As in Section 3.4, we assurne that the set of cornrnodities can be xh(p 2 ,M~), it must maximize utility subject to the budget constraint,

~
:1 ' ~ partitioned into two parts, for one of which the household is assurned p 2 x :S:: M~; therefore it must be that x 11 (p\MD does not satisfy that
to ha ve no utility; that is, we can write the vector, x 11 , as (x~,x~),
" 1

budget constraint.
where U11 (x 11 ) = U11 (x~,xD is, in fact, independent of x~. Analo-
''1 ;. Corollary 7 (Revealed Preference). If p 1 x 11 (p 2 ,M~) :s; M 1~ and
gously to the assurnption that Y1 is strictly convex with respect to
xlt(p\MD i= xh(p 2 ,Mn, then p 2 x 11 (p\Mk) > M~.
1:'1111' those cornrnodities that appear in it at al!, we strengthen our assurnp-
'" tions on preferences to strict convexity; that is, if xk :P: x~ and From T.4.7, if x 11 (p) is not defined for sorne p, then there is no
O < a < 1, then ax~ + (1 - a)x~ >- x~ provided xk and x~ differ in utility-maximizing x 11 under the budget constraint. The lack of
sorne of the a-cornponents. The dernand for the b-cornrnodities is definition comes from the fact that the household is not satiated in
O for all price levels; it is perrnissible, for sirnplicity, to assurne that sorne free goods so its demand is, in sorne appropriate sense, infinite.
all cornrnodities are a-cornrnodities. (Sorne cornplication may arise The example given at the beginning of Section 2.8 shows, however,
frorn the fact that sorne cornrnodities in the household's endowrnent that sorne care must be taken in defining the sense in which demands
are b-cornrnodities, not desired for its own consurnption; but we will may be infinite at zero price; even if the household is not satiated
carry incorne, M 11 , as a separate variable when needed.) in any comrnodity, demands need not approach infinity as prices
For any given p O, the set of cornrnodity vectors in Xh that approach a lirnit in which sotne cornponents are zero. On the other
satisfy the budget constraint, pxh :s; Mh, is a cornpact set, so there hand, in the same exarnple it was shown that the su m of the demands
exists at least one x~, rnaxirnizing Uh(xh) in this set. If xk also for all commodities does approach infinity as any set of prices
maxirnized Uh(x~) in this set, then Uh(xh) = Uh(xk). Let x~ be a approaches O. This is a general result, which will now be dernon-
proper convex cornbination of the two; then it satisfies the budget strated, so that assumption A.2.6 can be justified by being derived
constraint, but by strict quasi-concavity of the utility function, it has from utility-maximizing considerations.
a higher utility than either, which contradicts the choice of x~.
DEFINITION 17. We define
THEOREM 7.. If Uh(x 11 ) is strictly quasi-concave, then for every p
there is, at rnost, one x~ that rnaxirnizes Uh(xh) subject to pxh :S:: Mh,
xh E Xh. If p O, there is one such x~.
in the natural way at any p for which xh(p) is defined and as equal
In view of T.4. 7, it is legitirnate to define to + oo otherwise.
DEFINITION 15. The uncompensated demandfunction xh(p,Mh) is the We will show that the function
unique x~ that rnaxirnizes U11 (xh) subject to px11 :S:: Mh, xh E X 11 .
In general equilibriurn theory, M 11 is, in turn, a function of p, as
2 Xll(p),

defined by A.4.3.
so defined, is continuous. Continuity for an extended-real-valued
DEFINITION 16. The demand function xh(p) = x 11 [p,M11 (p)], where function that can take on the value +oo has the usual meaning at
Mh(p) is defined. by A.4.3. any point where the function is finite, while for any sequence {pv}
approaching p 0 , where
Then T.4.7 implies that the uncornpensated demand function and
the demand function are both well defined on a domain that includes
all strictly positive price vectors. A particular consequence is the
'i
1 i well-known weak assumption of revealed preference. If x~ is a we require that
vector satisfying the budget constraint p 1 x~ :S:: M~, but x~ i=
: 1

r
xh(p\Mk), then Uh[x 1.(p\Mk)] > U1.(x~). If in particular, x~ =
'"""Ir
i

100 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONSUMER DECISIONS AND EFFIC!ENT ALLOCATIONS 101
" '
,, As in Section 3.4, we assurne that the set of cornrnodities can be xh(p 2 ,M~), it must maximize utility subject to the budget constraint,

~
:1 ' ~ partitioned into two parts, for one of which the household is assurned p 2 x :S:: M~; therefore it must be that x 11 (p\MD does not satisfy that
to ha ve no utility; that is, we can write the vector, x 11 , as (x~,x~),
" 1

budget constraint.
where U11 (x 11 ) = U11 (x~,xD is, in fact, independent of x~. Analo-
''1 ;. Corollary 7 (Revealed Preference). If p 1 x 11 (p 2 ,M~) :s; M 1~ and
gously to the assurnption that Y1 is strictly convex with respect to
xlt(p\MD i= xh(p 2 ,Mn, then p 2 x 11 (p\Mk) > M~.
1:'1111' those cornrnodities that appear in it at al!, we strengthen our assurnp-
'" tions on preferences to strict convexity; that is, if xk :P: x~ and From T.4.7, if x 11 (p) is not defined for sorne p, then there is no
O < a < 1, then ax~ + (1 - a)x~ >- x~ provided xk and x~ differ in utility-maximizing x 11 under the budget constraint. The lack of
sorne of the a-cornponents. The dernand for the b-cornrnodities is definition comes from the fact that the household is not satiated in
O for all price levels; it is perrnissible, for sirnplicity, to assurne that sorne free goods so its demand is, in sorne appropriate sense, infinite.
all cornrnodities are a-cornrnodities. (Sorne cornplication may arise The example given at the beginning of Section 2.8 shows, however,
frorn the fact that sorne cornrnodities in the household's endowrnent that sorne care must be taken in defining the sense in which demands
are b-cornrnodities, not desired for its own consurnption; but we will may be infinite at zero price; even if the household is not satiated
carry incorne, M 11 , as a separate variable when needed.) in any comrnodity, demands need not approach infinity as prices
For any given p O, the set of cornrnodity vectors in Xh that approach a lirnit in which sotne cornponents are zero. On the other
satisfy the budget constraint, pxh :s; Mh, is a cornpact set, so there hand, in the same exarnple it was shown that the su m of the demands
exists at least one x~, rnaxirnizing Uh(xh) in this set. If xk also for all commodities does approach infinity as any set of prices
maxirnized Uh(x~) in this set, then Uh(xh) = Uh(xk). Let x~ be a approaches O. This is a general result, which will now be dernon-
proper convex cornbination of the two; then it satisfies the budget strated, so that assumption A.2.6 can be justified by being derived
constraint, but by strict quasi-concavity of the utility function, it has from utility-maximizing considerations.
a higher utility than either, which contradicts the choice of x~.
DEFINITION 17. We define
THEOREM 7.. If Uh(x 11 ) is strictly quasi-concave, then for every p
there is, at rnost, one x~ that rnaxirnizes Uh(xh) subject to pxh :S:: Mh,
xh E Xh. If p O, there is one such x~.
in the natural way at any p for which xh(p) is defined and as equal
In view of T.4. 7, it is legitirnate to define to + oo otherwise.
DEFINITION 15. The uncompensated demandfunction xh(p,Mh) is the We will show that the function
unique x~ that rnaxirnizes U11 (xh) subject to px11 :S:: Mh, xh E X 11 .
In general equilibriurn theory, M 11 is, in turn, a function of p, as
2 Xll(p),

defined by A.4.3.
so defined, is continuous. Continuity for an extended-real-valued
DEFINITION 16. The demand function xh(p) = x 11 [p,M11 (p)], where function that can take on the value +oo has the usual meaning at
Mh(p) is defined. by A.4.3. any point where the function is finite, while for any sequence {pv}
approaching p 0 , where
Then T.4.7 implies that the uncornpensated demand function and
the demand function are both well defined on a domain that includes
all strictly positive price vectors. A particular consequence is the
'i
1 i well-known weak assumption of revealed preference. If x~ is a we require that
vector satisfying the budget constraint p 1 x~ :S:: M~, but x~ i=
: 1

r
xh(p\Mk), then Uh[x 1.(p\Mk)] > U1.(x~). If in particular, x~ =
T
1
r
!

102 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSJS CONSUMER.DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 103

on the subsequence (if infinite) for which As v approaches infinity, pvx(p)--+ M(p), M(pv)--+ M(p), and f3v
remains bounded.
X{pv) < +oo.
i px':::; M(p).
As the discussion in Section 4.1 (preceding Lemma 4.2) suggests, Since x' =6 x(p), it follows by definition that U(x') < U[x(p)];
we are unlikely to achieve continuity in any sense if income is at the therefore
mnimum possible. It will follow from Lemma 5.1 that M is above U(x'v) < U[x(p)]
the mnimum possible if and only if M > O. We will therefore
for v sufficiently large; from (7), then, U[x(pv)] :::; U(x'v). Also, by
assume M > Ofor all possible prices-a strong assumption, because
continuity, we can choose ,\ > Oso that U(x') < U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)],
it means, in effect, that X O, unless the household owns shares in
so that
a firm that makes positive profits at any set of prices.
U(x'v) :::; U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)] v large,
THEOREM 8. If the utility function U(X) is strictly quasi-concave
and Mh > O for all p, then X(p) is continuous in its domain of and therefore
definition, which includes all p O, and U[x(pv)] :::; U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)],
which implies that

as extended by D.4.17, is continuous everywhere on the unit simplex,


Sn Let v approach infinity.

Proof In this proof, we will drop the subscript h. Suppose ,\px + (1 - ,\)M(p) ;::: M(p),
x(p) is defined, but not continuous, at sorne price vector p. Then
or px ;::: M(p). But as will be seen in Lemma 5.1, this is impossible
there is a sequence {pv}, pv--+ p, and a positive number " such that
if M(p) > O.
lx(pv) - x(p)l ;::: E > O all v. It remains to show that if x is not defined at p, then for every
sequence {pv}, pv--+ p, : X(pv)--+ oo. If not, then there is a sequence
Let i
{pv} converging to p for which {x(pv)} is bounded. Let x' be a limit
E point of the sequence. Since pvx(pv) :::; M(pv), px' :::; M(p). We
f3v = lx(pv) - x(p)l' show, in fact, that x' maximizes U(x) subject to px :::; M(p); then
x'v = f3vx(pv) + (1 - f3v)x(p). x(p) would be defined equal to x', a contradiction. Consider any
x" for which U(x") > U(x'). Then, for sorne ,\ > O,
Since O < f3v :::; 1, x'v is a convex combination of two members of X
and hence belongs to X. By quasi-concavity,
U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > U(x'),

and therefore
if U[x(p)] > U(x'v), then U(x'v) ;::: U[x(pv)]. (7)
U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > U[x(pv)],
Since lx'v - x(p)l = E, we can choose a subsequence for which
x'v--+ x', where lx' - x(p)l = E. Then x' E X, since X is closed. for v sufficiently large along the appropriate subsequence. By
Since pvx(pv) :::; M(pv), definition of x(pv), this implies that

pVx'V :::; f3vM(pV) + (1 - f3v)pVx(p) = pVX(p) + f3v[M(pv) - pVx(p)]. pv[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > M(pv).
T
1
r
!

102 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSJS CONSUMER.DECISIONS AND EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 103

on the subsequence (if infinite) for which As v approaches infinity, pvx(p)--+ M(p), M(pv)--+ M(p), and f3v
remains bounded.
X{pv) < +oo.
i px':::; M(p).
As the discussion in Section 4.1 (preceding Lemma 4.2) suggests, Since x' =6 x(p), it follows by definition that U(x') < U[x(p)];
we are unlikely to achieve continuity in any sense if income is at the therefore
mnimum possible. It will follow from Lemma 5.1 that M is above U(x'v) < U[x(p)]
the mnimum possible if and only if M > O. We will therefore
for v sufficiently large; from (7), then, U[x(pv)] :::; U(x'v). Also, by
assume M > Ofor all possible prices-a strong assumption, because
continuity, we can choose ,\ > Oso that U(x') < U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)],
it means, in effect, that X O, unless the household owns shares in
so that
a firm that makes positive profits at any set of prices.
U(x'v) :::; U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)] v large,
THEOREM 8. If the utility function U(X) is strictly quasi-concave
and Mh > O for all p, then X(p) is continuous in its domain of and therefore
definition, which includes all p O, and U[x(pv)] :::; U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x(p)],
which implies that

as extended by D.4.17, is continuous everywhere on the unit simplex,


Sn Let v approach infinity.

Proof In this proof, we will drop the subscript h. Suppose ,\px + (1 - ,\)M(p) ;::: M(p),
x(p) is defined, but not continuous, at sorne price vector p. Then
or px ;::: M(p). But as will be seen in Lemma 5.1, this is impossible
there is a sequence {pv}, pv--+ p, and a positive number " such that
if M(p) > O.
lx(pv) - x(p)l ;::: E > O all v. It remains to show that if x is not defined at p, then for every
sequence {pv}, pv--+ p, : X(pv)--+ oo. If not, then there is a sequence
Let i
{pv} converging to p for which {x(pv)} is bounded. Let x' be a limit
E point of the sequence. Since pvx(pv) :::; M(pv), px' :::; M(p). We
f3v = lx(pv) - x(p)l' show, in fact, that x' maximizes U(x) subject to px :::; M(p); then
x'v = f3vx(pv) + (1 - f3v)x(p). x(p) would be defined equal to x', a contradiction. Consider any
x" for which U(x") > U(x'). Then, for sorne ,\ > O,
Since O < f3v :::; 1, x'v is a convex combination of two members of X
and hence belongs to X. By quasi-concavity,
U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > U(x'),

and therefore
if U[x(p)] > U(x'v), then U(x'v) ;::: U[x(pv)]. (7)
U[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > U[x(pv)],
Since lx'v - x(p)l = E, we can choose a subsequence for which
x'v--+ x', where lx' - x(p)l = E. Then x' E X, since X is closed. for v sufficiently large along the appropriate subsequence. By
Since pvx(pv) :::; M(pv), definition of x(pv), this implies that

pVx'V :::; f3vM(pV) + (1 - f3v)pVx(p) = pVX(p) + f3v[M(pv) - pVx(p)]. pv[,\x + (1 - ,\)x"] > M(pv).
104 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T CONSUMER DECISIONS ANO EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 105

Let v approach infinity a1ong the appropriate subsequence. If C" is twice differentiable, then, by (b) of the theorem, the
Jacobian with elements o2 C1.Jop[Jp1 is negative semi-definite and
p[.\x + (1 - .\)x"] ;::: M(p). symmetrk. Thus,
Since M(p) > O, M(p) > px, by Lemma 5.1. Hence, o2 C" oxh1(p,uh)
(9)
op 1op 1 = op 1
.\M(p) + (1 - .\)px" > M(p),
and the elements of the Jacobian are the substitution terms of
or px" > M(p). That is, any x" preferred to x' must be unavailable traditional theory.
at income M(p) and prices p, or equivalently, x' maximizes U(x) to Now differentiate (8) with respect to p1
px::::; M(p).
'ox(p,uh) = ox(p,M) ~ [ox(p,M)] (oC);
Now let us examine sorne well-known properties of compensated op1 ap1 oM op 1
demand for those price vectors p for which M" > O. Define the
function substitution for oCjop1 from T.4.9(b) yields
ox(p,U) ox(p,M) + ox(p,M) .
C(p,u) = inf{px 1 U(X) ;::: U, x" E X 1.}, op1 = op 1 aM" xhj,
and interpret it as the lowest cost for household h of attaining a 1
,,
the last term is the well-known income effect. Holding all other 1
prescribed utility leve! U, given the market prices p. The com- prices and money income constant, the effect of a change in one
pensated demand correspondence X(I), u) is then defined by
l!
price, which is the first term on the right-hand side, can be expressed
as the difference between a substitution effect and an income effect. il
X(p,u) = {x" px" = C1.(p,u), x" E X}.
1
From (9) and T.4.9, we deduce 11

If U(X) is strictly quasi-concave, X(p,u") has only one member THEOREM 10. Let U(X) be strictly quasi-concave. Then for all p
for each p for which C(p,u) > O and, therefore, is a function. Por for which M" > O,
by Lemma 4.3 and T.4.7, X(p,u) is the unique element that maxi-
mizes U(x") subject to the budget constraint, px ::::; C(p,u), that
is,

(8)
(b) the matrix with typical element,
The following theorem is proved in exactly the same way as T.3.4
and T.3.6, and we do not repeat the proof here. ox(p,M) + oX;(p,M)
a'P j oMh X,
THEOREM 9. Let U(x) be strictly quasi-concave. Then for all p
is negative semi-definite; in particular,
for which C(p,u) = inf{px" 1 U( X) ;::: u,, X E X"} > O,
oX;(p,M) + OX(p,M) X < O
(a) X(p,u,t) is a function, op; O'M" ht -
(b) C(p,u) is a strictly concave differentiable function of p
over Sn for fixed U, where
Notes
SectiQn J. For the most part, the assumptions of this section are
standard in the economic theory of the household. The treatment of

il
' 1:
!' ~ 1

::i: 1

11'
1 1

:[
104 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T CONSUMER DECISIONS ANO EFFICIENT ALLOCATIONS 105

Let v approach infinity a1ong the appropriate subsequence. If C" is twice differentiable, then, by (b) of the theorem, the
Jacobian with elements o2 C1.Jop[Jp1 is negative semi-definite and
p[.\x + (1 - .\)x"] ;::: M(p). symmetrk. Thus,
Since M(p) > O, M(p) > px, by Lemma 5.1. Hence, o2 C" oxh1(p,uh)
(9)
op 1op 1 = op 1
.\M(p) + (1 - .\)px" > M(p),
and the elements of the Jacobian are the substitution terms of
or px" > M(p). That is, any x" preferred to x' must be unavailable traditional theory.
at income M(p) and prices p, or equivalently, x' maximizes U(x) to Now differentiate (8) with respect to p1
px::::; M(p).
'ox(p,uh) = ox(p,M) ~ [ox(p,M)] (oC);
Now let us examine sorne well-known properties of compensated op1 ap1 oM op 1
demand for those price vectors p for which M" > O. Define the
function substitution for oCjop1 from T.4.9(b) yields
ox(p,U) ox(p,M) + ox(p,M) .
C(p,u) = inf{px 1 U(X) ;::: U, x" E X 1.}, op1 = op 1 aM" xhj,
and interpret it as the lowest cost for household h of attaining a 1
,,
the last term is the well-known income effect. Holding all other 1
prescribed utility leve! U, given the market prices p. The com- prices and money income constant, the effect of a change in one
pensated demand correspondence X(I), u) is then defined by
l!
price, which is the first term on the right-hand side, can be expressed
as the difference between a substitution effect and an income effect. il
X(p,u) = {x" px" = C1.(p,u), x" E X}.
1
From (9) and T.4.9, we deduce 11

If U(X) is strictly quasi-concave, X(p,u") has only one member THEOREM 10. Let U(X) be strictly quasi-concave. Then for all p
for each p for which C(p,u) > O and, therefore, is a function. Por for which M" > O,
by Lemma 4.3 and T.4.7, X(p,u) is the unique element that maxi-
mizes U(x") subject to the budget constraint, px ::::; C(p,u), that
is,

(8)
(b) the matrix with typical element,
The following theorem is proved in exactly the same way as T.3.4
and T.3.6, and we do not repeat the proof here. ox(p,M) + oX;(p,M)
a'P j oMh X,
THEOREM 9. Let U(x) be strictly quasi-concave. Then for all p
is negative semi-definite; in particular,
for which C(p,u) = inf{px" 1 U( X) ;::: u,, X E X"} > O,
oX;(p,M) + OX(p,M) X < O
(a) X(p,u,t) is a function, op; O'M" ht -
(b) C(p,u) is a strictly concave differentiable function of p
over Sn for fixed U, where
Notes
SectiQn J. For the most part, the assumptions of this section are
standard in the economic theory of the household. The treatment of

il
' 1:
!' ~ 1

::i: 1

11'
1 1

:[
106 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1

Chapter Five
different kinds of labor as displacements of different kinds of leisure and THE EXISTENCE OF
the consequent time constraint on types of leisure was introduced by
Arrow and Debreu [1954, pp. 268-269]. The time constraints on COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
consumption in general have been stressed by Becker [1965].
Section 2. Since the introduction of indifference surfaces by Pareto
and Irving Fisher, it has been taken for granted that they could be At length 1 saw these lovers full were
represented by a utility function. Wold seems to have been the first to come
see the need of specifying assumptions under which the representation
lnto their torture of equilibrium.
by a continuous utility function exists [1943-44, sections 31, 37]. Wold
assumed that Xn is the entire non-negative orthant and that preference - John Crowe Ransom,
is strictly monotonic in each commodity. In that case, it is easy to The Equilibrists
verify that each possible consumption vector is indifferent to precisely
one vector of the form p,e, and p, can be used as the utility function. A
very considerable generalization, based on a mathematical paper by
l. Compensated and Competitive Equilibrium: Definitions and
Eilenberg [1941], was achieved with deeper methods by Debreu [1954]; Interrelations
he assumed only the continuity of preferences and the connectedness of
An (uncompensated) competitive equilibrium has the meaning
Xj, (a property weaker than convexity). The construction of the utility
function involves selection of a denumerable subset of Xn everywhere usual in the economic literature: a set of prices and production and 1

:,"
dense in it, defining a utility function by placing it inductively into one- consumption allocations such that each firm maximizes profits at
to-one correspondence with the rational numbers on the unit interval, the given prices, each household maximizes utility at the given prices
,' 1, and extending this utility function to the entire consumption possibility and with the income implied by those prices and its initial holdings
:,l'i set by a limiting process. The proof is straightforward, but lengthy;
'1'1'': of assets and profit shares, and aggregate consumption is feasible in
jill,: the result is valid in infinite-dimensional spaces with suitable properties.
Further extensions are due to Rader [1963], who gives a simple con- not exceeding the sum of aggregate production and initial endow-
:'1 .li'',
'1' struction, and to Debreu [1964]; the proof of one of the lemmas in the ments. Formally,
.i :lf
1

1
,11'
'
'
last paper has beennotably simplified by Bowen [1968].
'1 A more elementary approach in the spirit of Wold's can also be DEFINITION l. A price vector, p*, a consumption allocation, a::*, and
supplied for general convex Xn and continuous preferences. Choose a production allocatioh, y*, consttute a competitive equilibrium if
any strictly positive price vector p0 and define Un(x) to be the cheapest
way of buying a commodity vector not inferior to x. Then if x mini- (a) p* >O;
mizes p 0 x over X, it is very easy to verify that Un(x) is a continuous (b) L; x;;' ~ L; Y1' + L;h x11 ;
utility function over the subset of Xn for which Xn ~ x. However, this } f
utility function cannot be extended to the entire set Xn without addi- (e) yj maximizes p*y1 subject to Yr E Y1 ;
tional assumptions; one set that suffices is to assume that Xn is poly- (d) x;;' maximizes U(X) subject to p*x11 ~ M;;' = p*x1 +
hedral and preferences are convex. ; dhf(p*yj).
The approach used here was suggested to the authors by James f
Mirrlees, to whom we are grateful.
Section 4. The basic theorem of welfare economics, T.4.4, has a As already suggested in Section 4.1, it is convenient as an inter-
well-known long history. The use of convex set theory to provide a
rigorous statement is due independently to Arrow [1951] and Debreu media te step in deriving sufficient conditions for the existence of a
[1951]. competitive equilibrium to find sufficient conditions for the existence
Section 6. Most of the material in this section is too familiar for of another type of equilibrium, which we call a compensated equi-
reference; see also the Notes to Section 3.4. T.4.8 is new; the proof librium. This differs from the competitive equilibrium in the
here is James Mirrlees' simplification of our original proof. assumptions about consumer behavior; households are assumed
to minimize the cost of achieving a given utility level, and it is then
postulated separately that their income is sufficient to cover these
mnimum costs.
!1'.:11
ji 1
107
il!
1!11
1''1'
1 1
!!
il
!l
i
ti:
106 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1

Chapter Five
different kinds of labor as displacements of different kinds of leisure and THE EXISTENCE OF
the consequent time constraint on types of leisure was introduced by
Arrow and Debreu [1954, pp. 268-269]. The time constraints on COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
consumption in general have been stressed by Becker [1965].
Section 2. Since the introduction of indifference surfaces by Pareto
and Irving Fisher, it has been taken for granted that they could be At length 1 saw these lovers full were
represented by a utility function. Wold seems to have been the first to come
see the need of specifying assumptions under which the representation
lnto their torture of equilibrium.
by a continuous utility function exists [1943-44, sections 31, 37]. Wold
assumed that Xn is the entire non-negative orthant and that preference - John Crowe Ransom,
is strictly monotonic in each commodity. In that case, it is easy to The Equilibrists
verify that each possible consumption vector is indifferent to precisely
one vector of the form p,e, and p, can be used as the utility function. A
very considerable generalization, based on a mathematical paper by
l. Compensated and Competitive Equilibrium: Definitions and
Eilenberg [1941], was achieved with deeper methods by Debreu [1954]; Interrelations
he assumed only the continuity of preferences and the connectedness of
An (uncompensated) competitive equilibrium has the meaning
Xj, (a property weaker than convexity). The construction of the utility
function involves selection of a denumerable subset of Xn everywhere usual in the economic literature: a set of prices and production and 1

:,"
dense in it, defining a utility function by placing it inductively into one- consumption allocations such that each firm maximizes profits at
to-one correspondence with the rational numbers on the unit interval, the given prices, each household maximizes utility at the given prices
,' 1, and extending this utility function to the entire consumption possibility and with the income implied by those prices and its initial holdings
:,l'i set by a limiting process. The proof is straightforward, but lengthy;
'1'1'': of assets and profit shares, and aggregate consumption is feasible in
jill,: the result is valid in infinite-dimensional spaces with suitable properties.
Further extensions are due to Rader [1963], who gives a simple con- not exceeding the sum of aggregate production and initial endow-
:'1 .li'',
'1' struction, and to Debreu [1964]; the proof of one of the lemmas in the ments. Formally,
.i :lf
1

1
,11'
'
'
last paper has beennotably simplified by Bowen [1968].
'1 A more elementary approach in the spirit of Wold's can also be DEFINITION l. A price vector, p*, a consumption allocation, a::*, and
supplied for general convex Xn and continuous preferences. Choose a production allocatioh, y*, consttute a competitive equilibrium if
any strictly positive price vector p0 and define Un(x) to be the cheapest
way of buying a commodity vector not inferior to x. Then if x mini- (a) p* >O;
mizes p 0 x over X, it is very easy to verify that Un(x) is a continuous (b) L; x;;' ~ L; Y1' + L;h x11 ;
utility function over the subset of Xn for which Xn ~ x. However, this } f
utility function cannot be extended to the entire set Xn without addi- (e) yj maximizes p*y1 subject to Yr E Y1 ;
tional assumptions; one set that suffices is to assume that Xn is poly- (d) x;;' maximizes U(X) subject to p*x11 ~ M;;' = p*x1 +
hedral and preferences are convex. ; dhf(p*yj).
The approach used here was suggested to the authors by James f
Mirrlees, to whom we are grateful.
Section 4. The basic theorem of welfare economics, T.4.4, has a As already suggested in Section 4.1, it is convenient as an inter-
well-known long history. The use of convex set theory to provide a
rigorous statement is due independently to Arrow [1951] and Debreu media te step in deriving sufficient conditions for the existence of a
[1951]. competitive equilibrium to find sufficient conditions for the existence
Section 6. Most of the material in this section is too familiar for of another type of equilibrium, which we call a compensated equi-
reference; see also the Notes to Section 3.4. T.4.8 is new; the proof librium. This differs from the competitive equilibrium in the
here is James Mirrlees' simplification of our original proof. assumptions about consumer behavior; households are assumed
to minimize the cost of achieving a given utility level, and it is then
postulated separately that their income is sufficient to cover these
mnimum costs.
!1'.:11
ji 1
107
il!
1!11
1''1'
1 1
!!
il
!l
i
ti:
T
i

108 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 109

DEFINITION 2. A price vector, p*, a utility allocation, u*, a con- which both p 1 > O and x"1 > O; similarly, p(x,, - x") > O if and
sumption allocation, x*, and a production allocation, JI'*, constitute only if there is at least one component i for which p 1 > O and
a compensated equilibrium if xhl - x"1 > O. Hence,
(a) p* >O; px" > O if and only if p(x" - x") > O.
(b) 2: x;i' :;::; yj
f
+ h X.";
h Also, obviously,
(e) yj maximizes p*y1 subject to y1 E Y1 ;
(d) x;i' minimizes p*x" subject to Uh(xh) :2:: u;;'; M" > O if and only if either px" > O or f dh!(PYr) > O;
(e) p*x;i' =M;;'.
M" - px" > O if and only if either p(x" - x") > O or
As is already evident from Lemmas 4.2 and 4.3, there is a close
dhf(py) > o.
f
relation between the two kinds of equilibria. In one direction the
These statements taken together imply the lemma.
relation is very simple.
In particular, Lemma 5.1 implies that if M" > O, then there is
THEOREM l. If (p* ,x* ,y*) is a competitive equilibrium and u1~ = sorne x;, (
= x") in X" for which px~ < M".
U"(x;D for each h, then (p*,u*,x*,y*) is a compensated equilibrium.
TI-IEOREM 2. If (p* ,u* ,x* ,y*) is a compensated equilibrium and
,Proof D.5.2(a)-(c) are identical with D.5.I(a)-(c). Lemma 4.2 M;;' > O, all h, then (p* ,x* ,y*) is a competitive equilibrium.
asserts that a consumption vector that maximizes utility subject to
a budget constraint also minimizes the cost of achieving that utility Proof D.5.2(a)-(c) are identical with D.5.l(a)-(c). If M;;' > O,
leve!, so that D.5:I(d) implies D.5.2(d). Finally, suppose that then,. by D.5.2(e), p*x;i' = M;;' > p*x~ for some x~ in X", as just
D.5.2(e) does not hold. From D.5.l(d), p*x;i' < M;;'. But then, by remarked. By Lemma 4.3, it follows from D.5.2(d) that x;i' maxi-
Corollary 4. 1, we can choose x~ arbitrarily el ose to x;i' su eh that mizes U"(x") subject to the budget constraint, p*x" :;::; M;;'.
U(x;,) > U"(x;i'). In particular, x~ can be chosen so that p*x~ :;::;
It is not necessarily true that at a compensated equilibrium every
M;;', which is a contradiction to the assumption that x;i' is utility
household has positive income. The absence of positive inco,me
maximizing under the budget constraint.
implies that there cannot exist a possible consumption vector that
Corresponding to Lemma 4.3, a partial converse of T.5.1 is valid.
costs less than total income (since all possible consumption vectors
First, we note
are non-negative); in view of Lemma 4.3, this raises the possibility
LEMMA l. lf p > 0 and py r :2:: 0, all j, then that utility-maximizing and cost-minimizing behavior do not
coincide. In particular, from the discussion preceding Lemma 4.2,
(a) M" :2:: O, all h;
there is a possibility that the uncompensated demand functions are
(b) for any h, M,, > O if and only if M" > px".
discontinuous.
Proof By definition, It can be shown, however, that at least one household has positive
income.
M" = px" + 2:f d"r(PYr).
M" - px" = p(x~ - x") + dhr(PY1). LEMMA 2. If (p*,u*,x*,y-*) is a compensated equilibrium, then
f M;;' > O, for some h.
From the hypotheses, obviously, M :2:: O, all h. But from A.4.2, it
is assumed that :X - x" :2:: Oand that :X" has exactly the same positive
Proof It suffices to prove
components (and the same zero components) as :X" - x". Since
2M;;'> O.
p > O, px" > O if and only if there is at least one component i for h
T
i

108 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 109

DEFINITION 2. A price vector, p*, a utility allocation, u*, a con- which both p 1 > O and x"1 > O; similarly, p(x,, - x") > O if and
sumption allocation, x*, and a production allocation, JI'*, constitute only if there is at least one component i for which p 1 > O and
a compensated equilibrium if xhl - x"1 > O. Hence,
(a) p* >O; px" > O if and only if p(x" - x") > O.
(b) 2: x;i' :;::; yj
f
+ h X.";
h Also, obviously,
(e) yj maximizes p*y1 subject to y1 E Y1 ;
(d) x;i' minimizes p*x" subject to Uh(xh) :2:: u;;'; M" > O if and only if either px" > O or f dh!(PYr) > O;
(e) p*x;i' =M;;'.
M" - px" > O if and only if either p(x" - x") > O or
As is already evident from Lemmas 4.2 and 4.3, there is a close
dhf(py) > o.
f
relation between the two kinds of equilibria. In one direction the
These statements taken together imply the lemma.
relation is very simple.
In particular, Lemma 5.1 implies that if M" > O, then there is
THEOREM l. If (p* ,x* ,y*) is a competitive equilibrium and u1~ = sorne x;, (
= x") in X" for which px~ < M".
U"(x;D for each h, then (p*,u*,x*,y*) is a compensated equilibrium.
TI-IEOREM 2. If (p* ,u* ,x* ,y*) is a compensated equilibrium and
,Proof D.5.2(a)-(c) are identical with D.5.I(a)-(c). Lemma 4.2 M;;' > O, all h, then (p* ,x* ,y*) is a competitive equilibrium.
asserts that a consumption vector that maximizes utility subject to
a budget constraint also minimizes the cost of achieving that utility Proof D.5.2(a)-(c) are identical with D.5.l(a)-(c). If M;;' > O,
leve!, so that D.5:I(d) implies D.5.2(d). Finally, suppose that then,. by D.5.2(e), p*x;i' = M;;' > p*x~ for some x~ in X", as just
D.5.2(e) does not hold. From D.5.l(d), p*x;i' < M;;'. But then, by remarked. By Lemma 4.3, it follows from D.5.2(d) that x;i' maxi-
Corollary 4. 1, we can choose x~ arbitrarily el ose to x;i' su eh that mizes U"(x") subject to the budget constraint, p*x" :;::; M;;'.
U(x;,) > U"(x;i'). In particular, x~ can be chosen so that p*x~ :;::;
It is not necessarily true that at a compensated equilibrium every
M;;', which is a contradiction to the assumption that x;i' is utility
household has positive income. The absence of positive inco,me
maximizing under the budget constraint.
implies that there cannot exist a possible consumption vector that
Corresponding to Lemma 4.3, a partial converse of T.5.1 is valid.
costs less than total income (since all possible consumption vectors
First, we note
are non-negative); in view of Lemma 4.3, this raises the possibility
LEMMA l. lf p > 0 and py r :2:: 0, all j, then that utility-maximizing and cost-minimizing behavior do not
coincide. In particular, from the discussion preceding Lemma 4.2,
(a) M" :2:: O, all h;
there is a possibility that the uncompensated demand functions are
(b) for any h, M,, > O if and only if M" > px".
discontinuous.
Proof By definition, It can be shown, however, that at least one household has positive
income.
M" = px" + 2:f d"r(PYr).
M" - px" = p(x~ - x") + dhr(PY1). LEMMA 2. If (p*,u*,x*,y-*) is a compensated equilibrium, then
f M;;' > O, for some h.
From the hypotheses, obviously, M :2:: O, all h. But from A.4.2, it
is assumed that :X - x" :2:: Oand that :X" has exactly the same positive
Proof It suffices to prove
components (and the same zero components) as :X" - x". Since
2M;;'> O.
p > O, px" > O if and only if there is at least one component i for h
T
1

110 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 111


By definition, however, such that U"(xk) > u;, all h. Since x/t minimizes the cost of
achieving the utility leve] u/t,
2: M/t = [p*x" + d,(p*yj)J = p*x,, + dM(p*yj)
h h f h h f p*x/t :::; p*xk all h,
= 2: p*x" + (2: dnr) (p*yj) = p*x, + p*yj, or, in view of D.5.2(e), the balanced budget condition,
h f h h f

since
M/t :::; p*xk all h.
By Lemma 5.2, there is at least one h for which M/t > O. By
for allf Lemma 5.1, p*x/t = M/t > p*x~z for that h, and therefore, x/t is a]so
utility maximizing subject to the budget constraint p*x" :::; M/t, by
We have assumed (A.3.5) that the economy is capable of supplying Lemma 4.3. Since U,.(xk) > U~z(x/t) = u/t in this case, it must be 1:
a positive amount of each good; that is, there exists a socially '1

possible production vector, y, such that, x + y O. Since p* > O,


that 1 ~
sorne h,
p*x + p*y = p*(x + y) > o. so that
Since yj is profit maximizing over Y1 , eachf, p*xk > 2 M/t = 2 p*x~z + 2: p*yJ.
h h h f
(2)

y* = L YJ is profit maximizing over Y= LY 1,


On the other hand, from (1), since p* > O,
f 1

so that 2 p*xk :::; 2 p*x" + 2 p*y}. f


p*yJ = p*y* 2 p*y,
f Finally, since
h h

YJ is profit maximizing, p*y} :::; p*yJ', all J, so


and therefore,
2 p*xk :::; 2 p*x" + 2 p*yJ,
M/t = p*x + p*yJ > o. h h f

h f in contradiction to (2).

Por our purposes, Lemma 5.2 will be usefullater in establishing It may be worthwhile noting at this point that the theorems and
a condition under which a compensated equilibrium is also a com- lemmas of this section depend on only a few of the assumptions made
petitive equilibrium. It is worthwhile, however, to note here that a in Chapters 3 and 4; in particular, they do not depend on the
sufficiency theorem for Pareto efficiency can be established at this convexity assumptions.
stage, although this theorem is not directly relevant to our main aim
of proving the existence of equilibrium. 2. Mapping the Pareto Frontier into a Simplex
THEOREM 3. If (p*,u*,x*,y*) is a compensated equilibrium, then u* The main tool in proving the existence of equilibrium is Kakutani's
is a Pareto-efficient utility allocation. fixed-point theorem (see T.C.4). This theorem states that an upper
Proof Suppose not. Then there would exist an allocation semi-continuous correspondence that maps points in a compact
(xl,y 1), which is feasible, convex set into convex subsets of that set has a fixed point; that
is, there is one point that belongs to the subset associated with
(1) it by the correspondence. As we will see in the next section, there
is a very natural mapping whose fixed point can be seen to be a
T
1

110 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 111


By definition, however, such that U"(xk) > u;, all h. Since x/t minimizes the cost of
achieving the utility leve] u/t,
2: M/t = [p*x" + d,(p*yj)J = p*x,, + dM(p*yj)
h h f h h f p*x/t :::; p*xk all h,
= 2: p*x" + (2: dnr) (p*yj) = p*x, + p*yj, or, in view of D.5.2(e), the balanced budget condition,
h f h h f

since
M/t :::; p*xk all h.
By Lemma 5.2, there is at least one h for which M/t > O. By
for allf Lemma 5.1, p*x/t = M/t > p*x~z for that h, and therefore, x/t is a]so
utility maximizing subject to the budget constraint p*x" :::; M/t, by
We have assumed (A.3.5) that the economy is capable of supplying Lemma 4.3. Since U,.(xk) > U~z(x/t) = u/t in this case, it must be 1:
a positive amount of each good; that is, there exists a socially '1

possible production vector, y, such that, x + y O. Since p* > O,


that 1 ~
sorne h,
p*x + p*y = p*(x + y) > o. so that
Since yj is profit maximizing over Y1 , eachf, p*xk > 2 M/t = 2 p*x~z + 2: p*yJ.
h h h f
(2)

y* = L YJ is profit maximizing over Y= LY 1,


On the other hand, from (1), since p* > O,
f 1

so that 2 p*xk :::; 2 p*x" + 2 p*y}. f


p*yJ = p*y* 2 p*y,
f Finally, since
h h

YJ is profit maximizing, p*y} :::; p*yJ', all J, so


and therefore,
2 p*xk :::; 2 p*x" + 2 p*yJ,
M/t = p*x + p*yJ > o. h h f

h f in contradiction to (2).

Por our purposes, Lemma 5.2 will be usefullater in establishing It may be worthwhile noting at this point that the theorems and
a condition under which a compensated equilibrium is also a com- lemmas of this section depend on only a few of the assumptions made
petitive equilibrium. It is worthwhile, however, to note here that a in Chapters 3 and 4; in particular, they do not depend on the
sufficiency theorem for Pareto efficiency can be established at this convexity assumptions.
stage, although this theorem is not directly relevant to our main aim
of proving the existence of equilibrium. 2. Mapping the Pareto Frontier into a Simplex
THEOREM 3. If (p*,u*,x*,y*) is a compensated equilibrium, then u* The main tool in proving the existence of equilibrium is Kakutani's
is a Pareto-efficient utility allocation. fixed-point theorem (see T.C.4). This theorem states that an upper
Proof Suppose not. Then there would exist an allocation semi-continuous correspondence that maps points in a compact
(xl,y 1), which is feasible, convex set into convex subsets of that set has a fixed point; that
is, there is one point that belongs to the subset associated with
(1) it by the correspondence. As we will see in the next section, there
is a very natural mapping whose fixed point can be seen to be a
112 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T 113
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

compensated equilibrium; but the domain from which the mapping It is easy to see that if the inverse of v(u) is well defined, it must be
takes place is, in part, the Pareto frontier (more precise1y, the domain continuous. To show that it is well defined is to say that the
is the Cartesian product of severa! sets, one of which is the set of equation
non-negative, Pareto-efficient utility allocations). However, the v(u) = v
Pareto frontier certainly need not be itself a convex set. Indeed,
since the utility functions are defined only up to monotone trans- has a unique so!ution, U, for every VE Sj. If
formations, convexity, which is a cardinal property, can ha ve no real
significance.
,\ = 2: u,,
h
i 1 Nevertheless, the non-negative Pareto frontier can be shown to be
1 a positive 'scalar, then v(u) = v implies
essentially identical to a convex set, in fact to a simplex, from the
topological point of view. It is sufficient to show that there is a u = ,\v for some ,\ > O, u E U'. (4)
simplex, whose dimensionality is one less than the number of house-
Conversely, if (4) holds, then clearly, from (3), v(u) = v. Hence, it
holds, which can be mapped in one-to-one, continuous fashion into
suffices to show that (4) holds for every v E V for a unique ,\,
the non-negative Pareto frontier.
The functions U,(x") together define a mapping from the set of
We will first note that the non-negative Pareto frontier can be
feasible consumption allocations to the set of feasible utility alloca-
mapped continuously into a unit simplex and then show that the
tions. Since the set of feasible consumption allocations is compact,
inverse of this mapping is defined and unique for all elements of the
simplex. as implied by T.4.2, and the functions U" are continuous, the set of
feasible utility allocations is compact For fixed v, then, the set of
Let U' be the non-negative Pareto frontier, that is, the set
scalars,
U' = Un {u 1 u ;:o: O},
{ ,\ 1 ,\v a feasible utility allocation}, (5)
where U is the set of Pareto-efficient points (see D.4.'13). By
Lemma 4.9, O is not Pareto efficient, so every non-negative efficient is also compact. Since O = Ov is certainly feasible for all v (let
allocation is semi-positive, and in particular, x = .v,lf = 0), the set (5) is non-null and hence has a maximum.

u,> o.
h
X(v) = max{,\ 1 ,\v a feasible utility allocation}.
We will show that ,\v is efficient if and only if ,\ = X(v); as pre-
Then the mapping viously remarked, this suffices for the existence of an inverse to v(u).
u If ,\ > X(v), then, by definition, ,\v is not feasible and, therefore, not
v(u) =(tu") (3)
efficient. Now suppose ,\ = X(v). By definition, X(v)v is feasible.
Suppose it were dominated; then, for some feasible u, u X(v)v (see
is well defined and continuous on U'. Further, we obviously have D.4.12). But then there exists ,\ > X(v) for which u ;:o: A.v. Then
,\v is feasible, contrary to the definition of X(v). Hence, X(v)v is
v(u) ;:o: O
undominated and, therefore, efficient.
Since, as already remarked, O = Ov is not efficient, it must be that
so that v(u) maps U' into a unit simplex, SH, where H is the number
of households. X(v) > O.
DEFINITION 3. The set of relative utility vectors is defined by Suppose now ,\ < X(v). Then trivially,
,\v :s; X(v)v, ,\v" < X(v)v" if X(v)v, > O.
By Lemma 4.13, then, ,\vis dominated and, therefore, not efficient.
112 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T 113
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

compensated equilibrium; but the domain from which the mapping It is easy to see that if the inverse of v(u) is well defined, it must be
takes place is, in part, the Pareto frontier (more precise1y, the domain continuous. To show that it is well defined is to say that the
is the Cartesian product of severa! sets, one of which is the set of equation
non-negative, Pareto-efficient utility allocations). However, the v(u) = v
Pareto frontier certainly need not be itself a convex set. Indeed,
since the utility functions are defined only up to monotone trans- has a unique so!ution, U, for every VE Sj. If
formations, convexity, which is a cardinal property, can ha ve no real
significance.
,\ = 2: u,,
h
i 1 Nevertheless, the non-negative Pareto frontier can be shown to be
1 a positive 'scalar, then v(u) = v implies
essentially identical to a convex set, in fact to a simplex, from the
topological point of view. It is sufficient to show that there is a u = ,\v for some ,\ > O, u E U'. (4)
simplex, whose dimensionality is one less than the number of house-
Conversely, if (4) holds, then clearly, from (3), v(u) = v. Hence, it
holds, which can be mapped in one-to-one, continuous fashion into
suffices to show that (4) holds for every v E V for a unique ,\,
the non-negative Pareto frontier.
The functions U,(x") together define a mapping from the set of
We will first note that the non-negative Pareto frontier can be
feasible consumption allocations to the set of feasible utility alloca-
mapped continuously into a unit simplex and then show that the
tions. Since the set of feasible consumption allocations is compact,
inverse of this mapping is defined and unique for all elements of the
simplex. as implied by T.4.2, and the functions U" are continuous, the set of
feasible utility allocations is compact For fixed v, then, the set of
Let U' be the non-negative Pareto frontier, that is, the set
scalars,
U' = Un {u 1 u ;:o: O},
{ ,\ 1 ,\v a feasible utility allocation}, (5)
where U is the set of Pareto-efficient points (see D.4.'13). By
Lemma 4.9, O is not Pareto efficient, so every non-negative efficient is also compact. Since O = Ov is certainly feasible for all v (let
allocation is semi-positive, and in particular, x = .v,lf = 0), the set (5) is non-null and hence has a maximum.

u,> o.
h
X(v) = max{,\ 1 ,\v a feasible utility allocation}.
We will show that ,\v is efficient if and only if ,\ = X(v); as pre-
Then the mapping viously remarked, this suffices for the existence of an inverse to v(u).
u If ,\ > X(v), then, by definition, ,\v is not feasible and, therefore, not
v(u) =(tu") (3)
efficient. Now suppose ,\ = X(v). By definition, X(v)v is feasible.
Suppose it were dominated; then, for some feasible u, u X(v)v (see
is well defined and continuous on U'. Further, we obviously have D.4.12). But then there exists ,\ > X(v) for which u ;:o: A.v. Then
,\v is feasible, contrary to the definition of X(v). Hence, X(v)v is
v(u) ;:o: O
undominated and, therefore, efficient.
Since, as already remarked, O = Ov is not efficient, it must be that
so that v(u) maps U' into a unit simplex, SH, where H is the number
of households. X(v) > O.
DEFINITION 3. The set of relative utility vectors is defined by Suppose now ,\ < X(v). Then trivially,
,\v :s; X(v)v, ,\v" < X(v)v" if X(v)v, > O.
By Lemma 4.13, then, ,\vis dominated and, therefore, not efficient.
T
114 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 115

LEMMA 3: Let SH be the simplex of relative utilities. Then there By the definitions already cited,
is a continuous function, u(v), mapping SH into the non-negative
Pareto frontier, such that Vn = O if and only if un(v) = O. P[u(v)] e P V(p,w) e SH if'[u(v)] e if',
so that the correspondence does map the domain into subsets of
3. . The Existence of Compensated Equilibrium itself. By T.4.6, P(u) is compact and convex for fixed u and upper
semi-continuous in u; since u(v) is continuous in v and u is fixed for
We are now ready to prove expeditiously the existence of a com- fixed v, P[u(v)] is compact and convex for fixed v, and upper semi-
pensated equilibrium. We introduce two more pieces of notation, continuous in v. From Theorem 4.5, Corollary 5, it follows

sn(p,w) = p[x~~ + f dhf(py1) - x~~J = M 11(p,y) - px11 , (6)


similarly that if'[u(v)] is compact and convex for fixed v and upper
semi-continuous in v. From (7), for fixed p and w, V(p,to) is the
intersection of a compact convex set, SH, with a closed convex set
the budgetary surplus for household h if prices are p and the alloca- and, therefore, is compact and convex. We wish to prove that it,
tion is w, and too, is upper semi-continuous in its variables.
V(p,w) = SH n{v 1 VJ = o if sh(p,w) < 0}. (7) Let pv--+ p0 , wv--+ w 0 , vv--+ v0 , vv E V(pv,tt;v). Consider any h for
which
We may think of (7) as an instruction to punish households that
incur budgetary deficits by setting their relative utility, v11 , equal to
O, while imposing no conditions on other households. By Lemma
5.3, equating a relative utility to O is equivalent to equating the Since s11 is a continuous function of p and w, it must be that for v
sufficiently large s11(pv,wv) < O. Then, by definition (7), v); = O for all
utility of that household to O.
The idea of the mapping can be expressed simply. We start with such v. Trivially, vg = O. But then we have shown that vg = O
whenever (9) holds. Since vv E V, all v, it is certainly true that
a price vector, p, a relative utility allocation, v, and a feasible com-
modity allocation, to. These need not be consistent with each other; v0 E V; by (7), v0 E V(p 0 ,w0 ), as was to be proved.
Thus, all three components of the mapping (8) are compact and
we assume each arbitrarily chosen from its appropriate domain.
convex for fixed values of p,v,w and, hence, so is the entire mapping.
The relative utility allocation determines uniquely a non-negative
Also, all three components are upper semi-continuous functions of
Pareto-efficient utility allocation, u = u(v), by Lemma 5.3. Then
there is a non-mili set of price vectors, P(u), that supports the these variables and, hence, sois the entire mapping. By Kakutani's
allocation u, by T.4.4 and D.4.14; by definition of efficiency and fixed-point theorem (see T.C.4), this mapping has a fixed point; that
feasibility, there is a set of feasible allocations, if'(u), that permits is, there is a point (p*,v*,to*) E Sn x SH x if' such that
the realization ofthe utility allocation u, by D.4.10 and D.4.12; and (p* ,v* ,w*) E P [u(v*)] x V(p* ,w*) x "F[u(v*)J. (10)
the initial prices and allocation define budgetary surpluses and there-
with a new set of relative utilities, by (6) and (7). We show that this fixed point in fact satisfies all the conditions for a
' Since u is a function of v, the sets of prices and of feasible alloca- compensated equilibrium, as given in D.5.2. First, let
,,''1
tions can be written P[u(v)] and if'[u(v)], respectively. u* = u(v*). (11)
The doma~n of the mapping, then, is the Cartesian product,
s" x SH x "#"'. s11 and S. are simplexes and, therefore, compact Then (10) can be written as the three statements,
convex sets; by T.4.2, "F is compact and convex. Hence, the
p* E P(u*), (12)
domain is compact and convex.
The correspondence defined on s11 x V x if' is, formally, v* E V(p*,w*), (13)
P [u(v)] x V(p,to) x if'[u(v)]. (8) w* E if'(u*). (14)
T
114 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 115

LEMMA 3: Let SH be the simplex of relative utilities. Then there By the definitions already cited,
is a continuous function, u(v), mapping SH into the non-negative
Pareto frontier, such that Vn = O if and only if un(v) = O. P[u(v)] e P V(p,w) e SH if'[u(v)] e if',
so that the correspondence does map the domain into subsets of
3. . The Existence of Compensated Equilibrium itself. By T.4.6, P(u) is compact and convex for fixed u and upper
semi-continuous in u; since u(v) is continuous in v and u is fixed for
We are now ready to prove expeditiously the existence of a com- fixed v, P[u(v)] is compact and convex for fixed v, and upper semi-
pensated equilibrium. We introduce two more pieces of notation, continuous in v. From Theorem 4.5, Corollary 5, it follows

sn(p,w) = p[x~~ + f dhf(py1) - x~~J = M 11(p,y) - px11 , (6)


similarly that if'[u(v)] is compact and convex for fixed v and upper
semi-continuous in v. From (7), for fixed p and w, V(p,to) is the
intersection of a compact convex set, SH, with a closed convex set
the budgetary surplus for household h if prices are p and the alloca- and, therefore, is compact and convex. We wish to prove that it,
tion is w, and too, is upper semi-continuous in its variables.
V(p,w) = SH n{v 1 VJ = o if sh(p,w) < 0}. (7) Let pv--+ p0 , wv--+ w 0 , vv--+ v0 , vv E V(pv,tt;v). Consider any h for
which
We may think of (7) as an instruction to punish households that
incur budgetary deficits by setting their relative utility, v11 , equal to
O, while imposing no conditions on other households. By Lemma
5.3, equating a relative utility to O is equivalent to equating the Since s11 is a continuous function of p and w, it must be that for v
sufficiently large s11(pv,wv) < O. Then, by definition (7), v); = O for all
utility of that household to O.
The idea of the mapping can be expressed simply. We start with such v. Trivially, vg = O. But then we have shown that vg = O
whenever (9) holds. Since vv E V, all v, it is certainly true that
a price vector, p, a relative utility allocation, v, and a feasible com-
modity allocation, to. These need not be consistent with each other; v0 E V; by (7), v0 E V(p 0 ,w0 ), as was to be proved.
Thus, all three components of the mapping (8) are compact and
we assume each arbitrarily chosen from its appropriate domain.
convex for fixed values of p,v,w and, hence, so is the entire mapping.
The relative utility allocation determines uniquely a non-negative
Also, all three components are upper semi-continuous functions of
Pareto-efficient utility allocation, u = u(v), by Lemma 5.3. Then
there is a non-mili set of price vectors, P(u), that supports the these variables and, hence, sois the entire mapping. By Kakutani's
allocation u, by T.4.4 and D.4.14; by definition of efficiency and fixed-point theorem (see T.C.4), this mapping has a fixed point; that
feasibility, there is a set of feasible allocations, if'(u), that permits is, there is a point (p*,v*,to*) E Sn x SH x if' such that
the realization ofthe utility allocation u, by D.4.10 and D.4.12; and (p* ,v* ,w*) E P [u(v*)] x V(p* ,w*) x "F[u(v*)J. (10)
the initial prices and allocation define budgetary surpluses and there-
with a new set of relative utilities, by (6) and (7). We show that this fixed point in fact satisfies all the conditions for a
' Since u is a function of v, the sets of prices and of feasible alloca- compensated equilibrium, as given in D.5.2. First, let
,,''1
tions can be written P[u(v)] and if'[u(v)], respectively. u* = u(v*). (11)
The doma~n of the mapping, then, is the Cartesian product,
s" x SH x "#"'. s11 and S. are simplexes and, therefore, compact Then (10) can be written as the three statements,
convex sets; by T.4.2, "F is compact and convex. Hence, the
p* E P(u*), (12)
domain is compact and convex.
The correspondence defined on s11 x V x if' is, formally, v* E V(p*,w*), (13)
P [u(v)] x V(p,to) x if'[u(v)]. (8) w* E if'(u*). (14)
-ll
li:

116 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 117

Recall the definitions of P(u) (D.4.14) and il'(u) (D.4.10), and then We will say that household h' is resource related to household h"
use (12) and (14) in conjunction with the basic theorem on Pareto if some increase in those assets held by household h' in so me positive
efficiency, T.4.4. From (12) and part (a) of T.4.4, D.5.2(a) holds. amounts can be used in a reallocation of the en tire economy so that
From the definition of il'(u), (14) implies D.5.2(b). From (14) and no household is worse off and household h" is strictly better off.
(12) together, part (d) of the theorem implies D.5.2(c) and (d) and Note that the only property of household h' that is relevant to the
al so definition is a list of those commodities with which he is endowed in
sorne positive amount; the only relevant property of household h" is
its utility function. Note too that the manner by which the addi-
tional endowments improve the lots of household h" may be very
which, from (6), can be written indirect. Of course, they may en ter directly into the utility function
of h"; they may be factors of production used to produce com-
2: sJt(p*,w*) = O.
h
(15) modities that in crease the utility of h"; they may be neither of these,
but rather, they may enable the production of commodities that
We seek to show that D.5.2(e) holds; that is, S(p*,w*)=O, all h. increase the welfare of some other household, permitting the last to
From (15), it suffices to show that s(p* ,w*) 2 O, all h. Suppose, give up some other goods so that its utility leve! does not on balance
then, s"(p*,to*) < O, some h. From (7) and (13), v~ = O; by fall below the initial level, while h" is made better off by the goods
Lemma 5.3 and (11), u~ = O. By construction, X E X"(O); since given up.
x~ minimizes p*x11 subject to X E X11(u;) = X 11 (0),
DEFINITION 4. Household h' is said to be resource related to house-
p*x~ :::; p*x11 :::; p*x11 :::; M~.
hold h" if, for every feasible allocation, (.v,y), there exists an alloca-
The last two inequalities follow from the facts that x" :::; x11 and tion (a::',z/) anda vector x' such that (a::',y') would be feasible if the
p*y* 2 p*O = O, bY. profit maximization. Hence, the assumption endowment were x', that is,
S(p*,w*) < O implies that s(p*,to*) 2 O, a contradiction.
THEOREM 4. Under the assumptions made, a compensated equi-
librium exists. everybody is at least as well off under (x',y') as under (a::,y) and
household h" is better off,
4. The Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium (b) U(x~) 2 U11 (x11), all h,
To complete the program of proving existence of competitive (e) U11 .,(x~") > U.,(x 11 .,);
equilibrium, we have to use T.5.4 by giving a condition under which and x' is an increase in endowment only for those commodities in
a compensated equilibrium is a competitive equilibrium. We the endowment of household h' in positive amounts,
already have such a condition in T.5.2, but by itself it is not very
useful. Therefore, we need a sufficient condition that Mt > O for (d) x' 2 x,
all h at a compensatcd cquilibr\um. (e) x; > x1 only if x11 1 > O.
In terms of the example preceding Lemma 4.2, what is wanted is
a condition to ensure that the price that the household receives for We use this definition to show that if, at a compensated equi-
its sole asset does not approach zero. Intuitively, the condition librium, sorne household has a positive income, then any household
required is that the asset in question be of value, directly or that is resource related to it has a positive income; in effect the first
indirectly, to others, so that as the price declines there will eventually household has an effective demand for the endowment .of the second
arise a demand that will equal supply at a positive price. and, therefore, makes its income positive.
-ll
li:

116 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 117

Recall the definitions of P(u) (D.4.14) and il'(u) (D.4.10), and then We will say that household h' is resource related to household h"
use (12) and (14) in conjunction with the basic theorem on Pareto if some increase in those assets held by household h' in so me positive
efficiency, T.4.4. From (12) and part (a) of T.4.4, D.5.2(a) holds. amounts can be used in a reallocation of the en tire economy so that
From the definition of il'(u), (14) implies D.5.2(b). From (14) and no household is worse off and household h" is strictly better off.
(12) together, part (d) of the theorem implies D.5.2(c) and (d) and Note that the only property of household h' that is relevant to the
al so definition is a list of those commodities with which he is endowed in
sorne positive amount; the only relevant property of household h" is
its utility function. Note too that the manner by which the addi-
tional endowments improve the lots of household h" may be very
which, from (6), can be written indirect. Of course, they may en ter directly into the utility function
of h"; they may be factors of production used to produce com-
2: sJt(p*,w*) = O.
h
(15) modities that in crease the utility of h"; they may be neither of these,
but rather, they may enable the production of commodities that
We seek to show that D.5.2(e) holds; that is, S(p*,w*)=O, all h. increase the welfare of some other household, permitting the last to
From (15), it suffices to show that s(p* ,w*) 2 O, all h. Suppose, give up some other goods so that its utility leve! does not on balance
then, s"(p*,to*) < O, some h. From (7) and (13), v~ = O; by fall below the initial level, while h" is made better off by the goods
Lemma 5.3 and (11), u~ = O. By construction, X E X"(O); since given up.
x~ minimizes p*x11 subject to X E X11(u;) = X 11 (0),
DEFINITION 4. Household h' is said to be resource related to house-
p*x~ :::; p*x11 :::; p*x11 :::; M~.
hold h" if, for every feasible allocation, (.v,y), there exists an alloca-
The last two inequalities follow from the facts that x" :::; x11 and tion (a::',z/) anda vector x' such that (a::',y') would be feasible if the
p*y* 2 p*O = O, bY. profit maximization. Hence, the assumption endowment were x', that is,
S(p*,w*) < O implies that s(p*,to*) 2 O, a contradiction.
THEOREM 4. Under the assumptions made, a compensated equi-
librium exists. everybody is at least as well off under (x',y') as under (a::,y) and
household h" is better off,
4. The Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium (b) U(x~) 2 U11 (x11), all h,
To complete the program of proving existence of competitive (e) U11 .,(x~") > U.,(x 11 .,);
equilibrium, we have to use T.5.4 by giving a condition under which and x' is an increase in endowment only for those commodities in
a compensated equilibrium is a competitive equilibrium. We the endowment of household h' in positive amounts,
already have such a condition in T.5.2, but by itself it is not very
useful. Therefore, we need a sufficient condition that Mt > O for (d) x' 2 x,
all h at a compensatcd cquilibr\um. (e) x; > x1 only if x11 1 > O.
In terms of the example preceding Lemma 4.2, what is wanted is
a condition to ensure that the price that the household receives for We use this definition to show that if, at a compensated equi-
its sole asset does not approach zero. Intuitively, the condition librium, sorne household has a positive income, then any household
required is that the asset in question be of value, directly or that is resource related to it has a positive income; in effect the first
indirectly, to others, so that as the price declines there will eventually household has an effective demand for the endowment .of the second
arise a demand that will equal supply at a positive price. and, therefore, makes its income positive.
118 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 119

LEMMA 4. Let M~ be the income of household h at sorne com- An example will show that the relation "indirectly resource
pensated equilibrium. If h' is resource related to h" and M~, > O, related" is, in fact, weaker (holds more often) than the relation
then M~, > O. "resource related." Consider a pure exchange economy with three
Proof. Let the compensated equilibrium be (p*,u*,x*,y*). By households, 1, 2, and 3. Household h holds an initial stock of
D.5.4, we can find a vector :X' and an allocation (x',y') satisfying commodity h only; but the utility function of household 1 values
(a)-(e) with (x,y) replaced by (x*,y*). Since x~ minimizes p*xh only commodity 3, that of household 2 only commodity 1, and that
ut
subject to U,.(x,.) ; : :; it follows from (b) that of household 3 only commodity 2. Then it is easy to verify that
household 1 is resource related to household 2 and household 2 to
p*x~ ;;:::; p*x/:' all h. household 3, so that household 1 is indirectly resource related to
Since M~, > O, it follows, as in the proof of T.5.2, that x~~~ maxi- household 3; but household 1 is not resource related to household 3,
mizes U,,(x,,) subject to p*x,, ::::; p*x~~~. From (e), then, it is since, given an allocation in which households 1, 2, and 3 receive all
impossible that x~~~ satisfies this budget constraint: of commodities 3, 1, and 2, respective! y, an in crease in the initial
p*x~" > p*x~~~. endowment of commodity 1 cannot be used to increase the utility
of household 3.
Thus,
p* L X~ > p* L X~. Corollary J. Let M/:' be the income of household h at sorne
compensated equilibrium. If h' is indirectly resource related to h"
h "
By profit maximization, p*yj ; : :; p*y~, all f, so that, and M~, > O, then M:', > O.

p* y~ ::::; p* yj. Proof. By definition, hn_ 1 is resource related to hn = h". Since


f f M~, > O, M~" _1 > O, by Lemma 5.4. Then, repeating this argu-
From D.5.2(e), summed over all h, ment, we must have M~n- 2 > O, and so forth, so that finally
p* x~ = p*yj' + p*x,
11 f
M~0 =M~,> O.

It is now simple to state and prove a theorem that ensures that at


so that
a compensated equilibrium M~ > O, all h, and therefore, it is a
p* x~ - p* y~ > p*x. competitive equilibrium by T.5.2.
1,
" f
On the other hand, since p* > O, it follows from D.5.4(a) that THEOREM 5. If every household is indirectly resource related to l,i
every other and if all the other assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4 hold, i'
p* x~ - p* y~ ::::; p*x', then a competitive equilibrium exists.
" f
so that p*(x' - :X) > O. This is equivalent to saying that, for sorne Proof. Since all assumptions hold, there exists a compensated
i, both pj > O and x; - x1 > O. From D.5.4(e), this implies that, equilibrium, by T.5.4. By Lemma 5.2, M~, > O, sorne h". By
for sorne i, p'{ > O and x,.. 1 > O, which implies that p*x,., > O, and hypothesis, every household is indirectly resource related to house-
therefore, M~, > O. hold h", so that by Corollary 1, M~ > O, all h.
The condition that one household must be resource related to
another is weak, in view of all the possible reallocations that are 5. Equilibrium with Debt and Bankruptcy
permitted. A still weaker relation is the following: If the proofs of T.5.4 and the lemmas and theorems leading to it
DEFINITION 5. Household h' is indirectly resource related to house- are examined in detail, it will be seen that assumption A.4.2 (that
hold h" if there is a sequence of households, h;, (i = O, ... , n), with the initial endowment more or less dominates an element, xh, of
h0 = h', hn = h", and h1 resource related to hl+ 1 (i = O, ... , n - 1). the consumption possibility set) was used at only two points: in the
118 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 119

LEMMA 4. Let M~ be the income of household h at sorne com- An example will show that the relation "indirectly resource
pensated equilibrium. If h' is resource related to h" and M~, > O, related" is, in fact, weaker (holds more often) than the relation
then M~, > O. "resource related." Consider a pure exchange economy with three
Proof. Let the compensated equilibrium be (p*,u*,x*,y*). By households, 1, 2, and 3. Household h holds an initial stock of
D.5.4, we can find a vector :X' and an allocation (x',y') satisfying commodity h only; but the utility function of household 1 values
(a)-(e) with (x,y) replaced by (x*,y*). Since x~ minimizes p*xh only commodity 3, that of household 2 only commodity 1, and that
ut
subject to U,.(x,.) ; : :; it follows from (b) that of household 3 only commodity 2. Then it is easy to verify that
household 1 is resource related to household 2 and household 2 to
p*x~ ;;:::; p*x/:' all h. household 3, so that household 1 is indirectly resource related to
Since M~, > O, it follows, as in the proof of T.5.2, that x~~~ maxi- household 3; but household 1 is not resource related to household 3,
mizes U,,(x,,) subject to p*x,, ::::; p*x~~~. From (e), then, it is since, given an allocation in which households 1, 2, and 3 receive all
impossible that x~~~ satisfies this budget constraint: of commodities 3, 1, and 2, respective! y, an in crease in the initial
p*x~" > p*x~~~. endowment of commodity 1 cannot be used to increase the utility
of household 3.
Thus,
p* L X~ > p* L X~. Corollary J. Let M/:' be the income of household h at sorne
compensated equilibrium. If h' is indirectly resource related to h"
h "
By profit maximization, p*yj ; : :; p*y~, all f, so that, and M~, > O, then M:', > O.

p* y~ ::::; p* yj. Proof. By definition, hn_ 1 is resource related to hn = h". Since


f f M~, > O, M~" _1 > O, by Lemma 5.4. Then, repeating this argu-
From D.5.2(e), summed over all h, ment, we must have M~n- 2 > O, and so forth, so that finally
p* x~ = p*yj' + p*x,
11 f
M~0 =M~,> O.

It is now simple to state and prove a theorem that ensures that at


so that
a compensated equilibrium M~ > O, all h, and therefore, it is a
p* x~ - p* y~ > p*x. competitive equilibrium by T.5.2.
1,
" f
On the other hand, since p* > O, it follows from D.5.4(a) that THEOREM 5. If every household is indirectly resource related to l,i
every other and if all the other assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4 hold, i'
p* x~ - p* y~ ::::; p*x', then a competitive equilibrium exists.
" f
so that p*(x' - :X) > O. This is equivalent to saying that, for sorne Proof. Since all assumptions hold, there exists a compensated
i, both pj > O and x; - x1 > O. From D.5.4(e), this implies that, equilibrium, by T.5.4. By Lemma 5.2, M~, > O, sorne h". By
for sorne i, p'{ > O and x,.. 1 > O, which implies that p*x,., > O, and hypothesis, every household is indirectly resource related to house-
therefore, M~, > O. hold h", so that by Corollary 1, M~ > O, all h.
The condition that one household must be resource related to
another is weak, in view of all the possible reallocations that are 5. Equilibrium with Debt and Bankruptcy
permitted. A still weaker relation is the following: If the proofs of T.5.4 and the lemmas and theorems leading to it
DEFINITION 5. Household h' is indirectly resource related to house- are examined in detail, it will be seen that assumption A.4.2 (that
hold h" if there is a sequence of households, h;, (i = O, ... , n), with the initial endowment more or less dominates an element, xh, of
h0 = h', hn = h", and h1 resource related to hl+ 1 (i = O, ... , n - 1). the consumption possibility set) was used at only two points: in the
i;
120 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 121 !:

proof of Lemma 4.9, that O is a dominated utility vector, and at the Then in an economy with bonds we can define a compensated
very end, to show the impossibility of a budgetary deficit at equi- equilibrium concept in which bankruptcy is allowed.
librium; the mapping used ensures that a budgetary deficit (s 11 < O)
DEFINITION 6. In an economy with initial holdings of bonds, a
implies zero utility, which can be achieved, however, without any
price vector p*, a non-negative utility allocation u*, a consumption
deficit since the zero utility leve! can always be achieved without any
allocation x*, a production allocationy*, anda redistribution vector
trade at all. In ordinary language, assumption A.4.2 serves to avoid
s* constitute a compensated equilibrium with bankruptcy if D.5.2(a)-
the possibility of bankruptcy.
(d) hold, and in addition,
Therefore, if we replace A.4.2 by the assumption that O is domi-
nated, it turns out that an existence theorem for equilibrium with (e) p*x; = M; - s; = p*x11 + d111 (p*y1) + b,(p*)- s~,
bankruptcy has been proved. We still have that (15) holds, so that f

s;
1
budgetary surpluses total to zero, but it is no longer true that (f) =O, 1
h !
s 11 (p*,to*) = O for all h. Instead, for sorne households, s 11 < O at i
equilibrium; they are the bankrupts. The mapping, however, does (g) u; = O for any household for which s; < O. q,
!;1
insist that the utility of a bankrupt be zero. If we drop A.4.2, we
can redefine the zero utility leve! arbitrarily. We can now interpret It is ll?W obvious that the following theorem holds.
it as the mnimum leve! that society insists on providing for every THEOREM 7. If the assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4, other than
household, even for those that cannot achieve this leve! in the A.4.2, hold, if a zero utility leve! is prescribed for each household in
marketplace. Of course, the budgetary deficits of the bankrupts such a way that there exists a feasible allocation (x,y) for which
must be balanced by budgetary surpluses of others; these may be U11 (x11) > O, all h, and if b11 (p) is continuous for each h,
interpreted as the taxes needed to be paid to maintain the mnimum
guaranteed utility leve!. L bn(P) =O for all p,
With this new concept of equilibrium, it is also possible. to intro- h

duce initial debts into the system. In addition to their commodity then there exists a compensated equilibrium with bankruptcy.
endowments and their ownership of shares in firms, households may
be supposed to start with debts owed to others or with credits owed Remark J. The conditions under which this compensated equi-
by others. Let the instruments of debt be termed bonds, and let b 11 librium is a competitive equilibrium and, indeed, the exact defini-
be the initial bond holdings of household h. A negative value tion of a competitive equilibriurn with bankruptcy rernain open
represents a net debtor position. In a closed economy questions.

2hh =o.
h
Remark 2. In Section 4.4, it was noted that a Pareto-efficient
allocation possibly cou1d be realized as a cornpetitive equilibriurn
A bond is an obligation to pay that rnay be stated in terrns of units after sorne reallocation of the initial endowrnent. It is clear that a
of account or in terrns of sorne one cornrnodity or in terrns of a reallocation in real terrns is not necessary; a reallocation by creating
bundle of cornmodities. To cover all these cases, we suppose sirnply debts and credits would always do. If to* is a Pareto-efficient
that b11 is rneasured in units of account and is a continuous function allocation that is sustained by a price vector p*, then if we define
of prices. (Thus, if N is the bond holding stated as an obligation
to pay in units of comrnodity 1, b, = p 1 bk.)
With debts, the income of the household is
b11 = p*x11 -[p*x~~ + f dhf(p*yj) J.
M11 = PX11 + 2 dM(PYr) + b11(p). and if we define u;
= U,(x;), then it is obvious that (p*,u*,to*,O)
f constitutes a cornpensated equilibriurn in the sense of D.5.6, indeed
i;
120 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 121 !:

proof of Lemma 4.9, that O is a dominated utility vector, and at the Then in an economy with bonds we can define a compensated
very end, to show the impossibility of a budgetary deficit at equi- equilibrium concept in which bankruptcy is allowed.
librium; the mapping used ensures that a budgetary deficit (s 11 < O)
DEFINITION 6. In an economy with initial holdings of bonds, a
implies zero utility, which can be achieved, however, without any
price vector p*, a non-negative utility allocation u*, a consumption
deficit since the zero utility leve! can always be achieved without any
allocation x*, a production allocationy*, anda redistribution vector
trade at all. In ordinary language, assumption A.4.2 serves to avoid
s* constitute a compensated equilibrium with bankruptcy if D.5.2(a)-
the possibility of bankruptcy.
(d) hold, and in addition,
Therefore, if we replace A.4.2 by the assumption that O is domi-
nated, it turns out that an existence theorem for equilibrium with (e) p*x; = M; - s; = p*x11 + d111 (p*y1) + b,(p*)- s~,
bankruptcy has been proved. We still have that (15) holds, so that f

s;
1
budgetary surpluses total to zero, but it is no longer true that (f) =O, 1
h !
s 11 (p*,to*) = O for all h. Instead, for sorne households, s 11 < O at i
equilibrium; they are the bankrupts. The mapping, however, does (g) u; = O for any household for which s; < O. q,
!;1
insist that the utility of a bankrupt be zero. If we drop A.4.2, we
can redefine the zero utility leve! arbitrarily. We can now interpret It is ll?W obvious that the following theorem holds.
it as the mnimum leve! that society insists on providing for every THEOREM 7. If the assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4, other than
household, even for those that cannot achieve this leve! in the A.4.2, hold, if a zero utility leve! is prescribed for each household in
marketplace. Of course, the budgetary deficits of the bankrupts such a way that there exists a feasible allocation (x,y) for which
must be balanced by budgetary surpluses of others; these may be U11 (x11) > O, all h, and if b11 (p) is continuous for each h,
interpreted as the taxes needed to be paid to maintain the mnimum
guaranteed utility leve!. L bn(P) =O for all p,
With this new concept of equilibrium, it is also possible. to intro- h

duce initial debts into the system. In addition to their commodity then there exists a compensated equilibrium with bankruptcy.
endowments and their ownership of shares in firms, households may
be supposed to start with debts owed to others or with credits owed Remark J. The conditions under which this compensated equi-
by others. Let the instruments of debt be termed bonds, and let b 11 librium is a competitive equilibrium and, indeed, the exact defini-
be the initial bond holdings of household h. A negative value tion of a competitive equilibriurn with bankruptcy rernain open
represents a net debtor position. In a closed economy questions.

2hh =o.
h
Remark 2. In Section 4.4, it was noted that a Pareto-efficient
allocation possibly cou1d be realized as a cornpetitive equilibriurn
A bond is an obligation to pay that rnay be stated in terrns of units after sorne reallocation of the initial endowrnent. It is clear that a
of account or in terrns of sorne one cornrnodity or in terrns of a reallocation in real terrns is not necessary; a reallocation by creating
bundle of cornmodities. To cover all these cases, we suppose sirnply debts and credits would always do. If to* is a Pareto-efficient
that b11 is rneasured in units of account and is a continuous function allocation that is sustained by a price vector p*, then if we define
of prices. (Thus, if N is the bond holding stated as an obligation
to pay in units of comrnodity 1, b, = p 1 bk.)
With debts, the income of the household is
b11 = p*x11 -[p*x~~ + f dhf(p*yj) J.
M11 = PX11 + 2 dM(PYr) + b11(p). and if we define u;
= U,(x;), then it is obvious that (p*,u*,to*,O)
f constitutes a cornpensated equilibriurn in the sense of D.5.6, indeed
122 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

hold h can be described by the numbers .X8 , the amount of com-


123

one in which no bankruptcy occurs in fact. For further discussion 1

of the implications of bankruptcy for the existence of equilibrium, modity i held by household h if state s occurs. Similarly, a possible
see Section 14.3. production vector for a firm,J, may depe.nd on the state of the world
(e.g., the dependence of farm output on weather). Thus YJ's is a
possible production vector for firm f if state s occurs. We can
6. Equilibrium under Uncertainty describe endowments and production possibilities then by vectors
We note briefly that the general equilibrium model of Chapters whose components vary according to both commodity and state of
3-5 has more than one interpretation. It is well known, of course, the world. The vector X~, has the components X~, 8 , where both i and
that the commodities can be regarded as differentiated in time or in s vary. A possible production vector y1 then has also components
space or in both even when they are physically identical. Then the Yns The extent that sorne components are independent of the state
equilibrium found is one in time or space. In the case of a spatial of the world will be reflected in the fact that for sorne i, Yns will be
economy there would be different markets and different prices in the same for all s, as will typically be true if sorne inputs have to be
different localities; more specific theorems might be obtained by committed before knowing the state of the world.
noting that there are special kinds of activities, such as transporta- If endowments and production possibilities depend on the state of
tion, that transform commodities in one place to commodities in the world, then the feasibility of an allocation depends, of course, on
another; if these activities have special properties, such as constant the state of the world, and therefore commitments to consumption
returns, special theorems can be stated concerning the relations must vary similarly. Hence, a consumption vector, X~,, must have
between prices in different locations. dimensions conforming to those of X~, and y1 , that is, its components
Similarly, if the equilibrium model is regarded as extended in time, must be written, X~, 8 For a given state of the world, feasibility is
there will be different markets for commodities at different times. defined as befo re; hence, it follows easily that with the new inter-
A market for a commodity to be delivered at sorne future time is a pretation of the production and consumption vectors, feasibility is
futures market. In the pure model, all markets, current and also defined as before. Now it means feasibility for all states of
futures, are operating in the present; once the transactions have been nature, in the sense that the commitments have enough flexibility to
carried out, there will be no need, in principie, for any more markets, be always satisfiable.
since all future transactions will have already been contracted for. It should be noted that a preference ordering for consumption
Note that allowance is made in this intertemporal model for the fact vectors in the new interpretation contains elements of judgment
that production takes time; in a possible production vector, the about the likelihoods of the different states of the world as well as
positive components may all refer to future commodities, while the elements of evaluation of tastes. A consumption vector in the
inputs are current. Again special assumptions about the nature of present sense can be regarded as a sequence of consumption vectors
production, such as its recursive character, and in particular, about in the narrower sense, one for each state of the world; let X~, 8 be the
the transfer of commodities from the present to the future, as through vector with components X~,;"' where i varies over commodities. For
storage, lead to the special theorems that constitute capital theory. simplicity of discussion assume that there are only two possible
i 1
states of the world, s = 1,2. Thus, in comparing X~, = (X~,,x, 2 )
Rather than enlarge on these well-known themes, we will briefly
111

:
1
discuss another interpretation. Suppose that, in fact, there is with x~ = (x~ 1 ,x~ 2 ), a small preference for xhl over x~ 1 may out-
11 1

uncertainty about endowments and production. This can be weigh a very large preference for x~ 2 over x, 2 if state 2 is believed to
established by saying that endowments and production possibilities be very unlikely to occur. The decomposition of a utility function
depend on the state of the world; that is, a state of the world is a for consumption vectors into elements of belief and of pure taste (as
description so complete that, if known to be true, it would com- under certainty) has been the subject of much research; the expected-
pletely define all endowments and production possibilities. If there utility hypothesis of Bernoulli [1938, 1954] has been the most
are finitely many states of the world, then the endowment of house- favored. According to this hypothesis, the preference ordering over
122 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

hold h can be described by the numbers .X8 , the amount of com-


123

one in which no bankruptcy occurs in fact. For further discussion 1

of the implications of bankruptcy for the existence of equilibrium, modity i held by household h if state s occurs. Similarly, a possible
see Section 14.3. production vector for a firm,J, may depe.nd on the state of the world
(e.g., the dependence of farm output on weather). Thus YJ's is a
possible production vector for firm f if state s occurs. We can
6. Equilibrium under Uncertainty describe endowments and production possibilities then by vectors
We note briefly that the general equilibrium model of Chapters whose components vary according to both commodity and state of
3-5 has more than one interpretation. It is well known, of course, the world. The vector X~, has the components X~, 8 , where both i and
that the commodities can be regarded as differentiated in time or in s vary. A possible production vector y1 then has also components
space or in both even when they are physically identical. Then the Yns The extent that sorne components are independent of the state
equilibrium found is one in time or space. In the case of a spatial of the world will be reflected in the fact that for sorne i, Yns will be
economy there would be different markets and different prices in the same for all s, as will typically be true if sorne inputs have to be
different localities; more specific theorems might be obtained by committed before knowing the state of the world.
noting that there are special kinds of activities, such as transporta- If endowments and production possibilities depend on the state of
tion, that transform commodities in one place to commodities in the world, then the feasibility of an allocation depends, of course, on
another; if these activities have special properties, such as constant the state of the world, and therefore commitments to consumption
returns, special theorems can be stated concerning the relations must vary similarly. Hence, a consumption vector, X~,, must have
between prices in different locations. dimensions conforming to those of X~, and y1 , that is, its components
Similarly, if the equilibrium model is regarded as extended in time, must be written, X~, 8 For a given state of the world, feasibility is
there will be different markets for commodities at different times. defined as befo re; hence, it follows easily that with the new inter-
A market for a commodity to be delivered at sorne future time is a pretation of the production and consumption vectors, feasibility is
futures market. In the pure model, all markets, current and also defined as before. Now it means feasibility for all states of
futures, are operating in the present; once the transactions have been nature, in the sense that the commitments have enough flexibility to
carried out, there will be no need, in principie, for any more markets, be always satisfiable.
since all future transactions will have already been contracted for. It should be noted that a preference ordering for consumption
Note that allowance is made in this intertemporal model for the fact vectors in the new interpretation contains elements of judgment
that production takes time; in a possible production vector, the about the likelihoods of the different states of the world as well as
positive components may all refer to future commodities, while the elements of evaluation of tastes. A consumption vector in the
inputs are current. Again special assumptions about the nature of present sense can be regarded as a sequence of consumption vectors
production, such as its recursive character, and in particular, about in the narrower sense, one for each state of the world; let X~, 8 be the
the transfer of commodities from the present to the future, as through vector with components X~,;"' where i varies over commodities. For
storage, lead to the special theorems that constitute capital theory. simplicity of discussion assume that there are only two possible
i 1
states of the world, s = 1,2. Thus, in comparing X~, = (X~,,x, 2 )
Rather than enlarge on these well-known themes, we will briefly
111

:
1
discuss another interpretation. Suppose that, in fact, there is with x~ = (x~ 1 ,x~ 2 ), a small preference for xhl over x~ 1 may out-
11 1

uncertainty about endowments and production. This can be weigh a very large preference for x~ 2 over x, 2 if state 2 is believed to
established by saying that endowments and production possibilities be very unlikely to occur. The decomposition of a utility function
depend on the state of the world; that is, a state of the world is a for consumption vectors into elements of belief and of pure taste (as
description so complete that, if known to be true, it would com- under certainty) has been the subject of much research; the expected-
pletely define all endowments and production possibilities. If there utility hypothesis of Bernoulli [1938, 1954] has been the most
are finitely many states of the world, then the endowment of house- favored. According to this hypothesis, the preference ordering over
1
!

l24 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 125
1!,l consumption vectors Xn = (xhl> ... , x"., ... ) can be represented by even without convexity of preferences at least an approximate
!'
a utility function with the special form equilibrium exists.
The equilibrium will then yield a set of prices p~, the price paid in
L rr8Un(Xh8),
8
return for a promise to supply one unit of commodity i if state s
occurs and nothing otherwise. The firm then will be maximizing
where rr,. 8 ;:: O, all s, rrn 8 > O, sorne s. Without loss of generality,
we may assume LP~Yt8;
f 8

this is linear in input-output decisions, so that, in equilibrium, the


firm acts as if it were risk-neutral. All the risk-bearing activities of
Then rr" 8 may be thought of as the probability of s as believed by the economy are carried on by households in accordance with their
household h (sometimes called subjective or personal probability), tastes for risk bearing and their assessments of the likelihoods of
uh a function reflecting tastes, including tastes for taking or rejecting different states of the world. In effect, the households, in addition
risks as well as for choices among commodities. The function U,. to their economic functions of satisfying their consumption needs and
associated with a given preference ordering is unique up to a linear supplying inputs, will also be. writing and selling insurance policies.
transformation. The Bernoulli hypothesis has been shown by The approach sketched so far implies that there is a final settle-
various writers to be implied in turn by seemingly weaker and more ment after one period when all uncertainty is resolved. This can be
plausible sets of hypotheses; see Ramsey [1926], de Finetti [1937], generalized. Suppose, to illustrate, that sorne information will be
von Neuinann and Morgenstern [1947, Appendix], and Savage available at time 1, and all uncertainties will be resolved at time 2.
[1954]. Thus, there may be uncertainties about the weather in both periods;
With the new interpretation, the entire formalism of this and the the state of the world involves a description of the weather in both
preceding two chapters remains valid. Each commodity now must periods. At time 1, however, only the weather at that time is known.
be interpreted as a contingent claim with the double index i.s, a Then the state of the world might be described by a pair of integers
promise to supply one unit of commodity i if state s occurs and (sl>s 2 ), where s 1 is known at time 1 and s 2 at time 2. Commodities
nothing otherwise. The assumptions have to be reinterpreted, a now ber two subscripts denoting uncertainty, thus, Xht 8182 How-
task that will not be undertaken in detail here. For the most part, ever, commitments for transactions at time 1 must in fact be inde- !'

the arguments for the plausibility of these assumptions remain pendent of s2, though not of S. Contracts for time 2 will depend, 1:
'1
. unchanged, but the assumption of convexity of preferences has a new in general, on both s 1 and s 2 .
implication in the case of uncertainty. With this more general interpretation, it is again possible to
Consider a simple examp1e. Suppose that there are just two reinterpret the model of this and the last two chapters to show the
states of the world and the preference ordering is symmetric with existence of equilibrium. There is a very important qualification to
respect to them, that is, that x" ~" x~ if x1n = x~ 2 and x112 = x~ 1 . the possibility of' this interpretation of equilibrium under uncertainty
This cou1d arise because the household judged the two states to be that must be specified. For simplicity, we return to the one-period
equally possible (in the Bernoulli case, if rrh 1 = rrh 2 ) and if tastes in model. The participants in a market for a commodity conditional
the two statcs wcrc the same. Then convexity implies that x~ = upon a state of the world all must know which state has occurred.
!xh + !x~ ~h x,.. But X~ = x;:2 = !x111 + !x112 ; that is, the cer- Obviously, an individual whose endowment is different in all states
tainty of the average bundle is preferred to a bundle varying by ofthe world will know which has occurred. On the other hand, even
chance. Thus, convexity of preferences under uncertainty implies an individual whose endowment is independent of the state of the
risk aversion. This may well be a plausible assumption for the usual world may still want to make conditional contracts because the terms
run of business decisions, but it should be understood that an on which he can buy goods depend on endowments and production
additional hypothesis is implied. It will be shown in Chapter 7 that possibilities of others, which, in turn, do depend on the state of the
1
!

l24 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 125
1!,l consumption vectors Xn = (xhl> ... , x"., ... ) can be represented by even without convexity of preferences at least an approximate
!'
a utility function with the special form equilibrium exists.
The equilibrium will then yield a set of prices p~, the price paid in
L rr8Un(Xh8),
8
return for a promise to supply one unit of commodity i if state s
occurs and nothing otherwise. The firm then will be maximizing
where rr,. 8 ;:: O, all s, rrn 8 > O, sorne s. Without loss of generality,
we may assume LP~Yt8;
f 8

this is linear in input-output decisions, so that, in equilibrium, the


firm acts as if it were risk-neutral. All the risk-bearing activities of
Then rr" 8 may be thought of as the probability of s as believed by the economy are carried on by households in accordance with their
household h (sometimes called subjective or personal probability), tastes for risk bearing and their assessments of the likelihoods of
uh a function reflecting tastes, including tastes for taking or rejecting different states of the world. In effect, the households, in addition
risks as well as for choices among commodities. The function U,. to their economic functions of satisfying their consumption needs and
associated with a given preference ordering is unique up to a linear supplying inputs, will also be. writing and selling insurance policies.
transformation. The Bernoulli hypothesis has been shown by The approach sketched so far implies that there is a final settle-
various writers to be implied in turn by seemingly weaker and more ment after one period when all uncertainty is resolved. This can be
plausible sets of hypotheses; see Ramsey [1926], de Finetti [1937], generalized. Suppose, to illustrate, that sorne information will be
von Neuinann and Morgenstern [1947, Appendix], and Savage available at time 1, and all uncertainties will be resolved at time 2.
[1954]. Thus, there may be uncertainties about the weather in both periods;
With the new interpretation, the entire formalism of this and the the state of the world involves a description of the weather in both
preceding two chapters remains valid. Each commodity now must periods. At time 1, however, only the weather at that time is known.
be interpreted as a contingent claim with the double index i.s, a Then the state of the world might be described by a pair of integers
promise to supply one unit of commodity i if state s occurs and (sl>s 2 ), where s 1 is known at time 1 and s 2 at time 2. Commodities
nothing otherwise. The assumptions have to be reinterpreted, a now ber two subscripts denoting uncertainty, thus, Xht 8182 How-
task that will not be undertaken in detail here. For the most part, ever, commitments for transactions at time 1 must in fact be inde- !'

the arguments for the plausibility of these assumptions remain pendent of s2, though not of S. Contracts for time 2 will depend, 1:
'1
. unchanged, but the assumption of convexity of preferences has a new in general, on both s 1 and s 2 .
implication in the case of uncertainty. With this more general interpretation, it is again possible to
Consider a simple examp1e. Suppose that there are just two reinterpret the model of this and the last two chapters to show the
states of the world and the preference ordering is symmetric with existence of equilibrium. There is a very important qualification to
respect to them, that is, that x" ~" x~ if x1n = x~ 2 and x112 = x~ 1 . the possibility of' this interpretation of equilibrium under uncertainty
This cou1d arise because the household judged the two states to be that must be specified. For simplicity, we return to the one-period
equally possible (in the Bernoulli case, if rrh 1 = rrh 2 ) and if tastes in model. The participants in a market for a commodity conditional
the two statcs wcrc the same. Then convexity implies that x~ = upon a state of the world all must know which state has occurred.
!xh + !x~ ~h x,.. But X~ = x;:2 = !x111 + !x112 ; that is, the cer- Obviously, an individual whose endowment is different in all states
tainty of the average bundle is preferred to a bundle varying by ofthe world will know which has occurred. On the other hand, even
chance. Thus, convexity of preferences under uncertainty implies an individual whose endowment is independent of the state of the
risk aversion. This may well be a plausible assumption for the usual world may still want to make conditional contracts because the terms
run of business decisions, but it should be understood that an on which he can buy goods depend on endowments and production
additional hypothesis is implied. It will be shown in Chapter 7 that possibilities of others, which, in turn, do depend on the state of the
'1,

126 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

world. If, in fact, he is unable to enter into such contracts because


f
1

'
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

Notes
127

he will never know the true state, the model of equilibrium under
uncertainty just sketched is untenable. An individual who knows The first theorem on existence of equilibrium in a fully developed
.,1 that information will beco me available to part of the market, but not mo del of production and consumer choice, in which supply and demand
may be multi-valued correspondences, is due to Arrow and Debreu
to him, will be unable to enter into conditional contracts. But since [1954]; they were influenced by the earlier work of Wald, as well as by
he knows that future prices, in fact, will depend on this information, Nash's fundamental result on the somewhat related problem of existence ::
,,,
he treats them from his viewpoint as random variables. Thus, he of equilibrium points in n-person games (see Section 1.5 and Notes to 111

may be led to take certain prudent actions, such as investing in highly Chapter 2). An independent proof was that of Nikaid [1956]. A
safe securities, possibly money, which will be available to meet the systematic presentation with much improvement is the subject of
Debreu [1959]. The most general existence theorems, more general
future uncertainties. The single market for all uncertainties, than those proved here, can be found in Debreu [1962].
present and future, must be dissolved into a sequence pf markets While proving the existence of equilibrium with single-valued excess-
that come into equilibrium at successive time points as information demand functions in Chapter 2, it was sufficient to use a mapping from
becomes available to sorne members of the economy. Then the price simplex into itself. The basic reason why the domain of the
decisions are made in earlier markets on the basis of current esti- mapping is more complex here is beca use of the multi-valuedness of the
mates of the likelihoods of alternative possible outcomes on future excess demands; in the case of Chapter 2, specifying quantities as well
would have been superfluous since prices uniquely determine quantities.
markets. McKenzie [1959] in fact has shown that a price-to-price mapping can
A particular case of failures of markets to exist beca use of inequali- be used even in the general case; however, since he assumes constant
ties in information structure is the so-called moral hazard, to use a returns to scale, there are no profits to distribute, and hence, the problem
tenn found in insurance literature. An insurance company may be of determining the profits of individual firms does not arise. In any
unwilling to sell an unduly large amount of fire insurance to a, case, bis ingenious proof involves sorne artificialities that are avoided
he re.
household because it creates an incentive to carelessness. The The mapping used in Section 5.3 is novel. Negishi [1960] used a
matter may' be put this way in the formal language we have been mapping that, like this, involved welfare-economic considerations, but
using: There are three possible states of the world-no fire hazard, in a considerably different way.
mild fire hazard, which leads to fire only when the household is The problem created by discontinuity of uncompensated demand
careless, and severe fire hazard, which leads to fire regardless of functions when sorne prices are zero was recognized by Arrow and
Debreu [1954, Sections 4 and 5]; they stated a condition that ensured
precautions. According to the analysis of this section, there is an that the endowments of any household are desired, directly or indirectly,
equilibrium in which the two kinds of fire hazard are distinguished by others, so that incomes cannot fall to zero. A general and very
and different insurance policies, with different premiums, written for elegant formulation of such a condition is dueto McKenzie [1959, 1961],
each. Thus, the household might be compensated for the occurrence based on an earlier suggestion of Gale [1957]. The definitions of
of a mild fire hazard, whether or not fire actually breaks out; resource relatedness and indirect resource relatedness used in Section
5.4 are variants of McKenzie's.
whether it does depends on the household's carelessness, for which The proofs of existence of competitive equilibrium in Arrow and
it bears full financialresponsibility. Debreu and in McKenzie are based on approximations by economies
In fact, of course, the insurance company can only observe in which continuity is not a problem because, in effect, the households
whether or not a fire has occurred; it cannot distinguish between have endowments with positive quantities of all commodities. The
mild and severe fire hazards. Therefore, it will write a single policy present discussion is closer to that of Debreu [1962]; he first pro ved the
existence of what he calls a quasi-equilibrium, a concept closely related
against fire. Then, however, the incentive for the household to be to, but not identical with, that of a compensated equilibl'ium and then
careful will be removed. An equilibrium can be shown to exist, but stated conditions under which a quasi-equilibrium is a competitive
it will certainly not have the Pareto-efficiency properties of the pure equilibrium.
model of equilibrium under uncertainty as first sketched in this The interpretation of equilibrium theory for the case of uncertainty
sketched in Section 5.6 was first introduced by Arrow [1953, 1963-64]
section. for a pure exchange economy. The extension to production and to
'1,

126 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

world. If, in fact, he is unable to enter into such contracts because


f
1

'
THE EXISTENCE OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM

Notes
127

he will never know the true state, the model of equilibrium under
uncertainty just sketched is untenable. An individual who knows The first theorem on existence of equilibrium in a fully developed
.,1 that information will beco me available to part of the market, but not mo del of production and consumer choice, in which supply and demand
may be multi-valued correspondences, is due to Arrow and Debreu
to him, will be unable to enter into conditional contracts. But since [1954]; they were influenced by the earlier work of Wald, as well as by
he knows that future prices, in fact, will depend on this information, Nash's fundamental result on the somewhat related problem of existence ::
,,,
he treats them from his viewpoint as random variables. Thus, he of equilibrium points in n-person games (see Section 1.5 and Notes to 111

may be led to take certain prudent actions, such as investing in highly Chapter 2). An independent proof was that of Nikaid [1956]. A
safe securities, possibly money, which will be available to meet the systematic presentation with much improvement is the subject of
Debreu [1959]. The most general existence theorems, more general
future uncertainties. The single market for all uncertainties, than those proved here, can be found in Debreu [1962].
present and future, must be dissolved into a sequence pf markets While proving the existence of equilibrium with single-valued excess-
that come into equilibrium at successive time points as information demand functions in Chapter 2, it was sufficient to use a mapping from
becomes available to sorne members of the economy. Then the price simplex into itself. The basic reason why the domain of the
decisions are made in earlier markets on the basis of current esti- mapping is more complex here is beca use of the multi-valuedness of the
mates of the likelihoods of alternative possible outcomes on future excess demands; in the case of Chapter 2, specifying quantities as well
would have been superfluous since prices uniquely determine quantities.
markets. McKenzie [1959] in fact has shown that a price-to-price mapping can
A particular case of failures of markets to exist beca use of inequali- be used even in the general case; however, since he assumes constant
ties in information structure is the so-called moral hazard, to use a returns to scale, there are no profits to distribute, and hence, the problem
tenn found in insurance literature. An insurance company may be of determining the profits of individual firms does not arise. In any
unwilling to sell an unduly large amount of fire insurance to a, case, bis ingenious proof involves sorne artificialities that are avoided
he re.
household because it creates an incentive to carelessness. The The mapping used in Section 5.3 is novel. Negishi [1960] used a
matter may' be put this way in the formal language we have been mapping that, like this, involved welfare-economic considerations, but
using: There are three possible states of the world-no fire hazard, in a considerably different way.
mild fire hazard, which leads to fire only when the household is The problem created by discontinuity of uncompensated demand
careless, and severe fire hazard, which leads to fire regardless of functions when sorne prices are zero was recognized by Arrow and
Debreu [1954, Sections 4 and 5]; they stated a condition that ensured
precautions. According to the analysis of this section, there is an that the endowments of any household are desired, directly or indirectly,
equilibrium in which the two kinds of fire hazard are distinguished by others, so that incomes cannot fall to zero. A general and very
and different insurance policies, with different premiums, written for elegant formulation of such a condition is dueto McKenzie [1959, 1961],
each. Thus, the household might be compensated for the occurrence based on an earlier suggestion of Gale [1957]. The definitions of
of a mild fire hazard, whether or not fire actually breaks out; resource relatedness and indirect resource relatedness used in Section
5.4 are variants of McKenzie's.
whether it does depends on the household's carelessness, for which The proofs of existence of competitive equilibrium in Arrow and
it bears full financialresponsibility. Debreu and in McKenzie are based on approximations by economies
In fact, of course, the insurance company can only observe in which continuity is not a problem because, in effect, the households
whether or not a fire has occurred; it cannot distinguish between have endowments with positive quantities of all commodities. The
mild and severe fire hazards. Therefore, it will write a single policy present discussion is closer to that of Debreu [1962]; he first pro ved the
existence of what he calls a quasi-equilibrium, a concept closely related
against fire. Then, however, the incentive for the household to be to, but not identical with, that of a compensated equilibl'ium and then
careful will be removed. An equilibrium can be shown to exist, but stated conditions under which a quasi-equilibrium is a competitive
it will certainly not have the Pareto-efficiency properties of the pure equilibrium.
model of equilibrium under uncertainty as first sketched in this The interpretation of equilibrium theory for the case of uncertainty
sketched in Section 5.6 was first introduced by Arrow [1953, 1963-64]
section. for a pure exchange economy. The extension to production and to
r
!
---------

128 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS Chapter Six


multi-period models is dueto Debreu [1959, Chapter 7]. The relation
between convexity of preferences and risk aversion was noted by Arrow GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM
[1953, Section 4; 1963-64, Section 4]. The difficulties created for this UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS
equilibrium concept by the varying information structures of the
economic agents were noted by Radner [1968]; the particular problems
of moral hazard were emphasized by Arrow [1963, 961-962 1965
55-56; 1970, 142-143]. ' ' The expense
Is what one thought and more.
-Yvor Winters,
At the San Francisco Airport

The existence of general equilibrium has been proved in the last


chapter .under the assumptions set forth in Chapters 3 and 4-the
usual assumptions of the perfectly competitive economy. In this
chapter, we will show that the methods of analysis used so far can
also demonstrate the existence of equilibrium in severa! cases in
which sorne of these conditions are relaxed.

l. Prices Affecting Utilities


It has been frequently suggested in the literature that an individual's
preferences among commodity vectors are influenced by the prices;
typically, it is argued that if the price of a commodity goes up, the
commodity will be more highly valued (in the sense that, for any
VNIVERSiJT~ ttARIS 1 given quantities, the marginal rate of substitution between that
106-1 q: ~bouley~rq d~ l'Hopitl commodity and any other increases) either because it serves as a
better public demonstration ofthe household's wealth [Veblen, 1899]
75013 P.ARIS or because price is used by the ,household as an index of quality
'fl. : o1 45 8'7 23 00 [Scitovsky, 1944--45]. The emprica! importance of the price effect
Fax : 01 4~ a.7 24 00 has never been assessed (it would be difficult to measure even in
principie), but a modification of our general model to include this
possibility will be didactically useful. It will be shown that the
methods of ~malysis used can easily be modified to establish the
existence of equilibrium in this case. This may seem surprising,
because our methods are closely related to the optimality properties
of competitive equilibrium; when the utility function is no longer a
given for the economic system, but instead, varies with sorne of its
variables (in this case, price) the significance of Pareto efficiency
becomes obscure, since an allocation that is dominated at one set of

129
r
!
---------

128 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS Chapter Six


multi-period models is dueto Debreu [1959, Chapter 7]. The relation
between convexity of preferences and risk aversion was noted by Arrow GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM
[1953, Section 4; 1963-64, Section 4]. The difficulties created for this UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS
equilibrium concept by the varying information structures of the
economic agents were noted by Radner [1968]; the particular problems
of moral hazard were emphasized by Arrow [1963, 961-962 1965
55-56; 1970, 142-143]. ' ' The expense
Is what one thought and more.
-Yvor Winters,
At the San Francisco Airport

The existence of general equilibrium has been proved in the last


chapter .under the assumptions set forth in Chapters 3 and 4-the
usual assumptions of the perfectly competitive economy. In this
chapter, we will show that the methods of analysis used so far can
also demonstrate the existence of equilibrium in severa! cases in
which sorne of these conditions are relaxed.

l. Prices Affecting Utilities


It has been frequently suggested in the literature that an individual's
preferences among commodity vectors are influenced by the prices;
typically, it is argued that if the price of a commodity goes up, the
commodity will be more highly valued (in the sense that, for any
VNIVERSiJT~ ttARIS 1 given quantities, the marginal rate of substitution between that
106-1 q: ~bouley~rq d~ l'Hopitl commodity and any other increases) either because it serves as a
better public demonstration ofthe household's wealth [Veblen, 1899]
75013 P.ARIS or because price is used by the ,household as an index of quality
'fl. : o1 45 8'7 23 00 [Scitovsky, 1944--45]. The emprica! importance of the price effect
Fax : 01 4~ a.7 24 00 has never been assessed (it would be difficult to measure even in
principie), but a modification of our general model to include this
possibility will be didactically useful. It will be shown that the
methods of ~malysis used can easily be modified to establish the
existence of equilibrium in this case. This may seem surprising,
because our methods are closely related to the optimality properties
of competitive equilibrium; when the utility function is no longer a
given for the economic system, but instead, varies with sorne of its
variables (in this case, price) the significance of Pareto efficiency
becomes obscure, since an allocation that is dominated at one set of

129
130 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 131
prices is not dominated at another. However, we can use a concept utilities are measured by the utility function appropriate to the given
that might be termed conditional Pareto efficiency: For any fixed price vector, p.
price vector, we take the utility functions corresponding to it and Let X,(u",p) be the set of consumptions vectors, x" E X", that
find the Pareto-efficient allocations corresponding to them. Thus, achieve utility level at least u" conditional upon the price vector p.
the set of prices associated with a given Pareto-efficient allocation, as Then, from A.6.1, it is easy to generalize Lemma 4.11 to say that
defined in T.4.4 and D.4.14, now depend upon the price initially X"(u",p) is continuous jointly in u" and p. The upper semi-
given as well as the utility allocation. Other parts of the mapping continuity argument proceeds exactly as before with obvious
used in Section 5.3 are modified similarly; the fixed point still exists substitutions. For the proof of lower semi-continuity, we start with
and at this point the price that determines the utility functions is, in sequences, u{. approaching u~ and pv approaching p0 , with x~ E
fact, the prevailing price, so that the final equilibrium situation is X"(u~,p 0). Choose xk so that U"(xk,p 0) > U"(x~,p ). By A.6.1,
0

consisten t. U"(xk,pv) > U,(x~,pv) for v sufficiently large. Then, at least for v
Formally, we modify assumption A.4.3 as follows: large, we can divide the sequence into three subsequences according
AssuMPTION l. For each price vector p > O, there is a preference as (a) u; > U"(xk,pv) (which can hold only for finitely many v), (b)
ordering, ~hp for each household h that satisfies all the conditions U,(x~,pv) .:s; u~ .:s; U,(xk,pv), and (e) U"(x~,pv) > u{.. Then we can
of A.4.3 and, in addition, varies continuously with p in the sense that choose x; E X,.(u;,pv), each v, as before, and prove that x;---+ xg.
it is represented by a utility function, U"(x",p), that is jointly con- Once the generalization of Lemma 4.11 has been accomplished, it
tinuous in its arguments. follows exactly as before that the corresponding generalizations of
Corollary 4.5 and T.4.6 hold, that.is, that 1P'(u,p) and P(u,p) are
As before, we can, with no loss of generality, assume that upper semi-continuous in (u,p). The two sets are, exactly as before,
U"(x",p) = O, all p; for example, first, let U~(x",p) be any utility convex and compact for each (u,p).
function satisfying the hypotheses of A.6.1 and then define Define V(p,w) exactly as in 5.(7). Then there exists a fixed point
U"(x",p) = u;~(x",p) - U~(x",p). of the correspondence
P[u(v,p),p] >< V(p,w) x 1f"[u(v,p),p]
For fixed p, say, the functions U"(x",p) are a set of utility functions,
one for each household, and we can define the conditionally Pareto- that takes Sn x SH x 1f' into subsets of itself. This fixed point
efficient allocations for these functions. The set of conditionally is a compensated equilibrium.
efficient utility allocations may be denoted by U(p); it vares, of To pass from a compensated to a competitive equilibrium, we
course, with p. However, for any fixed p, the argument of Section again use the concept of resource relatedness. The definitions must
5.2 still holds; the non-negative elements of U(p) can be mapped -be rephrased to hold for the utility functions conditional on every p.
one-to-one and continuously onto a unit simplex, SH, through a DEFINITION l. Household h' is resource related to household h" for
function, v(u,p); for each p, this function has an in verse, u(v,p), given price vector p if D.5.4 holds when U"(x") is everywhere replaced
mapping SH into U(p), which, it is easy to verify, is jointly continuous
by U"(x",p).
in its arguments.
For any fixed p and fixed conditionally efficient utility allocation, DEFINITION 2. Household h' is resource related to household h" if it
u E U(p), there exists a price vector, p', that supports that allocation is resource related for every p > O.
in the sen se of T.4.4. In general, p' need not equal p; it will be a The definition of being indirectly resource related remains as in
condition of equilibrium that the equality hold; The set of such p', D.5.5, with the new definition of being resource related substituted.
normalized to lie on the unit simplex for prices, will be denoted by THEOREM l. If the assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4 hold, except
P(u,p). There is also a set of feasible allocations, 1P'(u,p), for each that A.4.3 is replaced by A.6.1 so that utilities may ~ary con-
u in U(p) that achieve (at least) the utility levels prescribed, where tinuously with prices; then there exists a competitive equilibrium.
:.
1

1..

1:

iL
11
130 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 131
prices is not dominated at another. However, we can use a concept utilities are measured by the utility function appropriate to the given
that might be termed conditional Pareto efficiency: For any fixed price vector, p.
price vector, we take the utility functions corresponding to it and Let X,(u",p) be the set of consumptions vectors, x" E X", that
find the Pareto-efficient allocations corresponding to them. Thus, achieve utility level at least u" conditional upon the price vector p.
the set of prices associated with a given Pareto-efficient allocation, as Then, from A.6.1, it is easy to generalize Lemma 4.11 to say that
defined in T.4.4 and D.4.14, now depend upon the price initially X"(u",p) is continuous jointly in u" and p. The upper semi-
given as well as the utility allocation. Other parts of the mapping continuity argument proceeds exactly as before with obvious
used in Section 5.3 are modified similarly; the fixed point still exists substitutions. For the proof of lower semi-continuity, we start with
and at this point the price that determines the utility functions is, in sequences, u{. approaching u~ and pv approaching p0 , with x~ E
fact, the prevailing price, so that the final equilibrium situation is X"(u~,p 0). Choose xk so that U"(xk,p 0) > U"(x~,p ). By A.6.1,
0

consisten t. U"(xk,pv) > U,(x~,pv) for v sufficiently large. Then, at least for v
Formally, we modify assumption A.4.3 as follows: large, we can divide the sequence into three subsequences according
AssuMPTION l. For each price vector p > O, there is a preference as (a) u; > U"(xk,pv) (which can hold only for finitely many v), (b)
ordering, ~hp for each household h that satisfies all the conditions U,(x~,pv) .:s; u~ .:s; U,(xk,pv), and (e) U"(x~,pv) > u{.. Then we can
of A.4.3 and, in addition, varies continuously with p in the sense that choose x; E X,.(u;,pv), each v, as before, and prove that x;---+ xg.
it is represented by a utility function, U"(x",p), that is jointly con- Once the generalization of Lemma 4.11 has been accomplished, it
tinuous in its arguments. follows exactly as before that the corresponding generalizations of
Corollary 4.5 and T.4.6 hold, that.is, that 1P'(u,p) and P(u,p) are
As before, we can, with no loss of generality, assume that upper semi-continuous in (u,p). The two sets are, exactly as before,
U"(x",p) = O, all p; for example, first, let U~(x",p) be any utility convex and compact for each (u,p).
function satisfying the hypotheses of A.6.1 and then define Define V(p,w) exactly as in 5.(7). Then there exists a fixed point
U"(x",p) = u;~(x",p) - U~(x",p). of the correspondence
P[u(v,p),p] >< V(p,w) x 1f"[u(v,p),p]
For fixed p, say, the functions U"(x",p) are a set of utility functions,
one for each household, and we can define the conditionally Pareto- that takes Sn x SH x 1f' into subsets of itself. This fixed point
efficient allocations for these functions. The set of conditionally is a compensated equilibrium.
efficient utility allocations may be denoted by U(p); it vares, of To pass from a compensated to a competitive equilibrium, we
course, with p. However, for any fixed p, the argument of Section again use the concept of resource relatedness. The definitions must
5.2 still holds; the non-negative elements of U(p) can be mapped -be rephrased to hold for the utility functions conditional on every p.
one-to-one and continuously onto a unit simplex, SH, through a DEFINITION l. Household h' is resource related to household h" for
function, v(u,p); for each p, this function has an in verse, u(v,p), given price vector p if D.5.4 holds when U"(x") is everywhere replaced
mapping SH into U(p), which, it is easy to verify, is jointly continuous
by U"(x",p).
in its arguments.
For any fixed p and fixed conditionally efficient utility allocation, DEFINITION 2. Household h' is resource related to household h" if it
u E U(p), there exists a price vector, p', that supports that allocation is resource related for every p > O.
in the sen se of T.4.4. In general, p' need not equal p; it will be a The definition of being indirectly resource related remains as in
condition of equilibrium that the equality hold; The set of such p', D.5.5, with the new definition of being resource related substituted.
normalized to lie on the unit simplex for prices, will be denoted by THEOREM l. If the assumptions of Chapters 3 and 4 hold, except
P(u,p). There is also a set of feasible allocations, 1P'(u,p), for each that A.4.3 is replaced by A.6.1 so that utilities may ~ary con-
u in U(p) that achieve (at least) the utility levels prescribed, where tinuously with prices; then there exists a competitive equilibrium.
:.
1

1..

1:

iL
11
1':
',i :

,,,

132 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 133

2. Externalities with the allocation, Yr( w); again, the effect of to is assumed not to
In fact, not all the effects of the economic behavior of others are depend u pon its y-componen t.
mediated through the price system. In general, it is usually held In accordance with the atomistic connotations of the concept of
that the utility of a household and the production possibility set of competitive equilibrium, each household and firm is assumed to take
a firm is itself affected by the allocation of resources among other externalities as parametrically given. Pormally,
households and firms. Such effects are usually tenned, "externali-
DEFINITION 3. The pair (p*,to*) constitute a competitive equilibrium
ties." We do not attempt a complete analysis of this concept here,
with externalities if D.5.I holds with U"(x1.) replaced everywhere by
but simply assume that the utility function of household h has the
Uh(x1.,to*) and Yr by Yr(to*).
form, U"(x",o ). It is understood in this notation that the effect of
w on Uh does not depend on its XhCOmponent, whose effect S That is, at the equilibrium, each household is maximizing utility
represented explicitly. Pormally, if to 1 and w 2 are two allocations under a budget constraint given the activities of all other households
that differ only in their x"-component, then and of all firms, and each firm is maximizing profits given the
for all x". activities of all households and all other firms.
On the consumptions side, the assumptions made are strictly
This understanding permits us to ascribe meaning to the symbols
parallel to those of'the last section:
U"(x 1.,w) even when the x"-component of to differs from x"; the
former simply doesn't matter. AsSUMPTION 2. Por each allocation, tt/, there is a preference order-
It should be noted that there are two somewhat different possible ing ';phw for each household h that satisfies all the conditions of
interpretations of U"(x",w): It represents the preference ordering for A.4.3 and, in addition, varies continuously with .w in the sense that
Xh E Xh for given Values of the consumption VeCtOfS Of Other house-
it is represented by a utility function Uh(x",to) that is jointly con-
holds and of productlon possibility vectors for firms; and it might tinuous in its arguments.
represent a preference ordering o ver the en tire space of allocations;
the household may be assumed to have preferences with regard to This assumption replaces A.4.3. As before, A.4.1 and A.4.2 are
the actions of others for all the usual reasons of externality (e.g., maintained.
pollution of air or water). The second interpretation implies the On the production side, somewhat more complicated modifica-
first, though not conversely; if Uix",to) represents a preference tions must be made. Note that at equilibrium the firm is maxi-
ordering over allocations, then for fixed w (with the understanding mizing profits at fixed prices; hence, we cannot drop the convexity
given above), it represents a preference ordering over X" alone. Por assumption on Y1(to ), at least not completely, for with increasing
the purposes of welfare analysis, it is the second interpretation that returns there need not exist any maximum. On the other hand, we
is needed, but for descriptive analysis and the proof of existence of do not want to exclude the possibility of increasing returns to the
equilibrium, it is the first that is needed and will be assumed here. economy as a whole. Indeed, one important implication of the
With this interpretation, we can enforce without difficulty the notion of externalities (more specifically, externa! economies) has
convention that U"(xh,w) = O for all w. (This utility function been the viability of competitive equilibrium under social-increasing
would not satisfy the second interpretation, in general, since there is returns. What happens, of course, is that the increasing returns are
no reason why the household would be indifferent among allocations caused by the influence of one firm on another's productivity, an
when x" = x"; but such a utility function can be derived, of course, influence that for one reason or another is not compensated for in
from a utility function over all allocations by subtracting the utility the market.
of (x",w ), the result being still consistent with the first interpretation.) We first assume that the assumptions previousy held about the
On the production side, we have a parallel situation; the produc- production possibility sets of individual firms continue to hold for
tion possibility set, Y, of firm f is no longer a constan t. It vares any given allocation.
1':
',i :

,,,

132 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 133

2. Externalities with the allocation, Yr( w); again, the effect of to is assumed not to
In fact, not all the effects of the economic behavior of others are depend u pon its y-componen t.
mediated through the price system. In general, it is usually held In accordance with the atomistic connotations of the concept of
that the utility of a household and the production possibility set of competitive equilibrium, each household and firm is assumed to take
a firm is itself affected by the allocation of resources among other externalities as parametrically given. Pormally,
households and firms. Such effects are usually tenned, "externali-
DEFINITION 3. The pair (p*,to*) constitute a competitive equilibrium
ties." We do not attempt a complete analysis of this concept here,
with externalities if D.5.I holds with U"(x1.) replaced everywhere by
but simply assume that the utility function of household h has the
Uh(x1.,to*) and Yr by Yr(to*).
form, U"(x",o ). It is understood in this notation that the effect of
w on Uh does not depend on its XhCOmponent, whose effect S That is, at the equilibrium, each household is maximizing utility
represented explicitly. Pormally, if to 1 and w 2 are two allocations under a budget constraint given the activities of all other households
that differ only in their x"-component, then and of all firms, and each firm is maximizing profits given the
for all x". activities of all households and all other firms.
On the consumptions side, the assumptions made are strictly
This understanding permits us to ascribe meaning to the symbols
parallel to those of'the last section:
U"(x 1.,w) even when the x"-component of to differs from x"; the
former simply doesn't matter. AsSUMPTION 2. Por each allocation, tt/, there is a preference order-
It should be noted that there are two somewhat different possible ing ';phw for each household h that satisfies all the conditions of
interpretations of U"(x",w): It represents the preference ordering for A.4.3 and, in addition, varies continuously with .w in the sense that
Xh E Xh for given Values of the consumption VeCtOfS Of Other house-
it is represented by a utility function Uh(x",to) that is jointly con-
holds and of productlon possibility vectors for firms; and it might tinuous in its arguments.
represent a preference ordering o ver the en tire space of allocations;
the household may be assumed to have preferences with regard to This assumption replaces A.4.3. As before, A.4.1 and A.4.2 are
the actions of others for all the usual reasons of externality (e.g., maintained.
pollution of air or water). The second interpretation implies the On the production side, somewhat more complicated modifica-
first, though not conversely; if Uix",to) represents a preference tions must be made. Note that at equilibrium the firm is maxi-
ordering over allocations, then for fixed w (with the understanding mizing profits at fixed prices; hence, we cannot drop the convexity
given above), it represents a preference ordering over X" alone. Por assumption on Y1(to ), at least not completely, for with increasing
the purposes of welfare analysis, it is the second interpretation that returns there need not exist any maximum. On the other hand, we
is needed, but for descriptive analysis and the proof of existence of do not want to exclude the possibility of increasing returns to the
equilibrium, it is the first that is needed and will be assumed here. economy as a whole. Indeed, one important implication of the
With this interpretation, we can enforce without difficulty the notion of externalities (more specifically, externa! economies) has
convention that U"(xh,w) = O for all w. (This utility function been the viability of competitive equilibrium under social-increasing
would not satisfy the second interpretation, in general, since there is returns. What happens, of course, is that the increasing returns are
no reason why the household would be indifferent among allocations caused by the influence of one firm on another's productivity, an
when x" = x"; but such a utility function can be derived, of course, influence that for one reason or another is not compensated for in
from a utility function over all allocations by subtracting the utility the market.
of (x",w ), the result being still consistent with the first interpretation.) We first assume that the assumptions previousy held about the
On the production side, we have a parallel situation; the produc- production possibility sets of individual firms continue to hold for
tion possibility set, Y, of firm f is no longer a constan t. It vares any given allocation.
r
134 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 135

AssuMPTION 3. Assumptions A.3.1-A.3.3 hold with Y1 replaced by assumption that xh is bounded from below that if"(u,w) is compact
Y1(w). for all u and w. '
W e al so assume The convexity of this set follows immediately from the convexity
of X 11 (uh,w) and of Y 1(to) for fixed u and w.
AssUMPTION 4. For each f, Y1(to) is a continuous correspondence Also, just as in the previous section, the continuity of X 11 (uh,w) in
in to.
its arguments follows easily from the assumptions and from this, the
Recall that a correspondence is continuous if it is both lower and continuity of '#"(u,w) follows from A.6.4. Again as in Section 6.1,
upper semi-continuous. we have for each w, a set of conditionally Pareto-efficient allocations,
Corresponding to D.3.3, D.4.6-D.4.8, and D.4.10, we have: U(to ), and for each u in U(to ); a non-m11l set of price vectors, P(u,w ),
DEFINITION 4. Xh(u 11 ,w) = {x11 1 U11 (x 11 ,w) 2: u11 }. that support that allocation. From the continuity of "/r(u,w), it
follows, as in the proofs of Corollary 4.5 and T.4.6, that "lf'(u,to) and
DEFINITION 5. El'(u,w) = X X 11(uh,to). P(u,w) are upper semi-continuous correspondences.
h

DEFINITION 6. <??f(w) = X Y(w). Finally, for each w, we can find a one-one continuous function
f mapping U(w) into the unit simplex, SH; let u(v,w) map SH into
DEFINITION 7. '#"(u,w) = E(u,w) X <??f(w). U(w). Then, again as in Section 6.1, u(v,to) is jointly continuous in
the two variables.
DEFINITION 8. if"(u,w) = "/r(u,w) X {m 1 L Xh ~ L Yt + L x11};
n f h Then the correspondence
that is, if"(u,w) is the set of u-feasible allocations conditional on an
P[u(v,w),w] X V(p,w) x if"[u(v,to),to]
allocation w.
We need an assumption to ensure the compactness of the last set. has a fixed point, which can be seen to be a compe'nsated equilibrium
To this end, we make an assumption parallel to A.3.4 (impossibility in the sense that each household is minimizing the cost of achieving
of producing something from rtothing), but apply: it to a somewhat a given utility measured at the equilibrium allocation and similarly
wider set than that of the actually possible production allocations each firm is maximizing profits among the production vectors
that are mutually consistent. Define possible at the equilibrium allocation. It follows also that the
equilibrium allocation is consistent, in that if each firm produces and
DEFINITION 9. Yj* = {y1 1 Yt E Y1(w) for sorne (w)}, each household consumes according to it, then the production
Yj is the closed convex hull of Yj*. vectors for each firm in fact will be possible because the externa!
(For the definition of a convex hull, see D.B.l2.) effects are those assumed.
For the passage to a competitive equilibrium, use
ASSUMPTION 5. Ify1 E Yj, eachf, and Lf Yt = 0, then Yt = 0.
'
1
In words, even if we ascribe to each firm all the production possi- DEFINITION 10. Household h' is resource relat~d to household h" if
1'
bility vectors it could have for any pssible actions of other firms and definitions D.6.1 and D.6.2 hold with p replaced by w.
then take the convex hull of that set, it would not have been so THEOREM 2. Competitive equilibrium exists in the presence of
expanded as to permit either production without inputs or externalities if assumptions A.6.2-A.6.5, A.4.1 and A.4.2 hold and
reversibility. if every household is indirectly resource related to every other.
From A.6.5 we have a conclusion like T.3.2:
In the presence of externalities, the competitive equilibrium is
(>f Yj) n {:~>1 + x 2: O} is compact. conditionally Pareto efficient, that is, Pareto efficient according to
the utility functions and productio~ possibility sets corresponding to
Since Y1(to) e Yj, all f, it follows from the definitions, plus the the equilibrium allocation. Of cotirSe, the equilibrium is not Pareto
r
134 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 135

AssuMPTION 3. Assumptions A.3.1-A.3.3 hold with Y1 replaced by assumption that xh is bounded from below that if"(u,w) is compact
Y1(w). for all u and w. '
W e al so assume The convexity of this set follows immediately from the convexity
of X 11 (uh,w) and of Y 1(to) for fixed u and w.
AssUMPTION 4. For each f, Y1(to) is a continuous correspondence Also, just as in the previous section, the continuity of X 11 (uh,w) in
in to.
its arguments follows easily from the assumptions and from this, the
Recall that a correspondence is continuous if it is both lower and continuity of '#"(u,w) follows from A.6.4. Again as in Section 6.1,
upper semi-continuous. we have for each w, a set of conditionally Pareto-efficient allocations,
Corresponding to D.3.3, D.4.6-D.4.8, and D.4.10, we have: U(to ), and for each u in U(to ); a non-m11l set of price vectors, P(u,w ),
DEFINITION 4. Xh(u 11 ,w) = {x11 1 U11 (x 11 ,w) 2: u11 }. that support that allocation. From the continuity of "/r(u,w), it
follows, as in the proofs of Corollary 4.5 and T.4.6, that "lf'(u,to) and
DEFINITION 5. El'(u,w) = X X 11(uh,to). P(u,w) are upper semi-continuous correspondences.
h

DEFINITION 6. <??f(w) = X Y(w). Finally, for each w, we can find a one-one continuous function
f mapping U(w) into the unit simplex, SH; let u(v,w) map SH into
DEFINITION 7. '#"(u,w) = E(u,w) X <??f(w). U(w). Then, again as in Section 6.1, u(v,to) is jointly continuous in
the two variables.
DEFINITION 8. if"(u,w) = "/r(u,w) X {m 1 L Xh ~ L Yt + L x11};
n f h Then the correspondence
that is, if"(u,w) is the set of u-feasible allocations conditional on an
P[u(v,w),w] X V(p,w) x if"[u(v,to),to]
allocation w.
We need an assumption to ensure the compactness of the last set. has a fixed point, which can be seen to be a compe'nsated equilibrium
To this end, we make an assumption parallel to A.3.4 (impossibility in the sense that each household is minimizing the cost of achieving
of producing something from rtothing), but apply: it to a somewhat a given utility measured at the equilibrium allocation and similarly
wider set than that of the actually possible production allocations each firm is maximizing profits among the production vectors
that are mutually consistent. Define possible at the equilibrium allocation. It follows also that the
equilibrium allocation is consistent, in that if each firm produces and
DEFINITION 9. Yj* = {y1 1 Yt E Y1(w) for sorne (w)}, each household consumes according to it, then the production
Yj is the closed convex hull of Yj*. vectors for each firm in fact will be possible because the externa!
(For the definition of a convex hull, see D.B.l2.) effects are those assumed.
For the passage to a competitive equilibrium, use
ASSUMPTION 5. Ify1 E Yj, eachf, and Lf Yt = 0, then Yt = 0.
'
1
In words, even if we ascribe to each firm all the production possi- DEFINITION 10. Household h' is resource relat~d to household h" if
1'
bility vectors it could have for any pssible actions of other firms and definitions D.6.1 and D.6.2 hold with p replaced by w.
then take the convex hull of that set, it would not have been so THEOREM 2. Competitive equilibrium exists in the presence of
expanded as to permit either production without inputs or externalities if assumptions A.6.2-A.6.5, A.4.1 and A.4.2 hold and
reversibility. if every household is indirectly resource related to every other.
From A.6.5 we have a conclusion like T.3.2:
In the presence of externalities, the competitive equilibrium is
(>f Yj) n {:~>1 + x 2: O} is compact. conditionally Pareto efficient, that is, Pareto efficient according to
the utility functions and productio~ possibility sets corresponding to
Since Y1(to) e Yj, all f, it follows from the definitions, plus the the equilibrium allocation. Of cotirSe, the equilibrium is not Pareto
T
,,,''
,,1
'1
~'
1 '1'

136 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 137
efficient in any broader sen se; other allocations may indeed improve a firm is "realistic enough" not to plan indefinitely large production.
the utility of all, when the utility considered is a function of the en tire 1t is preferable, however, to incorporate the argument from realism
allocation. into our construction in a way more in the spirit of the perfectly
By the same token, there are private pressures toward making competitive model. We do this by insisting that the price expecta-
deals not compatible with the competitive equilibrium. In par- tions of firms be "sensible." This is done la ter in A.6. 7(b ).
ticular, there can be profit in the merger of two or more firms, a As already noted, plans for future production must have con-
profit that is absent in the absence of externalities. sequences in current markets. In fact, we shall assume that each
firm offers in the current bond market a quantity of bonds equal to
3. Temporary Equilibrium its expected profit in the future. This means that there is a" current"
representaton of the future plans, which, in turn, allows us to
In Sections 2.9 and 2.10 we noted the need for a model of general incorporate these in the framework of our earlier discussion. This 1!'
equilibrium for a world in which households and firms planned on ismade precise in (1) and D.6.12.
the basis of an assumed future, but in which future markets did not When we cometo consumers, a number of special problems arise.
exist or were severely limited in scope. We now return to this issue First, we must decide what we mean by the initial endowment of
in the context of the more general and detailed model of Chapters bonds held by a household. We simply. take it to equal its antici-
3 and 4. pated receipts of the future period; that is, it represents the maximum
We will now see that the components of the possible production the household believes it could repay. Note that the household's
and consumption vectors extend over severa! periods of time. For anticipated receipts may differ from what any other agent would
simplicity, we will confine ourselves to two periods, present and i
expect them to be, given the household's plans-that is, we allow for ! ~

future. We assume that the only commodities traded in currently 1:,1


differences in price expectations.
;:1
are commodities of the current period plus bonds; a unit bond is a The differences in expectations also mean that different households '
promise to pay one unit of the currency of account in tl1e next will value any given firm differently. We assume that the actual
period. Let the subscript b refer to bonds. We use here the current market value of any firm is equal to the highest value any
notation x to refer to the vector of commodities currently traded in agent places on it and suppose that the ownership of the firm will
by households; thus x = (x\xb), not x = (x\x 2). Similarly, for shift to the hands of that household or those households that value
firms, y = (Y\Yb) where Yb is the supply of bonds issued by firms, and it most highly (D.6.16 and A.6.9). Therefore, we now treat dh 1 , the
p = (p\]Jb). share of household h in firmj, as a variable of the equilibrium. All
The main task of this section is to show how, by suitable modifica- this leads to modifications in the manner in which we must write the
tions of the methods and concepts of Chapters 3-5, the existence of households' budget constraints [see (10) and (15)].
an equilibrium on the current markets can be established. Befare We must ensure also that our assumptions about consumption
going into details, we will discuss the main difficulties and the possibility sets, A.4.1 and A.4.2, hold when reinterpreted in terms of
strategy for overcoming them. The modifications to be made to the current markets. This is fairly straightforward (see A.6.8, (16), and
definition of and assumptions on the production sets are straight- D.6.17).
forward except for one particular. Consider one firm whose pro- Lastly thcrc is thc following problem: We know that the house-
duction plan for the future has consequences in current markets hold utility depends on its future plans, and in the existence proof of
beca use it affects the current value of the firm and the amount it will Section 6.2, the utilities of the households played an important part.
borrow. Since there is no current market for the resources of the Our procedure incorporating the expected future into arguments
subsequent period, the availability of resources then cannot be used about the present is to use a "derived utility function" (D.6.18).
to argue that production plans are bounded. This creates obvious This will be the maximum utility of the household, given its first-
difficulties, which are partly academic since it could be argued that period allocation, under an appropriate budget constraint. 1t will

,,
,
Ji
d
T
,,,''
,,1
'1
~'
1 '1'

136 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 137
efficient in any broader sen se; other allocations may indeed improve a firm is "realistic enough" not to plan indefinitely large production.
the utility of all, when the utility considered is a function of the en tire 1t is preferable, however, to incorporate the argument from realism
allocation. into our construction in a way more in the spirit of the perfectly
By the same token, there are private pressures toward making competitive model. We do this by insisting that the price expecta-
deals not compatible with the competitive equilibrium. In par- tions of firms be "sensible." This is done la ter in A.6. 7(b ).
ticular, there can be profit in the merger of two or more firms, a As already noted, plans for future production must have con-
profit that is absent in the absence of externalities. sequences in current markets. In fact, we shall assume that each
firm offers in the current bond market a quantity of bonds equal to
3. Temporary Equilibrium its expected profit in the future. This means that there is a" current"
representaton of the future plans, which, in turn, allows us to
In Sections 2.9 and 2.10 we noted the need for a model of general incorporate these in the framework of our earlier discussion. This 1!'
equilibrium for a world in which households and firms planned on ismade precise in (1) and D.6.12.
the basis of an assumed future, but in which future markets did not When we cometo consumers, a number of special problems arise.
exist or were severely limited in scope. We now return to this issue First, we must decide what we mean by the initial endowment of
in the context of the more general and detailed model of Chapters bonds held by a household. We simply. take it to equal its antici-
3 and 4. pated receipts of the future period; that is, it represents the maximum
We will now see that the components of the possible production the household believes it could repay. Note that the household's
and consumption vectors extend over severa! periods of time. For anticipated receipts may differ from what any other agent would
simplicity, we will confine ourselves to two periods, present and i
expect them to be, given the household's plans-that is, we allow for ! ~

future. We assume that the only commodities traded in currently 1:,1


differences in price expectations.
;:1
are commodities of the current period plus bonds; a unit bond is a The differences in expectations also mean that different households '
promise to pay one unit of the currency of account in tl1e next will value any given firm differently. We assume that the actual
period. Let the subscript b refer to bonds. We use here the current market value of any firm is equal to the highest value any
notation x to refer to the vector of commodities currently traded in agent places on it and suppose that the ownership of the firm will
by households; thus x = (x\xb), not x = (x\x 2). Similarly, for shift to the hands of that household or those households that value
firms, y = (Y\Yb) where Yb is the supply of bonds issued by firms, and it most highly (D.6.16 and A.6.9). Therefore, we now treat dh 1 , the
p = (p\]Jb). share of household h in firmj, as a variable of the equilibrium. All
The main task of this section is to show how, by suitable modifica- this leads to modifications in the manner in which we must write the
tions of the methods and concepts of Chapters 3-5, the existence of households' budget constraints [see (10) and (15)].
an equilibrium on the current markets can be established. Befare We must ensure also that our assumptions about consumption
going into details, we will discuss the main difficulties and the possibility sets, A.4.1 and A.4.2, hold when reinterpreted in terms of
strategy for overcoming them. The modifications to be made to the current markets. This is fairly straightforward (see A.6.8, (16), and
definition of and assumptions on the production sets are straight- D.6.17).
forward except for one particular. Consider one firm whose pro- Lastly thcrc is thc following problem: We know that the house-
duction plan for the future has consequences in current markets hold utility depends on its future plans, and in the existence proof of
beca use it affects the current value of the firm and the amount it will Section 6.2, the utilities of the households played an important part.
borrow. Since there is no current market for the resources of the Our procedure incorporating the expected future into arguments
subsequent period, the availability of resources then cannot be used about the present is to use a "derived utility function" (D.6.18).
to argue that production plans are bounded. This creates obvious This will be the maximum utility of the household, given its first-
difficulties, which are partly academic since it could be argued that period allocation, under an appropriate budget constraint. 1t will

,,
,
Ji
d
138 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 139

be obvious that this derived function can be treated as a function of The firm chooses its production plan so as to maximize (2) among
current plans only, as is desired. all production plans yp E Y} 2 . Provisionally, we will assume that
Proceeding to detailed argument, Iet us first consider the behavior all price expectations are totally inelastic, that is, that p] is a datum
of the firm. We take the viewpoint that the firm is an entity that, for the firm independent of current prices. Then (1) maps the
on its own, has' expectations of future prices and maximizes profits elements of Y} 2 into a set Y1 of (n + !)-dimensional vectors; in
in accordance with them. At the end ofthis section we will comment effect, with fixed expectations, the firm's future possibilities amount
on this assumption. to its ability to produce bonds for today's market.
We retain the assumptions on the production possibility sets ofthe DEFINITION 12. The set of possible current production vectors, Y 1 ,
individual firms with appropriate changes of notation and add a for firm f is the image of Y} 2 under the linear mapping (1 ),
hypothesis that embodies the possibility of abandoning a productive
enterprise without loss. Yr = {y 1 1 Yr = (y},y 1b) such that

DEFINITION 11. The set of possible two,period production vectors for Y!b = PJYJ for sorne (y},y7) E Y} 2}.
firmfis Y} 2 An element is denoted by y} 2 = (y},y7), where y} are The set of possible current production allocations is qy = X Y 1
f
the components of y} 2 referring to the first period and y] are those
It is easy to verify from A.6.6 that
referring to the second period. We al so refer to y} and YJ as first- 1,,
period and second-period production vectors, respectively. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold under D.6.12. (3)

The set of possible two-period production allocations for the From D.6.12 and (2):
economy is l{l/ 12 = X Y} 2 The firm maximizes py1 . (4)
f
Suppose pb > O and the firm has chosen a production plan, y} 2 ,
ASSUMPTION 6. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold with Yr replaced by yj2 and Y1
for which there will be negative receipts in the future, PJYJ < O.
by Yj2. If (y},y7) E Y} 2, then there exists yJ' :2: O such that
Then by the second half of A.6.6, it is possible to choose another
(y},y7') E Y} 2
plan with higher profits.
The firm observes current prices, p = (p\pb), and is assumed to
have subjectively certain expectations for prices in period 2, PJ; since lf Pb > O, then PJYJ = Y!b :2: O
there are no future markets, different firms may have different at any profit-maximizing plan. (5)
expectations. A production plan, (y},yJ), yields net revenue p 1 y} in We now make an assumption about the impossibility of produc-
period 1 and is expected to yield net revenue PJYJ in period 2. If tion without inputs and about irreversibility that is somewhat
bonds sell in period 1 at pb, then a revenue of PJYJ in period 2 is stronger than that obtained simply by replacing y1 by y} 2 and Y1 by
equivalent on perfect markets to a first-period income of pb(pJyJ). Y} 2 in A.4.4. The reason the stronger assumption is needed is that
Without loss of generality, we can assume that the firm actually sells future resource limitations do not directly restrain production, since
bonds to the extent of its anticipated second-period income; if, in there are no future markets on which they appear. We still do have
fact, it does not do so, we can imagine that it does and then dis- the constraints on first-period resources and, in addition, we will, in
tributes the difference to its stockholders. Under the assumptions accordance with (5), restrict ourselves at certain stages in the
being made here, the two actions are completely indifferent to argument to plans for which PJYJ :2: O, since only those will satisfy
everyone. Its offering of bonds is our equilibrium conditions.
Ytb = PJYJ, (1) ASSUMPTION 7. (a) lf L y} :2: 0, then y} = 0, allf
f
and its current receipts from a given production plan are (b) The future returns to any production plan requiring no first-
P1Y} + Pb(pJyJ). (2) period inputs are bounded for any firm; that is, pJyJ is bounded as
138 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 139

be obvious that this derived function can be treated as a function of The firm chooses its production plan so as to maximize (2) among
current plans only, as is desired. all production plans yp E Y} 2 . Provisionally, we will assume that
Proceeding to detailed argument, Iet us first consider the behavior all price expectations are totally inelastic, that is, that p] is a datum
of the firm. We take the viewpoint that the firm is an entity that, for the firm independent of current prices. Then (1) maps the
on its own, has' expectations of future prices and maximizes profits elements of Y} 2 into a set Y1 of (n + !)-dimensional vectors; in
in accordance with them. At the end ofthis section we will comment effect, with fixed expectations, the firm's future possibilities amount
on this assumption. to its ability to produce bonds for today's market.
We retain the assumptions on the production possibility sets ofthe DEFINITION 12. The set of possible current production vectors, Y 1 ,
individual firms with appropriate changes of notation and add a for firm f is the image of Y} 2 under the linear mapping (1 ),
hypothesis that embodies the possibility of abandoning a productive
enterprise without loss. Yr = {y 1 1 Yr = (y},y 1b) such that

DEFINITION 11. The set of possible two,period production vectors for Y!b = PJYJ for sorne (y},y7) E Y} 2}.
firmfis Y} 2 An element is denoted by y} 2 = (y},y7), where y} are The set of possible current production allocations is qy = X Y 1
f
the components of y} 2 referring to the first period and y] are those
It is easy to verify from A.6.6 that
referring to the second period. We al so refer to y} and YJ as first- 1,,
period and second-period production vectors, respectively. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold under D.6.12. (3)

The set of possible two-period production allocations for the From D.6.12 and (2):
economy is l{l/ 12 = X Y} 2 The firm maximizes py1 . (4)
f
Suppose pb > O and the firm has chosen a production plan, y} 2 ,
ASSUMPTION 6. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold with Yr replaced by yj2 and Y1
for which there will be negative receipts in the future, PJYJ < O.
by Yj2. If (y},y7) E Y} 2, then there exists yJ' :2: O such that
Then by the second half of A.6.6, it is possible to choose another
(y},y7') E Y} 2
plan with higher profits.
The firm observes current prices, p = (p\pb), and is assumed to
have subjectively certain expectations for prices in period 2, PJ; since lf Pb > O, then PJYJ = Y!b :2: O
there are no future markets, different firms may have different at any profit-maximizing plan. (5)
expectations. A production plan, (y},yJ), yields net revenue p 1 y} in We now make an assumption about the impossibility of produc-
period 1 and is expected to yield net revenue PJYJ in period 2. If tion without inputs and about irreversibility that is somewhat
bonds sell in period 1 at pb, then a revenue of PJYJ in period 2 is stronger than that obtained simply by replacing y1 by y} 2 and Y1 by
equivalent on perfect markets to a first-period income of pb(pJyJ). Y} 2 in A.4.4. The reason the stronger assumption is needed is that
Without loss of generality, we can assume that the firm actually sells future resource limitations do not directly restrain production, since
bonds to the extent of its anticipated second-period income; if, in there are no future markets on which they appear. We still do have
fact, it does not do so, we can imagine that it does and then dis- the constraints on first-period resources and, in addition, we will, in
tributes the difference to its stockholders. Under the assumptions accordance with (5), restrict ourselves at certain stages in the
being made here, the two actions are completely indifferent to argument to plans for which PJYJ :2: O, since only those will satisfy
everyone. Its offering of bonds is our equilibrium conditions.
Ytb = PJYJ, (1) ASSUMPTION 7. (a) lf L y} :2: 0, then y} = 0, allf
f
and its current receipts from a given production plan are (b) The future returns to any production plan requiring no first-
P1Y} + Pb(pJyJ). (2) period inputs are bounded for any firm; that is, pJyJ is bounded as
T
1

140 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 141

YJ varies over all two-period production vectors (O,y]) in Y} 2 with no tively. We assume also that Uk 2 (xk,x~) is not satiated in x~ for
current inputs. any xk.
We will argue that this assumption is not unreasonable. First, it Like the firm, the household knows current prices, including that
must be understood that any factor availabilities in period 1 as the of bonds, and anticipates second-period prices, p~. It plans pur-
result of earlier production (e.g., durable capital goods or maturing chases and sales for both periods. In each period, there is a budget
agricultura! products) are to be included in the initial endowment of constraint. The two constraints are linked through the purchase of
current flows, x1 Hence, the absence of net inputs means the bonds, which constitutes an expense in period 1 and a source of
absence of capital, labor, and current raw materials; it is reasonable, purchasing power in period 2 (or vice versa, if the household is a net
then, to conclude that no production takes place in period 1, that is, borrower in period 1). The household can be considered to have
y} = O, all f As far as (b) is concerned, if it were not true, then a an initial endowment of bonds, x"b' which is precise! y its anticipated
firm could expect indefinitely large profits in the next period even if volume of receipts in period 2 (but see Remark 2 at the end of this
it would shut down today. But then the firm would know that its section). The net purchase of bonds in period 1 is denoted then by
price expectations are not consistent with any equilibrium, so it is xhb - xhb Total expenditures for goods and bonds in period 1 are
reasonable to argue that it does not hold any such expectations. p 1xk + pb(xhb - xhb), while planned expenditures in period 2 are p~x~.
Thus (b) is really a weak requirement on the rationality of The purchasing power available in period 1 is the sum of the sale
expectations. of endowment, p 1 xk, and receipts from firms in that period. The
'To ha ve a temporarily useful terminology, we define planned receipts in period 2 equal the planned sale of endowment,
p~x~, plus receipts from firms in period 2, and this sum equals x"b'
DEFINITION 13. The set of quasi-jeasible two-period production
as remarked. The purchasing power planned to be available in
allocations is,
period 2 is the repayment to the household of its net purchase of ,,,,
qjj 12 = C!JI12 n {~12/f y} + x1 ;:o: O, PJYJ ;:o: O for all f} bonds, xhb - Xb, plus planned receipts and, therefore, is simply xhb
One feature in this model is not present in the static model or its
!.
intertemporal analog with all future markets. Since different
From A.6.7, the argument used in the proof of T.3.2 can be easily households hold different expectations of future prices, they have '
ll
adapted to prove different expectations of the profitability of any particular firm. 1:

qjj 12 is compact and convex. (6) Hence, a market for shares in firms will arise; the initial stock-
holders may value the firm less highly than sorne others, and there- ,,
In the theory of consumer behavior, we apply again the assump-
fore, the stock of the firm should change hands.

tions made earlier to the intertemporal consumption vectors.
After the firm has chosen its production plans, y} 2 , household h
DEFINITION 14. The set of possible two-period consumption vectors values the plan according to current prices and its expectations of
for household h is Xk 2 , with elements xk 2 = (xk,x~), the com- future priceL
ponents being referred to as the first-period and second-period DEFINITION 15. The capital value of jirm f according to household h
possible consumption vectors, respectively;
lS
The set of possible .two-period consumption Khf(p,y}2) = P1 YY + Pb(P~YJ).
allocations for the economy is The value of the firm in the market is the highest value that any
ff12 =X Xk2. household gives to it.
h
DEFINITION 16. The market capital value of jirm f is
ASSUMPTION 8. A.4.1-A.4.. 3 hold under D.6.14 w1'th x U (x)
2 2 "' h h ' K1(p,y} 2) = max K1(p,y}2).
xh, X, and xh replaced by xk , u12(xP), :Xk , 'Xk , and Xk , respec-
2 2
h
i
T
1

140 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 141

YJ varies over all two-period production vectors (O,y]) in Y} 2 with no tively. We assume also that Uk 2 (xk,x~) is not satiated in x~ for
current inputs. any xk.
We will argue that this assumption is not unreasonable. First, it Like the firm, the household knows current prices, including that
must be understood that any factor availabilities in period 1 as the of bonds, and anticipates second-period prices, p~. It plans pur-
result of earlier production (e.g., durable capital goods or maturing chases and sales for both periods. In each period, there is a budget
agricultura! products) are to be included in the initial endowment of constraint. The two constraints are linked through the purchase of
current flows, x1 Hence, the absence of net inputs means the bonds, which constitutes an expense in period 1 and a source of
absence of capital, labor, and current raw materials; it is reasonable, purchasing power in period 2 (or vice versa, if the household is a net
then, to conclude that no production takes place in period 1, that is, borrower in period 1). The household can be considered to have
y} = O, all f As far as (b) is concerned, if it were not true, then a an initial endowment of bonds, x"b' which is precise! y its anticipated
firm could expect indefinitely large profits in the next period even if volume of receipts in period 2 (but see Remark 2 at the end of this
it would shut down today. But then the firm would know that its section). The net purchase of bonds in period 1 is denoted then by
price expectations are not consistent with any equilibrium, so it is xhb - xhb Total expenditures for goods and bonds in period 1 are
reasonable to argue that it does not hold any such expectations. p 1xk + pb(xhb - xhb), while planned expenditures in period 2 are p~x~.
Thus (b) is really a weak requirement on the rationality of The purchasing power available in period 1 is the sum of the sale
expectations. of endowment, p 1 xk, and receipts from firms in that period. The
'To ha ve a temporarily useful terminology, we define planned receipts in period 2 equal the planned sale of endowment,
p~x~, plus receipts from firms in period 2, and this sum equals x"b'
DEFINITION 13. The set of quasi-jeasible two-period production
as remarked. The purchasing power planned to be available in
allocations is,
period 2 is the repayment to the household of its net purchase of ,,,,
qjj 12 = C!JI12 n {~12/f y} + x1 ;:o: O, PJYJ ;:o: O for all f} bonds, xhb - Xb, plus planned receipts and, therefore, is simply xhb
One feature in this model is not present in the static model or its
!.
intertemporal analog with all future markets. Since different
From A.6.7, the argument used in the proof of T.3.2 can be easily households hold different expectations of future prices, they have '
ll
adapted to prove different expectations of the profitability of any particular firm. 1:

qjj 12 is compact and convex. (6) Hence, a market for shares in firms will arise; the initial stock-
holders may value the firm less highly than sorne others, and there- ,,
In the theory of consumer behavior, we apply again the assump-
fore, the stock of the firm should change hands.

tions made earlier to the intertemporal consumption vectors.
After the firm has chosen its production plans, y} 2 , household h
DEFINITION 14. The set of possible two-period consumption vectors values the plan according to current prices and its expectations of
for household h is Xk 2 , with elements xk 2 = (xk,x~), the com- future priceL
ponents being referred to as the first-period and second-period DEFINITION 15. The capital value of jirm f according to household h
possible consumption vectors, respectively;
lS
The set of possible .two-period consumption Khf(p,y}2) = P1 YY + Pb(P~YJ).
allocations for the economy is The value of the firm in the market is the highest value that any
ff12 =X Xk2. household gives to it.
h
DEFINITION 16. The market capital value of jirm f is
ASSUMPTION 8. A.4.1-A.4.. 3 hold under D.6.14 w1'th x U (x)
2 2 "' h h ' K1(p,y} 2) = max K1(p,y}2).
xh, X, and xh replaced by xk , u12(xP), :Xk , 'Xk , and Xk , respec-
2 2
h
i
T
142 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 143

We will assume that, for each production plan for each firm, there In period 2, the household is responsible for its share of the bonds
is at least one household that values the plan at least as highly as the issued by firm j, a total of PJYJ According to its expectations,
firm itself does; we might rationalize this by noting that the firm's however, the firm will receive p~yJ. From (9), the household invests
manager is presumably himself the head of a household. only in firms whose production plans it values at least as highly as
AssuMPTION 9. The market capital value of a firm is at least equal anyone else, so that from (7), any firm for which dhf > O will be
to the maximum profits anticipated by the firm itself; in symbols, expected by household h to ha ve second-period receipts KJ. Hence,
the anticipated total receipts from firms in period 2 by household h
K(p,y} 2 ) :2:: PYr will be
From D.6.15 and D.6.16 d,(KJ -
f
PJYJ).

K1 = max[p 1 y}
n
+ pb(p~yJ)] = p 1 y} + Pb max(p~yJ),
n
From earlier remarks, then,
~ d (Kz
since p 1y} and Pb are independent of h. Let
-
xM 2-2
= PnXn + L, 2 2)
hf r - PrYr (11)
f

K7(yJ) = max(p~yJ). (7) Then


n
.xb = .xhb = (p~x~) + (K7 - PJYJ). (12)
If we recall that py1 = p 1y} + pb(p7yJ) then A.6.9 implies n " 1
Note that xb is a function of the yJ's, orto use an obvious notation,
K - PYr = Pb(KJ - PJYJ) :2:: O. (8)
of y 2 , the second-period production allocation. Note also that,
Let Jhf be the share of firm f held initially by household h; we from (8), the summation terms in (11) and (12) are non-negative.
assume that it sells its shares at the market price and buys others, Now we seek to define a "minimal" current cohsumption vector,
but only in those firms that it values at least as highly as any other Xn, that will satisfy the analog in this temporary equilibrium model
household. We assume the absence of short sales. Let dhf be its of A.4.2. For this purpose, let
share of firm f after the stock market has operated. Its net receipts
from sale less purchase of stocks (possibly negative, of course) are
given by From A.6.8 and A.4.2, we have assumed that xk s xk, x~ s x~.
Multiply through in the second inequality by p~ :2:: O, and use (11)
and the definitions of xhb; then xM s p~x~ s Xnb and so, from the
definition ofx" in (13), we have that
Also,
xh s Xn
dhf = O unless Khf = K 1 (9) The assumptions imply also that .X" > O implies X, < X,
It will be recalled that the current receipts of the firm are given by (i = 1, ... , n), since .X"= xki and x" 1 = xki for such i. We need to
(2) or (4); it is assumed that they are all distributed among its new show only that the same is true when i = b. Suppose xhb > O.
owners, so that household h receives From (11), there are two possibilities, xhb > p~x~, or xhb = p?,xr,.
In the first case, since x"b s pr,x~, as already seen, we certainly have
dhf(py).
f
xhb > xhb In the second case, the non-negative vectors, p~ and x~,
must have at least one positive component in common. Yet, since,
Hence, the budget constraint for period 1 reads
by A.6.8 and A.4.2, any positive component of xr, must also be a
p 1xk + Pb(x"b - xhb) s p 1x1 + d"(py1) + (Jhf - dhf)K1. (10) positive component of xr, - x~, it follows that
f f
p~(xf. - xr,) > o,
T
142 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 143

We will assume that, for each production plan for each firm, there In period 2, the household is responsible for its share of the bonds
is at least one household that values the plan at least as highly as the issued by firm j, a total of PJYJ According to its expectations,
firm itself does; we might rationalize this by noting that the firm's however, the firm will receive p~yJ. From (9), the household invests
manager is presumably himself the head of a household. only in firms whose production plans it values at least as highly as
AssuMPTION 9. The market capital value of a firm is at least equal anyone else, so that from (7), any firm for which dhf > O will be
to the maximum profits anticipated by the firm itself; in symbols, expected by household h to ha ve second-period receipts KJ. Hence,
the anticipated total receipts from firms in period 2 by household h
K(p,y} 2 ) :2:: PYr will be
From D.6.15 and D.6.16 d,(KJ -
f
PJYJ).

K1 = max[p 1 y}
n
+ pb(p~yJ)] = p 1 y} + Pb max(p~yJ),
n
From earlier remarks, then,
~ d (Kz
since p 1y} and Pb are independent of h. Let
-
xM 2-2
= PnXn + L, 2 2)
hf r - PrYr (11)
f

K7(yJ) = max(p~yJ). (7) Then


n
.xb = .xhb = (p~x~) + (K7 - PJYJ). (12)
If we recall that py1 = p 1y} + pb(p7yJ) then A.6.9 implies n " 1
Note that xb is a function of the yJ's, orto use an obvious notation,
K - PYr = Pb(KJ - PJYJ) :2:: O. (8)
of y 2 , the second-period production allocation. Note also that,
Let Jhf be the share of firm f held initially by household h; we from (8), the summation terms in (11) and (12) are non-negative.
assume that it sells its shares at the market price and buys others, Now we seek to define a "minimal" current cohsumption vector,
but only in those firms that it values at least as highly as any other Xn, that will satisfy the analog in this temporary equilibrium model
household. We assume the absence of short sales. Let dhf be its of A.4.2. For this purpose, let
share of firm f after the stock market has operated. Its net receipts
from sale less purchase of stocks (possibly negative, of course) are
given by From A.6.8 and A.4.2, we have assumed that xk s xk, x~ s x~.
Multiply through in the second inequality by p~ :2:: O, and use (11)
and the definitions of xhb; then xM s p~x~ s Xnb and so, from the
definition ofx" in (13), we have that
Also,
xh s Xn
dhf = O unless Khf = K 1 (9) The assumptions imply also that .X" > O implies X, < X,
It will be recalled that the current receipts of the firm are given by (i = 1, ... , n), since .X"= xki and x" 1 = xki for such i. We need to
(2) or (4); it is assumed that they are all distributed among its new show only that the same is true when i = b. Suppose xhb > O.
owners, so that household h receives From (11), there are two possibilities, xhb > p~x~, or xhb = p?,xr,.
In the first case, since x"b s pr,x~, as already seen, we certainly have
dhf(py).
f
xhb > xhb In the second case, the non-negative vectors, p~ and x~,
must have at least one positive component in common. Yet, since,
Hence, the budget constraint for period 1 reads
by A.6.8 and A.4.2, any positive component of xr, must also be a
p 1xk + Pb(x"b - xhb) s p 1x1 + d"(py1) + (Jhf - dhf)K1. (10) positive component of xr, - x~, it follows that
f f
p~(xf. - xr,) > o,
111:
1\ll!
li.: T
!'[:,:
! ::
144 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 145

or from the definition of xhb and the assumption that xhb = p~x~, From A.6.8 and A.4.1, it is easy to see that Uh is continuous. lt
Xhb > x11b. We conclude that A.6.8 and A.4.2 ensure is also true that it is semi-strictly quasi-concave. Suppose that
(14) U,(x~) > Uh(x~) xh = o:x~ + (1 - o:)xg O < o: < l.
Then define x~ 2 as the possible second-period consumption vector
As already remarked, the anticipated budget constraint for period
that maximizes u,; 2 (x/,x~) with respect to x~ subject to the constraint
2 is simply
p~x~ :::; x~b; define x~ 2 similarly. By definition of a maximizing
(15) va1ue,
so it is convenient to introduce the following definition: U,(x~)
= U/ (x~\x~ ), 2 2
U,(x~) = U/ 2 (x~\x~2 ).

DEFINITION 17. The set of current consumption vectors is Now define x~ = o:x~ + (1 - 2
o:)x~2 By semi-strict quasi-con-
2
cavity of U/ ,
X, = {x, x 11 b
1 :?: p~x~ for sorne x/ 2 E X/ 2}.
U/ 2 (x/,x~) > U/ 2 (x~\x~ 2 ).
The set of current consumption allocations is
But clearly p~x~ :::; xho By definition of a maximum,
PE= Xh x,. Uh(x,) ::::: U/ (x/,xD > U/ 2 (x~\x~2 )
2
= U"(xn,
which establishes the semi-strict quasi-concavity of U,.
From (15) and A.6.8, Xnb :?: o, and also xh E xh. From A.6.8,. lt is also very easy to establish that U, is locally non-satiated in
(14), and D.6.17, we can conclude x11 By a suitable choice of origin, we can ensure that U,(xh) = O.
A.4.1 and A.4.2 hold with the interpretations of x,, Uh(xh) is continuous, semi-strictly quasi-concave,
xh, and Xh in (11), (13), and D.6.17, respectively. (16) and admits no local satiation; Uh(xh) = O, U" is
The maximization of U/ 2 (x~,x~) subject to the budget constraints strictly increasing in xho for any x/. (17)
(10) and (15) can be thought of as occurring in two stages. For any These are, except for the last, the properties of U, used in proof of
given x, = (x/,x,b), we can maximize with respect to x~ subject to existence in Chapters 3-5. The last clause follows from D.6.18 and
(15); the maximum is now a function of x/ and of x,b, that is, of x,, the last part of A.6.8.
with respect to which it can be maximized subject to (10). The aim of the household, then, is to maximize u, subject to (10),
which can be written
DEFINITION 18. First-period derived utility is
(18)
Uh(x,) = max Uk 2 (x/,x~) subject to p~x~ :::; x, 0
where
We must assume that the maximum in D.6.18 actually exists. M" = pxh + 2 dhf(PYr) + 2 (a,r - dhf)K(p,y},yJ). (19)
The existence depends primarily on p~, the household's anticipations f f
of future prices. It will be assumed that the household is sufficiently Another way of writing (19) will be useful. First, rewrite it
realistic for this purpose; this is not an unreasonable assumption slightly; note that by our notation px, = p1 x/ + pbxh 0, then
since the household would know, from the fact that a maximum does substitute from (11).
not exist, that the prices could not be equilibrium prices.
M, = px" + 2 a"r(PYr) + 2 (ah! - d")(Kr - PYr)
AssUMPTION 10. For given x/, the function U/ 2 (xk,x~) assumes a l f f
maximum subject to the constraint p~x~ :::; xho for any x,b permitting
possible second-period consumption, that is, for any x 11 E Xh. = p xk +
1
f a, 1(py 1) + Polp~x~ + f ahf(K]- PJYJ)l (20)
111:
1\ll!
li.: T
!'[:,:
! ::
144 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 145

or from the definition of xhb and the assumption that xhb = p~x~, From A.6.8 and A.4.1, it is easy to see that Uh is continuous. lt
Xhb > x11b. We conclude that A.6.8 and A.4.2 ensure is also true that it is semi-strictly quasi-concave. Suppose that
(14) U,(x~) > Uh(x~) xh = o:x~ + (1 - o:)xg O < o: < l.
Then define x~ 2 as the possible second-period consumption vector
As already remarked, the anticipated budget constraint for period
that maximizes u,; 2 (x/,x~) with respect to x~ subject to the constraint
2 is simply
p~x~ :::; x~b; define x~ 2 similarly. By definition of a maximizing
(15) va1ue,
so it is convenient to introduce the following definition: U,(x~)
= U/ (x~\x~ ), 2 2
U,(x~) = U/ 2 (x~\x~2 ).

DEFINITION 17. The set of current consumption vectors is Now define x~ = o:x~ + (1 - 2
o:)x~2 By semi-strict quasi-con-
2
cavity of U/ ,
X, = {x, x 11 b
1 :?: p~x~ for sorne x/ 2 E X/ 2}.
U/ 2 (x/,x~) > U/ 2 (x~\x~ 2 ).
The set of current consumption allocations is
But clearly p~x~ :::; xho By definition of a maximum,
PE= Xh x,. Uh(x,) ::::: U/ (x/,xD > U/ 2 (x~\x~2 )
2
= U"(xn,
which establishes the semi-strict quasi-concavity of U,.
From (15) and A.6.8, Xnb :?: o, and also xh E xh. From A.6.8,. lt is also very easy to establish that U, is locally non-satiated in
(14), and D.6.17, we can conclude x11 By a suitable choice of origin, we can ensure that U,(xh) = O.
A.4.1 and A.4.2 hold with the interpretations of x,, Uh(xh) is continuous, semi-strictly quasi-concave,
xh, and Xh in (11), (13), and D.6.17, respectively. (16) and admits no local satiation; Uh(xh) = O, U" is
The maximization of U/ 2 (x~,x~) subject to the budget constraints strictly increasing in xho for any x/. (17)
(10) and (15) can be thought of as occurring in two stages. For any These are, except for the last, the properties of U, used in proof of
given x, = (x/,x,b), we can maximize with respect to x~ subject to existence in Chapters 3-5. The last clause follows from D.6.18 and
(15); the maximum is now a function of x/ and of x,b, that is, of x,, the last part of A.6.8.
with respect to which it can be maximized subject to (10). The aim of the household, then, is to maximize u, subject to (10),
which can be written
DEFINITION 18. First-period derived utility is
(18)
Uh(x,) = max Uk 2 (x/,x~) subject to p~x~ :::; x, 0
where
We must assume that the maximum in D.6.18 actually exists. M" = pxh + 2 dhf(PYr) + 2 (a,r - dhf)K(p,y},yJ). (19)
The existence depends primarily on p~, the household's anticipations f f
of future prices. It will be assumed that the household is sufficiently Another way of writing (19) will be useful. First, rewrite it
realistic for this purpose; this is not an unreasonable assumption slightly; note that by our notation px, = p1 x/ + pbxh 0, then
since the household would know, from the fact that a maximum does substitute from (11).
not exist, that the prices could not be equilibrium prices.
M, = px" + 2 a"r(PYr) + 2 (ah! - d")(Kr - PYr)
AssUMPTION 10. For given x/, the function U/ 2 (xk,x~) assumes a l f f
maximum subject to the constraint p~x~ :::; xho for any x,b permitting
possible second-period consumption, that is, for any x 11 E Xh. = p xk +
1
f a, 1(py 1) + Polp~x~ + f ahf(K]- PJYJ)l (20)
146 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 147

Recall that K1 - py1 = pb(KJ - PJYJ) by (8). One important The set of current al!ocations is
implication of (20) is that the actual final share allocation does not
affect the household budget constraints and, therefore, does not
"f//' = !!( X qlj.

affect the equilibrium. The reason is that, since shares in firms are The set of feasible current allocations is
assumed to be sold to those who value them most highly at a price
equal to that value, each potential buyer is, in fact, indifferent
between making the purchase and investing in bonds, and none of
his other behavior is affected by the choice. The set of quasi-feasible two-period allocations is
Por later reference we note that M 2: O and, further, M,. > O if
and only if M, > px, at any possible equilibrium, specifically at any
point at which firms are making non-negative planned profits.
if'12 = "'f"12 n { (x,y12) 1 f xfi ::::; f y} + xl, PJYJ 2: O, all f}
Then PYr 2: O, while pb(KJ - pyyJ) 2: O, for allf, by (8). Prom (20),
Since x (more specifically, xb) depends on y 2 , feasibility of current
M, 2: p xfi1
+ pbp~x~. allocations depends on y 2 , as the notation seeks to make clear.
Prom A.6.8 and A.4.2, we have, by the reasoning of Lemma 5.1, Any two-period production allocation, y 12 , such that (x, 1y 12) E
nfi/'12 for sorne x, certainly satisfies the conditions
M,. > O if and only if M, > p 1xfi + pbp~x~ = px,.. (21)
The last step follows from (13). y} + x1 2: o, p 2 yy 2: o allf,
f
We now have all the threads of the model in hand. Since equi-
librium occurs only on current markets, the only relevant prices are and so belongs to the bounded set @12 , by D.6.13 and (6). Then
those for current commodities and bonds. Basically, the model is xb, as a function of y 2 , is also bounded; hence, from the conditions
very similar to that of static competitive equilibrium; the an of the on the components of x,, the entire set, "V 12 , must be bounded. It
firm is to maximize py1 subject to y1 E Y1, according to (4) and is obviously closed and convex.
D.6.12, while the consumer aims to maximize a (first-period derived) # 12 is compact and convex.
utility function subject to a budget constraint (18). The feasibility
As before, we can define u-possible and u-feasible current alloca-
conditions for the current markets have the same form as before;
tions; the definitions remain unchanged, but it should be remarked
demand for first-period commodities and for bonds shall not exceed
that the set of u-feasible current allocations now depends upon y 2
supply, including the initial endowment of bonds as defined. How-
Let us formally define competitive and compensated temporary
ever, there are two complications: The budget constraint, using the
equilibrium.
definition of Mn in (20), is somewhat different than that of Chapter
4, and more especially, it contains variables, the yJ's, that are not DEFINITION 20. Competitive and compensated temporary equi-
in the standard system; by (12) one component of the social endow- librium are defined exactly as before (see D.5.1 and D.5.2) with the
ment vector, namely, xb, also depends on y 2 notation introduced in this section, except that the variables YJ must
We define severa! types of allocations; notice that in non e of them be consistent with intertemporal profit maximization and the budget
do the second-period consumption allocations enter, since they are equations now take the form
not relevant to equilibrium. We do need the household demand for px,. = Mn(p,y12)
bonds, however.
where the function M, is defined by (19) or (20).
DEFINITION 19. The set of two-period allocations, "'f" 12 , is
To prove existence of compensated equilibrium, the previous
"'f"12 = !![ X qtj12, mapping has to be modified only slightly. Por any given y 2 , there
146 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 147

Recall that K1 - py1 = pb(KJ - PJYJ) by (8). One important The set of current al!ocations is
implication of (20) is that the actual final share allocation does not
affect the household budget constraints and, therefore, does not
"f//' = !!( X qlj.

affect the equilibrium. The reason is that, since shares in firms are The set of feasible current allocations is
assumed to be sold to those who value them most highly at a price
equal to that value, each potential buyer is, in fact, indifferent
between making the purchase and investing in bonds, and none of
his other behavior is affected by the choice. The set of quasi-feasible two-period allocations is
Por later reference we note that M 2: O and, further, M,. > O if
and only if M, > px, at any possible equilibrium, specifically at any
point at which firms are making non-negative planned profits.
if'12 = "'f"12 n { (x,y12) 1 f xfi ::::; f y} + xl, PJYJ 2: O, all f}
Then PYr 2: O, while pb(KJ - pyyJ) 2: O, for allf, by (8). Prom (20),
Since x (more specifically, xb) depends on y 2 , feasibility of current
M, 2: p xfi1
+ pbp~x~. allocations depends on y 2 , as the notation seeks to make clear.
Prom A.6.8 and A.4.2, we have, by the reasoning of Lemma 5.1, Any two-period production allocation, y 12 , such that (x, 1y 12) E
nfi/'12 for sorne x, certainly satisfies the conditions
M,. > O if and only if M, > p 1xfi + pbp~x~ = px,.. (21)
The last step follows from (13). y} + x1 2: o, p 2 yy 2: o allf,
f
We now have all the threads of the model in hand. Since equi-
librium occurs only on current markets, the only relevant prices are and so belongs to the bounded set @12 , by D.6.13 and (6). Then
those for current commodities and bonds. Basically, the model is xb, as a function of y 2 , is also bounded; hence, from the conditions
very similar to that of static competitive equilibrium; the an of the on the components of x,, the entire set, "V 12 , must be bounded. It
firm is to maximize py1 subject to y1 E Y1, according to (4) and is obviously closed and convex.
D.6.12, while the consumer aims to maximize a (first-period derived) # 12 is compact and convex.
utility function subject to a budget constraint (18). The feasibility
As before, we can define u-possible and u-feasible current alloca-
conditions for the current markets have the same form as before;
tions; the definitions remain unchanged, but it should be remarked
demand for first-period commodities and for bonds shall not exceed
that the set of u-feasible current allocations now depends upon y 2
supply, including the initial endowment of bonds as defined. How-
Let us formally define competitive and compensated temporary
ever, there are two complications: The budget constraint, using the
equilibrium.
definition of Mn in (20), is somewhat different than that of Chapter
4, and more especially, it contains variables, the yJ's, that are not DEFINITION 20. Competitive and compensated temporary equi-
in the standard system; by (12) one component of the social endow- librium are defined exactly as before (see D.5.1 and D.5.2) with the
ment vector, namely, xb, also depends on y 2 notation introduced in this section, except that the variables YJ must
We define severa! types of allocations; notice that in non e of them be consistent with intertemporal profit maximization and the budget
do the second-period consumption allocations enter, since they are equations now take the form
not relevant to equilibrium. We do need the household demand for px,. = Mn(p,y12)
bonds, however.
where the function M, is defined by (19) or (20).
DEFINITION 19. The set of two-period allocations, "'f" 12 , is
To prove existence of compensated equilibrium, the previous
"'f"12 = !![ X qtj12, mapping has to be modified only slightly. Por any given y 2 , there
148 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 149

is a set of Pareto-efficient current uti1ity allocations, U(;/), that The correspondence


depends upon zl because it determines the initia1 endowment of
bonds. For fixed !J 2 , there is a function, u(v,zl), that maps the unit P[u(v,y 2),J 2] x V(p,m 12) x 'i? 12 [u(v,y 2),1 2]
simplex, SH, nto U(/); the function, u(v,y 2) is continuous in its then has a fixed point, which can be seen to be a compensated
variables. The correspondence to be used maps the set equilibrium by the arguments of Section 5.3.
Sn X SH X 11!' 12 , We ha ve assumed that all price expectations are totally inelastic;
this assumption can easily be relaxed.
into subsets of itself. Any e1ement of "lf" 12 defines, in particular, a
second-period production allocation, y 2 For fixed y 2 , there are AssuMPTION 11. For each household and firm, anticipated second-
correspondences, P(u,y 2) and 'i?(u,y 2), which are upper semi- period prices are a continuous function of current prices; that is,
continuous with respect to their arguments where u vares over the p~(p) and pJ(p) are continuous functions.
set U(y 2 ) and which define the sets of prices and feasible current
We now interpret those assumptions that referred to anticpated
allocations, respectively, which correspond to a given Pareto-
second-period prices, namely, A.6.7, A.6.9, and A.6.10, to hold for
efficient utility allocation. A current production allocation in
all values of p~ and pJ in the ranges of the anticipation functions,
1i'(u,y 2) is itself the image of a two-period production allocation
p~(p) and pJ(p).
under the mapping (1), Ytb = PJYJ Hence, define
The various functions and correspondences now depend explictly
1f'1 2 (u,y 2) = {(x,y12 ') 1 (x,y) E 'i?(u,y2) where on p, through PJ and p~; all the relevant continuity properties are
y 1 = y 1 ', Ytb = PJYJ', for allf}. easily seen to hold. Thus, U" depends on p through p~, Y1 and p
The notation ; 12 ' is designed to emphasize that yJ' need not equal through py.
the original yy; the latter entered only through its effect on xb. It is N ow redefine
easy to see that "fF 12 (u,y 2 ), is closed and convex and is upper semi-
continuous in its arguments. We show that "ff'12 = 1r12 n { (.v,y12) 1 f y} + x1 ~ f xk, pJ(p )YJ ~ O
1f'l2(u,y2) e 11J'l2. (22)
lf p E P(u,zl), it follows from the last clause of (17) that Pb > O.
for all,f, for some p}.
Then profit maximization imples that PJYJ ~ O, according to (5). Since pJ(p) is a continuous function over a compact set, the unit
Since feasibility already implies that simplex, its range is compact. It is then easy to demonstrate ftom
A.6.7 that "/il' 12 is compact. It is not necessarily convex, but its
: y} + x ~ : x~,
f
1

h convex hull, denoted by con 1il'12 , is both compact and convex (see
Lemma B.3).
(22) follows from D.6.19.
Both U" and Y1 depend upon p; also, the initial current endow-
If we now define
ment of bonds, xb, as defined by (12) also depends continuously on
sh(p,to12) = M,(p,y12) - pxh, p through its dependence on the anticipated prices, py and p~. Now
where to 12 = (x,y 12), we can define we can consider the set of current utility allocations that are Pareto
efficient conditional upon p as well as :l Let U(y 2 ,p) be this set;
V(p,y 12) = SH n{v v,
1 = o if sh(p,w 12) < 0}.
then, as before, there is a continuous function, u(v,!l,p), that maps
From (14) and (20), the unit simplex, Su, into U(y 2 ,p). We then define the corre-
spondences
always.
148 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 149

is a set of Pareto-efficient current uti1ity allocations, U(;/), that The correspondence


depends upon zl because it determines the initia1 endowment of
bonds. For fixed !J 2 , there is a function, u(v,zl), that maps the unit P[u(v,y 2),J 2] x V(p,m 12) x 'i? 12 [u(v,y 2),1 2]
simplex, SH, nto U(/); the function, u(v,y 2) is continuous in its then has a fixed point, which can be seen to be a compensated
variables. The correspondence to be used maps the set equilibrium by the arguments of Section 5.3.
Sn X SH X 11!' 12 , We ha ve assumed that all price expectations are totally inelastic;
this assumption can easily be relaxed.
into subsets of itself. Any e1ement of "lf" 12 defines, in particular, a
second-period production allocation, y 2 For fixed y 2 , there are AssuMPTION 11. For each household and firm, anticipated second-
correspondences, P(u,y 2) and 'i?(u,y 2), which are upper semi- period prices are a continuous function of current prices; that is,
continuous with respect to their arguments where u vares over the p~(p) and pJ(p) are continuous functions.
set U(y 2 ) and which define the sets of prices and feasible current
We now interpret those assumptions that referred to anticpated
allocations, respectively, which correspond to a given Pareto-
second-period prices, namely, A.6.7, A.6.9, and A.6.10, to hold for
efficient utility allocation. A current production allocation in
all values of p~ and pJ in the ranges of the anticipation functions,
1i'(u,y 2) is itself the image of a two-period production allocation
p~(p) and pJ(p).
under the mapping (1), Ytb = PJYJ Hence, define
The various functions and correspondences now depend explictly
1f'1 2 (u,y 2) = {(x,y12 ') 1 (x,y) E 'i?(u,y2) where on p, through PJ and p~; all the relevant continuity properties are
y 1 = y 1 ', Ytb = PJYJ', for allf}. easily seen to hold. Thus, U" depends on p through p~, Y1 and p
The notation ; 12 ' is designed to emphasize that yJ' need not equal through py.
the original yy; the latter entered only through its effect on xb. It is N ow redefine
easy to see that "fF 12 (u,y 2 ), is closed and convex and is upper semi-
continuous in its arguments. We show that "ff'12 = 1r12 n { (.v,y12) 1 f y} + x1 ~ f xk, pJ(p )YJ ~ O
1f'l2(u,y2) e 11J'l2. (22)
lf p E P(u,zl), it follows from the last clause of (17) that Pb > O.
for all,f, for some p}.
Then profit maximization imples that PJYJ ~ O, according to (5). Since pJ(p) is a continuous function over a compact set, the unit
Since feasibility already implies that simplex, its range is compact. It is then easy to demonstrate ftom
A.6.7 that "/il' 12 is compact. It is not necessarily convex, but its
: y} + x ~ : x~,
f
1

h convex hull, denoted by con 1il'12 , is both compact and convex (see
Lemma B.3).
(22) follows from D.6.19.
Both U" and Y1 depend upon p; also, the initial current endow-
If we now define
ment of bonds, xb, as defined by (12) also depends continuously on
sh(p,to12) = M,(p,y12) - pxh, p through its dependence on the anticipated prices, py and p~. Now
where to 12 = (x,y 12), we can define we can consider the set of current utility allocations that are Pareto
efficient conditional upon p as well as :l Let U(y 2 ,p) be this set;
V(p,y 12) = SH n{v v,
1 = o if sh(p,w 12) < 0}.
then, as before, there is a continuous function, u(v,!l,p), that maps
From (14) and (20), the unit simplex, Su, into U(y 2 ,p). We then define the corre-
spondences
always.
150 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 151

in obvious analogy to the inelastic case. As in (22), as current prices change, different households value the firm most
highly, and so PJ might change discontinuously as p changes. '"_fhis
if"12(u,y2,p) e "/f'12 e con "/f'12.
could be avoided if we assumed there is, in fact, a continuum of
Then the correspondence households filling up a whole area in p~-space for any given p; then
P[u(v,y2,p),z2,p] x V(p,z;12) x if"l2[u(v,y2,p),y2,p] PJ as defined would vary continuously with p. Such a theory
requires advanced methods for analysis.
maps the set Sn x Su x con "'P12 'into subsets of itself and possesses
a fixed point that, again, is a compensated equilibrium. Remark 2. The model here has assumed that there are no debts
Finally, to show that the compensated equilibrium is a competitive in the initial period, though, in general, there will be debts at the
equilibrium, we need a suitable definition of resource relatedness. beginning of the next period. The discussion of Section 5.5 is
applicable here; if expectations are falsified, then it can happen that
DEFINITION 21. Household h' is resource related to household h" for no equilibrium in the next period will exist without bankruptcy,
given xb and p if D.5.4 holds when y1 is computed as of a fixed PJ because the distribution of debt that is the result of the present ,
determined by p, uh is computed as of a fixed p~ determined by p, period's choices and, therefore, the initial distribution for the next
and xb is taken as given, and when the impact of an alternative period is inappropriate.
il
allocation on these parameters is ignored. !! 1

Household h' is resource related to household h" if it is so resource Remark 3. Of course, we are neglecting uncertainty. This is a
related for any given xb and p. more serious problem than we might think, for in the presence of 1
Household h' is indirectly resource related to household h" if uncertainty it is unreasonable to assume that bonds of different
D.5.5 holds. firms and households are perfect substitutes. If we are not willing
to assume that all individuals have the same probability distributions
THEOREM 3. Competitive temporary equi1ibrium exists if A.6.6-
of prices, then it is reasonable to suppose that any firm or household
A.6.11 hold and if every household is indirectly resource related to
has more information about matters that concern it most, and there-
every other.
fore, a household will have different subjective probability distri-
Remark l. The theory of the firm u sed he re is somewhere between butions for the bonds of different firms. Then, if a given firm is the
.1' two currently popular views. It is "managerial" in that only the only supplier of a commodity (its bonds) for which there are no
1', expectations of managers en ter into the firm's decisions; stock- perfect substitutes, the capital markets cannot be assumed perfect.
!11
,1 holders appear only as passive investors. In contradistinction to "'' 1'
!:

~ 1' ! theories such as those of Marris [1964] and Williamson [1964], Remark 4. The restriction to two periods prevents us from
examining speculation in the market for shares based on other
;~ '
however, we do not ascribe to managers any motives other than 11

profit maximization according to their expectations. A more households' expectations, a matter to which Keynes [1936, pp. 154- i.'
general model would introduce a utility function for managers that 159] dramatically called attention. In a three-or-more-period '1i.:
l,

depends in some more complicated way on the firm's production model, a household may buy shares in a firm because it has expecta- 1~i
!:,

vector and current and anticipated profits; we have not investigated tions that in the second period others will have expectations that will l'i
make it profitab1e to sell the shares then. i,i
such a model here.
l:
An alternative theory has the firm maximizing the current market 'l
value of its stock; that is, the firm chooses y} 2 to maximize K 1 This
::
1
4. Equilibrium under Monopolistic Competition :,
1

could be included in the present model by identifying py with p~ for


that household for which Khf is a maximum, where, for each h, Kh 1 We now return to a static formulation, assuming this time that :i
1

has itself been defined by maximizing over Y} 2 at given p and p~. there are some firms in the economy that are capable of exercising i'l
monopolistic or monopsonistic power over certain markets. We :
The only difficulty with this theory in the present framework is that

il
150 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 151

in obvious analogy to the inelastic case. As in (22), as current prices change, different households value the firm most
highly, and so PJ might change discontinuously as p changes. '"_fhis
if"12(u,y2,p) e "/f'12 e con "/f'12.
could be avoided if we assumed there is, in fact, a continuum of
Then the correspondence households filling up a whole area in p~-space for any given p; then
P[u(v,y2,p),z2,p] x V(p,z;12) x if"l2[u(v,y2,p),y2,p] PJ as defined would vary continuously with p. Such a theory
requires advanced methods for analysis.
maps the set Sn x Su x con "'P12 'into subsets of itself and possesses
a fixed point that, again, is a compensated equilibrium. Remark 2. The model here has assumed that there are no debts
Finally, to show that the compensated equilibrium is a competitive in the initial period, though, in general, there will be debts at the
equilibrium, we need a suitable definition of resource relatedness. beginning of the next period. The discussion of Section 5.5 is
applicable here; if expectations are falsified, then it can happen that
DEFINITION 21. Household h' is resource related to household h" for no equilibrium in the next period will exist without bankruptcy,
given xb and p if D.5.4 holds when y1 is computed as of a fixed PJ because the distribution of debt that is the result of the present ,
determined by p, uh is computed as of a fixed p~ determined by p, period's choices and, therefore, the initial distribution for the next
and xb is taken as given, and when the impact of an alternative period is inappropriate.
il
allocation on these parameters is ignored. !! 1

Household h' is resource related to household h" if it is so resource Remark 3. Of course, we are neglecting uncertainty. This is a
related for any given xb and p. more serious problem than we might think, for in the presence of 1
Household h' is indirectly resource related to household h" if uncertainty it is unreasonable to assume that bonds of different
D.5.5 holds. firms and households are perfect substitutes. If we are not willing
to assume that all individuals have the same probability distributions
THEOREM 3. Competitive temporary equi1ibrium exists if A.6.6-
of prices, then it is reasonable to suppose that any firm or household
A.6.11 hold and if every household is indirectly resource related to
has more information about matters that concern it most, and there-
every other.
fore, a household will have different subjective probability distri-
Remark l. The theory of the firm u sed he re is somewhere between butions for the bonds of different firms. Then, if a given firm is the
.1' two currently popular views. It is "managerial" in that only the only supplier of a commodity (its bonds) for which there are no
1', expectations of managers en ter into the firm's decisions; stock- perfect substitutes, the capital markets cannot be assumed perfect.
!11
,1 holders appear only as passive investors. In contradistinction to "'' 1'
!:

~ 1' ! theories such as those of Marris [1964] and Williamson [1964], Remark 4. The restriction to two periods prevents us from
examining speculation in the market for shares based on other
;~ '
however, we do not ascribe to managers any motives other than 11

profit maximization according to their expectations. A more households' expectations, a matter to which Keynes [1936, pp. 154- i.'
general model would introduce a utility function for managers that 159] dramatically called attention. In a three-or-more-period '1i.:
l,

depends in some more complicated way on the firm's production model, a household may buy shares in a firm because it has expecta- 1~i
!:,

vector and current and anticipated profits; we have not investigated tions that in the second period others will have expectations that will l'i
make it profitab1e to sell the shares then. i,i
such a model here.
l:
An alternative theory has the firm maximizing the current market 'l
value of its stock; that is, the firm chooses y} 2 to maximize K 1 This
::
1
4. Equilibrium under Monopolistic Competition :,
1

could be included in the present model by identifying py with p~ for


that household for which Khf is a maximum, where, for each h, Kh 1 We now return to a static formulation, assuming this time that :i
1

has itself been defined by maximizing over Y} 2 at given p and p~. there are some firms in the economy that are capable of exercising i'l
monopolistic or monopsonistic power over certain markets. We :
The only difficulty with this theory in the present framework is that

il
152 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 153
assume, however, the absence of interaction among the monopolistic production possibility set for the competitive sector as a whole
firms. Each firm takes the current prices of products not under its is
control as given and perceives a demand (or supply) function that
may or may not be correct. The perception is made on the basis of Yc = Ycr
f
observed prices and allocation. It is assumed that, at least at
equilibrium, the demand functions are correct at the observed point, and similarly,
though not necessarily elsewhere; in other words, for the quantities
actually produced, the firm correctly perceives the prices that will
clear the markets. It is not necessarily assumed, however, that the
monopolistic firms correctly perceive the elasticities of demand at The e1ements of these sets are represented by y with the appropriate 1
the equilibrium point. subscripts. A monopolized commodity, of course, will not be the 1

The production possibility sets for monopolistic firms need not be i


output of any vector in Y0 , but it may be an input. Also, we use :':
convex; indeed, the non-convexity (in particular, the increasing the term "monopolized" to include "monopsonized." :1

returns to scale) is presumably one reason for the existence of


monopoly. f{owever, it is assumed that the prices charged by ASSUMPTION 12. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold for the sets Y 01 li'
Ir
monopolistic firms are continuous functions of other prices and AssuMPTION 13. O E YMg and YMg is closed, for each g. r,,
other production and consumption decisions. lf we assume, in the 1'
:i
usual way, that monopolists are maximizing profits according to We now need an assumption that extends A.3.4 (impossibility of
their perceived demand curves, then what we are saying is that the getting something for nothing) to .include the monopolistic firms;
perceived marginal revenue curves fall more sharply than marginal since the production possibility sets of the latter need not be convex,
cost curves. we will imagine the assumption to hold even if these sets are replaced
Though we will weaken the convexity assumptions on the produc- by their convex hulls (see Section B.4). In other words, the in-
tion possibility sets of the monopolists, we still need to make sorne creasing returns are sufficiently limited so that if we were to expand
hypotheses that will ensure that the set of feasible production the production possibility sets so as to ensure convexity, we would
allocations satisfies sorne reasonable conditions, specifically that it is not violate the laws of conservation. The extension is somewhat
bounded if resources are bounded and that it is a set that does not less drastic than A.6.5 above.
break up into severa! parts or have holes in its middle. The second
AssuMPTION 14. If con YMg is the convex hull of YMu and
provision can be expressed more precisely by requiring that the sets
of those production possibility vectors for the monopolistic sector Ycr + YMg :2': 0,
that are compatible with feasibility for the entire production sector f g

can be expressed as the image of a compact convex set under a where y cr E ycr and y Mg E con YMg, then
continuous mapping.
The assumptions on the competitive sector will remain those made Ycr =O allf,
befo re.
and
There are two kinds of firms, competitive and monopolistic. A
subscript C will indicate a vector of al! commodities that is possible YMg =O all g.
for a competitive firm or for the competitive sector as a whole;
similarly a subscript M denotes a commodity vector possible for a From A.6.12-A.6.14, it follows by the same proof as that of
monopolistic firm or sector. Thus, Y01 is the production possibility T.3.2 that
set for competitive firm f, YMg for monopolistic firm g. The (<??10 x con <??/M) n{0fc.,t~M) Ye 1 + YM + x : : : O} is compact. (23)

--1
152 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 153
assume, however, the absence of interaction among the monopolistic production possibility set for the competitive sector as a whole
firms. Each firm takes the current prices of products not under its is
control as given and perceives a demand (or supply) function that
may or may not be correct. The perception is made on the basis of Yc = Ycr
f
observed prices and allocation. It is assumed that, at least at
equilibrium, the demand functions are correct at the observed point, and similarly,
though not necessarily elsewhere; in other words, for the quantities
actually produced, the firm correctly perceives the prices that will
clear the markets. It is not necessarily assumed, however, that the
monopolistic firms correctly perceive the elasticities of demand at The e1ements of these sets are represented by y with the appropriate 1
the equilibrium point. subscripts. A monopolized commodity, of course, will not be the 1

The production possibility sets for monopolistic firms need not be i


output of any vector in Y0 , but it may be an input. Also, we use :':
convex; indeed, the non-convexity (in particular, the increasing the term "monopolized" to include "monopsonized." :1

returns to scale) is presumably one reason for the existence of


monopoly. f{owever, it is assumed that the prices charged by ASSUMPTION 12. A.3.1-A.3.3 hold for the sets Y 01 li'
Ir
monopolistic firms are continuous functions of other prices and AssuMPTION 13. O E YMg and YMg is closed, for each g. r,,
other production and consumption decisions. lf we assume, in the 1'
:i
usual way, that monopolists are maximizing profits according to We now need an assumption that extends A.3.4 (impossibility of
their perceived demand curves, then what we are saying is that the getting something for nothing) to .include the monopolistic firms;
perceived marginal revenue curves fall more sharply than marginal since the production possibility sets of the latter need not be convex,
cost curves. we will imagine the assumption to hold even if these sets are replaced
Though we will weaken the convexity assumptions on the produc- by their convex hulls (see Section B.4). In other words, the in-
tion possibility sets of the monopolists, we still need to make sorne creasing returns are sufficiently limited so that if we were to expand
hypotheses that will ensure that the set of feasible production the production possibility sets so as to ensure convexity, we would
allocations satisfies sorne reasonable conditions, specifically that it is not violate the laws of conservation. The extension is somewhat
bounded if resources are bounded and that it is a set that does not less drastic than A.6.5 above.
break up into severa! parts or have holes in its middle. The second
AssuMPTION 14. If con YMg is the convex hull of YMu and
provision can be expressed more precisely by requiring that the sets
of those production possibility vectors for the monopolistic sector Ycr + YMg :2': 0,
that are compatible with feasibility for the entire production sector f g

can be expressed as the image of a compact convex set under a where y cr E ycr and y Mg E con YMg, then
continuous mapping.
The assumptions on the competitive sector will remain those made Ycr =O allf,
befo re.
and
There are two kinds of firms, competitive and monopolistic. A
subscript C will indicate a vector of al! commodities that is possible YMg =O all g.
for a competitive firm or for the competitive sector as a whole;
similarly a subscript M denotes a commodity vector possible for a From A.6.12-A.6.14, it follows by the same proof as that of
monopolistic firm or sector. Thus, Y01 is the production possibility T.3.2 that
set for competitive firm f, YMg for monopolistic firm g. The (<??10 x con <??/M) n{0fc.,t~M) Ye 1 + YM + x : : : O} is compact. (23)

--1
154 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 155

Here we have used the obvious extensions of earlier notation discussion); let the corresponding allocation in the competitive
'
sector be (x\$18), so that the competitive components of
,'1
1'
:x~
h
- L: y8, - x
f
Yc = 2;Ycr, YM = 2;YMg are all negative, while the monopolistic components are all O. If the
'1'
'1
f g l
production possibility set for the monopolistic sector admits free
Also, we introduce the following definitions; the superscript v implies disposal, this vector certainly belongs to that set, since we can
that the convex hull of CflJM, con CflJM, has been substituted for CflJM in certainly assume it contains O. Further, since compettive goods in
the corresponding definition. the aggregate are productive in the monopolistic sector, we can
increase all components, monopolistic and competitive alike, and
1f/' = f!l' X f/l(c X CflJM,
still ha ve a possible vector for the monopolistic sector; the cor-
"ff/'" = f!l' x CflJ0 x con CflJM,
responding allocation will be taken to be (x 0 ,$f8.$f~), and it is cer-
ii?' = 1f/' n {(x,yc,yM) 1 X S Ye + YM + x}, tainly feasible. From the construction, it is reasonable to hold that
if'v = "ff/'"n{(x,yc,yM) 1 X S Yc + YM + x}, the same is true for all neighboring points. Now consider for each
ii?'~ is the projection of if'v on f!l' x CflJ0 , g any other point of Y MY say y Mg The vector y~g contains its share
qf) M is the projection of ii?' on CflJM. of an input of competitive goods; as the vector m oves along the line
segment to YM 9 , it may be assumed that the failures of convexity due
From (23), it follows immediately that ii?' and nj/'v are compact
to indivisibilities are overcome by inputs of competitive goods. The
(we are assuming, as will be explained shortly, that all elements of
point is illustrated by Figure 6.1, where the horizontal axis gives the
f!l' are non-negative). Then,
input, derived from the competitive sector, while the vertical axis
if'& and qf) M are compact. (24) gives the output. Let
W e now make a basic assumption on the structure of the monopo- Zc = L: Xn -
lt
X- L: Ycr
f
listic production possibility sets. It amounts to saying that the
extent of increasing returns there is not too great relative to the
resources that the competitive sector would be capable of supplying.
In D.B.4, we introduce the definition that a point x 1 is visible from
another point x 2 in a set C if the line segment joining the two points
is entirely contained in C.
AssuMPTION 15. There exist allocations x 0 E f!l' and y& E CflJ0 and a
neighborhood in CflJ M such that, for all y~ in that neighborhood,
(x 0 ,y&,y~) is feasible and every point of Y Mg is visible from y& 9

In terms of D.B.6, we assume that cpM is strictly star shapcd.


This assumption s admittedly not very transparent. However, first
note that if Y Mg is convex, then A.6.15 is automatically satisfied if
LEGEND:
y~ 9 can be chosen to be a relative interior point of Y Mg for which
(x 0 ,yS,y~) is feasible, for by definition, a convex set is one in which IJiyM "'
1

every point is visible from any other. More generally, suppose that . . WM (= common part of YM and Zc)
the competitive sector (includi'ng households) is capable of achieving
, a net supply of all competitive commodities (see A.3.5 and following Figure 6-1
154 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 155

Here we have used the obvious extensions of earlier notation discussion); let the corresponding allocation in the competitive
'
sector be (x\$18), so that the competitive components of
,'1
1'
:x~
h
- L: y8, - x
f
Yc = 2;Ycr, YM = 2;YMg are all negative, while the monopolistic components are all O. If the
'1'
'1
f g l
production possibility set for the monopolistic sector admits free
Also, we introduce the following definitions; the superscript v implies disposal, this vector certainly belongs to that set, since we can
that the convex hull of CflJM, con CflJM, has been substituted for CflJM in certainly assume it contains O. Further, since compettive goods in
the corresponding definition. the aggregate are productive in the monopolistic sector, we can
increase all components, monopolistic and competitive alike, and
1f/' = f!l' X f/l(c X CflJM,
still ha ve a possible vector for the monopolistic sector; the cor-
"ff/'" = f!l' x CflJ0 x con CflJM,
responding allocation will be taken to be (x 0 ,$f8.$f~), and it is cer-
ii?' = 1f/' n {(x,yc,yM) 1 X S Ye + YM + x}, tainly feasible. From the construction, it is reasonable to hold that
if'v = "ff/'"n{(x,yc,yM) 1 X S Yc + YM + x}, the same is true for all neighboring points. Now consider for each
ii?'~ is the projection of if'v on f!l' x CflJ0 , g any other point of Y MY say y Mg The vector y~g contains its share
qf) M is the projection of ii?' on CflJM. of an input of competitive goods; as the vector m oves along the line
segment to YM 9 , it may be assumed that the failures of convexity due
From (23), it follows immediately that ii?' and nj/'v are compact
to indivisibilities are overcome by inputs of competitive goods. The
(we are assuming, as will be explained shortly, that all elements of
point is illustrated by Figure 6.1, where the horizontal axis gives the
f!l' are non-negative). Then,
input, derived from the competitive sector, while the vertical axis
if'& and qf) M are compact. (24) gives the output. Let
W e now make a basic assumption on the structure of the monopo- Zc = L: Xn -
lt
X- L: Ycr
f
listic production possibility sets. It amounts to saying that the
extent of increasing returns there is not too great relative to the
resources that the competitive sector would be capable of supplying.
In D.B.4, we introduce the definition that a point x 1 is visible from
another point x 2 in a set C if the line segment joining the two points
is entirely contained in C.
AssuMPTION 15. There exist allocations x 0 E f!l' and y& E CflJ0 and a
neighborhood in CflJ M such that, for all y~ in that neighborhood,
(x 0 ,y&,y~) is feasible and every point of Y Mg is visible from y& 9

In terms of D.B.6, we assume that cpM is strictly star shapcd.


This assumption s admittedly not very transparent. However, first
note that if Y Mg is convex, then A.6.15 is automatically satisfied if
LEGEND:
y~ 9 can be chosen to be a relative interior point of Y Mg for which
(x 0 ,yS,y~) is feasible, for by definition, a convex set is one in which IJiyM "'
1

every point is visible from any other. More generally, suppose that . . WM (= common part of YM and Zc)
the competitive sector (includi'ng households) is capable of achieving
, a net supply of all competitive commodities (see A.3.5 and following Figure 6-1
~
lj:
1

1
;

156 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 157

Let y] belong to the neighborhood specified in A.6.15..: Then, by


definition, y] E qf} M Let J/M be any other element of !f!l M and y~ a
convex combination of the two. Since YMg is visible from y]g in
YMg, J/M is visible from y]. Because the feasibility cond~tion is
linear and the sets fl', 1[!/0 are convex, it is immediate to venfy that
y~ E qf} M Hence, every point of qf} M is visible from every point in a
neighborhood. We can now apply T.B.3 to assert
There exists a continuous function with a unique
inverse that maps & M into a compact convex setA. (25)
LEGEND:
We now turn to the behavior of the monopolist. At any given
~a~~ . . Zc moment, the monopolists observe current prices and the current
allocation and (individually) dcide on their prices. We do not here
necessarily derive their behavior from any hypothesis of profit-or
Figure 6-2 utility-maximization, but 'we do assume that, whatever criterion
they employ, their choices of prices and quantities will de?end
continuously on observations ofthe rest ofthe market. Under ddfer-
be any feasible excess-demand vector of the competitive sector, and ent alternative perceptions of demand conditions, the prices and
let Z 0 be the set of all such z0 In effect, - z0 is the vector of quantities chosen will differ, but there will be a functional rel.ation
amounts made available to the monopolistic sector by the com- on which all the price-quantity choices willlie for given behavwr of
petitive sector; in general, z0 may ha ve sorne positive components the rest of the economy. In equilibrium, the actual behavior of the
among the monopolized goods and these correspond to demands by monopolist will be jointly determined by the posited relation an~ ~he
the competitive sector on the monopolistic sector. In particular, in true demand relation derived from .the behavior of the competitive
Figure 6-1, let zb have a positive competitive component anda zero
sector.
monopolistic component. Then any possible production for the We shall illustrate the assumptions in the conventional parta!
monopolistic sector is visible from zg, chosen slightly larger than equilibrium analysis of monopoly. The monopol.ist bel~eves that
za in each component, and indeed, from any point in its neighbor- the demand curve is given by p = d(y,e), where e 1s a sh1ft param-
hood. On the other hand, if the competitive sector can produce eter. Let R'(y,e) be the corresponding perceived marginal revenue
only zg with zero demand on the monopolistic sector, then there are curve for any e and C'(y) the monopolist's marginal cost curve.
points of YMg not visible from zg or any nearby point. Then, for any given e, output and price are determined as the solu-
In Figure 6-2, we illustrate what the consequences might be of a tions of the pair of equations p = d(y,e), C'(y) = R'(y,e). If we
failure of A.6. 15. Suppose that the monopolistic commodity can be eliminate e in these two relations, we have a single relation between
used by the competitive sector to increase its production. Then the p and y, say, y = f(p). This relation might be termed the mono~o
set Z 0 might take the indicated form. The darkest area is & M list's supply curve. It is a relation between his price and his quantlty
which now consists of two disjoint areas. It is certainly conceivable that holds regardless of the demand curves he perceives. The
that no equilibrium will exist; from an initial allocation correspond- actual equilibrium of the economy will be determined b~ this rela-
ing to one area, the monopolist might always be motivated to choose tion together with the true demand curve, say, p = d(y). The
a price that moves demand into the other area. At the very least, function d(y) need not coincide with the function d(y,e), for any
the weak assumptions we will make about the monopolist's behavior e, if the monopolist's perceived family of demand curves ~oes
will not suffice to exclude this possibility.
not include the true one. If p*, y* satisfy the two equatwns
~
lj:
1

1
;

156 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 157

Let y] belong to the neighborhood specified in A.6.15..: Then, by


definition, y] E qf} M Let J/M be any other element of !f!l M and y~ a
convex combination of the two. Since YMg is visible from y]g in
YMg, J/M is visible from y]. Because the feasibility cond~tion is
linear and the sets fl', 1[!/0 are convex, it is immediate to venfy that
y~ E qf} M Hence, every point of qf} M is visible from every point in a
neighborhood. We can now apply T.B.3 to assert
There exists a continuous function with a unique
inverse that maps & M into a compact convex setA. (25)
LEGEND:
We now turn to the behavior of the monopolist. At any given
~a~~ . . Zc moment, the monopolists observe current prices and the current
allocation and (individually) dcide on their prices. We do not here
necessarily derive their behavior from any hypothesis of profit-or
Figure 6-2 utility-maximization, but 'we do assume that, whatever criterion
they employ, their choices of prices and quantities will de?end
continuously on observations ofthe rest ofthe market. Under ddfer-
be any feasible excess-demand vector of the competitive sector, and ent alternative perceptions of demand conditions, the prices and
let Z 0 be the set of all such z0 In effect, - z0 is the vector of quantities chosen will differ, but there will be a functional rel.ation
amounts made available to the monopolistic sector by the com- on which all the price-quantity choices willlie for given behavwr of
petitive sector; in general, z0 may ha ve sorne positive components the rest of the economy. In equilibrium, the actual behavior of the
among the monopolized goods and these correspond to demands by monopolist will be jointly determined by the posited relation an~ ~he
the competitive sector on the monopolistic sector. In particular, in true demand relation derived from .the behavior of the competitive
Figure 6-1, let zb have a positive competitive component anda zero
sector.
monopolistic component. Then any possible production for the We shall illustrate the assumptions in the conventional parta!
monopolistic sector is visible from zg, chosen slightly larger than equilibrium analysis of monopoly. The monopol.ist bel~eves that
za in each component, and indeed, from any point in its neighbor- the demand curve is given by p = d(y,e), where e 1s a sh1ft param-
hood. On the other hand, if the competitive sector can produce eter. Let R'(y,e) be the corresponding perceived marginal revenue
only zg with zero demand on the monopolistic sector, then there are curve for any e and C'(y) the monopolist's marginal cost curve.
points of YMg not visible from zg or any nearby point. Then, for any given e, output and price are determined as the solu-
In Figure 6-2, we illustrate what the consequences might be of a tions of the pair of equations p = d(y,e), C'(y) = R'(y,e). If we
failure of A.6. 15. Suppose that the monopolistic commodity can be eliminate e in these two relations, we have a single relation between
used by the competitive sector to increase its production. Then the p and y, say, y = f(p). This relation might be termed the mono~o
set Z 0 might take the indicated form. The darkest area is & M list's supply curve. It is a relation between his price and his quantlty
which now consists of two disjoint areas. It is certainly conceivable that holds regardless of the demand curves he perceives. The
that no equilibrium will exist; from an initial allocation correspond- actual equilibrium of the economy will be determined b~ this rela-
ing to one area, the monopolist might always be motivated to choose tion together with the true demand curve, say, p = d(y). The
a price that moves demand into the other area. At the very least, function d(y) need not coincide with the function d(y,e), for any
the weak assumptions we will make about the monopolist's behavior e, if the monopolist's perceived family of demand curves ~oes
will not suffice to exclude this possibility.
not include the true one. If p*, y* satisfy the two equatwns
158 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1

GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 159

y* = f(p*) and p* = d(y*), then the monopolist will perceive the We now repeat the assumptions on consumer behavior discussed
demand curve as that determined by the value of the shift param- in Chapter 4 with a rather technical strengthening of A.4.2.
eter 8* determined by the relation p* == d(y*, 8*). He must perceive
the correct actual demand, though not necessarily the true demand AssuMPTION 17. (a) Assumptions A.4.1, A.4.3, and A.4.4 hold.
function. (b) There exist possible consumption vectors x~ E X", k = 1, 2,
Thus, we are assuming a stable relation between the price and not indifferent to each other, such that
quantity decisions of the monopolists, given the observations on for k= 1, 2.
prices and quantities in the rest of the economy. If we regard the
From (b), we can assume without Ioss of generality that
monopolist's output as the dependent variable, we can think of it
also as a function of all prices and quantities; this is not to imply x~ >-"xk all h.
that he takes his price as given, but rather that, given all other prices The utility function, U"(x"), can be so chosen that U"(xk) = O,
U"(x~) = 2, aii h. Then any household can clearly achieve a
and all other quantities, his output decision is functionally related
to his price decision. Given the monopolized outputs, the choice of utility of more than 1 regardless of prices. Without loss of general-
competitive inputs to produce them is determined on a cost-mini- ity, then, we restrict ourselves, where appropriate, to allocations
mizing basis. Hence, the total production decision of the monopoly that achieve a utility of 1 at least for each individual. Define
is a function of all prices and quantities. Though we are not 11/'(e) = .%'(e) x I!JJ e x I!JJ M
assuming profit maximization, it is necessary in a private-enterprise
economy to insist on viability; no monopoly can be making a if'(e) = 11/'(e) n {(x,lf'clf'M)Ix S Yc + YM + x},
1

: '1
negative profit. W111 (e) is the projection ofif'(e) on I!JJM.
!.
AssuMPTION 16. For each monopolistic firm, g, the production As before, e is the vector all of whose components are 1; in this case,
vector is a continuous function, yMg(p,w), of prices and allocations its dimensionality is equal to H, the number of households.
such that PYMg(p,w) :2:: O for all p and w. The reasoning Ieading to (25) can be repeated with I!JJ M replaced by
I!JJ M(e).
We now turn to the competitive sector, which determines the
demand for monopolized goods. Sorne further notation is needed. There exists a continuous function, a(lf'M), with a
For any .fixed monopolistic production allocation, lfM there is a unique inverse, that maps 1!JJ M( e) into a compact convex
range _of feasible allocations for the competitive sectors, provided ~A. 9n
lfM E I!JJ M' namely, those allocations w 0 = (x,1fc) for which For fixed 1/M E <2?1 M(e), we can consider the range of feasible utility
2 xh S 2 Ycr + X + 2 YMu
h f g
Ycr E Ycr, xh E xh.
vectors in the competitive sector, that is, the set of vectors u for
which "if'(u,lf'M) is non-null. By definition of <2?1 M(e), the vector e
is always feasible, so there are always sorne non-negative utility
The productive activity of the monopolistic sector can be treated
vectors. We can consider then the range of non-negative Pareto-
as a modification of the initial endowment from the viewpoint of the
competitive sector. The set of allocations (oc satisfying these efficient utility aiiocations, U(I!JJ 111). For each u E U(I!JJ M), the set of
Pareto-efficient competitive allocations is "if' u(u,!fM) By A.6.17,
conditions will be denoted by if' c(lf'M).
the reasoning leading to T.4.4, the basic theorem of welfare econom-
As in Section 4.4, especially D. 4.6-11, we shall be interested in
ics, is still valid here, so aiiocations in this set are al! supported by
feasible allocations in the competitive sect~r that yield each house-
hold at Ieast a prescribed utility leve!. For any vector of utilities, a set of price vectors,
u, we define P0 (U,1fM) (28)
if' c(U,1fM) = if' c(lf'M) n {(x,lf'c)l U"(x") :2:: u", all h}. (26) Since e is feasible, O is always dominated. Hence Lemma 4.13
158 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1

GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 159

y* = f(p*) and p* = d(y*), then the monopolist will perceive the We now repeat the assumptions on consumer behavior discussed
demand curve as that determined by the value of the shift param- in Chapter 4 with a rather technical strengthening of A.4.2.
eter 8* determined by the relation p* == d(y*, 8*). He must perceive
the correct actual demand, though not necessarily the true demand AssuMPTION 17. (a) Assumptions A.4.1, A.4.3, and A.4.4 hold.
function. (b) There exist possible consumption vectors x~ E X", k = 1, 2,
Thus, we are assuming a stable relation between the price and not indifferent to each other, such that
quantity decisions of the monopolists, given the observations on for k= 1, 2.
prices and quantities in the rest of the economy. If we regard the
From (b), we can assume without Ioss of generality that
monopolist's output as the dependent variable, we can think of it
also as a function of all prices and quantities; this is not to imply x~ >-"xk all h.
that he takes his price as given, but rather that, given all other prices The utility function, U"(x"), can be so chosen that U"(xk) = O,
U"(x~) = 2, aii h. Then any household can clearly achieve a
and all other quantities, his output decision is functionally related
to his price decision. Given the monopolized outputs, the choice of utility of more than 1 regardless of prices. Without loss of general-
competitive inputs to produce them is determined on a cost-mini- ity, then, we restrict ourselves, where appropriate, to allocations
mizing basis. Hence, the total production decision of the monopoly that achieve a utility of 1 at least for each individual. Define
is a function of all prices and quantities. Though we are not 11/'(e) = .%'(e) x I!JJ e x I!JJ M
assuming profit maximization, it is necessary in a private-enterprise
economy to insist on viability; no monopoly can be making a if'(e) = 11/'(e) n {(x,lf'clf'M)Ix S Yc + YM + x},
1

: '1
negative profit. W111 (e) is the projection ofif'(e) on I!JJM.
!.
AssuMPTION 16. For each monopolistic firm, g, the production As before, e is the vector all of whose components are 1; in this case,
vector is a continuous function, yMg(p,w), of prices and allocations its dimensionality is equal to H, the number of households.
such that PYMg(p,w) :2:: O for all p and w. The reasoning Ieading to (25) can be repeated with I!JJ M replaced by
I!JJ M(e).
We now turn to the competitive sector, which determines the
demand for monopolized goods. Sorne further notation is needed. There exists a continuous function, a(lf'M), with a
For any .fixed monopolistic production allocation, lfM there is a unique inverse, that maps 1!JJ M( e) into a compact convex
range _of feasible allocations for the competitive sectors, provided ~A. 9n
lfM E I!JJ M' namely, those allocations w 0 = (x,1fc) for which For fixed 1/M E <2?1 M(e), we can consider the range of feasible utility
2 xh S 2 Ycr + X + 2 YMu
h f g
Ycr E Ycr, xh E xh.
vectors in the competitive sector, that is, the set of vectors u for
which "if'(u,lf'M) is non-null. By definition of <2?1 M(e), the vector e
is always feasible, so there are always sorne non-negative utility
The productive activity of the monopolistic sector can be treated
vectors. We can consider then the range of non-negative Pareto-
as a modification of the initial endowment from the viewpoint of the
competitive sector. The set of allocations (oc satisfying these efficient utility aiiocations, U(I!JJ 111). For each u E U(I!JJ M), the set of
Pareto-efficient competitive allocations is "if' u(u,!fM) By A.6.17,
conditions will be denoted by if' c(lf'M).
the reasoning leading to T.4.4, the basic theorem of welfare econom-
As in Section 4.4, especially D. 4.6-11, we shall be interested in
ics, is still valid here, so aiiocations in this set are al! supported by
feasible allocations in the competitive sect~r that yield each house-
hold at Ieast a prescribed utility leve!. For any vector of utilities, a set of price vectors,
u, we define P0 (U,1fM) (28)
if' c(U,1fM) = if' c(lf'M) n {(x,lf'c)l U"(x") :2:: u", all h}. (26) Since e is feasible, O is always dominated. Hence Lemma 4.13
''

' '
'1''
i, 1
'''1
il',,"'11 1
160 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 161
,1

i!'!
i:l remains valid (see the Remar k to that Iemma). Hence, the proof of (e) Y~r maximizes p*y 0 , subject to Yor E Yor;
Lemma 5.3 remains valid, so that, for fixed !fM, there is a function,
(d) x~ maximizes U"(x") subject to
u(v,yM),
p*x" ~ M;t = p*x" + df,(p*y~,) + d~(p*yttg);
mapping the unit simplex SH into U(yM); the function, u(v,yM), can f g

easily be seen to be continuous in both variables. (e) ytcr = !fM(p*,w*).


We now make an assumption that plays the same role as A.3.5,
The function
the ability of the economy to produce a positive amount of every
1 good. This assumption was used to show that the aggregate !fM(p,w)
i.'J:
1,, income of the economy must be positive. Here, we simply make in part (e) of this definition is the allocation whose firm components
;!111,
that assumption more directly. are the functions
!::,11
11, AssuMPTION 18. For any price vector p, at least one ofthe following
11' 1 must hold:
,1
' introduced in A.6.16.
(a) px > O;
Unlike the procedure of Chapter 5, we do not explicitly introduce
(b) for sorne j, PYor > O for sorne Yor E Yor; a corresponding definition of compensated equilibrium. We shall
(e) for any to, PYM9(p,w) > O for sorne g. still need an assumption of resource relatedness to prove the ex-
Suppose neither (a) nor (b) hold. Then all primary factors are istence ofmonopolistic competitive equilibrium. We use definitions
free, and no competitive firm can make any profit. Then this D.5.4-5 but relate them to the competitive sector only; monopolistic
assumption simply asserts that at least one monopolistic firm must inputs and outputs are treated as alterations ofthe initial endowment.
be capable of making positive profits.
AssuMPTION 19. Every household is indirectly resource related to
In defining equilibrium for monopolistic competition, we must
every other through the competitive sector alone for every initial
provide for the distribution of monopolistic profits to households.
endowment obtained by replacing x by
The income of the household is now given by
M" = PXn + df?r(PYor) + d/({;(pyM 9 ), (29)
x + YM
g
9 for sorne . !IM E !fM(e).
f g
We now construct the mapping used to prove the existence of
where, of course,
equilibrium. The basic principie of the mapping of Chapter 5 is
df(, ;::: o retained, but modified to introduce both quantities used in the
competitive sector and production decisions of monopolists. The
d? = 1
h monopolized commodities appear twice in the space in which
so that the mapping takes place, but the mapping is so arranged that, at
the fixed point, the two output variables corresponding to the same
M" = px + PYM + PYo
h
(30) good are equa.l. The other variables in the mapping are, as before,
prices and relative utilities. The prices in the image will be those
DEFINITION 22. A price vector, p*, and an allocation, w* = that sustain an efficient allocation in the competitive sector for given
(x*,y~,ytcr) constitute a monopolistic competitive equilibrium if monopolistic production decisions. For the image vector ofrelative
:!
(a) p* > O; utilities, the previous construction is modified in the obvious way. ,1

Simply define
(b) x~ ~ xh + Y~r + ytrg;
h h f g
(31)
'
1

'i
1

,ll il
1'
,11' '1,
,,1
L.t ,,1
''

' '
'1''
i, 1
'''1
il',,"'11 1
160 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 161
,1

i!'!
i:l remains valid (see the Remar k to that Iemma). Hence, the proof of (e) Y~r maximizes p*y 0 , subject to Yor E Yor;
Lemma 5.3 remains valid, so that, for fixed !fM, there is a function,
(d) x~ maximizes U"(x") subject to
u(v,yM),
p*x" ~ M;t = p*x" + df,(p*y~,) + d~(p*yttg);
mapping the unit simplex SH into U(yM); the function, u(v,yM), can f g

easily be seen to be continuous in both variables. (e) ytcr = !fM(p*,w*).


We now make an assumption that plays the same role as A.3.5,
The function
the ability of the economy to produce a positive amount of every
1 good. This assumption was used to show that the aggregate !fM(p,w)
i.'J:
1,, income of the economy must be positive. Here, we simply make in part (e) of this definition is the allocation whose firm components
;!111,
that assumption more directly. are the functions
!::,11
11, AssuMPTION 18. For any price vector p, at least one ofthe following
11' 1 must hold:
,1
' introduced in A.6.16.
(a) px > O;
Unlike the procedure of Chapter 5, we do not explicitly introduce
(b) for sorne j, PYor > O for sorne Yor E Yor; a corresponding definition of compensated equilibrium. We shall
(e) for any to, PYM9(p,w) > O for sorne g. still need an assumption of resource relatedness to prove the ex-
Suppose neither (a) nor (b) hold. Then all primary factors are istence ofmonopolistic competitive equilibrium. We use definitions
free, and no competitive firm can make any profit. Then this D.5.4-5 but relate them to the competitive sector only; monopolistic
assumption simply asserts that at least one monopolistic firm must inputs and outputs are treated as alterations ofthe initial endowment.
be capable of making positive profits.
AssuMPTION 19. Every household is indirectly resource related to
In defining equilibrium for monopolistic competition, we must
every other through the competitive sector alone for every initial
provide for the distribution of monopolistic profits to households.
endowment obtained by replacing x by
The income of the household is now given by
M" = PXn + df?r(PYor) + d/({;(pyM 9 ), (29)
x + YM
g
9 for sorne . !IM E !fM(e).
f g
We now construct the mapping used to prove the existence of
where, of course,
equilibrium. The basic principie of the mapping of Chapter 5 is
df(, ;::: o retained, but modified to introduce both quantities used in the
competitive sector and production decisions of monopolists. The
d? = 1
h monopolized commodities appear twice in the space in which
so that the mapping takes place, but the mapping is so arranged that, at
the fixed point, the two output variables corresponding to the same
M" = px + PYM + PYo
h
(30) good are equa.l. The other variables in the mapping are, as before,
prices and relative utilities. The prices in the image will be those
DEFINITION 22. A price vector, p*, and an allocation, w* = that sustain an efficient allocation in the competitive sector for given
(x*,y~,ytcr) constitute a monopolistic competitive equilibrium if monopolistic production decisions. For the image vector ofrelative
:!
(a) p* > O; utilities, the previous construction is modified in the obvious way. ,1

Simply define
(b) x~ ~ xh + Y~r + ytrg;
h h f g
(31)
'
1

'i
1

,ll il
1'
,11' '1,
,,1
L.t ,,1
r i
162 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 163

where w = (x,y 0 ,yM) and Mh is defined in (29), and P0(u,bfM) and 11"0 (u,bfM) are defined in (28) and (26), respectively.
V(p,w) = SH n {vlvh =o if sh(p,w) < 0}. (32) Then Kakutani's theorem guarantees the existence of a :fixed point
for this correspondence, (p*,v*,w~,a*). Let lf~ be defined by
We also map the initial situation into the efficient allocation of
commodities in the competitive sector, conditional on the outputs a(y~) =a*
of the monopolistic sector. For the monopolistic sector, we would
and
like the new value ofthe monopolistic production vector to be on the
response function postulated in A.6.16. We also want this image u* = u(v*,y~).
to be in or correspond to a point in A, that is, equivalent to a pro- Sin ce
duction vector in qfjM(e), the set that is indexed by A according to (27).
The second property will be satisfied at equilibrium if there is one, p* E P0 (u*,y~) w~ E if' 0 (u*,y~), (36)
but not in general for an arbitrary initial p, w. We therefore it follows from T.4.4 that D.6.22 (a)-(c) hold, and also
construct a mapping into A as follows. First, find !fM(p,w), the
monopolist's response according to A.6.16. Then map this point x~ minimizes p*x~< subject to Uh(xh) :2:: u~. (37)
into @M(e) in such a way that it is unchanged if it is already in this From (31) and (36), it follows, as in Section 5.3, that
set. Then map the resulting point into A according to (27). To
do this, choose !1~ to belong to the interior of the neighborhood sh(p*,w*) = O.
speci:fied in A.6.15. Clearly we can do this in such a way that h

x 0 yg + y~ + :X for sorne x0 E El'(e), yg E Y0 (33) At the :fixed point, v* E V(p*,w*). Again as m Section 5.3, it
follows that
Let p(yM) be the gauge function for the set@ M(e) with center lf~ (see
Section B.2, especially T.B.2). Then !/M E qf)M(e) if and only if s,(p*,w*) :2:: O all h,
p(yM) ::::; l. Let q(yM) = max[p(bfM), 1]. Then q(yM) = 1 for and therefore
bfM E WM(e), q(yM) > 1 for Y' M E qf)M(e). Define
sh(p*,w*) = O all h,
!f~(p,w) =y~ + $fMiP'(~-
q bfM ,w
[J~. (34)
or equivalently,
1
a (p,w) = a[y~(p,w)]. (35) (38)
In (34), we accept the monopolist's response if it permits a utility We know that (37) and (38) imply that D.6.22(d) (utility maxi-
of at least 1 to each household (a utility that can be achieved without mization) holds if it can be demonstrated that M(: > O(see the proof
trade); if not, we move the response toward a given point until it of T.5.2). Because of A.6.19 (resource relatedness), it suffices to
satis:fies this condition. In (35), we relabel this point to put it in a show that
convex compact set.
We map the set M(:> O.
h
Sn X SH X if'& X A
From (33), we know that
into the correspondence
Po(u,yM) x V(p,w) X "lf' 0 (n,yM) X {a1(p,w )},
p*(yg + y~ + :X) > o.
where By pro:fit maximization, p*y~ :2:: p*yg and also p*y~ :2:: O. Hence,
bfM satisfies the condition a(yM) = a, and u = u(v,yM), p*(i + y~ + y~) > o (39)

,,

11
,,
,,,,

;
:'11

'.,
1
.111)1
r i
162 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 163

where w = (x,y 0 ,yM) and Mh is defined in (29), and P0(u,bfM) and 11"0 (u,bfM) are defined in (28) and (26), respectively.
V(p,w) = SH n {vlvh =o if sh(p,w) < 0}. (32) Then Kakutani's theorem guarantees the existence of a :fixed point
for this correspondence, (p*,v*,w~,a*). Let lf~ be defined by
We also map the initial situation into the efficient allocation of
commodities in the competitive sector, conditional on the outputs a(y~) =a*
of the monopolistic sector. For the monopolistic sector, we would
and
like the new value ofthe monopolistic production vector to be on the
response function postulated in A.6.16. We also want this image u* = u(v*,y~).
to be in or correspond to a point in A, that is, equivalent to a pro- Sin ce
duction vector in qfjM(e), the set that is indexed by A according to (27).
The second property will be satisfied at equilibrium if there is one, p* E P0 (u*,y~) w~ E if' 0 (u*,y~), (36)
but not in general for an arbitrary initial p, w. We therefore it follows from T.4.4 that D.6.22 (a)-(c) hold, and also
construct a mapping into A as follows. First, find !fM(p,w), the
monopolist's response according to A.6.16. Then map this point x~ minimizes p*x~< subject to Uh(xh) :2:: u~. (37)
into @M(e) in such a way that it is unchanged if it is already in this From (31) and (36), it follows, as in Section 5.3, that
set. Then map the resulting point into A according to (27). To
do this, choose !1~ to belong to the interior of the neighborhood sh(p*,w*) = O.
speci:fied in A.6.15. Clearly we can do this in such a way that h

x 0 yg + y~ + :X for sorne x0 E El'(e), yg E Y0 (33) At the :fixed point, v* E V(p*,w*). Again as m Section 5.3, it
follows that
Let p(yM) be the gauge function for the set@ M(e) with center lf~ (see
Section B.2, especially T.B.2). Then !/M E qf)M(e) if and only if s,(p*,w*) :2:: O all h,
p(yM) ::::; l. Let q(yM) = max[p(bfM), 1]. Then q(yM) = 1 for and therefore
bfM E WM(e), q(yM) > 1 for Y' M E qf)M(e). Define
sh(p*,w*) = O all h,
!f~(p,w) =y~ + $fMiP'(~-
q bfM ,w
[J~. (34)
or equivalently,
1
a (p,w) = a[y~(p,w)]. (35) (38)
In (34), we accept the monopolist's response if it permits a utility We know that (37) and (38) imply that D.6.22(d) (utility maxi-
of at least 1 to each household (a utility that can be achieved without mization) holds if it can be demonstrated that M(: > O(see the proof
trade); if not, we move the response toward a given point until it of T.5.2). Because of A.6.19 (resource relatedness), it suffices to
satis:fies this condition. In (35), we relabel this point to put it in a show that
convex compact set.
We map the set M(:> O.
h
Sn X SH X if'& X A
From (33), we know that
into the correspondence
Po(u,yM) x V(p,w) X "lf' 0 (n,yM) X {a1(p,w )},
p*(yg + y~ + :X) > o.
where By pro:fit maximization, p*y~ :2:: p*yg and also p*y~ :2:: O. Hence,
bfM satisfies the condition a(yM) = a, and u = u(v,yM), p*(i + y~ + y~) > o (39)

,,

11
,,
,,,,

;
:'11

'.,
1
.111)1
-
164 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 165

and Since each household is maximizing utility and since each can
achieve a utility of 2 without using the market, it must be that
p*(x + yt) :2: o.
From A.6.16, u~ :2: 2 all h.

P*YMg(p*,w*) :2: O If yXr were changed to any J/M in its neighborhood, there would still
and, therefore, summing over g, exist competitive allocations feasible conditional on the monopolistic
allocation J/M which would achieve a utility strictly greater than 1
p*yM(p*,w*) :2: O for each individual. Then yXt must belong to the interior of the set
so that !fY M(e).

P*[-
X + Ya* + YM(p*,w*)] :?: O. (40) By definition of the gauge function,
From (35), at the fixed point,
p(yft) < l.
al(p*,w*) = a*,
By (34),
or
p( *) = p(ffM(p*,to*)] < 1
ykt(p*,w*) = yXt, J/M q((JfMp*,w*)) ,
so. from
. (34) an d summmg
over g, we see that y* . From the definitions, this can happen only if q* = 1, that is, if
bmatwn of yo and ( * * . . M IS a convex com-
M YM P ,w ), With we1ghts 1 _ (ljq*) and ( 1/ *)
respectively, where q , yXr = fM(p*,w*),
which is D.6.22(e).
q* = q[oYM(p*,w*)].
Then, from (39) and ( 40), THEOREM 4. Under assumptions A.6.12-19, monopolistic competi-
tive equilibrium exists. . ;

p*(x + Y~ + yft) :2:: o, (41) Remark l. No explicit mention has been made of product 1

and the strict inequality holds if q* > l. differentiation, a central theme of monopolistic competition theory,
q* = 1, then If, on the contrary, 1
:,

:
but note that the model admits the possibility that any rnonopolistic
firm can produce a variety of goods. Suppose that all conceivable ll
yft = YM(p*,w*), ::
goods are included in the list of commodities; even what are usually 11

and by A.6.16, regarded as varieties of the same good must be distinguished in this
1
1:

11

p*yft :?: o. list if they are not perfect substitutes in both production and con-
11

sumption. In general, a monopolist will find it profitable to


Then equality can hoJd in (41) only if simultaneously produce a number of varieties. The definition of a monopoly
p*x = O, p*yt = O, and p*yft = o implies that, for some reason or another, two different monopolists
produce non-overlapping sets of goods, but of course the goods
in contradiction to A 6 18 Th f '
in (41) in any case; by.cJO): ere ore, the strict inequaJity hoJds produced by one monopolist may be quite clase substitutes for
those produced by another. The usual idea in product differentia-
2M/t >O tion-that a firm produces just one commodity-is not a con-
h venient assumption for general equilibrium analysis, but it is
and, therefore, D.6.22(d) hoJds., equally certainly not a good description of the real world.
-
164 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 165

and Since each household is maximizing utility and since each can
achieve a utility of 2 without using the market, it must be that
p*(x + yt) :2: o.
From A.6.16, u~ :2: 2 all h.

P*YMg(p*,w*) :2: O If yXr were changed to any J/M in its neighborhood, there would still
and, therefore, summing over g, exist competitive allocations feasible conditional on the monopolistic
allocation J/M which would achieve a utility strictly greater than 1
p*yM(p*,w*) :2: O for each individual. Then yXt must belong to the interior of the set
so that !fY M(e).

P*[-
X + Ya* + YM(p*,w*)] :?: O. (40) By definition of the gauge function,
From (35), at the fixed point,
p(yft) < l.
al(p*,w*) = a*,
By (34),
or
p( *) = p(ffM(p*,to*)] < 1
ykt(p*,w*) = yXt, J/M q((JfMp*,w*)) ,
so. from
. (34) an d summmg
over g, we see that y* . From the definitions, this can happen only if q* = 1, that is, if
bmatwn of yo and ( * * . . M IS a convex com-
M YM P ,w ), With we1ghts 1 _ (ljq*) and ( 1/ *)
respectively, where q , yXr = fM(p*,w*),
which is D.6.22(e).
q* = q[oYM(p*,w*)].
Then, from (39) and ( 40), THEOREM 4. Under assumptions A.6.12-19, monopolistic competi-
tive equilibrium exists. . ;

p*(x + Y~ + yft) :2:: o, (41) Remark l. No explicit mention has been made of product 1

and the strict inequality holds if q* > l. differentiation, a central theme of monopolistic competition theory,
q* = 1, then If, on the contrary, 1
:,

:
but note that the model admits the possibility that any rnonopolistic
firm can produce a variety of goods. Suppose that all conceivable ll
yft = YM(p*,w*), ::
goods are included in the list of commodities; even what are usually 11

and by A.6.16, regarded as varieties of the same good must be distinguished in this
1
1:

11

p*yft :?: o. list if they are not perfect substitutes in both production and con-
11

sumption. In general, a monopolist will find it profitable to


Then equality can hoJd in (41) only if simultaneously produce a number of varieties. The definition of a monopoly
p*x = O, p*yt = O, and p*yft = o implies that, for some reason or another, two different monopolists
produce non-overlapping sets of goods, but of course the goods
in contradiction to A 6 18 Th f '
in (41) in any case; by.cJO): ere ore, the strict inequaJity hoJds produced by one monopolist may be quite clase substitutes for
those produced by another. The usual idea in product differentia-
2M/t >O tion-that a firm produces just one commodity-is not a con-
h venient assumption for general equilibrium analysis, but it is
and, therefore, D.6.22(d) hoJds., equally certainly not a good description of the real world.
166 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 167

Remark 2. The notion of free entry, and with it the famous irrelevant. The problem may be important, however, if his per-
double-tangency solution of Chamberlin [1956, pp. 81-100] and ceptions are accurate only at equilibrium or if there are severa!
Robinson [1933, pp. 93-94], has no role here either. The list of monopolists; the discontinuity in the behavior of any one affects the
monopolists is assumed given, so that in effect there is a scarcity perceived demand functions for the others, though, again, if the
of the appropriate type of entrepreneurship, and there is no reason monopolists are relatively separated in markets and each is relatively
for profits to be wiped out. No doubt if there are severa! firms small on the scale of the economy, then the discontinuities involved
producing producs that are close substitutes in consumption and may be unimportant.
have very similar production possibility sets otherwise, they should
behave about the same way, and if there are enough of them, it may
Remark 4. It must always be remembered that monopolistic
competition models of the type discussed here ignore the mutual
well be that each is making very little in the way of profit. But the
recognition of power among firms, the oligopoly problem.
question then is the one raised originally by Kaldor [1935]: Would
not the elasticity of demand to the individual firm be essentially
infinite, so that the situation is essentially one ofperfect competition? Notes
This question has not been fully answered, since a more specific Section 2. The analysis of this section was developed jointly with
model defining close substitutes and their production possibilities David Starrett. It is rather hard to make out from the usual literature f.
has not yet been explicitly formulated. whether it is assumed that competitive equilibrium is compatible with ,,
,,
externalities. Chipman [1970] reviews sorne of the literature. In a
Remark 3. An open and potentially important research area is particular case he shows how externalities that give rise to social-
the specification of conditions under which monopolistic behavior, increasing returns, but priva te constant returns, are compatible with the
existence of competitive equilibrium and even, under special circum-
as expressed in the function yM(I),.w) is, in fact, continuous. The
stances, to Pareto efficiency. Por a good general statement of the
formulation is very general; it is certainly compatible with utility- usual doctrine of equilibrium with externalities in production, see Bohm
maximizing behavior (e.g., preference for size or particular kind of [1963, Chapter 2]. Por a rigorous proof of the existence of equilibrium
expenditure or product) as well as profit-maximizing behavior. with externalities in consumption, see McKenzie [1955b].
The assumption of continuity may be strong nevertheless; in effect, Section 3. The analysis of temporary equilibrum was introduced
by Hicks [1939, pp. 130-133]. A more recent methodological dis-
it denies the role of increasing returns as a barrier to entry. As
cussion can be found in Hicks [1965, Chapter VI]. The possibility of
demand shifts upward, the firm might pass from zero output (i.e., a an existence theorem for temporary equilibrium was indicated by
purely potential existence) to a minimum positive output. A zero Saito [1961, pp. 233-236]. The results of this section have appeared in
output must be interpreted as a price decision at a leve! correspond- slightly different forro in Arrow [1971 ].
ing to zero demand, but if the demand curve slopes downward, Section 4. The model presented here is a formalization of Chamber-
lin's case of monopolistic competition with Iarge numbers [1956, pp.
then entry at a positive leve! far removed from zero implies a dis-
81-100; originally published in 1933]. As Triffin [1940] showed, the
continuous drop in price. The importance of this problem is not essential aspects of monopolistic competition aRpcar as soon as we
easy to assess. The situation can arise only if the (perceived) attempt to introduce sorne monopolies into a system of general com-
marginal revenue curve is, broadly speaking, flatter than the marginal petitive equilibrium. . The only previous complete formal model is that
cost curve (otherwise entry would be a continuous phenomenon) of the brilliant paper of Negishi [1960-61], who proved an existence
theorem for it, the only previous work of this type known to us. Negishi
but the demand curve must also be relatively flat and therefore the
assumed that each monopolist produced only one commodity and
' i price discontinuity may be mild even if the output discontinuity is maximized profits according to a perceived demand curve that was a
1
r,, large. Also, if there were only a single monopolist who correctly function of all prces and the entire allocation, but, in particular, was
perceived the excess-demand correspondence of the competitive linear in the price of the commodity. He saw the importance of in-
sector, he could choose his most preferred point, which would be sisting that at equilibrium the monopolist's perceived demand curve
should at Ieast pass through the observed price-quantity point. In his
then an equilibrium; the discontinuity of his behavior would be
formulation, which was originally suggested by Bushaw and Clower
166 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS GENERAL EQUILIBRIUM UNDER ALTERNATIVE ASSUMPTIONS 167

Remark 2. The notion of free entry, and with it the famous irrelevant. The problem may be important, however, if his per-
double-tangency solution of Chamberlin [1956, pp. 81-100] and ceptions are accurate only at equilibrium or if there are severa!
Robinson [1933, pp. 93-94], has no role here either. The list of monopolists; the discontinuity in the behavior of any one affects the
monopolists is assumed given, so that in effect there is a scarcity perceived demand functions for the others, though, again, if the
of the appropriate type of entrepreneurship, and there is no reason monopolists are relatively separated in markets and each is relatively
for profits to be wiped out. No doubt if there are severa! firms small on the scale of the economy, then the discontinuities involved
producing producs that are close substitutes in consumption and may be unimportant.
have very similar production possibility sets otherwise, they should
behave about the same way, and if there are enough of them, it may
Remark 4. It must always be remembered that monopolistic
competition models of the type discussed here ignore the mutual
well be that each is making very little in the way of profit. But the
recognition of power among firms, the oligopoly problem.
question then is the one raised originally by Kaldor [1935]: Would
not the elasticity of demand to the individual firm be essentially
infinite, so that the situation is essentially one ofperfect competition? Notes
This question has not been fully answered, since a more specific Section 2. The analysis of this section was developed jointly with
model defining close substitutes and their production possibilities David Starrett. It is rather hard to make out from the usual literature f.
has not yet been explicitly formulated. whether it is assumed that competitive equilibrium is compatible with ,,
,,
externalities. Chipman [1970] reviews sorne of the literature. In a
Remark 3. An open and potentially important research area is particular case he shows how externalities that give rise to social-
the specification of conditions under which monopolistic behavior, increasing returns, but priva te constant returns, are compatible with the
existence of competitive equilibrium and even, under special circum-
as expressed in the function yM(I),.w) is, in fact, continuous. The
stances, to Pareto efficiency. Por a good general statement of the
formulation is very general; it is certainly compatible with utility- usual doctrine of equilibrium with externalities in production, see Bohm
maximizing behavior (e.g., preference for size or particular kind of [1963, Chapter 2]. Por a rigorous proof of the existence of equilibrium
expenditure or product) as well as profit-maximizing behavior. with externalities in consumption, see McKenzie [1955b].
The assumption of continuity may be strong nevertheless; in effect, Section 3. The analysis of temporary equilibrum was introduced
by Hicks [1939, pp. 130-133]. A more recent methodological dis-
it denies the role of increasing returns as a barrier to entry. As
cussion can be found in Hicks [1965, Chapter VI]. The possibility of
demand shifts upward, the firm might pass from zero output (i.e., a an existence theorem for temporary equilibrium was indicated by
purely potential existence) to a minimum positive output. A zero Saito [1961, pp. 233-236]. The results of this section have appeared in
output must be interpreted as a price decision at a leve! correspond- slightly different forro in Arrow [1971 ].
ing to zero demand, but if the demand curve slopes downward, Section 4. The model presented here is a formalization of Chamber-
lin's case of monopolistic competition with Iarge numbers [1956, pp.
then entry at a positive leve! far removed from zero implies a dis-
81-100; originally published in 1933]. As Triffin [1940] showed, the
continuous drop in price. The importance of this problem is not essential aspects of monopolistic competition aRpcar as soon as we
easy to assess. The situation can arise only if the (perceived) attempt to introduce sorne monopolies into a system of general com-
marginal revenue curve is, broadly speaking, flatter than the marginal petitive equilibrium. . The only previous complete formal model is that
cost curve (otherwise entry would be a continuous phenomenon) of the brilliant paper of Negishi [1960-61], who proved an existence
theorem for it, the only previous work of this type known to us. Negishi
but the demand curve must also be relatively flat and therefore the
assumed that each monopolist produced only one commodity and
' i price discontinuity may be mild even if the output discontinuity is maximized profits according to a perceived demand curve that was a
1
r,, large. Also, if there were only a single monopolist who correctly function of all prces and the entire allocation, but, in particular, was
perceived the excess-demand correspondence of the competitive linear in the price of the commodity. He saw the importance of in-
sector, he could choose his most preferred point, which would be sisting that at equilibrium the monopolist's perceived demand curve
should at Ieast pass through the observed price-quantity point. In his
then an equilibrium; the discontinuity of his behavior would be
formulation, which was originally suggested by Bushaw and Clower
~
1
1
1

1'
,
r
168 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS Chapter Seven
1

1'
1'
[1957, p. 181], the monopolist's price equaled the given one if, at the MARKETS WITH
given allocation, supply and demand were equal for that commodity.
i
1' Also, Negishi restricted attention to the case in which the monopolists NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES
!'
1

have convex production possibility sets, a severe condition since the AND PRODUCTION
1,::
occurrence of monopoly is unlikely under those circumstances, as Negishi
:1
1:
himself noted [p. 109, middle]. He raised the possibility of more general
!11 assumptions, similar to A.6.15.
!.' A guif profound as that Serbonian
A model in tended to represent the ideas of this sectin has already been
presented in Arrow [1971]. The results given there, however, while Bog
mathematically correct, suffer from considerable difficulties in interpre- Betwixt Damiata and mount Casius
tation. We are greatly indebted to Tatsuro Ichiishi, Keio University, old,
and James Mirrlees, Oxford, for demonstrating to us the need for new Where Armies whole have sunk.
thinking on these questions.
-John Milton, Paradise Lost

1. Introduction

The assumptions of convexity of production (A.3.3) and of


preferences (A.4.4( d)) ha ve played an essential role in the proof of
existence of competitive equilibrium. Convexity implies that
responses of firms and households to changes in prices tend to be
continuous; even when jumps occur (as under constant returns for
a firm), every point jn the whole interval between the two extremities
of the jump is a permissible response so that there are no gaps in
which an inequality between supply and demand can be fitted. This
point can be seen for firms by contrasting Figures 3-1-3-3 with
Figure 3-4 (see a1so the accompanying text). In Figure 7-1 we
reproduce the production possibility set of Figure 3-4a and add the
implied demand function for the input. Let commodity 1 be input
and commodity 2 output. Then, for p 2 (Jh less than sorne critica!
price ratio, a, the firm will make negative profits at any positive
output leve! and, therefore, will supply and demand zero. At
p 2 (p 1 = a, the firm will make a zero profit at precisely one non-zero
activity, (y~,y~) and negative profits at all others. Thus, the profit-
maximizing firm is indifferent between (0,0) and (yLyn; the demand
by the firm is two-valued, the values being O and -y~. For p 2 /Pl >
a, the demand will exceed -y~.
Suppose the firm is the only one in the economy, the initial endow-
ment of the economy (summed over all households) is (.X\,0), and
commodity 1 does not enter anyone's utility function, so that the
sale demand for the commodity arises from the firm's productive
activity. Then if O < .X1 < -y~, it is clear that no equilibrium
price ratio exists. If p 2 (p 1 < a, then supply of commodity 1 exceeds

169
~
1
1
1

1'
,
r
168 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS Chapter Seven
1

1'
1'
[1957, p. 181], the monopolist's price equaled the given one if, at the MARKETS WITH
given allocation, supply and demand were equal for that commodity.
i
1' Also, Negishi restricted attention to the case in which the monopolists NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES
!'
1

have convex production possibility sets, a severe condition since the AND PRODUCTION
1,::
occurrence of monopoly is unlikely under those circumstances, as Negishi
:1
1:
himself noted [p. 109, middle]. He raised the possibility of more general
!11 assumptions, similar to A.6.15.
!.' A guif profound as that Serbonian
A model in tended to represent the ideas of this sectin has already been
presented in Arrow [1971]. The results given there, however, while Bog
mathematically correct, suffer from considerable difficulties in interpre- Betwixt Damiata and mount Casius
tation. We are greatly indebted to Tatsuro Ichiishi, Keio University, old,
and James Mirrlees, Oxford, for demonstrating to us the need for new Where Armies whole have sunk.
thinking on these questions.
-John Milton, Paradise Lost

1. Introduction

The assumptions of convexity of production (A.3.3) and of


preferences (A.4.4( d)) ha ve played an essential role in the proof of
existence of competitive equilibrium. Convexity implies that
responses of firms and households to changes in prices tend to be
continuous; even when jumps occur (as under constant returns for
a firm), every point jn the whole interval between the two extremities
of the jump is a permissible response so that there are no gaps in
which an inequality between supply and demand can be fitted. This
point can be seen for firms by contrasting Figures 3-1-3-3 with
Figure 3-4 (see a1so the accompanying text). In Figure 7-1 we
reproduce the production possibility set of Figure 3-4a and add the
implied demand function for the input. Let commodity 1 be input
and commodity 2 output. Then, for p 2 (Jh less than sorne critica!
price ratio, a, the firm will make negative profits at any positive
output leve! and, therefore, will supply and demand zero. At
p 2 (p 1 = a, the firm will make a zero profit at precisely one non-zero
activity, (y~,y~) and negative profits at all others. Thus, the profit-
maximizing firm is indifferent between (0,0) and (yLyn; the demand
by the firm is two-valued, the values being O and -y~. For p 2 /Pl >
a, the demand will exceed -y~.
Suppose the firm is the only one in the economy, the initial endow-
ment of the economy (summed over all households) is (.X\,0), and
commodity 1 does not enter anyone's utility function, so that the
sale demand for the commodity arises from the firm's productive
activity. Then if O < .X1 < -y~, it is clear that no equilibrium
price ratio exists. If p 2 (p 1 < a, then supply of commodity 1 exceeds

169
T

: i ,

'1 170 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 171
.1

maximizing. Suppose first that O < .X1 ::::; - yV2. Assume the
price ratio is a. Then, if the firm purchases zero, there is an excess
supply .X 1 If, on the contrary, the firm purchased - y~-an equally
profitable decision-demand would exceed supply by -y~ - .X 1 ::o:
.X 1 . There is, then, a price ratio, a, anda profit-maximizing demand,
O, for which the absolute discrepancy between supply and demand
does not exceed - yV2. If the price ratio were different from a, the
discrepancy could not be smaller. Now, ifwe suppose that -yV2 <
.X1 < -y~, the smallest discrepancy between supply and demand
occurs at price ratio a and profit-maximizing demand -y~; this time
there is excess supply, but again the discrepancy does not exceed
(a) - yV2 in absolute value.
Now, to continue the example, suppose an economy with two
identical firms, each with the production possibility set defined by
Demand for Demand for Figure 7-la. The aggregate demand for two firms is represented in
input (-y 1 ) input (-y 1 )
Figure 7-1c. Then aggregate demand for commodity 1 is zero for

-y~

x,
-2y~

x,
-y~
---- p 2 /p 1 < a, and it exceeds - 2y~ for p 2 /p 1 > a. If p2 /p 1 = a, each
firm will, as befare, demand either zero or -y~. Since neither, one,
or both of the two firms may be demanding a positive amount of
commodity 1, the aggregate demand at p 2 /p 1 = a is tri-valued, the
three possible values being O, -y~, and - 2y~. Now, if .X1 lies
'------e------pz/p, between O and - 2y~, it is clear that at the price ratio a we can
a a arrange that the discrepancy between supply and demand not exceed
(b) (e)
l - yV2 without violating the assumption that firms maximize profits;
. ,1.
: ' '1 Figure 7-1 all that is needed is to choose that one of three possible magnitudes
:il 1
that is closest to xl.
11
r demand. If p 2 /p 1 > a, then demand exceeds supply on that market. This conclusion suggests the interesting implication that the
, lf P2/P 1 = a, there is no behavior of the firm that simultaneously possible discrepancies between supply and demand do not neces-
ll maximizes profits and absorbs exactly the available supply. sarily increase with the number of agents in the economy. Put
11'!'1 Suppose that Figure 7-la were modified by adding to the produc- another way, the ratio of the possible disequilibrium to the size of
:.. tion possibility set every production vector on or below the straight the economy decreases. The aim of this chapter is to give a general
!j: line segment OA. Then at the price ratio a all these points would formulation of this result.
yield a zero profit; the demand correspondence for the input would The possibility that, at the price ratio a, one firm may be operating
l.i include the whole vertical segment from Oto -y~. Then the equi- while the other is not suggests another implication of non-convexity:
librium input would be .X1 and the equilibrium price ratio a. This At an equilibrium or approximate equilibrium it may be necessary
11'.1
1' comparison brings out more specifically the role of convexity in that identical firms behave very differently.
1
establishing the existence of equilibrium. The possibilities for validity or invalidity of the convexity
11'!
Since existence of equilibrium is not assured in the presence of hypothesis have been discussed in Section 3.2. It was argued there
'1
i non-convexity, it may be worthwhile to ask how clase to equilibrium that non-convex production possibility sets could be expected to
the economy can come, under the assumption that the firm is profit arise from indivisibilities in production processes .

.1
T

: i ,

'1 170 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 171
.1

maximizing. Suppose first that O < .X1 ::::; - yV2. Assume the
price ratio is a. Then, if the firm purchases zero, there is an excess
supply .X 1 If, on the contrary, the firm purchased - y~-an equally
profitable decision-demand would exceed supply by -y~ - .X 1 ::o:
.X 1 . There is, then, a price ratio, a, anda profit-maximizing demand,
O, for which the absolute discrepancy between supply and demand
does not exceed - yV2. If the price ratio were different from a, the
discrepancy could not be smaller. Now, ifwe suppose that -yV2 <
.X1 < -y~, the smallest discrepancy between supply and demand
occurs at price ratio a and profit-maximizing demand -y~; this time
there is excess supply, but again the discrepancy does not exceed
(a) - yV2 in absolute value.
Now, to continue the example, suppose an economy with two
identical firms, each with the production possibility set defined by
Demand for Demand for Figure 7-la. The aggregate demand for two firms is represented in
input (-y 1 ) input (-y 1 )
Figure 7-1c. Then aggregate demand for commodity 1 is zero for

-y~

x,
-2y~

x,
-y~
---- p 2 /p 1 < a, and it exceeds - 2y~ for p 2 /p 1 > a. If p2 /p 1 = a, each
firm will, as befare, demand either zero or -y~. Since neither, one,
or both of the two firms may be demanding a positive amount of
commodity 1, the aggregate demand at p 2 /p 1 = a is tri-valued, the
three possible values being O, -y~, and - 2y~. Now, if .X1 lies
'------e------pz/p, between O and - 2y~, it is clear that at the price ratio a we can
a a arrange that the discrepancy between supply and demand not exceed
(b) (e)
l - yV2 without violating the assumption that firms maximize profits;
. ,1.
: ' '1 Figure 7-1 all that is needed is to choose that one of three possible magnitudes
:il 1
that is closest to xl.
11
r demand. If p 2 /p 1 > a, then demand exceeds supply on that market. This conclusion suggests the interesting implication that the
, lf P2/P 1 = a, there is no behavior of the firm that simultaneously possible discrepancies between supply and demand do not neces-
ll maximizes profits and absorbs exactly the available supply. sarily increase with the number of agents in the economy. Put
11'!'1 Suppose that Figure 7-la were modified by adding to the produc- another way, the ratio of the possible disequilibrium to the size of
:.. tion possibility set every production vector on or below the straight the economy decreases. The aim of this chapter is to give a general
!j: line segment OA. Then at the price ratio a all these points would formulation of this result.
yield a zero profit; the demand correspondence for the input would The possibility that, at the price ratio a, one firm may be operating
l.i include the whole vertical segment from Oto -y~. Then the equi- while the other is not suggests another implication of non-convexity:
librium input would be .X1 and the equilibrium price ratio a. This At an equilibrium or approximate equilibrium it may be necessary
11'.1
1' comparison brings out more specifically the role of convexity in that identical firms behave very differently.
1
establishing the existence of equilibrium. The possibilities for validity or invalidity of the convexity
11'!
Since existence of equilibrium is not assured in the presence of hypothesis have been discussed in Section 3.2. It was argued there
'1
i non-convexity, it may be worthwhile to ask how clase to equilibrium that non-convex production possibility sets could be expected to
the economy can come, under the assumption that the firm is profit arise from indivisibilities in production processes .

.1
T
172 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PR~FERENCES ANO PRODUCTION 173

It is similarly possible that the preference orderings of households may well prefer either to splitting the week between the two. (On
do not satisfy the convexity condition A.4.4(d). Sorne pairs of the other hand, a different choice may be made if the alterna ti ves are
commodities may be antagonistic in consumption. Whiskey and London and Cambridge.) Evaluations of esthetic satisfaction of
gin form a frequently cited pair of this kind. A more serious tastes, in general, re al so unlikely to be convex. "There is no
example is residential location. An individual may be indifferent excellent Beauty that hath not sorne strangenesse in the proportion,"
between consuming seven days a week a day of living in California says Bacon. "A man cannot tell whether Appelles or Albert
and consuming the same amount of living in Massachusetts, but he Drer were the more trifler; whereof the one would make a Per-
sonage by geometrical proportions; the other, by taking the best
parts out of diverse Faces to make one excellent." Nor would a
Xz
convex combination of tripe it la mode de Caen and filet de so/e
Margury be regarded highly by the gourmet (perhaps Chinese
cuisine admits more convexity in preferences among its dishes than
does the French). No doubt the root of any non-convexity in
household preference orderings is sorne indivisibility; in any con-
sumption activity, one input is the individual. For our purposes it
suffices to recognize the possibility that preference orderings may
exhibit non-convexities without seeking a deeper explanation.
Figure 7-2 illustrates the demands derived from non-convex
preferences, analogous to those derived from non-convex production
possibility sets in Figure 7-1. It is assumed that the household has
an initial endowment vector, x. Then again the demand corre-
spondence at sorne price ratio will be two valued, but it will have a
gap.
2. The Method of Analysis anda Measure of Non-Convexity
In this chapter, we will state a general theorem on the degree to
(a) which an economy not satisfying the convexity assumptions in
production and consumption nevertheless can possess approximately
a competitive equilibrium; that is, we will show the existence of a

--
price vector, a consumption vector for each household that mini-
mizes the cost of achieving a given utility leve! and satisfies the budget
constraint at those prices, and a production vector for each firm that
maximizes profits at- those prices, such that the social excess demand
for all commodities is bounded in a manner determined by the degree
of non-convexity of the preference orderings and the production
possibility sets. Further, we can so determine this upper bound on
the discrepancy that it does not increase with the size ofthe economy;
'----------------P2fPt hence, the discrepancy divided by sorne measure of the size of the
(b) economy (e.g., the number of economic agents) approaches zero.
This result is stated with greater precision in T. 7.1.
Figure 7-2
T
172 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PR~FERENCES ANO PRODUCTION 173

It is similarly possible that the preference orderings of households may well prefer either to splitting the week between the two. (On
do not satisfy the convexity condition A.4.4(d). Sorne pairs of the other hand, a different choice may be made if the alterna ti ves are
commodities may be antagonistic in consumption. Whiskey and London and Cambridge.) Evaluations of esthetic satisfaction of
gin form a frequently cited pair of this kind. A more serious tastes, in general, re al so unlikely to be convex. "There is no
example is residential location. An individual may be indifferent excellent Beauty that hath not sorne strangenesse in the proportion,"
between consuming seven days a week a day of living in California says Bacon. "A man cannot tell whether Appelles or Albert
and consuming the same amount of living in Massachusetts, but he Drer were the more trifler; whereof the one would make a Per-
sonage by geometrical proportions; the other, by taking the best
parts out of diverse Faces to make one excellent." Nor would a
Xz
convex combination of tripe it la mode de Caen and filet de so/e
Margury be regarded highly by the gourmet (perhaps Chinese
cuisine admits more convexity in preferences among its dishes than
does the French). No doubt the root of any non-convexity in
household preference orderings is sorne indivisibility; in any con-
sumption activity, one input is the individual. For our purposes it
suffices to recognize the possibility that preference orderings may
exhibit non-convexities without seeking a deeper explanation.
Figure 7-2 illustrates the demands derived from non-convex
preferences, analogous to those derived from non-convex production
possibility sets in Figure 7-1. It is assumed that the household has
an initial endowment vector, x. Then again the demand corre-
spondence at sorne price ratio will be two valued, but it will have a
gap.
2. The Method of Analysis anda Measure of Non-Convexity
In this chapter, we will state a general theorem on the degree to
(a) which an economy not satisfying the convexity assumptions in
production and consumption nevertheless can possess approximately
a competitive equilibrium; that is, we will show the existence of a

--
price vector, a consumption vector for each household that mini-
mizes the cost of achieving a given utility leve! and satisfies the budget
constraint at those prices, and a production vector for each firm that
maximizes profits at- those prices, such that the social excess demand
for all commodities is bounded in a manner determined by the degree
of non-convexity of the preference orderings and the production
possibility sets. Further, we can so determine this upper bound on
the discrepancy that it does not increase with the size ofthe economy;
'----------------P2fPt hence, the discrepancy divided by sorne measure of the size of the
(b) economy (e.g., the number of economic agents) approaches zero.
This result is stated with greater precision in T. 7.1.
Figure 7-2
,
1 !
i

1
1

174 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 175

The rnethod of analysis is the following. Frorn the given econorny, is bounded by a rnagnitude that depends on the rnaxirnurn degree of
we construct a new one satisfying all the conditions of the existence non-convexity of the production possibility sets. The price vector,
theory of Chapters 3-5. Recall the definition of a convex hull. p*, and the allocation a ..t = (xt,y: together constitute an approxi-
1
')

(See D.B.3, D.B.12, and T.B.7.) A vector x' is said to be the convex rnate equilibriurn in the sense that the discrepancy between supply
cornbination of the vectors in a finite set T if there exists a non- and dernand is also bounded (with a rnodification for free goods).
negative real-valued function, a(x), defined for x E T, such that, No rnatter how large the econorny, the bound is deterrnined by the
2; a(x) = 1 2; a(x)x = x'. rnaxirnurn degree of non-convexity.
xeT xeT For a pure-exchange econorny in the special case where Xh, the
We will say also that the set T spans x'. The convex hui! of a set S consurnption possibility set, is the entire non-negative orthant, a
is the set of all vectors, x', that are convex cornbinations of finite considerably stronger conclusion can be derived; there is a feasible
subsets of S. An alternative and equivalent definition is that the allocation w** whose distance frorn the allocation tot is bounded
convex hull of S is the intersection of all convex sets of which S is a sirnilarly to the above. This irnplies that for each individual the
subset. It is clear that the convex hull of a convex set is the set distance between his bundle under the feasible allocation, x;t'*, and
itself; in general, the convex hull of S is the srnallest convex set that his chosen bundle, xh, approaches zero as the nurnber of participants
contains S. in the econorny grows.
Starting with a given econorny, then, we replace the production We have referred vaguely to the "degree of non-convexity"; it is
possibility set of each firrn by its convex hull. Sirnilarly, we replace necessary to introduce a specific rneasure. First, we define the
the preference ordering of each household by an ordering that radius of a set S, rad(S), as the radius of the srnallest ball (i.e., set of
satisfies the convexity property; this is done by replacing each upper the forrn {x llx - x 0 l s R}) containing S. We now define the
contour set, that is, {xh 1xh >=h x~} for each possible x~, by its convex inner radius r(S) of a set as follows: for every x E2 con S, there is, by
hull. We assurne that the convexified econorny so defined satisfies definition, a finite subset Te S that spans x. For every such x,
all the assurnptions of Chapters 3-5. Then it has a competitive find the infirnurn of rad(T) as T vares o ver all such spanning sets; 1 1

equilibriurn, that is, a price vector, p*' and a feasible allocation, then define r(S) as the suprernurn o ver all x in con S of this infirnurn. 1 1

to* = (x*,,Y'*), where x;t' is cost rninirnizing at sorne given level of Note that if x E S, it is, in particular, spanned by the one-elernent
the convexified utility and satisfies the budget constraint and yj is set {x} and therefore inf rad T over all spanning sets Te SisO. For
profit rnaxirnizing in the convexified production possibility set. a convex set, con S = S; hence, r(S) = O if and only if S is convex.
Each x;t' is a convex cornbination of vectors that belong to the corn- Thus, r(S) is a rneasure of non-convexity and will
be used as such in
pensated dernand correspondence for the original econorny for sorne this and the following chapter.
utility level and the given price vector, p*. It can be shown that we
can choose, for each h, one arnong these vectors, say xl;, in such a
3. Approximation to Market Equilibrium
way that
In accordance with the discussion in the previous section, we now
assurne that if each production possibility set is replaced by its con-
is bounded by a rnagnitude that depends on the rnaxirnurn degree of vex hull, then all thc assurnptions of Chapter 3 are satisfied.
non-convexity of the preference orderings. Sirnilarly, we can AssuMPTION l. A.3.1-A.3.4 hold when Y1 is replaced by con Y1 in
choose y}, which is profit rnaxirnizing in the original production each of thern.
possibility set at p*, such that the discrepancy
It is slightly less obvious how we replace a non-convex preference
ordering by a convex one. The original preference ordering
defines (and is defined by) the class of upper contour sets, that is, the
,
1 !
i

1
1

174 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 175

The rnethod of analysis is the following. Frorn the given econorny, is bounded by a rnagnitude that depends on the rnaxirnurn degree of
we construct a new one satisfying all the conditions of the existence non-convexity of the production possibility sets. The price vector,
theory of Chapters 3-5. Recall the definition of a convex hull. p*, and the allocation a ..t = (xt,y: together constitute an approxi-
1
')

(See D.B.3, D.B.12, and T.B.7.) A vector x' is said to be the convex rnate equilibriurn in the sense that the discrepancy between supply
cornbination of the vectors in a finite set T if there exists a non- and dernand is also bounded (with a rnodification for free goods).
negative real-valued function, a(x), defined for x E T, such that, No rnatter how large the econorny, the bound is deterrnined by the
2; a(x) = 1 2; a(x)x = x'. rnaxirnurn degree of non-convexity.
xeT xeT For a pure-exchange econorny in the special case where Xh, the
We will say also that the set T spans x'. The convex hui! of a set S consurnption possibility set, is the entire non-negative orthant, a
is the set of all vectors, x', that are convex cornbinations of finite considerably stronger conclusion can be derived; there is a feasible
subsets of S. An alternative and equivalent definition is that the allocation w** whose distance frorn the allocation tot is bounded
convex hull of S is the intersection of all convex sets of which S is a sirnilarly to the above. This irnplies that for each individual the
subset. It is clear that the convex hull of a convex set is the set distance between his bundle under the feasible allocation, x;t'*, and
itself; in general, the convex hull of S is the srnallest convex set that his chosen bundle, xh, approaches zero as the nurnber of participants
contains S. in the econorny grows.
Starting with a given econorny, then, we replace the production We have referred vaguely to the "degree of non-convexity"; it is
possibility set of each firrn by its convex hull. Sirnilarly, we replace necessary to introduce a specific rneasure. First, we define the
the preference ordering of each household by an ordering that radius of a set S, rad(S), as the radius of the srnallest ball (i.e., set of
satisfies the convexity property; this is done by replacing each upper the forrn {x llx - x 0 l s R}) containing S. We now define the
contour set, that is, {xh 1xh >=h x~} for each possible x~, by its convex inner radius r(S) of a set as follows: for every x E2 con S, there is, by
hull. We assurne that the convexified econorny so defined satisfies definition, a finite subset Te S that spans x. For every such x,
all the assurnptions of Chapters 3-5. Then it has a competitive find the infirnurn of rad(T) as T vares o ver all such spanning sets; 1 1

equilibriurn, that is, a price vector, p*' and a feasible allocation, then define r(S) as the suprernurn o ver all x in con S of this infirnurn. 1 1

to* = (x*,,Y'*), where x;t' is cost rninirnizing at sorne given level of Note that if x E S, it is, in particular, spanned by the one-elernent
the convexified utility and satisfies the budget constraint and yj is set {x} and therefore inf rad T over all spanning sets Te SisO. For
profit rnaxirnizing in the convexified production possibility set. a convex set, con S = S; hence, r(S) = O if and only if S is convex.
Each x;t' is a convex cornbination of vectors that belong to the corn- Thus, r(S) is a rneasure of non-convexity and will
be used as such in
pensated dernand correspondence for the original econorny for sorne this and the following chapter.
utility level and the given price vector, p*. It can be shown that we
can choose, for each h, one arnong these vectors, say xl;, in such a
3. Approximation to Market Equilibrium
way that
In accordance with the discussion in the previous section, we now
assurne that if each production possibility set is replaced by its con-
is bounded by a rnagnitude that depends on the rnaxirnurn degree of vex hull, then all thc assurnptions of Chapter 3 are satisfied.
non-convexity of the preference orderings. Sirnilarly, we can AssuMPTION l. A.3.1-A.3.4 hold when Y1 is replaced by con Y1 in
choose y}, which is profit rnaxirnizing in the original production each of thern.
possibility set at p*, such that the discrepancy
It is slightly less obvious how we replace a non-convex preference
ordering by a convex one. The original preference ordering
defines (and is defined by) the class of upper contour sets, that is, the
176 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSJS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 177

class of all sets of the form {xh xh :P:~t x~} as x~ vares over all
1 AssUMPTION 2. A.4.1-A.4.4 hold when :P:~t is replaced by :P:hlc
elements in Xh. (Of course, many elements x~ may define the same
upper contour set.) Of any two upper contour sets, one must always No doubt, it is possible to specify assumptions on the original
production possibility sets and preference orderings from which
include the other; in particular, they may include each other, in
A.7.1-A.7.2 could be deduced, but we refrain here.
which case they are identical. Now, if S 1 and S 2 are sets in the same
vector space and S 1 e S 2 , con S 1 e con S 2 Hence, among the In view of the basic theorem, T. 5.4, we can assert that, under these
class of sets that are convex hulls of the upper contour sets, it must assumptions, there exists a compensated equilibrium for the con-
also be true of any pair of such sets that one includes the other. It vcxified economy, in other words, that defined by replacing produc-
is possible, therefore, to define a new ordering, which we may refer tion possibility sets and upper contour sets by their convex hulls.
to as the convexijication of the original, by the condition that x 1 is That is, there exists a price vector p* and an allocation .w* = (a:* ,!f*)
preferred or indifferent to x 2 (in the new ordering) if every convex such that p* > O,
hull of an upper contour set that contains x 2 also contains x 1 (see x* :::;; y* + x, (1)
Figure 7-3). In symbols,
yj maximizes p*y1 subject to Yr E con Y1 , (2)
DEFINITION l. x~ :P:~t" x~ is defined to mean that for every x~ for x~ minimizes p*xh subject to xh :P:h1c x~, (3)
which x~ E con{xh 1 xh >=h x~}, it is also true that x~ E con{xh 1 :P:~t x~}.
p*xh* = M*h = P*-xh + 'Vd
, hf (p*y*)
r (4)
From the preceding remarks, the relation >=hlc is certainly con- f
nected, while transitivity follows directly from 0.7.1. Hence, :P:~tlc When convexity obtains, an equilibrium allocation achieves all of
is certainly an ordering. We now assume the following: feasibility, optimization for each individual at
equilibrium prices (profit maximization for firms, cost minimization
for given utility for households), and satisfaction of the household
budget constraints. With non-convexity, of course, we cannot hope
for so much. lnstead, we will find a price vector and two allocations,
one of which is feasible and the other optimal for each individual
and satisfying household budget constraints at the given prices, such
that in the aggregate the two allocations are close. Formally, we
introduce the following definition.
DEFINITION 2. A social-approximate compensated equilibrium of
modulus A is a price vector p* > O and two allocations, <o* =
(a:*,y*) and .wt = (a:t,y't), such that
(a) x* :::;; y*+ x,
(b) p[ = O if xt < y[ + X;,
(e) yj maximizes p*yr for Yr E Y,
(d) x); minimizes p*xh subject to xh :P:h xi;,
(e) p*x); = Mht = p*-xh + "d
, hf (P*Yr1) = M*h = P*-
xh
LEGEND: Original indifference curves f
+ 2: dh(p*yj),
______ Convexified indifference curves f
(f) l(x* -y*) - (xl - yt)l :::;; A.
Figure 7-3 Then the following theorem will be demonstrated.
176 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSJS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 177

class of all sets of the form {xh xh :P:~t x~} as x~ vares over all
1 AssUMPTION 2. A.4.1-A.4.4 hold when :P:~t is replaced by :P:hlc
elements in Xh. (Of course, many elements x~ may define the same
upper contour set.) Of any two upper contour sets, one must always No doubt, it is possible to specify assumptions on the original
production possibility sets and preference orderings from which
include the other; in particular, they may include each other, in
A.7.1-A.7.2 could be deduced, but we refrain here.
which case they are identical. Now, if S 1 and S 2 are sets in the same
vector space and S 1 e S 2 , con S 1 e con S 2 Hence, among the In view of the basic theorem, T. 5.4, we can assert that, under these
class of sets that are convex hulls of the upper contour sets, it must assumptions, there exists a compensated equilibrium for the con-
also be true of any pair of such sets that one includes the other. It vcxified economy, in other words, that defined by replacing produc-
is possible, therefore, to define a new ordering, which we may refer tion possibility sets and upper contour sets by their convex hulls.
to as the convexijication of the original, by the condition that x 1 is That is, there exists a price vector p* and an allocation .w* = (a:* ,!f*)
preferred or indifferent to x 2 (in the new ordering) if every convex such that p* > O,
hull of an upper contour set that contains x 2 also contains x 1 (see x* :::;; y* + x, (1)
Figure 7-3). In symbols,
yj maximizes p*y1 subject to Yr E con Y1 , (2)
DEFINITION l. x~ :P:~t" x~ is defined to mean that for every x~ for x~ minimizes p*xh subject to xh :P:h1c x~, (3)
which x~ E con{xh 1 xh >=h x~}, it is also true that x~ E con{xh 1 :P:~t x~}.
p*xh* = M*h = P*-xh + 'Vd
, hf (p*y*)
r (4)
From the preceding remarks, the relation >=hlc is certainly con- f
nected, while transitivity follows directly from 0.7.1. Hence, :P:~tlc When convexity obtains, an equilibrium allocation achieves all of
is certainly an ordering. We now assume the following: feasibility, optimization for each individual at
equilibrium prices (profit maximization for firms, cost minimization
for given utility for households), and satisfaction of the household
budget constraints. With non-convexity, of course, we cannot hope
for so much. lnstead, we will find a price vector and two allocations,
one of which is feasible and the other optimal for each individual
and satisfying household budget constraints at the given prices, such
that in the aggregate the two allocations are close. Formally, we
introduce the following definition.
DEFINITION 2. A social-approximate compensated equilibrium of
modulus A is a price vector p* > O and two allocations, <o* =
(a:*,y*) and .wt = (a:t,y't), such that
(a) x* :::;; y*+ x,
(b) p[ = O if xt < y[ + X;,
(e) yj maximizes p*yr for Yr E Y,
(d) x); minimizes p*xh subject to xh :P:h xi;,
(e) p*x); = Mht = p*-xh + "d
, hf (P*Yr1) = M*h = P*-
xh
LEGEND: Original indifference curves f
+ 2: dh(p*yj),
______ Convexified indifference curves f
(f) l(x* -y*) - (xl - yt)l :::;; A.
Figure 7-3 Then the following theorem will be demonstrated.
178 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 179

THEOREM l. Under A.7.1 and A.7.2, if Lis such that r(Y1) :::; L, all (For the last relation, see Lemma B.2.) Sincerad S" and rad(- Tr)
J, r({x" 1 x" ':?=" xh})
:::; L, all h, then there exists a social-approximate are all uniformly bounded by L, we can apply the Shapley-Folkman
,,
compensated equilibrium of modulus LVn,where n is the number of theorem (T.B.9) and assert the existence of
commodities.
1. ztEs" + :LC-Tr)
Proof We take p* and ro* to be the equilibrium for the con- h f
vexified economy, so that (1)-(4) are satisfied and, therefore, D.7.2
for which lx* - y* - ztl :::; LVn; that is, we can find x" E S" and
(a)-(b ). Sin ce y'J E con Y1 , y'J is the convex combination of at least
Yr E T1 such that
one finite subset of Y 1 . Among al! such subsets, choose the one with 1'

the smallest radius; by the definition of inner radius and the assump- zt = L x" - L Yr
h f
1

tion that r( Y1) :::; L, we can find a set, T1 e Y1 , that spans yj and 1

for which rad(T1) :::; L. By definition, there exists a non-negative- Then, with the aid of (5)-(7), it is clear that D.7.2(c)-(f) hold, and
valued function, a(y1), defined for Yr E T1 , such that T.7.1 is proved.
Remark. If the economy increases in size, say by increasel;> in the
L a(y1)y1 = yj L a(y1) = l. numbers of firms and households of roughly similar types, then we
~E~ ~E~
may expect the upper bound, L, on the non-convexities to remain
Clearly, we can assume a(y 1) > O without loss of generality, for
roughly constant; the theorem then assures us that the discrepancy
otherwise the corresponding y 1 can be deleted from T 1 without
between supply and demand (for non-free goods) will have the same
altering either of these relations. Then
upper bound in the aggregate and, therefore, will approach zero as
p*y'J = L
YET
a(yr)p*y r; a proportion to total supply or demand.

but Yr E Y 1 e con Y 1 foral! Yr E T1 . By (2) (profit maximization),


4. Approximation of Equilibrium for Individual Behavior
p*yj ;::: p*y1 for all Yr E T1 . With rx(y1) > O, al! Yr E T, it is neces-
sary that p*y1 = p*y'J foral! Yr E Tr, and therefore, certainly If we restrict ourselves to a pure exchange economy and assume
that for each household the consumption possibility set, X", is the
Al! y's in Tr maximize p*yr for Yr E Y1 (5)
non-negative orthant, the approximate equilibrium has a much
The set {x" 1 x" ':?="'' x;i'} is the convex hull of a set of the form stronger property, namely, we can find an allocation with the same
{x" 1 x" ':?=" x~}, for sorne x~. By the same argument, then, we can totals as ..v* (therefore also feasible) that is close to the individual
find a finite subset S" ofthis set, with rad(S") :::; L, such that S" spans optimal allocation a:;~. The closeness of two allocations is, of
x;i' and course, a much stronger property than the closeness of the market
totals.
All x"'s in S" minimize p*x" for x" ':?=" x~; (6)
DEFINITION 3. An individual-approximate compensated equilibrium
p*xh = p*x;!' for all xh in slt. (7) of modulus A is a price vector, p* > O, and two allocations, w** =
From (6) it is clear also that we can choose x~ to be any element of (x**,!f**) and to 1' = (xt,yt), such that
sh and that all elements of sh are indifferent. (a) x** :::; y** + X:,
By the construction, (b) pf = O if xt* < y* + X,
x* - y* = x;!' - yj E con S" + con(- Tr) (e) y} maximizes p*yr for Yr E Y,
h f h f (d) x/, minimizes p*x" for x" ':?=" xi,
(e) p*x); = M); = M;;',
=con[: S"+ ( -Tr)J.
lt .f (f) lto** - totl :::; A.
178 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 179

THEOREM l. Under A.7.1 and A.7.2, if Lis such that r(Y1) :::; L, all (For the last relation, see Lemma B.2.) Sincerad S" and rad(- Tr)
J, r({x" 1 x" ':?=" xh})
:::; L, all h, then there exists a social-approximate are all uniformly bounded by L, we can apply the Shapley-Folkman
,,
compensated equilibrium of modulus LVn,where n is the number of theorem (T.B.9) and assert the existence of
commodities.
1. ztEs" + :LC-Tr)
Proof We take p* and ro* to be the equilibrium for the con- h f
vexified economy, so that (1)-(4) are satisfied and, therefore, D.7.2
for which lx* - y* - ztl :::; LVn; that is, we can find x" E S" and
(a)-(b ). Sin ce y'J E con Y1 , y'J is the convex combination of at least
Yr E T1 such that
one finite subset of Y 1 . Among al! such subsets, choose the one with 1'

the smallest radius; by the definition of inner radius and the assump- zt = L x" - L Yr
h f
1

tion that r( Y1) :::; L, we can find a set, T1 e Y1 , that spans yj and 1

for which rad(T1) :::; L. By definition, there exists a non-negative- Then, with the aid of (5)-(7), it is clear that D.7.2(c)-(f) hold, and
valued function, a(y1), defined for Yr E T1 , such that T.7.1 is proved.
Remark. If the economy increases in size, say by increasel;> in the
L a(y1)y1 = yj L a(y1) = l. numbers of firms and households of roughly similar types, then we
~E~ ~E~
may expect the upper bound, L, on the non-convexities to remain
Clearly, we can assume a(y 1) > O without loss of generality, for
roughly constant; the theorem then assures us that the discrepancy
otherwise the corresponding y 1 can be deleted from T 1 without
between supply and demand (for non-free goods) will have the same
altering either of these relations. Then
upper bound in the aggregate and, therefore, will approach zero as
p*y'J = L
YET
a(yr)p*y r; a proportion to total supply or demand.

but Yr E Y 1 e con Y 1 foral! Yr E T1 . By (2) (profit maximization),


4. Approximation of Equilibrium for Individual Behavior
p*yj ;::: p*y1 for all Yr E T1 . With rx(y1) > O, al! Yr E T, it is neces-
sary that p*y1 = p*y'J foral! Yr E Tr, and therefore, certainly If we restrict ourselves to a pure exchange economy and assume
that for each household the consumption possibility set, X", is the
Al! y's in Tr maximize p*yr for Yr E Y1 (5)
non-negative orthant, the approximate equilibrium has a much
The set {x" 1 x" ':?="'' x;i'} is the convex hull of a set of the form stronger property, namely, we can find an allocation with the same
{x" 1 x" ':?=" x~}, for sorne x~. By the same argument, then, we can totals as ..v* (therefore also feasible) that is close to the individual
find a finite subset S" ofthis set, with rad(S") :::; L, such that S" spans optimal allocation a:;~. The closeness of two allocations is, of
x;i' and course, a much stronger property than the closeness of the market
totals.
All x"'s in S" minimize p*x" for x" ':?=" x~; (6)
DEFINITION 3. An individual-approximate compensated equilibrium
p*xh = p*x;!' for all xh in slt. (7) of modulus A is a price vector, p* > O, and two allocations, w** =
From (6) it is clear also that we can choose x~ to be any element of (x**,!f**) and to 1' = (xt,yt), such that
sh and that all elements of sh are indifferent. (a) x** :::; y** + X:,
By the construction, (b) pf = O if xt* < y* + X,
x* - y* = x;!' - yj E con S" + con(- Tr) (e) y} maximizes p*yr for Yr E Y,
h f h f (d) x/, minimizes p*x" for x" ':?=" xi,
(e) p*x); = M); = M;;',
=con[: S"+ ( -Tr)J.
lt .f (f) lto** - totl :::; A.
180 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 181

Note that Since xj, E X", x'h1 ;::: O; hence, x;i'* ;::: O for i E N if (18) holds.
Therefore, condition (16) is redundant.
lto** - tol = jL lx;i'* -
h
x);l
2
+ L IYJ* - yfiZ.
f
For i E P, xt > O and xf /xt < l. Therefore, if we define

Hence, if m is the number of agents in the economy and A is a ** = tX* x,


xhl t for i E P,
constant with respect to m, we can see by dividing both sides of (f) X

by m that the root-mean-square deviation between the bund1es


(1 2), (15), and (1 7) will be satisfied. lt remains to show that ( 13),
chosen by agents under the two allocations approaches zero.
(14), and (18) can be satisfied by choice of x;:'* (i E N). From (17),
THEOREM 2. In a pure-exchange economy where A.7.2 holds, X, is a, ;::: O. Let
the non-negative orthant for each h, and r({x, 1 x, :p., xh}) :s; L for
all h, there exists an individual-approximate compensated equilibrium if a> O.
of modulus LVn.
Let w" be arbitrary non-negative with
Proof We take p* and xt as in T.7.1. Take also x* as given
in T. 7.1, and we will find x** such that
L w" =
h
1 if a= O.
x** = x*, (8)
Define
p*x;i'* = p*x'h x;i'* ;::: O all h, (9)
Xhi** - Xhi
t + Wh (X* - Xt) for i E N.
x); 1 - x;:'1* is not opposed in sign to xt - xf for all h and i. (1 O)
From the definition of N in (1 1), (1 8) certainly holds. Sin ce
Jf such x** can be found, it is clear from T.7.1 and (8) and (9) that
D.7.3(a)-(e) are satisfied with x;i'* E X"; it wiii be shown'below that
that T.7.1 and (10) imply D.7.3(f) with A = Lvn.
w, = 1,
h

We first show that (8)-( 1O) can be satisfied. Let


(13) holds. Multiply by pf and sum over i E N:
P xi - xf > O} N = {i 1 xj - xf :s; 0}. (11)
= {i 1
L pf(x;:'* - Xh;) = w" L pf(xf - xt).
Conditions (8)-(1 O) then can be written iEN ieN

From T.7.1 and D.7.2(e), p*x;i' = p*xh, and therefore,


"'
L.. xhi** -- L..
"' *
xhl (i E P), (12)
h h
L pf(xf -
iEN
xt) = L ieN
L pf(x;i' 1 - x'h 1) == Lh ieP
L pt(x'ht - x;')
(i E N), (13) h

=ah= a,
"' Pi*(Xht** - xhi
L.. t ) - "'
L.. p*(xhi **) - ah,
t - xhi say (14) h
leN ieP in view of (12), so that
x~*;::: O (i E P), (15)
X~* ;:e: 0 (i E N),
L pf(x~* - x);) = w"a = ah;
(16) ieN

Xh- X~*;::: 0 (i E P), (17) that is, (14) holds. Hence, (8)-(10) have been shown to hold for a
suitable aiiocation .v**.
xl;t - X~* :s; O (i E N). (18) By T.7.1, lx* - xtl :s; LVn, and then, by (8), lx** - x11 :s; Lv.
180 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS MARKETS WITH NON-CONVEX PREFERENCES AND PRODUCTION 181

Note that Since xj, E X", x'h1 ;::: O; hence, x;i'* ;::: O for i E N if (18) holds.
Therefore, condition (16) is redundant.
lto** - tol = jL lx;i'* -
h
x);l
2
+ L IYJ* - yfiZ.
f
For i E P, xt > O and xf /xt < l. Therefore, if we define

Hence, if m is the number of agents in the economy and A is a ** = tX* x,


xhl t for i E P,
constant with respect to m, we can see by dividing both sides of (f) X

by m that the root-mean-square deviation between the bund1es


(1 2), (15), and (1 7) will be satisfied. lt remains to show that ( 13),
chosen by agents under the two allocations approaches zero.
(14), and (18) can be satisfied by choice of x;:'* (i E N). From (17),
THEOREM 2. In a pure-exchange economy where A.7.2 holds, X, is a, ;::: O. Let
the non-negative orthant for each h, and r({x, 1 x, :p., xh}) :s; L for
all h, there exists an individual-approximate compensated equilibrium if a> O.
of modulus LVn.
Let w" be arbitrary non-negative with
Proof We take p* and xt as in T.7.1. Take also x* as given
in T. 7.1, and we will find x** such that
L w" =
h
1 if a= O.
x** = x*, (8)
Define
p*x;i'* = p*x'h x;i'* ;::: O all h, (9)
Xhi** - Xhi
t + Wh (X* - Xt) for i E N.
x); 1 - x;:'1* is not opposed in sign to xt - xf for all h and i. (1 O)
From the definition of N in (1 1), (1 8) certainly holds. Sin ce
Jf such x** can be found, it is clear from T.7.1 and (8) and (9) that
D.7.3(a)-(e) are satisfied with x;i'* E X"; it wiii be shown'below that
that T.7.1 and (10) imply D.7.3(f) with A = Lvn.
w, = 1,
h

We first show that (8)-( 1O) can be satisfied. Let


(13) holds. Multiply by pf and sum over i E N:
P xi - xf > O} N = {i 1 xj - xf :s; 0}. (11)
= {i 1
L pf(x;:'* - Xh;) = w" L pf(xf - xt).
Conditions (8)-(1 O) then can be written iEN ieN

From T.7.1 and D.7.2(e), p*x;i' = p*xh, and therefore,


"'
L.. xhi** -- L..
"' *
xhl (i E P), (12)
h h
L pf(xf -
iEN
xt) = L ieN
L pf(x;i' 1 - x'h 1) == Lh ieP
L pt(x'ht - x;')
(i E N), (13) h

=ah= a,
"' Pi*(Xht** - xhi
L.. t ) - "'
L.. p*(xhi **) - ah,
t - xhi say (14) h
leN ieP in view of (12), so that
x~*;::: O (i E P), (15)
X~* ;:e: 0 (i E N),
L pf(x~* - x);) = w"a = ah;
(16) ieN

Xh- X~*;::: 0 (i E P), (17) that is, (14) holds. Hence, (8)-(10) have been shown to hold for a
suitable aiiocation .v**.
xl;t - X~* :s; O (i E N). (18) By T.7.1, lx* - xtl :s; LVn, and then, by (8), lx** - x11 :s; Lv.
182

But
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYS!S
T Chapter Eight
THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY

and
2 My bonds in thee qre all determinate.
(xt* - xt) 2 = [f(x~* - xf1)J For how do I hold thee but by thy
granting?
From (1 0), the sum in brackets consists of terms all of the same sign; -William Shakespeare, Sonnet 87
hence,
(xf* - xt) 2
(x~1* - x);1) 2
h

If we now sum over i, we see immediately that 1. Equilibrium in Bargaining


l.?t** - .?ttl :s; lx** - xtl :s; LVn, In the preceding chapters, and indeed in most of the remainder of
as was to be shown. the book, emphasis has been placed on the allocation of resources
through a price system. All individuals (except monopolists and
monopsonists) behave as though they can huy or sell unlimited
Notes
quantities at prices taken as given by_them. They do not take into
Traditional economics texts frequently assumed thc U-shaped cost account any resource Iimitation or tastes of the particular individual
curve in the context of a discussion of perfect competition; by implica- with whom they may be dealing.
tion, then, they were asserting something like the results of the present An entirely different approach is to assume that allocations are
chapter. As the modern study of the theory of competitive equi-
arrived at through quantity bargaining. The bargains considered
librium emphasized more strongly the importance of the convexity
assumption, efforts began to relax it. Farrell [1959] noted first that may be multilateral as well as bilateral. Thus any set of economic
non-convexities of individual economic units correspond to relatively agents are permitted to allocate resources between themselves pro-
small discontinuities in aggregate behavior. His paper gave rise to a vided only that their initial endowments and productive capabilities
considerable discussion, by Bator [1961] and especially by Rothenberg are sufficient so that the allocation is feasible without using the
[1960], who showed graphically in great thoroughness how with large
numbers of households the effect on aggregate demand is the same as if resources of other individuals.
the concavities in the indifference curves were replaced by straight lines. For simplicity, we first consider a pure exchange economy; pro-
A rigorous general treatment is dueto Starr [1969], on whose work the duction will be introduced in Section 8.5. We have to define sorne
present chapter is entirely based; he made use of sorne mathematical notions of equilibrium for bargains. These will take the form of
results developed by L. S. Shapley and J. H. Folkman, which have not specified conditions under which we would expect a bargain not to
yet been published by them, but which he reported in his paper. be maintained. One is the notion of dominance already introduced
An alternative, very bold approach has been taken by Aumann [1966].
To begin with, he assumes a continuum of households, each of infini- in defining Pareto efficiency (see D.4.12). Given a feasible alloca-
tesimal endowment. Then, by use of sorne deep results in measure tion, x, if there is another feasible allocation, x', such that every
theory, he demonstrates the existence of competitive equilibrium household is better off under x' than under m, that is, x~ >-" x 11 , all
without makirfg any assumptions about convexity. This approach h, then we expect that x cannot be the equilibrium of the bargaining
works because the discontinuity in the behitvior of any individual has process. Thus, we assume that equilibria in bargaining must be
infinitesimal weight in the aggregate, but so far it has been confined to
a pure-exchange economy. Pareto efficient. Again, an allocation is hardly an acceptable bar-
gain if any individual is better off with his initial endowment than
i,, with the proposed allocation; thus, x is not a bargaining equilibrium
:; if x1, "?- 1, x 11 for sorne h.
1 i :

.f' 1

183

J
182

But
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYS!S
T Chapter Eight
THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY

and
2 My bonds in thee qre all determinate.
(xt* - xt) 2 = [f(x~* - xf1)J For how do I hold thee but by thy
granting?
From (1 0), the sum in brackets consists of terms all of the same sign; -William Shakespeare, Sonnet 87
hence,
(xf* - xt) 2
(x~1* - x);1) 2
h

If we now sum over i, we see immediately that 1. Equilibrium in Bargaining


l.?t** - .?ttl :s; lx** - xtl :s; LVn, In the preceding chapters, and indeed in most of the remainder of
as was to be shown. the book, emphasis has been placed on the allocation of resources
through a price system. All individuals (except monopolists and
monopsonists) behave as though they can huy or sell unlimited
Notes
quantities at prices taken as given by_them. They do not take into
Traditional economics texts frequently assumed thc U-shaped cost account any resource Iimitation or tastes of the particular individual
curve in the context of a discussion of perfect competition; by implica- with whom they may be dealing.
tion, then, they were asserting something like the results of the present An entirely different approach is to assume that allocations are
chapter. As the modern study of the theory of competitive equi-
arrived at through quantity bargaining. The bargains considered
librium emphasized more strongly the importance of the convexity
assumption, efforts began to relax it. Farrell [1959] noted first that may be multilateral as well as bilateral. Thus any set of economic
non-convexities of individual economic units correspond to relatively agents are permitted to allocate resources between themselves pro-
small discontinuities in aggregate behavior. His paper gave rise to a vided only that their initial endowments and productive capabilities
considerable discussion, by Bator [1961] and especially by Rothenberg are sufficient so that the allocation is feasible without using the
[1960], who showed graphically in great thoroughness how with large
numbers of households the effect on aggregate demand is the same as if resources of other individuals.
the concavities in the indifference curves were replaced by straight lines. For simplicity, we first consider a pure exchange economy; pro-
A rigorous general treatment is dueto Starr [1969], on whose work the duction will be introduced in Section 8.5. We have to define sorne
present chapter is entirely based; he made use of sorne mathematical notions of equilibrium for bargains. These will take the form of
results developed by L. S. Shapley and J. H. Folkman, which have not specified conditions under which we would expect a bargain not to
yet been published by them, but which he reported in his paper. be maintained. One is the notion of dominance already introduced
An alternative, very bold approach has been taken by Aumann [1966].
To begin with, he assumes a continuum of households, each of infini- in defining Pareto efficiency (see D.4.12). Given a feasible alloca-
tesimal endowment. Then, by use of sorne deep results in measure tion, x, if there is another feasible allocation, x', such that every
theory, he demonstrates the existence of competitive equilibrium household is better off under x' than under m, that is, x~ >-" x 11 , all
without makirfg any assumptions about convexity. This approach h, then we expect that x cannot be the equilibrium of the bargaining
works because the discontinuity in the behitvior of any individual has process. Thus, we assume that equilibria in bargaining must be
infinitesimal weight in the aggregate, but so far it has been confined to
a pure-exchange economy. Pareto efficient. Again, an allocation is hardly an acceptable bar-
gain if any individual is better off with his initial endowment than
i,, with the proposed allocation; thus, x is not a bargaining equilibrium
:; if x1, "?- 1, x 11 for sorne h.
1 i :

.f' 1

183

J
184 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 185

These two principies can be subsumed into a more general one: To clarify sorne of these remarks, consider first the thrice-familiar
If any set of households can find an allocation rv' that is feasible Edgeworth box case-pure exchange, two households, convex indif-
given only their endowments and such that each member of the set ference maps (the usual restriction to two commodities is no sim-
is better off under m' than under sorne given allocation r:r, it cannot plification from the analytic viewpoint; it serves only to permit
be that m is a bat'gaining equilibrium. The two preceding principies graphic representation). The core consists of all allocations that are
are special cases in which the set of households in question consists Pareto efficient and that do not make either household worse off than
of all households or one household, respectively. We now formalize if it were to consume only its endowment. If the endowments are
these considerations by introducing the following definitions. sufficiently different in commodity proportions from each other, then,
with suitable indifference maps, the potential gains from trade are
DEFINITION l. A coalition is a set of households. Iarge. The core contains the allocation that maximizes the utility
DEFINITION 2. An allocation, rv, is feasible for coalition S if of household 1 subject to the constraint that household 2's utility is
at least what it receives from its endowment and, similarly, the
2: xh :s; xh.
heS heS
corresponding allocation with the two households' roles reversed.
For any utility leve! for household 1 between its endowment leve! and
Remark. Let V be the coalition composed of all households. the above' maximum, there will be an unblocked allocation that
Then an allocation that is feasible for V, according to D.8.2, is yields household 1 that utility leve!.
feasible in the usual sense (see D.4.5 for the special case in which In particular, the competitive equilibrium (or equilibria, if not
there is no production). unique) is Pareto efficient and certainly neither household can be
DEFINITION 3. An allocation, m, is blocked by coalition S if there forced below its endowment utility' leve!. Hence, the competitive
exists another allocation, rv ', that is feasible for coalition S such equilibria are in the core. However, with two households, the core
that x~ >- h xh for all h E S. might be much larger than the set of competitive equilibria. Sup-
pose now that a third household enters the economy. New possi-
DEFINITION 4. The core of a (pure-exchange) economy is the set of
bilities of bargaining and, therefore, of blocking arise from the
all allocations that are feasible and not blocked by any coalition.
two-member coalitions. Thus, a proposed allocation is blocked not
In particular, any allocation in the core is not blocked by the merely if any one household is driven below its endowment leve!,
coalition of all households, and therefore, is Pareto fficient, nor is but also if.any two members can jointly improve their lots by trades
it blocked by a coalition consisting of any one household. These that do not involve the third. This suggests that in sorne sense the
are properties possessed by the allocation corresponding to any range of unblocked allocations becomes smaller when there are more
competitive equilibrium, for any such is Pareto efficient and of households.
course any household must be at least as well off at the competitive It turns out that there is a natural way of formalizing the idea that
equilibrium as it would be without trade. This suggests what is, in with large economies the core tends to be close to the competitive
fact, the case-that there is a close connection between allocations equilibria. Roughly speaking (see Section 8.3 for details), we con-
achievable as competitive equilibria and those achievable as a mem- sider a sequence of larger and larger economies and, for each one,
ber of the core; but this connection holds only for economies in an unblocked allocation. Then for each economy we can find a
which competitive equilibria exist and cores are non-empty or at price system such that every coalition in every economy behaves
least where these conditions are approximately true. Further, and approximately like a group of price-taking utility maximizers; that
this is of great importance, the relation between competitive equi- is, the difference between the quantities the coalition receives in the
libria and unblocked allocations is especially close when any given given unblocked allocation and the total demands of the same set
economic agent is, in an appropriate sense, small relative to the en tire of households at those prices if they maximize utility under com-
market. petitive conditions is bounded uniformly in the size of the economy
184 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 185

These two principies can be subsumed into a more general one: To clarify sorne of these remarks, consider first the thrice-familiar
If any set of households can find an allocation rv' that is feasible Edgeworth box case-pure exchange, two households, convex indif-
given only their endowments and such that each member of the set ference maps (the usual restriction to two commodities is no sim-
is better off under m' than under sorne given allocation r:r, it cannot plification from the analytic viewpoint; it serves only to permit
be that m is a bat'gaining equilibrium. The two preceding principies graphic representation). The core consists of all allocations that are
are special cases in which the set of households in question consists Pareto efficient and that do not make either household worse off than
of all households or one household, respectively. We now formalize if it were to consume only its endowment. If the endowments are
these considerations by introducing the following definitions. sufficiently different in commodity proportions from each other, then,
with suitable indifference maps, the potential gains from trade are
DEFINITION l. A coalition is a set of households. Iarge. The core contains the allocation that maximizes the utility
DEFINITION 2. An allocation, rv, is feasible for coalition S if of household 1 subject to the constraint that household 2's utility is
at least what it receives from its endowment and, similarly, the
2: xh :s; xh.
heS heS
corresponding allocation with the two households' roles reversed.
For any utility leve! for household 1 between its endowment leve! and
Remark. Let V be the coalition composed of all households. the above' maximum, there will be an unblocked allocation that
Then an allocation that is feasible for V, according to D.8.2, is yields household 1 that utility leve!.
feasible in the usual sense (see D.4.5 for the special case in which In particular, the competitive equilibrium (or equilibria, if not
there is no production). unique) is Pareto efficient and certainly neither household can be
DEFINITION 3. An allocation, m, is blocked by coalition S if there forced below its endowment utility' leve!. Hence, the competitive
exists another allocation, rv ', that is feasible for coalition S such equilibria are in the core. However, with two households, the core
that x~ >- h xh for all h E S. might be much larger than the set of competitive equilibria. Sup-
pose now that a third household enters the economy. New possi-
DEFINITION 4. The core of a (pure-exchange) economy is the set of
bilities of bargaining and, therefore, of blocking arise from the
all allocations that are feasible and not blocked by any coalition.
two-member coalitions. Thus, a proposed allocation is blocked not
In particular, any allocation in the core is not blocked by the merely if any one household is driven below its endowment leve!,
coalition of all households, and therefore, is Pareto fficient, nor is but also if.any two members can jointly improve their lots by trades
it blocked by a coalition consisting of any one household. These that do not involve the third. This suggests that in sorne sense the
are properties possessed by the allocation corresponding to any range of unblocked allocations becomes smaller when there are more
competitive equilibrium, for any such is Pareto efficient and of households.
course any household must be at least as well off at the competitive It turns out that there is a natural way of formalizing the idea that
equilibrium as it would be without trade. This suggests what is, in with large economies the core tends to be close to the competitive
fact, the case-that there is a close connection between allocations equilibria. Roughly speaking (see Section 8.3 for details), we con-
achievable as competitive equilibria and those achievable as a mem- sider a sequence of larger and larger economies and, for each one,
ber of the core; but this connection holds only for economies in an unblocked allocation. Then for each economy we can find a
which competitive equilibria exist and cores are non-empty or at price system such that every coalition in every economy behaves
least where these conditions are approximately true. Further, and approximately like a group of price-taking utility maximizers; that
this is of great importance, the relation between competitive equi- is, the difference between the quantities the coalition receives in the
libria and unblocked allocations is especially close when any given given unblocked allocation and the total demands of the same set
economic agent is, in an appropriate sense, small relative to the en tire of households at those prices if they maximize utility under com-
market. petitive conditions is bounded uniformly in the size of the economy
T
186 GENERAL CMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 187

and of the coalition. Thus, for large coalitions, the approximation arms (see especially Schelling [1960]). If a coalition with monopoly
of the unblocked allocation to a competitive equilibrium is good power somehow makes it credible to all others that its demands will
relative to the magnitudes involved. not be compromised no matter how much it suffers and that none of
The implications of these conclusions are striking in many ways. its members can be drawn off into side bargains, then it may indeed
They suggest that under appropriate hypotheses, especially con- get its way. This is the value of burning one's bridges behind one.
vexity and the presence of all markets (absence of externalities), The difficulty with this type of argument is its asymmetry. If one
competitive equilibrium is very sturdy. There is no strong incentive coalition can threaten in this way, so can the coalition composed of
for subgroups to try to coalesce and to achieve,more than they could all others; the result is mutual destruction, by no means an uncom-
in the competitive equilibrium; for any such attempt would be mon occurrence in international politics, but much rarer among those
unstable. This is contrary to the view sometimes expressed that playing for economic advantage only. The asymmetry in expected
competitive equilibrium has an inherent instability in that it would behavior needed for the efficacy of threat strategies is plausible only
pay, for example, the owers of sorne one commodity to form a when based either on differential bargaining costs (so that the counter-
cartel and exploit their monopoly power. The theorems on the coalition cannot really form) or on extra-economic motives of
relation between competitive equilibria and the core suggest that any loyalty to and identification with sorne group, such as nation, class,
such attempt would be broken up by the formation of coalitions or race.
involving sorne buyers and sorne sellers of that commodity. The Then, if the economy is large, bargaining costs are low or at least
sellers ultimately can depend for sure only on what they can achieve uniform, and expectations of behavior are symmetric, the theorems
by trade among themselves, and of course, this may be very little on the core imply that departures from perfectly competitive
indeed. behavior occur only when there are non-convexities or market
In reallife, no doubt, there are many qualifications to these con- failures of one kind or another.
clusions. Perhaps the most important is the neglect of costs of
forming coalitions. Actually, it is probably the fact that the costs 2. Competitive Equilibria Are Unblocked
of forming coalitions of different kinds of individuals are different
rather than the mere existence of bargaining costs that is of critica! We already know that any competitive equilibrium is Pareto
importance. The competitive price system may be expected to pre- efficient (see T.5.3). By definition, any unblocked allocation is
vail when all costs of bargaining are high relative to the costs of Pareto efficient. We now show, by using the same reasoning as
price-directed markets,. If all costs of bargaining are low, then befo re,
again the theory of the core may be the chief predictive device; the THEORM l. In a pure-exchange economy, if (p* ,a:*) is a competitive
' theorems of this chapter suggest that under appropriate conditions, equilibrium, then x* belongs to the core.
the outcome will be very similar to that under perfect competition.
1
On the other hand, if the costs of bargaining are not uniform for Proof. Suppose a:* is blocked by coalition S (see D.8.1-D.8.4).
.1
1, different coalitions, then indeed quite different results may prevail. Then there exists a coalition S and an allocation x' such that
Adam Smith suggested in a famous passage that producers of the
1
:
1
same commodity find it easy to communicate with each other; in x;,::; i"
heS heS
(1)
1
' that case, the possibility of forming stable cartels to exploit con-
sumers may be enhanced. No real theory of this type has yet been and
developed, however. all hE S. (2)
There is another qualification arising out of the possible rationality
of seemingly irrational actions, a point that has emerged most From the definition of competitive equilibrium (see D.5.1), x~ 1:=" x,.
especially in the discussions of strategy in the context of nuclear if p*x" ::; p*i" for all h; hence, from (2), p*x~ > p*i1, all hin S, and
T
186 GENERAL CMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 187

and of the coalition. Thus, for large coalitions, the approximation arms (see especially Schelling [1960]). If a coalition with monopoly
of the unblocked allocation to a competitive equilibrium is good power somehow makes it credible to all others that its demands will
relative to the magnitudes involved. not be compromised no matter how much it suffers and that none of
The implications of these conclusions are striking in many ways. its members can be drawn off into side bargains, then it may indeed
They suggest that under appropriate hypotheses, especially con- get its way. This is the value of burning one's bridges behind one.
vexity and the presence of all markets (absence of externalities), The difficulty with this type of argument is its asymmetry. If one
competitive equilibrium is very sturdy. There is no strong incentive coalition can threaten in this way, so can the coalition composed of
for subgroups to try to coalesce and to achieve,more than they could all others; the result is mutual destruction, by no means an uncom-
in the competitive equilibrium; for any such attempt would be mon occurrence in international politics, but much rarer among those
unstable. This is contrary to the view sometimes expressed that playing for economic advantage only. The asymmetry in expected
competitive equilibrium has an inherent instability in that it would behavior needed for the efficacy of threat strategies is plausible only
pay, for example, the owers of sorne one commodity to form a when based either on differential bargaining costs (so that the counter-
cartel and exploit their monopoly power. The theorems on the coalition cannot really form) or on extra-economic motives of
relation between competitive equilibria and the core suggest that any loyalty to and identification with sorne group, such as nation, class,
such attempt would be broken up by the formation of coalitions or race.
involving sorne buyers and sorne sellers of that commodity. The Then, if the economy is large, bargaining costs are low or at least
sellers ultimately can depend for sure only on what they can achieve uniform, and expectations of behavior are symmetric, the theorems
by trade among themselves, and of course, this may be very little on the core imply that departures from perfectly competitive
indeed. behavior occur only when there are non-convexities or market
In reallife, no doubt, there are many qualifications to these con- failures of one kind or another.
clusions. Perhaps the most important is the neglect of costs of
forming coalitions. Actually, it is probably the fact that the costs 2. Competitive Equilibria Are Unblocked
of forming coalitions of different kinds of individuals are different
rather than the mere existence of bargaining costs that is of critica! We already know that any competitive equilibrium is Pareto
importance. The competitive price system may be expected to pre- efficient (see T.5.3). By definition, any unblocked allocation is
vail when all costs of bargaining are high relative to the costs of Pareto efficient. We now show, by using the same reasoning as
price-directed markets,. If all costs of bargaining are low, then befo re,
again the theory of the core may be the chief predictive device; the THEORM l. In a pure-exchange economy, if (p* ,a:*) is a competitive
' theorems of this chapter suggest that under appropriate conditions, equilibrium, then x* belongs to the core.
the outcome will be very similar to that under perfect competition.
1
On the other hand, if the costs of bargaining are not uniform for Proof. Suppose a:* is blocked by coalition S (see D.8.1-D.8.4).
.1
1, different coalitions, then indeed quite different results may prevail. Then there exists a coalition S and an allocation x' such that
Adam Smith suggested in a famous passage that producers of the
1
:
1
same commodity find it easy to communicate with each other; in x;,::; i"
heS heS
(1)
1
' that case, the possibility of forming stable cartels to exploit con-
sumers may be enhanced. No real theory of this type has yet been and
developed, however. all hE S. (2)
There is another qualification arising out of the possible rationality
of seemingly irrational actions, a point that has emerged most From the definition of competitive equilibrium (see D.5.1), x~ 1:=" x,.
especially in the discussions of strategy in the context of nuclear if p*x" ::; p*i" for all h; hence, from (2), p*x~ > p*i1, all hin S, and
188 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 189

therefore, dimension n such that r(S) ::;; L for sorne L. For any finite subfamily
F' e F, if
S'= :S,
SeF'
Since p* > O, however, it follows by multiplying both sides of (1) by
p* that then for every x E con S', there exists x' E S' such that lx - x'l ::;;
vv.
Thus, no matter how many of the sets S are being added, the
difference between the convex hull of the vector su m and the vector
a contradiction. sum itself is uniformly bounded. In particular, the discrepancy
between the vector average and its convex hull approaches zero
3. The Core Approximates the Competitive Equilibria where the vector average of a family of sets is obtained by dividing
each element of the vector sum by the number of sets in the family.
The near-converse to T.8.1 is much deeper and relies for proof on We now state a very general relation between cores and com-
theorems due to Shapley and Folkman and to Starr on the extent to petitive equilibria. In what follows, we shall understand by an
which the vector sum of a large number of sets is approximately a economy any set of households, where a household is defined by a
convex set (see Section B.4). We restate sorne concepts here. preference ordering and an endowment.
First, the radius of any bounded set S, rad(S), is defined to be the
radius of the smallest ball that contains S. Then, we define the THEOREM 2. Considera class of pairs (E,:X ), where E is an economy
inner radius of a set S as follows: Any point x in con S (the convex and ,; is a member of the core of E (assumed non-empty). For
hull of S) is the convex combination of the members of at least one each household h in any economy E, define
finite, and hence bounded, subset T of S. For any such x, consider x~ = x" u {x,},
the infimum of rad(T) for subsets T of S that span x, and then define
X "" = { x"" 1 x,, :2: x,' e
10r X'}
sorne x,' m ".
the inner radius, r(S), as the supremum over x in con S of these
intima: Assume that, for sorne L, r(X~) ::;; L for all h in all economies E in
r(S) = sup inf rad(T). the class. Then there exists a constant M ( = 2Lv', where n is the
xeconS Te S, T spans x number of commodities) and, for each E, a vector p* > O, p*e = 1,
Note that if x E S, it is spanned by the one-element set consisting such that for any economy E the following statements hold:
of itself, so that (a)
,,,1'

i inf rad(T) = O. (b)


Tc.S, Tspansx
i;'
Hence, if S is convex, so that x E: con S only if x E S, r(S) = O, and
Before proceeding to the proof, let us first comment on the
conversely, r(S) = O only if S is convex. Therefore, r(S) is a meas-
meaning of the hypotheses and the conclusions. The class of
ure of the extent to which a set is non-convex.
economies is quite arbitrary, but it may be thought of most usefully
We know that a vector sum of convex sets is convex. It is shown
as a sequence of economies growing larger and larger in the sense of
in T.B.l O that the vector su m of any number of sets that are of
consisting of more and more households. The household charac-
uniformly bounded non-convexity (as measured by the inner radius)
teristics of the different economies are statistically similar in the sense
uniformly approximates its convex hui!. We restate the result here.
that the distribution of preference orderings and endowment vectors
LEMMA l. Let F be a family of sets in a given vector space of among them are not too remote from each other. Each economy
188 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 189

therefore, dimension n such that r(S) ::;; L for sorne L. For any finite subfamily
F' e F, if
S'= :S,
SeF'
Since p* > O, however, it follows by multiplying both sides of (1) by
p* that then for every x E con S', there exists x' E S' such that lx - x'l ::;;
vv.
Thus, no matter how many of the sets S are being added, the
difference between the convex hull of the vector su m and the vector
a contradiction. sum itself is uniformly bounded. In particular, the discrepancy
between the vector average and its convex hull approaches zero
3. The Core Approximates the Competitive Equilibria where the vector average of a family of sets is obtained by dividing
each element of the vector sum by the number of sets in the family.
The near-converse to T.8.1 is much deeper and relies for proof on We now state a very general relation between cores and com-
theorems due to Shapley and Folkman and to Starr on the extent to petitive equilibria. In what follows, we shall understand by an
which the vector sum of a large number of sets is approximately a economy any set of households, where a household is defined by a
convex set (see Section B.4). We restate sorne concepts here. preference ordering and an endowment.
First, the radius of any bounded set S, rad(S), is defined to be the
radius of the smallest ball that contains S. Then, we define the THEOREM 2. Considera class of pairs (E,:X ), where E is an economy
inner radius of a set S as follows: Any point x in con S (the convex and ,; is a member of the core of E (assumed non-empty). For
hull of S) is the convex combination of the members of at least one each household h in any economy E, define
finite, and hence bounded, subset T of S. For any such x, consider x~ = x" u {x,},
the infimum of rad(T) for subsets T of S that span x, and then define
X "" = { x"" 1 x,, :2: x,' e
10r X'}
sorne x,' m ".
the inner radius, r(S), as the supremum over x in con S of these
intima: Assume that, for sorne L, r(X~) ::;; L for all h in all economies E in
r(S) = sup inf rad(T). the class. Then there exists a constant M ( = 2Lv', where n is the
xeconS Te S, T spans x number of commodities) and, for each E, a vector p* > O, p*e = 1,
Note that if x E S, it is spanned by the one-element set consisting such that for any economy E the following statements hold:
of itself, so that (a)
,,,1'

i inf rad(T) = O. (b)


Tc.S, Tspansx
i;'
Hence, if S is convex, so that x E: con S only if x E S, r(S) = O, and
Before proceeding to the proof, let us first comment on the
conversely, r(S) = O only if S is convex. Therefore, r(S) is a meas-
meaning of the hypotheses and the conclusions. The class of
ure of the extent to which a set is non-convex.
economies is quite arbitrary, but it may be thought of most usefully
We know that a vector sum of convex sets is convex. It is shown
as a sequence of economies growing larger and larger in the sense of
in T.B.l O that the vector su m of any number of sets that are of
consisting of more and more households. The household charac-
uniformly bounded non-convexity (as measured by the inner radius)
teristics of the different economies are statistically similar in the sense
uniformly approximates its convex hui!. We restate the result here.
that the distribution of preference orderings and endowment vectors
LEMMA l. Let F be a family of sets in a given vector space of among them are not too remote from each other. Each economy
~1
1 .i;
l.,
'1,

ii'' .
~ 1

190 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAtYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 191

in the cl~ss is assumed to have a non-empty core. This will certainly larger economies that are more and more nearly satiated with
li

be true 1f each possesses a competitive equilibrium, by T.8.1. We commodity 2 (relative to commodity 1) at levels only moderately 'ji'
.
~o .not exclude the possibility that households have non-convex greater than the initial endowment. Finally, though not illustrated, '1

mdlfference maps. However, it should be noted that as far as r(X~) may become indefinitely large if the non-convexities in the
present theorems go, the existence of an element in the core is indifference curve through x" become indefi.nitely large. (
guaran~eed only if preference orderings are convex; hence, it must It thus appears that the assumption that r(X~) is uniformly
be spec1ally assumed that the core has at least one member. bounded means that gains from trade do not become unbalanced,
The set 2" is, for any given household, the upper contour set that the households in the different economies have stath:;tically
defined by the given. allocati.on in the core. If there are any gains similar preference orderings, and that the non-convexities in them
fro.m t~ade at all, th1s set w1ll not contain the original endowment are bounded.
pomt, X~, so that ~~ will consist of an upper contour set (modified The conclusions state that, for each pair consisting of an economy
t~ allow for free d1sposal) ~lus all points to the northeast of x" (see and an unblocked allocation for it, we can choose a price vector so
Figure 8-1).. In general, :h1s set wdl not be convex even if the upper that -allocation approximately satisfies the conditions for a com-
contour set 1s, so that r(X ") > O. In Figure 8-1 the point in con X" pensated equilibrium. Conclusion (a) asserts that the sum of the
w_hose spannm? . set has. maximum radius is a point
' like xl, the span-"
absolute deviations from the budget constraint for the entire
~m~ set for wh1ch cons1sts of the points x" and x 2, where x2 is on the economy is uniformly bounded over all ecoriomies. This conclusion
md1fference curve through x". From Figure 8-1a it is clear that a has little force for small economies. But if both sides of (a) are
necess~ry condition that r(XZ) be bounded uniformly for all house- divided by the number of members of the economy E, it is asserted
holds ~~ all the econo~ies considered is that we are considering that the average discrepancy from a budget constraint is bounded by
ec~nom1es and allocatwns that are sufficiently balanced that the a number that is inversely proportional to the size of the economy
~ar?s from trade for any one household are bounded (so that the and therefore approaches zero for large economies. Conclusion (b)
md1n:erence curve through x" is not too far away from x1). Figure deals with the relation between the given unblocked allocation and
8-lb dlustra~es a different possible case where r(X~) is Iarge, namely, the compensated demand. It asserts that the cost savings totalled !,,
where there 1s a sequence of households associated with successively over an entire economy in which each household achieves the ,,
11

utility associated with the given allocation in the cheapest possible !11

way is also bounded uniformly; again, this implies that the unneces- 11:
',:
sary cost associated with the given allocation averaged over any large ,
economy is very small. :i
1
Proof For any economy E, Jet
1

X"= LX~.
he E

Since X" has been defined in terms of an allocation in the core of E,


it follows that it must be disjoint from the set of strictly feasible
(a) (b) LEGEND: social-demand vectors, that is, those for which
~X: x x= LX~.
Figure 8-x he E
~1
1 .i;
l.,
'1,

ii'' .
~ 1

190 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAtYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 191

in the cl~ss is assumed to have a non-empty core. This will certainly larger economies that are more and more nearly satiated with
li

be true 1f each possesses a competitive equilibrium, by T.8.1. We commodity 2 (relative to commodity 1) at levels only moderately 'ji'
.
~o .not exclude the possibility that households have non-convex greater than the initial endowment. Finally, though not illustrated, '1

mdlfference maps. However, it should be noted that as far as r(X~) may become indefinitely large if the non-convexities in the
present theorems go, the existence of an element in the core is indifference curve through x" become indefi.nitely large. (
guaran~eed only if preference orderings are convex; hence, it must It thus appears that the assumption that r(X~) is uniformly
be spec1ally assumed that the core has at least one member. bounded means that gains from trade do not become unbalanced,
The set 2" is, for any given household, the upper contour set that the households in the different economies have stath:;tically
defined by the given. allocati.on in the core. If there are any gains similar preference orderings, and that the non-convexities in them
fro.m t~ade at all, th1s set w1ll not contain the original endowment are bounded.
pomt, X~, so that ~~ will consist of an upper contour set (modified The conclusions state that, for each pair consisting of an economy
t~ allow for free d1sposal) ~lus all points to the northeast of x" (see and an unblocked allocation for it, we can choose a price vector so
Figure 8-1).. In general, :h1s set wdl not be convex even if the upper that -allocation approximately satisfies the conditions for a com-
contour set 1s, so that r(X ") > O. In Figure 8-1 the point in con X" pensated equilibrium. Conclusion (a) asserts that the sum of the
w_hose spannm? . set has. maximum radius is a point
' like xl, the span-"
absolute deviations from the budget constraint for the entire
~m~ set for wh1ch cons1sts of the points x" and x 2, where x2 is on the economy is uniformly bounded over all ecoriomies. This conclusion
md1fference curve through x". From Figure 8-1a it is clear that a has little force for small economies. But if both sides of (a) are
necess~ry condition that r(XZ) be bounded uniformly for all house- divided by the number of members of the economy E, it is asserted
holds ~~ all the econo~ies considered is that we are considering that the average discrepancy from a budget constraint is bounded by
ec~nom1es and allocatwns that are sufficiently balanced that the a number that is inversely proportional to the size of the economy
~ar?s from trade for any one household are bounded (so that the and therefore approaches zero for large economies. Conclusion (b)
md1n:erence curve through x" is not too far away from x1). Figure deals with the relation between the given unblocked allocation and
8-lb dlustra~es a different possible case where r(X~) is Iarge, namely, the compensated demand. It asserts that the cost savings totalled !,,
where there 1s a sequence of households associated with successively over an entire economy in which each household achieves the ,,
11

utility associated with the given allocation in the cheapest possible !11

way is also bounded uniformly; again, this implies that the unneces- 11:
',:
sary cost associated with the given allocation averaged over any large ,
economy is very small. :i
1
Proof For any economy E, Jet
1

X"= LX~.
he E

Since X" has been defined in terms of an allocation in the core of E,


it follows that it must be disjoint from the set of strictly feasible
(a) (b) LEGEND: social-demand vectors, that is, those for which
~X: x x= LX~.
Figure 8-x he E
'11

192 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECO!')OMY 193

For suppose x" E X", x" x. From the definitions of x;; and X"
!
there is a set S of the members of E such that

where x~ ;::: x" for sorne


Xh E Xh, X~ ;::>: X1o (3)
J
If S were the null set, x" ;::: X:, which is impossible if x" x. This ;
last conditon can be written, from (3),

and therefore,

or,
Figure 8-2
xh E xh for h E S.

Then, by Lemma 4.l(a), we can choose x;, >-h x", x~ arbitrarily close By Lemma 8.1, ifx- p,e' E con X", we can find x" E X" such that
to x" for each h E S, so that
IX: - p,e' - x"l :::; M' = vv.
But from (4), x" - X: must have at least one non-negative component.

and X~ >-h xh ~h xh, all hE S. From D.8.2-D.8.3, the allocation lx - p,e' - x"l = lp,e' + (x" - x)l ::::: p, + max(x7 j
- X) ::::: p,,
x is blocked by the allocation x', contrary to assumption. Hence,
we can assert so that
X: - p,e' E con X" implies p, :::; M'. (5)
X" is disjoint from {x 1x X:}. (4)
Since the set {p, 1 X: - p,e' E con X"} is bounded, it has a supremum,
Let e' be the column vector all of whose components are l. We p,*. Then the point X: - p,*e' is necessarily a boundary point of
will consider all vectors of the form X: - p,e', p, ;::: O, that belong to con X". Hence by a well-known theorem in convex set theory (see
con X". These points lie on a ray that starts from the social Corollary B.5), there is a supporting hyperplane to con X" at that
endowment point and proceeds in a strictly negative direction into point, that is, a vector p* =lo O for which
the strictly feasible region as long as the points on the rayare convex
p*x" ;::: p*(x - p,*e') for all x" E con X". (6)
combinations of the points in X" (see Figure 8-2). Since
In particular, (6) holds for x" E X". But by construction, if x" E X",
x= x"
he E then so does x" + ,\u for any ,\ ;::: O, u ;::: O. If we replace x" by
x" + ,\u in (6), divide through by ,\, and let ,\ approach infinity, we
and xh E x;; by definition, X: E X" and, therefore, certainly X: E con X".
conclude that p*u :::::: O for aii u ;::: O, which implies that p* ::::: O;
Hence, the endowment point, corresponding to p, = O, certainly
since p* =jo O, p* > O. From (6), we can assume without loss of
belongs to the desired set. The set may or may not contain other
generality that p*e' = l. Then we conclude from (6) that
points, for which p, > O. We wish to show that the set of such
points is bounded uniformly for all economies considered. p*x" ::::: p*x - p,* for all x" E con X", p* > O, p*e' = l. (7)
'
1,

~
11
:
;;
'11

192 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECO!')OMY 193

For suppose x" E X", x" x. From the definitions of x;; and X"
!
there is a set S of the members of E such that

where x~ ;::: x" for sorne


Xh E Xh, X~ ;::>: X1o (3)
J
If S were the null set, x" ;::: X:, which is impossible if x" x. This ;
last conditon can be written, from (3),

and therefore,

or,
Figure 8-2
xh E xh for h E S.

Then, by Lemma 4.l(a), we can choose x;, >-h x", x~ arbitrarily close By Lemma 8.1, ifx- p,e' E con X", we can find x" E X" such that
to x" for each h E S, so that
IX: - p,e' - x"l :::; M' = vv.
But from (4), x" - X: must have at least one non-negative component.

and X~ >-h xh ~h xh, all hE S. From D.8.2-D.8.3, the allocation lx - p,e' - x"l = lp,e' + (x" - x)l ::::: p, + max(x7 j
- X) ::::: p,,
x is blocked by the allocation x', contrary to assumption. Hence,
we can assert so that
X: - p,e' E con X" implies p, :::; M'. (5)
X" is disjoint from {x 1x X:}. (4)
Since the set {p, 1 X: - p,e' E con X"} is bounded, it has a supremum,
Let e' be the column vector all of whose components are l. We p,*. Then the point X: - p,*e' is necessarily a boundary point of
will consider all vectors of the form X: - p,e', p, ;::: O, that belong to con X". Hence by a well-known theorem in convex set theory (see
con X". These points lie on a ray that starts from the social Corollary B.5), there is a supporting hyperplane to con X" at that
endowment point and proceeds in a strictly negative direction into point, that is, a vector p* =lo O for which
the strictly feasible region as long as the points on the rayare convex
p*x" ;::: p*(x - p,*e') for all x" E con X". (6)
combinations of the points in X" (see Figure 8-2). Since
In particular, (6) holds for x" E X". But by construction, if x" E X",
x= x"
he E then so does x" + ,\u for any ,\ ;::: O, u ;::: O. If we replace x" by
x" + ,\u in (6), divide through by ,\, and let ,\ approach infinity, we
and xh E x;; by definition, X: E X" and, therefore, certainly X: E con X".
conclude that p*u :::::: O for aii u ;::: O, which implies that p* ::::: O;
Hence, the endowment point, corresponding to p, = O, certainly
since p* =jo O, p* > O. From (6), we can assume without loss of
belongs to the desired set. The set may or may not contain other
generality that p*e' = l. Then we conclude from (6) that
points, for which p, > O. We wish to show that the set of such
points is bounded uniformly for all economies considered. p*x" ::::: p*x - p,* for all x" E con X", p* > O, p*e' = l. (7)
'
1,

~
11
:
;;
1'
1"
11'

T --1
194 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TI-lE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 195 1'

For any coalition S, let in particular, or


x" =
heS
2x + 2 11
/leE-S
x11 ; p* 2(x11
/
- x~) ::::; ...*. (11)

since x 11 E X~, x 11 E X~, x" E X" e con X". Substitute in (7) and From the definition of S and (9),
recall that
p*2(x11
/
- x 11)::::; p* 2
/lEE -S
(x11 - x 11)::::; ...*. (12)

then Addition of (11) and (12) yields


p* 2 (x
heS
11 - x11 ) ::::; ...*. (8) 2 p*(x 11 - xn ::::; 2...* ::::; 2Lv',
/

Since (8) holds for any coalition S, it holds with S replaced by


from (5), so that (b) of the theorem holds.
E"' S.
(9)

Since the allocation a, is feasible, 4. The Case of Finitely Many Types of Households

We now turn to a much studied special case of T.8.2, for which a


since p* > O, stronger conclusion holds. Let us say that two households are of
p
*""- *""-
~X_
/
<p ~X,
/
the same type if they have the same preference ordering and the same
endowment vector. Suppose further we consider a sequence of
i
!l
or economies with increasing numbers of households in which, however, ~ !'' 1
there are only a fixed finite number of types of households in all the
economies in the sequence. Suppose finally that the successive
Add this last result to (8). economies represent balanced expansions; specifically, assume that
the numbers of households in the different types are equal for any
p* 2
he E-S
(x11 - x 11 ) ::::; ...*. (10) one economy. Hence, the size of the economy is indicated by the
number of households in any one type. The successive economies
In particular, let S = {h 1 p*x11 ;::: p*x11 }. Then may be thought of as obtained by replication of one .economy.
If it is assumed, in addition, that the preference orderings are
p*(x" - X) = IP*(X - x 11 )1 for hE S, p*(x11 - x 11 ) = IP*(x11 - x 11 )1
convex, then it will be shown that, with a slightly different definition
for hE E "' S. Then if we add (8) and (10) and use (5), conclusion of blocking, any unblocked allocation must yield the same utility to
(a) of the theorem follows. any two individuals in the same type (since any two such individuals
Now let x! minimize p*x11 subject to x" ~" x". Since x! E have the same indifference map, such an interpersonal comparison
X11 e X~, is meaningful). Thus an unblocked allocation, as far as utilities are
,, ""x*h E X" ' concerned, can be characterized by the utility allocation to types;
~
/ this has a fixed dimensionality as the size of the economy changes.
so that, from (7), It is obvious that the competitive equilibria for any economy of this
p* 2 x! ;::: p*x -
h
... *,
class are simply replications of the competitive equilibria for the
economy with one member per type, and each of these yields a
1'
1"
11'

T --1
194 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TI-lE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 195 1'

For any coalition S, let in particular, or


x" =
heS
2x + 2 11
/leE-S
x11 ; p* 2(x11
/
- x~) ::::; ...*. (11)

since x 11 E X~, x 11 E X~, x" E X" e con X". Substitute in (7) and From the definition of S and (9),
recall that
p*2(x11
/
- x 11)::::; p* 2
/lEE -S
(x11 - x 11)::::; ...*. (12)

then Addition of (11) and (12) yields


p* 2 (x
heS
11 - x11 ) ::::; ...*. (8) 2 p*(x 11 - xn ::::; 2...* ::::; 2Lv',
/

Since (8) holds for any coalition S, it holds with S replaced by


from (5), so that (b) of the theorem holds.
E"' S.
(9)

Since the allocation a, is feasible, 4. The Case of Finitely Many Types of Households

We now turn to a much studied special case of T.8.2, for which a


since p* > O, stronger conclusion holds. Let us say that two households are of
p
*""- *""-
~X_
/
<p ~X,
/
the same type if they have the same preference ordering and the same
endowment vector. Suppose further we consider a sequence of
i
!l
or economies with increasing numbers of households in which, however, ~ !'' 1
there are only a fixed finite number of types of households in all the
economies in the sequence. Suppose finally that the successive
Add this last result to (8). economies represent balanced expansions; specifically, assume that
the numbers of households in the different types are equal for any
p* 2
he E-S
(x11 - x 11 ) ::::; ...*. (10) one economy. Hence, the size of the economy is indicated by the
number of households in any one type. The successive economies
In particular, let S = {h 1 p*x11 ;::: p*x11 }. Then may be thought of as obtained by replication of one .economy.
If it is assumed, in addition, that the preference orderings are
p*(x" - X) = IP*(X - x 11 )1 for hE S, p*(x11 - x 11 ) = IP*(x11 - x 11 )1
convex, then it will be shown that, with a slightly different definition
for hE E "' S. Then if we add (8) and (10) and use (5), conclusion of blocking, any unblocked allocation must yield the same utility to
(a) of the theorem follows. any two individuals in the same type (since any two such individuals
Now let x! minimize p*x11 subject to x" ~" x". Since x! E have the same indifference map, such an interpersonal comparison
X11 e X~, is meaningful). Thus an unblocked allocation, as far as utilities are
,, ""x*h E X" ' concerned, can be characterized by the utility allocation to types;
~
/ this has a fixed dimensionality as the size of the economy changes.
so that, from (7), It is obvious that the competitive equilibria for any economy of this
p* 2 x! ;::: p*x -
h
... *,
class are simply replications of the competitive equilibria for the
economy with one member per type, and each of these yields a
196 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 197

all h and t. Now define for each t the average


utility allocation to types that is independent of the size of the U1(x 11) :o; Ut (Xht ) ' 1
econorny. It turns out, rernarkably, that the converse of this state- bundle received by rnernbers of that type, narne y,
rnent is true; if there is an unblocked allocation for each econorny 1< X
in the sequence that yields the sarne utility allocation to type~ for all xf = "L." y
ht
1!=1
the econornies, then there is a price vector (the sarne for all econo-
rnies) that, together with the given unblocked allocation, is a U(
By serni-strict quas1-conc~vlty: a) > Ut(x lt ) ' all t ' while. U1(x >
t X -
cornpensated equilibriurn for the econorny. U (x ) Since x is feas1b1e, 1t follows that
1 11 , le m m

~ Xf = k~ i i
W e assurne, then, that there are m types of households; each type
has, say, k rnernbers. We will index households with the double t-:1 h=1 t= 1
Xht :o; ~ X = ~/t
h= 1 t=1 -
subscript ht, for the hth household. of type t (h = 1, ... , k; t =
1, ... , m); the preference ordering, utility function, and endowrnent Consider the coalition that consists o~ all.th~ househ(ol~ t1mrnbere)d
h th 1th md1ces 1 t t - , ' m
vector of household h,t will have the single subscript t. 1 frorn all the types, t at ts, ose w- 't f llow~ that the alloca-
It is convenient here to use a slightly different definition of Since household 1,t has endow.ment X, 1 o rnodit vector xf is
blocking. tion that gives every house,hold m type t t.he com :Own that the
feasib1e for this coalition, and therefo~e, 1t h~s. beenTsh by D 8 5
DEFINITION 5. An allocation, x, is weakly blocked by coalition S if . . 11 b1 ked by th1s coal!tiOn. en . .
allocatiOn x ts wea < y oc h t U ( ) ol
there exists another allocation, x', that is feasible for coalition S 8 6 an allocation '" with the property t a t xh't
such that x~ >" x" for all hE S, x~ >-" x" for at least one hE S. and D .. '
U(x,)
1
y
1 for sorne tan
d , h' h" is not strongly unblocked.
sorne pair ' f t
DEFINITION 6. An allocation is strongly unblocked if it is feasible (b) By (a), then, if x is strong1y unb1ocked, xh't ""t xh"t or any '
and not weakly blocked by any coalition S. h', h". The sets
THEOREM 3. Suppose there are m types of households, where all Xht = {xht 1 Xht >t X~}
hoi.Jseholds of each type have the sarne endowrnent and the sarne are then the same for all h for any given. t, and, thheref?reX~~e~a;;
preference ordering, and Jet there be k households of each type. rnust b e t rue o f the Sets X"nt' defined as m T.8.2, t at 1s, ht - 11
Then for all h and t. Now note that
(a) The bundles yielded by any strongly unblocked allocation m le ~ " (13)
con x~, 1 = k con ~ X 11
to two households of the sarne type rnust be indifferent in 1=1 h=1 t- 1
the preference ordering for that type.
(Recall that for any set of vectors e' fe( means the set obtainedh l' d by
't
(b) If the nurnber of types and the endowrnents and preference fe by the sca1ar k) To see t e va 1 1y
orderings defining thern rernain constant, but k, the nurnber rnultip1ying each e1ernent 0 .' establish that
[: of (13), first note that for any convex set e, 1t ts easy to .
of households in each type, vares, if, for each k, a}" is a r
strongly unblocked allocation such that U1(xi;1) = u~ is the e= re.
sarne for all k (it is independent of h by (a)), and if r(X;) is != 1

finite when k = 1 for all t, then there is a price vector p* . L B 2 the convex hull of a vector surn
Second, as shown m ernrna . ' , X" - X" all h,
such that (p*,u1",x 1e) is a cornpensated equilibriurn for all is the vector surn of the convex hulls. Thus, smce nt - w
k, where ulc is the vector with mk cornponents defined by le le "
uftt =u~. con X~t = con X~t =k con X1~>
h=1 h=1
Proof. (a) Let x be a feasible allocation, and suppose that for
and therefore,
sorne t, say 1, there are two househo1ds, h' and h", such that U1 (x~, 1 )
ol U1 (x"" 1). Then for each t Jet the households be nurnbered so that m k m 1 '"
"" X"
con m '" X~t = ""
L. ""
L. con X""1 = L.
"" k con X t = k con t=l
L. lt
household 1 has the least utility under the given allocation; that is, t=l h=l t=1 h=l t=l

1
~ i

/
196 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 197

all h and t. Now define for each t the average


utility allocation to types that is independent of the size of the U1(x 11) :o; Ut (Xht ) ' 1
econorny. It turns out, rernarkably, that the converse of this state- bundle received by rnernbers of that type, narne y,
rnent is true; if there is an unblocked allocation for each econorny 1< X
in the sequence that yields the sarne utility allocation to type~ for all xf = "L." y
ht
1!=1
the econornies, then there is a price vector (the sarne for all econo-
rnies) that, together with the given unblocked allocation, is a U(
By serni-strict quas1-conc~vlty: a) > Ut(x lt ) ' all t ' while. U1(x >
t X -
cornpensated equilibriurn for the econorny. U (x ) Since x is feas1b1e, 1t follows that
1 11 , le m m

~ Xf = k~ i i
W e assurne, then, that there are m types of households; each type
has, say, k rnernbers. We will index households with the double t-:1 h=1 t= 1
Xht :o; ~ X = ~/t
h= 1 t=1 -
subscript ht, for the hth household. of type t (h = 1, ... , k; t =
1, ... , m); the preference ordering, utility function, and endowrnent Consider the coalition that consists o~ all.th~ househ(ol~ t1mrnbere)d
h th 1th md1ces 1 t t - , ' m
vector of household h,t will have the single subscript t. 1 frorn all the types, t at ts, ose w- 't f llow~ that the alloca-
It is convenient here to use a slightly different definition of Since household 1,t has endow.ment X, 1 o rnodit vector xf is
blocking. tion that gives every house,hold m type t t.he com :Own that the
feasib1e for this coalition, and therefo~e, 1t h~s. beenTsh by D 8 5
DEFINITION 5. An allocation, x, is weakly blocked by coalition S if . . 11 b1 ked by th1s coal!tiOn. en . .
allocatiOn x ts wea < y oc h t U ( ) ol
there exists another allocation, x', that is feasible for coalition S 8 6 an allocation '" with the property t a t xh't
such that x~ >" x" for all hE S, x~ >-" x" for at least one hE S. and D .. '
U(x,)
1
y
1 for sorne tan
d , h' h" is not strongly unblocked.
sorne pair ' f t
DEFINITION 6. An allocation is strongly unblocked if it is feasible (b) By (a), then, if x is strong1y unb1ocked, xh't ""t xh"t or any '
and not weakly blocked by any coalition S. h', h". The sets
THEOREM 3. Suppose there are m types of households, where all Xht = {xht 1 Xht >t X~}
hoi.Jseholds of each type have the sarne endowrnent and the sarne are then the same for all h for any given. t, and, thheref?reX~~e~a;;
preference ordering, and Jet there be k households of each type. rnust b e t rue o f the Sets X"nt' defined as m T.8.2, t at 1s, ht - 11
Then for all h and t. Now note that
(a) The bundles yielded by any strongly unblocked allocation m le ~ " (13)
con x~, 1 = k con ~ X 11
to two households of the sarne type rnust be indifferent in 1=1 h=1 t- 1
the preference ordering for that type.
(Recall that for any set of vectors e' fe( means the set obtainedh l' d by
't
(b) If the nurnber of types and the endowrnents and preference fe by the sca1ar k) To see t e va 1 1y
orderings defining thern rernain constant, but k, the nurnber rnultip1ying each e1ernent 0 .' establish that
[: of (13), first note that for any convex set e, 1t ts easy to .
of households in each type, vares, if, for each k, a}" is a r
strongly unblocked allocation such that U1(xi;1) = u~ is the e= re.
sarne for all k (it is independent of h by (a)), and if r(X;) is != 1

finite when k = 1 for all t, then there is a price vector p* . L B 2 the convex hull of a vector surn
Second, as shown m ernrna . ' , X" - X" all h,
such that (p*,u1",x 1e) is a cornpensated equilibriurn for all is the vector surn of the convex hulls. Thus, smce nt - w
k, where ulc is the vector with mk cornponents defined by le le "
uftt =u~. con X~t = con X~t =k con X1~>
h=1 h=1
Proof. (a) Let x be a feasible allocation, and suppose that for
and therefore,
sorne t, say 1, there are two househo1ds, h' and h", such that U1 (x~, 1 )
ol U1 (x"" 1). Then for each t Jet the households be nurnbered so that m k m 1 '"
"" X"
con m '" X~t = ""
L. ""
L. con X""1 = L.
"" k con X t = k con t=l
L. lt
household 1 has the least utility under the given allocation; that is, t=l h=l t=1 h=l t=l

1
~ i

/
198 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 199

i Since a; is strongly unblocked, it certainly belongs to the core, and The definitions of blocked allocations and of the core (D.8.3-D.8.4)
!11, T.8.2 and its proof can be applied. Let remain unchanged, provided feasibility is understood in the sense of
D.8.7.
p," = sup{p, 1 k t~ xt - p,e' E con t~ "~ x~J An unblocked consumption allocation, ii, then has associated
with it a production vector, y, which makes it feasible; the pair
From (13), it is obvious that p, 1' = kp, 1 From the hypothesis, the (:V,y) will be referred to as an unblocked allocation. For any such
sets X,t are independent of k, as well as of h; therefore, the same is allocation, we can define x;; as in the statement of T.8.2. Now
true of X~t Since there are then only finitely many distinct such define
sets and since r(X~t) is finite for each such, it follows that r(X~t) is
.ji
'
bounded above uniformly over all households in all economies in the z~ = x~- Y z" = z~.
he E
1, sequence formed by letting n increase indefinitely. Therefore, by
,11 Since Y is a cone,
l' (5), fk'' is bounded above uniformly in n. But if fk" = kfk 1 ;:;:: O, this
'.'1'
1:
. '
is possible only if fk 1 = O, and therefore fk'' = O, all k. We can take 2, Y= y
heS
1 ,,
M= O in T.8.2. Then, p*x, = p*x, = p*xt, that is, at the prices 1

p*, x, minimizes the cost of achieving its utility and, at the same for any coalition S. If we use D.8.7 and the definition of blocking,
lt.
time, that bundle satisfies the budget constraint. Hence, there is we can use the same reasoning as in the proof of T.8.2 to show the
exactly a competitive equilibrium. following extension of (4): 11

::1

Z" is disjoint from {x 1 X x}. (14) i

5, The Core of a Productive Economy l!!


Assume that r(Z~) s L for all h in all economies E for sorne L. '1

The preceding two theorems concern only the case of a pure 1

We can then parallel the arguments of T.8.2. As there, the set


exchange economy. Sorne care must be taken in the introduction
{/k 1 x - p,e'} E con Z" has a supremum, fk*, not exceeding M=
of production into the theory of the core. Here we start without a
L Vn. Hence, we can find p* so that
concept of prices and a fortiori of profits. The model of Chapters
3-5, with production taking place in firms separate from households p*z" ;:;:: p*x - p,* for all z" E con Z", p* > O, p*e' = l. (15)
and profits then being distributed to the firmsl owners, is inappro-
priate to the present discussion; it might be said that an adequate Since Z" = ;
heE
X~ - ;
heE
Y= X" - Y, we have, from (15),
theory of bargaining should explain the formation of firms, not
merely take them for granted.
p*x" ;:;:: p*x - fk* + p*y for all x" E X", y E Y. (16)
As an alternative, it will be assumed that there is a production Clearly, then, p*y is bounded above for y E Y. Since Y is a cone,
possibility set associated with each possible coalition. The simplest it must be that
case is that in which this is the same, a convex cone Y, for each p*y s O for all y E Y. (17)
coalition. It will be seen later that, with a suitable redefinition of
the commodity space, this condition is less restrictive than it might If we set y = O in (16), we have (7), so that (8) and (9) still hold.
appear at first. Since (:V,y) is a feasible allocation,
We can now generalize the definitions of feasibility.
2,x" s x, +y,
11 h
DEFINITION 7. A consumption allocation, x, is feasible for a coali-
tion, S, if, for sorne y E Y, and since p* > O,
x, s x, +y.
/leS heS
p* ~
"' x"
- s p * "' -
~ x, + p*-y. (18)
h h
198 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 199

i Since a; is strongly unblocked, it certainly belongs to the core, and The definitions of blocked allocations and of the core (D.8.3-D.8.4)
!11, T.8.2 and its proof can be applied. Let remain unchanged, provided feasibility is understood in the sense of
D.8.7.
p," = sup{p, 1 k t~ xt - p,e' E con t~ "~ x~J An unblocked consumption allocation, ii, then has associated
with it a production vector, y, which makes it feasible; the pair
From (13), it is obvious that p, 1' = kp, 1 From the hypothesis, the (:V,y) will be referred to as an unblocked allocation. For any such
sets X,t are independent of k, as well as of h; therefore, the same is allocation, we can define x;; as in the statement of T.8.2. Now
true of X~t Since there are then only finitely many distinct such define
sets and since r(X~t) is finite for each such, it follows that r(X~t) is
.ji
'
bounded above uniformly over all households in all economies in the z~ = x~- Y z" = z~.
he E
1, sequence formed by letting n increase indefinitely. Therefore, by
,11 Since Y is a cone,
l' (5), fk'' is bounded above uniformly in n. But if fk" = kfk 1 ;:;:: O, this
'.'1'
1:
. '
is possible only if fk 1 = O, and therefore fk'' = O, all k. We can take 2, Y= y
heS
1 ,,
M= O in T.8.2. Then, p*x, = p*x, = p*xt, that is, at the prices 1

p*, x, minimizes the cost of achieving its utility and, at the same for any coalition S. If we use D.8.7 and the definition of blocking,
lt.
time, that bundle satisfies the budget constraint. Hence, there is we can use the same reasoning as in the proof of T.8.2 to show the
exactly a competitive equilibrium. following extension of (4): 11

::1

Z" is disjoint from {x 1 X x}. (14) i

5, The Core of a Productive Economy l!!


Assume that r(Z~) s L for all h in all economies E for sorne L. '1

The preceding two theorems concern only the case of a pure 1

We can then parallel the arguments of T.8.2. As there, the set


exchange economy. Sorne care must be taken in the introduction
{/k 1 x - p,e'} E con Z" has a supremum, fk*, not exceeding M=
of production into the theory of the core. Here we start without a
L Vn. Hence, we can find p* so that
concept of prices and a fortiori of profits. The model of Chapters
3-5, with production taking place in firms separate from households p*z" ;:;:: p*x - p,* for all z" E con Z", p* > O, p*e' = l. (15)
and profits then being distributed to the firmsl owners, is inappro-
priate to the present discussion; it might be said that an adequate Since Z" = ;
heE
X~ - ;
heE
Y= X" - Y, we have, from (15),
theory of bargaining should explain the formation of firms, not
merely take them for granted.
p*x" ;:;:: p*x - fk* + p*y for all x" E X", y E Y. (16)
As an alternative, it will be assumed that there is a production Clearly, then, p*y is bounded above for y E Y. Since Y is a cone,
possibility set associated with each possible coalition. The simplest it must be that
case is that in which this is the same, a convex cone Y, for each p*y s O for all y E Y. (17)
coalition. It will be seen later that, with a suitable redefinition of
the commodity space, this condition is less restrictive than it might If we set y = O in (16), we have (7), so that (8) and (9) still hold.
appear at first. Since (:V,y) is a feasible allocation,
We can now generalize the definitions of feasibility.
2,x" s x, +y,
11 h
DEFINITION 7. A consumption allocation, x, is feasible for a coali-
tion, S, if, for sorne y E Y, and since p* > O,
x, s x, +y.
/leS heS
p* ~
"' x"
- s p * "' -
~ x, + p*-y. (18)
h h
1,'

T
1

200 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 201


In view of (7), however, (10) still holds, and therefore, T.8.2(a) can It will then be assumed that the production possibility set for a
be deduced as befare. From (18) and (8) (with S = E), we can also coalition S depends only on its profile and, therefore, can be repre-
deduce sented as Y[k(S)]. Thus, Y(k) is a correspondence mapping vectors
p*y 2: -.,*. (19) with non-negative integer components into production possibility
Since (10) and (7) are still valid, it follows also that the argument sets. We assume first,
leading to T.8.2(b) is still valid. AssUMPTION l. For each non-negative integer vector k, Y(k)
Tr-IEOREM 4. Consider a class of economies E such that the produc- satisfies assumptions A.3.1-A.3.4.
tion possibility sets for all coalitions in a given economy are the same Suppose two coalitions with the same profiles combine into one.
convex cone Y (\vhich may depend on E). For each E, consider an In the absence of any kind of increasing returns to scale, the pro-
allocation (::V,Y) in its core (assumed non-empty). For each house- duction possibility set may be presumed to undergo merely a scale
hold h in any economy E, define, expansion.
Xh = {xit 1 xit >h xlt} X~ = Xh U {x~t} AssuMPTION 2. For any non-negative integer N and any non-
1
11
X~ = {x;; x;; 1 2: x~ for sorne x;, Ex;,} Y.z~ = x;;- negative integer vector k, Y(Nk) = NY(k).
li'1 11
Assume that, for sorne L, r(Z~) s; L for all h in all economies E in Although Y(k) is defined in the first instance only for integer
:11
the class. Then there exists a constant M ( = 2LVn, where n is the vectors, A.8.2 permits a natural extension to rational vectors. If k
number of commodities) and, for each E, a vector p* > O, such that is rational, choose N so that Nk is integer valued. Then Y(Nk) is
11,
for any economy E, the following statements hold: well defined; we then define Y(k) to mean Y(Nk)/N, so that A.8.2
(a) .L IP*(xlt - xlt)l s: M; remains valid in the extended domain of definition. Note that this
lliil' hE E
is a proper definition, for the set Y(Nk)/N is the same for any
!::1
;1''1
(b) p* x, - min p*x" S: M; integer N for which Nk is integer valued.
hE E hE E Xh~h;:'l~
:1 It is now reasonable to insist that the correspondence Y(k) defined
(e) - M s; p*y s; O; p*y s; O, all y in Y.
for rational vectors k has appropriate continuity properties. Specifi-
Part (e) shows that the production decision may not be profit cally, it will be assumed that there exists a continuous correspondence,
maximizing, but that the departure from profit maximization is Y(k), defined for all non-negative vectors k, that coincides on the
1!
'1'
bounded. Thus, for large economies, the' difference between actual rationals with the just-described extension of Y(k) from integer
and maximum profits becomes small relative to any measure of the valued vectors k. (Recall, from Section 4.5, that a correspondence
'i is continuous if it is both lower and upper semi-continuous.)
1
size of the economy.

,, We now argue that seemingly more general hypotheses about the AssuMPTION 3. There exists a continuous correspondence Y(k),
'1'
11
production possibility sets available to coalitions lead essentially to defined for all k 2: O, such that for any non-negative rational k and
the above assumption that every such production possibility set is positive integer N for which Nk is integer valued, Y(Nk)/N = Y(k).
'11
the same convex cone (within a given economy). Essentially the Suppose now that two disjoint coalitions, S 1 and S 2 , combine into
argument is that any productive capacities that distinguish individuals one. Presumab1y one possib1e way of organizing production would
as they enter into different coalitions can be treated as separate be to split again, produce in the component coalitions, and then total
1
1,
commodities. It will be assumed that households are of finitely the resulting production vectors. In symbols then, Y[k(S1 )] +
1
many productive types (say, m in number); any two households of the Y[k(S2 )] e Y[k(S1 U S2 )]. Since k(S1 U S2 ) = k(S1 ) + k(S2 ), we
same productive type are interchangeable in production. can write this assumption of super additivity as follows:
1

DEFINITION 8. The profile of a coalition S, k(S), is an m vector such AssuMPTION 4. Y(k 1) + Y(k 2) e Y(k 1 + k 2) for any non-negative
that k 1(S) is the number of households of productive type t in S. integer vectors k\k 2 .

1:
L
1,'

T
1

200 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 201


In view of (7), however, (10) still holds, and therefore, T.8.2(a) can It will then be assumed that the production possibility set for a
be deduced as befare. From (18) and (8) (with S = E), we can also coalition S depends only on its profile and, therefore, can be repre-
deduce sented as Y[k(S)]. Thus, Y(k) is a correspondence mapping vectors
p*y 2: -.,*. (19) with non-negative integer components into production possibility
Since (10) and (7) are still valid, it follows also that the argument sets. We assume first,
leading to T.8.2(b) is still valid. AssUMPTION l. For each non-negative integer vector k, Y(k)
Tr-IEOREM 4. Consider a class of economies E such that the produc- satisfies assumptions A.3.1-A.3.4.
tion possibility sets for all coalitions in a given economy are the same Suppose two coalitions with the same profiles combine into one.
convex cone Y (\vhich may depend on E). For each E, consider an In the absence of any kind of increasing returns to scale, the pro-
allocation (::V,Y) in its core (assumed non-empty). For each house- duction possibility set may be presumed to undergo merely a scale
hold h in any economy E, define, expansion.
Xh = {xit 1 xit >h xlt} X~ = Xh U {x~t} AssuMPTION 2. For any non-negative integer N and any non-
1
11
X~ = {x;; x;; 1 2: x~ for sorne x;, Ex;,} Y.z~ = x;;- negative integer vector k, Y(Nk) = NY(k).
li'1 11
Assume that, for sorne L, r(Z~) s; L for all h in all economies E in Although Y(k) is defined in the first instance only for integer
:11
the class. Then there exists a constant M ( = 2LVn, where n is the vectors, A.8.2 permits a natural extension to rational vectors. If k
number of commodities) and, for each E, a vector p* > O, such that is rational, choose N so that Nk is integer valued. Then Y(Nk) is
11,
for any economy E, the following statements hold: well defined; we then define Y(k) to mean Y(Nk)/N, so that A.8.2
(a) .L IP*(xlt - xlt)l s: M; remains valid in the extended domain of definition. Note that this
lliil' hE E
is a proper definition, for the set Y(Nk)/N is the same for any
!::1
;1''1
(b) p* x, - min p*x" S: M; integer N for which Nk is integer valued.
hE E hE E Xh~h;:'l~
:1 It is now reasonable to insist that the correspondence Y(k) defined
(e) - M s; p*y s; O; p*y s; O, all y in Y.
for rational vectors k has appropriate continuity properties. Specifi-
Part (e) shows that the production decision may not be profit cally, it will be assumed that there exists a continuous correspondence,
maximizing, but that the departure from profit maximization is Y(k), defined for all non-negative vectors k, that coincides on the
1!
'1'
bounded. Thus, for large economies, the' difference between actual rationals with the just-described extension of Y(k) from integer
and maximum profits becomes small relative to any measure of the valued vectors k. (Recall, from Section 4.5, that a correspondence
'i is continuous if it is both lower and upper semi-continuous.)
1
size of the economy.

,, We now argue that seemingly more general hypotheses about the AssuMPTION 3. There exists a continuous correspondence Y(k),
'1'
11
production possibility sets available to coalitions lead essentially to defined for all k 2: O, such that for any non-negative rational k and
the above assumption that every such production possibility set is positive integer N for which Nk is integer valued, Y(Nk)/N = Y(k).
'11
the same convex cone (within a given economy). Essentially the Suppose now that two disjoint coalitions, S 1 and S 2 , combine into
argument is that any productive capacities that distinguish individuals one. Presumab1y one possib1e way of organizing production would
as they enter into different coalitions can be treated as separate be to split again, produce in the component coalitions, and then total
1
1,
commodities. It will be assumed that households are of finitely the resulting production vectors. In symbols then, Y[k(S1 )] +
1
many productive types (say, m in number); any two households of the Y[k(S2 )] e Y[k(S1 U S2 )]. Since k(S1 U S2 ) = k(S1 ) + k(S2 ), we
same productive type are interchangeable in production. can write this assumption of super additivity as follows:
1

DEFINITION 8. The profile of a coalition S, k(S), is an m vector such AssuMPTION 4. Y(k 1) + Y(k 2) e Y(k 1 + k 2) for any non-negative
that k 1(S) is the number of households of productive type t in S. integer vectors k\k 2 .

1:
L
T
202 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 203
1
1
,

It is easy to verify, frorn the continuity of Y(k), that the analogs of DEFINITION 9. An allocation (x,y) is feasible for a coalition S if,
A.8.2 and A.8.4 hold for all non-negative k, not rnerely those with for ~orne y E Y[k(S)],
integer values. Note first the following generallernrna.
LEMMA 2. If <D(x) is lower serni-continuous, ifi(x) upper serni-
continuous, and {xv} a sequence converging to x such that <D(xv) e The definitions of blocked allocations and of the core then rernain
ifi(xv), all v, then <D(x) e ifi(x). unchanged in forrn.
Proof Let y E <D(x). By definition of lower serni-continuity, THEOREM 5. Suppose that the production possibility sets of the
there is a sequence {yv}, yv E <D(xv), all v, yv ___,..y. Then by hypothe- coalitions in each econorny E in a class satisfy A.8.1-A.8.4. For
sis yv E r/J(xv), all v, and by the upper serni-continuity of fl, y E ifi(x). each E, consideran allocation (.V, y) in its core (assurned non-ernpty).
Define Y = {(y,- k) / y E Y(k)}. For each household h of produc-
Corollary 2. If <D(x) and ifi(x) are continuous correspondences
tive type t in any econorny E, define the following sets in (n + m)-
and {xv} is a sequence converging to x such that <D(xv) = r/1(xv), all space.
v, then <D(x) = ifi(x).

Now let ,\ be any non-negative real nurnber, k any non-negative


vector. Let {,\v} be a sequence of non-negative rational nurnbers
converging to ,\, {kv} a sequence of non-negative rational vectors
converging to k, and for each v, Nv a positive integer such that
X "h-- {x"h x"h>
J - x'h for sorne x;
1 E X~},

,\vNv and AvNvkv are both integer valued. Then, by A.8.2-A.8.3, Z~ =X~- Y.
Assurne that for sorne L, r(Z~) .:::; L, for all h in all econornies E in
the class. Then there exists a constant M= 2LVn + m and, for
Divide the last equality by Nv, and let v approach infinity. Frorn each E, an n vector p* ;::: O andan m vector w* ;::: O, with (p* ,w*)e =
t~e continuity of Y and the Corollary to Lernrna 8.2, Y(,\k) = ,\ Y(k). 1, such that for any econorny E, the following staternents hold:
For any non-negative vectors, k 1 and k 2 , choose two sequences of
non-negative rational vectors, {klv} and {k 2 v}, converging to k 1 and
(a) 2 /p*(xh -
he E
xh) - w~">l .: :; M;

k 2 , and then choose, for each v, a positive integer Nv so that Nvk 1 v


and Nvk 2 v are both integer valued. Frorn A.8.4,
(b) p*
he E
2 xh- 2 rnin p*x~t .:::; M;
he E Xh~hxJ~

(e) w*k(E) - M s p*y s w*k(E); p*y s w*k(S), all


y E Y[k(S)] and all S e E;
or frorn A.8.3,
(d) for any econorny E for which k(E) > M, all t, p* > O.
Nv Y(klv) + 2
Nv Y(k v) e Nv Y(klv +k 2
v).
The vector el is the unit m vector with 1 in the tth place and O
Divide through by Nv and let v approach infinity; then by Lernrna 8.2, elsewhere, and t(h) is the productive type of household h. In the
Y(k 1 ) + Y(k 2 ) e Y(k 1 + k 2 ). definition of Y, the sign of the profile k is reversed, since the pro-
ductive types of the participants are to be regarded as inputs.
LEMMA 3. Under A.8.1-A.8.4, Y(Ak) = AY(k) for all ,\ ;::: O, k ;::: O,
and Y(k 1 ) + Y(k 2 ) e Y(k 1 + k 2 ) for all k 1 ;::: O, k 2 ;::: O. Proof Frorn Lernrna 8.3, it follows irnrnediately that Y is a
convex cone. We can sirnply expand the cornrnodity space by
We rnust generalize again the definition of feasibility. adding m new cornponents as follows:
T
202 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 203
1
1
,

It is easy to verify, frorn the continuity of Y(k), that the analogs of DEFINITION 9. An allocation (x,y) is feasible for a coalition S if,
A.8.2 and A.8.4 hold for all non-negative k, not rnerely those with for ~orne y E Y[k(S)],
integer values. Note first the following generallernrna.
LEMMA 2. If <D(x) is lower serni-continuous, ifi(x) upper serni-
continuous, and {xv} a sequence converging to x such that <D(xv) e The definitions of blocked allocations and of the core then rernain
ifi(xv), all v, then <D(x) e ifi(x). unchanged in forrn.
Proof Let y E <D(x). By definition of lower serni-continuity, THEOREM 5. Suppose that the production possibility sets of the
there is a sequence {yv}, yv E <D(xv), all v, yv ___,..y. Then by hypothe- coalitions in each econorny E in a class satisfy A.8.1-A.8.4. For
sis yv E r/J(xv), all v, and by the upper serni-continuity of fl, y E ifi(x). each E, consideran allocation (.V, y) in its core (assurned non-ernpty).
Define Y = {(y,- k) / y E Y(k)}. For each household h of produc-
Corollary 2. If <D(x) and ifi(x) are continuous correspondences
tive type t in any econorny E, define the following sets in (n + m)-
and {xv} is a sequence converging to x such that <D(xv) = r/1(xv), all space.
v, then <D(x) = ifi(x).

Now let ,\ be any non-negative real nurnber, k any non-negative


vector. Let {,\v} be a sequence of non-negative rational nurnbers
converging to ,\, {kv} a sequence of non-negative rational vectors
converging to k, and for each v, Nv a positive integer such that
X "h-- {x"h x"h>
J - x'h for sorne x;
1 E X~},

,\vNv and AvNvkv are both integer valued. Then, by A.8.2-A.8.3, Z~ =X~- Y.
Assurne that for sorne L, r(Z~) .:::; L, for all h in all econornies E in
the class. Then there exists a constant M= 2LVn + m and, for
Divide the last equality by Nv, and let v approach infinity. Frorn each E, an n vector p* ;::: O andan m vector w* ;::: O, with (p* ,w*)e =
t~e continuity of Y and the Corollary to Lernrna 8.2, Y(,\k) = ,\ Y(k). 1, such that for any econorny E, the following staternents hold:
For any non-negative vectors, k 1 and k 2 , choose two sequences of
non-negative rational vectors, {klv} and {k 2 v}, converging to k 1 and
(a) 2 /p*(xh -
he E
xh) - w~">l .: :; M;

k 2 , and then choose, for each v, a positive integer Nv so that Nvk 1 v


and Nvk 2 v are both integer valued. Frorn A.8.4,
(b) p*
he E
2 xh- 2 rnin p*x~t .:::; M;
he E Xh~hxJ~

(e) w*k(E) - M s p*y s w*k(E); p*y s w*k(S), all


y E Y[k(S)] and all S e E;
or frorn A.8.3,
(d) for any econorny E for which k(E) > M, all t, p* > O.
Nv Y(klv) + 2
Nv Y(k v) e Nv Y(klv +k 2
v).
The vector el is the unit m vector with 1 in the tth place and O
Divide through by Nv and let v approach infinity; then by Lernrna 8.2, elsewhere, and t(h) is the productive type of household h. In the
Y(k 1 ) + Y(k 2 ) e Y(k 1 + k 2 ). definition of Y, the sign of the profile k is reversed, since the pro-
ductive types of the participants are to be regarded as inputs.
LEMMA 3. Under A.8.1-A.8.4, Y(Ak) = AY(k) for all ,\ ;::: O, k ;::: O,
and Y(k 1 ) + Y(k 2 ) e Y(k 1 + k 2 ) for all k 1 ;::: O, k 2 ;::: O. Proof Frorn Lernrna 8.3, it follows irnrnediately that Y is a
convex cone. We can sirnply expand the cornrnodity space by
We rnust generalize again the definition of feasibility. adding m new cornponents as follows:
T
204 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 205

(a) The preference orderings of the households do not depend If the productive types are identified with the types in Section 8.4,
on the additional commodities. the following theorem is obvious.
(b) The endowment vector of a household of type t contains
one unit of commodity n + t and O of commodity n + t' THEOREM 6. Suppose there are m types of households, where all
for any t' =6 t. households of each type have the same endowment and the same
(e) The production possibility for every coalition is taken to preference ordering and are indistinguishable in production, so that
be Y. the production possibility sets of the coalitions satisfy A.8.1-A.8.4.
Suppose further that there are k households of each type, indexed
In view of (a), we can assume that in seeking for a blocking allocation as in the statement of T.8.3. Then
we need only consider consurnption vectors in which the quantities
of the additional commodities are zero. Hence, the feasibility (a) The bundles yield by any strongly unblocked allocation to
condition D.8.9 applied to the extended cornrnodity space states two households of the same type rnust be indifferent in the
(with Xht = O for i > n) preference ordering for that type.
(b) If the numbers of types and the endowrnents, preference
O::::; 2 et<h>- k (y,--k) E Y, orderings, and coalition production possibility sets defining
hES
thern remain constant, but k, the nurnber of households in
where t(h) is the productive type of household h. But obviously each type, vares, if, for each k, (x 1',Y~c) is a strongly
2 et<n> = k(S), unblocked allocation such that U1 (x~t) = ul' is the same for
hES all k (it is independent of h by (a)), and if r(Z~ 1) is finite
so that, from the definition of Y, the last two conditions become when k = 1 for all t, then there is a price vector p* and a
k ::::; k(S), y E Y(k), .or since Y(k) is certainly monotonic in k, the dividend share d1 for each household of type t such that
single condition, y E Y[k(S)]. Thus the feasibility condition in the (p*,u~c,x",y 1') is a compensated equilibrium foral! k, where

extended space reduces to that already used. We can apply T.8.4 u" is the vector with mk components defined by u~ 1 = ul',
by straightforward reinterpretation of symbols. In particular, we y'' maximizes p*y for y in the production possibility set for
let (p* ,w*) correspond to p*; then T.8.4(a)-(c) follow immediately. the coalition of all members of the economy with k mem-
Further, if p* = O, then w*e' = 1, by the normalization used. If bers of each type, and the income, Mi', of any household
k 1(E) > M, all t, then w*k(E) > M; but from the first inequality in of type t is
(e), w*k(E) - M ::::; O if p* = O, a contradiction. Hence, p* > O
when kt(E) > M, all t.
Remark. The quantities wt are the distribution of pure profits.
Under the assumptions made, two households ofthe same productive Notes
type receive the same dividends. Thus, these magnitudes might be
thought of leading to the distribution parameters, dhf used in the As discussed in Section 1.3, the concept of the core was introduced
(though not with that terminology) by Edgeworth [1881, pp. 20-56],
model of Chapters 4 and 5. Then (a) asserts that the given un- who gave a thorough analysis of the case of two individuals. He further
blocked allocation approximately satisfies the budget constraint for suggested that with two types of households (in the sense of Section 8.4)
each coalition. The first part of (e) asserts that dividends in the the core would shrink to the competitive equilibria.
aggregate are approximately equal to total profits; the second part The concept of the core was introduced in the general theory of non-
asserts that no coalition can gain at the prevailing prices by engaging zero-sum games for which market economies are a special case. The
first to apply it to market economies was Shubik [1959]. Shubik's
in separate production for the market. Statement (d) shows that for work, like that of von Neumann and Morgenstern, Gillies, and Shapley,
sufficiently large econornies, at least, the price systern is non-trivial. operated under the highly restrictive assumption of transferable utility.
T
204 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE CORE OF A MARKET ECONOMY 205

(a) The preference orderings of the households do not depend If the productive types are identified with the types in Section 8.4,
on the additional commodities. the following theorem is obvious.
(b) The endowment vector of a household of type t contains
one unit of commodity n + t and O of commodity n + t' THEOREM 6. Suppose there are m types of households, where all
for any t' =6 t. households of each type have the same endowment and the same
(e) The production possibility for every coalition is taken to preference ordering and are indistinguishable in production, so that
be Y. the production possibility sets of the coalitions satisfy A.8.1-A.8.4.
Suppose further that there are k households of each type, indexed
In view of (a), we can assume that in seeking for a blocking allocation as in the statement of T.8.3. Then
we need only consider consurnption vectors in which the quantities
of the additional commodities are zero. Hence, the feasibility (a) The bundles yield by any strongly unblocked allocation to
condition D.8.9 applied to the extended cornrnodity space states two households of the same type rnust be indifferent in the
(with Xht = O for i > n) preference ordering for that type.
(b) If the numbers of types and the endowrnents, preference
O::::; 2 et<h>- k (y,--k) E Y, orderings, and coalition production possibility sets defining
hES
thern remain constant, but k, the nurnber of households in
where t(h) is the productive type of household h. But obviously each type, vares, if, for each k, (x 1',Y~c) is a strongly
2 et<n> = k(S), unblocked allocation such that U1 (x~t) = ul' is the same for
hES all k (it is independent of h by (a)), and if r(Z~ 1) is finite
so that, from the definition of Y, the last two conditions become when k = 1 for all t, then there is a price vector p* and a
k ::::; k(S), y E Y(k), .or since Y(k) is certainly monotonic in k, the dividend share d1 for each household of type t such that
single condition, y E Y[k(S)]. Thus the feasibility condition in the (p*,u~c,x",y 1') is a compensated equilibrium foral! k, where

extended space reduces to that already used. We can apply T.8.4 u" is the vector with mk components defined by u~ 1 = ul',
by straightforward reinterpretation of symbols. In particular, we y'' maximizes p*y for y in the production possibility set for
let (p* ,w*) correspond to p*; then T.8.4(a)-(c) follow immediately. the coalition of all members of the economy with k mem-
Further, if p* = O, then w*e' = 1, by the normalization used. If bers of each type, and the income, Mi', of any household
k 1(E) > M, all t, then w*k(E) > M; but from the first inequality in of type t is
(e), w*k(E) - M ::::; O if p* = O, a contradiction. Hence, p* > O
when kt(E) > M, all t.
Remark. The quantities wt are the distribution of pure profits.
Under the assumptions made, two households ofthe same productive Notes
type receive the same dividends. Thus, these magnitudes might be
thought of leading to the distribution parameters, dhf used in the As discussed in Section 1.3, the concept of the core was introduced
(though not with that terminology) by Edgeworth [1881, pp. 20-56],
model of Chapters 4 and 5. Then (a) asserts that the given un- who gave a thorough analysis of the case of two individuals. He further
blocked allocation approximately satisfies the budget constraint for suggested that with two types of households (in the sense of Section 8.4)
each coalition. The first part of (e) asserts that dividends in the the core would shrink to the competitive equilibria.
aggregate are approximately equal to total profits; the second part The concept of the core was introduced in the general theory of non-
asserts that no coalition can gain at the prevailing prices by engaging zero-sum games for which market economies are a special case. The
first to apply it to market economies was Shubik [1959]. Shubik's
in separate production for the market. Statement (d) shows that for work, like that of von Neumann and Morgenstern, Gillies, and Shapley,
sufficiently large econornies, at least, the price systern is non-trivial. operated under the highly restrictive assumption of transferable utility.
:
'11


T
:;'lll
206 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1.1

Chapter Nine
The decisive step in giving a general treatment of Edgeworth's propo-
sitions while retaining his assumption of non-transferable utility is due THE UNIQUENESS OF
to Scarf [1962], who proved T.8.3 (indeed, a more general form since
' 1
he did not assume that the inner radii of certain sets must be finite). A COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
greatly simplified presentation is due to Debreu and Scarf [1963], who
also extended the results to the case of produdion, in which each coalition
has access to the same production possibility set, which is a cone (this Alone, alone, all, all alone,
is a special case of T.8.6). Alone on a wide, wide sea,
Aumann [1964] gave an alternative treatment of the core by assuming
to begin with that the households form a continuum. Of course, his -Samuel T. Coleridge,
methods require sophisticated measure-theoretic arguments. The Ancient Mariner
Scarf's theorem applies to a replicated economy, Aumann's to one
that is a continuum. An alternative formulation of the problem is to
consider a sequence of economies with successively greater numbers of
j'
!
1
participants and ask under what conditions the cores of these economies l. The Problem
,1 ~ i tend to approximate their equilibria. It is this approach that underlies
the present analysis. The only (somewhat) similar approaches known We return now toa world of excess demand functions discussed in
,'
to us are those of Nishino [1970, Theorem 8] and Hildenbrand [1970]. Chapter 2. In particular, we assume F, H, W, B, and C', that is,
Nishino makes sorne strong assumptions about the utility functions and assumptions A.2.1-A.2.3, A.2.5, and A.2.6. The main question we
1
then asserts a theorem that, in a sequence of economies of increasing will investigate is this: In what circumstances will it be true that the
1

numbers of participants, there is a corresponding sequence of price


'li abstract economy discussed in the first part of Chapter 1 has only
vectors such that the maximum budgetary deficit of any household
:.11
approaches zero. Hildenbrand's methods and theorems make strong a single possible equilibrium p* in S? The question is not only
,,' ,,
:,1:
use of measure theory, so only a rough version of his main result along interesting in its own right, but requires an answer if one proposes
these lines (his Corollary 1 .to Theorem 2) will be stated: Given a to consider problems in comparative statics. Moreover, it will turn
sequence of finite economies converging (in an appropriate sense) to an out that the analysis of the uniqueness of an equilibrium is very
economy with a continuum of households and, for each such economy, helpful in examining the dynamic behavior of general equilibrium
an unblocked allocation, if the sequence of allocations converges con-
tinuously to an allocation in the limit economy, then there is a price systems.
vector, p, such that the sequence of allocations approaches the demand Our procedure will be as follows. First, we shall show that if a
correspondences of the households uniformly. (The sequence of func- purely mathematical condition is satisfied by the excess demand
tions Uv} is said to converge continuously to a function, J, if xv-+ x functions, then the equilibrium of the economy must be unique.
implies f,(xv) ->- /(x).) We shall then take a good deal of time to discuss the possible
economic cases that lead to the fulfillment of the mathematical
condition, and we shall also note cases for which more direct or
different approaches are possible.

2. The Main Assumptions


It will prove convenient in what follows to carry out the analysis
in terms of excess supplies rather than excess demands. We write
s1 = - Z, all i. Of course, s1(p) is the excess supply function for good
i. Also, ifp* is our equilibrium it must imply s1(p*) ::::: O, all i. We
postulate:
AssuMPTION 1 (D). For all i and for all p in Sn, s1(p) is differentiable.
The reader is reminded that this is a stronger assuinption than C'.

207
:
'11


T
:;'lll
206 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1.1

Chapter Nine
The decisive step in giving a general treatment of Edgeworth's propo-
sitions while retaining his assumption of non-transferable utility is due THE UNIQUENESS OF
to Scarf [1962], who proved T.8.3 (indeed, a more general form since
' 1
he did not assume that the inner radii of certain sets must be finite). A COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM
greatly simplified presentation is due to Debreu and Scarf [1963], who
also extended the results to the case of produdion, in which each coalition
has access to the same production possibility set, which is a cone (this Alone, alone, all, all alone,
is a special case of T.8.6). Alone on a wide, wide sea,
Aumann [1964] gave an alternative treatment of the core by assuming
to begin with that the households form a continuum. Of course, his -Samuel T. Coleridge,
methods require sophisticated measure-theoretic arguments. The Ancient Mariner
Scarf's theorem applies to a replicated economy, Aumann's to one
that is a continuum. An alternative formulation of the problem is to
consider a sequence of economies with successively greater numbers of
j'
!
1
participants and ask under what conditions the cores of these economies l. The Problem
,1 ~ i tend to approximate their equilibria. It is this approach that underlies
the present analysis. The only (somewhat) similar approaches known We return now toa world of excess demand functions discussed in
,'
to us are those of Nishino [1970, Theorem 8] and Hildenbrand [1970]. Chapter 2. In particular, we assume F, H, W, B, and C', that is,
Nishino makes sorne strong assumptions about the utility functions and assumptions A.2.1-A.2.3, A.2.5, and A.2.6. The main question we
1
then asserts a theorem that, in a sequence of economies of increasing will investigate is this: In what circumstances will it be true that the
1

numbers of participants, there is a corresponding sequence of price


'li abstract economy discussed in the first part of Chapter 1 has only
vectors such that the maximum budgetary deficit of any household
:.11
approaches zero. Hildenbrand's methods and theorems make strong a single possible equilibrium p* in S? The question is not only
,,' ,,
:,1:
use of measure theory, so only a rough version of his main result along interesting in its own right, but requires an answer if one proposes
these lines (his Corollary 1 .to Theorem 2) will be stated: Given a to consider problems in comparative statics. Moreover, it will turn
sequence of finite economies converging (in an appropriate sense) to an out that the analysis of the uniqueness of an equilibrium is very
economy with a continuum of households and, for each such economy, helpful in examining the dynamic behavior of general equilibrium
an unblocked allocation, if the sequence of allocations converges con-
tinuously to an allocation in the limit economy, then there is a price systems.
vector, p, such that the sequence of allocations approaches the demand Our procedure will be as follows. First, we shall show that if a
correspondences of the households uniformly. (The sequence of func- purely mathematical condition is satisfied by the excess demand
tions Uv} is said to converge continuously to a function, J, if xv-+ x functions, then the equilibrium of the economy must be unique.
implies f,(xv) ->- /(x).) We shall then take a good deal of time to discuss the possible
economic cases that lead to the fulfillment of the mathematical
condition, and we shall also note cases for which more direct or
different approaches are possible.

2. The Main Assumptions


It will prove convenient in what follows to carry out the analysis
in terms of excess supplies rather than excess demands. We write
s1 = - Z, all i. Of course, s1(p) is the excess supply function for good
i. Also, ifp* is our equilibrium it must imply s1(p*) ::::: O, all i. We
postulate:
AssuMPTION 1 (D). For all i and for all p in Sn, s1(p) is differentiable.
The reader is reminded that this is a stronger assuinption than C'.

207
-r
1

',
208 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 209

The second assumption we shall need will be further discussed :::; O, v1 > O. Also, we can readily find T2 such that T2A21T1v 1 :S: O.
below when we have proved the basic result. Then let
AssuMPTION 2 (N). In every equilibrium of the system there is a
good, give it the label n, for which V=(~}
2: S(p) =
1
-00
and find
when Pn = O. This good is called the numeraire. 1
TtAllTt V ) O
11 TATv = ( T2A21T1v1 :S: ,
Now, let us write siJ(P) as the parta! deriva ti ve of s1 with respect
'!1 to its jth argument at p and J(p) as the (n - 1) x (n - 1) Jacobian which contradicts the assumption that A has GP.
matrix of these partais. (In J(p ), i and j run from 1 to n - 1). We
:: require the following definition. The following definition was introduced by Hicks in his discussion
11"
11
of perfect stability.
11
DEFINITION 1 (GP). Let A be a square matrix and T a diagonal
1'1 matrix of the same order as A, with - 1 or + 1 or both, along the DEFINITION 2. A matrix, A, is said to be Hicksian if all the principal
main diagonal. Then if vis a column vector, A will be said to have minors have positive determinants.
the Cale property if for all T the problem TATv :::; O, v ;:::: O, has only LEMMA 2. A square matrix is Hicksian if and only if it has GP.
the solution v = O.
Proof For a matrix of order one, both conditions are equivalent
Remar!<:-. The Gale property (GP) can be given an alternative
to the statement that the single element is positive. Suppose the
useful statement. Let u be any non-zero vector, w = Au. Choose
lemma is true for matrices of order less than n, and let A be a matrix
the diagonal matrix T, with t; = 1, so that tu1 > O if u1 =!= O,
=o,
lW :::; o if U and let V=Tu;:::: o. Since T = u=
r-I, Tv.
of order n.
First, suppose A has GP. lt is certainly non-singular, for other-
Substitute in the definition of w, and multiply both sides by T, so wise we could find u with Au = O, u =!= O, contrary to the Remark to
that T ATv = Tw. Then GP is equivalent to the statement that Tw
D.9.1. Now choose u so that
has at least one positive component; that is, tW > O for at least one
i. By choice of T, it is impossible that u~,= O, and it can be seen Au = e(n),
that u1 and w1 must be both positive or both negative. Thus GP is where e(n) is the nth unit vector. From the Remar k to D.9.1, it
equivalent to the following statement: For any non-zero u, there is at follows that Un > O. Let Ann consist of the first n - 1 rows and
least one non-zero componen! that has the same sign as the correspond- columns of A. By Cramer's rule,
ing componen! of Au.
det Ann
W e now note, Un= det A

LEMMA l. If a matrix A has GP, then every principal minor must But by Lemma 9.1, Ann has GP; by the induction hypothesis, Ann is
have GP. Hicksian and in particular det Ann > O; hence det A > O. Since
Proof Let Lemma 9.1 and the induction hypothesis also ensure that the deter-
minants of all principal minors of A other than A itself are positive,
A must be Hicksian.
Now suppose that A is Hicksian, but does not have GP. Then
for sorne v > O, TATv:::; O. Since TAT is also Hicksian, we can
and suppose A11 does not have GP. For sorne v1 and Tto T1A11 T1 v1 replace it by A with no loss of generality.
-r
1

',
208 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 209

The second assumption we shall need will be further discussed :::; O, v1 > O. Also, we can readily find T2 such that T2A21T1v 1 :S: O.
below when we have proved the basic result. Then let
AssuMPTION 2 (N). In every equilibrium of the system there is a
good, give it the label n, for which V=(~}
2: S(p) =
1
-00
and find
when Pn = O. This good is called the numeraire. 1
TtAllTt V ) O
11 TATv = ( T2A21T1v1 :S: ,
Now, let us write siJ(P) as the parta! deriva ti ve of s1 with respect
'!1 to its jth argument at p and J(p) as the (n - 1) x (n - 1) Jacobian which contradicts the assumption that A has GP.
matrix of these partais. (In J(p ), i and j run from 1 to n - 1). We
:: require the following definition. The following definition was introduced by Hicks in his discussion
11"
11
of perfect stability.
11
DEFINITION 1 (GP). Let A be a square matrix and T a diagonal
1'1 matrix of the same order as A, with - 1 or + 1 or both, along the DEFINITION 2. A matrix, A, is said to be Hicksian if all the principal
main diagonal. Then if vis a column vector, A will be said to have minors have positive determinants.
the Cale property if for all T the problem TATv :::; O, v ;:::: O, has only LEMMA 2. A square matrix is Hicksian if and only if it has GP.
the solution v = O.
Proof For a matrix of order one, both conditions are equivalent
Remar!<:-. The Gale property (GP) can be given an alternative
to the statement that the single element is positive. Suppose the
useful statement. Let u be any non-zero vector, w = Au. Choose
lemma is true for matrices of order less than n, and let A be a matrix
the diagonal matrix T, with t; = 1, so that tu1 > O if u1 =!= O,
=o,
lW :::; o if U and let V=Tu;:::: o. Since T = u=
r-I, Tv.
of order n.
First, suppose A has GP. lt is certainly non-singular, for other-
Substitute in the definition of w, and multiply both sides by T, so wise we could find u with Au = O, u =!= O, contrary to the Remark to
that T ATv = Tw. Then GP is equivalent to the statement that Tw
D.9.1. Now choose u so that
has at least one positive component; that is, tW > O for at least one
i. By choice of T, it is impossible that u~,= O, and it can be seen Au = e(n),
that u1 and w1 must be both positive or both negative. Thus GP is where e(n) is the nth unit vector. From the Remar k to D.9.1, it
equivalent to the following statement: For any non-zero u, there is at follows that Un > O. Let Ann consist of the first n - 1 rows and
least one non-zero componen! that has the same sign as the correspond- columns of A. By Cramer's rule,
ing componen! of Au.
det Ann
W e now note, Un= det A

LEMMA l. If a matrix A has GP, then every principal minor must But by Lemma 9.1, Ann has GP; by the induction hypothesis, Ann is
have GP. Hicksian and in particular det Ann > O; hence det A > O. Since
Proof Let Lemma 9.1 and the induction hypothesis also ensure that the deter-
minants of all principal minors of A other than A itself are positive,
A must be Hicksian.
Now suppose that A is Hicksian, but does not have GP. Then
for sorne v > O, TATv:::; O. Since TAT is also Hicksian, we can
and suppose A11 does not have GP. For sorne v1 and Tto T1A11 T1 v1 replace it by A with no loss of generality.
210 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 211

If v has a zero component, partition its components into their for which its price and its excess supply change in the same direction.
positive and zero elements respectively, so that Thus stated, the assumption A.9.3 seems comparatively innocuous.
Yet it does rule out Giffen goods, at least if supply is fixed or highly
v1 o, v2 = o. inelastic, for if only one price changes GP requires that the excess
supply of that good increase.
The fundamental result to be established can now be stated.
With the same partitioning of components write
THEOREM l. If D, N, and A.9.3, then there is only one p in Sn, call
it p*, such that s1(p*) ~ O, all i. (H, W, B, and C' are taken to hold.)

3. Proof of T.9.1
Then A11 v1 = w\ v1 'o. w1 :::;; O. Yet if A is Hicksian, then, by
D.9.2, sois every principal minor, and in particular, A11 is Hicksian The proof will proceed by induction; that is we shall show first
and has GP by the induction hypothesis, a contradiction. that the theorem is true for an economy with two goods (n = 2).
Now suppose v has no zero components, so that v O. Let D Then we shall stipulate that it is true for an economy with n - 1
be the diagonal matrix with d = - wjv1 ~ O, A(t) = A + tD. By goods and show that it must also hold for an economy with n goods.
induction on n, the order of the matrix, we show that det A(t) > O In order to do this we shall make use of the fact that an n-goods
for t ~ O. The statement is trivial for n = 1; suppose it true for economy in which the relative prices of two goods are fixed may be
matrices of order n - l. By expansion of a determinant on its ith treated like an economy with n - 1 goods. We shall explore this
row, we see tb.at idea first.
Consider an n-goods economy in which variables have been trans-
8 det (A+ D) _ d A
8du - et , formed as follows:
Por all p in S with Pn > O, let
where A is the principal minor of A formed by deleting the ith row
and column. Then, q1 = p, S = S, (i < n - 1);
n qn-1 = Pn-1 + Pn;
d det A(t)
dt
L du det AH(t).
1= 1
Sn-1 = asn-1 + (1 - a)Sn Where a = Pn-1
qn-1
By the induction hypothesis, det A(t) > O, while d ~ O; hence and let s be the (n - 1) vector with components s1, and q the (n - 1)
det A(t) is a monotone increasing function of t. Since det A(O) = vector with components q1
det A > O by hypothesis, det A(t) > O, all t ~ O. The reader may verify the following properties of the construction:
In particular, for t = 1, A + D is non-singular. By construction, (a) Por all p in Sn, q is in Sn- 1 ;
however, Dv = -w, so that (A + D)v = O, v O, a contradiction. (b) qs(q,a) =O for all q in Sn_ 1 (W holds);
We now make the following assumption about the economic (e) s(q,a) satisfies H, C', and B.
system.
Hence by T.2.3 there exists, for fixed a, a vector q(a), such that
ASSUMPTION 3. Por all p in Sn, J(p) has GP. s(q(a),a) ~ O (q(a) is an equilibrium). Also, by N it must be that
Later we give severa! sufficient conditions for A.9.3 to hold. qn-1(a) > O.
However, it may be immediately observed from the Remark to It will now be convenient to have the nomenclature given below.
D.9.1 that A.9.3 is equivalent to the following: Por any small change DEFINITION 3. The system s with prices q, given a, will be called
in prices (relative to the numeraire), there is at least one commodity the reduced economy R(a).

1
1
11
.!J
210 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 211

If v has a zero component, partition its components into their for which its price and its excess supply change in the same direction.
positive and zero elements respectively, so that Thus stated, the assumption A.9.3 seems comparatively innocuous.
Yet it does rule out Giffen goods, at least if supply is fixed or highly
v1 o, v2 = o. inelastic, for if only one price changes GP requires that the excess
supply of that good increase.
The fundamental result to be established can now be stated.
With the same partitioning of components write
THEOREM l. If D, N, and A.9.3, then there is only one p in Sn, call
it p*, such that s1(p*) ~ O, all i. (H, W, B, and C' are taken to hold.)

3. Proof of T.9.1
Then A11 v1 = w\ v1 'o. w1 :::;; O. Yet if A is Hicksian, then, by
D.9.2, sois every principal minor, and in particular, A11 is Hicksian The proof will proceed by induction; that is we shall show first
and has GP by the induction hypothesis, a contradiction. that the theorem is true for an economy with two goods (n = 2).
Now suppose v has no zero components, so that v O. Let D Then we shall stipulate that it is true for an economy with n - 1
be the diagonal matrix with d = - wjv1 ~ O, A(t) = A + tD. By goods and show that it must also hold for an economy with n goods.
induction on n, the order of the matrix, we show that det A(t) > O In order to do this we shall make use of the fact that an n-goods
for t ~ O. The statement is trivial for n = 1; suppose it true for economy in which the relative prices of two goods are fixed may be
matrices of order n - l. By expansion of a determinant on its ith treated like an economy with n - 1 goods. We shall explore this
row, we see tb.at idea first.
Consider an n-goods economy in which variables have been trans-
8 det (A+ D) _ d A
8du - et , formed as follows:
Por all p in S with Pn > O, let
where A is the principal minor of A formed by deleting the ith row
and column. Then, q1 = p, S = S, (i < n - 1);
n qn-1 = Pn-1 + Pn;
d det A(t)
dt
L du det AH(t).
1= 1
Sn-1 = asn-1 + (1 - a)Sn Where a = Pn-1
qn-1
By the induction hypothesis, det A(t) > O, while d ~ O; hence and let s be the (n - 1) vector with components s1, and q the (n - 1)
det A(t) is a monotone increasing function of t. Since det A(O) = vector with components q1
det A > O by hypothesis, det A(t) > O, all t ~ O. The reader may verify the following properties of the construction:
In particular, for t = 1, A + D is non-singular. By construction, (a) Por all p in Sn, q is in Sn- 1 ;
however, Dv = -w, so that (A + D)v = O, v O, a contradiction. (b) qs(q,a) =O for all q in Sn_ 1 (W holds);
We now make the following assumption about the economic (e) s(q,a) satisfies H, C', and B.
system.
Hence by T.2.3 there exists, for fixed a, a vector q(a), such that
ASSUMPTION 3. Por all p in Sn, J(p) has GP. s(q(a),a) ~ O (q(a) is an equilibrium). Also, by N it must be that
Later we give severa! sufficient conditions for A.9.3 to hold. qn-1(a) > O.
However, it may be immediately observed from the Remark to It will now be convenient to have the nomenclature given below.
D.9.1 that A.9.3 is equivalent to the following: Por any small change DEFINITION 3. The system s with prices q, given a, will be called
in prices (relative to the numeraire), there is at least one commodity the reduced economy R(a).

1
1
11
.!J
T
212 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 213

We also define two vectors, P and Q, by (b) Suppose the theorem true for (n - 1) goods, but false for
11. Let P* =f. P** be two equilibria in the n economy, and
P = !. and Q = q Q(a*), Q(a**) the corresponding equilibria for R(a*) and
Pn (1 - a)qn-1 R(a**). (If. P* is an equilibrium for n, then for a* =
By H, if p* is an equilibrium for the n-goods economy, then so is P,~-1/Q~-1> Q(a*) must be an equilibrium for R(a*) and
P*, and if q(a) is an equilibrium for R(a) then sois Q(a). Note that similarly for Q(a**).) Since, by Lemma 9.1, R(a), the
Qn- 1 = 1/(1 -a), which is the value of qn_ 1 if we setpn = l. Jacobian for which has GP, must have a unique equi-
Finally let P(a) be defined as follows: librium, we must have a* =f. a**. Take a* > a**.
(e) We first note that
P1(a) = Q1(a) alli<n-1
ds1(P(a)) dP(a) <
a 0 alli<n-1. (2)
da da -
Pn-1(a) = (1 _a)
For if ds 1(P(a))jda > O, it follows from (1) that s1(P(a')) > O
Pn(a) =1 for a' > a and sufficiently close, so that P1(a') = O, whence dP1(a)jda
Then for i < n - 1, s1(q(a),a) = s1(P(a)). But q(a) is an equi- s O. By the same argument we have: ds1(P(a))jda s O implies
dP1(a)jda s O.
ljbrium for R(a) and so
Let T be the (n - 1) x (n - 1) diagonal matrix with T = + 1 or
For i < n - 1, s1(P(a)) ;::: O, and s1(P(a)) > O implies P(a) = O. (1) -l. We may evidently choose it so that
T(dP1(a)) O if dP(a) =f. O
We shall also need the following: da > (3)
da '
LEMMA 3. If for .all O s a s 1, R(a) has a unique equilibrium, q(a), ,.,-. ds(P(a)) if dP(a) =O
then q(a) is continuous in a. .
1 da s 0 da

Proof Consider a sequence ar--+ a0, O s ar s l. Let qr = Note that since Pn_ 1(a) = a/(1 -a), dPn_ 1jda > O, we have
q(ar) be the equilibrium for ar. Since the q's are bounded, there will Tn-1,n-1 > O.
be a convergent subsequence, say, qrk--+ q 0 Since s(qr,ar) is a
vector of continuous functions, Let s(P(a)) be the vector ofthe first (n - 1) components ofs(P(a)).
By the chain rule,
lim "s(qr,ar) = s(q 0 ,a 0).
r-> co
ds(P(a)) = J(P(a)) dP(a)
But by construction, s(qr,ar)) ;::: O, all r, and so s(q 0 ,a0 ) ;::: O. Then, da da
by the uniqueness hypothesis, q0 = q(a 0 ). Evidently the same so that
argument establishes the continuity of Q(a) for a < l.
T ~s(P(a)) = TJ(P(a))TT dP(a)
We may now proceed to the proof of T.9.1 by induction on the da da
number of goods.
or in obvious notation:
(a) T.9.1 is true for n = 2. For if P* =f. P** are both u = TJ(P(a))Tv. (4)
equilibria, take Pf* > Pf. But J(p) = s 11 (P) has GP, so
s 1 must be strictly increasing in Pl> that is, s 1 (P**) > From (3) and dPn_ 1jda > O we have v > O. From (2) and (3) we
s 1 (P*) ;::: O and so p** is not an equilibrium. know that the first (n - 2) components of u are non-positive.

111!
'i
1~
li
T
212 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 213

We also define two vectors, P and Q, by (b) Suppose the theorem true for (n - 1) goods, but false for
11. Let P* =f. P** be two equilibria in the n economy, and
P = !. and Q = q Q(a*), Q(a**) the corresponding equilibria for R(a*) and
Pn (1 - a)qn-1 R(a**). (If. P* is an equilibrium for n, then for a* =
By H, if p* is an equilibrium for the n-goods economy, then so is P,~-1/Q~-1> Q(a*) must be an equilibrium for R(a*) and
P*, and if q(a) is an equilibrium for R(a) then sois Q(a). Note that similarly for Q(a**).) Since, by Lemma 9.1, R(a), the
Qn- 1 = 1/(1 -a), which is the value of qn_ 1 if we setpn = l. Jacobian for which has GP, must have a unique equi-
Finally let P(a) be defined as follows: librium, we must have a* =f. a**. Take a* > a**.
(e) We first note that
P1(a) = Q1(a) alli<n-1
ds1(P(a)) dP(a) <
a 0 alli<n-1. (2)
da da -
Pn-1(a) = (1 _a)
For if ds 1(P(a))jda > O, it follows from (1) that s1(P(a')) > O
Pn(a) =1 for a' > a and sufficiently close, so that P1(a') = O, whence dP1(a)jda
Then for i < n - 1, s1(q(a),a) = s1(P(a)). But q(a) is an equi- s O. By the same argument we have: ds1(P(a))jda s O implies
dP1(a)jda s O.
ljbrium for R(a) and so
Let T be the (n - 1) x (n - 1) diagonal matrix with T = + 1 or
For i < n - 1, s1(P(a)) ;::: O, and s1(P(a)) > O implies P(a) = O. (1) -l. We may evidently choose it so that
T(dP1(a)) O if dP(a) =f. O
We shall also need the following: da > (3)
da '
LEMMA 3. If for .all O s a s 1, R(a) has a unique equilibrium, q(a), ,.,-. ds(P(a)) if dP(a) =O
then q(a) is continuous in a. .
1 da s 0 da

Proof Consider a sequence ar--+ a0, O s ar s l. Let qr = Note that since Pn_ 1(a) = a/(1 -a), dPn_ 1jda > O, we have
q(ar) be the equilibrium for ar. Since the q's are bounded, there will Tn-1,n-1 > O.
be a convergent subsequence, say, qrk--+ q 0 Since s(qr,ar) is a
vector of continuous functions, Let s(P(a)) be the vector ofthe first (n - 1) components ofs(P(a)).
By the chain rule,
lim "s(qr,ar) = s(q 0 ,a 0).
r-> co
ds(P(a)) = J(P(a)) dP(a)
But by construction, s(qr,ar)) ;::: O, all r, and so s(q 0 ,a0 ) ;::: O. Then, da da
by the uniqueness hypothesis, q0 = q(a 0 ). Evidently the same so that
argument establishes the continuity of Q(a) for a < l.
T ~s(P(a)) = TJ(P(a))TT dP(a)
We may now proceed to the proof of T.9.1 by induction on the da da
number of goods.
or in obvious notation:
(a) T.9.1 is true for n = 2. For if P* =f. P** are both u = TJ(P(a))Tv. (4)
equilibria, take Pf* > Pf. But J(p) = s 11 (P) has GP, so
s 1 must be strictly increasing in Pl> that is, s 1 (P**) > From (3) and dPn_ 1jda > O we have v > O. From (2) and (3) we
s 1 (P*) ;::: O and so p** is not an equilibrium. know that the first (n - 2) components of u are non-positive.

111!
'i
1~
li

~
,Ji
1'!11'
214 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 215
:1
' .'1'1 Hence if Un- 1 ,n- 1 ~ O, (4) would have a contradiction of GP. construction, then, P(a***) is an equilibrium. Proceeding in this
Hence Un-1,n- 1 >O or way, we must be able to find a arbitrarily close to a** such that
P(a) is an equilibrium. Clearly, then, A.9.3' is contradicted. We
dsn_ 1(P(a))
da > 0 have pro ved:
THEOREM 2. If D, N, and A.9.3', then the competitive economy has
But if both P* = P(a*) and P** = P(a**) are equilibria then
a pnique equilibrium.
Sn- 1(P(a**)) ;::: Oand so sn_ 1 (P(a*)) > O since a** < a*. But then,
by the definition of an equilibrium, P~_ 1 =O and so a* =O and we Our main' task now will be to examine a number of economic
cannot have a* > a** ;::: O. Hence P* and P** cannot both be restrictions on the excess-demand functions that lead to the unique-
equilibria. ness of an equilibrium. We shall do this, roughly, in increasing
order of generality (i.e., plausibility of the restrictions). In a
number of cases, we shall be able to establish the required result
4. A Weaker Assurnption without appeal to the two theorems we have just proved. In one
The method of our proof suggests the following weakening of A.9.3: case at least, we shall prove uniqueness and find that this could not
':i
be done by the use of the theorems. This underlines the important
AsSUMPTION 3'. J(P) and all its principal submatrices have GP at point that only sufficient conditions for a uriique equilibrium to exist
all P in E = {P 1 s(P) ;::: 0}. are available and that the ones we have utilized may well be a good
We show that this weaker version is sufficient to establish that E deal stronger than others that may be found eventually. We shall
has only one member, proceeding in the same manner as in Section also examine a number of examples.
9.3.
(a) Suppose that n = 2 and that P* and P** are in E. Also, 5. A Partial Converse
Pt* > Pt, Then, evidently, by A.9.3' it must be that It is clear that GP will not be a necessary condition for an economy
s1 (P* + (e,O)) > Oand S 1 (P** - (E,O)) < O, for e > Oand to have a unique equilibrium. However, we now show that a rather
small enough. (Since Pt* > O, s1 (P**) = O; since Pt ;::: stronger uniqueness postulate does indeed imply that the excess
O, s 1 (P*) ;::: 0.) But then by C ', since s1 changes sign supply functions have GP at p* O.
between the two price situations, there must be Pt** with The "reduced" economy that we constructed previously is only
Pt* > Pt** > Pt, such that P*** is in E. Proceeding in one of a large number of possible reduced economies. In particular,
this way we may find equilibrium values of P 1 arbitrarily let N be any subset of the goods not including the numeraire and
close to Pt, but this clearly contradicts A.9.3' for J(P*). its complement in the set of goods. Let a superscript N or to a
Hence there is only one equilibrium. vector denote that it has all its components in N or , respectively.
(b) We again suppose that A.9.3' is sufficient, with the other Let ~N be non-negative and h > O a scalar, and write
conditions of T.9.1 to ensure uniqueness for an economy
with n - 1 goods and proceed by induction in the same pH = h~H.
manner as in the previous section. In particular, we again Then we call R(~N) the reduced economy having excess supply
use R(a) and all the notation established there. functions (sN,sH) and prices (pN,h~A'). The idea is just as before
except that now we construct reduced economies by arbitrarily
We know from the previous section that dsn_ 1 (P(a*))fda > O,
fixing the relative prices of any subset of goods that includes the
dsn_ 1(P(a**))fda > O. We take a* > a**. It follows that for
a' < a* and close enough, sn_ 1(P(a')) < O. By continuity, there numeraire. We now prove
exista*** such that a* > a*** > a**, and sn_ 1 (P(a***)) = O. By THEOREM 3. Suppose that for every possible N and ~n, R(~H) has a

,

~
,Ji
1'!11'
214 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 215
:1
' .'1'1 Hence if Un- 1 ,n- 1 ~ O, (4) would have a contradiction of GP. construction, then, P(a***) is an equilibrium. Proceeding in this
Hence Un-1,n- 1 >O or way, we must be able to find a arbitrarily close to a** such that
P(a) is an equilibrium. Clearly, then, A.9.3' is contradicted. We
dsn_ 1(P(a))
da > 0 have pro ved:
THEOREM 2. If D, N, and A.9.3', then the competitive economy has
But if both P* = P(a*) and P** = P(a**) are equilibria then
a pnique equilibrium.
Sn- 1(P(a**)) ;::: Oand so sn_ 1 (P(a*)) > O since a** < a*. But then,
by the definition of an equilibrium, P~_ 1 =O and so a* =O and we Our main' task now will be to examine a number of economic
cannot have a* > a** ;::: O. Hence P* and P** cannot both be restrictions on the excess-demand functions that lead to the unique-
equilibria. ness of an equilibrium. We shall do this, roughly, in increasing
order of generality (i.e., plausibility of the restrictions). In a
number of cases, we shall be able to establish the required result
4. A Weaker Assurnption without appeal to the two theorems we have just proved. In one
The method of our proof suggests the following weakening of A.9.3: case at least, we shall prove uniqueness and find that this could not
':i
be done by the use of the theorems. This underlines the important
AsSUMPTION 3'. J(P) and all its principal submatrices have GP at point that only sufficient conditions for a uriique equilibrium to exist
all P in E = {P 1 s(P) ;::: 0}. are available and that the ones we have utilized may well be a good
We show that this weaker version is sufficient to establish that E deal stronger than others that may be found eventually. We shall
has only one member, proceeding in the same manner as in Section also examine a number of examples.
9.3.
(a) Suppose that n = 2 and that P* and P** are in E. Also, 5. A Partial Converse
Pt* > Pt, Then, evidently, by A.9.3' it must be that It is clear that GP will not be a necessary condition for an economy
s1 (P* + (e,O)) > Oand S 1 (P** - (E,O)) < O, for e > Oand to have a unique equilibrium. However, we now show that a rather
small enough. (Since Pt* > O, s1 (P**) = O; since Pt ;::: stronger uniqueness postulate does indeed imply that the excess
O, s 1 (P*) ;::: 0.) But then by C ', since s1 changes sign supply functions have GP at p* O.
between the two price situations, there must be Pt** with The "reduced" economy that we constructed previously is only
Pt* > Pt** > Pt, such that P*** is in E. Proceeding in one of a large number of possible reduced economies. In particular,
this way we may find equilibrium values of P 1 arbitrarily let N be any subset of the goods not including the numeraire and
close to Pt, but this clearly contradicts A.9.3' for J(P*). its complement in the set of goods. Let a superscript N or to a
Hence there is only one equilibrium. vector denote that it has all its components in N or , respectively.
(b) We again suppose that A.9.3' is sufficient, with the other Let ~N be non-negative and h > O a scalar, and write
conditions of T.9.1 to ensure uniqueness for an economy
with n - 1 goods and proceed by induction in the same pH = h~H.
manner as in the previous section. In particular, we again Then we call R(~N) the reduced economy having excess supply
use R(a) and all the notation established there. functions (sN,sH) and prices (pN,h~A'). The idea is just as before
except that now we construct reduced economies by arbitrarily
We know from the previous section that dsn_ 1 (P(a*))fda > O,
fixing the relative prices of any subset of goods that includes the
dsn_ 1(P(a**))fda > O. We take a* > a**. It follows that for
a' < a* and close enough, sn_ 1(P(a')) < O. By continuity, there numeraire. We now prove
exista*** such that a* > a*** > a**, and sn_ 1 (P(a***)) = O. By THEOREM 3. Suppose that for every possible N and ~n, R(~H) has a

,
216 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 217
unique equilibrium. Let the numeraire assumption N hold, and d _ Sm+l(a)- Sm+l(a*) O
suppose the economy has a unique equilibrium at p* O. Then the - a- a* >
Jacobian of excess supply functions has GP at p* if all its principal
minors are non-singular. Let s11 = 8sj8p1 ; since s1(a) is constant, that is, O for i :-:; m,
m+l dq
Remark. By analogy to Hicksian "perfect stability," we may call
f=l
S-dJ = 0,
a
the first requirement of the theorem one of perfect uniqueness.
Since, when N consists only of the numeraire, we have a reduced when evaluated at the equilibrium of R(W'\a) for any a. By the
economy that is the actual economy, ordinary uniqueness is included mean value theorem,
in perfect uniqueness, but does not imply it. Hence the assumption m+l dq
of perfect uniqueness is certainly stronger. d=
f=l
Sm+l,f -d '
a
Proof (a) Let N contain the first m + 1 goods, and let N' be the where the derivatives are all evaluated at sorne a', a < a' < a*.
first m of these. Also, let Let S~ be the matrix with elements s1, i, j = 1, ... , m, evaluated at
1'
1 :
PN = (
PN' Pm+l ) a'. The_n we can write
PN = (1 - a)k(3N
Choose [3N so that the unique equilibrium of R([3n), written as s~+l ~~ = (:).
(p*N,h*) is also the equilibrium for the economy, that is, p* =
(p*N,h*[3N). Let s; be the matrix with elements s11 , i, j = 1, ... , m, evaluated
Let (pN'(a), ak(a), (1 - a)k(a)) be the unique equilibrium of at a*. By hypothesis, S~ is non-singular, and therefore, for a'
R([3n'), that is, of R([3n,a). For a < 1, the assumption N ensures sufficiently close toa*, S~ is non-singular, all m. By Cramer's rule,
that (1 - a)k(a) > O. Let dqm+ 1 d det S~
N'( ) - pN'(a) -;;- = det S~+ 1
q a - (1 - a)k(a)
Since qm+ 1 = aj(l - a), dqm+ 1 /da > O. It has already been shown
qN(a) = ( qN'(a), 1: a) that d > O; therefore det S~ and det S~+l have the same sign. As
a approaches a*, a' approaches a* and S~ approaches S~, each m.
Then by H and perfect uniqueness there can be only one value of a, Since det S~ ;6 O, it must be that det S~ and det s:,+ 1 ha ve the
say a*, 8uch that same non-zero sign. This holds for all m, so that det s; has the
a* same sign for all m.
(p*N,h*) - ( N'( *)
(1 - a*)k(a*) - q a ' 1 -a*'
To complete the proof it suffices to show that det st = s 11 > O,
when s 11 is evaluated at a = a* and m = O in the above argument.
Also, a* < l. Then, as before, s 1 (a) = s1 (apt,h) < O for a < a*; if s11 ;6 O, it must
For a < a*, consider the equilibrium of R((3N,a). Let s1(a) = be that s 11 > O.
s1(qN'(a), a/(1 - a), (3N), i = 1, . .. , m. For any a, s;(a) = O, (i = It has now 'been shown that all the principal minors of J(p*) ha ve
1, . .. , m) if we ignore free goods, as we may for these purposes. positive determinants; that is, J(p*) is Hicksian by D.9.2 and,
If Sm+ 1 (a) =O, then the equilibrium for R([3n,a) would also be an therefore, has GP by Lemma 9.2.
equilibrium for R([3N'), which we know is unique; hence sm+ 1 (a) =
O if and only if a= a*. Then sm+ 1 (a) has a constant sign for
a < a*; if that sign were positive, then sm+ 1 (0) ;::: O, and the equi- 6. The Hicksian Economy
librium for R((3n,O) would be a corner equilibrium for R((3N'), con- Consider an economy with only one household and let p* be an
trary to uniqueness. Thus, Sm+l(a) < O for a < a*, or equilibrium for that economy and p any other price vector. By W
216 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 217
unique equilibrium. Let the numeraire assumption N hold, and d _ Sm+l(a)- Sm+l(a*) O
suppose the economy has a unique equilibrium at p* O. Then the - a- a* >
Jacobian of excess supply functions has GP at p* if all its principal
minors are non-singular. Let s11 = 8sj8p1 ; since s1(a) is constant, that is, O for i :-:; m,
m+l dq
Remark. By analogy to Hicksian "perfect stability," we may call
f=l
S-dJ = 0,
a
the first requirement of the theorem one of perfect uniqueness.
Since, when N consists only of the numeraire, we have a reduced when evaluated at the equilibrium of R(W'\a) for any a. By the
economy that is the actual economy, ordinary uniqueness is included mean value theorem,
in perfect uniqueness, but does not imply it. Hence the assumption m+l dq
of perfect uniqueness is certainly stronger. d=
f=l
Sm+l,f -d '
a
Proof (a) Let N contain the first m + 1 goods, and let N' be the where the derivatives are all evaluated at sorne a', a < a' < a*.
first m of these. Also, let Let S~ be the matrix with elements s1, i, j = 1, ... , m, evaluated at
1'
1 :
PN = (
PN' Pm+l ) a'. The_n we can write
PN = (1 - a)k(3N
Choose [3N so that the unique equilibrium of R([3n), written as s~+l ~~ = (:).
(p*N,h*) is also the equilibrium for the economy, that is, p* =
(p*N,h*[3N). Let s; be the matrix with elements s11 , i, j = 1, ... , m, evaluated
Let (pN'(a), ak(a), (1 - a)k(a)) be the unique equilibrium of at a*. By hypothesis, S~ is non-singular, and therefore, for a'
R([3n'), that is, of R([3n,a). For a < 1, the assumption N ensures sufficiently close toa*, S~ is non-singular, all m. By Cramer's rule,
that (1 - a)k(a) > O. Let dqm+ 1 d det S~
N'( ) - pN'(a) -;;- = det S~+ 1
q a - (1 - a)k(a)
Since qm+ 1 = aj(l - a), dqm+ 1 /da > O. It has already been shown
qN(a) = ( qN'(a), 1: a) that d > O; therefore det S~ and det S~+l have the same sign. As
a approaches a*, a' approaches a* and S~ approaches S~, each m.
Then by H and perfect uniqueness there can be only one value of a, Since det S~ ;6 O, it must be that det S~ and det s:,+ 1 ha ve the
say a*, 8uch that same non-zero sign. This holds for all m, so that det s; has the
a* same sign for all m.
(p*N,h*) - ( N'( *)
(1 - a*)k(a*) - q a ' 1 -a*'
To complete the proof it suffices to show that det st = s 11 > O,
when s 11 is evaluated at a = a* and m = O in the above argument.
Also, a* < l. Then, as before, s 1 (a) = s1 (apt,h) < O for a < a*; if s11 ;6 O, it must
For a < a*, consider the equilibrium of R((3N,a). Let s1(a) = be that s 11 > O.
s1(qN'(a), a/(1 - a), (3N), i = 1, . .. , m. For any a, s;(a) = O, (i = It has now 'been shown that all the principal minors of J(p*) ha ve
1, . .. , m) if we ignore free goods, as we may for these purposes. positive determinants; that is, J(p*) is Hicksian by D.9.2 and,
If Sm+ 1 (a) =O, then the equilibrium for R([3n,a) would also be an therefore, has GP by Lemma 9.2.
equilibrium for R([3N'), which we know is unique; hence sm+ 1 (a) =
O if and only if a= a*. Then sm+ 1 (a) has a constant sign for
a < a*; if that sign were positive, then sm+ 1 (0) ;::: O, and the equi- 6. The Hicksian Economy
librium for R((3n,O) would be a corner equilibrium for R((3N'), con- Consider an economy with only one household and let p* be an
trary to uniqueness. Thus, Sm+l(a) < O for a < a*, or equilibrium for that economy and p any other price vector. By W
218 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF. COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 219

and the definition of an equilibrium, we have has GP. Suppose not; in other words, suppose there is a non- ,'1
'1~
negative, non-zero vector, v, anda diagonal matrix, T, with t = 1
ps(p*) ?::: ps(p). (5)
such that TJ(p*)Tv ::::; O, whence v'TJ(p*)Tv ::::; O. C1early, there is ~~
,,

Prom the definition ofs and the assumption ofprofit maximization, sorne P in E such that for k > O and sufficiently small, we have
(P - P*) = kTv', and thus (7) is violated. Thus, if any equilibrium
p[x(p) - x(p*)] ?::: p[y(p) - y(p*)]
of the one-household economy must have strictly positive prices,
?::: o. A.9.3' holds and we may use ,it to establish uniqueness. Also, of
By the assumption that the weak axiom ofrevealed preference (WAR) course, N causes no difficulty. If, however, P* semi"positive is
holds for the household (see Corollary 4.6), it must be that possible then we cannot establish that J(P*) has GP and this method
of proof fails us. Of course, if we postulate non-satiability of every
p*[x(p) - x(p*)] ?::: O, good, an upper bound on stocks of goods and on the amount of any
whence again by the maximization of profits one good that can be produced, then we can exclude eqtJilibria with
sorne zero prices. Not only is that an assumption we do not need
p*s(p*) ?::: p*s(p). (6)
for T.9.4, but also the method of proof we employed to establish
Since P (A.2.1) has been postulated, it must be that either x(p) costs this theorem is considerably more direct than the alternative route
strictly more at p* than does x(p*) or profits are strictly greater at p* via T.9.2 and does not require D. Por this case, the work of the
when y(p*) is produced than when y(p) or both are produced. lf earlier sections was unnecessary.
not, there would be more than one supply or demand vector that It is now time that we inquired why this case should command our
satisfies agents at p* and so not F. Hence the inequality in (6) is interest.
strict, and Intuition suggests that an economy in which all individuals are
alike in sorne sense, will behave "as if" there were only one indi-
p*s(p) < O. vidual (with his space of possible choices suitably enlarged). If this
This is true for al! p =F p*, and since p* is non-negative, it follows is so, then the sense in which the households are alike is easy to
that for al! such p it is impossible that s(p) ?::: O. Hence p* is the deduce. Pirstly, at any p, the distribution of wealth between house-
unique equilibrium of this economy. holds must have no effect on the aggregate excess-demand (-supply)
'
'1
~ i' vector. Secondly, the redistribution effect of a price change must
THEOREM 4. A one-household economy has a unique equilibrium. have no effect on the economy's excess-demand vector. Evidently,
Before we discuss the question of why this result is of sorne if the first requirement is met, then sois the second. Moreover, it is
interest, it will be instructive to see whether it could be established not hard to see that both requirements can be met only if starting
by means of T.9.1 or T.9.2. Por this purpose, consider the price from any arbitrary distribution of wealth among households and
vectors P, where we have set Pn = l. This supposes that N holds, taking sorne wealth away from one of them and giving it to any
a point to which we return. Also, we write N(E) as the set of P for other causes the loser to take decisions in the market that are
which IP - P*l : : ; "' where " is positive and sufficiently small. opposite in sign and of the same absolute magnitude to the decisions
Since ps(p) = O, we have, from (6), (P - P*)s(P) > O, so for P in taken by the gainers. Now we shall make this precise.
E, up to terms of higher order, To do so it will be convenient to take the demand vector of a
household as having no negative components. We do this by
(P - P*)s(P) ~ (P - P*)s(P*) + (P - P*)J(P*)(P - P*)' > O. letting the household be. endowed with maximum quantities of
(7) various kinds of leisure and by taking it to demand various kinds
Now, if P* is strictly positive, the first term on the right-hand side of leisure. The difference between the leisure of a kind demanded
of (6) is zero. Since (7) holds for all P in N(E), it must be that J(P*) and the maximum there is is the supply of a service (Section 4.1 ). We
218 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF. COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 219

and the definition of an equilibrium, we have has GP. Suppose not; in other words, suppose there is a non- ,'1
'1~
negative, non-zero vector, v, anda diagonal matrix, T, with t = 1
ps(p*) ?::: ps(p). (5)
such that TJ(p*)Tv ::::; O, whence v'TJ(p*)Tv ::::; O. C1early, there is ~~
,,

Prom the definition ofs and the assumption ofprofit maximization, sorne P in E such that for k > O and sufficiently small, we have
(P - P*) = kTv', and thus (7) is violated. Thus, if any equilibrium
p[x(p) - x(p*)] ?::: p[y(p) - y(p*)]
of the one-household economy must have strictly positive prices,
?::: o. A.9.3' holds and we may use ,it to establish uniqueness. Also, of
By the assumption that the weak axiom ofrevealed preference (WAR) course, N causes no difficulty. If, however, P* semi"positive is
holds for the household (see Corollary 4.6), it must be that possible then we cannot establish that J(P*) has GP and this method
of proof fails us. Of course, if we postulate non-satiability of every
p*[x(p) - x(p*)] ?::: O, good, an upper bound on stocks of goods and on the amount of any
whence again by the maximization of profits one good that can be produced, then we can exclude eqtJilibria with
sorne zero prices. Not only is that an assumption we do not need
p*s(p*) ?::: p*s(p). (6)
for T.9.4, but also the method of proof we employed to establish
Since P (A.2.1) has been postulated, it must be that either x(p) costs this theorem is considerably more direct than the alternative route
strictly more at p* than does x(p*) or profits are strictly greater at p* via T.9.2 and does not require D. Por this case, the work of the
when y(p*) is produced than when y(p) or both are produced. lf earlier sections was unnecessary.
not, there would be more than one supply or demand vector that It is now time that we inquired why this case should command our
satisfies agents at p* and so not F. Hence the inequality in (6) is interest.
strict, and Intuition suggests that an economy in which all individuals are
alike in sorne sense, will behave "as if" there were only one indi-
p*s(p) < O. vidual (with his space of possible choices suitably enlarged). If this
This is true for al! p =F p*, and since p* is non-negative, it follows is so, then the sense in which the households are alike is easy to
that for al! such p it is impossible that s(p) ?::: O. Hence p* is the deduce. Pirstly, at any p, the distribution of wealth between house-
unique equilibrium of this economy. holds must have no effect on the aggregate excess-demand (-supply)
'
'1
~ i' vector. Secondly, the redistribution effect of a price change must
THEOREM 4. A one-household economy has a unique equilibrium. have no effect on the economy's excess-demand vector. Evidently,
Before we discuss the question of why this result is of sorne if the first requirement is met, then sois the second. Moreover, it is
interest, it will be instructive to see whether it could be established not hard to see that both requirements can be met only if starting
by means of T.9.1 or T.9.2. Por this purpose, consider the price from any arbitrary distribution of wealth among households and
vectors P, where we have set Pn = l. This supposes that N holds, taking sorne wealth away from one of them and giving it to any
a point to which we return. Also, we write N(E) as the set of P for other causes the loser to take decisions in the market that are
which IP - P*l : : ; "' where " is positive and sufficiently small. opposite in sign and of the same absolute magnitude to the decisions
Since ps(p) = O, we have, from (6), (P - P*)s(P) > O, so for P in taken by the gainers. Now we shall make this precise.
E, up to terms of higher order, To do so it will be convenient to take the demand vector of a
household as having no negative components. We do this by
(P - P*)s(P) ~ (P - P*)s(P*) + (P - P*)J(P*)(P - P*)' > O. letting the household be. endowed with maximum quantities of
(7) various kinds of leisure and by taking it to demand various kinds
Now, if P* is strictly positive, the first term on the right-hand side of leisure. The difference between the leisure of a kind demanded
of (6) is zero. Since (7) holds for all P in N(E), it must be that J(P*) and the maximum there is is the supply of a service (Section 4.1 ). We
220 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 221
shall not change notation to take account of this; however, x 1, is now the same ratio to bread, as he did when he was richer. Yet it ought
non-negative, and x" includes the leisure endowment. We also to be recalled that all theorizing that makes use of community indif-
write M" = px" + d"py, the "wealth of h," and x" = x"(p,M"). ference curves must be based on the supposition that the economy is
DEfiNITION 4. The economy will be said to be Hicksian if Hicksian and that there is a good deal of such theorizing. In any
event, we have proved
(a) for all k > O and all h, x"(p,M") = (1/k)x"(p,kM"), and
(b) if x~ = x"/M" = x"(p,1), M" > O, then x~ is the same for Corollary 5. The Hicksian economy has a unique equilibrium.
all h (with M" > 0). We must now inquire, not unnaturally, whether we cannot find
sorne more appealing economies with this property.
The first part of this assumption postulates that all demands are
linear and homogeneous in wealth (all households have linear Engel
curves through the origin), while the second part requires the amount 7. Gross Substitutes
of anything demanded per unit wealth to be the same for all house- We know from elementary theory of demand that, for a given
holds (the Engel curves of households are parallel). household, the consequences of a given price change may be split into
THEOREM 5. The Hicksian economy behaves as if there is only one an "income" effect and a "substitution" effect (see T.4.10). If the
household. jth price changes and the substitution term for the th good is posi-
tive, then the two goods i and j are, in the literature, said to be
Proo.f. By D.9.4(a), substitutes. In this section we extend this notion to the whole
excess-demand (-supply) function for i, that is to say we include
2: x~(p,1)M" = x(p, Ml> .. . , MH),
h income effects as well as supply effects in a classification of
commodities.
the economy's demand. By D.9.4(b), if, say M" > O, ths may be
written as DEFINITION 5 (GS). Two goods, i and j, i i= j, are said to be gross
substitutes at p when we have s1(p) < O whenever s(p) is defined.
(We may write equivalently: If z(p) is defined, then z1(p) > 0.)

and so x may be written as For the moment, we shall postpone a consideration of the realism
of supposing all goods to be GS at sorne or at all p and proceed to
establish a number of propositions about such an economy. In
what follows we shall write p(i) as the vector p with zero in the ith
that is, as depending only on total wealth and not on its distribution place.
between households. Moreover, we may analyze the economy as THEOREM 6. If all goods are GS at p and, for sorne i, p 1 = O, then
if only household H exists. s(p) is not defined at p and
We can show also that the Hicksian economy is the only one for 2:s(p) = -oo.
which T.9.5 holds-the conditional of that theorem is both necessary j

and sufficient (Gorman [1953], Nataf [1953]). It is apparent that Proo.f. Supp6se the theorem false so that, say, p(i) = p, s(p)
the restrictions involved are pretty stringent. It is hard to believe defined. By H, for k > 1, s1[p(i)] = s1[kp(i)], while for k clase to
not only that all households are alike in this sense, but also that all 1, GS implies s[p(i)] < s[kp(i)]. This last inequality follows from
Engel curves pass through the origin so that as an individual gets the fact that at kp(i) all prices other than the ith are no lower than,
poorer and poorer he nonetheless continues to mix holidays, say, in and the ith is the same as, at p(i), and at least one price is higher.
220 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 221
shall not change notation to take account of this; however, x 1, is now the same ratio to bread, as he did when he was richer. Yet it ought
non-negative, and x" includes the leisure endowment. We also to be recalled that all theorizing that makes use of community indif-
write M" = px" + d"py, the "wealth of h," and x" = x"(p,M"). ference curves must be based on the supposition that the economy is
DEfiNITION 4. The economy will be said to be Hicksian if Hicksian and that there is a good deal of such theorizing. In any
event, we have proved
(a) for all k > O and all h, x"(p,M") = (1/k)x"(p,kM"), and
(b) if x~ = x"/M" = x"(p,1), M" > O, then x~ is the same for Corollary 5. The Hicksian economy has a unique equilibrium.
all h (with M" > 0). We must now inquire, not unnaturally, whether we cannot find
sorne more appealing economies with this property.
The first part of this assumption postulates that all demands are
linear and homogeneous in wealth (all households have linear Engel
curves through the origin), while the second part requires the amount 7. Gross Substitutes
of anything demanded per unit wealth to be the same for all house- We know from elementary theory of demand that, for a given
holds (the Engel curves of households are parallel). household, the consequences of a given price change may be split into
THEOREM 5. The Hicksian economy behaves as if there is only one an "income" effect and a "substitution" effect (see T.4.10). If the
household. jth price changes and the substitution term for the th good is posi-
tive, then the two goods i and j are, in the literature, said to be
Proo.f. By D.9.4(a), substitutes. In this section we extend this notion to the whole
excess-demand (-supply) function for i, that is to say we include
2: x~(p,1)M" = x(p, Ml> .. . , MH),
h income effects as well as supply effects in a classification of
commodities.
the economy's demand. By D.9.4(b), if, say M" > O, ths may be
written as DEFINITION 5 (GS). Two goods, i and j, i i= j, are said to be gross
substitutes at p when we have s1(p) < O whenever s(p) is defined.
(We may write equivalently: If z(p) is defined, then z1(p) > 0.)

and so x may be written as For the moment, we shall postpone a consideration of the realism
of supposing all goods to be GS at sorne or at all p and proceed to
establish a number of propositions about such an economy. In
what follows we shall write p(i) as the vector p with zero in the ith
that is, as depending only on total wealth and not on its distribution place.
between households. Moreover, we may analyze the economy as THEOREM 6. If all goods are GS at p and, for sorne i, p 1 = O, then
if only household H exists. s(p) is not defined at p and
We can show also that the Hicksian economy is the only one for 2:s(p) = -oo.
which T.9.5 holds-the conditional of that theorem is both necessary j

and sufficient (Gorman [1953], Nataf [1953]). It is apparent that Proo.f. Supp6se the theorem false so that, say, p(i) = p, s(p)
the restrictions involved are pretty stringent. It is hard to believe defined. By H, for k > 1, s1[p(i)] = s1[kp(i)], while for k clase to
not only that all households are alike in this sense, but also that all 1, GS implies s[p(i)] < s[kp(i)]. This last inequality follows from
Engel curves pass through the origin so that as an individual gets the fact that at kp(i) all prices other than the ith are no lower than,
poorer and poorer he nonetheless continues to mix holidays, say, in and the ith is the same as, at p(i), and at least one price is higher.
T
222 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Since we now have a contradiction, we conclude s(p) is not defined.


THE UNIQUENESS OF

Corollary 7.
COMPETIT~VE EQUILIBRIUM 223
If all goods are OS for all p E Sn, then equilibriurn
I i

But then, by C' (A.2.6), is unique.


Of course, the proof of this corollary is trivial in the light of the
theorern and Corollary 6', but there are two available rnethods of
Corollary 6. Let p* be an equilibriurn. Then, if all goods are establishing this result that rnake no appeal to T.9.2 and that it will
1

OS at p*, it rnust be that p* O. be instructive to consider. ,:,

Suppose that P* is an equilibriurn and that P > O is any different


Corollary 6'. lf, for all pe:: Sn, all goods are OS, then N holds. price vector. Let v1 = PdPt, and suppose, say,
THEOREM 7. If all goods are OS for every pE E and if N holds, then v1, = rnax v1 = m.
1
,,
1

E has only one rnernber (equilibriurn is unique). J


:
,
Then, by H and the fact that P* is an equilibriurn, we have O =
Proof Let p* E E. Then we know that p* O. Since N holds, "
"
by T.9.6, we rnay use the norrnalized price vector P*, where p~ = l.
s,c(P*) = s,c(mP*). Now we can construct a sequence of price
vectors, starting at mP* and ending at P, such that at each step of
By H and OS,
the sequence, the kth price rernains unchanged while at least sorne
L s (P*)P* =
1 -s1n(P*) > O i=l, ... ,n-1. (8) other price is lowered and none is raised. By OS, then, s1, must
Nn increase with every step in the sequence and, in particular, s1,(P) > O.
Since s"(P) < O, j # i, sH(P*) > O, it must be that J(P*) has OP at Since P O, it follows that P cannot be an equilibriurn. Since
P*. If not, there is sorne v > O with TJ(P*)Tv :;:; O. Since every equilibrium price vector rnust be strictly positive, the corollary
P* O, we may define a vector w, with components follows at once. We note that in this elernentary proof we have
established, incidentally, a proposition concerning the excess supply
V
of the good whose price rose in the greatest proportion between P*
W = P(
and P. This will be useful in another part of the book and, accord-
and define J(P*) as the matrix with elements s11 (P*)P*. Certainly, ingly, we shall formally record it here.
TJ(P*)Tw :;:; O, w > O. Then let THEOREM 8. Let P > O and P' O be two unequal price vectors,
w,, = max w1 v1 the ratio of the ith element of P to the ith element of P'. Let
i max v 1 = V10 min v 1 = vh. Then, if for all P, all goods are OS,
Since t1, 1,t11 = + 1 or -1, for eachj, it is easily verified that trc~cw 1,;::: siP) > s,cCP'), sh(P) < sh(P).
t1,1ctJJw1, all j. By use of OS, the kth component of TJ(P*)Tw The second inequality of this theorem is established in exactly the
satisfies the condition same manner as the first.
L f~c~cslc(P*)PftJJW = t~~cs1, 1,(P*)Ptw1, + L t1,~cS~c(P*)Pft11 w1
Nn J,Pn
T.9.8 demonstrates in a striking way that OS certainly irnplies OP.
Suppose there is a change in prices relative to a nurneraire; if any
N le
;::: s,,lc(P*)P~wlc + L s,,(P*)Pfw,,
Nn
have risen relative to the nurneraire, the excess supply of the good
with the largest price rise must have increased, while if any have
N le
fallen relative to the numeraire, the good whose price has fallen most
=(L s~c(P*)P 1*) w 1, > O, must have hada decrease in excess supply. Thus, in any case, there
Nn is at least one cornmodity whose price has changed in the sane
by (8), which contradicts TJ(P*)Tw :;:; O. Hence, J(P*) does have direction as its excess supply, which is the essential property of OP,
OP, and T.9.2 proves the theorem. according to the Remark to D.9.1. When OS holds, we have much

'
1
1
T
222 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Since we now have a contradiction, we conclude s(p) is not defined.


THE UNIQUENESS OF

Corollary 7.
COMPETIT~VE EQUILIBRIUM 223
If all goods are OS for all p E Sn, then equilibriurn
I i

But then, by C' (A.2.6), is unique.


Of course, the proof of this corollary is trivial in the light of the
theorern and Corollary 6', but there are two available rnethods of
Corollary 6. Let p* be an equilibriurn. Then, if all goods are establishing this result that rnake no appeal to T.9.2 and that it will
1

OS at p*, it rnust be that p* O. be instructive to consider. ,:,

Suppose that P* is an equilibriurn and that P > O is any different


Corollary 6'. lf, for all pe:: Sn, all goods are OS, then N holds. price vector. Let v1 = PdPt, and suppose, say,
THEOREM 7. If all goods are OS for every pE E and if N holds, then v1, = rnax v1 = m.
1
,,
1

E has only one rnernber (equilibriurn is unique). J


:
,
Then, by H and the fact that P* is an equilibriurn, we have O =
Proof Let p* E E. Then we know that p* O. Since N holds, "
"
by T.9.6, we rnay use the norrnalized price vector P*, where p~ = l.
s,c(P*) = s,c(mP*). Now we can construct a sequence of price
vectors, starting at mP* and ending at P, such that at each step of
By H and OS,
the sequence, the kth price rernains unchanged while at least sorne
L s (P*)P* =
1 -s1n(P*) > O i=l, ... ,n-1. (8) other price is lowered and none is raised. By OS, then, s1, must
Nn increase with every step in the sequence and, in particular, s1,(P) > O.
Since s"(P) < O, j # i, sH(P*) > O, it must be that J(P*) has OP at Since P O, it follows that P cannot be an equilibriurn. Since
P*. If not, there is sorne v > O with TJ(P*)Tv :;:; O. Since every equilibrium price vector rnust be strictly positive, the corollary
P* O, we may define a vector w, with components follows at once. We note that in this elernentary proof we have
established, incidentally, a proposition concerning the excess supply
V
of the good whose price rose in the greatest proportion between P*
W = P(
and P. This will be useful in another part of the book and, accord-
and define J(P*) as the matrix with elements s11 (P*)P*. Certainly, ingly, we shall formally record it here.
TJ(P*)Tw :;:; O, w > O. Then let THEOREM 8. Let P > O and P' O be two unequal price vectors,
w,, = max w1 v1 the ratio of the ith element of P to the ith element of P'. Let
i max v 1 = V10 min v 1 = vh. Then, if for all P, all goods are OS,
Since t1, 1,t11 = + 1 or -1, for eachj, it is easily verified that trc~cw 1,;::: siP) > s,cCP'), sh(P) < sh(P).
t1,1ctJJw1, all j. By use of OS, the kth component of TJ(P*)Tw The second inequality of this theorem is established in exactly the
satisfies the condition same manner as the first.
L f~c~cslc(P*)PftJJW = t~~cs1, 1,(P*)Ptw1, + L t1,~cS~c(P*)Pft11 w1
Nn J,Pn
T.9.8 demonstrates in a striking way that OS certainly irnplies OP.
Suppose there is a change in prices relative to a nurneraire; if any
N le
;::: s,,lc(P*)P~wlc + L s,,(P*)Pfw,,
Nn
have risen relative to the nurneraire, the excess supply of the good
with the largest price rise must have increased, while if any have
N le
fallen relative to the numeraire, the good whose price has fallen most
=(L s~c(P*)P 1*) w 1, > O, must have hada decrease in excess supply. Thus, in any case, there
Nn is at least one cornmodity whose price has changed in the sane
by (8), which contradicts TJ(P*)Tw :;:; O. Hence, J(P*) does have direction as its excess supply, which is the essential property of OP,
OP, and T.9.2 proves the theorem. according to the Remark to D.9.1. When OS holds, we have much

'
1
1
'! '

1
1
' 1
224 GENERALCOMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 225 1
1
more specific information as to which excess supply must have risen But then i:l
or fallen.
The other alternative proof of Corollary 2 is not quite so simple, 0 = h 2>fSr(P) = PrSrr(p)
J
+h 2 PfSr(P) < pSr(p) < 0,
Ni J
but it is worth having for its own sake and for its use in other parts
of general equilibrium analysis. We shall prove the following, which is impossible. Therefore, (9) is satisfied only at p = p*.
rather striking result. Since an interior maximum exists, the theorem is proved.
THEOREM 9. If all goods are GS for all p, then if p* is an equi- The result we ha ve just established is a suitable point of departure
librium, p*s(p) < O, for all p i= p* E Sn. . for a consideration of the economics of the GS assumption in both
It is clear that a proof of this theorem is also a proof of Corollary its global eas for all p) and its local (GS for all pE E) forms.
2: Indeed, the conclusion to be proved is the same as the one we The first point to emphasize is that the fact that W AR can be
'1 shown to hold in a comparison of any two price situations, of which
established for the economy with one household.
1!1
one is an equilibrium, does not mean that this is true also for com-
l'il
Prooj. lf we can establish that the expression p*s(p) is maxi- parisons between any two arbitrarily chosen price situations. This
mized uniquely at p*, then since by W, p*s(p*) = O the theorem will is a fundamental difference between the Hicksian and the global
have been proved. GS cas. In the former, non-intersecting community indifference
Since p and s(p) are bounded above and C', we know that a surfaces exist; in the latter they generally do not. For instance, the
maximum for p*s(p) exists. Since, by T.9.6, p 1 = O implies s(P) reader may verify that if the utility functions of households are of the
undefined and, therefore, form

Un== nx~7' a,1 > O, all j


j
the maximum must be an interior one, so that if it is attained at p,
then 8xj8p1 > O, all j i= i, however much the constants ahi ma:y
2pjs1ip) = 0 k= 1, .. . , n. (9) differ for different h. For instance, in a pure-exchange economy ean
j
economy without production), this would certainly be enough to
But by W and by virtue of p* O, we know that, for p = p*, ensure global GS. It is true that in this example the Engel curves
8[ps(p)] - O - "p*s (p*) are linear, but they are n,ot parallel for different households.
8p, - - ~ i ilc '
On the other hand, if we calculate the substitution terms for this
since s 1,(p*) = O, so that (9) must hold at p = p*. We show that it example, we find that they are all positive for i i= j, and this is a
can hold for no other p. clue to a judgment as to the restrictiveness of the GS postulate. In
If p i= p* satisfies e9), let, say, general, elementary theory esee T.4.10) gives 8xn 1f8p 1 by the expres-
sion below:
Pr = max PJ =h.
i': j pj -8xh1
-
8'Pi
= 11'"11 + e-xhl - )
xhl r 1n,
By T.9.8, sr(p} > O since sr(P*) = O. By W,
8 where ,.\~1 is the substitution term and r~' is household h's marginal
'li
- epsep)) = 2p1s1r(P)
8'Pr
+ s;ep) =O propensity to buy goodj. Omitting superscripts to denote summa-
1
tion over h gives
and so
"e-Xnt
= IIJt + L.
88xJ' - X )h
r 1 eio)
'Pi h
'! '

1
1
' 1
224 GENERALCOMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 225 1
1
more specific information as to which excess supply must have risen But then i:l
or fallen.
The other alternative proof of Corollary 2 is not quite so simple, 0 = h 2>fSr(P) = PrSrr(p)
J
+h 2 PfSr(P) < pSr(p) < 0,
Ni J
but it is worth having for its own sake and for its use in other parts
of general equilibrium analysis. We shall prove the following, which is impossible. Therefore, (9) is satisfied only at p = p*.
rather striking result. Since an interior maximum exists, the theorem is proved.
THEOREM 9. If all goods are GS for all p, then if p* is an equi- The result we ha ve just established is a suitable point of departure
librium, p*s(p) < O, for all p i= p* E Sn. . for a consideration of the economics of the GS assumption in both
It is clear that a proof of this theorem is also a proof of Corollary its global eas for all p) and its local (GS for all pE E) forms.
2: Indeed, the conclusion to be proved is the same as the one we The first point to emphasize is that the fact that W AR can be
'1 shown to hold in a comparison of any two price situations, of which
established for the economy with one household.
1!1
one is an equilibrium, does not mean that this is true also for com-
l'il
Prooj. lf we can establish that the expression p*s(p) is maxi- parisons between any two arbitrarily chosen price situations. This
mized uniquely at p*, then since by W, p*s(p*) = O the theorem will is a fundamental difference between the Hicksian and the global
have been proved. GS cas. In the former, non-intersecting community indifference
Since p and s(p) are bounded above and C', we know that a surfaces exist; in the latter they generally do not. For instance, the
maximum for p*s(p) exists. Since, by T.9.6, p 1 = O implies s(P) reader may verify that if the utility functions of households are of the
undefined and, therefore, form

Un== nx~7' a,1 > O, all j


j
the maximum must be an interior one, so that if it is attained at p,
then 8xj8p1 > O, all j i= i, however much the constants ahi ma:y
2pjs1ip) = 0 k= 1, .. . , n. (9) differ for different h. For instance, in a pure-exchange economy ean
j
economy without production), this would certainly be enough to
But by W and by virtue of p* O, we know that, for p = p*, ensure global GS. It is true that in this example the Engel curves
8[ps(p)] - O - "p*s (p*) are linear, but they are n,ot parallel for different households.
8p, - - ~ i ilc '
On the other hand, if we calculate the substitution terms for this
since s 1,(p*) = O, so that (9) must hold at p = p*. We show that it example, we find that they are all positive for i i= j, and this is a
can hold for no other p. clue to a judgment as to the restrictiveness of the GS postulate. In
If p i= p* satisfies e9), let, say, general, elementary theory esee T.4.10) gives 8xn 1f8p 1 by the expres-
sion below:
Pr = max PJ =h.
i': j pj -8xh1
-
8'Pi
= 11'"11 + e-xhl - )
xhl r 1n,
By T.9.8, sr(p} > O since sr(P*) = O. By W,
8 where ,.\~1 is the substitution term and r~' is household h's marginal
'li
- epsep)) = 2p1s1r(P)
8'Pr
+ s;ep) =O propensity to buy goodj. Omitting superscripts to denote summa-
1
tion over h gives
and so
"e-Xnt
= IIJt + L.
88xJ' - X )h
r 1 eio)
'Pi h
T
!l
11

'1
226 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQU,ILIBRIUM 227

Now, if A11 < O, the burden of ensuring (lO) to be positive is thrown strictly positive, the sum of the terms multiplying r~ is zero. Cer-
onto the income term. But this depends partly on the disparity in tainly, then, if A11 > O,j f= i, and the covariance of r~and (.Xn 1 - X~t~)
the marginal properisities r~ between households, and partly on the is small, local GS seems reasonable. The smallness ofthe covariance
distribution of goods between households. For a given p, there are in question could surely be defended also (Section 12.5), but once
m~ny distributions of x between households that leave pxn the same again we require A11 > O and that remains an unhappy postulate.
for all h and so leave Xn unchanged. We can readily construct Yet if production considerations are introduced again, we might feel
examples where (10) changes sign over such distributions. Nor is it less certain that local GS makes unreasonable demands on our
clear what would be most helpful to postulate about the marginal credulity. Taking one thing with another, though, there seems
propensities. If they are the same for all h and p is an equilibrium plenty of reason for searching for more agreeable sufficient conditions
with p 1 > O, the income term evidently disappears altogether and GS for uniqueness than are provided by GS.
will not hold. If the marginal propensities differ widely, then we
will be able to find distributions of x that lead (10) to change sign. 8. Weak Gross Substitutes
If we then say that GS should only be postulated for a particular
A slight weakening of GS is obtained by dropping the demand
distribution, then the range of interesting application is rather
that, for all j f= i, we ha ve s11 < O and replacing it with the require-
restricted. To say that we also require A11 > O, all j f= i, would be
ment that all these terms are non-positive. As we shall see, even
very unrealistic because it is easy to think of examples of goods
this slight relaxation of the conditions has considerable conse-
(petrol and motoring); for which we feel pretty sure that the
quences for the uniqueness problem. We introduce the following
assumption will be violated. nomenclature.
Another unpalatable implication of GS in the absence of produc-
tion is that the elasticity of net demand for every good is less than DEFINITION 6 (WGS). Two goods i andj, i f= j, are said to be weak
-l. For if, say, a rise in the price of i raises the demand for every gross substitutes at p if s 11(p) ,:::; O when s(p) is defined.
good other than i, then it must be that the total expenditure on In view of our preceding discussion, there is no need to emphasize
good i diminishes. Lastly, there is the objection that the assumption that the increase in generality obtained by replacing GS by WGS is
forces us to conclude that demands go to infinity as the price of any by no means great. On the principie of Occam's razor, however,
good goes to zero. we must certainly see whether this relaxation, however slight, still
When account is taken of production, the assumption of GS does allows us to deduce sorne of the main results of the previous section.
not become any more convincing. Even .if differentiability is If we are willing to add one more postulate to that of WGS, then
assumed, there is no good reason to suppose that we may take indeed it will not be hard to show that all the theorems proved in the
8y1f8p 1 < Ofor i f= j. Certainly, in the absence of joint production, previous section will continue to hold for this new economy. We
a ceteris paribus rise, say, in p, will cause those producers who use i introduce this extra assumption in the following.
as an input to reduce (or not increase) their use of that input, so that DEFINITION 7. The economy will be called connected at p if there is
we may argue that the net supply of good j of all producers, other no set of goods 1 such that s1(p) = O for all 1 E 1, j ~l.
than the ith, taken together, will not increase. However, the demand
for good j by the producers of good i may increase sufficiently to Suppose now that an economy has WGS and is connected at p*, an
cause an increase in the total net supply of goodj. Indeed, there are equilibrium. Then it can be left to the reader 1 to show that we can
no satisfactory assumptions, even in the absence of joint production, 1 By connectedness, s(p*(i)) < O, sorne j =!= i, otherwise s = O for i E 1 =
11
':
that imply all goods are gross substitutes in production alone. Thus, {i}, j ~ l. Suppose this is so only for j = h. Then, if s 1(p*(i)) = s1(k(p*(i))),
it rnust be that p~ = O. Let p*(i,h) be the vector with p* = p: = O and apply
' 1

the main burden of the GS postulate falls on household demands. the sarne argurnent to s"(p*(i,h)) = s,(kp*(i,h)). Note that s, 1 < O, sorne
To hypothesize, local GS only is weaker, largely beca use we require j =!= i,h, for else we contradict connectedness. Proceeding in this way, we
rather less of the income term in (10); atan equilibrium, since it is finish up with either p* = O or s1 = - co, sorne j.
T
!l
11

'1
226 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQU,ILIBRIUM 227

Now, if A11 < O, the burden of ensuring (lO) to be positive is thrown strictly positive, the sum of the terms multiplying r~ is zero. Cer-
onto the income term. But this depends partly on the disparity in tainly, then, if A11 > O,j f= i, and the covariance of r~and (.Xn 1 - X~t~)
the marginal properisities r~ between households, and partly on the is small, local GS seems reasonable. The smallness ofthe covariance
distribution of goods between households. For a given p, there are in question could surely be defended also (Section 12.5), but once
m~ny distributions of x between households that leave pxn the same again we require A11 > O and that remains an unhappy postulate.
for all h and so leave Xn unchanged. We can readily construct Yet if production considerations are introduced again, we might feel
examples where (10) changes sign over such distributions. Nor is it less certain that local GS makes unreasonable demands on our
clear what would be most helpful to postulate about the marginal credulity. Taking one thing with another, though, there seems
propensities. If they are the same for all h and p is an equilibrium plenty of reason for searching for more agreeable sufficient conditions
with p 1 > O, the income term evidently disappears altogether and GS for uniqueness than are provided by GS.
will not hold. If the marginal propensities differ widely, then we
will be able to find distributions of x that lead (10) to change sign. 8. Weak Gross Substitutes
If we then say that GS should only be postulated for a particular
A slight weakening of GS is obtained by dropping the demand
distribution, then the range of interesting application is rather
that, for all j f= i, we ha ve s11 < O and replacing it with the require-
restricted. To say that we also require A11 > O, all j f= i, would be
ment that all these terms are non-positive. As we shall see, even
very unrealistic because it is easy to think of examples of goods
this slight relaxation of the conditions has considerable conse-
(petrol and motoring); for which we feel pretty sure that the
quences for the uniqueness problem. We introduce the following
assumption will be violated. nomenclature.
Another unpalatable implication of GS in the absence of produc-
tion is that the elasticity of net demand for every good is less than DEFINITION 6 (WGS). Two goods i andj, i f= j, are said to be weak
-l. For if, say, a rise in the price of i raises the demand for every gross substitutes at p if s 11(p) ,:::; O when s(p) is defined.
good other than i, then it must be that the total expenditure on In view of our preceding discussion, there is no need to emphasize
good i diminishes. Lastly, there is the objection that the assumption that the increase in generality obtained by replacing GS by WGS is
forces us to conclude that demands go to infinity as the price of any by no means great. On the principie of Occam's razor, however,
good goes to zero. we must certainly see whether this relaxation, however slight, still
When account is taken of production, the assumption of GS does allows us to deduce sorne of the main results of the previous section.
not become any more convincing. Even .if differentiability is If we are willing to add one more postulate to that of WGS, then
assumed, there is no good reason to suppose that we may take indeed it will not be hard to show that all the theorems proved in the
8y1f8p 1 < Ofor i f= j. Certainly, in the absence of joint production, previous section will continue to hold for this new economy. We
a ceteris paribus rise, say, in p, will cause those producers who use i introduce this extra assumption in the following.
as an input to reduce (or not increase) their use of that input, so that DEFINITION 7. The economy will be called connected at p if there is
we may argue that the net supply of good j of all producers, other no set of goods 1 such that s1(p) = O for all 1 E 1, j ~l.
than the ith, taken together, will not increase. However, the demand
for good j by the producers of good i may increase sufficiently to Suppose now that an economy has WGS and is connected at p*, an
cause an increase in the total net supply of goodj. Indeed, there are equilibrium. Then it can be left to the reader 1 to show that we can
no satisfactory assumptions, even in the absence of joint production, 1 By connectedness, s(p*(i)) < O, sorne j =!= i, otherwise s = O for i E 1 =
11
':
that imply all goods are gross substitutes in production alone. Thus, {i}, j ~ l. Suppose this is so only for j = h. Then, if s 1(p*(i)) = s1(k(p*(i))),
it rnust be that p~ = O. Let p*(i,h) be the vector with p* = p: = O and apply
' 1

the main burden of the GS postulate falls on household demands. the sarne argurnent to s"(p*(i,h)) = s,(kp*(i,h)). Note that s, 1 < O, sorne
To hypothesize, local GS only is weaker, largely beca use we require j =!= i,h, for else we contradict connectedness. Proceeding in this way, we
rather less of the income term in (10); atan equilibrium, since it is finish up with either p* = O or s1 = - co, sorne j.
228 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 229

use the same method of proof as in T.9.5 to establish that p* O. WGS and connectedness are weaker than GS, and this is sorne
Next, consider J(P*). By connectedness, it must be that s1n(P) # O, improvement. Now we must see how far we can go without
sorne i. Hence, all the right-hand sides in (8) are non-negative and connectedness.
at least one is positive. Proceeding as in the proof of T.9.7, we now THEOREM 10. Suppose for sorne p(i), s1(p(i)) > O. Then S(p) >
have O all pE S. (Recall that p(i) is the vector p with zero in the ith

2 s~clP*)Pfw1
i*n
;:::: w~c( 2 s,,(P*)Pf)
f*n
;:::: O.
place.)
Proof (a) By WGS and H, S(p) ;:::: O, all pE S, and so
If the first or second inequality is strict, there is nothing more to do,
s{p) ;:::: s1(p(i))
and we proceed as before. The first inequality fails to be strict only
if, for allj for which s1,(P*) < O, we have w1 = w,,. Suppose, then, Therefore, we need to prove only that s1(p(i)) > O, sorne p(i), implies
that s1,"(P*) < O and w" = W~c. But then s1(p(i)) > O all p(i) E S.
(b) If the theorem is false, there is, by C', so me p'(i) such that
;:
? s"(P*)Pfw1 ;:::: w"(? shi(P*)Pf) ;:::: O. s1(p'(i)) = O. _Define p"(i) so that
*n *n
' .!:!1':1 p'j(i) = min[p(i),p;(i)].
1
1111 Once again, if any inequality is strict, we have nothing more to do.
;, :

, 1
Moreover, if the first inequality fails to be strict, then, by connected- Then, by WGS,
ness, there must be j # k,h such that s"(P*) < O and w1 = w,,. (11)
;
1
"11,
," S(p"(i)) ;:::: S(p(i)) > 0.
Proceeding in this way, either all w's are equal-in which case, in
.::
1

!
11
view of s1n(P*) < O, sorne i, the second inequality must be strict for Now let p(a) = (1 - a)p"(i) + ap'(i), O ~ a s 1. By (11) and
sorne k-or the w's are not all equal and the first inequality must be C'
strict for sorne k. Hence J(P*) has GP. It then follows 'also that '
s1(p(a)) > O for a > O and sufficiently srnall. (12)
with WGS replacing GS in Corollary 6 and by adding the connected-
ness assurnption, the conclusion of the corollary will continue to
By construction, for a > O, p(a) > O if and only if pj(i) > O.
hold.
For all such j, s11(p(a)) =O. Otherwise, by WGS, S(p(a)) < O;
Next consider T.9.8 with WGS and connectedness instead of GS.
then s1(p(a)) > s1(kp(a)), for k > 1 and sufficiently small, contra-
Using the sarne notation as ernployed in the proof of that theorem,
dicting H. (Note that, by (12), s{p(a)) = --oo is irnpossible.) Then,
we note that siP) can only now fail to be positive, if for all j
for all j, either s11 (p(a)) = O or p(a) is constant at O, so that s,(p(a))
for which s~c 1 (P) < O, we have v,, = v1 An argurnent exactly analo-
is constant. Since p'(i) = p(l),
gous to the one we have just used in discussing T.9.7 with the new
assurnptions shows that there must be sorne h such that v" = v,, and s1(p(a)) = s1(p'(i)) = O all a > O,
s"(P) > O. Hence one of the goods whose price has risen by no in contradiction to (12).
srnaller proportion from its equilibriurn value than has that of any
other good, rnust now be in excess supply. Since this is the result Corollary 10. Suppose that for sorne p'(i), s1[p'(i)] = O. Then
we need for the last crucial inequality ernployed in the proof of s1[p(i)] = O for all p(i).
T.9.9, it follows that WGS and connectedness are sufficient to give Proof If not, then there must be sorne p(i) such that s[p(i)] < O,
P*s(P) < O all P # P*. for by T.9.10, there cannot be any p(i) such that S[p(i)] > O. Let
It should be clear that the assurnption that the economy is con-
pj(i) = rnin[pj(i),p(i)].
nected plays a considerable role in preserving all the results of GS
for the case of WGS. Since a GS economy is certainly connected, Then, by WGS, s1[p"(i)] ;:::: O. By T.9.10, the inequality is not
228 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 229

use the same method of proof as in T.9.5 to establish that p* O. WGS and connectedness are weaker than GS, and this is sorne
Next, consider J(P*). By connectedness, it must be that s1n(P) # O, improvement. Now we must see how far we can go without
sorne i. Hence, all the right-hand sides in (8) are non-negative and connectedness.
at least one is positive. Proceeding as in the proof of T.9.7, we now THEOREM 10. Suppose for sorne p(i), s1(p(i)) > O. Then S(p) >
have O all pE S. (Recall that p(i) is the vector p with zero in the ith

2 s~clP*)Pfw1
i*n
;:::: w~c( 2 s,,(P*)Pf)
f*n
;:::: O.
place.)
Proof (a) By WGS and H, S(p) ;:::: O, all pE S, and so
If the first or second inequality is strict, there is nothing more to do,
s{p) ;:::: s1(p(i))
and we proceed as before. The first inequality fails to be strict only
if, for allj for which s1,(P*) < O, we have w1 = w,,. Suppose, then, Therefore, we need to prove only that s1(p(i)) > O, sorne p(i), implies
that s1,"(P*) < O and w" = W~c. But then s1(p(i)) > O all p(i) E S.
(b) If the theorem is false, there is, by C', so me p'(i) such that
;:
? s"(P*)Pfw1 ;:::: w"(? shi(P*)Pf) ;:::: O. s1(p'(i)) = O. _Define p"(i) so that
*n *n
' .!:!1':1 p'j(i) = min[p(i),p;(i)].
1
1111 Once again, if any inequality is strict, we have nothing more to do.
;, :

, 1
Moreover, if the first inequality fails to be strict, then, by connected- Then, by WGS,
ness, there must be j # k,h such that s"(P*) < O and w1 = w,,. (11)
;
1
"11,
," S(p"(i)) ;:::: S(p(i)) > 0.
Proceeding in this way, either all w's are equal-in which case, in
.::
1

!
11
view of s1n(P*) < O, sorne i, the second inequality must be strict for Now let p(a) = (1 - a)p"(i) + ap'(i), O ~ a s 1. By (11) and
sorne k-or the w's are not all equal and the first inequality must be C'
strict for sorne k. Hence J(P*) has GP. It then follows 'also that '
s1(p(a)) > O for a > O and sufficiently srnall. (12)
with WGS replacing GS in Corollary 6 and by adding the connected-
ness assurnption, the conclusion of the corollary will continue to
By construction, for a > O, p(a) > O if and only if pj(i) > O.
hold.
For all such j, s11(p(a)) =O. Otherwise, by WGS, S(p(a)) < O;
Next consider T.9.8 with WGS and connectedness instead of GS.
then s1(p(a)) > s1(kp(a)), for k > 1 and sufficiently small, contra-
Using the sarne notation as ernployed in the proof of that theorem,
dicting H. (Note that, by (12), s{p(a)) = --oo is irnpossible.) Then,
we note that siP) can only now fail to be positive, if for all j
for all j, either s11 (p(a)) = O or p(a) is constant at O, so that s,(p(a))
for which s~c 1 (P) < O, we have v,, = v1 An argurnent exactly analo-
is constant. Since p'(i) = p(l),
gous to the one we have just used in discussing T.9.7 with the new
assurnptions shows that there must be sorne h such that v" = v,, and s1(p(a)) = s1(p'(i)) = O all a > O,
s"(P) > O. Hence one of the goods whose price has risen by no in contradiction to (12).
srnaller proportion from its equilibriurn value than has that of any
other good, rnust now be in excess supply. Since this is the result Corollary 10. Suppose that for sorne p'(i), s1[p'(i)] = O. Then
we need for the last crucial inequality ernployed in the proof of s1[p(i)] = O for all p(i).
T.9.9, it follows that WGS and connectedness are sufficient to give Proof If not, then there must be sorne p(i) such that s[p(i)] < O,
P*s(P) < O all P # P*. for by T.9.10, there cannot be any p(i) such that S[p(i)] > O. Let
It should be clear that the assurnption that the economy is con-
pj(i) = rnin[pj(i),p(i)].
nected plays a considerable role in preserving all the results of GS
for the case of WGS. Since a GS economy is certainly connected, Then, by WGS, s1[p"(i)] ;:::: O. By T.9.10, the inequality is not
230 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 231

possible and so Clearly (13) holds for PR = p~, and we rnust show that it cannot hold
0 = S(p"(i)) > s 1[p(i)]. for any other PR
Suppose (13) holds for PR =6 p~, and that the first r elernents of
Let p(a) = (1 - a)p"(i) + ap(i). Then, for a > O and srnall
PR are zero. (Of course, r rnay be zero, i.e., no elernent of PR is zero;
enough,
the nurnbering is inessential.) Let p~(r) be the vector p~ with its
S 1[p(a)] > S[p(i)), first r elernents set equal to zero. Also let k 1 = pfpt and nurnber
and p(a) > O if and only if p(i) > O. Then, by the sarne argurnent goods so that
as in T.9.10, we obtain s 1[p(1)] = s1[p(i)] > s1[p(i)], a contradiction.
kr+ 1 ;;:::: kr+ 2 ;;:::: ' ;;:::: km,
The theorern and corollary we ha ve just established rnust take the
where we take R as containing all i :S m.
place of T.9.6 for the GS case. We see that we can no longer clairn
1'
Then, by WGS, certainly
that s 1(p(i)) is undefined, so we can no longer establish p* O. If
:j
a rnarket reaches an equilibriurn ata zero price, however, then it can Sr+l(p~,O) :S Sr+l(p~(r),O)), (14)
never be in excess dernand at any set of prices and this is a property since in p~(r) the prices of goods i :S r are lower than they are in
of the situation that we shall exploit in the following: p~ and no price is higher. By H,
THEOREM 11. Let p* E E, the set of equilibriurn price vectors.
Sr+ 1(p~(r),O) = Sr+l(kr+ 1P~(r),O). (15)
Then, if all goods are WGS at all p, p*s(p) < O, for all p not in E.
Before ernbarking on a proof of this theorern we should note that By the definition of kr+b it rnust be that (r + 1)th cornponent of
it is a good deal weaker than T.9.9; if true, it clearly does not enable kr+ 1 p~(r) is equal to Pr+ 1o while no cornponent of PR can exceed the
us to deduce that E has a single rnernber _only. Nonetheless, we corresponding cornponent of kr+ 1 p~(r). But by WGS,
shall find that the result will be useful in characterizing the equi- Sr+ 1(kr+1P~(r),0) :S Sr+ 1(pR,O), (16)
libriurn set E. lt will prove useful in later chapters as well.
1
and so by (14), (15), and (16),
Proof. (a) Let R = {i 1 pt > O} and R' = {i 1 pt = 0}. Let the
Sr+1(p~,0) :S Sr+l(PR,O). (17)
1

subscript R to a vector denote that it has cornponents in R and


1

sirnilarly for a subscript R'. Then, by WGS, If in (17) the inequality is strict, we rnay argue as follows: Differen-
sR(pR,pR') S SR(pR,0). tiating W with respect to Pr+ 1 gives

Hence, if we can show that for all (pR,O) not in E, p~sR(pR,O) < O, we L pSJ,r+l(PR,O) =
jER
-Sr+1(pR,0). (18)
shall have proved the theorern.
(b) lf i E R, p1 = O, then Frorn (17) and the fact that (p~,0) is an equilibriurn with P~+ 1 > O,
we deduce that the right-hand side of (18) is negative. Yet frorn the
s{pR,O) :S 0.
definition of kr+ 1 and WGS,
Suppose not, that is, for sorne such i, s1(pR,O) > O. Then, by T.9.9,
s1(p:,o) > O. But pt > O, and so we contradict (p~,O) E E. kr+1 L PtSJ,r+1(pR,0) :S L pSJ,r+l(pR,O),
jER }ER
(e) We propose to show that p*s(p) cannot reach a rnaxirnurn at
any p not in E. By the argurnent of (a), we note that the rnaxirnurn and so in view of (18)
rnust occur at sorne (pR,O), where we rnay take PR > O, and so a (19)
necessary condition for a rnaxirnurn is
Lpts ,c(pR,O) ;;:::: O,
/ER
1 all k E R. (13) Since (19) contradicts (13), p*s(p) cannot attain a rnaxirnum at
(pR,O).
230 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 231

possible and so Clearly (13) holds for PR = p~, and we rnust show that it cannot hold
0 = S(p"(i)) > s 1[p(i)]. for any other PR
Suppose (13) holds for PR =6 p~, and that the first r elernents of
Let p(a) = (1 - a)p"(i) + ap(i). Then, for a > O and srnall
PR are zero. (Of course, r rnay be zero, i.e., no elernent of PR is zero;
enough,
the nurnbering is inessential.) Let p~(r) be the vector p~ with its
S 1[p(a)] > S[p(i)), first r elernents set equal to zero. Also let k 1 = pfpt and nurnber
and p(a) > O if and only if p(i) > O. Then, by the sarne argurnent goods so that
as in T.9.10, we obtain s 1[p(1)] = s1[p(i)] > s1[p(i)], a contradiction.
kr+ 1 ;;:::: kr+ 2 ;;:::: ' ;;:::: km,
The theorern and corollary we ha ve just established rnust take the
where we take R as containing all i :S m.
place of T.9.6 for the GS case. We see that we can no longer clairn
1'
Then, by WGS, certainly
that s 1(p(i)) is undefined, so we can no longer establish p* O. If
:j
a rnarket reaches an equilibriurn ata zero price, however, then it can Sr+l(p~,O) :S Sr+l(p~(r),O)), (14)
never be in excess dernand at any set of prices and this is a property since in p~(r) the prices of goods i :S r are lower than they are in
of the situation that we shall exploit in the following: p~ and no price is higher. By H,
THEOREM 11. Let p* E E, the set of equilibriurn price vectors.
Sr+ 1(p~(r),O) = Sr+l(kr+ 1P~(r),O). (15)
Then, if all goods are WGS at all p, p*s(p) < O, for all p not in E.
Before ernbarking on a proof of this theorern we should note that By the definition of kr+b it rnust be that (r + 1)th cornponent of
it is a good deal weaker than T.9.9; if true, it clearly does not enable kr+ 1 p~(r) is equal to Pr+ 1o while no cornponent of PR can exceed the
us to deduce that E has a single rnernber _only. Nonetheless, we corresponding cornponent of kr+ 1 p~(r). But by WGS,
shall find that the result will be useful in characterizing the equi- Sr+ 1(kr+1P~(r),0) :S Sr+ 1(pR,O), (16)
libriurn set E. lt will prove useful in later chapters as well.
1
and so by (14), (15), and (16),
Proof. (a) Let R = {i 1 pt > O} and R' = {i 1 pt = 0}. Let the
Sr+1(p~,0) :S Sr+l(PR,O). (17)
1

subscript R to a vector denote that it has cornponents in R and


1

sirnilarly for a subscript R'. Then, by WGS, If in (17) the inequality is strict, we rnay argue as follows: Differen-
sR(pR,pR') S SR(pR,0). tiating W with respect to Pr+ 1 gives

Hence, if we can show that for all (pR,O) not in E, p~sR(pR,O) < O, we L pSJ,r+l(PR,O) =
jER
-Sr+1(pR,0). (18)
shall have proved the theorern.
(b) lf i E R, p1 = O, then Frorn (17) and the fact that (p~,0) is an equilibriurn with P~+ 1 > O,
we deduce that the right-hand side of (18) is negative. Yet frorn the
s{pR,O) :S 0.
definition of kr+ 1 and WGS,
Suppose not, that is, for sorne such i, s1(pR,O) > O. Then, by T.9.9,
s1(p:,o) > O. But pt > O, and so we contradict (p~,O) E E. kr+1 L PtSJ,r+1(pR,0) :S L pSJ,r+l(pR,O),
jER }ER
(e) We propose to show that p*s(p) cannot reach a rnaxirnurn at
any p not in E. By the argurnent of (a), we note that the rnaxirnurn and so in view of (18)
rnust occur at sorne (pR,O), where we rnay take PR > O, and so a (19)
necessary condition for a rnaxirnurn is
Lpts ,c(pR,O) ;;:::: O,
/ER
1 all k E R. (13) Since (19) contradicts (13), p*s(p) cannot attain a rnaxirnum at
(pR,O).
T
1
r
1'
11

11

1!
l.
232 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 233
!
Suppose, then, the inequality in (17) is not strict. If kr+ 2 = kr+ 1 , weaker than those that were establishable with GS, or WGS with
it is easily checked that we can obtain (17) for Sr+ 2 Ifthat inequality connectedness. Yet for many purposes of economic analysis it is
were strict, we would again get (19) for "r + 2" with the same correct to say that the convexity of the equilibrium set is as good as
conclusion. So consider kr+ 2 < kr+ 1 Then every component uniqueness, and WAR for all comparisons in which one price
kr+ 1P"t of kr+ 1 p~(r), with i > r + 1, exceeds p 1 Then, sin ce the belongs to E is as good as WAR for all comparisons in which one
inequality in (16) is not strict, it must be true, because of WGS, that price vector is the unique equilibrium one. This will become clear
Sr+ 1jpn,O) = O for j > r + l. Additionally, by H, Sr+ 1,r+ 1 = O later in this book. The drawback of the WGS assumption, there-
and we conclude fore, is not the weakness of its implications for the equilibrium set,
but rather the weak appeal of the assumption itself. It is only
allj;::: r +1 if kr+1 > kr+2 slightly less ~estrictive and unappealing than GS and that makes it
and (17) not strict. pretty unpalatable still. There is much incentive to look for a
Now, from (18) and the fact that (17) holds with equality, we have hypothesis that is less disagreeable to common sense.

L PrSi,r+1(pn,O) =O.
jeR 9. Diagonal Dominance
But Sr+ 1,r+ 1(pn,O) = O, so by WGS and the fact that Pi > O, all Suppose that we wished to investigate the consequences of the
> r, it must be that hypothesis that the excess demand (supply) of each good is "more
S;,r+1 =O allj>r+l. sensitive" to a change in its own price than it is to a change in the
prices of all other goods combined. If this idea is to be made
Once again (17) must hold with sr+ 2 and k,+l replaced by kr+ 2 Jf precise, it is clear that careful attention will have to be given to the
the inequality is strict for this good, we again deduce (19) for units in which goods are measured. If we imagine the demand
"r + 2" and, therefore, (13) cannot hold. lf not, we proceed as function for a good plotted in a multi-dimensional diagram whose
_/

before to r + 3, and so on. lf at no stage we obtain a strict axes are the different prices, the slope of the resulting demand surface
inequality in the appropriate form of (17), then it must be that in any direction will depend on the units in which we have chosen to
s;(pn,O) = O for all j > r. But then, sin ce by the argument of (b) measure the various goods. It is, of course, for this reason that we
s;(pn,O) ~ O, all j ~ r, and since p~ O and by assumption (Pn,O) is use elasticities to measure the responsiveness of demand to changes
not an equilibrium, it follows that for some j ~ r, s;(pn,O) < O and in price. In formulating our hypothesis precisely, therefore, we
so p~sn(Pn,O) < O and p~sn(P) is not maximized at (pn,O). Since shall wish to put it in the form: There is at p so me way of measuring
p~sn(P~,O) = O clearly cannot be a minimum of p~sn(p), the theorem goods such that for all of them it is true that their excess demands
is proved. are more sensitive to a change in their own price than they are to a
Coro llar y 11. lf all goods are W GS at all p then the set of change in other prices combined. We shall also impose a restriction
equilibrium prices (E) is co~vex. on the sign of the term giving the change in the excess demand for a
good when its own price changes.
Proof Let p* and p** be two unequal vectors in E and p(a) =
ap* + (! - a)p**: O ~ a ~ l. If the corollary is false, then for DEFINITION 8 (DD). The economy is said to have Diagonal
some a in the given range, p(a) is not in E. Then p(a)s(p(a)) = Dominance at p with Pn > O if
(ap* + (1 - a)p**)s(p(a)) = ap*s(p(a)) + (1 - a)p**s(p(a)) < O by (a) s(p) > O, all i,
T.9.11, and we have a contradiction of W. Hence p(a) EE, for all (b) there is a vector h(p) O, such that
a in the range.

The results we have established for the WGS case are a good deal
h1(p)s(p) > :
n>NI
Js1;(p)Jh(p) all i < n.
T
1
r
1'
11

11

1!
l.
232 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 233
!
Suppose, then, the inequality in (17) is not strict. If kr+ 2 = kr+ 1 , weaker than those that were establishable with GS, or WGS with
it is easily checked that we can obtain (17) for Sr+ 2 Ifthat inequality connectedness. Yet for many purposes of economic analysis it is
were strict, we would again get (19) for "r + 2" with the same correct to say that the convexity of the equilibrium set is as good as
conclusion. So consider kr+ 2 < kr+ 1 Then every component uniqueness, and WAR for all comparisons in which one price
kr+ 1P"t of kr+ 1 p~(r), with i > r + 1, exceeds p 1 Then, sin ce the belongs to E is as good as WAR for all comparisons in which one
inequality in (16) is not strict, it must be true, because of WGS, that price vector is the unique equilibrium one. This will become clear
Sr+ 1jpn,O) = O for j > r + l. Additionally, by H, Sr+ 1,r+ 1 = O later in this book. The drawback of the WGS assumption, there-
and we conclude fore, is not the weakness of its implications for the equilibrium set,
but rather the weak appeal of the assumption itself. It is only
allj;::: r +1 if kr+1 > kr+2 slightly less ~estrictive and unappealing than GS and that makes it
and (17) not strict. pretty unpalatable still. There is much incentive to look for a
Now, from (18) and the fact that (17) holds with equality, we have hypothesis that is less disagreeable to common sense.

L PrSi,r+1(pn,O) =O.
jeR 9. Diagonal Dominance
But Sr+ 1,r+ 1(pn,O) = O, so by WGS and the fact that Pi > O, all Suppose that we wished to investigate the consequences of the
> r, it must be that hypothesis that the excess demand (supply) of each good is "more
S;,r+1 =O allj>r+l. sensitive" to a change in its own price than it is to a change in the
prices of all other goods combined. If this idea is to be made
Once again (17) must hold with sr+ 2 and k,+l replaced by kr+ 2 Jf precise, it is clear that careful attention will have to be given to the
the inequality is strict for this good, we again deduce (19) for units in which goods are measured. If we imagine the demand
"r + 2" and, therefore, (13) cannot hold. lf not, we proceed as function for a good plotted in a multi-dimensional diagram whose
_/

before to r + 3, and so on. lf at no stage we obtain a strict axes are the different prices, the slope of the resulting demand surface
inequality in the appropriate form of (17), then it must be that in any direction will depend on the units in which we have chosen to
s;(pn,O) = O for all j > r. But then, sin ce by the argument of (b) measure the various goods. It is, of course, for this reason that we
s;(pn,O) ~ O, all j ~ r, and since p~ O and by assumption (Pn,O) is use elasticities to measure the responsiveness of demand to changes
not an equilibrium, it follows that for some j ~ r, s;(pn,O) < O and in price. In formulating our hypothesis precisely, therefore, we
so p~sn(Pn,O) < O and p~sn(P) is not maximized at (pn,O). Since shall wish to put it in the form: There is at p so me way of measuring
p~sn(P~,O) = O clearly cannot be a minimum of p~sn(p), the theorem goods such that for all of them it is true that their excess demands
is proved. are more sensitive to a change in their own price than they are to a
Coro llar y 11. lf all goods are W GS at all p then the set of change in other prices combined. We shall also impose a restriction
equilibrium prices (E) is co~vex. on the sign of the term giving the change in the excess demand for a
good when its own price changes.
Proof Let p* and p** be two unequal vectors in E and p(a) =
ap* + (! - a)p**: O ~ a ~ l. If the corollary is false, then for DEFINITION 8 (DD). The economy is said to have Diagonal
some a in the given range, p(a) is not in E. Then p(a)s(p(a)) = Dominance at p with Pn > O if
(ap* + (1 - a)p**)s(p(a)) = ap*s(p(a)) + (1 - a)p**s(p(a)) < O by (a) s(p) > O, all i,
T.9.11, and we have a contradiction of W. Hence p(a) EE, for all (b) there is a vector h(p) O, such that
a in the range.

The results we have established for the WGS case are a good deal
h1(p)s(p) > :
n>NI
Js1;(p)Jh(p) all i < n.
T
1

234 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 235

Part (a) ofthe definition means that when we cometo stipulate DD (P = (1/pn)p). Suppose there exists v > O, such that TJ(P*)Tv ::5: O. i
:1
for an economy, we shall be implying that the substitution terms .\11 Then, setting w1 = v1/h{P*), it must be that TJ+(P*)Tw ::5: O. Let
in Eq. (10) (for j = i), which are known to be negative, are large in 1

absolute value relative to the income term. If that is not so, we


must rely on a high responsiveness (known to be positive) in the
Then
supply of the ith good to a change in its price. W e can think of
examples where this is not the case, but far less readily than was the tMr(P*)Srr(P*)wr ::5: -
i*r

trrh(P*)sr(P*)tfiWf ::5: Wrf*r
h{P*)[srJ(P*)[,
case for OS, and even less readily when DD is taken to hold locally
only. By and large, assuming part (a) to hold does not appear which contradicts DD. Hence J(P*) has OP, and T.9.2 establishes
absurd and is in conformity with much of economic theory. the result.
Part (b) is in the spirit of our introductory remarks. Note that
Corollary 12. If for all p the economy has DD and N holds, then
s11 is the partial of s1 when i and j are measured in any given units; equilibrium is unique.
so (h 1/h 1)s11 will be the value of the partial when one new unit of i
is now equal to h1 old units and one new unit of j is equal to h1 old By and large, we may rest quite satisfied with the results of this
units of j. Thus (b) says that there are sorne units in which to section. As we have already argued, DD is not an obviously silly 1:

measure goods such that the diagonal term dominates the off- restriction to impose on the system. Of course, this does not mean
diagonal terms with j < n. lt is reasonable to ask why we should that all actual systems will satisfy DD. What it does mean is that
have excluded the nth good. it will be worthwhile, ata later stage in the book, to further investigate
,, the properties of such economies. 1 1
1
'
First, it should be clear that the choice of n was arbitrary. If
1 ,,
' 11 Ps > O, and on excluding the sth good in the same way, but including 1
,
:
: 1 the nth, (a) and (b) are satisfied and we should still say that the 10. Other Sufficient Conditions for Uniqueness :1
1

li
economy has DD at p. Secondly, let h1, i = 1, ... , n, be any set of llii
positive numbers. Let q1 = pjh1 and say qr = max q1 Then, using In this section we shall investigate a number of other restrictions
H, on the excess-demand functions that are sufficient to ensure the
uniqueness of an equilibrium. These conditions share the dis-
advantage that it is hard to give them any obvious economic motiva-
tion. However, that does not mean that they are without interest,
and clearly DD is impossible if we include all goods. since there is no reason to explain further the actual properties of,
Lastly, it is worth noting that DD is definitely a weaker require- say, the Jacobian J(P) of an actual eco no my by more or less common
ment than OS for p O. The latter implies DD, while DD does sense appeals to economic theory.
not imply OS. The second part of this statement is obvious. The DEFINITION 9. A matrix A is said to be positive definite if for aii
first foilows at once from H. If we set h;(p) = P;, aii j and p recall non-zero values of the vector v~ v'Av > O, and A is symmetric. A
s1n > O, we at once verify (b) of the definition; that (a) must hold is said to be positive quasi-definite if for all non-zero values of the
is obvious. By the same argument, DD is weaker than WOS for vector v, v'[(A + A')/2]v > O. (A' is the transpose of A.)
p O and s1n(P) > O, sorne i.
lt is easy to establish the following results. THEOREM 13. If, for all P* E E, J(P*) is either positive definite or
positive quasi-definite and if N holds, then the economy has a
THEOREM 12. If for all pE E, the set of equilibrium prices, the unique equilibrium.
economy lias DD, and if N holds, then equilibrium is unique.
Proof. We establish that J(P*) has OP.
Proof Let J+(P*) have elements h;(P*)s1{P*), where p* E E, (a) Suppose that J(P*) is positive definite, but does not have

'
l.\'
T
1

234 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 235

Part (a) ofthe definition means that when we cometo stipulate DD (P = (1/pn)p). Suppose there exists v > O, such that TJ(P*)Tv ::5: O. i
:1
for an economy, we shall be implying that the substitution terms .\11 Then, setting w1 = v1/h{P*), it must be that TJ+(P*)Tw ::5: O. Let
in Eq. (10) (for j = i), which are known to be negative, are large in 1

absolute value relative to the income term. If that is not so, we


must rely on a high responsiveness (known to be positive) in the
Then
supply of the ith good to a change in its price. W e can think of
examples where this is not the case, but far less readily than was the tMr(P*)Srr(P*)wr ::5: -
i*r

trrh(P*)sr(P*)tfiWf ::5: Wrf*r
h{P*)[srJ(P*)[,
case for OS, and even less readily when DD is taken to hold locally
only. By and large, assuming part (a) to hold does not appear which contradicts DD. Hence J(P*) has OP, and T.9.2 establishes
absurd and is in conformity with much of economic theory. the result.
Part (b) is in the spirit of our introductory remarks. Note that
Corollary 12. If for all p the economy has DD and N holds, then
s11 is the partial of s1 when i and j are measured in any given units; equilibrium is unique.
so (h 1/h 1)s11 will be the value of the partial when one new unit of i
is now equal to h1 old units and one new unit of j is equal to h1 old By and large, we may rest quite satisfied with the results of this
units of j. Thus (b) says that there are sorne units in which to section. As we have already argued, DD is not an obviously silly 1:

measure goods such that the diagonal term dominates the off- restriction to impose on the system. Of course, this does not mean
diagonal terms with j < n. lt is reasonable to ask why we should that all actual systems will satisfy DD. What it does mean is that
have excluded the nth good. it will be worthwhile, ata later stage in the book, to further investigate
,, the properties of such economies. 1 1
1
'
First, it should be clear that the choice of n was arbitrary. If
1 ,,
' 11 Ps > O, and on excluding the sth good in the same way, but including 1
,
:
: 1 the nth, (a) and (b) are satisfied and we should still say that the 10. Other Sufficient Conditions for Uniqueness :1
1

li
economy has DD at p. Secondly, let h1, i = 1, ... , n, be any set of llii
positive numbers. Let q1 = pjh1 and say qr = max q1 Then, using In this section we shall investigate a number of other restrictions
H, on the excess-demand functions that are sufficient to ensure the
uniqueness of an equilibrium. These conditions share the dis-
advantage that it is hard to give them any obvious economic motiva-
tion. However, that does not mean that they are without interest,
and clearly DD is impossible if we include all goods. since there is no reason to explain further the actual properties of,
Lastly, it is worth noting that DD is definitely a weaker require- say, the Jacobian J(P) of an actual eco no my by more or less common
ment than OS for p O. The latter implies DD, while DD does sense appeals to economic theory.
not imply OS. The second part of this statement is obvious. The DEFINITION 9. A matrix A is said to be positive definite if for aii
first foilows at once from H. If we set h;(p) = P;, aii j and p recall non-zero values of the vector v~ v'Av > O, and A is symmetric. A
s1n > O, we at once verify (b) of the definition; that (a) must hold is said to be positive quasi-definite if for all non-zero values of the
is obvious. By the same argument, DD is weaker than WOS for vector v, v'[(A + A')/2]v > O. (A' is the transpose of A.)
p O and s1n(P) > O, sorne i.
lt is easy to establish the following results. THEOREM 13. If, for all P* E E, J(P*) is either positive definite or
positive quasi-definite and if N holds, then the economy has a
THEOREM 12. If for all pE E, the set of equilibrium prices, the unique equilibrium.
economy lias DD, and if N holds, then equilibrium is unique.
Proof. We establish that J(P*) has OP.
Proof Let J+(P*) have elements h;(P*)s1{P*), where p* E E, (a) Suppose that J(P*) is positive definite, but does not have

'
l.\'
1
1
r
1

236 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 237

GP, that is, for sorne T and sorne v > O, TJ(P*)Tv s O. But then THEOREM 16. Let the Leontief economy satisfy A.2.10-A.2.13.
(Tv)'J(P*)Tv s O, which contradicts J(P*) positive definite. Then equilibrium is unique.
(b) If J(P *) is positive quasi-definite, the same argument as in
(a) holds since Proof Let 7T(p) be the unit profit function of the ith sector, that
'J(P*) V_- V, J(P*) + J(P*)' V. is,
V
2 7T(p) = p - C(p) i=1, ... ,n-1
But if J(P*) has GP then T.9.2 establishes the theorem.
where C1(p) is the mnimum unit cost function of l (see A.2.13). If
THEOREM 14. If, for all P* E E, the determinant of every principal
p~ is the equilibrium price of labor, we know (T.2.6) that p~ > O,
submatrix of J(P*) is positive and if N holds, then the economy has a In addition, if p* is an equilibrium, 1t(p*) = O and, of course,
unique equilibrium.
7r(p*k) = k7T(p*), for k > O. Hence, by Euler's theorem,
This is a restatement of Lemma 9.2.
'

1 ''
1 ~
It should be noted that the conditions of T.9.14 are weaker than 7T(p*)pf + ;
n>Ni
7T(p*)pj = -7Tn{p*)p~ i= 1, ... ,n-1,
any case (except for the Hicksian with sorne zero equilibrium prices
(20)
1 i where no comparison is possible) we have considered so far. This is
1 i i' clear from the single fact that, by T.9.12, DD implies GP, which is where 7T(p*) = 87T(p*)/8p1. But we know (T.3.6) that 7T1n(p*) =
1 '

: :: equivalent to the condition of T.9.14, but not vice versa. The - a1n, where ain is the input of labor per unit of output of i, so the
second part of this statement is obvious as a simple 2 x 2 example right-hand side of (20) is positive. Since 7Ttt(P*) > O (see T.3.6) and
1!
would illustrate. 7T(p*) s O for j i= i, (20) tells us that the matrix H(p*) = [7r(p*)],
r:IJJ The following theorem is weaker in sorne respects and stronger in has DD (where H(p*) is (n - 1) x (n - 1)). Hence, by proof of
1! others than T.9.14. T.9.12, H(p*) has GP. Since this must be true at every equilibrium,
THEOREM 15. If J(P) is non-singular and J - 1 z(P) is continuously it follows from T.9.2 that there is only one equilibrium.
differentiable for all P O, where z(P) is the vector of excess
1
j
demands for the non-numeraire commodities, and if
; Z(p)

12. Economies with No Joint Production but Many Factors

approaches +oo whenever p approaches a limit, p 0 with pf = O, sorne The Leontief economy can be generalized by dropping the
i, then the economy has a unique, strictly positive equilibrium. requirement that there can be only one primary factor. We retain
the assurriptions of constant returns to scale and no joint production
This theorem makes global rather than local assumptions about and postulate that any net output requires sorne use of factors.
the Jacobian and, in addition, makes strong requirements with Let y be the vector of produced goods, z the vector of demands for
respect to the boundary, though these may be capable of relaxation. factor inputs (taken non-negative)_y and L the vector of initial factor
On the other hand, only the non-singularity of the Jacobian is holdings. As before, there are no endowments of produced goods.
assumed; nothing is said about the principal minors. Let p be the vector of prices of produced goods, w the vector of
The proof we will give depends on dynamic arguments and is factor prices. Let C(p,w) be the vector of mnimum unit cost
postponed to Section 12.8. functions. Then, if all goods are produced, equilibrium requires
that p = C(p,w). There are a number of questions that may be
11. The Leontief Economy asked of this model; the "two-sector" m o del and factor price
We considered this economy in Section 2.11. Here we give equalization discussed below have been much discussed in the
conditions that suffice for it to have a unique equilibrium. literature.

'1"
"'
1

il
1
1
r
1

236 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 237

GP, that is, for sorne T and sorne v > O, TJ(P*)Tv s O. But then THEOREM 16. Let the Leontief economy satisfy A.2.10-A.2.13.
(Tv)'J(P*)Tv s O, which contradicts J(P*) positive definite. Then equilibrium is unique.
(b) If J(P *) is positive quasi-definite, the same argument as in
(a) holds since Proof Let 7T(p) be the unit profit function of the ith sector, that
'J(P*) V_- V, J(P*) + J(P*)' V. is,
V
2 7T(p) = p - C(p) i=1, ... ,n-1
But if J(P*) has GP then T.9.2 establishes the theorem.
where C1(p) is the mnimum unit cost function of l (see A.2.13). If
THEOREM 14. If, for all P* E E, the determinant of every principal
p~ is the equilibrium price of labor, we know (T.2.6) that p~ > O,
submatrix of J(P*) is positive and if N holds, then the economy has a In addition, if p* is an equilibrium, 1t(p*) = O and, of course,
unique equilibrium.
7r(p*k) = k7T(p*), for k > O. Hence, by Euler's theorem,
This is a restatement of Lemma 9.2.
'

1 ''
1 ~
It should be noted that the conditions of T.9.14 are weaker than 7T(p*)pf + ;
n>Ni
7T(p*)pj = -7Tn{p*)p~ i= 1, ... ,n-1,
any case (except for the Hicksian with sorne zero equilibrium prices
(20)
1 i where no comparison is possible) we have considered so far. This is
1 i i' clear from the single fact that, by T.9.12, DD implies GP, which is where 7T(p*) = 87T(p*)/8p1. But we know (T.3.6) that 7T1n(p*) =
1 '

: :: equivalent to the condition of T.9.14, but not vice versa. The - a1n, where ain is the input of labor per unit of output of i, so the
second part of this statement is obvious as a simple 2 x 2 example right-hand side of (20) is positive. Since 7Ttt(P*) > O (see T.3.6) and
1!
would illustrate. 7T(p*) s O for j i= i, (20) tells us that the matrix H(p*) = [7r(p*)],
r:IJJ The following theorem is weaker in sorne respects and stronger in has DD (where H(p*) is (n - 1) x (n - 1)). Hence, by proof of
1! others than T.9.14. T.9.12, H(p*) has GP. Since this must be true at every equilibrium,
THEOREM 15. If J(P) is non-singular and J - 1 z(P) is continuously it follows from T.9.2 that there is only one equilibrium.
differentiable for all P O, where z(P) is the vector of excess
1
j
demands for the non-numeraire commodities, and if
; Z(p)

12. Economies with No Joint Production but Many Factors

approaches +oo whenever p approaches a limit, p 0 with pf = O, sorne The Leontief economy can be generalized by dropping the
i, then the economy has a unique, strictly positive equilibrium. requirement that there can be only one primary factor. We retain
the assurriptions of constant returns to scale and no joint production
This theorem makes global rather than local assumptions about and postulate that any net output requires sorne use of factors.
the Jacobian and, in addition, makes strong requirements with Let y be the vector of produced goods, z the vector of demands for
respect to the boundary, though these may be capable of relaxation. factor inputs (taken non-negative)_y and L the vector of initial factor
On the other hand, only the non-singularity of the Jacobian is holdings. As before, there are no endowments of produced goods.
assumed; nothing is said about the principal minors. Let p be the vector of prices of produced goods, w the vector of
The proof we will give depends on dynamic arguments and is factor prices. Let C(p,w) be the vector of mnimum unit cost
postponed to Section 12.8. functions. Then, if all goods are produced, equilibrium requires
that p = C(p,w). There are a number of questions that may be
11. The Leontief Economy asked of this model; the "two-sector" m o del and factor price
We considered this economy in Section 2.11. Here we give equalization discussed below have been much discussed in the
conditions that suffice for it to have a unique equilibrium. literature.

'1"
"'
1

il
r i

11
,l

i !1
238 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 239
1
i
Determination of commodity prices by factor prices. For any What we have just proved clearly holds for any two-goods
given factor price vector, w > O, we can regard the factors as a economy, and we sum up this result in the following.
composite commodity; then all the assumptions of the Leontief THEOREM 17. Let p be a price vector in the two-dimensional sim-
economy are satisfied, and from T.9 .16 we can find a unique vector plex, z(p) a two-dimensional excess-demand vector function. Then
p that satisfies the conditions of zero profit in each industry. Then a necessary and sufficient condition that p* is the unique equilibrium
p = p(w) is a function of w; since all the demand and cost functions for the two-goods economy is that p*z(p) > O for all p for which
are continuous, it can easily be seen that p is a continuous function p =1= p*. (The two-goods economy is assumed to satisfy all the
of w. Further, as we know, we can choose the activity levels in each usual assumptions that we have used to show that at least one
industry so that supply equals demand on each produced goods eq uili bri um exists.)
market and the total value of demand for factors, at the vector w,
equals the value of initial endowment. Assume that producers We now know that we need conditions that ensure w*S(w) < O
supply exactly what is demanded when prices satisfy the zero-profit for all w =1= w* in the simplex. Certainly it is easy to check that this
condition. Then we hf\ve defined an excess-supply function, will be the case if the economy is "Hicksian" in the outputs. We
s(p,w) = s[p(w),w] = S(w), say, for the factors, and this must itself shall consider instead a situation that has been much discussed in the
satisfy W; that is, wS(w) = O, for all w > O. It then follows that w* recent literature on the theory of economic growth.
can be so chosen as to define equilibrium in the factor markets and Suppose there are two kinds of households; one kind labeled "1"
hence, with p* = p(w*), a general equilibrium. owns all of the input labeled "1" and derives utility only from the
This equilibrium need not be unique, in general, but p is defined good labeled "1 ," while similar! y the kind labeled "2" owns all of
uniquely by w. In fact, if we consider different economies with the the input with that label and derives utility only from the good
same technology, but possibly different factor endowments and labeled "2." (This can be translated to the "classical" savings
demand functions, we can still say that two equilibria with the same assumption of growth literature.) The househoids n each group
factor prices must have the same produced goods prices. are Hicksian. From these assumptions we quickly verify, assuming
all demands differentiable,
The "two-sector" model. Now consider, in particular, the OX
Pt 8p = -X i = 1, 2
uniqueness of equilibrium in the case of two primary factors. Since
S is certainly homogeneous of degree zero in w, we may normalize OX
by considering W E S2. Pt ow = L i = 1, 2,
We already know that if w* is an equilibrium (here assumed to where L 1 is the amount of the ith input available.
exist), then w*S(w) < O, all w not proportional to w*, is a sufficient Further suppose that the production of each good requires on1y
condition for the uniqueness of the equilibrium. Here it is neces- primary factors; neither good serves as an intermedia te product.
saty. For example, suppose equilibrium is unique. If (0,1) is not If y 1 is the producers' demand for factor i, then,
an equilibrium, then, with the aid of W, we must have S 1(0,1) < O,
S2(0,1) =O, so that w*S(0,1) < O. Similarly, if (1,0) is not an y 1(x,w) = aflx
j
1 i = 1, 2,
equilibrium, w*S(1,0) < O. Suppose the equation w*S(w) = O had
a solution on the unit simplex different from w*, say w'. Then where a11 is the amount of factor input i per unit of output j; it
w*S(w') = O, while, by W, w'S(w') =O. Since the matrix with rows depends on w, and from T.3.6, dp 1fdw 1 = a1, i, j = 1, 2.
w* ,w' is certainly non-singular, it must be that S(w') = O, contrary Now consideran equilibrium w*. Let Z 1 (= -S1) be the excess
to the assumption that w* is the unique equilibrium. lf w*S(w) = O demand for input 1, and write Z 12 =
8Z1/8w 2. Using these relations
only for w = w* and w*S(w) < O for sorne w, it must be that for all and the household-demand conditions and taking all derivatives at
w =!= w*, w*S(w) < O. w*, we have

'L
,,
'l -~~--~--'--~-----~-
r i

11
,l

i !1
238 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 239
1
i
Determination of commodity prices by factor prices. For any What we have just proved clearly holds for any two-goods
given factor price vector, w > O, we can regard the factors as a economy, and we sum up this result in the following.
composite commodity; then all the assumptions of the Leontief THEOREM 17. Let p be a price vector in the two-dimensional sim-
economy are satisfied, and from T.9 .16 we can find a unique vector plex, z(p) a two-dimensional excess-demand vector function. Then
p that satisfies the conditions of zero profit in each industry. Then a necessary and sufficient condition that p* is the unique equilibrium
p = p(w) is a function of w; since all the demand and cost functions for the two-goods economy is that p*z(p) > O for all p for which
are continuous, it can easily be seen that p is a continuous function p =1= p*. (The two-goods economy is assumed to satisfy all the
of w. Further, as we know, we can choose the activity levels in each usual assumptions that we have used to show that at least one
industry so that supply equals demand on each produced goods eq uili bri um exists.)
market and the total value of demand for factors, at the vector w,
equals the value of initial endowment. Assume that producers We now know that we need conditions that ensure w*S(w) < O
supply exactly what is demanded when prices satisfy the zero-profit for all w =1= w* in the simplex. Certainly it is easy to check that this
condition. Then we hf\ve defined an excess-supply function, will be the case if the economy is "Hicksian" in the outputs. We
s(p,w) = s[p(w),w] = S(w), say, for the factors, and this must itself shall consider instead a situation that has been much discussed in the
satisfy W; that is, wS(w) = O, for all w > O. It then follows that w* recent literature on the theory of economic growth.
can be so chosen as to define equilibrium in the factor markets and Suppose there are two kinds of households; one kind labeled "1"
hence, with p* = p(w*), a general equilibrium. owns all of the input labeled "1" and derives utility only from the
This equilibrium need not be unique, in general, but p is defined good labeled "1 ," while similar! y the kind labeled "2" owns all of
uniquely by w. In fact, if we consider different economies with the the input with that label and derives utility only from the good
same technology, but possibly different factor endowments and labeled "2." (This can be translated to the "classical" savings
demand functions, we can still say that two equilibria with the same assumption of growth literature.) The househoids n each group
factor prices must have the same produced goods prices. are Hicksian. From these assumptions we quickly verify, assuming
all demands differentiable,
The "two-sector" model. Now consider, in particular, the OX
Pt 8p = -X i = 1, 2
uniqueness of equilibrium in the case of two primary factors. Since
S is certainly homogeneous of degree zero in w, we may normalize OX
by considering W E S2. Pt ow = L i = 1, 2,
We already know that if w* is an equilibrium (here assumed to where L 1 is the amount of the ith input available.
exist), then w*S(w) < O, all w not proportional to w*, is a sufficient Further suppose that the production of each good requires on1y
condition for the uniqueness of the equilibrium. Here it is neces- primary factors; neither good serves as an intermedia te product.
saty. For example, suppose equilibrium is unique. If (0,1) is not If y 1 is the producers' demand for factor i, then,
an equilibrium, then, with the aid of W, we must have S 1(0,1) < O,
S2(0,1) =O, so that w*S(0,1) < O. Similarly, if (1,0) is not an y 1(x,w) = aflx
j
1 i = 1, 2,
equilibrium, w*S(1,0) < O. Suppose the equation w*S(w) = O had
a solution on the unit simplex different from w*, say w'. Then where a11 is the amount of factor input i per unit of output j; it
w*S(w') = O, while, by W, w'S(w') =O. Since the matrix with rows depends on w, and from T.3.6, dp 1fdw 1 = a1, i, j = 1, 2.
w* ,w' is certainly non-singular, it must be that S(w') = O, contrary Now consideran equilibrium w*. Let Z 1 (= -S1) be the excess
to the assumption that w* is the unique equilibrium. lf w*S(w) = O demand for input 1, and write Z 12 =
8Z1/8w 2. Using these relations
only for w = w* and w*S(w) < O for sorne w, it must be that for all and the household-demand conditions and taking all derivatives at
w =!= w*, w*S(w) < O. w*, we have

'L
,,
'l -~~--~--'--~-----~-
--

1
1

240 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 241

212
= BYt ox1 dp1 + By1 (ox2 dp 2 + .ox2) + oy 1 solves these equations. But oCtfow is the intensity with which
ox1 8Pl dw2 ox 2 8p 2 dw 2 ow 2 ow 2 industry i uses input j (T.3.6), so for instance, if there is sorne
ordering of inputs and sectors such that each sector uses the input
a22
X1
-a11a12- - a21X2- + a 2 1L2- +-
8Yt
with the same label more intensively than it does all other inputs
P1 P P2 8w2
combined; that is, if the Jacobian has DD, then it will also ha ve GP
and w will uniquely solve the above equations.
In this example the economics of our conditions are extremely
unattractive. Pearce [1967] has shown that rather weaker con-
ditions will suffice provided we are willing to extend the domain of
C( ) to the set of all W that make C( ) non-negative. Since this
since in equilibrium L 1 = x 1 a 12 + x 2a22 . Hence, Z 12 (w*) > O if includes negative factor prices the meaning of such an extension of
a21/P2 > a 11 /p 1 since 8Ytfi7w 2 ;:::: O. Since both industries are the domain is somewhat obscure.
making zero profits, PJ = a 1 W 1 + a 2 w2 , it is easy to verify that the As our example illustrates, however, the most general uniqueness
condition a 21 /p 2 > a 11 /p 1 is equivalent to the same condition with conditions discussed in this chapter are still extremely restrictive,
the subscripts "1 " and "2" interchanged, so that this condition and we must hope that acceptable weaker conditions will become
ensures Z 21 (w) > O. Hence, the two inputs are gross substitutes in available. Even so, a reformulation of the question posed at the
every equilibrium if good i uses inputj (j -1= i) more intensively than beginning of this example does allow us to give a definite answer.
good j does. This means that equilibrium is unique and so, by Suppose that the economy has a given endowment vector. Is it
T.9.17, w*S(w) < O, all w i= w*. possible to ha ve given p, two values of w for which the economy is
There are, of course, other assumptions on household behavior in equilibrium, and not only in the sense that unit costs are covered,
and the production sets that ensure uniqueness. They all, however, but also in the sense that all markets are cleared ?
seem to entail the GS property (though we have not made an Suppose there are two equilibria, (p,w) and (p,w*), with the same
exhaustive check). vector of goods prices. Let (y,z) be the vector of outputs and inputs
This example is instructive for two reasons. First of all, it shows corresponding to the first equilibrium, (y* ,z*) to the second. Since
the need to examine the economics of purely formal uniqueness maximum profits in either case are zero, we must have
conditions. Second, it makes clear how special the case of two
goods is (a recurring result, e.g., T.12.I)". In the present instance, py- w*z :si O py* - wz* .:::; O. (21)
the fact that w*S(w) < O, for w -1= w*, is necessary for uniqueness is By W, py = wL, py* = w*L. If we add the above inequalities and
helpful, but this property will not hold for an economy with more make the indicated substitutions, we see that wS* + w*S .:::; O. By
than two inputs. definition of equilibrium, however, S* ;:::: O, S ;:::: O, so that equality
must hold. Hence, we must have py - w*z = O (and also py* -
Factor price equalization. We now considera problem arising in wz* = O). If (y1,z1) is the equilibrium input-output vector for the
the theory of international trade. In the general model with no ith industry at (p,w), then profit maximization implies that py 1 -
joint production and constant returns, goods prices and factor prices w*z1 .:::; O, each i; summing over i implies that py - w*z .:::; O; since
satisfy the relation p = C(p,w), as we have noted. We now assume we know the equality holds, it must hold for each i, since a sum of
that the number of factors, m, equals the number of goods. The non-positive numbers is zero if and only if each one is zero. By
question asked is this: Given p, is there a unique w that sol ves these constant returns, py 1 - wz1 = O for each i, so (w* - w)(z 1 z"') =
equations? O, where (z 1 z"') is the matrix with columns z1
lf (C11) is the Jacobian with element (8Cjow 1), then if this Jacobian Now assume that at the equilibrium (p,w) all goods are produced
has GP we know that there can be only one w in the simplex that and the input vectors of the various industries are linearly
--

1
1

240 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 241

212
= BYt ox1 dp1 + By1 (ox2 dp 2 + .ox2) + oy 1 solves these equations. But oCtfow is the intensity with which
ox1 8Pl dw2 ox 2 8p 2 dw 2 ow 2 ow 2 industry i uses input j (T.3.6), so for instance, if there is sorne
ordering of inputs and sectors such that each sector uses the input
a22
X1
-a11a12- - a21X2- + a 2 1L2- +-
8Yt
with the same label more intensively than it does all other inputs
P1 P P2 8w2
combined; that is, if the Jacobian has DD, then it will also ha ve GP
and w will uniquely solve the above equations.
In this example the economics of our conditions are extremely
unattractive. Pearce [1967] has shown that rather weaker con-
ditions will suffice provided we are willing to extend the domain of
C( ) to the set of all W that make C( ) non-negative. Since this
since in equilibrium L 1 = x 1 a 12 + x 2a22 . Hence, Z 12 (w*) > O if includes negative factor prices the meaning of such an extension of
a21/P2 > a 11 /p 1 since 8Ytfi7w 2 ;:::: O. Since both industries are the domain is somewhat obscure.
making zero profits, PJ = a 1 W 1 + a 2 w2 , it is easy to verify that the As our example illustrates, however, the most general uniqueness
condition a 21 /p 2 > a 11 /p 1 is equivalent to the same condition with conditions discussed in this chapter are still extremely restrictive,
the subscripts "1 " and "2" interchanged, so that this condition and we must hope that acceptable weaker conditions will become
ensures Z 21 (w) > O. Hence, the two inputs are gross substitutes in available. Even so, a reformulation of the question posed at the
every equilibrium if good i uses inputj (j -1= i) more intensively than beginning of this example does allow us to give a definite answer.
good j does. This means that equilibrium is unique and so, by Suppose that the economy has a given endowment vector. Is it
T.9.17, w*S(w) < O, all w i= w*. possible to ha ve given p, two values of w for which the economy is
There are, of course, other assumptions on household behavior in equilibrium, and not only in the sense that unit costs are covered,
and the production sets that ensure uniqueness. They all, however, but also in the sense that all markets are cleared ?
seem to entail the GS property (though we have not made an Suppose there are two equilibria, (p,w) and (p,w*), with the same
exhaustive check). vector of goods prices. Let (y,z) be the vector of outputs and inputs
This example is instructive for two reasons. First of all, it shows corresponding to the first equilibrium, (y* ,z*) to the second. Since
the need to examine the economics of purely formal uniqueness maximum profits in either case are zero, we must have
conditions. Second, it makes clear how special the case of two
goods is (a recurring result, e.g., T.12.I)". In the present instance, py- w*z :si O py* - wz* .:::; O. (21)
the fact that w*S(w) < O, for w -1= w*, is necessary for uniqueness is By W, py = wL, py* = w*L. If we add the above inequalities and
helpful, but this property will not hold for an economy with more make the indicated substitutions, we see that wS* + w*S .:::; O. By
than two inputs. definition of equilibrium, however, S* ;:::: O, S ;:::: O, so that equality
must hold. Hence, we must have py - w*z = O (and also py* -
Factor price equalization. We now considera problem arising in wz* = O). If (y1,z1) is the equilibrium input-output vector for the
the theory of international trade. In the general model with no ith industry at (p,w), then profit maximization implies that py 1 -
joint production and constant returns, goods prices and factor prices w*z1 .:::; O, each i; summing over i implies that py - w*z .:::; O; since
satisfy the relation p = C(p,w), as we have noted. We now assume we know the equality holds, it must hold for each i, since a sum of
that the number of factors, m, equals the number of goods. The non-positive numbers is zero if and only if each one is zero. By
question asked is this: Given p, is there a unique w that sol ves these constant returns, py 1 - wz1 = O for each i, so (w* - w)(z 1 z"') =
equations? O, where (z 1 z"') is the matrix with columns z1
lf (C11) is the Jacobian with element (8Cjow 1), then if this Jacobian Now assume that at the equilibrium (p,w) all goods are produced
has GP we know that there can be only one w in the simplex that and the input vectors of the various industries are linearly
242 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1
r

THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 243

independent. Then the matrix (z 1 zm) is non-singular, so that w columns of the Jacobian, all its leading principal minors are non-
must equal w*; that is, factor prices are uniquely determined by vanishing. This proposition paid insufficient attention to the domain
goods prices. of the mapping and Gale and Nikaid [1965] showed it to be false by
means of a counter example. They then established a sufficient con-
dition, here called "Gale Property," which is the foundation of much .of
this chapter. More recently, Pearce [1967] and Pearce and W1se
13. Conclusion [unpublished] have sought to find much weaker sufficient conditions.
Almost all economists, whether or not they are "theoretical," These studies turn on theorems on covering mappings and lead to
conditions that require only that over the requisite domain a certain
when asked to evaluate the fairly long-run consequences of a shift Jacobian should not vanish. We have commented briefly on one aspect
in sorne parameter of an economy, will attempt, certainly in the first of this work in Section 9.12. The more recent work of Pearce and Wise
stage, a comparison of the equilibrium before and after the change. appeared too late to be thoroughly explored here. On one matter,
If equilibrium is not unique this procedure may break down. In this however, comment is appropriate.
chapter, we have explored sorne of the sufficient conditions for this Pearce and Wise examine the case in which ps(P) ---+ O as Pt ---+ O.
Suppose the economy has an equilibrium P* O. We may construct
method to have a ci;lance. Unfortunately, necessary conditions are
unlikely to be available. Nonetheless, it can be argued that the
=
a reduced economy by setting p 1 O and noting that W holds for this
reduced economy. (This was discussed in another context by Hahn
conditions we have stated are not, in general, unreasonably demand- [1965].) Let the reduced economy have an equilibrium p**, with
ing, although the last example suggests that in sorne cases they may p** = O, of course. Suppose the two economies have non-vanishing
become so. Whether reasonable or not, they are the best available Jacobians in the neighborhoods of p* and p**, respectively. Then they
show that it is possible to find a p t p* that is an equilibrium, so that
at this stage to help answer an important question, on which so much the mapping is not univalent. Then the economy cannot have GP, but
of current analysis depends. Probably the most appealing of the we know that GS implies GP. Hence GS must imply ps1(p) does not
possible postulates leading to uniqueness is Diagonal Dominance. go to zero as p 1 ~>-O, whence s1(p) must be unbounded below. This i

This condition, if fulfilled in fact, would give a general equilibrium Pearce and Wise consider to be absurd. 1

system a kind of Mashallian flavor, inasmuch as the properties of the There are two comments we should like to make on this. First, GS
ensures that any equilibrium must be in the interior of the simplex and
demand and supply curves in the plane of the price of the good in we need never be concerned with the behavior of excess supplies at, or
question and the quantity supplied or demanded are in sorne sense indeed with suitable assumptions near, the boundaries. Surely they
lj! the "dominating" properties. lt means that partial analysis may take "unbounded demand" possibilities too literally. It is true that
not make serious mistakes. When the price of a good changes and GS forces this on us as a price goes to zero, but assuming GS over the
whole simplex (including boundaries) is to be taken as an idealization
il
we take others as fixed, it is reasonable to suppose in many cases
(as recent measure-theoretic approaches to general equilibrium are also
that, in fact, they are "almost" fixed. But then, in view of DD, the to be taken), which with care in application simplifies analysis without
answers we obtain from the "fixed" assumption will not be very leading us astray. Second, as T.9.3. shows, only assumptions of GP or
different from the correct answer. Whatever our intellectual pre- GS at equilibrium are needed.
disposition on the matter of partial versus general equilibrium That both weak revealed preference and GS imply uniqueness was 1'
first pointed out by Wald [1936; 1951, pp. 375~376, 385-387]. Arrow, t
analysis may be, we all meet practica! problems by a partial approach .!11
Block, and Hurwicz [1959, p. 90] first showed that if GS holds, weak
first, so these are comforting conclusions. Of cotlfSe, it still remains
revealed preference holds as between an equilibrium price vector and i:ll
to see how "good" the DD assumption is in fact. any other. The weak gross substitute extensions are dueto McKenzie '"l1!'
'1
[1960], Uzawa [1961], Morishima [1959, unpublished], and Arrow and '1

Hurwicz [1960].
Notes Much of the discussion of uniqueness in the literature was motivated
by the theory of factor-price equalization in international trade theory.
The study of uniqueness by examining the Jacobian of an appropriate The literature since Samuelson's [1948] paper is large; the results of
mapping was initiated by Samuelson [1953~54]. He thought a sufficient Section 9.12 are discussed more fully in McKenzie [1955a].
condition for uniqueness to be that for one permutation of the rows and Debreu [1970] has recently reexamined the possibilities for multiple

1'

1 11
242 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1
r

THE UNIQUENESS OF COMPETITIVE EQUILIBRIUM 243

independent. Then the matrix (z 1 zm) is non-singular, so that w columns of the Jacobian, all its leading principal minors are non-
must equal w*; that is, factor prices are uniquely determined by vanishing. This proposition paid insufficient attention to the domain
goods prices. of the mapping and Gale and Nikaid [1965] showed it to be false by
means of a counter example. They then established a sufficient con-
dition, here called "Gale Property," which is the foundation of much .of
this chapter. More recently, Pearce [1967] and Pearce and W1se
13. Conclusion [unpublished] have sought to find much weaker sufficient conditions.
Almost all economists, whether or not they are "theoretical," These studies turn on theorems on covering mappings and lead to
conditions that require only that over the requisite domain a certain
when asked to evaluate the fairly long-run consequences of a shift Jacobian should not vanish. We have commented briefly on one aspect
in sorne parameter of an economy, will attempt, certainly in the first of this work in Section 9.12. The more recent work of Pearce and Wise
stage, a comparison of the equilibrium before and after the change. appeared too late to be thoroughly explored here. On one matter,
If equilibrium is not unique this procedure may break down. In this however, comment is appropriate.
chapter, we have explored sorne of the sufficient conditions for this Pearce and Wise examine the case in which ps(P) ---+ O as Pt ---+ O.
Suppose the economy has an equilibrium P* O. We may construct
method to have a ci;lance. Unfortunately, necessary conditions are
unlikely to be available. Nonetheless, it can be argued that the
=
a reduced economy by setting p 1 O and noting that W holds for this
reduced economy. (This was discussed in another context by Hahn
conditions we have stated are not, in general, unreasonably demand- [1965].) Let the reduced economy have an equilibrium p**, with
ing, although the last example suggests that in sorne cases they may p** = O, of course. Suppose the two economies have non-vanishing
become so. Whether reasonable or not, they are the best available Jacobians in the neighborhoods of p* and p**, respectively. Then they
show that it is possible to find a p t p* that is an equilibrium, so that
at this stage to help answer an important question, on which so much the mapping is not univalent. Then the economy cannot have GP, but
of current analysis depends. Probably the most appealing of the we know that GS implies GP. Hence GS must imply ps1(p) does not
possible postulates leading to uniqueness is Diagonal Dominance. go to zero as p 1 ~>-O, whence s1(p) must be unbounded below. This i

This condition, if fulfilled in fact, would give a general equilibrium Pearce and Wise consider to be absurd. 1

system a kind of Mashallian flavor, inasmuch as the properties of the There are two comments we should like to make on this. First, GS
ensures that any equilibrium must be in the interior of the simplex and
demand and supply curves in the plane of the price of the good in we need never be concerned with the behavior of excess supplies at, or
question and the quantity supplied or demanded are in sorne sense indeed with suitable assumptions near, the boundaries. Surely they
lj! the "dominating" properties. lt means that partial analysis may take "unbounded demand" possibilities too literally. It is true that
not make serious mistakes. When the price of a good changes and GS forces this on us as a price goes to zero, but assuming GS over the
whole simplex (including boundaries) is to be taken as an idealization
il
we take others as fixed, it is reasonable to suppose in many cases
(as recent measure-theoretic approaches to general equilibrium are also
that, in fact, they are "almost" fixed. But then, in view of DD, the to be taken), which with care in application simplifies analysis without
answers we obtain from the "fixed" assumption will not be very leading us astray. Second, as T.9.3. shows, only assumptions of GP or
different from the correct answer. Whatever our intellectual pre- GS at equilibrium are needed.
disposition on the matter of partial versus general equilibrium That both weak revealed preference and GS imply uniqueness was 1'
first pointed out by Wald [1936; 1951, pp. 375~376, 385-387]. Arrow, t
analysis may be, we all meet practica! problems by a partial approach .!11
Block, and Hurwicz [1959, p. 90] first showed that if GS holds, weak
first, so these are comforting conclusions. Of cotlfSe, it still remains
revealed preference holds as between an equilibrium price vector and i:ll
to see how "good" the DD assumption is in fact. any other. The weak gross substitute extensions are dueto McKenzie '"l1!'
'1
[1960], Uzawa [1961], Morishima [1959, unpublished], and Arrow and '1

Hurwicz [1960].
Notes Much of the discussion of uniqueness in the literature was motivated
by the theory of factor-price equalization in international trade theory.
The study of uniqueness by examining the Jacobian of an appropriate The literature since Samuelson's [1948] paper is large; the results of
mapping was initiated by Samuelson [1953~54]. He thought a sufficient Section 9.12 are discussed more fully in McKenzie [1955a].
condition for uniqueness to be that for one permutation of the rows and Debreu [1970] has recently reexamined the possibilities for multiple

1'

1 11
1
244 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS Chapter Ten
equilibria. He assumes only that excess-demand functions are dif-
ferentiable functions of both prices and the distribution of endowments; COMPARING EQUILIBRIA
the absolute value of the excess-demand vector is assumed to approach
infinity as any price approaches zero, so that only strictly positive equi-
libria are possible. Then it is shown that there is a closed set of measure The ald arder changeth, yielding plac1
zero in the space of endowment allocations such that for all other ta the new.
endowment allocations there are only finitely many equilibria. This
seems to be the best possible result short of the much more restrictive -A. Tennyson, Marte d'Arthw
assumptions of the type used in this chapter.

l. The Problem
In analyzing the effects of a given change in the parameters of ar
economy, say, taste or technology, it is often useful as a first approad
to neglect the questions ofadjustment to this change and to compan:
the equilibrium that results (if all goes well) with the equilibrium we
started with. One of the questions we shall have to answer is just
when this approach is in fact likely to prove useful. The method of
comparing equilibria is often referred to as the method of compara-
ti ve statics or comparative dynamics. The force of the terms
"statics" and "dynamics" is by no means clear. For instance, for
economies with all possible futures markets it is not easy to say
whether we are dealing with statics, because all contracts are made
at a moment of time, or with dynamics, beca use quantities of goods
produced and stored may be changing as the future develops. We
therefore think it best to avoid this terminology.
The main problem we set ourselves in this chapter is an inquiry
into the power of general equilibrium models in giving unambiguous
predictions of how the equilibrium of an economy will be affected
by a given parameter change. As we have already argued in the
previous section, this problem must be intimately related to that of
the uniqueness of an equilibrium and it is pretty clear that we shall
not expect to get very far without stipulating one or the other of the
conditions that ensure such uniqueness. Even so, the kind of
parameter changes for which predictiolis become possible is pretty
limited.

2. Binary Changes
We start our investigation with the simplest case. Suppose there
is a change in the tastes of households so that at a given p O, they

245

!'
1
244 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS Chapter Ten
equilibria. He assumes only that excess-demand functions are dif-
ferentiable functions of both prices and the distribution of endowments; COMPARING EQUILIBRIA
the absolute value of the excess-demand vector is assumed to approach
infinity as any price approaches zero, so that only strictly positive equi-
libria are possible. Then it is shown that there is a closed set of measure The ald arder changeth, yielding plac1
zero in the space of endowment allocations such that for all other ta the new.
endowment allocations there are only finitely many equilibria. This
seems to be the best possible result short of the much more restrictive -A. Tennyson, Marte d'Arthw
assumptions of the type used in this chapter.

l. The Problem
In analyzing the effects of a given change in the parameters of ar
economy, say, taste or technology, it is often useful as a first approad
to neglect the questions ofadjustment to this change and to compan:
the equilibrium that results (if all goes well) with the equilibrium we
started with. One of the questions we shall have to answer is just
when this approach is in fact likely to prove useful. The method of
comparing equilibria is often referred to as the method of compara-
ti ve statics or comparative dynamics. The force of the terms
"statics" and "dynamics" is by no means clear. For instance, for
economies with all possible futures markets it is not easy to say
whether we are dealing with statics, because all contracts are made
at a moment of time, or with dynamics, beca use quantities of goods
produced and stored may be changing as the future develops. We
therefore think it best to avoid this terminology.
The main problem we set ourselves in this chapter is an inquiry
into the power of general equilibrium models in giving unambiguous
predictions of how the equilibrium of an economy will be affected
by a given parameter change. As we have already argued in the
previous section, this problem must be intimately related to that of
the uniqueness of an equilibrium and it is pretty clear that we shall
not expect to get very far without stipulating one or the other of the
conditions that ensure such uniqueness. Even so, the kind of
parameter changes for which predictiolis become possible is pretty
limited.

2. Binary Changes
We start our investigation with the simplest case. Suppose there
is a change in the tastes of households so that at a given p O, they

245

!'
,..

~
!i
'
~~
11
1:
:!
1

246 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 247

demand more of a certain good. Then, by W, the demandfor at If the economy has a unique equilibrium before and after the
'11
least one other good must be affected by the change in taste. The bi11ary cha11ge, T.IO.l tells us that wi* < wi (and w~* > w~).
' 1' simplest of our cases arises when at a given price vector the demand Thus, if the factor of type 1 is "capital," the equilibrium with more
:1 for two goods only is affected by the change. We shall call such a capital, other thi11gs consta11t, must also have a lower renta! of capital.
1'1, change a "binary" change: It is important to understa11d that this prediction depends crucially
1 011 the suppositio11 of u11iqueness.
'"111 DEFINITION l. A change in the parameters of an economy at p will
It is 110t hard to see that the lesso11s of this example can be applied
be called a binary change, if, when z'(p) is the excess-demand vector
to other situatio11s, for i11stance to the two-country, two-good
when the parameters have changed, z(p) - z'(p) has only two nol1-
1

zero compo11e11ts. neoclassical model of i11ternational trade. Thus suppose that the
' 1
cou11try experie11cing a once-over increase in the stock of capital was
It should be noted that this defi11ition stipulates that a change is an exporter of the capital-intensive good. The11, assumi11g the
binary ata give11 price. Thus a change that satisfies the requirement world equilibrium u11ique, since we know that the equilibrium wage-
that it be bi11ary at p need 11ot ha ve the same effects 011 z at sorne other rental ratio must go up a11d since this must mean that the price of the
price vector p'. Por co11venie11ce, we shall take z~(p) > z 1 (p) and capital-inte11sive good must fall relatively to that of the other good,
z~(p) < z 2 (p). (The inequalities must differ, taki11g p 1 > O, p 2 > O we have at once the result that the terms of trade of our country
for the two goods because of W.) must deteriora te. These are all simple co11sequences of T.l 0.1, a11d
The simplest case for this simplest of all parameter changes is the it must be confessed that they will not generalize to an eco11omy with
two-good eco11omy. Here every parameter change is ipso jacto more goods, except if the contemplated cha11ge is bi11ary. We shall
bi11ary. We also get a very simple result. return to this questio11 presently. First, we shall examine what can
be said about binary cha11ges in a world of ma11y goods.
THEOREM l. Let p* be the unique equilibrium before a11d p** the
unique equilibrium after the change in parameter. Thenpt* >PI THEOREM 2. Let the parameter change be bi11ary at p*, an equi-
librium. Then if (a) the economy is Hicksian for all p and has
Proof In T.9.17 we showed that for a two-good eco11omy the p* O or (b) all goods are GS at all p, there is a new equilibrium
condition p*s(p) < O for p i= p* was necessary and sufficient for price vector p** with pr* > PI and p~* < pr ;.1'

uniqueness. So in the present application,


Proof If the economy is Hicksian, then by assumption, and if
p**s'(p*) < O GS, by Corollary 9.6, p* O. Therefore, we may choose units for
and, by W, the goods such that p* = e, the unit vector. By the proof of T.9.4,
T.9.9, and W, we have for either type of economy for p i= p**
(p** - p*)s'(p*) < O.
(p - p**)s'(p) > O
By assumption s~(p*) < s 1 (p*), a11d p** and p* E S2 If the theorem
and so, in particular,
is false, it must be that pi* < PI (since pi* = PI would mean
p~* = p~, which is impossible). But then PI > O, so that s 1 (p*) = O, (e - p**)s'(e) > O. (1)
a11d also p~* > p~. Hence, s~(p*) < O :::; s 2 (p*) contrary to By the defi11ition of a binary change, s~(e) + s;(e) = O, s~(e) < O and
assumptio11. Hence pi* > pf. s;(e) =O, all i i= 1,2 (since p* 0). Hence from (1),
As an application, consider the "two-sector" model of 9.12. pi* - 1 > p~* - l. (2)
Suppose there is an exogenous increase in Ll> the amount of the
factor of type 1 available. lt is trivial to show that, in the notation Then there is sorne k > O, such that with p** = kp**,
of 9.12, this implies fii* - 1 > O and p~* - 1 < O. (3)
By H, p** is an equilibrium.
,..

~
!i
'
~~
11
1:
:!
1

246 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 247

demand more of a certain good. Then, by W, the demandfor at If the economy has a unique equilibrium before and after the
'11
least one other good must be affected by the change in taste. The bi11ary cha11ge, T.IO.l tells us that wi* < wi (and w~* > w~).
' 1' simplest of our cases arises when at a given price vector the demand Thus, if the factor of type 1 is "capital," the equilibrium with more
:1 for two goods only is affected by the change. We shall call such a capital, other thi11gs consta11t, must also have a lower renta! of capital.
1'1, change a "binary" change: It is important to understa11d that this prediction depends crucially
1 011 the suppositio11 of u11iqueness.
'"111 DEFINITION l. A change in the parameters of an economy at p will
It is 110t hard to see that the lesso11s of this example can be applied
be called a binary change, if, when z'(p) is the excess-demand vector
to other situatio11s, for i11stance to the two-country, two-good
when the parameters have changed, z(p) - z'(p) has only two nol1-
1

zero compo11e11ts. neoclassical model of i11ternational trade. Thus suppose that the
' 1
cou11try experie11cing a once-over increase in the stock of capital was
It should be noted that this defi11ition stipulates that a change is an exporter of the capital-intensive good. The11, assumi11g the
binary ata give11 price. Thus a change that satisfies the requirement world equilibrium u11ique, since we know that the equilibrium wage-
that it be bi11ary at p need 11ot ha ve the same effects 011 z at sorne other rental ratio must go up a11d since this must mean that the price of the
price vector p'. Por co11venie11ce, we shall take z~(p) > z 1 (p) and capital-inte11sive good must fall relatively to that of the other good,
z~(p) < z 2 (p). (The inequalities must differ, taki11g p 1 > O, p 2 > O we have at once the result that the terms of trade of our country
for the two goods because of W.) must deteriora te. These are all simple co11sequences of T.l 0.1, a11d
The simplest case for this simplest of all parameter changes is the it must be confessed that they will not generalize to an eco11omy with
two-good eco11omy. Here every parameter change is ipso jacto more goods, except if the contemplated cha11ge is bi11ary. We shall
bi11ary. We also get a very simple result. return to this questio11 presently. First, we shall examine what can
be said about binary cha11ges in a world of ma11y goods.
THEOREM l. Let p* be the unique equilibrium before a11d p** the
unique equilibrium after the change in parameter. Thenpt* >PI THEOREM 2. Let the parameter change be bi11ary at p*, an equi-
librium. Then if (a) the economy is Hicksian for all p and has
Proof In T.9.17 we showed that for a two-good eco11omy the p* O or (b) all goods are GS at all p, there is a new equilibrium
condition p*s(p) < O for p i= p* was necessary and sufficient for price vector p** with pr* > PI and p~* < pr ;.1'

uniqueness. So in the present application,


Proof If the economy is Hicksian, then by assumption, and if
p**s'(p*) < O GS, by Corollary 9.6, p* O. Therefore, we may choose units for
and, by W, the goods such that p* = e, the unit vector. By the proof of T.9.4,
T.9.9, and W, we have for either type of economy for p i= p**
(p** - p*)s'(p*) < O.
(p - p**)s'(p) > O
By assumption s~(p*) < s 1 (p*), a11d p** and p* E S2 If the theorem
and so, in particular,
is false, it must be that pi* < PI (since pi* = PI would mean
p~* = p~, which is impossible). But then PI > O, so that s 1 (p*) = O, (e - p**)s'(e) > O. (1)
a11d also p~* > p~. Hence, s~(p*) < O :::; s 2 (p*) contrary to By the defi11ition of a binary change, s~(e) + s;(e) = O, s~(e) < O and
assumptio11. Hence pi* > pf. s;(e) =O, all i i= 1,2 (since p* 0). Hence from (1),
As an application, consider the "two-sector" model of 9.12. pi* - 1 > p~* - l. (2)
Suppose there is an exogenous increase in Ll> the amount of the
factor of type 1 available. lt is trivial to show that, in the notation Then there is sorne k > O, such that with p** = kp**,
of 9.12, this implies fii* - 1 > O and p~* - 1 < O. (3)
By H, p** is an equilibrium.
248 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 249
For the GS case we can establish a slightly stronger result by of an economy of a switch in government expenditure at p* from one
different methods. good to another or of a technical innovation in one sector of the
economy that has the consequence of reducing, at p*, the demand
THEOREM 3. Let the parameter change be binary at p*, an equi-
for one particular input and increasing the demand for another.
librium. Then, if al! goods are GS for all p and the nth good has
But no doubt all these examples are rather artificial. Befare we
been chosen as numeraire (Pn = 1 always), it must be thatp{* > p{,
~ttempt to be more adventurous, however, it will be useful to see
p~* < p~.
whether the hypotheses of WGS or DD allow us to make straight-
Proof By Corollary 9.6, we have p* O. Again Jet the units forward predictions for binary changes.
in which goods are measured be such asto give p* = e. Let p~* ;::: We know from our discussion of the case in Chapter 9 that if one
i
pf*, al! i. Then we claim that k = J. Suppose k =1- l. Then by postulates WGS and connectedness, all the theorems established for !
T.9.8, we ha ve s;c(p*) < s;,(p**). But s;c(p*) = Ofor k =1- 1,2 by the GS continue to hold. Thus it is clear that T.! 0.2 and T.! 0.3 with
binary change assumption and s;(p*) > O, by the same assumption. its corollaries continue to be valid for this economy. Accordingly, ;j:
Hence s;c(p**) > O and p** is not an equilibrium contrary to its we concentrate on the case in which connectedness is not stipulated. ,
definition. We conclude that indeed k = l. In the same way we
show that if p~* :S:: pt*; theti it must be that h = 2. Hence the THEOREM.4. Let all goods be WGS and let there be a binary change 1!1!
!:,,

such that for all p* E E, s~(p*) > s 2(p*), s~(p*) < O. Then there is
1

theorem is proved.
a new set of equilibrium price vectors E' such that if p** E E', then
Corollary 3. Let the economy have GS for all p. Then a binary for every p* E E, p** can be scaled so that p{* > p{, p~* :S:: p~.
change at p*, an equilibrium, will raise the equilibrium price of the
good whose excess demand has increased at p* in greater proportion Proof. We note first that if PT > O, for either i = 1 or i = 2,
than any other equilibrium price is raised and lower the equilibrium then PT > O, for both i = 1 and i = 2. This follows from W anc\
,,
,,
i1i price of the good whose excess demand was decreased ,at p* in the postulate that the change is binary. Suppose PT = o for
11
greater proportion than any other equilibrium price. i = 1,2. By T.9.11 and the assumptions that imply that p* is not in
:
,,',' E', p**s'(p*) < O. For each i #- 1,2, either s(p*) = O or s,(p*) > O
Jii'
Corollary 3'. Let the economy have GS at all p. Then a binary and, therefore, PT = O; in the Iatter case, s;(p*) > O, by the assump-
lil change at p* raises the pr{ces of all goods in terms of the good whose tion of a binary change, and by T.9.10, for all p** E E', pT* =O, so
1'1
; excess demand was reduced by the binary change at p*. that in any case p{*s;(p*) = O for i =1- 1,2. Then we have pf*s~(p*)
,,
1
Proof Choose the second good as numeraire; that is, set p 2 =
+ p~*s;(p*) < O and so certainly pf* > p{ = O. Since s~(p*) > O
ii by assumption when p~ = O, T.9.10 ensures that s~(p**) > O,
everywhere. Then if, say, p~* < p~ and p~*jp~ :S:: pf*fpt, all i, the
1

familiar argument would lead to s 1/p**) < O; if k =1- 2, then by the


whence pr = O. 1
If pf > O for i = 1,2 then we proceed as in T.l0.2.
binary change assumption s;,(p**) = s~c(P**) < O and we would
thus contradict p** as being an equilibrium. This is as it should be We must now note that this result is not only slightly weaker than
in view of GS: p~* = p~, and al! other prices rise relatively to that the corresponding one for GS, but its assumptions are also stronger
of the second good, so that the excess supp1y for the second good since we postulate the change in parameters to be of a certain type
is reduced as needed, since by hypothesis s~(p*) > O. not only at a given p, but over a whole set of p's. If this had not
The application of these results to actul situations is some.what been postulated, then it might be that E and E' ha ve price vectors in
Iimited simply because the supposition that the parameter change is common, and so we could not have utilized the Weak Axiom in the
binary is very limiting. Later we shall be able to illustrate a version way we in fact di d. In the case of GS we found (T.l 0.3) that we
of T.l0.3 for more interesting situations. Here we may find an could do without the Weak Axiom. Here this avenue is not
application in the analysis of the consequences for the equilibrium available, for we cannot now argue that if, say, p~* ;::: p'[*, all i,

i 1

1:
248 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 249
For the GS case we can establish a slightly stronger result by of an economy of a switch in government expenditure at p* from one
different methods. good to another or of a technical innovation in one sector of the
economy that has the consequence of reducing, at p*, the demand
THEOREM 3. Let the parameter change be binary at p*, an equi-
for one particular input and increasing the demand for another.
librium. Then, if al! goods are GS for all p and the nth good has
But no doubt all these examples are rather artificial. Befare we
been chosen as numeraire (Pn = 1 always), it must be thatp{* > p{,
~ttempt to be more adventurous, however, it will be useful to see
p~* < p~.
whether the hypotheses of WGS or DD allow us to make straight-
Proof By Corollary 9.6, we have p* O. Again Jet the units forward predictions for binary changes.
in which goods are measured be such asto give p* = e. Let p~* ;::: We know from our discussion of the case in Chapter 9 that if one
i
pf*, al! i. Then we claim that k = J. Suppose k =1- l. Then by postulates WGS and connectedness, all the theorems established for !
T.9.8, we ha ve s;c(p*) < s;,(p**). But s;c(p*) = Ofor k =1- 1,2 by the GS continue to hold. Thus it is clear that T.! 0.2 and T.! 0.3 with
binary change assumption and s;(p*) > O, by the same assumption. its corollaries continue to be valid for this economy. Accordingly, ;j:
Hence s;c(p**) > O and p** is not an equilibrium contrary to its we concentrate on the case in which connectedness is not stipulated. ,
definition. We conclude that indeed k = l. In the same way we
show that if p~* :S:: pt*; theti it must be that h = 2. Hence the THEOREM.4. Let all goods be WGS and let there be a binary change 1!1!
!:,,

such that for all p* E E, s~(p*) > s 2(p*), s~(p*) < O. Then there is
1

theorem is proved.
a new set of equilibrium price vectors E' such that if p** E E', then
Corollary 3. Let the economy have GS for all p. Then a binary for every p* E E, p** can be scaled so that p{* > p{, p~* :S:: p~.
change at p*, an equilibrium, will raise the equilibrium price of the
good whose excess demand has increased at p* in greater proportion Proof. We note first that if PT > O, for either i = 1 or i = 2,
than any other equilibrium price is raised and lower the equilibrium then PT > O, for both i = 1 and i = 2. This follows from W anc\
,,
,,
i1i price of the good whose excess demand was decreased ,at p* in the postulate that the change is binary. Suppose PT = o for
11
greater proportion than any other equilibrium price. i = 1,2. By T.9.11 and the assumptions that imply that p* is not in
:
,,',' E', p**s'(p*) < O. For each i #- 1,2, either s(p*) = O or s,(p*) > O
Jii'
Corollary 3'. Let the economy have GS at all p. Then a binary and, therefore, PT = O; in the Iatter case, s;(p*) > O, by the assump-
lil change at p* raises the pr{ces of all goods in terms of the good whose tion of a binary change, and by T.9.10, for all p** E E', pT* =O, so
1'1
; excess demand was reduced by the binary change at p*. that in any case p{*s;(p*) = O for i =1- 1,2. Then we have pf*s~(p*)
,,
1
Proof Choose the second good as numeraire; that is, set p 2 =
+ p~*s;(p*) < O and so certainly pf* > p{ = O. Since s~(p*) > O
ii by assumption when p~ = O, T.9.10 ensures that s~(p**) > O,
everywhere. Then if, say, p~* < p~ and p~*jp~ :S:: pf*fpt, all i, the
1

familiar argument would lead to s 1/p**) < O; if k =1- 2, then by the


whence pr = O. 1
If pf > O for i = 1,2 then we proceed as in T.l0.2.
binary change assumption s;,(p**) = s~c(P**) < O and we would
thus contradict p** as being an equilibrium. This is as it should be We must now note that this result is not only slightly weaker than
in view of GS: p~* = p~, and al! other prices rise relatively to that the corresponding one for GS, but its assumptions are also stronger
of the second good, so that the excess supp1y for the second good since we postulate the change in parameters to be of a certain type
is reduced as needed, since by hypothesis s~(p*) > O. not only at a given p, but over a whole set of p's. If this had not
The application of these results to actul situations is some.what been postulated, then it might be that E and E' ha ve price vectors in
Iimited simply because the supposition that the parameter change is common, and so we could not have utilized the Weak Axiom in the
binary is very limiting. Later we shall be able to illustrate a version way we in fact di d. In the case of GS we found (T.l 0.3) that we
of T.l0.3 for more interesting situations. Here we may find an could do without the Weak Axiom. Here this avenue is not
application in the analysis of the consequences for the equilibrium available, for we cannot now argue that if, say, p~* ;::: p'[*, all i,

i 1

1:
ll
' 1

T 11

1
1

!
250 GENERAL CO!vJPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 251
11!
s~(p**) > O for k 1, since it may be that the kth good belongs to
=1= and "'!',.
,,
the class of goods that is independent of prices, and so we could have ds[P(a),a] < O implies dP(a) > O
da . da - ' (5)
s~(p) = O, all p. Moreover, should p[ = O for i = 1,2, then if the
change is defined in the usual way to be binary at p* (not over the Thus, in the case of (4) we know that in the new equilibrium P1 = O.
whole of E), evidently it is quite possible for p** E E and p[* = O So either the ith price was zero already in the previous equilibrium,
for i = 1,2. Thus it would appear that the assumptions of T.10.4 or it must now become so. The inequalities of (5) have similar
are as weak as or weaker than any alternative ones we could impose explanation.
in order to obtain clearcut results. Now write J = (8s 1[]>(a),a]j8P1), i,j i- 2 and s for the excess
Unfortunatdy, the assumption that there is Diagonal Dominance, supply vector excluding the second good. Then
which, we argued in the last chapter, is the most attractive of the
restrictions on the forms of the excess.supply functions, is not very
ds[P(a),a] = JdP(a) + 8s ( )
da da 8a 6
powerful in allowing us to make definite statements when equilibria
are being compared. Let us see what can be done. Let T be the diagonal matrix with elements + 1 or - 1 such that
Consider a binary change at p* such that s~ (p*) - s1 (p*) = -a
and s;(p*) - s2 (p*) = b where p'{b - p~a = O. Then, since we
Q= Td~~a) ~ O. (7)
shall suppose there to be DD, it follows that there will be a new
If dP1(a)jda = O, let t11 have the opposite sign of dst/da. Thus, by
unique equilibrium, which we may write as p(a). Now let {av} be a
(4) and (5),
sequence with = a, which approaches O, and let pv = p(av). By
ds[P(a )a]
an argument exactly similar to that used in proving Lemma 9.3, we T 0' (8)
da S:
can show that
so that if H = TJT we have from (6), recalling TT = 1,
lim pv = p(lim av) = p(O) = p*,
v~oo V-400
HQ = Tds[P(a),a] _ Tos < -Tos,
so that p(a) is continuous ata = O. In fact we shall assume p(a) to da 8a - 8a
be differentiable at a = O. With this preliminary out of the way, but 8sJ8a = O for i ~ 3 and 8s1 /8a < O by assumption. Hence
we may now prove the following proposition. 111 = -1 implies HQ < O, which contradicts GP. Thus t 11 = + 1
~
and the theorem is proved.
1
THEOREM 5. Let s(p,a) be a oneparameter family of excess-supply
functions undergoing binary shifts so that 8s 1 /8a < O, all p, and This result is somewhat weaker than the corresponding one for
8sJ8a = O, all p and i ~ 3. Suppose that s2 (p,a) < O for all a and GS. There we wer~ able to prove that whichever good may be
p with p 2 = O and that for all p the economy has GP. Then, as a chosen as numeraire, the equilibrium price in terms of numeraire of
increases, ether good 1 is free or, if p(a) is the equilibrium for a, the good experiencing an increase in excess demand at P* by the
p 1 (a)/pia) increases. binary change must rise, while the price of the second good must fall.
This cannot be shown for the DD case. Nor should this be sur
Proof By assumption, p 2 (a) > O so that we may choose the prising since DD allows for extremely complex relationships between
second good as numeraire and write P as the vector of prices in goods. Thus, for instance, the excess demand for the first good
terms of a numeraire. caused by the binary change may be eliminated by a fall in its price
When a is varied, P(a) is varied so asto ensure a new equilibrium. in terms of numeraire, provided sorne other good j that is a gross
Hence we have complement for good 1 (s~ 1 > O) rises sufficiently in price.
ds 1[P(a),a] O . dP(a) O A simple example in which T.10.5 might be applicable would be
da > 1mp leS -----;;-- S: (4) to trace the consequence on equilibrium wages in terms of food in a
ll
' 1

T 11

1
1

!
250 GENERAL CO!vJPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 251
11!
s~(p**) > O for k 1, since it may be that the kth good belongs to
=1= and "'!',.
,,
the class of goods that is independent of prices, and so we could have ds[P(a),a] < O implies dP(a) > O
da . da - ' (5)
s~(p) = O, all p. Moreover, should p[ = O for i = 1,2, then if the
change is defined in the usual way to be binary at p* (not over the Thus, in the case of (4) we know that in the new equilibrium P1 = O.
whole of E), evidently it is quite possible for p** E E and p[* = O So either the ith price was zero already in the previous equilibrium,
for i = 1,2. Thus it would appear that the assumptions of T.10.4 or it must now become so. The inequalities of (5) have similar
are as weak as or weaker than any alternative ones we could impose explanation.
in order to obtain clearcut results. Now write J = (8s 1[]>(a),a]j8P1), i,j i- 2 and s for the excess
Unfortunatdy, the assumption that there is Diagonal Dominance, supply vector excluding the second good. Then
which, we argued in the last chapter, is the most attractive of the
restrictions on the forms of the excess.supply functions, is not very
ds[P(a),a] = JdP(a) + 8s ( )
da da 8a 6
powerful in allowing us to make definite statements when equilibria
are being compared. Let us see what can be done. Let T be the diagonal matrix with elements + 1 or - 1 such that
Consider a binary change at p* such that s~ (p*) - s1 (p*) = -a
and s;(p*) - s2 (p*) = b where p'{b - p~a = O. Then, since we
Q= Td~~a) ~ O. (7)
shall suppose there to be DD, it follows that there will be a new
If dP1(a)jda = O, let t11 have the opposite sign of dst/da. Thus, by
unique equilibrium, which we may write as p(a). Now let {av} be a
(4) and (5),
sequence with = a, which approaches O, and let pv = p(av). By
ds[P(a )a]
an argument exactly similar to that used in proving Lemma 9.3, we T 0' (8)
da S:
can show that
so that if H = TJT we have from (6), recalling TT = 1,
lim pv = p(lim av) = p(O) = p*,
v~oo V-400
HQ = Tds[P(a),a] _ Tos < -Tos,
so that p(a) is continuous ata = O. In fact we shall assume p(a) to da 8a - 8a
be differentiable at a = O. With this preliminary out of the way, but 8sJ8a = O for i ~ 3 and 8s1 /8a < O by assumption. Hence
we may now prove the following proposition. 111 = -1 implies HQ < O, which contradicts GP. Thus t 11 = + 1
~
and the theorem is proved.
1
THEOREM 5. Let s(p,a) be a oneparameter family of excess-supply
functions undergoing binary shifts so that 8s 1 /8a < O, all p, and This result is somewhat weaker than the corresponding one for
8sJ8a = O, all p and i ~ 3. Suppose that s2 (p,a) < O for all a and GS. There we wer~ able to prove that whichever good may be
p with p 2 = O and that for all p the economy has GP. Then, as a chosen as numeraire, the equilibrium price in terms of numeraire of
increases, ether good 1 is free or, if p(a) is the equilibrium for a, the good experiencing an increase in excess demand at P* by the
p 1 (a)/pia) increases. binary change must rise, while the price of the second good must fall.
This cannot be shown for the DD case. Nor should this be sur
Proof By assumption, p 2 (a) > O so that we may choose the prising since DD allows for extremely complex relationships between
second good as numeraire and write P as the vector of prices in goods. Thus, for instance, the excess demand for the first good
terms of a numeraire. caused by the binary change may be eliminated by a fall in its price
When a is varied, P(a) is varied so asto ensure a new equilibrium. in terms of numeraire, provided sorne other good j that is a gross
Hence we have complement for good 1 (s~ 1 > O) rises sufficiently in price.
ds 1[P(a),a] O . dP(a) O A simple example in which T.10.5 might be applicable would be
da > 1mp leS -----;;-- S: (4) to trace the consequence on equilibrium wages in terms of food in a
,
i!

11

252 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 253 1!1

,,r

country that, in an equilibrium situation, experiences an immigration W e first prove 1'


of labor that directs all its potential demand to food. If the con- LEMMA 1. lf all goods are GS, then J has a positive root A.* and an
!
ditions of the theorem are satisfied, then a fall in the food wage can associated positive eigenvector x* O.
be predicted. The rather artificial nature of this example, quite
apart from the necessary assumptions, is an indication of how Proof Let a > max s 11 (P*), Jet 1 be the unit matrix, and define
Iimited the results have been so far. It is time to see whether we can A by A = al - J(P*). Then, by GS, A is a positive matrix, (i.e., all
do any better. elements of A are positive). We know (T.A.l) that a positive matrix
has a largest root a, which is positive, and an associated eigenvector
y O. Also (T.A.5), if a 1 is the ith row vector in A,
3. More General Parameter Changes
a :::; max a 1e,
It is not hard to see that for the GS case, certainly, we may relax j

the requirement that the parameter change be binary and still get where e is the unit vector. Since P* O, we may choose units of
sorne definite conclusion as to the constellation of the new equi- goods so that P 7 = 1, all i. Then
Iibrium prices. Thus we easily establish the following:
a 1e = a - . s (P*) = a + s n(P*)
1 1
THEOREM 6. Let all goods be GS at aJI P. Let there be a parameter Nn

change at P*, an equilibrium with the nth good as numeraire, such and so, by GS, a < a. Clearly A.* = a - a is a root of J and has the
that s~(P*) > O and s;(P*) ::::; O, all i ,. n. Then sorne prices in associated eigenvector x* = y.
terms of numeraire will be higher and none wiii be Iower in the new
equilibrium. We now prove

Proof Apply the method of proof used in Coroiiary 3'. THEOREM 7. Let all goods be GS and Jet there be a parameter
change at P*. Then there exists a way of constructing a composite
Small as this extension is, it does allow us to give a more sensible
commodity and an associated price vector, such that the parameter
formulation to the immigration example of the previous section for
change causes this price to move in the opposite direction to the
an economy with GS. If we chose labor as our numeraire, we can
excess supply of the composite commodity.
surely predict a fall in the equilibrium real wage, however that may
be defined. The immigrants offer themselves on the labor market at Proof From (9), if x* is the strictly positive eigenvector,
the prevailing equilibrium prices and cause an excess supply there.
At the same time, they are potential demanders of goods and so the x*JdP(a) = -x* ~s.
drx Oa
excess demand at the prevailing prices will rise for sorne goods and
fall for none. There seems no good reason to suppose that the But x*J = A.*x*. Let P*(a) = x*P(a), * = x*s. Then,
immigration as such will cause a change in the existing plans of
dP*'(a) os*
residents. The example is, as we said, more sensible, but of course, A.*--=--,
da da
the restriction GS is correspondingly more severe than was DO.
For "small" para meter changes a somewhat more general result which, in view of A.* > O, proves the theorem.
(than the binary ones) can be established for GS. We use the same Not much can be claimed for the usefulness of T.l0.7, for it may
notation as in T.!0.5, but choose the nth good as numeraire. By GS, reasonably be argued that if we know enough to calculate the eigen-
P(a) O, all a, and s[P(a),a] = O, all a. Hence equation (6) of vectors then we certainly know enough about J to solve (9) directly.
Section 10.2 beco mes It is worth noting, however, that should the excess-supply functions
be linear over a certain range, then having done our calculations once
(9) puts us in the position of making the prediction of the theorem.
,
i!

11

252 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 253 1!1

,,r

country that, in an equilibrium situation, experiences an immigration W e first prove 1'


of labor that directs all its potential demand to food. If the con- LEMMA 1. lf all goods are GS, then J has a positive root A.* and an
!
ditions of the theorem are satisfied, then a fall in the food wage can associated positive eigenvector x* O.
be predicted. The rather artificial nature of this example, quite
apart from the necessary assumptions, is an indication of how Proof Let a > max s 11 (P*), Jet 1 be the unit matrix, and define
Iimited the results have been so far. It is time to see whether we can A by A = al - J(P*). Then, by GS, A is a positive matrix, (i.e., all
do any better. elements of A are positive). We know (T.A.l) that a positive matrix
has a largest root a, which is positive, and an associated eigenvector
y O. Also (T.A.5), if a 1 is the ith row vector in A,
3. More General Parameter Changes
a :::; max a 1e,
It is not hard to see that for the GS case, certainly, we may relax j

the requirement that the parameter change be binary and still get where e is the unit vector. Since P* O, we may choose units of
sorne definite conclusion as to the constellation of the new equi- goods so that P 7 = 1, all i. Then
Iibrium prices. Thus we easily establish the following:
a 1e = a - . s (P*) = a + s n(P*)
1 1
THEOREM 6. Let all goods be GS at aJI P. Let there be a parameter Nn

change at P*, an equilibrium with the nth good as numeraire, such and so, by GS, a < a. Clearly A.* = a - a is a root of J and has the
that s~(P*) > O and s;(P*) ::::; O, all i ,. n. Then sorne prices in associated eigenvector x* = y.
terms of numeraire will be higher and none wiii be Iower in the new
equilibrium. We now prove

Proof Apply the method of proof used in Coroiiary 3'. THEOREM 7. Let all goods be GS and Jet there be a parameter
change at P*. Then there exists a way of constructing a composite
Small as this extension is, it does allow us to give a more sensible
commodity and an associated price vector, such that the parameter
formulation to the immigration example of the previous section for
change causes this price to move in the opposite direction to the
an economy with GS. If we chose labor as our numeraire, we can
excess supply of the composite commodity.
surely predict a fall in the equilibrium real wage, however that may
be defined. The immigrants offer themselves on the labor market at Proof From (9), if x* is the strictly positive eigenvector,
the prevailing equilibrium prices and cause an excess supply there.
At the same time, they are potential demanders of goods and so the x*JdP(a) = -x* ~s.
drx Oa
excess demand at the prevailing prices will rise for sorne goods and
fall for none. There seems no good reason to suppose that the But x*J = A.*x*. Let P*(a) = x*P(a), * = x*s. Then,
immigration as such will cause a change in the existing plans of
dP*'(a) os*
residents. The example is, as we said, more sensible, but of course, A.*--=--,
da da
the restriction GS is correspondingly more severe than was DO.
For "small" para meter changes a somewhat more general result which, in view of A.* > O, proves the theorem.
(than the binary ones) can be established for GS. We use the same Not much can be claimed for the usefulness of T.l0.7, for it may
notation as in T.!0.5, but choose the nth good as numeraire. By GS, reasonably be argued that if we know enough to calculate the eigen-
P(a) O, all a, and s[P(a),a] = O, all a. Hence equation (6) of vectors then we certainly know enough about J to solve (9) directly.
Section 10.2 beco mes It is worth noting, however, that should the excess-supply functions
be linear over a certain range, then having done our calculations once
(9) puts us in the position of making the prediction of the theorem.
T
254 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 255

Without further restricting the model that we use in comparing Since R is homogeneous of degree one in p, we may normalize on
equilibria it does not seem possible to obtain any further results for labor. Let P* = p*fpN, P** = p**/pt*. Suppose that, contrary to
general parameter changes. This is neither surprising nor a cause assertion, there is a set of goods H such that
for despondency. The analysis of binary changes does in a general
P** P**
1
equilibrium context what Marshallian partial analysis achieves in a 1 < k = _n_ > - for h EH, i < N.
much more restricted setting; for general changes we must expect to - r;: - P!-
have fairly precise quantitative information as to the relationship Certainly kPt ;::: Pt*, and since all sectors use labor,
between goods before being able to make the kind of statement that C~(kP*) ::::: C[,(P**) hE H,
was possible for binary changes.
and so
'(P*) _ R~(kP*) R~(P**) hE H.
4. The Constant Returns Economy O -5, Rn - k -::; k

In this section we will study the L-economy of Section 2.11. If the right-hand inequality is not strict for any h EH, then the
Recall (T.3.6) that if C;(p) is the mnimum unit cost function of sectors in H use no goods produced by the sectors not in H, in
sector i, then contradiction to the assumption that the economy is production
connected unless H consists of all goods. In that case k cannot
exceed 1, since labor, which has not risen in price, enters the produc-
tion of all goods, and k cannot equal 1, for then P* = P** cannot
where - y;lp) is the cost minimizing input of "j" per unit of good i. be an equilibrium after the change. Hence, R~(P**) > O, sorne
We give labor the subscript N. h EH, and again P** cannot be an equilibrium. Hence, k < l.
It can be left to the reader to verify that in the absence of the
DEFINITION 2. The economy will be called production connected at connectedness assumption we prove P* > P** with a strict inequality
p if there is no set of goods H such that C;lP) = O for all i EH, j rf= H, in those components that represent the sectors in which the produc-
.i <N. tivity improvement has taken place. The advantage of the stronger
This notion of connectedness is, of course, similar to D.9.7, only assumption is that it allows us to make assertions such as: Technical
here it is related to the mnimum unit cost functions, that is, to the progress will raise the equilibrium "real" wage of labor, however
use of inputs in production. We may now prve "real" wage is defined. The result is not surprising, of course, but
it is worth having.
THEOREM 8. Let the economy be production connected at all p and Corollary 8. In the economy of T.10.8, let the parameter change
satisfy A.2.10-A.2.14. Let a parameter change lower unit produc- be such that the cost of production at the initial equilibrium prices,
tion costs for sorne sectors and raise it for none. Then the equi- P*, is lowered only for good s. Then it must be that
librium price of every good in terms of labor must fall.
P** P**
_s_ < - 1 - all i.
Note that, by T.2.6, the equilibrium price of labor is always P't - P!
positive, so it may be chosen as numeraire both before and after the
change. Proof Suppose that the asserted inequality does not hold for "s,"
but for "t." Then, by the same arguments as in the proof of the
Proof Let R(p) = p - C;(p) and R(p) the vector with com- theorem, w.e have
ponents R1(p). A prime denotes the value of a variable or vector
after the parameter change. By assumption, O= R;(P*) = R;(lt*) > R;(~**) =O; k=~:** < 1,
R(p*) =O R'(p*) > O. which is impossible.
T
254 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 255

Without further restricting the model that we use in comparing Since R is homogeneous of degree one in p, we may normalize on
equilibria it does not seem possible to obtain any further results for labor. Let P* = p*fpN, P** = p**/pt*. Suppose that, contrary to
general parameter changes. This is neither surprising nor a cause assertion, there is a set of goods H such that
for despondency. The analysis of binary changes does in a general
P** P**
1
equilibrium context what Marshallian partial analysis achieves in a 1 < k = _n_ > - for h EH, i < N.
much more restricted setting; for general changes we must expect to - r;: - P!-
have fairly precise quantitative information as to the relationship Certainly kPt ;::: Pt*, and since all sectors use labor,
between goods before being able to make the kind of statement that C~(kP*) ::::: C[,(P**) hE H,
was possible for binary changes.
and so
'(P*) _ R~(kP*) R~(P**) hE H.
4. The Constant Returns Economy O -5, Rn - k -::; k

In this section we will study the L-economy of Section 2.11. If the right-hand inequality is not strict for any h EH, then the
Recall (T.3.6) that if C;(p) is the mnimum unit cost function of sectors in H use no goods produced by the sectors not in H, in
sector i, then contradiction to the assumption that the economy is production
connected unless H consists of all goods. In that case k cannot
exceed 1, since labor, which has not risen in price, enters the produc-
tion of all goods, and k cannot equal 1, for then P* = P** cannot
where - y;lp) is the cost minimizing input of "j" per unit of good i. be an equilibrium after the change. Hence, R~(P**) > O, sorne
We give labor the subscript N. h EH, and again P** cannot be an equilibrium. Hence, k < l.
It can be left to the reader to verify that in the absence of the
DEFINITION 2. The economy will be called production connected at connectedness assumption we prove P* > P** with a strict inequality
p if there is no set of goods H such that C;lP) = O for all i EH, j rf= H, in those components that represent the sectors in which the produc-
.i <N. tivity improvement has taken place. The advantage of the stronger
This notion of connectedness is, of course, similar to D.9.7, only assumption is that it allows us to make assertions such as: Technical
here it is related to the mnimum unit cost functions, that is, to the progress will raise the equilibrium "real" wage of labor, however
use of inputs in production. We may now prve "real" wage is defined. The result is not surprising, of course, but
it is worth having.
THEOREM 8. Let the economy be production connected at all p and Corollary 8. In the economy of T.10.8, let the parameter change
satisfy A.2.10-A.2.14. Let a parameter change lower unit produc- be such that the cost of production at the initial equilibrium prices,
tion costs for sorne sectors and raise it for none. Then the equi- P*, is lowered only for good s. Then it must be that
librium price of every good in terms of labor must fall.
P** P**
_s_ < - 1 - all i.
Note that, by T.2.6, the equilibrium price of labor is always P't - P!
positive, so it may be chosen as numeraire both before and after the
change. Proof Suppose that the asserted inequality does not hold for "s,"
but for "t." Then, by the same arguments as in the proof of the
Proof Let R(p) = p - C;(p) and R(p) the vector with com- theorem, w.e have
ponents R1(p). A prime denotes the value of a variable or vector
after the parameter change. By assumption, O= R;(P*) = R;(lt*) > R;(~**) =O; k=~:** < 1,
R(p*) =O R'(p*) > O. which is impossible.
''

256 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 257


From this we conclude that although a technical improvement in Combining this last expression with (10), we have
one sector only must raise the equilibrium product wage everywhere,
it must raise it by the greatest proportion in the sector in which the -x*' Ydw* = L'dw* = x*'dp*
improvement has taken place. so
Let us now consider an economy in which there are a number of
different non-produced inputs that enter into production. As in L' dw* x*' dp*
9.12, we assume that there are as many non-produced inputs as there L'w* = L'w*
are goods. We first consider a fully integrated economy with no and we note that the left-hand side of this expression measures the
intermediate goods. As usual, we write w as the vector of input proportionate change in factor receipts. Let
prices and consider the equilibrium
dpt
h = max-
p* = C*(w*), j PT
where C*(w) is the vector of minimum unit-cost functions. We shall Then, by the assumption of the theorem, dptfpf < h, sorne j at
take p* O and w* O and consider what would be the con- xj > O, whence
sequence for the equilibrium prices of inputs of an autonomous
change in the prices of outputs. We shall discuss the economic x*' dp* hx*'p*
context of this question presently. First, we prove
-L w*' =h,
w*' < - L
where the last equality follows from constant returns to scale, which
THEOREM 9. Let p* O and w* O with p* = C*(w*) in a con-
ensures x*'p* = L'w*. Then, if h- = dp~fp~, say,
stant returns economy using n inputs to producen outputs in positive
amounts. Let p = p* + dp* where p - p* i= kp* for any scalar L'dw* dp~
k> O. Then L'w* < p~
(a) there is at least one good in terms of which total factor so that in terms of the rth good, total factor incomes fall.
income falls; (b) By the twmogeneity of the cost functions and the assumption
(b) there is at least one factor whose income does not fall in dp* i= kp*, there must be an s such that
terms of any good.
dw* >dw*
-!
_s a-11 i
Proof (a) If (C1(w*)) is the Jacobian at w* of C*(w*), Jet -Y= w~' - wt
(C1(w*)). Note (T.3.6) that - Y11 is the amount of factor j used in and
the production of one unit of good i. dw* >dw*
-!
_s sorne i; (11)
For dp* small enough we can find the required change, dw* in wt wt
factor prices that preserve equality between prices and unit produc-
for if factor prices all rose in the same proportion, so would goods
tion costs from
prices. Taking the rth equation of (10), and recalling - Yr 1 :?: O, all
- Ydw* = dp*. (lO) r andj,
Let x* O be the output column vector at (p*, w*), L the column
vector of available factor supplies. Then,
hp~ = - L Yr dwj = - L (Yr wj) dw
1 ::::; dw (- L YrWf)
1 (12)
W Ws

-x*'Y = L' or
dwt
where the prime denotes transposition. h ::::;-*'
Ws

1:,
''

256 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 257


From this we conclude that although a technical improvement in Combining this last expression with (10), we have
one sector only must raise the equilibrium product wage everywhere,
it must raise it by the greatest proportion in the sector in which the -x*' Ydw* = L'dw* = x*'dp*
improvement has taken place. so
Let us now consider an economy in which there are a number of
different non-produced inputs that enter into production. As in L' dw* x*' dp*
9.12, we assume that there are as many non-produced inputs as there L'w* = L'w*
are goods. We first consider a fully integrated economy with no and we note that the left-hand side of this expression measures the
intermediate goods. As usual, we write w as the vector of input proportionate change in factor receipts. Let
prices and consider the equilibrium
dpt
h = max-
p* = C*(w*), j PT
where C*(w) is the vector of minimum unit-cost functions. We shall Then, by the assumption of the theorem, dptfpf < h, sorne j at
take p* O and w* O and consider what would be the con- xj > O, whence
sequence for the equilibrium prices of inputs of an autonomous
change in the prices of outputs. We shall discuss the economic x*' dp* hx*'p*
context of this question presently. First, we prove
-L w*' =h,
w*' < - L
where the last equality follows from constant returns to scale, which
THEOREM 9. Let p* O and w* O with p* = C*(w*) in a con-
ensures x*'p* = L'w*. Then, if h- = dp~fp~, say,
stant returns economy using n inputs to producen outputs in positive
amounts. Let p = p* + dp* where p - p* i= kp* for any scalar L'dw* dp~
k> O. Then L'w* < p~
(a) there is at least one good in terms of which total factor so that in terms of the rth good, total factor incomes fall.
income falls; (b) By the twmogeneity of the cost functions and the assumption
(b) there is at least one factor whose income does not fall in dp* i= kp*, there must be an s such that
terms of any good.
dw* >dw*
-!
_s a-11 i
Proof (a) If (C1(w*)) is the Jacobian at w* of C*(w*), Jet -Y= w~' - wt
(C1(w*)). Note (T.3.6) that - Y11 is the amount of factor j used in and
the production of one unit of good i. dw* >dw*
-!
_s sorne i; (11)
For dp* small enough we can find the required change, dw* in wt wt
factor prices that preserve equality between prices and unit produc-
for if factor prices all rose in the same proportion, so would goods
tion costs from
prices. Taking the rth equation of (10), and recalling - Yr 1 :?: O, all
- Ydw* = dp*. (lO) r andj,
Let x* O be the output column vector at (p*, w*), L the column
vector of available factor supplies. Then,
hp~ = - L Yr dwj = - L (Yr wj) dw
1 ::::; dw (- L YrWf)
1 (12)
W Ws

-x*'Y = L' or
dwt
where the prime denotes transposition. h ::::;-*'
Ws

1:,
'i

258 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 259

since by constant returns to scale pj = - Yr 1wj. Hence the which contradicts the assumption of the theorem, and so r = l.
j
income of factor sin terms of good r, the good whose price has risen Since this same assumption ensures that - Yw* has GP (since it has
in the greatest proportion does not fall. DD) where w* is the diagonal matrix with elements wt, solving (10)
gives sr 1 > O, and (12) establishes the theorem.
Corollary 9. If all factors are used in the production of every
good then the real income of at least one factor will increase no Tt can be argued that this result is not of very great interest since
matter how deftated. the assumptions on which it rests are very unlikely to be fulfilled in
practice. If we are concerned on1y with a two-good, two-factor
Proa: The inequality in (12) is strict since - Yr 1 > O, all j.
world, then the supposition that each good uses one input more
These results of course in no way depend on the number of prices intensively than the other, at least in the vicinity of an equilibrium,
that are taken to be different. If, for instance, dpt = O, all i # 1, seems entirely plausible. But then we ha ve replaced the unpalatable
then the real incomes we make predictions about are incomes in assumptions of the theorem by the equally unpalatable one that
terms of good l. there are only two goods. It is also worth noting that the assump-
If we think of a world in which prices are set by the forces of free tion of T. lO. lO ensures that for every p there is only one w at which
international trade, then we may use the above results in analyzing production costs are covered. (We are here assuming DD to hold
the consequences for real factor income in a given country of a globally.) This might suggest that the uniqueness ofthe equilibrium
change in the world price of a given good. Alternatively, we may w, given p, and the problem of which input experiences a rise in its
think of the change in the prices coming about by an imposition or real wage when a given price is raised are connected problems.
removal of a tariff. In that case, for instance, our theory predicts Assertion in sorne of the literature notwithstanding, this is not the
that, tariff revenue apart, the raising of a tariff on one good must case, however. Thus the reader can check that if the production
reduce the real income of factors, but that there will be at least one functions are everywhere Cobb-Douglas with constant returns to
factor that is "not hurt" by this policy and that might gain. The scale, we may write the equations minimum unit cost = price as
question naturally arises, whether we can identify the factor that is
the subject of (b) of the theorem. !ogpi + constant = 2 atJ log w1
THEOREM 1O. Assume that there is one input for every output such where the ai/s are the exponents of the Cobb-Douglas. Since these
that the share of that input in the revenue of the output exceeds the equations are linear, it follows that there is a unique w that satisfies
sum of the shares of all other inputs. If one output price increases, them given p. On the other hand, there is no reason to suppose that
then the price of the corresponding input increases, in at least as the matrix (a 11 ) has DD.
great proportion. Now while it is true that the conditions of T.IO.lO are only
Proa: Let the price of the first good be changed. Number sufficient for its proposition, it is fairly clear that no very economi-
inputs as stated in the theorem and note that it is assumed that cally meaningful necessary conditions are likely. We must thus
conclude that it will be only in the rather special circumstances of the
- Ywt > 2 (~ YtJ)wj
Ni
all i. theorem that, for instance, the effect of a tariff on a particular good
o '1
on the real wage of a named factor can be predicted. At least
1

Let s11 = (dwtfdp[)(ptfwt) and consider r such that T.l 0.9 enables us to predict that there will be one factor that will not
[srl[ 2: [s11 [ all i. have its real wage lowered by the tariff.
1t is easy, however, to show that the output of the good whose
Then, if r # 1 we have by (10),
price is changed must move in a direction not opposite to the price
- Yrrw1[sn[ = /-,?"'r YrJwjsJ11 :o; [srl[ 2"'r (- Yr )wj,
J J
1
change. If we write y(p) as the vector of outputs of the economy
at p, then profit maximization implies
'i

258 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 259

since by constant returns to scale pj = - Yr 1wj. Hence the which contradicts the assumption of the theorem, and so r = l.
j
income of factor sin terms of good r, the good whose price has risen Since this same assumption ensures that - Yw* has GP (since it has
in the greatest proportion does not fall. DD) where w* is the diagonal matrix with elements wt, solving (10)
gives sr 1 > O, and (12) establishes the theorem.
Corollary 9. If all factors are used in the production of every
good then the real income of at least one factor will increase no Tt can be argued that this result is not of very great interest since
matter how deftated. the assumptions on which it rests are very unlikely to be fulfilled in
practice. If we are concerned on1y with a two-good, two-factor
Proa: The inequality in (12) is strict since - Yr 1 > O, all j.
world, then the supposition that each good uses one input more
These results of course in no way depend on the number of prices intensively than the other, at least in the vicinity of an equilibrium,
that are taken to be different. If, for instance, dpt = O, all i # 1, seems entirely plausible. But then we ha ve replaced the unpalatable
then the real incomes we make predictions about are incomes in assumptions of the theorem by the equally unpalatable one that
terms of good l. there are only two goods. It is also worth noting that the assump-
If we think of a world in which prices are set by the forces of free tion of T. lO. lO ensures that for every p there is only one w at which
international trade, then we may use the above results in analyzing production costs are covered. (We are here assuming DD to hold
the consequences for real factor income in a given country of a globally.) This might suggest that the uniqueness ofthe equilibrium
change in the world price of a given good. Alternatively, we may w, given p, and the problem of which input experiences a rise in its
think of the change in the prices coming about by an imposition or real wage when a given price is raised are connected problems.
removal of a tariff. In that case, for instance, our theory predicts Assertion in sorne of the literature notwithstanding, this is not the
that, tariff revenue apart, the raising of a tariff on one good must case, however. Thus the reader can check that if the production
reduce the real income of factors, but that there will be at least one functions are everywhere Cobb-Douglas with constant returns to
factor that is "not hurt" by this policy and that might gain. The scale, we may write the equations minimum unit cost = price as
question naturally arises, whether we can identify the factor that is
the subject of (b) of the theorem. !ogpi + constant = 2 atJ log w1
THEOREM 1O. Assume that there is one input for every output such where the ai/s are the exponents of the Cobb-Douglas. Since these
that the share of that input in the revenue of the output exceeds the equations are linear, it follows that there is a unique w that satisfies
sum of the shares of all other inputs. If one output price increases, them given p. On the other hand, there is no reason to suppose that
then the price of the corresponding input increases, in at least as the matrix (a 11 ) has DD.
great proportion. Now while it is true that the conditions of T.IO.lO are only
Proa: Let the price of the first good be changed. Number sufficient for its proposition, it is fairly clear that no very economi-
inputs as stated in the theorem and note that it is assumed that cally meaningful necessary conditions are likely. We must thus
conclude that it will be only in the rather special circumstances of the
- Ywt > 2 (~ YtJ)wj
Ni
all i. theorem that, for instance, the effect of a tariff on a particular good
o '1
on the real wage of a named factor can be predicted. At least
1

Let s11 = (dwtfdp[)(ptfwt) and consider r such that T.l 0.9 enables us to predict that there will be one factor that will not
[srl[ 2: [s11 [ all i. have its real wage lowered by the tariff.
1t is easy, however, to show that the output of the good whose
Then, if r # 1 we have by (10),
price is changed must move in a direction not opposite to the price
- Yrrw1[sn[ = /-,?"'r YrJwjsJ11 :o; [srl[ 2"'r (- Yr )wj,
J J
1
change. If we write y(p) as the vector of outputs of the economy
at p, then profit maximization implies
:1
COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 261
260 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

p*y(p*) - w*L ~ p*y(p**) - w*L, Suppose x* O, L O. We are interested in predicting the new
equilibrium output x** that would result if there was a small change
p**y(p**) -. w**L ~ p**y(p*) - w**L. in the availability of input of type 1 and p* were held constant:
So combining and noting that D.p:[ = O, al! i # 1, we ha ve This, in the two-factor case, was first investigated by Rybczynskt
[1955]. .
D..pt(yl(p**) - Yl(P*)] :?: O. Suppose -Y has GP. Then we want to examme
This concludes what seems possible to accomplish for this class -dx*' Y= (dLl> O, ... , 0).
of problem. Before we lea ve it, though, we must briefiy see how our
conclusions survive the introduction of intermediate goods. We By the Remark to D.9.1 (the definition ~f GP), the vectors dx* .an~
now write the equation mnimum unit cost = price as dL must have at Ieast one component w1th common non-zero stgn,
this can only be the first, so that we conclude that.dxfdLl > O.
p = H(p,w).
Certainly - y will have GP if, for sorne num~enng of t~e outputs
If, as before, we write - Y as the matrix of factor inputs per unit of and inputs, the sector uses input i more intens1vely than 1t does all
output and - Y as the matrix of the inputs of goods per unit of other inputs combined,
output, then (10) becomes
- Ydw* = (I + Y)dp*
where I is the unit matrix. The net output vector, x*'(I + Y), is In that case we then have the theorem that, say, an increase in the
assumed strictly positive. lf we define h as in T.l 0.9, dp* < p*h amount of ~1 put available, all goods prices constant, willlead to a
and, therefore, x*'(I + Y)dp* < x*'(I + Y)p*h. Since certainly, new equilibrium where more of the good usit1g i ~os~ inten~ively
will be produced. This result has proved useful m s1mple mter-
-x*' Y= L',
national trade theory, but it is achieved at a high cost.
as before, and by constant returns to scale,

i
L'w* = x*'(I + Y)p* 5. Conclusions
1 The most notable conclusion of our investigations in this chapter
the proof of T.l0.9(a) proceeds as before.
i That T.10.9(b) continues to hold is clear from the modified (12), appears to us to be that for very many interesting problem~ of
i
comparing equilibria, the information provided by th~ foun~at10~s
h(p; + ~ Yr;P1)
1
,.,
i
S hp; + 2 Yr;dpj s dw! (- 2 Yr;w1) of the models, profii and utility maximization, are ms~ffictent 111
J j Ws j giving us definite answers to our questions. Indeed, even tf t~e weak
That T.IO.IO also survives the introduction of intermediate goods axiom of revealed preference holds for the whole economy, etther for
is now clear. Thus, to suppose the economy to be fully integrated comparisons involving one equilibrium or generally: we soon find
turns out to be a harmless simplification in these problems. that we have insufficient information when we constder paramet~r
We conclude this discussion of the constant returns to scale changes that are not binary. At one time it ':'a~ thou~h.t that thts
economy with a simple example. paucity of definite rsults could be avoided, 1f m addttton to the
1
Consider an economy of the type here considered in equilibrium underlying maximizing behavior of agents, it was postulated. that the
with a factor endowment of L. (We again exclude intermediate equilibrium of the economy was "stable" under sorne adJUS~J~ent
goods for simplicity of exposition.) That is, in the usual notation, process. We shall see Iater, however, that t~e neces~ary cond1t1~ns
p* = C(w*) and - x*' Y = L', where x* is again the vector of for such stability do not provide the kind of mformat1?n. we reqmre,
outputs. while sufficient conditions now known involve restnct10ns on the
:1
COMPARING EQUILIBRIA 261
260 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

p*y(p*) - w*L ~ p*y(p**) - w*L, Suppose x* O, L O. We are interested in predicting the new
equilibrium output x** that would result if there was a small change
p**y(p**) -. w**L ~ p**y(p*) - w**L. in the availability of input of type 1 and p* were held constant:
So combining and noting that D.p:[ = O, al! i # 1, we ha ve This, in the two-factor case, was first investigated by Rybczynskt
[1955]. .
D..pt(yl(p**) - Yl(P*)] :?: O. Suppose -Y has GP. Then we want to examme
This concludes what seems possible to accomplish for this class -dx*' Y= (dLl> O, ... , 0).
of problem. Before we lea ve it, though, we must briefiy see how our
conclusions survive the introduction of intermediate goods. We By the Remark to D.9.1 (the definition ~f GP), the vectors dx* .an~
now write the equation mnimum unit cost = price as dL must have at Ieast one component w1th common non-zero stgn,
this can only be the first, so that we conclude that.dxfdLl > O.
p = H(p,w).
Certainly - y will have GP if, for sorne num~enng of t~e outputs
If, as before, we write - Y as the matrix of factor inputs per unit of and inputs, the sector uses input i more intens1vely than 1t does all
output and - Y as the matrix of the inputs of goods per unit of other inputs combined,
output, then (10) becomes
- Ydw* = (I + Y)dp*
where I is the unit matrix. The net output vector, x*'(I + Y), is In that case we then have the theorem that, say, an increase in the
assumed strictly positive. lf we define h as in T.l 0.9, dp* < p*h amount of ~1 put available, all goods prices constant, willlead to a
and, therefore, x*'(I + Y)dp* < x*'(I + Y)p*h. Since certainly, new equilibrium where more of the good usit1g i ~os~ inten~ively
will be produced. This result has proved useful m s1mple mter-
-x*' Y= L',
national trade theory, but it is achieved at a high cost.
as before, and by constant returns to scale,

i
L'w* = x*'(I + Y)p* 5. Conclusions
1 The most notable conclusion of our investigations in this chapter
the proof of T.l0.9(a) proceeds as before.
i That T.10.9(b) continues to hold is clear from the modified (12), appears to us to be that for very many interesting problem~ of
i
comparing equilibria, the information provided by th~ foun~at10~s
h(p; + ~ Yr;P1)
1
,.,
i
S hp; + 2 Yr;dpj s dw! (- 2 Yr;w1) of the models, profii and utility maximization, are ms~ffictent 111
J j Ws j giving us definite answers to our questions. Indeed, even tf t~e weak
That T.IO.IO also survives the introduction of intermediate goods axiom of revealed preference holds for the whole economy, etther for
is now clear. Thus, to suppose the economy to be fully integrated comparisons involving one equilibrium or generally: we soon find
turns out to be a harmless simplification in these problems. that we have insufficient information when we constder paramet~r
We conclude this discussion of the constant returns to scale changes that are not binary. At one time it ':'a~ thou~h.t that thts
economy with a simple example. paucity of definite rsults could be avoided, 1f m addttton to the
1
Consider an economy of the type here considered in equilibrium underlying maximizing behavior of agents, it was postulated. that the
with a factor endowment of L. (We again exclude intermediate equilibrium of the economy was "stable" under sorne adJUS~J~ent
goods for simplicity of exposition.) That is, in the usual notation, process. We shall see Iater, however, that t~e neces~ary cond1t1~ns
p* = C(w*) and - x*' Y = L', where x* is again the vector of for such stability do not provide the kind of mformat1?n. we reqmre,
outputs. while sufficient conditions now known involve restnct10ns on the
1'

1
1
1
262 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
Chapter Eleven
excess-demand functions such as GS or DD that, as we have seen in
this chapter, do not carry us a great deal further. INTRODUCTION TO
Now while such results as we were able to establish are useful and STABILITY ANALYSIS
worth having, the main negative lesson is also useful, for it points to
the dangers of partial analysis, in which it is often possible to get
quite definite predictions of the consequences of a given parameter Nine in the second position means:
change. We now know that such results, if they are to be correct He allows himself to be drawn into
for "other things not equal" involve very special assumptions, such returning.
as DD and binary changes. Good fortune.
-1 Ching

Notes
Hicks [1939] was probably the first to concern himself with the l. The Problem
questions of this chapter in the context of a full general equilibrium
model. His method, as well as that of his successors, sllch as Mosak The economist's interest in equilibrium situations may be justified
[1944] and Samuelson [1947], was based on calclllus and hence was by two kinds of arguments. An equilibrium has special claims to
concerned only with infinitesimal changes. Morishima [1959-60] was our attention because when we ask ourselves how to characterize a
the first to exploit the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference in binary decentralized economy that is also efficient we find that it is often an
comparisons of price situations of which one was an equilibrillm. economy in competitive equilibrium. This is not always so as, for
T.10.2-T.l0.4, were first noted by him. T.10.8 is also closely related to
a proposition of Morishima's [1964], although his analysis was in the instance, reftection on the case of an economy subject to increasing
context of a model of steady growth. Indeed, a nllmber of reslllts that returns will quickly show. It is true, however, for sufficiently
refer to comparisons of steady states have not been treated by us since interesting situations and so certainly merits attention. The second
they wollld have required liS to break off our main analysis. T.10.10 argument, familiar from Marshall, is simply that there are forces at
is, in the n-factor context, related to a well-known proposition of work in any actual economy that tend to drive an economy toward
Samuelson and Stolper [1941]. The other theorems do not appear to
be in the Iiterature. an equilibrium if it is not in equilibrium already. If this is correct,
In recent years, a suggestion of Samuelson's [1947] that local com- then for instance, the method of comparing equilibria may be a
parative reslllts might be obtainable from the sign pattern of the legitimate way of going about the business of predicting the con-
appropriate Jacobians has been mllch explored. The main references sequences of given parameter changes. In any case, it is with the
are Lancaster [1961-62, 1964, 1965], Gorman [1964], and Qllirk [1968]. question of a "tendency to equilibrium" that this and two of the
We have not discussed this development because it would have taken lis
following chapters will be concerned. We may agree at the outset
~ather ~ar afield. As might be expected, the reslllts so far, although
1'
1 mterestmg, ha ve not been very encouraging. For instance, for a binary that should our investigations convince us that Marshall was mis-
i
change, sign prediction is possible if and only if the matrix (s11 (p)), by taken, this in itself would be a conclusion of considerable importance.
permlltation and 111llltiplication by diagonal matrices with 1 on the Not only would it have immediate negative implications for the
diagonal, can be given the GS sign pattern or th~ GS sign pattern except method of comparing equilibria, but when we put on the hat of
for one colllmn where all off-diagonal elements can be positive. The welfare economists, it would have great relevance in helping us to
first case is, of collrse, GP, and llsing W, the second case can be shown
to imply GP also (since it implies DD). On the other hand, of course, judge, in the manner in which welfare economists do judge, the
GP does not imply this sign pattern., So we seem to have the following performance of actual economic systems.
result: Sign restrictions in the binary change case are possible from sign That the task we have set ourselves is a hard one seems evident.
information on the Jacobian only if this information sllffices to establish It would surely be foolish to suppose that the proper manner of
GP.
proceeding would be to plunge immediately into the complex prob-
lems of agents' reactions to disequilibrium situations. Accordingly,
1

263
1:
1 'i
'ill
1'

1
1
1
262 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
Chapter Eleven
excess-demand functions such as GS or DD that, as we have seen in
this chapter, do not carry us a great deal further. INTRODUCTION TO
Now while such results as we were able to establish are useful and STABILITY ANALYSIS
worth having, the main negative lesson is also useful, for it points to
the dangers of partial analysis, in which it is often possible to get
quite definite predictions of the consequences of a given parameter Nine in the second position means:
change. We now know that such results, if they are to be correct He allows himself to be drawn into
for "other things not equal" involve very special assumptions, such returning.
as DD and binary changes. Good fortune.
-1 Ching

Notes
Hicks [1939] was probably the first to concern himself with the l. The Problem
questions of this chapter in the context of a full general equilibrium
model. His method, as well as that of his successors, sllch as Mosak The economist's interest in equilibrium situations may be justified
[1944] and Samuelson [1947], was based on calclllus and hence was by two kinds of arguments. An equilibrium has special claims to
concerned only with infinitesimal changes. Morishima [1959-60] was our attention because when we ask ourselves how to characterize a
the first to exploit the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference in binary decentralized economy that is also efficient we find that it is often an
comparisons of price situations of which one was an equilibrillm. economy in competitive equilibrium. This is not always so as, for
T.10.2-T.l0.4, were first noted by him. T.10.8 is also closely related to
a proposition of Morishima's [1964], although his analysis was in the instance, reftection on the case of an economy subject to increasing
context of a model of steady growth. Indeed, a nllmber of reslllts that returns will quickly show. It is true, however, for sufficiently
refer to comparisons of steady states have not been treated by us since interesting situations and so certainly merits attention. The second
they wollld have required liS to break off our main analysis. T.10.10 argument, familiar from Marshall, is simply that there are forces at
is, in the n-factor context, related to a well-known proposition of work in any actual economy that tend to drive an economy toward
Samuelson and Stolper [1941]. The other theorems do not appear to
be in the Iiterature. an equilibrium if it is not in equilibrium already. If this is correct,
In recent years, a suggestion of Samuelson's [1947] that local com- then for instance, the method of comparing equilibria may be a
parative reslllts might be obtainable from the sign pattern of the legitimate way of going about the business of predicting the con-
appropriate Jacobians has been mllch explored. The main references sequences of given parameter changes. In any case, it is with the
are Lancaster [1961-62, 1964, 1965], Gorman [1964], and Qllirk [1968]. question of a "tendency to equilibrium" that this and two of the
We have not discussed this development because it would have taken lis
following chapters will be concerned. We may agree at the outset
~ather ~ar afield. As might be expected, the reslllts so far, although
1'
1 mterestmg, ha ve not been very encouraging. For instance, for a binary that should our investigations convince us that Marshall was mis-
i
change, sign prediction is possible if and only if the matrix (s11 (p)), by taken, this in itself would be a conclusion of considerable importance.
permlltation and 111llltiplication by diagonal matrices with 1 on the Not only would it have immediate negative implications for the
diagonal, can be given the GS sign pattern or th~ GS sign pattern except method of comparing equilibria, but when we put on the hat of
for one colllmn where all off-diagonal elements can be positive. The welfare economists, it would have great relevance in helping us to
first case is, of collrse, GP, and llsing W, the second case can be shown
to imply GP also (since it implies DD). On the other hand, of course, judge, in the manner in which welfare economists do judge, the
GP does not imply this sign pattern., So we seem to have the following performance of actual economic systems.
result: Sign restrictions in the binary change case are possible from sign That the task we have set ourselves is a hard one seems evident.
information on the Jacobian only if this information sllffices to establish It would surely be foolish to suppose that the proper manner of
GP.
proceeding would be to plunge immediately into the complex prob-
lems of agents' reactions to disequilibrium situations. Accordingly,
1

263
1:
1 'i
'ill
264
T INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 265
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

we shall start our en quiries with a quite artificial process of adjust- DEFINITION l. A ttonnement consists of the adoption of the follow-
ment, which we shall now describe and discuss. ing rules:
(a) If p(t) is a price vector at time t, then this price is changed
by some rule if and only if p(t) is notan equilibrium.
2. A Tatonnement (b) Agents are permitted to transact if and only if p(t) is an
equilibrium.
Suppose that in an economy with given tastes, endowments, and
technological knowledge, agents believe that they can transact on It seems pretty clear that when we have learned all we can about
terms given by the price vector p and that, of course, these terms do this kind of process, a great deal of work will remain before we shall
:: not depend on the amount of any given transaction. Suppose be able to claim to ha ve a proper understanding of the "price
further that, given p, agents plan to transact in amounts such that mechanism." It would be foolish, however, to maintain that we
for none of them is there an alternative set of transactions that they shall have learned nothing because the stage we have set bears too
would prefer, but that, in fact, not all the transactions can be carried little resemblance to the actual world. For one thing, it will be
out s!multa:neously. This means that p is not an equilibrium. In agreed that a tatonnement serves to isolate what might be called
practice, therefore, sorne agents will find their plans cannot be "pure price effects" from those that are due to changes in either the
brought to fruition, so that when we look at them a little later, we wealth or the composition of wealth of the agents. Since we shall
should find that the goods they have and the production they under- certainly have to understand these price effects in any full story, it
take are not the goods they planned to have or the production they is reasonable to suppose that a study of them in isolation is a hopeful
planned to undertake. We would then require to know just how procedure.
each agent fared in carrying out his transaction plans before we could It may also be argued that despite its abstract stance, a tatnne-
hope to carry the story further. This will be quite difficult to ment is what many economists must have had in mind when they
accomplish and it is the special feature of what we shall call a first proposed "the law of supply and demand." More than piety
tatonnement 1 that it sidesteps this difficulty by supposing tht no seems at stake in subjecting such venerable principies to the more
transactions at all are carried out when the transactions planned rigorous analysis of the present time. Additionally, it may be
cannot be brought to fruition simultaneously. maintained that although the process is pictured as taking place in
We may imagine, to give some ftesh to the abstraction we propose time, this is simply a device to aid understanding, and that the
to inv.estigate, the existence of a super-auctioneer who calls a given set calculations of the auctioneer may be taken as steps in a computer
of pr1ces p and receives transaction offers from the agents in the program designed, by a process of iteration, to calculate the equi-
econm_ny. If these do not match, he calls another set of prices, librium prices for an economy. Not too much can be made of this
followmg some rule, to be discussed, but no transactions are allowed point because, on the one hand, the rules we shall impose on the
to take place. This process either comes to some end or continues auctioneer do, however remotely, mimic what we believe goes on
indefinitely. In fact, we shall find that, like Achilles and the tortoise, in actual markets, and there is no reason why a computer program
th~ auctioneer following his rule will never be able to rectify a should be so restricted, and on the other, there is no reason to think
misiake completely, although in some proper sense, the mistake may the process computationally efficient.
get smaller and smaller. But that is a point that must await atten- Lastly, before turning to greater details, it may be worth noting
tion until the suitable moment has come. Here we better give a that we could think of actual economies for which a tatnnement
formal definition of the imaginary process. would not appear to be so remote a description, for instance, in a
world where all goods are perishable and where the goods agents
1
The word comes from Walras. It is not claimed that he used it in the same have in possession after given time intervals are independent of the
way as it is being used here. transactions they ha ve carried out. This world would not be greatly

'll
11:
264
T INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 265
GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

we shall start our en quiries with a quite artificial process of adjust- DEFINITION l. A ttonnement consists of the adoption of the follow-
ment, which we shall now describe and discuss. ing rules:
(a) If p(t) is a price vector at time t, then this price is changed
by some rule if and only if p(t) is notan equilibrium.
2. A Tatonnement (b) Agents are permitted to transact if and only if p(t) is an
equilibrium.
Suppose that in an economy with given tastes, endowments, and
technological knowledge, agents believe that they can transact on It seems pretty clear that when we have learned all we can about
terms given by the price vector p and that, of course, these terms do this kind of process, a great deal of work will remain before we shall
:: not depend on the amount of any given transaction. Suppose be able to claim to ha ve a proper understanding of the "price
further that, given p, agents plan to transact in amounts such that mechanism." It would be foolish, however, to maintain that we
for none of them is there an alternative set of transactions that they shall have learned nothing because the stage we have set bears too
would prefer, but that, in fact, not all the transactions can be carried little resemblance to the actual world. For one thing, it will be
out s!multa:neously. This means that p is not an equilibrium. In agreed that a tatonnement serves to isolate what might be called
practice, therefore, sorne agents will find their plans cannot be "pure price effects" from those that are due to changes in either the
brought to fruition, so that when we look at them a little later, we wealth or the composition of wealth of the agents. Since we shall
should find that the goods they have and the production they under- certainly have to understand these price effects in any full story, it
take are not the goods they planned to have or the production they is reasonable to suppose that a study of them in isolation is a hopeful
planned to undertake. We would then require to know just how procedure.
each agent fared in carrying out his transaction plans before we could It may also be argued that despite its abstract stance, a tatnne-
hope to carry the story further. This will be quite difficult to ment is what many economists must have had in mind when they
accomplish and it is the special feature of what we shall call a first proposed "the law of supply and demand." More than piety
tatonnement 1 that it sidesteps this difficulty by supposing tht no seems at stake in subjecting such venerable principies to the more
transactions at all are carried out when the transactions planned rigorous analysis of the present time. Additionally, it may be
cannot be brought to fruition simultaneously. maintained that although the process is pictured as taking place in
We may imagine, to give some ftesh to the abstraction we propose time, this is simply a device to aid understanding, and that the
to inv.estigate, the existence of a super-auctioneer who calls a given set calculations of the auctioneer may be taken as steps in a computer
of pr1ces p and receives transaction offers from the agents in the program designed, by a process of iteration, to calculate the equi-
econm_ny. If these do not match, he calls another set of prices, librium prices for an economy. Not too much can be made of this
followmg some rule, to be discussed, but no transactions are allowed point because, on the one hand, the rules we shall impose on the
to take place. This process either comes to some end or continues auctioneer do, however remotely, mimic what we believe goes on
indefinitely. In fact, we shall find that, like Achilles and the tortoise, in actual markets, and there is no reason why a computer program
th~ auctioneer following his rule will never be able to rectify a should be so restricted, and on the other, there is no reason to think
misiake completely, although in some proper sense, the mistake may the process computationally efficient.
get smaller and smaller. But that is a point that must await atten- Lastly, before turning to greater details, it may be worth noting
tion until the suitable moment has come. Here we better give a that we could think of actual economies for which a tatnnement
formal definition of the imaginary process. would not appear to be so remote a description, for instance, in a
world where all goods are perishable and where the goods agents
1
The word comes from Walras. It is not claimed that he used it in the same have in possession after given time intervals are independent of the
way as it is being used here. transactions they ha ve carried out. This world would not be greatly

'll
11:
266 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 267
misdescribed by a process that prohibits transactions at non- at t' to contradict the definition of t". But z1(p(t")) ::; O is also
equilibrium prices, simply because the change in the circumstances impossible for then the ith price would remain constant at zero
of agents due to transactions are quite transitory. On the other beyond t". Hence p 1(t) < O is not possible.
hand, we should still face a problem, endemic for perfect competition Suppose next that for sorne finite t' we have p(t') = O. We note
models, of how prices are changed. For, if no one can affect the that when p(t) i= O, it must be that for sorne i, z1(p(t)) > O. If not,
terms on which he may transact, it is hard to see, without the "as if" z(p(t)) ::; O and so, by D.2.1, p(t) is an equilibrium. It then must
auctioneer, how these terms ever come to be different. This is a be true, by T.2.1, that all goods in excess supply have a zero price
point to which we shall return later (see Chapter 13). and no good with a positive price is in excess demand. But then
p(t) = O, contrary to assumption. Since sorne price is always
3. The Auctioneer's Rules increasing as long as prices are changing and p(O) > O, not all prices
can become zero in finite time and the supposition at the beginning
We have already committed ourselves to one rule that we shall of the paragraph is not possible. However, the reader should note
take the auctioneer as following: Never change any price if the given that we ha ve not established the impossibility of p(t) approaching O
price vector is an equilibrium; never leave all prices unchanged if the as t approaches plus infinity. For reasons that will become apparent,
given price vector is not an equilibrium. We have also supposed we shall have to strengthen our requirements on the auctioneer's
implicitly that the price adjustment is in continuous time. This is 1.
rules in order to exclude that possibility also. So far we have
notan essential feature of the process and at sorne la ter stage we shall established
consider situations in which the adjustment is over discrete time
intervals. What we shall do now, bearing in mind that we wish THEOREM l. lf A.ll.l holds, then
to attain sorne eventual understanding of the price mechanism, is to (a) prices change if and only if the economy is not in
allow the other restrictions on the auctioneer to be what we take to equilibrium;
be most conducive to mimicking what may be an actual process. (b) for all finite t, p(t) > O if p(O) > O.
Thus, taking F, W, C, and B of Chapter 2 to hold and writing, as
usual, z1(p) as the excess-demand function for commodity i when the The "error" that causes a given price to change is a disparity
,
distribution of wealth between agents and its total amount can be between the planned transactions of agents in the market in which
taken as given, we stipulate the following rule for the auctioneer. that price is called. It will be agreed that the last property of the
AssuMPTION l. Let G1(z1) be a sign-preserving function of z1, with rule that we are imposing seems faithful to that "law" of supply and
G1(0) = O, and differentiable with o; > O. Then for all i: demand to which we have already referred. Yet it has caused sorne
disquiet on the grounds that while it is reasonable to postulate that,
Pt = O if p 1 ::;O and z1(p) < O for instance, an actual attempt to buy more shoes at a given price
jJ1 = G1[z1(p)] otherwise than are being supplied at that price will drive up the price of shoes,
(A dot over a symbol denotes the operation dfdt.) it is quite another matter to say that the plan to buy more shoes than
are planned for supply will drive up their price. It might just
The first thing to notice about this rule is that if p(O) > O, then happcn that when severa! markets are out of equilibrium and I ha ve
p(t) > Ofor allfinite t (i.e., t < +oo). We show this now. already found myself unable to buy the socks I had planned to buy,
Take p 1(0) > O and suppose that p 1(t') < O, t' > O. Then, by my actual pressure to have shoes supplied to me also will be less than
continuity, there is sorne t, where O < t < t', for which p 1(t) = O. I had planned it to be before I discovered my inability to fulfill my
Let t" be the time closest to t' for which the ith price is zero. Then plans. Therefore, is it sensible to deduce from people's plans what
it cannot be that z1(p(t")) > O, for the ith price is rising at t" and the actual pressure on individual markets is going to be when these
would have to pass through zero again in order to become negative plans are inconsistent? There is no doubt that these objections ha ve
266 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 267
misdescribed by a process that prohibits transactions at non- at t' to contradict the definition of t". But z1(p(t")) ::; O is also
equilibrium prices, simply because the change in the circumstances impossible for then the ith price would remain constant at zero
of agents due to transactions are quite transitory. On the other beyond t". Hence p 1(t) < O is not possible.
hand, we should still face a problem, endemic for perfect competition Suppose next that for sorne finite t' we have p(t') = O. We note
models, of how prices are changed. For, if no one can affect the that when p(t) i= O, it must be that for sorne i, z1(p(t)) > O. If not,
terms on which he may transact, it is hard to see, without the "as if" z(p(t)) ::; O and so, by D.2.1, p(t) is an equilibrium. It then must
auctioneer, how these terms ever come to be different. This is a be true, by T.2.1, that all goods in excess supply have a zero price
point to which we shall return later (see Chapter 13). and no good with a positive price is in excess demand. But then
p(t) = O, contrary to assumption. Since sorne price is always
3. The Auctioneer's Rules increasing as long as prices are changing and p(O) > O, not all prices
can become zero in finite time and the supposition at the beginning
We have already committed ourselves to one rule that we shall of the paragraph is not possible. However, the reader should note
take the auctioneer as following: Never change any price if the given that we ha ve not established the impossibility of p(t) approaching O
price vector is an equilibrium; never leave all prices unchanged if the as t approaches plus infinity. For reasons that will become apparent,
given price vector is not an equilibrium. We have also supposed we shall have to strengthen our requirements on the auctioneer's
implicitly that the price adjustment is in continuous time. This is 1.
rules in order to exclude that possibility also. So far we have
notan essential feature of the process and at sorne la ter stage we shall established
consider situations in which the adjustment is over discrete time
intervals. What we shall do now, bearing in mind that we wish THEOREM l. lf A.ll.l holds, then
to attain sorne eventual understanding of the price mechanism, is to (a) prices change if and only if the economy is not in
allow the other restrictions on the auctioneer to be what we take to equilibrium;
be most conducive to mimicking what may be an actual process. (b) for all finite t, p(t) > O if p(O) > O.
Thus, taking F, W, C, and B of Chapter 2 to hold and writing, as
usual, z1(p) as the excess-demand function for commodity i when the The "error" that causes a given price to change is a disparity
,
distribution of wealth between agents and its total amount can be between the planned transactions of agents in the market in which
taken as given, we stipulate the following rule for the auctioneer. that price is called. It will be agreed that the last property of the
AssuMPTION l. Let G1(z1) be a sign-preserving function of z1, with rule that we are imposing seems faithful to that "law" of supply and
G1(0) = O, and differentiable with o; > O. Then for all i: demand to which we have already referred. Yet it has caused sorne
disquiet on the grounds that while it is reasonable to postulate that,
Pt = O if p 1 ::;O and z1(p) < O for instance, an actual attempt to buy more shoes at a given price
jJ1 = G1[z1(p)] otherwise than are being supplied at that price will drive up the price of shoes,
(A dot over a symbol denotes the operation dfdt.) it is quite another matter to say that the plan to buy more shoes than
are planned for supply will drive up their price. It might just
The first thing to notice about this rule is that if p(O) > O, then happcn that when severa! markets are out of equilibrium and I ha ve
p(t) > Ofor allfinite t (i.e., t < +oo). We show this now. already found myself unable to buy the socks I had planned to buy,
Take p 1(0) > O and suppose that p 1(t') < O, t' > O. Then, by my actual pressure to have shoes supplied to me also will be less than
continuity, there is sorne t, where O < t < t', for which p 1(t) = O. I had planned it to be before I discovered my inability to fulfill my
Let t" be the time closest to t' for which the ith price is zero. Then plans. Therefore, is it sensible to deduce from people's plans what
it cannot be that z1(p(t")) > O, for the ith price is rising at t" and the actual pressure on individual markets is going to be when these
would have to pass through zero again in order to become negative plans are inconsistent? There is no doubt that these objections ha ve
.r.~.
i'i

::
:
l 1

11

1'
268 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 269
force in an argument designed to show that the rules we propose do number of possible different solutions; indeed, for general cases we
not properly mimic what we think may actually take place in might then find it impossible to analyze the time path of prices at
markets. Certainly we shall have to consider this matter at some all. Accordingly, we shall wish to exclude this possibility of mul-
stage. (Se e Cha pter 13.) tiple solutions. For reasons that .will become apparent in the next
It will have been noticed that A.ll.l applies the same rule of section, we shall also wish to be able to take for granted that p(t 1 p(O))
change to all prices. lt must be true, then, that we are taking these is continuous in p(O), that is, in the initial conditions.
as reckoned in some fictional unit of account. However, we are The ideal way of doing this would be to specify the class of
used to dealing with prices in terms of some numeraire, for example, functions G( ) for which we can be certain that the resulting path
money. It will be convenient to have an analysis also of a situation will ha ve the properties we desire. U nfortunately, our insistence
in which the prices called by the auctioneer are in terms of numeraire. that prices must never become negative precludes us from using the
Let us suppose that A.9.2(N) holds and consider the following standard sufficient restriction that the functions should satisfy a
modification of A.ll.l where P is the price vector in terms of "Lipschitz condition." 1 That condition certainly will not be
numeraire. satisfied if the functions determining the rate of change in prices are
! 1 AssuMPTrON 2. Let Fi(zi) ha ve all the properties of G1(z1) and choose not continuous, and our functions will not be continuous for al! p.
i the nth good as numeraire. Then for al! i #- n: Suppose that p has a zero member Pi and that zi(P) < O. Then for
1

al! p' close to p with p;> O, there is E > O such that


Pi = O if P 1 ::::; O and zi(P) < O
':1 zi(p) < -E.
1
Pi = Fi(zi(P)) otherwise
So, for some o> O in the same neighborhood
and Pn is equal to zero identically in t. Gi(z(p')) < -o.
It seems unnecessary to comment further on this assumption, But at p, Gi(zi(p)) = O so that Gis discontinuous at p.
since what was said concerning A.ll.l applies to it also. Yet even Certainly, we can avoid much of this trouble if we consider only
at this stage, we may note that we shall wish to ask ourselves whether classes of excess-demand functions (such as those that satisfy GS)
certain of the conclusions we may deduce for this process are for which we can be certain that, if we start with a strictly positive
independent of the choice of numeraire, if there are a number of price vector, the auctioneer will never find himself in the position of
goods that may be so chosen without logical objection. not cbanging a price although its excess demand is not zero. Of
Both of the auctioneer's rules suppose that when changes in course, this involves a certain cost-a rather severe restriction on the
prices do occur, they do so in continuous time. At some stage, it excess-demand functions. Instead, we ptefer to follow the rather
will be interesting also to consider them in discrete time. In that unsatisfactory procedure of stipulating directly the consequences we
case,insteadofpor:Pweshallwritepi(t +E)- Pi(t)andPi(t +E)- desire.
Pi(t). AssuMPTION 3. Let p(t 1 p(O)) be a solution of the rule in A.ll.l and
There are also a number of technical restrictions that we shall P(t 1 P(O)) a solution of the rule in A.ll.2. Then

impose on the rules followed by the auctioneer. If we look at these


(a) these solutions are uniquely determined by their initial
rules again, we see that they llre a set of simultaneous differential
conditions, p(O) or P(O);
equations. A solution of such equations is a path depending on t
'i (b) the solutions are continuous in p(O) and P(O), respectively.
and on initial conditions (p(O) or P(O)). From now on we shall
1
discuss only A.ll.l; what is said about A.ll.l applies equally to 1 The differential equations: :X = f(x), where x is a vector and f(x) is vector
valued, are said to obey a Lipschitz condition if for any two values of x, say
A.11.2. We write a solution as p(t p(O)) and note that if indeed it
1
x and x',
is a solution, it must be that p(t 1 p(O)) satisfies the rules at each t. lf(x) - f(x')l ;'i; Klx - x'l,
It would be very awkward if for given initial conditions there were a where K is a constant independent of x.
.r.~.
i'i

::
:
l 1

11

1'
268 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 269
force in an argument designed to show that the rules we propose do number of possible different solutions; indeed, for general cases we
not properly mimic what we think may actually take place in might then find it impossible to analyze the time path of prices at
markets. Certainly we shall have to consider this matter at some all. Accordingly, we shall wish to exclude this possibility of mul-
stage. (Se e Cha pter 13.) tiple solutions. For reasons that .will become apparent in the next
It will have been noticed that A.ll.l applies the same rule of section, we shall also wish to be able to take for granted that p(t 1 p(O))
change to all prices. lt must be true, then, that we are taking these is continuous in p(O), that is, in the initial conditions.
as reckoned in some fictional unit of account. However, we are The ideal way of doing this would be to specify the class of
used to dealing with prices in terms of some numeraire, for example, functions G( ) for which we can be certain that the resulting path
money. It will be convenient to have an analysis also of a situation will ha ve the properties we desire. U nfortunately, our insistence
in which the prices called by the auctioneer are in terms of numeraire. that prices must never become negative precludes us from using the
Let us suppose that A.9.2(N) holds and consider the following standard sufficient restriction that the functions should satisfy a
modification of A.ll.l where P is the price vector in terms of "Lipschitz condition." 1 That condition certainly will not be
numeraire. satisfied if the functions determining the rate of change in prices are
! 1 AssuMPTrON 2. Let Fi(zi) ha ve all the properties of G1(z1) and choose not continuous, and our functions will not be continuous for al! p.
i the nth good as numeraire. Then for al! i #- n: Suppose that p has a zero member Pi and that zi(P) < O. Then for
1

al! p' close to p with p;> O, there is E > O such that


Pi = O if P 1 ::::; O and zi(P) < O
':1 zi(p) < -E.
1
Pi = Fi(zi(P)) otherwise
So, for some o> O in the same neighborhood
and Pn is equal to zero identically in t. Gi(z(p')) < -o.
It seems unnecessary to comment further on this assumption, But at p, Gi(zi(p)) = O so that Gis discontinuous at p.
since what was said concerning A.ll.l applies to it also. Yet even Certainly, we can avoid much of this trouble if we consider only
at this stage, we may note that we shall wish to ask ourselves whether classes of excess-demand functions (such as those that satisfy GS)
certain of the conclusions we may deduce for this process are for which we can be certain that, if we start with a strictly positive
independent of the choice of numeraire, if there are a number of price vector, the auctioneer will never find himself in the position of
goods that may be so chosen without logical objection. not cbanging a price although its excess demand is not zero. Of
Both of the auctioneer's rules suppose that when changes in course, this involves a certain cost-a rather severe restriction on the
prices do occur, they do so in continuous time. At some stage, it excess-demand functions. Instead, we ptefer to follow the rather
will be interesting also to consider them in discrete time. In that unsatisfactory procedure of stipulating directly the consequences we
case,insteadofpor:Pweshallwritepi(t +E)- Pi(t)andPi(t +E)- desire.
Pi(t). AssuMPTION 3. Let p(t 1 p(O)) be a solution of the rule in A.ll.l and
There are also a number of technical restrictions that we shall P(t 1 P(O)) a solution of the rule in A.ll.2. Then

impose on the rules followed by the auctioneer. If we look at these


(a) these solutions are uniquely determined by their initial
rules again, we see that they llre a set of simultaneous differential
conditions, p(O) or P(O);
equations. A solution of such equations is a path depending on t
'i (b) the solutions are continuous in p(O) and P(O), respectively.
and on initial conditions (p(O) or P(O)). From now on we shall
1
discuss only A.ll.l; what is said about A.ll.l applies equally to 1 The differential equations: :X = f(x), where x is a vector and f(x) is vector
valued, are said to obey a Lipschitz condition if for any two values of x, say
A.11.2. We write a solution as p(t p(O)) and note that if indeed it
1
x and x',
is a solution, it must be that p(t 1 p(O)) satisfies the rules at each t. lf(x) - f(x')l ;'i; Klx - x'l,
It would be very awkward if for given initial conditions there were a where K is a constant independent of x.
270 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 271

The difficulty we have been discussing also can be overcome by Since it is bounded we know from elementary analysis that there
modifying the auctioneer's rules. For instance, Nikaido and Uzawa must be a convergent subsequence, p(tr-)---+ p*, say. Hence the
[1 960] ha ve suggested the following rule: solution path has at least one limit point.
Pt = max[kz(p) + p,O] - Pt i=1, ... ,n THEOREM 2. Let p(t p(O)) 1 ->- p* as t---+ +oo. Then p* is an
equilibrium of the economy.
where k > O and depends on p(O). Certainly, Pt = O and z(p) < O
now gives Pt = O. Also, kz(p) + Pt :s; O leads to Pt = -p for Proof. Suppose not, so that p* is not an equilibrium. This by
Pt > O. It is easy to check that no discontinuity occurs at Pt = O. D.2.l(E) means that for sorne i, Z(p*) > O. Write G(Z(p)) = g(p)
The continuity of z(p) over the simplex and standard theorems then and note that, by assumption, g(p*) > O. We now show that this
allows us to prove for this process what A. 11.3 assumes. This is leads to a contradiction.
satisfactory, but the result is bought at the cost of an ad hoc postula te By the continuity of G and Z, say,
that is not easily made economically persuasive. lim g(p(t)) = g(lim p(t)) = g(p*) = g[.
Another possibility, not noted in the literature, is the following t-"oo t-too

adjustment rule: Since g(.) is convergent, we may choose " > O and small enough to
Pt = max[pZ(p),z(p)] i=1, ... ,n. ensure g[ - E > O and such that for t large enough,

Then for Pt close to zero and Z(p) < O, Pt = pZ(p) and there is no lg(p(f)) - gfl < E

discontinuity at Pt = O. Once again we may establish A.ll.3 as a or


proposition, but as before, there is not much to recommend this
particular rule.
g(p(t)) > gf - E.

In the analysis of the behavior of prices in the large, we shall But jJ 1(t) = g(p(t)), whence
require the solution p(t p(O)) to be bounded. In a numbe~ of cases
1

this can be proved to be the case. For others, we may wish to


PtCt) > it - E.

suppose that the adjustment rule obeys this requirement. For ease For t large and t' > t, integrating the above expression from t to t'
i
ji: of reference, we now state this as an assumption, but we will show yields
why it is satisfied in specific cases in the following chapter. p 1(t') > p(t) + (g[ - e)(t' - t).

AssuMPTION 4. For all admissible p(O), the solution p(t 1 p(O)) is For our choice of E, then, it must be that as t'---+ +oo, p 1(t')---+ +oo,
bounded. which contradicts the convergence of p(t) to a finite limit. Hence
g(p*) ::;; O, all i, and p* is an equilibrium.
We have shown that if p(t p(O)) converges-to p*, then p* is an
1

4. Sorne Basic Results equilibrium. It will be useful to have the following definition.
In this section, we shall repeat a number of mathematical results DEFINITION 2. The auctioneer's rule will be called globally stable if
i!
for every p(O) > O, the solution p(t 1 p(O)) approaches an equilibrium.
1

that we shall need in the next chapter to investigate the behavior


over time of the prices that result from a tat6nnement.
'
If a solution p(t 1 p(O)) is convergent, say to p*, then of course p*
Let us start our investigation with an arbitrary p(O) > O and
is the only limit point of that solution. On the other hand, since
stipulate A.ll.l, A.ll.3, and A.ll.4. We have a unique solution
there are many different solution paths, depending on the choice of
path:
initial conditions, there may be many limit points to the paths
p(t) = p(t 1 p(O)). generated by the auctioneer's rule (differential equations). All we
270 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 271

The difficulty we have been discussing also can be overcome by Since it is bounded we know from elementary analysis that there
modifying the auctioneer's rules. For instance, Nikaido and Uzawa must be a convergent subsequence, p(tr-)---+ p*, say. Hence the
[1 960] ha ve suggested the following rule: solution path has at least one limit point.
Pt = max[kz(p) + p,O] - Pt i=1, ... ,n THEOREM 2. Let p(t p(O)) 1 ->- p* as t---+ +oo. Then p* is an
equilibrium of the economy.
where k > O and depends on p(O). Certainly, Pt = O and z(p) < O
now gives Pt = O. Also, kz(p) + Pt :s; O leads to Pt = -p for Proof. Suppose not, so that p* is not an equilibrium. This by
Pt > O. It is easy to check that no discontinuity occurs at Pt = O. D.2.l(E) means that for sorne i, Z(p*) > O. Write G(Z(p)) = g(p)
The continuity of z(p) over the simplex and standard theorems then and note that, by assumption, g(p*) > O. We now show that this
allows us to prove for this process what A. 11.3 assumes. This is leads to a contradiction.
satisfactory, but the result is bought at the cost of an ad hoc postula te By the continuity of G and Z, say,
that is not easily made economically persuasive. lim g(p(t)) = g(lim p(t)) = g(p*) = g[.
Another possibility, not noted in the literature, is the following t-"oo t-too

adjustment rule: Since g(.) is convergent, we may choose " > O and small enough to
Pt = max[pZ(p),z(p)] i=1, ... ,n. ensure g[ - E > O and such that for t large enough,

Then for Pt close to zero and Z(p) < O, Pt = pZ(p) and there is no lg(p(f)) - gfl < E

discontinuity at Pt = O. Once again we may establish A.ll.3 as a or


proposition, but as before, there is not much to recommend this
particular rule.
g(p(t)) > gf - E.

In the analysis of the behavior of prices in the large, we shall But jJ 1(t) = g(p(t)), whence
require the solution p(t p(O)) to be bounded. In a numbe~ of cases
1

this can be proved to be the case. For others, we may wish to


PtCt) > it - E.

suppose that the adjustment rule obeys this requirement. For ease For t large and t' > t, integrating the above expression from t to t'
i
ji: of reference, we now state this as an assumption, but we will show yields
why it is satisfied in specific cases in the following chapter. p 1(t') > p(t) + (g[ - e)(t' - t).

AssuMPTION 4. For all admissible p(O), the solution p(t 1 p(O)) is For our choice of E, then, it must be that as t'---+ +oo, p 1(t')---+ +oo,
bounded. which contradicts the convergence of p(t) to a finite limit. Hence
g(p*) ::;; O, all i, and p* is an equilibrium.
We have shown that if p(t p(O)) converges-to p*, then p* is an
1

4. Sorne Basic Results equilibrium. It will be useful to have the following definition.
In this section, we shall repeat a number of mathematical results DEFINITION 2. The auctioneer's rule will be called globally stable if
i!
for every p(O) > O, the solution p(t 1 p(O)) approaches an equilibrium.
1

that we shall need in the next chapter to investigate the behavior


over time of the prices that result from a tat6nnement.
'
If a solution p(t 1 p(O)) is convergent, say to p*, then of course p*
Let us start our investigation with an arbitrary p(O) > O and
is the only limit point of that solution. On the other hand, since
stipulate A.ll.l, A.ll.3, and A.ll.4. We have a unique solution
there are many different solution paths, depending on the choice of
path:
initial conditions, there may be many limit points to the paths
p(t) = p(t 1 p(O)). generated by the auctioneer's rule (differential equations). All we
272 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 273

can deduce from the information that the rule is globally stable is so that
that every possible path will approach one ofthese points. However
it may happen, for instance, when equilibrium for the economy is
p(O) = p(t1 1 p0 ).

unique, that if al! solutions converge, they must converge to the same Since the path is uniquely defined by p0 , p(t) must be the same
limit point-the unique equilibrium. This leads to the following. whether we take p0 or p(O) as our initial condition, since p('t) is
another unique path emanating from p0 . Hence
DEFINITION 3. If the rule followed by the auctioneer is globally
stable and if the economy possesses a unique equilibrium, then that p(t + tl 1 P0 ) = p(t 1 p(tl 1 P0 )).
equilibrium is called global/y stable.
Applying t,his to the limit path,
If the economy possesses more than one equilibrium then no
equilibrium can be globally stable. p*(t) = p(t p*) 1

Since the equations we are dealing with are non-linear and their = p[t lim p(tA p(O))]
1 1
A_,"'
number is large we shall not expect to be able to answer the question,
= lim p[t p(tA p(O))] 1 1
"Are they globally stable?" by explicitly solving them, nor would A_,"'
that be a pleasant task to attempt if it is possible. Fortunately, we = lim p(t
il->"'
+ tA 1 p(O)),
can often answer a qualitative question of this type, without actually
solving the equations. To this matter we now turn. so that every point of p*(t) is a limit point of p(t p(O)). 1

Suppose that we can find a continuous function of p(t), V[p(t)], Now by A.ll.4, the path p(t p(O)) is bounded so, since V() is
1

which has the property that it converges for every path p(t) can take taken as continuous, it too is bounded. By assumption, it con-
and is constant along the path p(t 1 p(O)) if and only if p(O) is an verges and so
equilibrium. The question is whether the existence of such a lim V[p(t 1 p(O))] = lim V[p(t + til 1 p(O))]
function together with the boundedness of all the paths of prices t->"' il->"'

would be sufficient to allow us to deduce the global stability of the = v[;~~ p(t + ril 1 p(O)) J
rules. We shall find that the answer is "almost" in the affirmative.
= V[p(t p*)]. 1
We say "almost" because without one further assumption only a
weaker proposition than global stability can be established. Let us lt follows that V[p(t p*)] is a constant; from the assumed proper-
1

see how far we can go. ties of V, it follows that p* is an equilibrium, and this for every limit
Since p(t) is bounded, it has a converging subsequence and we may !
point p*. Hence, if a function V() as specified can be found, every 1

write limit point of every solution path is an equilibrium, or to put it r

i
lim p(til) = p*. differently, every solution path converges tq the set of equilibria. i
il->"' Let us state this formally. 1:
Consider the solution path
DEFINITION 4. A function V(p) that is continuous in its arguments
p*(t) = p(t p*).
1
and such that V[p(t p(O))] converges for al! admissible p(O) and is
1

On this path we take a limit point ofp(t p(O)) as Our initial condition.
1 constant if and only if p(O) is an equilibrium is called a Lyapounov
We show that all points on this path are Iimit points of p(t 1 p(O)), so function.
that the path is wellnamed as a limit path.
THEOREM 3. If the rules of A. 11.1 or A.11.2, that is, the differential
Now, by A.ll.3(a), every path is a unique function of its starting
equations defined by it, allow the existence of a Lyapounov function
point. Let p 0 be such a point and consider
and if A.11.3 and A.11.4 hold, then every solution path of prices
p(f) = p(f + f1 1 p0 ) approaches arbitrarily close to the set of equilibria of the economy.
272 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 273

can deduce from the information that the rule is globally stable is so that
that every possible path will approach one ofthese points. However
it may happen, for instance, when equilibrium for the economy is
p(O) = p(t1 1 p0 ).

unique, that if al! solutions converge, they must converge to the same Since the path is uniquely defined by p0 , p(t) must be the same
limit point-the unique equilibrium. This leads to the following. whether we take p0 or p(O) as our initial condition, since p('t) is
another unique path emanating from p0 . Hence
DEFINITION 3. If the rule followed by the auctioneer is globally
stable and if the economy possesses a unique equilibrium, then that p(t + tl 1 P0 ) = p(t 1 p(tl 1 P0 )).
equilibrium is called global/y stable.
Applying t,his to the limit path,
If the economy possesses more than one equilibrium then no
equilibrium can be globally stable. p*(t) = p(t p*) 1

Since the equations we are dealing with are non-linear and their = p[t lim p(tA p(O))]
1 1
A_,"'
number is large we shall not expect to be able to answer the question,
= lim p[t p(tA p(O))] 1 1
"Are they globally stable?" by explicitly solving them, nor would A_,"'
that be a pleasant task to attempt if it is possible. Fortunately, we = lim p(t
il->"'
+ tA 1 p(O)),
can often answer a qualitative question of this type, without actually
solving the equations. To this matter we now turn. so that every point of p*(t) is a limit point of p(t p(O)). 1

Suppose that we can find a continuous function of p(t), V[p(t)], Now by A.ll.4, the path p(t p(O)) is bounded so, since V() is
1

which has the property that it converges for every path p(t) can take taken as continuous, it too is bounded. By assumption, it con-
and is constant along the path p(t 1 p(O)) if and only if p(O) is an verges and so
equilibrium. The question is whether the existence of such a lim V[p(t 1 p(O))] = lim V[p(t + til 1 p(O))]
function together with the boundedness of all the paths of prices t->"' il->"'

would be sufficient to allow us to deduce the global stability of the = v[;~~ p(t + ril 1 p(O)) J
rules. We shall find that the answer is "almost" in the affirmative.
= V[p(t p*)]. 1
We say "almost" because without one further assumption only a
weaker proposition than global stability can be established. Let us lt follows that V[p(t p*)] is a constant; from the assumed proper-
1

see how far we can go. ties of V, it follows that p* is an equilibrium, and this for every limit
Since p(t) is bounded, it has a converging subsequence and we may !
point p*. Hence, if a function V() as specified can be found, every 1

write limit point of every solution path is an equilibrium, or to put it r

i
lim p(til) = p*. differently, every solution path converges tq the set of equilibria. i
il->"' Let us state this formally. 1:
Consider the solution path
DEFINITION 4. A function V(p) that is continuous in its arguments
p*(t) = p(t p*).
1
and such that V[p(t p(O))] converges for al! admissible p(O) and is
1

On this path we take a limit point ofp(t p(O)) as Our initial condition.
1 constant if and only if p(O) is an equilibrium is called a Lyapounov
We show that all points on this path are Iimit points of p(t 1 p(O)), so function.
that the path is wellnamed as a limit path.
THEOREM 3. If the rules of A. 11.1 or A.11.2, that is, the differential
Now, by A.ll.3(a), every path is a unique function of its starting
equations defined by it, allow the existence of a Lyapounov function
point. Let p 0 be such a point and consider
and if A.11.3 and A.11.4 hold, then every solution path of prices
p(f) = p(f + f1 1 p0 ) approaches arbitrarily close to the set of equilibria of the economy.
1 1

274 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 275

DEFINITION 5. A set of differential equations that satisfy T.l1.3 is p(tf) converging on sorne limit point p***, which lies on the border
called quasi-globally stable. of N(p*). This contradicts the supposition that p* was an isolated
limit point. Therefore, we have proved
We see that we have finished up with quasi-global stability instead
of with global stability. What that means is that so far, while we THEOREM 4. lf the set of limit points of a solution path contains
can predict that after a sufficiently long lapse of time prices will be more than one point, then these points canno.t be isolated.
arbitrarily close to sorne equilibrium, we cannot pick out any par- Corollary 4. If the equilibria of the economy are isolated in a
ticular equilibrium for which this is true. This is better, indeed a g'iven region and the conditions of T.11.3 hold, then the rule A.ll.l
good deal better, than nothing, yet we may choose to be more (or A.l1.2) is globally stable.
ambitious.
If there exist only two equilibrium points, say p* and p**, then Proof If the set of limit points of a path p(t 1 p(O)) had more than
since any particular solution path gets arbitrarily close to this path, one member, the set would not be isolated, by T.11.4. But by
it must be arbitrarily close to one of these points or it must be close T.ll.3, every limit point is an equilibrium, so that the set of equilibria
to one of them at one moment and close to the other at the next. would not be isolated, contrary to assumption.
Is this last, in fact, a possibility? 1t would appear that, unless Corollary 4'. lf the conditions of T.ll.3 hold and the economy
something more is said, the path while in transit from one of these has a unique equilibrium, then that equilibrium is globally stable.
points to the other will not be el ose to either of them and this would
lead to a contradiction of the theorem. Evidently this difficulty can Since we know quite a bit about the uniqueness of equilibrium of
be avoided if we say that p* and p** are arbitrarily close to each a competitive economy (see Chapter 9), the result we have just
other; that is, any small neighborhood of one also contains the other. established should prove useful in an analysis of a tatonnement. Of
Then by the same token, iftheequilibria ofthe economy do not satisfy course, a good deal still depends on finding a suitable Lyapounov
this further restriction, that is, if on sorne measure of distance they function in each of the cases we propose to investigate. Yet it is
are a finite distance apart, we can take it that our theorem establishes sometimes true that this function, and indeed the auctioneer's rule,
the stronger results, namely that every solution path converges on to arises quite naturally from the problem itself. A consideration of '1
an eqllilibrium. Let liS make these ideas more precise. this class of cases will serve not only to illuminate the discussion up
Let N(p*) be a closed neighborhood of p* and N(p**) a closed to this point, but it also holds an economic lesson that we ought
neighborhood of p** (where p* and p** are limit points of sorne to learn before we plunge into the particular details of the
path). We are to suppose that it is possible to find such neighbor- tatonnement process.
hoods with the property that no eqllilibrium other than p** belongs
to N(p**) and no equilibrium other than p* belongs to N(p*). (p*
5. An Example: The Gradient Method
and p** are said to be isolated.) Then we can certainly find neigh-
borhoods such that N(p*) and N(p**) have no point in common, and Let liS considera Hicksian economy, which we know (Section 9.6)
we suppose that done. Now p(t) for t arbitrarily large must lie in may be treated as if it consisted of a single hollsehold. Let this
N(p*), for by definition, there is a seqllence of points on the path hollsehold have a strictly qllasi-concave lltility fllnction U(x). We
such that for t large enough it has points close to p*. By the same postlllate a pure-exchange economy with endowment vector x > O,
argument, for t' arbitrarily large, p(t') must lie in N(p**). Then for In reality, if there were only one hollsehold, the economy wollld
so me t * sllch that t < t * < t ', p(t *) mllst be on the bollndary of the always be in eqllilibrillm. As it is, the fictional hollsehold maxi-
closed neighborhood of N(p*). Clearly, we may make t* as large mizes U(x) Sllbject to p(x - x) = 0, (rather than sllbject to x s x), '
as we like since we may make t as large as we like. Also, the where p is the price vector called by the allctioneer. i:!
bollndary of N(p*) is bollnded. Hence there is a seqllence of point We know that this economy has a llniqlle eqllilibrillm p* and that 1,.'';
!
'1
1

i' 1

li

1,:'
11

il
li
l 1
.. ......,,.1
1 1

274 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 275

DEFINITION 5. A set of differential equations that satisfy T.l1.3 is p(tf) converging on sorne limit point p***, which lies on the border
called quasi-globally stable. of N(p*). This contradicts the supposition that p* was an isolated
limit point. Therefore, we have proved
We see that we have finished up with quasi-global stability instead
of with global stability. What that means is that so far, while we THEOREM 4. lf the set of limit points of a solution path contains
can predict that after a sufficiently long lapse of time prices will be more than one point, then these points canno.t be isolated.
arbitrarily close to sorne equilibrium, we cannot pick out any par- Corollary 4. If the equilibria of the economy are isolated in a
ticular equilibrium for which this is true. This is better, indeed a g'iven region and the conditions of T.11.3 hold, then the rule A.ll.l
good deal better, than nothing, yet we may choose to be more (or A.l1.2) is globally stable.
ambitious.
If there exist only two equilibrium points, say p* and p**, then Proof If the set of limit points of a path p(t 1 p(O)) had more than
since any particular solution path gets arbitrarily close to this path, one member, the set would not be isolated, by T.11.4. But by
it must be arbitrarily close to one of these points or it must be close T.ll.3, every limit point is an equilibrium, so that the set of equilibria
to one of them at one moment and close to the other at the next. would not be isolated, contrary to assumption.
Is this last, in fact, a possibility? 1t would appear that, unless Corollary 4'. lf the conditions of T.ll.3 hold and the economy
something more is said, the path while in transit from one of these has a unique equilibrium, then that equilibrium is globally stable.
points to the other will not be el ose to either of them and this would
lead to a contradiction of the theorem. Evidently this difficulty can Since we know quite a bit about the uniqueness of equilibrium of
be avoided if we say that p* and p** are arbitrarily close to each a competitive economy (see Chapter 9), the result we have just
other; that is, any small neighborhood of one also contains the other. established should prove useful in an analysis of a tatonnement. Of
Then by the same token, iftheequilibria ofthe economy do not satisfy course, a good deal still depends on finding a suitable Lyapounov
this further restriction, that is, if on sorne measure of distance they function in each of the cases we propose to investigate. Yet it is
are a finite distance apart, we can take it that our theorem establishes sometimes true that this function, and indeed the auctioneer's rule,
the stronger results, namely that every solution path converges on to arises quite naturally from the problem itself. A consideration of '1
an eqllilibrium. Let liS make these ideas more precise. this class of cases will serve not only to illuminate the discussion up
Let N(p*) be a closed neighborhood of p* and N(p**) a closed to this point, but it also holds an economic lesson that we ought
neighborhood of p** (where p* and p** are limit points of sorne to learn before we plunge into the particular details of the
path). We are to suppose that it is possible to find such neighbor- tatonnement process.
hoods with the property that no eqllilibrium other than p** belongs
to N(p**) and no equilibrium other than p* belongs to N(p*). (p*
5. An Example: The Gradient Method
and p** are said to be isolated.) Then we can certainly find neigh-
borhoods such that N(p*) and N(p**) have no point in common, and Let liS considera Hicksian economy, which we know (Section 9.6)
we suppose that done. Now p(t) for t arbitrarily large must lie in may be treated as if it consisted of a single hollsehold. Let this
N(p*), for by definition, there is a seqllence of points on the path hollsehold have a strictly qllasi-concave lltility fllnction U(x). We
such that for t large enough it has points close to p*. By the same postlllate a pure-exchange economy with endowment vector x > O,
argument, for t' arbitrarily large, p(t') must lie in N(p**). Then for In reality, if there were only one hollsehold, the economy wollld
so me t * sllch that t < t * < t ', p(t *) mllst be on the bollndary of the always be in eqllilibrillm. As it is, the fictional hollsehold maxi-
closed neighborhood of N(p*). Clearly, we may make t* as large mizes U(x) Sllbject to p(x - x) = 0, (rather than sllbject to x s x), '
as we like since we may make t as large as we like. Also, the where p is the price vector called by the allctioneer. i:!
bollndary of N(p*) is bollnded. Hence there is a seqllence of point We know that this economy has a llniqlle eqllilibrillm p* and that 1,.'';
!
'1
1

i' 1

li

1,:'
11

il
li
l 1
.. ......,,.1
276 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 277

the dernand vector is a function, x(p), (rather than a correspondence) prices the auctioneer calls converge to their unique equilibriurn value
of p. However, since px(p) = px 2 px(p*), provided the solution path is bounded (see below).
, What the auctioneer is doing in this exarnple is following an itera-
U[x(p)] > U[x(p*)] all p .., p*.
tive procedure for rninirnizing V(p). He does this by rnaking sure
In what follows, we write V(p) = U[x(p)], and taking U as differen- that he is always changing p in su eh a way as to be going "downhill";
tiable, we note that in fact, he is following a gradient rnethod for rninirnizing a function.

8V>)
ap,,
= V,,(p) = ; (8U) (8x
8x op,,
1) = _'Y (8U) (8s1 )
7 ox1 opk
DEFINITION 6. The gradient method of rninirnizing a differentiable
1 1 function .f(y) (where y is a vector) over a cornpact set is the rule:
where s1(p) is the excess supply of goods. sign J\ = - sign 8fj8y1 (if two nurnbers are zero they ha ve both the
For suitable .\, 8Uj8x1 -.\p1 ::::; O; if the strict inequality holds, sarne and opposite sign). If y 2 O is a requirernent of the problern,
x(p) = O and indeed remains O for srnall changes in p 1" so that we add y 1 = O if y 1 = O and 8fj!y1 > O.
8stf8p 1, = O if 8Uj!s1 - /p1 < O. Therefore, lt is for the reader to state the gradient rnethod for rnaxirnizing.f(y).
As another exarnple, take .f(y) as a strictly concave function that
we seek to rnaximize on a compact set; we do not preclude y1 < O,
sorne i. If we follow the gradient method, say y1 = w1[/;(y)], where
Sin ce w1 is sign preserving and w1(0) = 0,/;(y) = 8f(y)j8y, we have

dfdJ) = ;;(y)w[/;(y)]
i
we see, by differentiation with respect to PJ<, that
and this expression will be positive unless all the partial derivatives
of .f(y) vanish. Since .f(y) is strictly concave, it has a unique rnaxi-
rnurn, and if we suppose this to occur at y*, which is notan extreme
or point of the set of possible y, it is clear that we may treat .f(y) as a
,\>o Lyapounov function and that the gradient method will generate a
path for y, the limit point of which is y*.
where s1,(p) i's the excess supply of good k at p. (If p 1, = O, this is Jt should be noted now that in both the present exarnple and the
to be taken as the right-hand derivative.) previous exarnple, we had to make sure that a maximum or mini-
Assume that the auctioneer does not know p*, but he does know mum existed for the function we were interested in, which we did by
that if p is not an equilibrium, V(p) > V(p*) and V1c(p) < O, sorne taking it over a compact set, and that it was extremely useful to take
k. On the other hand, V,c(p) 2 O, all k, p 1,V1c(p) = O, al! k, if and this maximum as unique, which we accomplished in the present
only if p is an equilibrium. Accordingly, he argues as follows: If I example by making the function strictly concave and in the earlier
follow the rule example by taking U(x) strictly quasi,concave. Granted, it is
pretty clear that the gradierit rnethod in the last example will take us
A = - V,,(p), all k, unless PI< = O, Vk(p) > O, when A = O, to a point at which all the derivatives vanish (ignoring complications
then 1 will ensure that V(p) is declining as a function of time. This with corners). Of cotll'Se, this may be a mnimum of .f(y) or a local
can mean only that V(p) is getting nearer to its lower bound, which, maximum only. lf we can take .f(y) as concave, although not strictly
wherever it is, will be at an equilibriurn p. Since, on the above rule, concave, then we can avoid difficulty-every y for which the deriva-
V(p) acts like a Lyapounov function, the rule will indeed make the tives vanish is a maxirnum of the function. Now there may be
276 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 277

the dernand vector is a function, x(p), (rather than a correspondence) prices the auctioneer calls converge to their unique equilibriurn value
of p. However, since px(p) = px 2 px(p*), provided the solution path is bounded (see below).
, What the auctioneer is doing in this exarnple is following an itera-
U[x(p)] > U[x(p*)] all p .., p*.
tive procedure for rninirnizing V(p). He does this by rnaking sure
In what follows, we write V(p) = U[x(p)], and taking U as differen- that he is always changing p in su eh a way as to be going "downhill";
tiable, we note that in fact, he is following a gradient rnethod for rninirnizing a function.

8V>)
ap,,
= V,,(p) = ; (8U) (8x
8x op,,
1) = _'Y (8U) (8s1 )
7 ox1 opk
DEFINITION 6. The gradient method of rninirnizing a differentiable
1 1 function .f(y) (where y is a vector) over a cornpact set is the rule:
where s1(p) is the excess supply of goods. sign J\ = - sign 8fj8y1 (if two nurnbers are zero they ha ve both the
For suitable .\, 8Uj8x1 -.\p1 ::::; O; if the strict inequality holds, sarne and opposite sign). If y 2 O is a requirernent of the problern,
x(p) = O and indeed remains O for srnall changes in p 1" so that we add y 1 = O if y 1 = O and 8fj!y1 > O.
8stf8p 1, = O if 8Uj!s1 - /p1 < O. Therefore, lt is for the reader to state the gradient rnethod for rnaxirnizing.f(y).
As another exarnple, take .f(y) as a strictly concave function that
we seek to rnaximize on a compact set; we do not preclude y1 < O,
sorne i. If we follow the gradient method, say y1 = w1[/;(y)], where
Sin ce w1 is sign preserving and w1(0) = 0,/;(y) = 8f(y)j8y, we have

dfdJ) = ;;(y)w[/;(y)]
i
we see, by differentiation with respect to PJ<, that
and this expression will be positive unless all the partial derivatives
of .f(y) vanish. Since .f(y) is strictly concave, it has a unique rnaxi-
rnurn, and if we suppose this to occur at y*, which is notan extreme
or point of the set of possible y, it is clear that we may treat .f(y) as a
,\>o Lyapounov function and that the gradient method will generate a
path for y, the limit point of which is y*.
where s1,(p) i's the excess supply of good k at p. (If p 1, = O, this is Jt should be noted now that in both the present exarnple and the
to be taken as the right-hand derivative.) previous exarnple, we had to make sure that a maximum or mini-
Assume that the auctioneer does not know p*, but he does know mum existed for the function we were interested in, which we did by
that if p is not an equilibrium, V(p) > V(p*) and V1c(p) < O, sorne taking it over a compact set, and that it was extremely useful to take
k. On the other hand, V,c(p) 2 O, all k, p 1,V1c(p) = O, al! k, if and this maximum as unique, which we accomplished in the present
only if p is an equilibrium. Accordingly, he argues as follows: If I example by making the function strictly concave and in the earlier
follow the rule example by taking U(x) strictly quasi,concave. Granted, it is
pretty clear that the gradierit rnethod in the last example will take us
A = - V,,(p), all k, unless PI< = O, Vk(p) > O, when A = O, to a point at which all the derivatives vanish (ignoring complications
then 1 will ensure that V(p) is declining as a function of time. This with corners). Of cotll'Se, this may be a mnimum of .f(y) or a local
can mean only that V(p) is getting nearer to its lower bound, which, maximum only. lf we can take .f(y) as concave, although not strictly
wherever it is, will be at an equilibriurn p. Since, on the above rule, concave, then we can avoid difficulty-every y for which the deriva-
V(p) acts like a Lyapounov function, the rule will indeed make the tives vanish is a maxirnum of the function. Now there may be
278. GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1 INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 279

other maxima. lf these are isolated, we know that nonetheless the path of prices two possibilities arise: If p(O) is in the interior of the
method will drive us toward sorne particular maximum. specified neighborhood, it is true either that for all t, p(t 1 p(O)) will
All this has important lessons for anyone interested in the behavior always remain in the neighborhood or that p(t 1 p(O)) may leave the
of a tatonnement. If the auctioneer's rule may be treated as an neighborhood at sorne t. Evidently, in the second case we cannot
intelligent method of maximizing or minimizing sorne relevant stick to our resolution of examining the small neighborhood only,
function, then if such a function is well behaved in the sense just simply because we shall find that our quarry has left it at sorne
discussed, we should expect the rule to exhibit global stability. moment. Thus we cannot even be certain that p willnot, for sorne
Unfortunately, however, except in exceptional circumstances of stilllarger t, re-enter our neighborhood unless we look to see what
which the Hicksian is one instance, the price mechanism cannot be goes on outside it. In the first case, however, we can be thoroughly
taken to act as if someone were trying to maximize or minimize sorne provincial and never consider what the world looks like outside the
well-behaved function ofprices. ltis true that we should expect "it" vicinity of the equilibrium.
to recognize a situation that is not maximal in the sense that sorne
housebold can be made better off without another one being made DEFINITION 7. Let p* be an equilibrium. We say that it is stable in
worse off, for we know that such a situation cannot be an equi- the sense of Lyapounov if for every 8 there is an E such that, if
librium and we ha ve so arranged matters that prices change when the lp(O) - p* 1 < E, it is true also that lp(t 1 p(O)) - p* 1 < 8, all t ~ O.
economy is out of equilibrium. But being able to recognize that a
As we have already noted, we shall expect to be able to concentrate
function is not maximal at certain values of its arguments does not
on the behavior of a tatonnement in some neighborhood of an equi-
yet mean that we have a function of the kind for which the price
librium only if that equilibrium is stable in the sense of Lyapounov.
mechanism is the appropriate gradient method or that this method
will indeed be appropriate. We shall take up this point again in the DEFINITION 8. An equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable, if all
next chapter. paths starting in a close neighborhood converge to the equilibrium
and the equilibrium is stable in the sense of Lyapounov.
6. Local Stability
The idea ofthis definition is obvious. We impose the requirement
We conclude this preliminary discussion of methods by noting that the equilibrium must be stable since without it we cannot rely
that the requirement of global stability is extremely ambitious. on the "local" properties of the functions under investigation. But
For instance, when we consider a sequence of short-run equilibria suppose that, while equilibrium is stable in the sen se of D.ll. 7, the
in which expectations play an enormous role, we should certainly be equilibrium is not locally asymptotically stable. We may conclude,
surprised to hear that the system returns equally smoothly to an evidently, that it is not globally stable either. Thus, while an
equilibrium after, say, the burning down of one factory and after analysis of local properties cannot establish global stability, it can
half the factories have burned. Somehow we cannot help feeling establish a negative proposition of the kind just stated. In the next
that large shocks to a system will have to be treated in a qualitatively chapter we shall use this device to settle an important question.
different way than small ones. This feeling m~y turn out to be If we make enough stability demands on a system, it can easily be
based on misconceptions and we shall examine this again much later. seen that the system must have a unique equilibrium. Specifically,
Here we shall lay down rather obvious points concerning the more if we require global stability of the auctioneer's rule and also local
modest scheme of considering small deviations from equilibrium. asymptotic stability of every equilibrium, there can be only one such.
If we have chosen some appropriate measure of distance, say For illustration, consider the familiar case of two commodities. As
[2: (p 1 - pf) 2 ]1 12 , where p* is an equilibrium, and wish to utilize the will be shown later (T.l2.1), the system is always globally stable in
properties of the excess-demand functions known to hold in some that case; that is, the path starting from any initial set of prices
appropriate neighborhood of equilibrium in the examination of the always converges to sorne equilibrium. Then, as is well known
278. GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
1 INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 279

other maxima. lf these are isolated, we know that nonetheless the path of prices two possibilities arise: If p(O) is in the interior of the
method will drive us toward sorne particular maximum. specified neighborhood, it is true either that for all t, p(t 1 p(O)) will
All this has important lessons for anyone interested in the behavior always remain in the neighborhood or that p(t 1 p(O)) may leave the
of a tatonnement. If the auctioneer's rule may be treated as an neighborhood at sorne t. Evidently, in the second case we cannot
intelligent method of maximizing or minimizing sorne relevant stick to our resolution of examining the small neighborhood only,
function, then if such a function is well behaved in the sense just simply because we shall find that our quarry has left it at sorne
discussed, we should expect the rule to exhibit global stability. moment. Thus we cannot even be certain that p willnot, for sorne
Unfortunately, however, except in exceptional circumstances of stilllarger t, re-enter our neighborhood unless we look to see what
which the Hicksian is one instance, the price mechanism cannot be goes on outside it. In the first case, however, we can be thoroughly
taken to act as if someone were trying to maximize or minimize sorne provincial and never consider what the world looks like outside the
well-behaved function ofprices. ltis true that we should expect "it" vicinity of the equilibrium.
to recognize a situation that is not maximal in the sense that sorne
housebold can be made better off without another one being made DEFINITION 7. Let p* be an equilibrium. We say that it is stable in
worse off, for we know that such a situation cannot be an equi- the sense of Lyapounov if for every 8 there is an E such that, if
librium and we ha ve so arranged matters that prices change when the lp(O) - p* 1 < E, it is true also that lp(t 1 p(O)) - p* 1 < 8, all t ~ O.
economy is out of equilibrium. But being able to recognize that a
As we have already noted, we shall expect to be able to concentrate
function is not maximal at certain values of its arguments does not
on the behavior of a tatonnement in some neighborhood of an equi-
yet mean that we have a function of the kind for which the price
librium only if that equilibrium is stable in the sense of Lyapounov.
mechanism is the appropriate gradient method or that this method
will indeed be appropriate. We shall take up this point again in the DEFINITION 8. An equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable, if all
next chapter. paths starting in a close neighborhood converge to the equilibrium
and the equilibrium is stable in the sense of Lyapounov.
6. Local Stability
The idea ofthis definition is obvious. We impose the requirement
We conclude this preliminary discussion of methods by noting that the equilibrium must be stable since without it we cannot rely
that the requirement of global stability is extremely ambitious. on the "local" properties of the functions under investigation. But
For instance, when we consider a sequence of short-run equilibria suppose that, while equilibrium is stable in the sen se of D.ll. 7, the
in which expectations play an enormous role, we should certainly be equilibrium is not locally asymptotically stable. We may conclude,
surprised to hear that the system returns equally smoothly to an evidently, that it is not globally stable either. Thus, while an
equilibrium after, say, the burning down of one factory and after analysis of local properties cannot establish global stability, it can
half the factories have burned. Somehow we cannot help feeling establish a negative proposition of the kind just stated. In the next
that large shocks to a system will have to be treated in a qualitatively chapter we shall use this device to settle an important question.
different way than small ones. This feeling m~y turn out to be If we make enough stability demands on a system, it can easily be
based on misconceptions and we shall examine this again much later. seen that the system must have a unique equilibrium. Specifically,
Here we shall lay down rather obvious points concerning the more if we require global stability of the auctioneer's rule and also local
modest scheme of considering small deviations from equilibrium. asymptotic stability of every equilibrium, there can be only one such.
If we have chosen some appropriate measure of distance, say For illustration, consider the familiar case of two commodities. As
[2: (p 1 - pf) 2 ]1 12 , where p* is an equilibrium, and wish to utilize the will be shown later (T.l2.1), the system is always globally stable in
properties of the excess-demand functions known to hold in some that case; that is, the path starting from any initial set of prices
appropriate neighborhood of equilibrium in the examination of the always converges to sorne equilibrium. Then, as is well known
280 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
'(.

INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 281

since the days of Marshall, there will be alternating stable and its minimum unit cost. In the meantime, the auctioneer raises the
1
unstable equilibria. 1

price of every good for which unit cost exceeds its price unless he has
been informed that there is a zero demand for the good. In all
THEOREM 5. If the auctioneer's rule is globally stable and every
cases, he will lower the price of a good if that price exceeds its
equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable and if A.ll.3 holds, then
equilibrium is unique. minimum unit cost. Formally:
AssUMPTION 5. Let the economy produce everywhere under con-
Proof Since each equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable,
stant returns to scale. Let x(p) be the demand for a produced
each is surrounded by a neighborhood containing no other equilibria.
good, i, and Jet there be one non-produced good only with sub-
The set E of equilibria is then isolated and, therefore, finite.
script "0." Suppose that x(p) is a function. Then the auctioneer
Suppose there is more than one equilibrium. Let be a closed e follows the rule:
convex set containing more than one equilibrium, for example, a
line segment joining two equilibria. For any p* E E, let For all i t- O, jJ 1 =O if x 1(p) =O and p 1 < e1(p);
e(p*) = {po E e 1 p(t 1 Po)---',>- p*}, jJ 1 = H 1[C(p) - p] otherwise, where H 1( ) has the
same properties as the function G1( ) and F,( ),
e
in words, the set of points in from which solutins converge to p*. Po = O identically in t.
Since the rule is globally stable, every point of belongs to e(p*) e
for sorne p*; by A. 1 1.3(a), no point belongs to more than one such. A.11.5 is a numeraire process, and when we come to consider it,
It will be shown in Corollary B.ll that a convex set cannot be the we shall have to examine whether it indeed satisfies the requirements
union of two or more, but finitely many, disjoint non-null closed of such a process that the good chosen as numeraire always has a
sets. Hence, at least one of the non-null sets C(p*) is not closed; positive equilibrium price. We shall also have to see whether any
in other words, it has a limit point, p0 , not belonging to it. Since sensible rules can be found if there are severalnon-produced goods.
e is closed, p0 E e and so p0 E C(p**) for sorne p** i=' p*. By
D. 11 .8, there is a neighborhood N of p** such that p(t p1)---',>- p** 1
Notes
if p1 E N. Since p0 E C(p**), we can find t 1 so that p(t 1 1 p0 ) E N.
A well-known text for part of this chapter is E. A. Coddington and
By A.l1.3(b), p(t 1 p) is continuous in p; sin ce p0 is a limit point
1
N. Levinson [1955]. The Lyapounov method is described in J. LaSalle
of C(p*), we can find p00 E C(p*) such that p1 = p(t 1 1 p00 ) E N. and S. Lefschetz [1961] and in W. Hahn [1959]. The original Lyapounov
Then, for t > t1o p(t p00 ) = p(t- t 1 p1) ----i>- p**, a contradiction
1 1 paper appeared in translation in 1947.
since p00 E C(p*). The problems encountered by the requirement that prices must be
non-negative at all times have been discussed by H. Uzawa [1958] and
We shall use T. 1 1.5 to establish T.9.15; the argument will be M. Morishima [1959]. In a series of as yet unpublished papers C. Henry
completed in Section 12.8. of l'Ecole Polytechnique has investigated the solution of differential
equations whose trajectories must le in a closed convex set. This work
appeared too late to be noticed here, but it seems clear from it that A.11.3
1

7. The Auctioneer in a Constant-Returns Economy can be deduced as a theorem provided certain technical conditions are met
'11
i

r So far we ha ve taken it as given that F (see Chapter 2) is satisfied,


which, as we know, makes it hard to consideran economy in which
by the sign pre~erving functions G( ) and F( ).

r production is carried out under constant" returns to scale. lf the


minimum cost functions et(p) are well defined, however (see
Chapter 3), we could consider an alternative rule for the auctioneer
to follow. This time he will allow no transactions until the price of
every good planned for production in positive quantity just covers
280 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
'(.

INTRODUCTION TO STABILITY ANALYSIS 281

since the days of Marshall, there will be alternating stable and its minimum unit cost. In the meantime, the auctioneer raises the
1
unstable equilibria. 1

price of every good for which unit cost exceeds its price unless he has
been informed that there is a zero demand for the good. In all
THEOREM 5. If the auctioneer's rule is globally stable and every
cases, he will lower the price of a good if that price exceeds its
equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable and if A.ll.3 holds, then
equilibrium is unique. minimum unit cost. Formally:
AssUMPTION 5. Let the economy produce everywhere under con-
Proof Since each equilibrium is locally asymptotically stable,
stant returns to scale. Let x(p) be the demand for a produced
each is surrounded by a neighborhood containing no other equilibria.
good, i, and Jet there be one non-produced good only with sub-
The set E of equilibria is then isolated and, therefore, finite.
script "0." Suppose that x(p) is a function. Then the auctioneer
Suppose there is more than one equilibrium. Let be a closed e follows the rule:
convex set containing more than one equilibrium, for example, a
line segment joining two equilibria. For any p* E E, let For all i t- O, jJ 1 =O if x 1(p) =O and p 1 < e1(p);
e(p*) = {po E e 1 p(t 1 Po)---',>- p*}, jJ 1 = H 1[C(p) - p] otherwise, where H 1( ) has the
same properties as the function G1( ) and F,( ),
e
in words, the set of points in from which solutins converge to p*. Po = O identically in t.
Since the rule is globally stable, every point of belongs to e(p*) e
for sorne p*; by A. 1 1.3(a), no point belongs to more than one such. A.11.5 is a numeraire process, and when we come to consider it,
It will be shown in Corollary B.ll that a convex set cannot be the we shall have to examine whether it indeed satisfies the requirements
union of two or more, but finitely many, disjoint non-null closed of such a process that the good chosen as numeraire always has a
sets. Hence, at least one of the non-null sets C(p*) is not closed; positive equilibrium price. We shall also have to see whether any
in other words, it has a limit point, p0 , not belonging to it. Since sensible rules can be found if there are severalnon-produced goods.
e is closed, p0 E e and so p0 E C(p**) for sorne p** i=' p*. By
D. 11 .8, there is a neighborhood N of p** such that p(t p1)---',>- p** 1
Notes
if p1 E N. Since p0 E C(p**), we can find t 1 so that p(t 1 1 p0 ) E N.
A well-known text for part of this chapter is E. A. Coddington and
By A.l1.3(b), p(t 1 p) is continuous in p; sin ce p0 is a limit point
1
N. Levinson [1955]. The Lyapounov method is described in J. LaSalle
of C(p*), we can find p00 E C(p*) such that p1 = p(t 1 1 p00 ) E N. and S. Lefschetz [1961] and in W. Hahn [1959]. The original Lyapounov
Then, for t > t1o p(t p00 ) = p(t- t 1 p1) ----i>- p**, a contradiction
1 1 paper appeared in translation in 1947.
since p00 E C(p*). The problems encountered by the requirement that prices must be
non-negative at all times have been discussed by H. Uzawa [1958] and
We shall use T. 1 1.5 to establish T.9.15; the argument will be M. Morishima [1959]. In a series of as yet unpublished papers C. Henry
completed in Section 12.8. of l'Ecole Polytechnique has investigated the solution of differential
equations whose trajectories must le in a closed convex set. This work
appeared too late to be noticed here, but it seems clear from it that A.11.3
1

7. The Auctioneer in a Constant-Returns Economy can be deduced as a theorem provided certain technical conditions are met
'11
i

r So far we ha ve taken it as given that F (see Chapter 2) is satisfied,


which, as we know, makes it hard to consideran economy in which
by the sign pre~erving functions G( ) and F( ).

r production is carried out under constant" returns to scale. lf the


minimum cost functions et(p) are well defined, however (see
Chapter 3), we could consider an alternative rule for the auctioneer
to follow. This time he will allow no transactions until the price of
every good planned for production in positive quantity just covers
T
STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 283
Chapter Twelve
has engaged the most attention. The sequel will suggest that this is
STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING probably not sensible.
We prove the following, where we assume, as indeed we do else-
where in this chapter, that A.II.3 and A.ll.4 hold.
Turning and turning in the widening
gyre THEOREM l. Let a two-goods economy have isolated equilibria.
The falcon cannot hear the falconer. Then the rule A.ll.l is globally stable.
-W. B. Yeats, The Second Coming Proof. Consider p(O) E s2 (the two-dimensional simplex), E =
{p* 1 z(p*) :S: O, p* E S2}. Let p(O) $E and, without loss of
generality, take z 1 (p(O)) > O. By W, p 2 (0) > O and z 2 (p(O)) ::;; O.
Let p* E E and consider
1. The Problem 2
V(p) = L (PI- pt)2.
Our main task in this chapter is to investigate the qualita:tive 1=1

properties of the path of prices generated by an economy in which At t = O, differentiating V(p(O)) with respect to t and using the
no contract is binding except in equilibrium, that is, a tatonnement pricing rule gives
process (Section 11.2). In particular, we shall be interested in
describing the cases for which it is true that these paths are either V(p(O)) = 2 : (pi(O) - pt)GI[zl(p(O))].
1
globally or locally stable. Since we shall show by an example that
there are situations in which, for a properly constructed general Then, if p 1(0) > pf, it must be thatp 2(0) < p~. By assumption,
equilibrium model, the tatonnement path of prices is not stable, the G1 [z1 (p(O))] > O and G2 [z2 (p(O))] ::;; O, so V(p(O)) > O. By the
"case study" approach is necessary. However, we shall consider pricing rule, p 1(t) > pf, all t, since the price of the first good rises
whether it may be possible to characterize a class of cases for which as long as z 1 (p(t)) > O and remains constant when z 1 (p(t)) = O.
the tatonnement has either local or global stability properties. Similarly, p 2 (t) < p~(t), all t. Hence V(p(t)) > O, all t, as long as
Throughout this chapter it is rather important to remember that p(t) $E.
we are investigating as yet a laboratory situation only. Thus it An exactly analogous argument establishes that if p(O) < pf, then
would be quite wrong to conclude that the price mechanism works V(p(t)) < O, all t, as long as p(t) $E. Also, V(p(t)) = O if p(t) E E.
from a demonstration of stability, as it indeed would be wrong to Since V(p) is then monotone and p(t 1 p(O)) is bounded, it must be
conclude the reverse from demonstrations of instability. Such large convergent:
conclusions, if they are to be drawn at all, must await a discussion
of more acceptable models of adjustment in which the results of this lim V(p(t 1 p(O))) = V(lim p(t 1 p(O))) = V(p**) = V*.
t-too t-+co

1 chapter may well find sorne application.'


l,] By T.l1.2, we know that p** is an equilibrium. Since the equilibria
'
are isolated, there can be only one value of p, namely p**, for which
2. The Two-Goods Economy V(p) = V*. .
:i 1 i',

As is true in so much of general equilibrium analysis, there are Corollary l. A two-goods economy with a unique equilibrium is ':,
1

sorne rather general conclusions to be drawn from a model in which globally stable.
there are only two goods, conclusions that cannot be established for Proof. Directly by T.l2.1 and D.ll.3.
any other case. We shall investigate this special situation because in
so many parts of the literature of economic theory, for example, in An obvious application of the abdve results is to the traditional
the theory of international trade, it is this hypothetical economy that question of whether in a world with two goods, freely fluctuating '1

282
!]
:
,,
1

.,
T
STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 283
Chapter Twelve
has engaged the most attention. The sequel will suggest that this is
STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING probably not sensible.
We prove the following, where we assume, as indeed we do else-
where in this chapter, that A.II.3 and A.ll.4 hold.
Turning and turning in the widening
gyre THEOREM l. Let a two-goods economy have isolated equilibria.
The falcon cannot hear the falconer. Then the rule A.ll.l is globally stable.
-W. B. Yeats, The Second Coming Proof. Consider p(O) E s2 (the two-dimensional simplex), E =
{p* 1 z(p*) :S: O, p* E S2}. Let p(O) $E and, without loss of
generality, take z 1 (p(O)) > O. By W, p 2 (0) > O and z 2 (p(O)) ::;; O.
Let p* E E and consider
1. The Problem 2
V(p) = L (PI- pt)2.
Our main task in this chapter is to investigate the qualita:tive 1=1

properties of the path of prices generated by an economy in which At t = O, differentiating V(p(O)) with respect to t and using the
no contract is binding except in equilibrium, that is, a tatonnement pricing rule gives
process (Section 11.2). In particular, we shall be interested in
describing the cases for which it is true that these paths are either V(p(O)) = 2 : (pi(O) - pt)GI[zl(p(O))].
1
globally or locally stable. Since we shall show by an example that
there are situations in which, for a properly constructed general Then, if p 1(0) > pf, it must be thatp 2(0) < p~. By assumption,
equilibrium model, the tatonnement path of prices is not stable, the G1 [z1 (p(O))] > O and G2 [z2 (p(O))] ::;; O, so V(p(O)) > O. By the
"case study" approach is necessary. However, we shall consider pricing rule, p 1(t) > pf, all t, since the price of the first good rises
whether it may be possible to characterize a class of cases for which as long as z 1 (p(t)) > O and remains constant when z 1 (p(t)) = O.
the tatonnement has either local or global stability properties. Similarly, p 2 (t) < p~(t), all t. Hence V(p(t)) > O, all t, as long as
Throughout this chapter it is rather important to remember that p(t) $E.
we are investigating as yet a laboratory situation only. Thus it An exactly analogous argument establishes that if p(O) < pf, then
would be quite wrong to conclude that the price mechanism works V(p(t)) < O, all t, as long as p(t) $E. Also, V(p(t)) = O if p(t) E E.
from a demonstration of stability, as it indeed would be wrong to Since V(p) is then monotone and p(t 1 p(O)) is bounded, it must be
conclude the reverse from demonstrations of instability. Such large convergent:
conclusions, if they are to be drawn at all, must await a discussion
of more acceptable models of adjustment in which the results of this lim V(p(t 1 p(O))) = V(lim p(t 1 p(O))) = V(p**) = V*.
t-too t-+co

1 chapter may well find sorne application.'


l,] By T.l1.2, we know that p** is an equilibrium. Since the equilibria
'
are isolated, there can be only one value of p, namely p**, for which
2. The Two-Goods Economy V(p) = V*. .
:i 1 i',

As is true in so much of general equilibrium analysis, there are Corollary l. A two-goods economy with a unique equilibrium is ':,
1

sorne rather general conclusions to be drawn from a model in which globally stable.
there are only two goods, conclusions that cannot be established for Proof. Directly by T.l2.1 and D.ll.3.
any other case. We shall investigate this special situation because in
so many parts of the literature of economic theory, for example, in An obvious application of the abdve results is to the traditional
the theory of international trade, it is this hypothetical economy that question of whether in a world with two goods, freely fluctuating '1

282
!]
:
,,
1

.,
! 1

284 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 285

terms of trade would establish a world equilibrium,. In the literature stable if the economy has more than one equilibrium. From this
this question is often answered by considering the derivative of one we can say to the international trade theorist, "If you ha ve already
of the excess-demand functions at an equilibrium and implicitly supposed the equilibrium to be unique, as you often do, then you
supposing that the adjustment mechanism is one of recontracting. need worry no more about the stability of the adjustment path. lf
Thus, for instance, if P 1 is the price of the first good in terms of the you have not assumed uniqueness then you must be prepared to find
second, Pt a world equilibrium, then for all P 1 such that IP1 - P!l that sorne equilibrium is not locally stable, but you may nonetheless
is small enough we may write, assuming Pt > O, . t be sure that your adjustment process will converge to sorne
equilibrium."
zl(P) :::; Z(Pf) + la8pztl1 P1=P! P-PJ = la8pzll
1 P1=Pf
Pl-Pt lt seems pretty clear that this more complete statement of the
situation is to be much preferred to all the unpleasant elasticity
since z1 (Pf) = O. Then, if 8z1 (P)/8P1 < O when P 1 = Pt, we may formulas that keep cropping up in this subject. On the other hand,
take IP1 - P!l as providing a Lyapounov function provided P 1 (0) we can hardly take a two-goods world as a serious representation of
is in the specified neighborhood. For we can verify easily that, by what we are interested in; after all, the supposition that the adjust-
application of A.11.2, this function must be monotone declining as ment mechanism is a tatonnement is a serious enough restriction on
long as it is positive. This ensures that the rule is stable in the sense reality already. Nor is it likely that, for instance, an analysis that
of Lyapounov (i.e., we stay in the small neighborhood in which we allows us to consider two goods only, although there are many, by
started). Moreover, by the usual argument we can verify that the supposing the relative prices of goods in each of two groups of goods
function indeed converges and show that the convergence point is Pt, to be constant (a supposition that we know allows aggregation into
Recall that in Chapter 11 we distinguished two stability concepts: groups of goods) will be closer to the mark.
An adjustment rule is stable if it leads the economy to sorne equi-
librium, while a particular equilibrium is stable under an adjustment 3. The "Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference"
process if the latter returns the economy toward that particular
equilibrium. Careful scrutiny of the argument of the previous We shall start our investigation with the simplest cases. To begin
paragraph suggests that what is at stake is not the stability properties with, it will prove convenient to specialize the auctioneer's rule of
of the adjustment rule, but the question of whether a particular A.l1.1 or A.11.2 by supposing that
equilibrium is locally stable. This, of course, is a question of legiti-
mate interest. However, it leaves the question of the behavior of
k> o. (l)
the system unanswered should it turn out that the particular equi- Presently, we shall consider the more general case. It will be clear
librium is not locally stable. Let us see how we might deal with the that A. 11.1 specialized to (1) will give rise to solution paths that are
problem of adjustment in this model in the light of what we have bounded, because using (1) and W, we have
learned.
Suppose that Pf is a unique equilibrium for the world economy. d("i, pflk) -
dt -
2"' - o
L.._.PtZi- . (1)
Then, by Corollary 1, it is globally stable for the rule A.12.2 and so
certainly locally stable. Alternatively, (P1 - Pf)z1 (P) < O, P 1 -:1- THEOREM 2. Let p* be an equilibrium of the economy for which
Pf, is a necessary condition for the uniqueness of an equilibrium in p*s(p) < O, all p -:. p*. Then p* is globally stable for both the rules
a two-goods economy (T.9.17). Hence, if the derivative 8z 1 (Pf)/ A.l1.1 and A.11.2 specialized to (1).
8Pf :=::: O at P 1 = Pt, we conclude that there must be at 1east one
other equilibrium. From T.12. 1 we then predict that the auc- Proof. Let
tioneer's rule will take the economy arbitrarily close to one of the
other equilibria. We note that not all equilibria can be locally

i
Ji
! 1

284 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 285

terms of trade would establish a world equilibrium,. In the literature stable if the economy has more than one equilibrium. From this
this question is often answered by considering the derivative of one we can say to the international trade theorist, "If you ha ve already
of the excess-demand functions at an equilibrium and implicitly supposed the equilibrium to be unique, as you often do, then you
supposing that the adjustment mechanism is one of recontracting. need worry no more about the stability of the adjustment path. lf
Thus, for instance, if P 1 is the price of the first good in terms of the you have not assumed uniqueness then you must be prepared to find
second, Pt a world equilibrium, then for all P 1 such that IP1 - P!l that sorne equilibrium is not locally stable, but you may nonetheless
is small enough we may write, assuming Pt > O, . t be sure that your adjustment process will converge to sorne
equilibrium."
zl(P) :::; Z(Pf) + la8pztl1 P1=P! P-PJ = la8pzll
1 P1=Pf
Pl-Pt lt seems pretty clear that this more complete statement of the
situation is to be much preferred to all the unpleasant elasticity
since z1 (Pf) = O. Then, if 8z1 (P)/8P1 < O when P 1 = Pt, we may formulas that keep cropping up in this subject. On the other hand,
take IP1 - P!l as providing a Lyapounov function provided P 1 (0) we can hardly take a two-goods world as a serious representation of
is in the specified neighborhood. For we can verify easily that, by what we are interested in; after all, the supposition that the adjust-
application of A.11.2, this function must be monotone declining as ment mechanism is a tatonnement is a serious enough restriction on
long as it is positive. This ensures that the rule is stable in the sense reality already. Nor is it likely that, for instance, an analysis that
of Lyapounov (i.e., we stay in the small neighborhood in which we allows us to consider two goods only, although there are many, by
started). Moreover, by the usual argument we can verify that the supposing the relative prices of goods in each of two groups of goods
function indeed converges and show that the convergence point is Pt, to be constant (a supposition that we know allows aggregation into
Recall that in Chapter 11 we distinguished two stability concepts: groups of goods) will be closer to the mark.
An adjustment rule is stable if it leads the economy to sorne equi-
librium, while a particular equilibrium is stable under an adjustment 3. The "Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference"
process if the latter returns the economy toward that particular
equilibrium. Careful scrutiny of the argument of the previous We shall start our investigation with the simplest cases. To begin
paragraph suggests that what is at stake is not the stability properties with, it will prove convenient to specialize the auctioneer's rule of
of the adjustment rule, but the question of whether a particular A.l1.1 or A.11.2 by supposing that
equilibrium is locally stable. This, of course, is a question of legiti-
mate interest. However, it leaves the question of the behavior of
k> o. (l)
the system unanswered should it turn out that the particular equi- Presently, we shall consider the more general case. It will be clear
librium is not locally stable. Let us see how we might deal with the that A. 11.1 specialized to (1) will give rise to solution paths that are
problem of adjustment in this model in the light of what we have bounded, because using (1) and W, we have
learned.
Suppose that Pf is a unique equilibrium for the world economy. d("i, pflk) -
dt -
2"' - o
L.._.PtZi- . (1)
Then, by Corollary 1, it is globally stable for the rule A.12.2 and so
certainly locally stable. Alternatively, (P1 - Pf)z1 (P) < O, P 1 -:1- THEOREM 2. Let p* be an equilibrium of the economy for which
Pf, is a necessary condition for the uniqueness of an equilibrium in p*s(p) < O, all p -:. p*. Then p* is globally stable for both the rules
a two-goods economy (T.9.17). Hence, if the derivative 8z 1 (Pf)/ A.l1.1 and A.11.2 specialized to (1).
8Pf :=::: O at P 1 = Pt, we conclude that there must be at 1east one
other equilibrium. From T.12. 1 we then predict that the auc- Proof. Let
tioneer's rule will take the economy arbitrarily close to one of the
other equilibria. We note that not all equilibria can be locally

i
Ji
286 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 287
and let R*(p) = {i 1 p 1 = O; z1(p) < O} and R(p) the complement of THEOREM 3. Let the economy be Hicksian with a total production
R*(p). Then, by A.ll.l, (I), and W, we have set that is convex and differentiable. Then A.ll.l and A.l1.2 are
globally stable rules.
( [t = 2 ~
dV(p) L.; (p1
iER(p)
- pt)z1(p) = L pfs (p) :::; p*s(p),
ieR(p)
1
Proof By T.9.5, we may treat the economy as ifit had one house-
hold only with a strictly quasi-concave utility function U(x), where 1:
and so V(p) is monotonically declining along the solution path as :"!
x is the total consumption vector of households. Thus x(p), the li
long as p =F p*. Since p(t) is obviously bounded (quite inde-
consumption at p, can be found by maximizing U(x) subject to
pendently of the argument under (1)), it is a Lyapounov function,
pz(p) = O (recall that all profits are distributed to households).
and we can say that the rule is globally stable. By the assumption
This gives rise to first-order conditions:
of the theorem, p* is a unique equilibrium of the economy (see the
proof of T.9.4), so that the limit point of every solution path is p*. U1(x:(p)) :::; Ap1
So by Corollary 11.4' the theorem is established. 8U
U=-
8x1
Let P be the price vector in terms of numeraire and check that, by
the assumption of the theorem, (P* - P)s(P) < Ofor P =F P*. Let A = Lagrangean multiplier A > O. (2)
W(P) = 2 (P1 - Pt) 2 jk, and by the same argumentas the one just
We shall now show that we may take U(x(p)) as our Lyapounov
given, show that W(P) is a Lyapounov function for A.11.2 and (I).
function.
Note that by the monotonicity of W(P) it must be that all solution We know that the strict inequality in (2) for i implies x(p) = O.
paths are bounded. Hence, using (2) we have:
From this result we have at once,
dU(x(p)) _ ~ . ~U( (p)) 8x1 < ~ . A~ 8x1
y Corollary 2. If the economy is Hicksian, or if all goods are GS, dt -L.; Pi L.; j X 8'P - L.; Pi L;PJ -8
j ' j 'Pt
or if all goods are W GS and the economy is connected, then A.11.1
and A.ll.2 specialized to (I) are globally stable and the unique From pz(p) =O, we have
equilibrium of the economy is globally stable. ~ 8x1 ~ 8y
L.; Pi 8p = -z;(p) +L.; Pi 8p1 (3)
1 1 t
Proof By T.9.4, T.9.9, and the argument of pp. 227-228, it is
true for all these cases that p*s(p) < O for p =F p*. where y 1 is the jth component of the supply vector of producers.
Since py(p) is always ata maximum, we know (Corollary 3.6) that
These results are pleasant. It is important, however, not to be 8y1f8p 1 = 8ytf8p1, and since y;(p) is homogeneous of degree zero in
misled by the monotonicity of V(p) and W(P) into believing that all p, the term under the summation sign on the right-hand side of (3)
prices are monotonically approaching the equilibrium value. The is zero. Hence we have
monotonicity of the Lyapounov function here is quite consistent
with, say, fluctuations of individual prices of declining amplitude
about their equilibrium value.
dU~(p)) :::; A LP s (p) = A L
i
1 1
!ER(p)
G1(z1(p))s1(p),

The natural question to ask next is whether we can extend T.12.2 where R(p) is defined as before. It is cl~ar that the right-hand side
to the case in which the auctioneer's rule does not take the special of this expression is negative for non-equilibrium values of p. By
form (I). In answering this question we shall examine first the assumption, the solution path of prices is bounded. Since x(p) is a
Hicksian case and then the situation in which all goods are GS. continuous function of p, it too is bounded and so, therefore, is
Throughout, we assume that the adjustment rule satisfies A.11.1 and U(x(p)). Then U(x(p)) is convergent. Since the economy has a
A.11.2. unique equilibrium (Corollary 9.5), the theorem is established.
286 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 287
and let R*(p) = {i 1 p 1 = O; z1(p) < O} and R(p) the complement of THEOREM 3. Let the economy be Hicksian with a total production
R*(p). Then, by A.ll.l, (I), and W, we have set that is convex and differentiable. Then A.ll.l and A.l1.2 are
globally stable rules.
( [t = 2 ~
dV(p) L.; (p1
iER(p)
- pt)z1(p) = L pfs (p) :::; p*s(p),
ieR(p)
1
Proof By T.9.5, we may treat the economy as ifit had one house-
hold only with a strictly quasi-concave utility function U(x), where 1:
and so V(p) is monotonically declining along the solution path as :"!
x is the total consumption vector of households. Thus x(p), the li
long as p =F p*. Since p(t) is obviously bounded (quite inde-
consumption at p, can be found by maximizing U(x) subject to
pendently of the argument under (1)), it is a Lyapounov function,
pz(p) = O (recall that all profits are distributed to households).
and we can say that the rule is globally stable. By the assumption
This gives rise to first-order conditions:
of the theorem, p* is a unique equilibrium of the economy (see the
proof of T.9.4), so that the limit point of every solution path is p*. U1(x:(p)) :::; Ap1
So by Corollary 11.4' the theorem is established. 8U
U=-
8x1
Let P be the price vector in terms of numeraire and check that, by
the assumption of the theorem, (P* - P)s(P) < Ofor P =F P*. Let A = Lagrangean multiplier A > O. (2)
W(P) = 2 (P1 - Pt) 2 jk, and by the same argumentas the one just
We shall now show that we may take U(x(p)) as our Lyapounov
given, show that W(P) is a Lyapounov function for A.11.2 and (I).
function.
Note that by the monotonicity of W(P) it must be that all solution We know that the strict inequality in (2) for i implies x(p) = O.
paths are bounded. Hence, using (2) we have:
From this result we have at once,
dU(x(p)) _ ~ . ~U( (p)) 8x1 < ~ . A~ 8x1
y Corollary 2. If the economy is Hicksian, or if all goods are GS, dt -L.; Pi L.; j X 8'P - L.; Pi L;PJ -8
j ' j 'Pt
or if all goods are W GS and the economy is connected, then A.11.1
and A.ll.2 specialized to (I) are globally stable and the unique From pz(p) =O, we have
equilibrium of the economy is globally stable. ~ 8x1 ~ 8y
L.; Pi 8p = -z;(p) +L.; Pi 8p1 (3)
1 1 t
Proof By T.9.4, T.9.9, and the argument of pp. 227-228, it is
true for all these cases that p*s(p) < O for p =F p*. where y 1 is the jth component of the supply vector of producers.
Since py(p) is always ata maximum, we know (Corollary 3.6) that
These results are pleasant. It is important, however, not to be 8y1f8p 1 = 8ytf8p1, and since y;(p) is homogeneous of degree zero in
misled by the monotonicity of V(p) and W(P) into believing that all p, the term under the summation sign on the right-hand side of (3)
prices are monotonically approaching the equilibrium value. The is zero. Hence we have
monotonicity of the Lyapounov function here is quite consistent
with, say, fluctuations of individual prices of declining amplitude
about their equilibrium value.
dU~(p)) :::; A LP s (p) = A L
i
1 1
!ER(p)
G1(z1(p))s1(p),

The natural question to ask next is whether we can extend T.12.2 where R(p) is defined as before. It is cl~ar that the right-hand side
to the case in which the auctioneer's rule does not take the special of this expression is negative for non-equilibrium values of p. By
form (I). In answering this question we shall examine first the assumption, the solution path of prices is bounded. Since x(p) is a
Hicksian case and then the situation in which all goods are GS. continuous function of p, it too is bounded and so, therefore, is
Throughout, we assume that the adjustment rule satisfies A.11.1 and U(x(p)). Then U(x(p)) is convergent. Since the economy has a
A.11.2. unique equilibrium (Corollary 9.5), the theorem is established.
288 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 289

It is left to the reader to show that the same argument may be used is attained for a number of goods. We only sketch what is involved.
to show that A.11.2 gives a globally stable rule for the Hicksian Suppose, for instance, that V(p) = Pr - 1 = Ps - 1 and Pt < Pro all
economy. i #- s,r. Then Zr < O, Z 8 < O and 'the right-hand derivative
The common sen se of the procedure of the proof is not hard to see. dV(p)+ jdt = max(krzr,/( 8 Z 8 ). lt is well defined. The left-hand
The fictional household maximized utility subject to the constraint derivative dV(p)- jdt = min(krznk8 z8 ) and is also well defined.
pz(p) = O. For an equilibrium, however, it must have maximized Since V(p) is evidently bounded, it is a Lyapounov function and
utility subject to z ::; O. This constraint gives choices that are the theorem follows.
wholly contained in the set of choices that are feasible for the
contraint pz(p) = O. Hence it cannot be that the utility of the A similar argument can be developed for the rule of A.11.2, for
fictional household is less out of equilibrium than it is in equilibrium. which we note that, by definition, the price of the numeraire good is
By the Hicksian assumption of strict quasi-concavity of U, it must kept equal to unity throughout.
indeed be that the out-of-equilibrium utility is higher than the utility
Corollary 4. If all goods are WGS and the economy is connected,
possible in an equilibrium. The auctioneer's rule then serves to
A.ll.l and A.11.2 give globally stable rules.
reduce monotonically the difference [U(x(p)) - U(x(p*))]. Since he
raises the price of the good in excess demand and reduces the price Proof We know (pp. 227-228) that for this economy equilibrium
of the goods in excess supply, it must be that all the income terms in
is unique and strictly positive, and p*s(p) < O for p #- p*.
the basic equation of demand of the fictional household are negative;
in other words, the household is made "worse off" and the con- It is interesting to note that in the two cases we have just con-
clusion we reached then follows rather simply. sidered, where the process has such agreeable properties, we are able
We next turn to the GS case, which can be handled even more to say that the non-equilibrium situation is "superior" to the
easily. equilibrium one. In the Hicksian case this follows directly by the,
THEOREM 4. Let all goods be GS. Then the rules A.ll.l and argument just given, and in the GS case it follows from p*s(p) < O
A.11.2 are globally stable. (see Chapter 9). In the Hicksian case the auctioneer's rules are
Proof By Corollary 9.6, we know that the unique equilibrium gradient processes for minimizing [U(x(p)) - U(x(p*))]. In the GS
p* is strictly positive, so we may choose units in which to measure these rules are not easy to interpret as gradient processes, but they
goods that allow us to write p* = e, the unit vector. We show that lead to the minimization of (p - p*)s(p), which is a sort of measure
of the gap between the welfare that households hope to attain out of
V(p) = max(p 1 - 1)
i equilibrium and the welfare that they can attain (of course, this is not
is a Lyapounov function. By T.9.8, the good whose price exceeds a measure to be taken other than being suggestive).
its equilibrium value in the greatest proportion must be in excess Since, for any pair (p*,p) where p* is an equilibrium and pis not,
supply and the good whose price exceeds its equilibrium value in the p*s(p) < O when all goods are WGS (T.9.11), we should expect that
smallest proportion must be in excess demand. By the rule A.ll.l, for this case also we can establish the global stability of the rules we
the price of the former type of good must fall and that of the latter '1 are investigatipg. This is indeed the case when (I) is stipulated as
rise. Hence, certainly for p #- e, V(p) must be falling along the we now show, although, at first sight; the fact that in this case the
solution path. equilibrium set is convex (Corollary 9.11) and so the equilibrium
V(p) may not be differentiable everywhere, but it does not matter points are not isolated suggests that only global quasi-stability can
for our purposes since it is continuous and monotone declining. be established.
The lack of differentiability arises when
THEOREM 5. If all goods are WGS, then the rules A.ll.l and A.ll.2
max(pi- 1)
i of the form (I) are globally stable.
288 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 289

It is left to the reader to show that the same argument may be used is attained for a number of goods. We only sketch what is involved.
to show that A.11.2 gives a globally stable rule for the Hicksian Suppose, for instance, that V(p) = Pr - 1 = Ps - 1 and Pt < Pro all
economy. i #- s,r. Then Zr < O, Z 8 < O and 'the right-hand derivative
The common sen se of the procedure of the proof is not hard to see. dV(p)+ jdt = max(krzr,/( 8 Z 8 ). lt is well defined. The left-hand
The fictional household maximized utility subject to the constraint derivative dV(p)- jdt = min(krznk8 z8 ) and is also well defined.
pz(p) = O. For an equilibrium, however, it must have maximized Since V(p) is evidently bounded, it is a Lyapounov function and
utility subject to z ::; O. This constraint gives choices that are the theorem follows.
wholly contained in the set of choices that are feasible for the
contraint pz(p) = O. Hence it cannot be that the utility of the A similar argument can be developed for the rule of A.11.2, for
fictional household is less out of equilibrium than it is in equilibrium. which we note that, by definition, the price of the numeraire good is
By the Hicksian assumption of strict quasi-concavity of U, it must kept equal to unity throughout.
indeed be that the out-of-equilibrium utility is higher than the utility
Corollary 4. If all goods are WGS and the economy is connected,
possible in an equilibrium. The auctioneer's rule then serves to
A.ll.l and A.11.2 give globally stable rules.
reduce monotonically the difference [U(x(p)) - U(x(p*))]. Since he
raises the price of the good in excess demand and reduces the price Proof We know (pp. 227-228) that for this economy equilibrium
of the goods in excess supply, it must be that all the income terms in
is unique and strictly positive, and p*s(p) < O for p #- p*.
the basic equation of demand of the fictional household are negative;
in other words, the household is made "worse off" and the con- It is interesting to note that in the two cases we have just con-
clusion we reached then follows rather simply. sidered, where the process has such agreeable properties, we are able
We next turn to the GS case, which can be handled even more to say that the non-equilibrium situation is "superior" to the
easily. equilibrium one. In the Hicksian case this follows directly by the,
THEOREM 4. Let all goods be GS. Then the rules A.ll.l and argument just given, and in the GS case it follows from p*s(p) < O
A.11.2 are globally stable. (see Chapter 9). In the Hicksian case the auctioneer's rules are
Proof By Corollary 9.6, we know that the unique equilibrium gradient processes for minimizing [U(x(p)) - U(x(p*))]. In the GS
p* is strictly positive, so we may choose units in which to measure these rules are not easy to interpret as gradient processes, but they
goods that allow us to write p* = e, the unit vector. We show that lead to the minimization of (p - p*)s(p), which is a sort of measure
of the gap between the welfare that households hope to attain out of
V(p) = max(p 1 - 1)
i equilibrium and the welfare that they can attain (of course, this is not
is a Lyapounov function. By T.9.8, the good whose price exceeds a measure to be taken other than being suggestive).
its equilibrium value in the greatest proportion must be in excess Since, for any pair (p*,p) where p* is an equilibrium and pis not,
supply and the good whose price exceeds its equilibrium value in the p*s(p) < O when all goods are WGS (T.9.11), we should expect that
smallest proportion must be in excess demand. By the rule A.ll.l, for this case also we can establish the global stability of the rules we
the price of the former type of good must fall and that of the latter '1 are investigatipg. This is indeed the case when (I) is stipulated as
rise. Hence, certainly for p #- e, V(p) must be falling along the we now show, although, at first sight; the fact that in this case the
solution path. equilibrium set is convex (Corollary 9.11) and so the equilibrium
V(p) may not be differentiable everywhere, but it does not matter points are not isolated suggests that only global quasi-stability can
for our purposes since it is continuous and monotone declining. be established.
The lack of differentiability arises when
THEOREM 5. If all goods are WGS, then the rules A.ll.l and A.ll.2
max(pi- 1)
i of the form (I) are globally stable.
290 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-1 RECONTRACTING 291
Proof By T.9.11, p*s(p) < O for p* E E and p ~E. Hence, (See T.9.8, which clearly holds in this weak forni.) But, since i E N,
certainly for any p* E E, the inequality rnust be strict, whence by continuity, there is t* < t
V(p) = 2, (p - pt)2 such that
k
Z[p(t)] > 0 t* < t < t'.
is a Lyapounov function for A.11.1 (1) by the same argument as in
the proof of T.12.2. In particular, V(p(t)) converges to a unique For such t, the adjustment rule ensures jJ(t) > O, so that O = p 1(t') >
limit V*. Hence, ifp*(t) is the limit path ofp(t), it must be that for p 1(t *) :2:: O, which is a contradiction.
all points on that path V takes on the value V* ; that is, Next we note that if pE E, M(p) = O. Conversely, suppose
M(p) = O, PN O, then for all i E N, z1(p) = O, and for all i ~N,
V(p*(t)) = V*. z1(p) :<:::; O from our earlier discussion. Then by W, z1(p) < O, i ~N
In the definition of V(p) we rnay always choose p* to be a point on must mean p 1 = O, whence p E E.
p*(t). We can do this because V constant identically in t rneans that Let ,.11'
:'
all points on the path are equilibria. Then, evidently, it rnust be
true that V(p*) = O = V*. But V(p) = O has a unique solution m= {i J M[p(t)] = G1 zt~?]' iE N}
and so p* rnust be the only point on p*(t) and so p(t) converges on il
Then for all i E m, we have, omitting arguments from functions,
this point as t goes to plus infinity.
The question now arises whether this result depends on the special
1!
form of (I) of the auctioneer's rule. If we consider the more
general form, we shall certainly have to introduce as an assumption, ,

The inequalities follow from 11


as we have done elsewhere, that the solution path is bounded.
Having done so let us see how we fare. (a) G(z1) :<:::; O for j ~N and Zjj :2:: O, j =f i by WGS;
ili.l1,
Suppose first that there is sorne p(i) such that z1(p(i)) :<:::; O. Then
z1(p) :<:::; O, all p. Suppose not and suppose that for sorne p', z1(p') >
(b) by H and WGS JzJp1 :2:: 2, z11p 1 ;
Ni
O. Then, by WGS, z1(p'(i)) :2:: z1(p') > O, a contradiction of the
(e) G1 ;<;;G1,jEN,iEm.
result that z1(p'(i)) :<:::; O since z1(p(i)) :<:::; O (T.9.10, Corollary 9.10).
Now let N be the set of i such that z(p(i)) > O, all p(i). Then, by Now the right-hand derivative of M(p(t)) is
what has already been said, this set can be empty only if all p E E.
d G(Z)
If N is empty, z1(p) :<:::; O, all p and all i, and so W confirms that all max---
tem dt p
pE E.
Let us suppose, therefore, that N is not empty and consider and the left-hand derivative is
M(p) = rnax G[z(p)J. . d G(Z)
p mm---
leN iem dt p
Let PN be the price vector with components in N. It is easy to see Using the above inequalities, we have
that if PN(O) O, then PN(t) O, all t. Suppose not and let t' be
the first time that sorne price, say the ith, i E N, becomes zero. Then, dM[p(t)]+ = G'[dz;/dt _ G1(z)] < O
1
certainly, since no price can have fallen in greater proportion dt Pt Pt
relatively to its positive equilibriurn price than i has fallen, we have,
if p(t) ~E, since by A.ll.l, G; >O. We have assumed that the
by WGS,
solution path is bounded and so M(p) is indeed a Lyapounov
Z(p(t')] :?: 0. function.
290 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-1 RECONTRACTING 291
Proof By T.9.11, p*s(p) < O for p* E E and p ~E. Hence, (See T.9.8, which clearly holds in this weak forni.) But, since i E N,
certainly for any p* E E, the inequality rnust be strict, whence by continuity, there is t* < t
V(p) = 2, (p - pt)2 such that
k
Z[p(t)] > 0 t* < t < t'.
is a Lyapounov function for A.11.1 (1) by the same argument as in
the proof of T.12.2. In particular, V(p(t)) converges to a unique For such t, the adjustment rule ensures jJ(t) > O, so that O = p 1(t') >
limit V*. Hence, ifp*(t) is the limit path ofp(t), it must be that for p 1(t *) :2:: O, which is a contradiction.
all points on that path V takes on the value V* ; that is, Next we note that if pE E, M(p) = O. Conversely, suppose
M(p) = O, PN O, then for all i E N, z1(p) = O, and for all i ~N,
V(p*(t)) = V*. z1(p) :<:::; O from our earlier discussion. Then by W, z1(p) < O, i ~N
In the definition of V(p) we rnay always choose p* to be a point on must mean p 1 = O, whence p E E.
p*(t). We can do this because V constant identically in t rneans that Let ,.11'
:'
all points on the path are equilibria. Then, evidently, it rnust be
true that V(p*) = O = V*. But V(p) = O has a unique solution m= {i J M[p(t)] = G1 zt~?]' iE N}
and so p* rnust be the only point on p*(t) and so p(t) converges on il
Then for all i E m, we have, omitting arguments from functions,
this point as t goes to plus infinity.
The question now arises whether this result depends on the special
1!
form of (I) of the auctioneer's rule. If we consider the more
general form, we shall certainly have to introduce as an assumption, ,

The inequalities follow from 11


as we have done elsewhere, that the solution path is bounded.
Having done so let us see how we fare. (a) G(z1) :<:::; O for j ~N and Zjj :2:: O, j =f i by WGS;
ili.l1,
Suppose first that there is sorne p(i) such that z1(p(i)) :<:::; O. Then
z1(p) :<:::; O, all p. Suppose not and suppose that for sorne p', z1(p') >
(b) by H and WGS JzJp1 :2:: 2, z11p 1 ;
Ni
O. Then, by WGS, z1(p'(i)) :2:: z1(p') > O, a contradiction of the
(e) G1 ;<;;G1,jEN,iEm.
result that z1(p'(i)) :<:::; O since z1(p(i)) :<:::; O (T.9.10, Corollary 9.10).
Now let N be the set of i such that z(p(i)) > O, all p(i). Then, by Now the right-hand derivative of M(p(t)) is
what has already been said, this set can be empty only if all p E E.
d G(Z)
If N is empty, z1(p) :<:::; O, all p and all i, and so W confirms that all max---
tem dt p
pE E.
Let us suppose, therefore, that N is not empty and consider and the left-hand derivative is
M(p) = rnax G[z(p)J. . d G(Z)
p mm---
leN iem dt p
Let PN be the price vector with components in N. It is easy to see Using the above inequalities, we have
that if PN(O) O, then PN(t) O, all t. Suppose not and let t' be
the first time that sorne price, say the ith, i E N, becomes zero. Then, dM[p(t)]+ = G'[dz;/dt _ G1(z)] < O
1
certainly, since no price can have fallen in greater proportion dt Pt Pt
relatively to its positive equilibriurn price than i has fallen, we have,
if p(t) ~E, since by A.ll.l, G; >O. We have assumed that the
by WGS,
solution path is bounded and so M(p) is indeed a Lyapounov
Z(p(t')] :?: 0. function.
292 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 293
':',,
1
In particular, ifp*(t) is a limit path of the solution, The special adjustment form of A.ll.2 is this:
'1

1
M[p*(t)] = M* identically in t, for P1 >O. (11)
so that every point on p*(t) is an equilibrium.
In order to be able to use this rule without complications we further
By Corollary 9.11, the set of equilibria is convex when WGS holds,
stipulate:
so that the equilibria are not isolated if there are more than one.
From T.ll.3 and D.ll.5, therefore, quasi-global stability without ASSUMPTION l. For all P, x(P) 0 and z 1[P(i)] > 0, all i. (P(i)
global stability seems possible for this case, although we have not is P with the ith element replaced by zero.) Also, zn[P(n)] > O.
investigated this question. However, Arrow and Hurwicz [1962]
This assumption supposes that every good is demanded in positive
showed that if we postulate that at least one strictly positive equi-
amount at every set of prices and that every good is in excess demand
librium exists, the adjustment process is stable. They also gave an
when its own price is zero. It requires also that the demand for the
example in which, when this extra assumption (of at least one
numeraire good is large (in excess of the fixed supply) when its price
strictly positive equilibrium) is not made, the process is quasi-
goes to zero. We do not claim that all these assumptions have a
globally stable, but unbounded. In their example, however, G1(0)
great deal to recommend them. In any event, we may now establish
was not finite. The question whether the process under WGS may
be only quasi-globally stable, but not stable under slightly stronger THEOREM 7. If a pure-exchange economy has D*D* and it follows
conditions, is unsettled. the tatonnement rule (11), then, provided A.l2.1 and p(O) O hold,
We sum up what we have proved or stated. the rule will be globally stable.
THEOREM 6. Let all goods be WGS and let PN(O) O. Then A.ll.l Proof By an argument exactly analogous tq that used in the
is globally stable provided that all solution paths are bounded. If proof of T.12.6 we can show that P(O) Oimplies that P(t) O, all
there exists a strictly positive equilibrium, then A.ll.l is always t, since z(P(i)) > O. Hence, certainly, the solution path is bounded
globally stable. from below. By A.l2.1, zn(P) > O for J., Pt sufficiently large, for
While the analysis of the WGS case is rather more complex than
that of GS, we see that we do almost as well with the weaker assump-
tion as we did with the stronger. The "almost" is dueto the extra
fuss to ensure boundedness of the solution paths. The weakening by H, so that setting Pn = 1, zn(P) > O when 2., P1 = +oo and so
of the assumptions is to be welcomed, bt they are still pretty strong. zn(P) > O for P sufficiently large. By W, 2., P1z1(p) = -zn(P) and
(dfdt) 2., P1 = 2., P1z1(P) < O for J., Pt sufficiently large, so that the
4.. Diagonal Dominance
solution path is also bounded from above.
Let us again start with the simplest case, by supposing Diagonal We now let
Dominance and the adjustment rule to be of a special kind and the
economy to be a pure-exchange economy. Z(P) = max lz(P)I
i
Let X(P) be the demand for good i at the prices (in terms of and show that it is a Lyapounov function. Let m be the set of i
numeraire) P. Then we write eJ(P) = x 1JCP)P1jx(P) as the appro- for which lz(P)I = Z(P). Then, for i E m, consider log x(P),
priate elasticities of demand. The special form of Diagonal which, in view of A.ll.l, is well defined. Differentiating with
Dominance, which we refer toas D*D*, is this:
respect to t and using (11) gives
e(P) < O all i # n and P;
d[log x 1(P)] -_ L.,
'Y (P) zJ(P) .
lett(P)I > ,L
n>Ni
le1J(P)I all i i= n and P. dt Nn
eif
292 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 293
':',,
1
In particular, ifp*(t) is a limit path of the solution, The special adjustment form of A.ll.2 is this:
'1

1
M[p*(t)] = M* identically in t, for P1 >O. (11)
so that every point on p*(t) is an equilibrium.
In order to be able to use this rule without complications we further
By Corollary 9.11, the set of equilibria is convex when WGS holds,
stipulate:
so that the equilibria are not isolated if there are more than one.
From T.ll.3 and D.ll.5, therefore, quasi-global stability without ASSUMPTION l. For all P, x(P) 0 and z 1[P(i)] > 0, all i. (P(i)
global stability seems possible for this case, although we have not is P with the ith element replaced by zero.) Also, zn[P(n)] > O.
investigated this question. However, Arrow and Hurwicz [1962]
This assumption supposes that every good is demanded in positive
showed that if we postulate that at least one strictly positive equi-
amount at every set of prices and that every good is in excess demand
librium exists, the adjustment process is stable. They also gave an
when its own price is zero. It requires also that the demand for the
example in which, when this extra assumption (of at least one
numeraire good is large (in excess of the fixed supply) when its price
strictly positive equilibrium) is not made, the process is quasi-
goes to zero. We do not claim that all these assumptions have a
globally stable, but unbounded. In their example, however, G1(0)
great deal to recommend them. In any event, we may now establish
was not finite. The question whether the process under WGS may
be only quasi-globally stable, but not stable under slightly stronger THEOREM 7. If a pure-exchange economy has D*D* and it follows
conditions, is unsettled. the tatonnement rule (11), then, provided A.l2.1 and p(O) O hold,
We sum up what we have proved or stated. the rule will be globally stable.
THEOREM 6. Let all goods be WGS and let PN(O) O. Then A.ll.l Proof By an argument exactly analogous tq that used in the
is globally stable provided that all solution paths are bounded. If proof of T.12.6 we can show that P(O) Oimplies that P(t) O, all
there exists a strictly positive equilibrium, then A.ll.l is always t, since z(P(i)) > O. Hence, certainly, the solution path is bounded
globally stable. from below. By A.l2.1, zn(P) > O for J., Pt sufficiently large, for
While the analysis of the WGS case is rather more complex than
that of GS, we see that we do almost as well with the weaker assump-
tion as we did with the stronger. The "almost" is dueto the extra
fuss to ensure boundedness of the solution paths. The weakening by H, so that setting Pn = 1, zn(P) > O when 2., P1 = +oo and so
of the assumptions is to be welcomed, bt they are still pretty strong. zn(P) > O for P sufficiently large. By W, 2., P1z1(p) = -zn(P) and
(dfdt) 2., P1 = 2., P1z1(P) < O for J., Pt sufficiently large, so that the
4.. Diagonal Dominance
solution path is also bounded from above.
Let us again start with the simplest case, by supposing Diagonal We now let
Dominance and the adjustment rule to be of a special kind and the
economy to be a pure-exchange economy. Z(P) = max lz(P)I
i
Let X(P) be the demand for good i at the prices (in terms of and show that it is a Lyapounov function. Let m be the set of i
numeraire) P. Then we write eJ(P) = x 1JCP)P1jx(P) as the appro- for which lz(P)I = Z(P). Then, for i E m, consider log x(P),
priate elasticities of demand. The special form of Diagonal which, in view of A.ll.l, is well defined. Differentiating with
Dominance, which we refer toas D*D*, is this:
respect to t and using (11) gives
e(P) < O all i # n and P;
d[log x 1(P)] -_ L.,
'Y (P) zJ(P) .
lett(P)I > ,L
n>Ni
le1J(P)I all i i= n and P. dt Nn
eif
'F
1

294 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 295

If this expression were non-negative for non-equilibrium P, when It can be left to the reader to show that this expression has the same
z1 > O, it would have to be that the following is true for i E m: sign as z 1 for non-equilibrium P. As before, Z(P) is declining for
non-equilibrium P, and the proof proceeds as before.
lett(P)IIz1(P)I ~ L~~~ e1(P)z/P)I The result we have just established is worth having if for no other
reason that the Diagonal Dominance hypothesis, when framed in
~ L;
n>J;hi
let/P)IIz/P)I ~ lzt(P)I L;
n>J,Pi
le(P)I. terms of elasticities, seems particularly appealing. There is also
another, sadder reason. When we return to the more general form
where the last inequality follows from the definition of m. Evi- of the assumption and also to the more general form of the pricing
dently, the abo ve inequalities contradict D*D*. Similarly, if rule, it is not at present possible to establish global stability. This,
z1 < O, d[log x 1(p)]/dt must be positive. Hence, since we are in a if a conjecture may be made, is likely to be due to lack of skill on our
pure-exchange economy, Z(P) is declining at non-equilibrium P. part, rather than to any global instability in fact. The kind of result
Since we already know the solution path to be bounded, Z(P) is that we need here is one that would allow us to deduce global
indeed a Lyapounov function. Since, by T.9.12, the economy must stability from the postulate that the Jacobian of excess supplies has
have a unique equilibrium, the theorem is proved. (Of course, the everywhere DD. No such result is available, but neither are counter-
equilibrium as well as the rule is globally stable.) examples. In any event, we are able, at present, to prove only the
following, weaker result.
It is not hard to think of the kind of assumptions we should like
to malee in order to extend these results to an economy in which THEOREM 9. Let there be units in which goods are measured such
there is also production. We consider only one of these, the that if the economy has DD in these units, it has this property at all
simplest. prices. Then A.ll.2 gives a globally stable rule,
AssuMPTION 2. The numeraire good does not enter into the produc- Proof. We note formally the assumption of the theorem: There
tion of any good nor is it produced. Also, 8y1(P)/8P1 < O for all is a vector h O, such that for all i 1= n and all P
P O and j 1= i. lztt(P)Ih1 >
n>J,Pi
lz1(P)Ih1,
The last assumption supposes that, say, a rise in the price of good
j will decrease the economy's output of good i, if that good is where, of course, Z(P) < O, all i.
produced, or reduce the demand for that good (service) as input if We now show that
it is not. As usual, it is easy to think of technologies that would H(P) = max F[Z(P)]
falsify this assumption. If it is made in view of H applied to y(P), h
however, it follows at once from the supposition that the numeraire is a Lyapounov function. Let m be the set of i for which
good does not enter production in any way, that 8y1(P)/8P1 > O all F1[z1(P)]/h 1 = H(P). Then for i E m,
P O and all i.
THEOREM 8. If an economy has D*D*, follows the rule (II), and
dzd~P) = Z(P)FJ[z(P)] = ; z1 (P)~:F1 [zt(P)],
satisfies A.l2.1 and A.12.2, thcn for all P(O) O, the rule is globally The right-hand side of this expression must be negative for non-
stable. equilibrium P. If not, then
Proof Proceed as in the proof of T.l2.7. For i E m, we find,
writing YiJ(P) = 8y 1(P)/8P1 and using (II), Z(P) 1hH(P)
1 ~ >'-'"~. :. .:*i:._z_tJ_(P,)_h_F_J[z_l_P_)]
.:..:.:n

h
dy1(P) = L,
----- ""' y (P)P z(P).
i
1 1 ~ H(P)
n=NI
lzt1(P)Ih1,
'F
1

294 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 295

If this expression were non-negative for non-equilibrium P, when It can be left to the reader to show that this expression has the same
z1 > O, it would have to be that the following is true for i E m: sign as z 1 for non-equilibrium P. As before, Z(P) is declining for
non-equilibrium P, and the proof proceeds as before.
lett(P)IIz1(P)I ~ L~~~ e1(P)z/P)I The result we have just established is worth having if for no other
reason that the Diagonal Dominance hypothesis, when framed in
~ L;
n>J;hi
let/P)IIz/P)I ~ lzt(P)I L;
n>J,Pi
le(P)I. terms of elasticities, seems particularly appealing. There is also
another, sadder reason. When we return to the more general form
where the last inequality follows from the definition of m. Evi- of the assumption and also to the more general form of the pricing
dently, the abo ve inequalities contradict D*D*. Similarly, if rule, it is not at present possible to establish global stability. This,
z1 < O, d[log x 1(p)]/dt must be positive. Hence, since we are in a if a conjecture may be made, is likely to be due to lack of skill on our
pure-exchange economy, Z(P) is declining at non-equilibrium P. part, rather than to any global instability in fact. The kind of result
Since we already know the solution path to be bounded, Z(P) is that we need here is one that would allow us to deduce global
indeed a Lyapounov function. Since, by T.9.12, the economy must stability from the postulate that the Jacobian of excess supplies has
have a unique equilibrium, the theorem is proved. (Of course, the everywhere DD. No such result is available, but neither are counter-
equilibrium as well as the rule is globally stable.) examples. In any event, we are able, at present, to prove only the
following, weaker result.
It is not hard to think of the kind of assumptions we should like
to malee in order to extend these results to an economy in which THEOREM 9. Let there be units in which goods are measured such
there is also production. We consider only one of these, the that if the economy has DD in these units, it has this property at all
simplest. prices. Then A.ll.2 gives a globally stable rule,
AssuMPTION 2. The numeraire good does not enter into the produc- Proof. We note formally the assumption of the theorem: There
tion of any good nor is it produced. Also, 8y1(P)/8P1 < O for all is a vector h O, such that for all i 1= n and all P
P O and j 1= i. lztt(P)Ih1 >
n>J,Pi
lz1(P)Ih1,
The last assumption supposes that, say, a rise in the price of good
j will decrease the economy's output of good i, if that good is where, of course, Z(P) < O, all i.
produced, or reduce the demand for that good (service) as input if We now show that
it is not. As usual, it is easy to think of technologies that would H(P) = max F[Z(P)]
falsify this assumption. If it is made in view of H applied to y(P), h
however, it follows at once from the supposition that the numeraire is a Lyapounov function. Let m be the set of i for which
good does not enter production in any way, that 8y1(P)/8P1 > O all F1[z1(P)]/h 1 = H(P). Then for i E m,
P O and all i.
THEOREM 8. If an economy has D*D*, follows the rule (II), and
dzd~P) = Z(P)FJ[z(P)] = ; z1 (P)~:F1 [zt(P)],
satisfies A.l2.1 and A.12.2, thcn for all P(O) O, the rule is globally The right-hand side of this expression must be negative for non-
stable. equilibrium P. If not, then
Proof Proceed as in the proof of T.l2.7. For i E m, we find,
writing YiJ(P) = 8y 1(P)/8P1 and using (II), Z(P) 1hH(P)
1 ~ >'-'"~. :. .:*i:._z_tJ_(P,)_h_F_J[z_l_P_)]
.:..:.:n

h
dy1(P) = L,
----- ""' y (P)P z(P).
i
1 1 ~ H(P)
n=NI
lzt1(P)Ih1,
296 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-I RECONTRACTING 297
which would contradict the assumption of the theorem. Hence Premultiplying both si des of this expression by (P - P*)- 1,
H(P) is declining in value at every non-equilibrium P and the usual
(P - P*)DP' = - (P - P *)J(P *)(P - P *)'
argument proves the theorem.
The method of proof we ha ve just used shows why we needed the when D = - 1 . The left-hand side of this expression is equal to
rather special form of Diagonal Dominance. If we had taken h to [dV(P)fdt]/2 and so we would like to be able to say that the right-
be a function ofP, that is, h = h(P), we would have required to know hand side is negative for non-equilibrium P. The reader should
how h(P) behaves when P changes, and on this, no useful hypothesis prove to himself that this is indeed the case for a Hicksian or GS
seems available. economy. It is not necessarily true for DD because V(P) is not a
suitable fonn of the Lyapounov function for this case.
To proceed, it will be useful to look at the constituents of J(P*).
5, Local Stability Since s1 = x1 + y1 - X, we may write
In al! the cases we have considered so far, with the exception of J(P*) = Y(P*) - X(P*),
WGS, we know that the equilibrium is unique, and since we have
shown it to be globally stable, it must be that the equilibrium is where Y(P*) is the Jacobian of the production term y(P*) and
locally stable also. The question we shall briefly pose is whether X(P*) the Jacobian of the demand term x(P*) in s(P*). (We here
there are situations for which local, but not global, stability proper- assume that al! these are differentiable.) From profit maximization
ties can be established. We do not propose, however, to examine we know that (P - P*)[(y(P) - y(P*)] ;::: O (see T.3.8). By the
local stabi!ity problems at al! exhaustively. Taylor expansion,
We shall be considering the numeraire rule of A.ll.2 and conduct-
y(P) - y(P*) = Y(P*)(P - P*)'
ing our analysis in terms of the norm V(P) = (P - P*)D(P - P*)'
when P (taken as a row vector with transposition denoted by a and so
prime) is assumed to lie in an E neighborhood of P*, and ]) is a - (P - P*) Y(P*)(P - P*)' :::; O.
suitably chosen diagonal matrix. Of cotme, what we are looking
for are situations for which we can say that the norm is declining for It follows from this that if, for sorne cases, we can show
al! non-equilibrium P, for then, on the usual argument, we shall be
able to treat it as a Lyapounov function.
(P - P*)X(P*)(P - P*)' < O
For a suitable choice of E we may write z1(P) in a Taylor expansion, for non-equilibrium P, we can then say that for these assumptions
ignoring non-linear terms, as follows: V(P) is indeed a Lyapounov function. Thus the crucial problem is
Z(P) = Z(P*) + Z{P*)(P - Pj)'.
the behavior of households, not that of producers. We shall sim-
plify matters accordingly from here on by considering only a pure-
If P* O, then we know that it must be that z(P*) = O. By exchange economy.
A.11.2, we may then write We know that we may write X(P*) as the sum of the matrix of
substitution terms, say [au(P*)], and the matrix of income terms, say
F = F; Z(P*)(P - Pj). [[-t1{P*)]. The former is known to be negative definite (see T.4.9(b)),
so evidently the crux of the pro blem is presented by the income term
If, as usual, we write J(P*) as the Jacobian of the excess-supply matrix as no doubt we expected al! along. From elementary theory,
functions and fas the diagonalmatrix with non-zero elements given we may write the typical element of that matrix as
by F;, we have, in matrix notation,
P' = - fJ(P*)(P - P*)'.
f-ttiCP*) = L sh{P*)mh (P*)
h
1
296 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-I RECONTRACTING 297
which would contradict the assumption of the theorem. Hence Premultiplying both si des of this expression by (P - P*)- 1,
H(P) is declining in value at every non-equilibrium P and the usual
(P - P*)DP' = - (P - P *)J(P *)(P - P *)'
argument proves the theorem.
The method of proof we ha ve just used shows why we needed the when D = - 1 . The left-hand side of this expression is equal to
rather special form of Diagonal Dominance. If we had taken h to [dV(P)fdt]/2 and so we would like to be able to say that the right-
be a function ofP, that is, h = h(P), we would have required to know hand side is negative for non-equilibrium P. The reader should
how h(P) behaves when P changes, and on this, no useful hypothesis prove to himself that this is indeed the case for a Hicksian or GS
seems available. economy. It is not necessarily true for DD because V(P) is not a
suitable fonn of the Lyapounov function for this case.
To proceed, it will be useful to look at the constituents of J(P*).
5, Local Stability Since s1 = x1 + y1 - X, we may write
In al! the cases we have considered so far, with the exception of J(P*) = Y(P*) - X(P*),
WGS, we know that the equilibrium is unique, and since we have
shown it to be globally stable, it must be that the equilibrium is where Y(P*) is the Jacobian of the production term y(P*) and
locally stable also. The question we shall briefly pose is whether X(P*) the Jacobian of the demand term x(P*) in s(P*). (We here
there are situations for which local, but not global, stability proper- assume that al! these are differentiable.) From profit maximization
ties can be established. We do not propose, however, to examine we know that (P - P*)[(y(P) - y(P*)] ;::: O (see T.3.8). By the
local stabi!ity problems at al! exhaustively. Taylor expansion,
We shall be considering the numeraire rule of A.ll.2 and conduct-
y(P) - y(P*) = Y(P*)(P - P*)'
ing our analysis in terms of the norm V(P) = (P - P*)D(P - P*)'
when P (taken as a row vector with transposition denoted by a and so
prime) is assumed to lie in an E neighborhood of P*, and ]) is a - (P - P*) Y(P*)(P - P*)' :::; O.
suitably chosen diagonal matrix. Of cotme, what we are looking
for are situations for which we can say that the norm is declining for It follows from this that if, for sorne cases, we can show
al! non-equilibrium P, for then, on the usual argument, we shall be
able to treat it as a Lyapounov function.
(P - P*)X(P*)(P - P*)' < O
For a suitable choice of E we may write z1(P) in a Taylor expansion, for non-equilibrium P, we can then say that for these assumptions
ignoring non-linear terms, as follows: V(P) is indeed a Lyapounov function. Thus the crucial problem is
Z(P) = Z(P*) + Z{P*)(P - Pj)'.
the behavior of households, not that of producers. We shall sim-
plify matters accordingly from here on by considering only a pure-
If P* O, then we know that it must be that z(P*) = O. By exchange economy.
A.11.2, we may then write We know that we may write X(P*) as the sum of the matrix of
substitution terms, say [au(P*)], and the matrix of income terms, say
F = F; Z(P*)(P - Pj). [[-t1{P*)]. The former is known to be negative definite (see T.4.9(b)),
so evidently the crux of the pro blem is presented by the income term
If, as usual, we write J(P*) as the Jacobian of the excess-supply matrix as no doubt we expected al! along. From elementary theory,
functions and fas the diagonalmatrix with non-zero elements given we may write the typical element of that matrix as
by F;, we have, in matrix notation,
P' = - fJ(P*)(P - P*)'.
f-ttiCP*) = L sh{P*)mh (P*)
h
1
298 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 299
where s,(P*) is the difference between the amount of the jth good covariance term is small for all P, this does not seem sufficient to
household h has at P* and the amount it would like to have at P*, establish a global stability result.
household h's excess supply of goodj, and m,(P*) is the household's Indeed, local stability requires us to show that the real parts of
marginal propensity to consume good i at P*. Since P* O, it is the roots of X(P*) are negative. Suppose this to be the case not only
of course true that at P*, but at all P. We might conjecture, then, that provided P(t)
,. Ls,(P*) = O. is bounded and equilibrium is unique, global stability would follow.
This we have not been able to prove.
"
This enables us to write the typical element of the income term It is not clear how interesting the small covariance case is, since,
matrix also as for instance, a stratified society may well consist of a few kinds of
households only and. the covariance terms may be large. Indeed,
.t1(P*) = Ls,(P*)[m,(P*) - m1(P*)] we must recognize that we have here a double-edged weapon, for it
"
where m1(P*) is the average marginal propensity to consume good i
would seem clear that we ought to be able to construct at least
hypothetical examples where the income terms are sufficiently large
for household as a whole. Evidently, we may interpret the fore-
relative to the substitution terms to allow us to deduce that V(P) is
going expression as a covariance. If there is no reason we can think
increasing for all non-equilibrium P. In that case we shall have not
of why there should be any systematic relationship between being a 1'
only a case oflocal instability, but also of course an instance of global
net supplier or demander of good j and having a high or low mar-
instability should the equilibrium be unique. We shall consider
ginal propensity to consume good i, then we would be inclined to say
such an example now.
that this covariance is very close to zero. This inclination would be
reinforced if the number of households was large. Of course, if this
is a satisfactory description of the world, then V(P) will indeed 6. An Example of Global lnstability
qualify as a Lyapounov function, provided the covariance ,(income
Consider an economy with three goods, one of which, say that
terms) is sufficiently small relative to the substitution terms. Here
labelled "0," can be chosen as numeraire, and we are interested in
we get additional help from the fact that the leading diagonal elements
the process described by A.ll.2, (1). When examining local stability,
in the substitution matrix of every household must be negative (if the
that is, the behavior of the system in the neighborhood of an equi-
household consumes the good in question). Hence, as far as these
librium Pt, P~, we shall wish to ensure that the real parts of the
terms are concerned, they are additive when we come to write clown
roots of - DJ(P*) are negative, if there is to be local stability.
the substitution matrix for households as a whole. We cannot but
He re
think that this term at least will greatly outweigh the income term in
practice. Of course, this is not enough for the task of proving
stability, but it helps.
The condition that the covariance must be small ensures local
stability, but it does not eritail either that the economy be either
where D is the diagonal matrix with element k1 However, if R(/.1)
Hicksian or GS or WGS or DD even in a small neighborhood ofP*, is the real part of the ith root, we know that
let alone everywhere. Moreover, if the demand Jacobian is
evaluated at P i= P*, L R(/. 1) = LZ(P*)k 1 and /. 1 /. 2 = det(- DJ(P*)).
.t1(P) = L s,(P)[m 111 (P) - m1(P)] + s(P)m(P).

Is there anything in the underlying micro-theory of economic agents


"
The smallness of the covariance term no longer allows us to that ensures that 2 Z(P*)k 1 < O and det(- DJ(P*)) > O, which is
deduce desirable properties for the Jacobian. Thus, even if the a required necessary condition for local stability?

11
298 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 299
where s,(P*) is the difference between the amount of the jth good covariance term is small for all P, this does not seem sufficient to
household h has at P* and the amount it would like to have at P*, establish a global stability result.
household h's excess supply of goodj, and m,(P*) is the household's Indeed, local stability requires us to show that the real parts of
marginal propensity to consume good i at P*. Since P* O, it is the roots of X(P*) are negative. Suppose this to be the case not only
of course true that at P*, but at all P. We might conjecture, then, that provided P(t)
,. Ls,(P*) = O. is bounded and equilibrium is unique, global stability would follow.
This we have not been able to prove.
"
This enables us to write the typical element of the income term It is not clear how interesting the small covariance case is, since,
matrix also as for instance, a stratified society may well consist of a few kinds of
households only and. the covariance terms may be large. Indeed,
.t1(P*) = Ls,(P*)[m,(P*) - m1(P*)] we must recognize that we have here a double-edged weapon, for it
"
where m1(P*) is the average marginal propensity to consume good i
would seem clear that we ought to be able to construct at least
hypothetical examples where the income terms are sufficiently large
for household as a whole. Evidently, we may interpret the fore-
relative to the substitution terms to allow us to deduce that V(P) is
going expression as a covariance. If there is no reason we can think
increasing for all non-equilibrium P. In that case we shall have not
of why there should be any systematic relationship between being a 1'
only a case oflocal instability, but also of course an instance of global
net supplier or demander of good j and having a high or low mar-
instability should the equilibrium be unique. We shall consider
ginal propensity to consume good i, then we would be inclined to say
such an example now.
that this covariance is very close to zero. This inclination would be
reinforced if the number of households was large. Of course, if this
is a satisfactory description of the world, then V(P) will indeed 6. An Example of Global lnstability
qualify as a Lyapounov function, provided the covariance ,(income
Consider an economy with three goods, one of which, say that
terms) is sufficiently small relative to the substitution terms. Here
labelled "0," can be chosen as numeraire, and we are interested in
we get additional help from the fact that the leading diagonal elements
the process described by A.ll.2, (1). When examining local stability,
in the substitution matrix of every household must be negative (if the
that is, the behavior of the system in the neighborhood of an equi-
household consumes the good in question). Hence, as far as these
librium Pt, P~, we shall wish to ensure that the real parts of the
terms are concerned, they are additive when we come to write clown
roots of - DJ(P*) are negative, if there is to be local stability.
the substitution matrix for households as a whole. We cannot but
He re
think that this term at least will greatly outweigh the income term in
practice. Of course, this is not enough for the task of proving
stability, but it helps.
The condition that the covariance must be small ensures local
stability, but it does not eritail either that the economy be either
where D is the diagonal matrix with element k1 However, if R(/.1)
Hicksian or GS or WGS or DD even in a small neighborhood ofP*, is the real part of the ith root, we know that
let alone everywhere. Moreover, if the demand Jacobian is
evaluated at P i= P*, L R(/. 1) = LZ(P*)k 1 and /. 1 /. 2 = det(- DJ(P*)).
.t1(P) = L s,(P)[m 111 (P) - m1(P)] + s(P)m(P).

Is there anything in the underlying micro-theory of economic agents


"
The smallness of the covariance term no longer allows us to that ensures that 2 Z(P*)k 1 < O and det(- DJ(P*)) > O, which is
deduce desirable properties for the Jacobian. Thus, even if the a required necessary condition for local stability?

11

11

"'
300 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 301
The answer is no, as the following example dueto GaJe illustrates. consume the goods. Here the covariance, which we have already
Suppose all households are alike and that they own 12 units of the examined, is not small. Since this has been discussed at so me length
numeraire good and nothing of the other two goods. Write the already, we shall not pursue it further.
budget constraint:
7. The Choice of Numeraire
P1x1(P) + P 2x 2 (P) ;::::; 12.
In describing an equilibrium of an economy, it does not matter
Let the utility function be given by
which good with a positive exchange value we choose as numeraire.
U(xt.x 2 ) = :28xl + 28x2 - 2xr - 3x1x?. - 2x~. (4) The question arises whether this is a1so true for the analysis of the
The reader should check that (4) gives convex indifference curves pricing process.
[although they are not strictly convex for all (x 1 ,x 2)]. In the Certainly, if the economy is Hicksian or if all goods are GS, the
economy there are stocks of the two goods given by choice of numeraire cannot in any way affect the prediction of global
stability. That this is so follows from the manner in which stability
x1 = 6 x2 = 1. for these cases was established earlier. The DD postulate is not in
These goods are held by an agent in the economy who is always the same boat, however, for there is nothing in either the theory of
willing to trade the whole of his stock against numeraire at the going household choice or the theory of producer choice that rules out the
prices. possibility that a system may ha ve DD for one choice of numeraire
, We find the unique equilibrium prices to be given by P 1 = 1, and not for another. In that case, we may find ourselves in the
P 2 = 6. Setting k 1 = k 2 = 1, situation in which we can claim the auctioneer's rule to be globally
stable for one choice of numeraire and possibly divergent for another.
_ J(P *) = _!_
56 10
[24 -60]
-11
In any event, we may be unable to prove stability for the latter.
We know that if the economy has DD for some numeraire, then
and we verify that both roots have positive real parts, so that the it mu:;t have a unique equilibrium. Here the possible lack of DD
economy is locally unstable. for some other numeraire, of course, cannot affect the claim of
In this example, good 1 is inferior at the equilibrium prices. We uniqueness. Thus, if there is some choice of numeraire that allows
easily find the marginal propensity to consume this to be -t. us to show that for no prices in the vicinity of the equilibrium is the
Moreover, this income effect is strong enough to outweigh the sub- equilibriumlocally stable, for that choice of numeraire, we shall also
stitution effect. This means that the excess demand for this good is, have shown that the auctioneer's rules are not globally stable.
at the equilibrium prices, an increasing function of its own price and Suppose there are three goods and the economy has DD when the
the undesirable consequences follow. third good is chosen as numeraire, but not when the second good is
Two points may be made. If there is only one good in the so chosen. In the first case, the Jacobian we require for local
economy to which the Giffen paradox applies, that is sufficient to analysis is given by
give an example of instability for some adjustment speeds. If one z11 (P*) zdP*))
diagonal element of -J(P*) is positive, then there is always some D ( Z21(P*) Z22(P*)
such that the sum of the diagonal elements of - DJ(P*), the trace,
is positive, which in turn implies at least one root with positive real and in the second case, it is given by
part. Secondly, it should be noted that examples can be con- zll(Q*) zls(Q*))
structed, as they have been by Scarf, such that all goods are normal ( Zsl(Q*) Zss(Q*)
for every household and yet some diagonal term (or terms) of
- DJ(P*) is positive. This is due to differences in endowments where Q* is the equilibrium price vector in terms of the second good.
between the households that have different marginal propensities to Since we are not excluding the possibility that z 33 (Q*) > O, the
1:

11

"'
300 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 301
The answer is no, as the following example dueto GaJe illustrates. consume the goods. Here the covariance, which we have already
Suppose all households are alike and that they own 12 units of the examined, is not small. Since this has been discussed at so me length
numeraire good and nothing of the other two goods. Write the already, we shall not pursue it further.
budget constraint:
7. The Choice of Numeraire
P1x1(P) + P 2x 2 (P) ;::::; 12.
In describing an equilibrium of an economy, it does not matter
Let the utility function be given by
which good with a positive exchange value we choose as numeraire.
U(xt.x 2 ) = :28xl + 28x2 - 2xr - 3x1x?. - 2x~. (4) The question arises whether this is a1so true for the analysis of the
The reader should check that (4) gives convex indifference curves pricing process.
[although they are not strictly convex for all (x 1 ,x 2)]. In the Certainly, if the economy is Hicksian or if all goods are GS, the
economy there are stocks of the two goods given by choice of numeraire cannot in any way affect the prediction of global
stability. That this is so follows from the manner in which stability
x1 = 6 x2 = 1. for these cases was established earlier. The DD postulate is not in
These goods are held by an agent in the economy who is always the same boat, however, for there is nothing in either the theory of
willing to trade the whole of his stock against numeraire at the going household choice or the theory of producer choice that rules out the
prices. possibility that a system may ha ve DD for one choice of numeraire
, We find the unique equilibrium prices to be given by P 1 = 1, and not for another. In that case, we may find ourselves in the
P 2 = 6. Setting k 1 = k 2 = 1, situation in which we can claim the auctioneer's rule to be globally
stable for one choice of numeraire and possibly divergent for another.
_ J(P *) = _!_
56 10
[24 -60]
-11
In any event, we may be unable to prove stability for the latter.
We know that if the economy has DD for some numeraire, then
and we verify that both roots have positive real parts, so that the it mu:;t have a unique equilibrium. Here the possible lack of DD
economy is locally unstable. for some other numeraire, of course, cannot affect the claim of
In this example, good 1 is inferior at the equilibrium prices. We uniqueness. Thus, if there is some choice of numeraire that allows
easily find the marginal propensity to consume this to be -t. us to show that for no prices in the vicinity of the equilibrium is the
Moreover, this income effect is strong enough to outweigh the sub- equilibriumlocally stable, for that choice of numeraire, we shall also
stitution effect. This means that the excess demand for this good is, have shown that the auctioneer's rules are not globally stable.
at the equilibrium prices, an increasing function of its own price and Suppose there are three goods and the economy has DD when the
the undesirable consequences follow. third good is chosen as numeraire, but not when the second good is
Two points may be made. If there is only one good in the so chosen. In the first case, the Jacobian we require for local
economy to which the Giffen paradox applies, that is sufficient to analysis is given by
give an example of instability for some adjustment speeds. If one z11 (P*) zdP*))
diagonal element of -J(P*) is positive, then there is always some D ( Z21(P*) Z22(P*)
such that the sum of the diagonal elements of - DJ(P*), the trace,
is positive, which in turn implies at least one root with positive real and in the second case, it is given by
part. Secondly, it should be noted that examples can be con- zll(Q*) zls(Q*))
structed, as they have been by Scarf, such that all goods are normal ( Zsl(Q*) Zss(Q*)
for every household and yet some diagonal term (or terms) of
- DJ(P*) is positive. This is due to differences in endowments where Q* is the equilibrium price vector in terms of the second good.
between the households that have different marginal propensities to Since we are not excluding the possibility that z 33 (Q*) > O, the
1:
11

302 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 303

second Jacobian may have a positive trace anda positive determinant, two rules we have examined will be successful in seeking an equi-
and thus both roots may have positive real parts and the second librium for the economy. If, for a moment, we think of the auc-
system could not then be locally stable. To clinch the case, we tioneer as a planner who is seeking the equilibrium by trial and error
would need to show by example that this sort of situation can arise and forget all about simulating market procedures, it is reasonable
for sorne utility functions and wealth holdings of households. This to enquire whether there is sorne other rule that would lead to an
indeed can be done. equilibrium whatever the fine properties of the excess-demand
Since the DD situation is the most interesting of all we have functions might be.
investigated, the sensitivity of the qualitative analysis of the tatonne- We shall not attempt to answer this question in its full generality,
ment to the choice of numeraire must be taken seriously. If we since it is a little too farfetched to merit detailed attention. We shall
leave, for the moment, the abstract world we have been inhabiting, discuss one interesting example, however.
we would be inclined to argue that insofar as the tatonnement rule Let P be the price vector in terms of numeraire. Suppose the
simulates any aspect of reality, there would in practice be no choice planner can observe not only excess-demand vector z(P) for the non-
of numeraire at all; prices would be quoted in terms of the medium numeraire goods, but also their Jacobian -J(P). If this Jacobian
of exchange. Therefore, the proper procedure is not to enquire is non-singular, the planner can calculati~ what the equilibrium price
whether the system has DD for any arbitrary numeraire, but to vector, call it Q, of the economy would be if the excess-demand
enquire whether this is the case for this particular one. This argu- functions were linear with the coefficients J(P); that is, he sol ves
ment has sorne force, but it is open to at least two objections, First
z(P) - J(P)(Q - P) = O or (Q - P) = J(P)- 1 z(P),
we must recall that the formal structure of our economy is ill-suited
in its present form to accommodate what we would regard as a which is Newton's method for solving non-linear equations.
sensible theory of money. There is no uncertainty, and above all, Of course, in general, the exces.s-demand functions are not linear.
we ha ve given the economy no time sequence of transactions. This However, the planner follows the rule of raising the price of good i
objection, then, is simply one against the importation of casual if Q1 > P 1 and lowering it when Q1 < P 1 At each stage of the
empiricism into a construction as abstract as the present one. 1t is process he must recalculate Q, which depends on P. He may
an argument for postponing the discussion of the "choice of justify this procedure simply by the argument that he is always
numeraire" until we ha ve reached the stage at which we can bring moving prices in the direction of the only approximation to equi-
empirical evidence to bear. The second objection, however, is librium that he is able to calculate.
worth noting now. lt is that in a number of actual situations, Evidently, this manner of adjusting prices will be possible in this
whatever the power of our model to accommodate them, there is in simple way only if for all P generated, J(P) is non-singular. There
fact a choice of numeraire. Thus, in the theory of the balance of are other difficulties as well. Certainly, there is no guarantee that
payments, there are evidently policy choices such as whether to use Q will always have non-negative components. 1t may be argued :

a given currency (the dollar) as the .currency in terms of which all that this does not matter so long as P O, 'Since although the 1
1

others are quoted on the market for exchange or whether to use gold planner realizes that Q with negative components cannot be an
or sorne fictional unit such as bancors for this role. Thus it may equilibrium price vector, Q1 - P 1 still indicates the direction in
well be that our laboratory procedure has uncovered a point that which P 1 should be changed. Yet if P 1 itself is zero, we certainly
may yet be of practica! relevance. But the answer to this awaits the cannot let the planner reduce it any further. 1'

stage at which it appears reasonable to draw at least tentative Suppose that

inference from the theory to the facts. j


zt(P)-+ +oo as P 1 -+ O, any i,
:1
1

1 i
'1
8. Sorne Other Auctioneer's Rules and take P(O) O. The planner follows the rule 1'
:1

We have seen that it is by no means true that, in all situations, the P = Q - P = J(P)- 1 z(P)
11

302 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 303

second Jacobian may have a positive trace anda positive determinant, two rules we have examined will be successful in seeking an equi-
and thus both roots may have positive real parts and the second librium for the economy. If, for a moment, we think of the auc-
system could not then be locally stable. To clinch the case, we tioneer as a planner who is seeking the equilibrium by trial and error
would need to show by example that this sort of situation can arise and forget all about simulating market procedures, it is reasonable
for sorne utility functions and wealth holdings of households. This to enquire whether there is sorne other rule that would lead to an
indeed can be done. equilibrium whatever the fine properties of the excess-demand
Since the DD situation is the most interesting of all we have functions might be.
investigated, the sensitivity of the qualitative analysis of the tatonne- We shall not attempt to answer this question in its full generality,
ment to the choice of numeraire must be taken seriously. If we since it is a little too farfetched to merit detailed attention. We shall
leave, for the moment, the abstract world we have been inhabiting, discuss one interesting example, however.
we would be inclined to argue that insofar as the tatonnement rule Let P be the price vector in terms of numeraire. Suppose the
simulates any aspect of reality, there would in practice be no choice planner can observe not only excess-demand vector z(P) for the non-
of numeraire at all; prices would be quoted in terms of the medium numeraire goods, but also their Jacobian -J(P). If this Jacobian
of exchange. Therefore, the proper procedure is not to enquire is non-singular, the planner can calculati~ what the equilibrium price
whether the system has DD for any arbitrary numeraire, but to vector, call it Q, of the economy would be if the excess-demand
enquire whether this is the case for this particular one. This argu- functions were linear with the coefficients J(P); that is, he sol ves
ment has sorne force, but it is open to at least two objections, First
z(P) - J(P)(Q - P) = O or (Q - P) = J(P)- 1 z(P),
we must recall that the formal structure of our economy is ill-suited
in its present form to accommodate what we would regard as a which is Newton's method for solving non-linear equations.
sensible theory of money. There is no uncertainty, and above all, Of course, in general, the exces.s-demand functions are not linear.
we ha ve given the economy no time sequence of transactions. This However, the planner follows the rule of raising the price of good i
objection, then, is simply one against the importation of casual if Q1 > P 1 and lowering it when Q1 < P 1 At each stage of the
empiricism into a construction as abstract as the present one. 1t is process he must recalculate Q, which depends on P. He may
an argument for postponing the discussion of the "choice of justify this procedure simply by the argument that he is always
numeraire" until we ha ve reached the stage at which we can bring moving prices in the direction of the only approximation to equi-
empirical evidence to bear. The second objection, however, is librium that he is able to calculate.
worth noting now. lt is that in a number of actual situations, Evidently, this manner of adjusting prices will be possible in this
whatever the power of our model to accommodate them, there is in simple way only if for all P generated, J(P) is non-singular. There
fact a choice of numeraire. Thus, in the theory of the balance of are other difficulties as well. Certainly, there is no guarantee that
payments, there are evidently policy choices such as whether to use Q will always have non-negative components. 1t may be argued :

a given currency (the dollar) as the .currency in terms of which all that this does not matter so long as P O, 'Since although the 1
1

others are quoted on the market for exchange or whether to use gold planner realizes that Q with negative components cannot be an
or sorne fictional unit such as bancors for this role. Thus it may equilibrium price vector, Q1 - P 1 still indicates the direction in
well be that our laboratory procedure has uncovered a point that which P 1 should be changed. Yet if P 1 itself is zero, we certainly
may yet be of practica! relevance. But the answer to this awaits the cannot let the planner reduce it any further. 1'

stage at which it appears reasonable to draw at least tentative Suppose that

inference from the theory to the facts. j


zt(P)-+ +oo as P 1 -+ O, any i,
:1
1

1 i
'1
8. Sorne Other Auctioneer's Rules and take P(O) O. The planner follows the rule 1'
:1

We have seen that it is by no means true that, in all situations, the P = Q - P = J(P)- 1 z(P)
e l!

111

,11

304 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 305


i:
'1

whence equilibria, they must be isolated. Moreover, for a small enough


neighborhood and J(P) uniformly bounded, the planner's rule gives
1r [z'(P)z(P)] = -2[z'(P)z(P)] :S O
j> = J(P)- 1z(P) ~ -J(P)- 1 J(P*)(P- P*).

with equality if and only ifP is an equilibrium. Then, since z'(P)z(P) Por IP- P*l small enough, J(P)- 1J(P*) must have a dominant
is never increasing, it follows from our assumption that no P 1 can diagonal, so it is easy to see that P(t) converges to P *; that is, every
approach zero during this process. equilibrium P* is locally asymptotically stable.
This argument shows also that [z'(P)z(P)] is a Lyapounov func- We already know that the adjustment process is globally stable as
tion. Therefore, the planner's procedure, under the given assump- well, so by T. 11.5, we see that there can be only one equilibrium
tions, willlead to an equilibrium, provided that P* O. '
There is yet another procedure we might take the auctioneer as
(a) A. 11.3 is satisfied;
following, a procedure that also fails to mimic the market, but
(b) the solution path is bounded.
deserves attention if for no other reason than that Walras found it
Por (a), a Lipschitz condition is sufficient (see Section 11.3 and worthy of attention. As a matter of fact, it is useful to consider it
footnote). Since z'(P)z(P) is non-increasing, the path remains in a also as an example of a process taking place in discrete rather than
compact set away from the boundaries. Hence, if we assume, as we continuous time.
did in the hypothesis of T. 11.15, that J - 1z(P) is continuously dif- We now take the auctioneer as concentrating on one market at a
ferentiable, it follows that, in the relevant region, the derivatives are time. By this we mean, in the :first place, that if the system is not in
uniformly bounded and, therefore, the Lipschitz condition must equilibrium at t, then in the time interval, (t, t + 1), only one price
certainly hold. To see (b ), note that we ha ve airead y shown that is changed. Secondly, if it is the ith price that is changed, then the
our assumptions assure that P(t) is bounded below. To ensure that auctioneer changes it to the value that, given all the other prices, will
it is bounded above and, in any case, to assure that the mli11eraire ensure that the ith market is in equilibrium. Of course, we must
process can lead to an equilibrium, we made the numeraire assump- assume that one such value of the price exists, and we shall :find it
tion A.11.2. This implies that as IP(t)l--+ +co the excess demand safe to assume also that there is only one such value. Pormally, if
for the numeraire good goes to plus infinity. Then, by W and IIPII this process started at t = O, then the price vector at m will be
large enough, [z'(P)z(P)] must be increasing if IIPII increases further,
p(m) = {Pt(1),p2(2) 'Pm(m), Pm+l(O) Pn(O)},
and this we know to be impossible.
We have shown, therefore, that under fairly restrictive conditions, where we have supposed that the markets are numbered in the order
which, however, do not by themselves imply any of the stability in which they attract the attention of the auctioneer and that if one
conditions so far discussed, there exists a price adjustment process of these is in equilibrium, then prices do not change at all for one
that ensures stability. It is important to note that this is not a period.
process that mimicks the invisible hand-for instance, the price of It is fairly clear that this sequential price adjustment method will
a good may be raised even though it is in excess supply. not converge to an equilibrium for all possible forms of the excess-
The most restrictive of the conditions is that that requires J(P) to demand functions. But it is not hard to show that making someof
be non-singular for all P. To clarify this, we show that the assump- the now very familiar assumptions, such as GS, will be sufficient to
tion implies that there is a unique equilibrium with P O. (This is ensure stability. Thus stipulate GS. Consider the jth market at
the promised proof of T.9. 15.) time t. Let M(p) = max(p1 - 1), m(p) = min(p1 - 1), where, as
Certainly, if J(P*) is non-singular at sorne equilibrium P* O, usual in such a case, we take the unit vector e as the unique equilib-
then by a classical result in analysis there cannot be another equi- rium of the economy. Suppose that in order to bring the jth
librium in a small neighborhood of P*; that is, if there are many market into equilibrium the auctioneer has to choose p(t + 1)
e l!

111

,11

304 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 305


i:
'1

whence equilibria, they must be isolated. Moreover, for a small enough


neighborhood and J(P) uniformly bounded, the planner's rule gives
1r [z'(P)z(P)] = -2[z'(P)z(P)] :S O
j> = J(P)- 1z(P) ~ -J(P)- 1 J(P*)(P- P*).

with equality if and only ifP is an equilibrium. Then, since z'(P)z(P) Por IP- P*l small enough, J(P)- 1J(P*) must have a dominant
is never increasing, it follows from our assumption that no P 1 can diagonal, so it is easy to see that P(t) converges to P *; that is, every
approach zero during this process. equilibrium P* is locally asymptotically stable.
This argument shows also that [z'(P)z(P)] is a Lyapounov func- We already know that the adjustment process is globally stable as
tion. Therefore, the planner's procedure, under the given assump- well, so by T. 11.5, we see that there can be only one equilibrium
tions, willlead to an equilibrium, provided that P* O. '
There is yet another procedure we might take the auctioneer as
(a) A. 11.3 is satisfied;
following, a procedure that also fails to mimic the market, but
(b) the solution path is bounded.
deserves attention if for no other reason than that Walras found it
Por (a), a Lipschitz condition is sufficient (see Section 11.3 and worthy of attention. As a matter of fact, it is useful to consider it
footnote). Since z'(P)z(P) is non-increasing, the path remains in a also as an example of a process taking place in discrete rather than
compact set away from the boundaries. Hence, if we assume, as we continuous time.
did in the hypothesis of T. 11.15, that J - 1z(P) is continuously dif- We now take the auctioneer as concentrating on one market at a
ferentiable, it follows that, in the relevant region, the derivatives are time. By this we mean, in the :first place, that if the system is not in
uniformly bounded and, therefore, the Lipschitz condition must equilibrium at t, then in the time interval, (t, t + 1), only one price
certainly hold. To see (b ), note that we ha ve airead y shown that is changed. Secondly, if it is the ith price that is changed, then the
our assumptions assure that P(t) is bounded below. To ensure that auctioneer changes it to the value that, given all the other prices, will
it is bounded above and, in any case, to assure that the mli11eraire ensure that the ith market is in equilibrium. Of course, we must
process can lead to an equilibrium, we made the numeraire assump- assume that one such value of the price exists, and we shall :find it
tion A.11.2. This implies that as IP(t)l--+ +co the excess demand safe to assume also that there is only one such value. Pormally, if
for the numeraire good goes to plus infinity. Then, by W and IIPII this process started at t = O, then the price vector at m will be
large enough, [z'(P)z(P)] must be increasing if IIPII increases further,
p(m) = {Pt(1),p2(2) 'Pm(m), Pm+l(O) Pn(O)},
and this we know to be impossible.
We have shown, therefore, that under fairly restrictive conditions, where we have supposed that the markets are numbered in the order
which, however, do not by themselves imply any of the stability in which they attract the attention of the auctioneer and that if one
conditions so far discussed, there exists a price adjustment process of these is in equilibrium, then prices do not change at all for one
that ensures stability. It is important to note that this is not a period.
process that mimicks the invisible hand-for instance, the price of It is fairly clear that this sequential price adjustment method will
a good may be raised even though it is in excess supply. not converge to an equilibrium for all possible forms of the excess-
The most restrictive of the conditions is that that requires J(P) to demand functions. But it is not hard to show that making someof
be non-singular for all P. To clarify this, we show that the assump- the now very familiar assumptions, such as GS, will be sufficient to
tion implies that there is a unique equilibrium with P O. (This is ensure stability. Thus stipulate GS. Consider the jth market at
the promised proof of T.9. 15.) time t. Let M(p) = max(p1 - 1), m(p) = min(p1 - 1), where, as
Certainly, if J(P*) is non-singular at sorne equilibrium P* O, usual in such a case, we take the unit vector e as the unique equilib-
then by a classical result in analysis there cannot be another equi- rium of the economy. Suppose that in order to bring the jth
librium in a small neighborhood of P*; that is, if there are many market into equilibrium the auctioneer has to choose p(t + 1)
306 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-1 RECONTRACTING 307
such that (p(t + 1) - 1) M[p(t)]. Then, by T.9.8, since the market-imitative A.11.1 and A.12.2, but for discrete time. In par-
jth price would exceed its equilibrium value in the greatest propor- ticular, consider the rule
tion, it must be that z1[p(t + 1)] < O, contradicting the manner
in which the auctioneer has been supposed to determine the p 1(t + 1) = max{O,p1(t) + kz1(p(t))} k> o, (5)
th price. By the same argument, it is not possible to have :Vhich is reminiscent of the mapping whose fixed point was discussed
(Plt + 1) - 1) :::; m[p(t)]. Hence, certainly the price solution must ll1 C~apter 2. Evidently, (5) ensures that prices are always non-
be bounded since no price can ever exceed its equilibrium by more negatiVe. We shall not investigate this process for all of our cases
than M[p(O)] or fall short ofit by more than m[p(O)]. Also M(p) - since we are mainly interested in one particular lesson, which we ca~
m(p) is a Lyapounov function and so stability follows. learn by taking the GS situation only.
It can be readily seen also that similar results can be established As usual, the units we choose to measure goods allow us to write
with a strictly positive equilibrium for the case of DD when this the unique eq~ilib.rium as e. .we consider V(p) = (p - e)(p - e)'
property holds at all prices for sorne particular choice of units in to see whether It w1ll make a smtable Lyapounov function. We take
which to measure goods. Letting M'(p) = max(p1 - 1)/h1 and p(O) O and note ~hat because of GS we may take p(t) O, all t,
similarly modifying the definition of m(p), we can argue in exactly beca use the good w1th the lowest price at t must be in excess demand.
the same way as we did in the case of GS. If, say, it were true that Now what we wish to show, of course, is that for all p(t) i= e,
the auctioneer has io choose p1 such that (p(t + 1) - 1)fh1
M'(p(t)), then it must be true that we can find a sequence of prices V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] < O.
pv starting at e such that, at all v, This evidently enables us to kill two birds with one stone: The

1 1 solution path of price will be bounded and V will indeed be a
E>
-
IP1 -hPt- 1 >
_
IP! - hPl'- 1
all i, L~apounov function. But V(p(t)) = J.,pr(t) - 2 J.,p 1(t) + n, where
1''
1

1 n 1s the number of goods. By (5) and W, we have


where this sequence converges to p(t + 1). Then, at each step of
this sequence, it follows from DD that, if E is sufficiently small,
.2; [p(t + 1)] 2
= l;Pt(t) + k 2 .2; zt[p(t)],
so that

and since z1(p 0 ) = O, we again have a contradiction of the supposed


manner in which the auctioneer determines prices. A similar and
argumentholds,ofcourse,toensurethat[p(t + 1)- 1]fh1 > m'(p). V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] = k2 .2; zf(p(t)) - 2 .2; [p(t + 1) - p 1(t)].
The proofthatthe rule now under consideration will also be stable
if the economy is Hicksian is left to the reader. The rule does not By (5),
seem to permit a proof of stability for any cases that might be .2; [ p (t + 1)
1 - p 1(t)] = k L z(p(t))
regarded as less restrictive than those we considered for the "normal"
rules. Indeed, this successive tatonnement procedure has rather and so finally,
little to recommend it. Not only does it not imitate the market, but V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] = k 2 .2; zf[p(t)] - kez[p(t)].
it is doubtful whether it imitates an efficient computational program
for finding an equilibrium. It is, in fact, what is known as a Gauss- We know, however, that since all goods are GS, it must be that
Seidel method of solving a set of simultaneous equations, a method ez[p(t)] > O for all p(t) i= e by T.9.9. Consider the ratio
that is not particularly attractive as a computational means.
r[p(t)] = ez[p(t2J_ p(t) i= e,
To conclude this section on alternative rules, let us return to the ez 2 [p(t)]
306 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITI-1 RECONTRACTING 307
such that (p(t + 1) - 1) M[p(t)]. Then, by T.9.8, since the market-imitative A.11.1 and A.12.2, but for discrete time. In par-
jth price would exceed its equilibrium value in the greatest propor- ticular, consider the rule
tion, it must be that z1[p(t + 1)] < O, contradicting the manner
in which the auctioneer has been supposed to determine the p 1(t + 1) = max{O,p1(t) + kz1(p(t))} k> o, (5)
th price. By the same argument, it is not possible to have :Vhich is reminiscent of the mapping whose fixed point was discussed
(Plt + 1) - 1) :::; m[p(t)]. Hence, certainly the price solution must ll1 C~apter 2. Evidently, (5) ensures that prices are always non-
be bounded since no price can ever exceed its equilibrium by more negatiVe. We shall not investigate this process for all of our cases
than M[p(O)] or fall short ofit by more than m[p(O)]. Also M(p) - since we are mainly interested in one particular lesson, which we ca~
m(p) is a Lyapounov function and so stability follows. learn by taking the GS situation only.
It can be readily seen also that similar results can be established As usual, the units we choose to measure goods allow us to write
with a strictly positive equilibrium for the case of DD when this the unique eq~ilib.rium as e. .we consider V(p) = (p - e)(p - e)'
property holds at all prices for sorne particular choice of units in to see whether It w1ll make a smtable Lyapounov function. We take
which to measure goods. Letting M'(p) = max(p1 - 1)/h1 and p(O) O and note ~hat because of GS we may take p(t) O, all t,
similarly modifying the definition of m(p), we can argue in exactly beca use the good w1th the lowest price at t must be in excess demand.
the same way as we did in the case of GS. If, say, it were true that Now what we wish to show, of course, is that for all p(t) i= e,
the auctioneer has io choose p1 such that (p(t + 1) - 1)fh1
M'(p(t)), then it must be true that we can find a sequence of prices V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] < O.
pv starting at e such that, at all v, This evidently enables us to kill two birds with one stone: The

1 1 solution path of price will be bounded and V will indeed be a
E>
-
IP1 -hPt- 1 >
_
IP! - hPl'- 1
all i, L~apounov function. But V(p(t)) = J.,pr(t) - 2 J.,p 1(t) + n, where
1''
1

1 n 1s the number of goods. By (5) and W, we have


where this sequence converges to p(t + 1). Then, at each step of
this sequence, it follows from DD that, if E is sufficiently small,
.2; [p(t + 1)] 2
= l;Pt(t) + k 2 .2; zt[p(t)],
so that

and since z1(p 0 ) = O, we again have a contradiction of the supposed


manner in which the auctioneer determines prices. A similar and
argumentholds,ofcourse,toensurethat[p(t + 1)- 1]fh1 > m'(p). V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] = k2 .2; zf(p(t)) - 2 .2; [p(t + 1) - p 1(t)].
The proofthatthe rule now under consideration will also be stable
if the economy is Hicksian is left to the reader. The rule does not By (5),
seem to permit a proof of stability for any cases that might be .2; [ p (t + 1)
1 - p 1(t)] = k L z(p(t))
regarded as less restrictive than those we considered for the "normal"
rules. Indeed, this successive tatonnement procedure has rather and so finally,
little to recommend it. Not only does it not imitate the market, but V[p(t + 1)] - V[p(t)] = k 2 .2; zf[p(t)] - kez[p(t)].
it is doubtful whether it imitates an efficient computational program
for finding an equilibrium. It is, in fact, what is known as a Gauss- We know, however, that since all goods are GS, it must be that
Seidel method of solving a set of simultaneous equations, a method ez[p(t)] > O for all p(t) i= e by T.9.9. Consider the ratio
that is not particularly attractive as a computational means.
r[p(t)] = ez[p(t2J_ p(t) i= e,
To conclude this section on alternative rules, let us return to the ez 2 [p(t)]
308 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 309
where the denominator vector z2 has components zf. Clearly it may well be the artificial restriction we have imposed on the
r[p(t)] > O and, therefore, must be bounded away from zero for all problem, namely that there shall be no transactions out of equi-
non-equilibrium p*. Iibrium, that is at least partly responsible for our predicament. Is it
Let R = {p j[z(p)[ :2: E, E > 0}. Then, from what has been not reasonable to suppose that when exchange is permitted at aii p,
said, we may choose k* such that k* < (r(p)) for pE R. Inserting it will take place only if it is to the advantage of the transactors and,
k* in (5) shows that V[p(t)] will be monotonically declining for all therefore, that in such a world we may hope to use the utility
p(t) E R. Hence, for Tlarge enough, [z[p(t)][ < E, all t > T. Thus indicators of households as our Lyapounov function as we use that
there is a choice of k* such that prices converge to any given small of the fictional household in the Hicksian case? These matters will
neighborhood of the equilibrium. be discussed in Chapter 13 and we reserve judgment until then.
The lesson we seem to have learned is that in the finite time
adjustment rule stability depends on the fine properties of the
9. Short-Period Equilibrium
adjustment rule itself even when so convenient a hypothesis as GS
is made. This is in marked contrast to what we found to be true in So far our analysis can well apply to an abstract economy with aii
the continuous time case. It is not hard to see that this conclusion possible futures markets. Of course, this makes it even more
does not really depend on the manner in which we choose to try to remote from reality. It is worthwhile to enquire whether sorne of
prove the stability of the process. If we take the set of all p, our results will survive a change in model that is designed to aiiow
such that [p - e[ = E, then for that set there will be sorne p' that for the possibility that the only way of undertaking intertemporal
maximizes r(p). Ifwe then choose k > r(p), it will be true that V(p) transactions may be by means of storage of one or more goods.
is increasing at every point of that set of prices. Then, if [p(O) - e[ This probably errs on the side of pessimism as to the existence of
> E, it is clear that the adjustment process could never return us to futures markets.
the equilibrium. This is a sad Iesson. So far we have been content We shaii consider a pure-exchange economy because it is simpler
to Jet the auctioneer imita te the market in the sense of raising prices and beca use if such an economy permits a stable adjustment process,
in response to excess demand, and so on, but of course, any proper then under the usual assumpton on the production set, a more
imitation would also have to take account of the lag structures we realistic construction will also have this property. We suppose that
1 find in the world. Given the great variety of these structures and time is divided into the present, a finite time interval, and the future,
,1 given the lesson just Iearned, it is fairly clear that we shall not be also a finite time interval. The only good that may be transferred
1 able to predict, in general, stability of any such process from a from the present to the future is the good with the index n. The
, knowledge only of the kinds of excess-demand functions with which price vector rulng in the present is written as p. Households are
we are dealing. Such knowledge will still be relevant and helpful; assumed also to form expectatons as to the prices that will rule in
:1'
it just will not be sufficient. the future. We assume that they do not subdivide the future into
There is a notable exception to this conclusion, however, namely smaller time periods and write q as the price vector expected to rule
the case of the Hicksian economy. In such an economy any rule over the entire future. At this stage, we do not distinguish between
that raises the prices of goods in excess demand and lowers those of the expectations of the various households and take it that they are
goods in excess supply must, whatever the lag structure, serve to all the same. We are conccrned only with the excess-demand
Iower the utility of the fictionl household whose behavior we may vector of the present, which, as usual, we write as z, but it willnow
take as generating the actual excess demands we observe. There- depend not only on p, but al so on q: z(p,q) is the excess-demand
fore, we may take this household's utility function as our Lyapounov vector at p and q. It is homogeneous of degree zero in these argu-
function. Of course, the Hicksian case is exceptional. But the ments and W holds: pz(p,q) = O. We also take it to be differen-
argument showing that, for that case, stability is assured for a wide tiable where required. In Chapter 2 we discussed an economy of
variety of lag structures in the adjustment mechanism suggests that which the present one is a special instance. We showed that if we
308 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 309
where the denominator vector z2 has components zf. Clearly it may well be the artificial restriction we have imposed on the
r[p(t)] > O and, therefore, must be bounded away from zero for all problem, namely that there shall be no transactions out of equi-
non-equilibrium p*. Iibrium, that is at least partly responsible for our predicament. Is it
Let R = {p j[z(p)[ :2: E, E > 0}. Then, from what has been not reasonable to suppose that when exchange is permitted at aii p,
said, we may choose k* such that k* < (r(p)) for pE R. Inserting it will take place only if it is to the advantage of the transactors and,
k* in (5) shows that V[p(t)] will be monotonically declining for all therefore, that in such a world we may hope to use the utility
p(t) E R. Hence, for Tlarge enough, [z[p(t)][ < E, all t > T. Thus indicators of households as our Lyapounov function as we use that
there is a choice of k* such that prices converge to any given small of the fictional household in the Hicksian case? These matters will
neighborhood of the equilibrium. be discussed in Chapter 13 and we reserve judgment until then.
The lesson we seem to have learned is that in the finite time
adjustment rule stability depends on the fine properties of the
9. Short-Period Equilibrium
adjustment rule itself even when so convenient a hypothesis as GS
is made. This is in marked contrast to what we found to be true in So far our analysis can well apply to an abstract economy with aii
the continuous time case. It is not hard to see that this conclusion possible futures markets. Of course, this makes it even more
does not really depend on the manner in which we choose to try to remote from reality. It is worthwhile to enquire whether sorne of
prove the stability of the process. If we take the set of all p, our results will survive a change in model that is designed to aiiow
such that [p - e[ = E, then for that set there will be sorne p' that for the possibility that the only way of undertaking intertemporal
maximizes r(p). Ifwe then choose k > r(p), it will be true that V(p) transactions may be by means of storage of one or more goods.
is increasing at every point of that set of prices. Then, if [p(O) - e[ This probably errs on the side of pessimism as to the existence of
> E, it is clear that the adjustment process could never return us to futures markets.
the equilibrium. This is a sad Iesson. So far we have been content We shaii consider a pure-exchange economy because it is simpler
to Jet the auctioneer imita te the market in the sense of raising prices and beca use if such an economy permits a stable adjustment process,
in response to excess demand, and so on, but of course, any proper then under the usual assumpton on the production set, a more
imitation would also have to take account of the lag structures we realistic construction will also have this property. We suppose that
1 find in the world. Given the great variety of these structures and time is divided into the present, a finite time interval, and the future,
,1 given the lesson just Iearned, it is fairly clear that we shall not be also a finite time interval. The only good that may be transferred
1 able to predict, in general, stability of any such process from a from the present to the future is the good with the index n. The
, knowledge only of the kinds of excess-demand functions with which price vector rulng in the present is written as p. Households are
we are dealing. Such knowledge will still be relevant and helpful; assumed also to form expectatons as to the prices that will rule in
:1'
it just will not be sufficient. the future. We assume that they do not subdivide the future into
There is a notable exception to this conclusion, however, namely smaller time periods and write q as the price vector expected to rule
the case of the Hicksian economy. In such an economy any rule over the entire future. At this stage, we do not distinguish between
that raises the prices of goods in excess demand and lowers those of the expectations of the various households and take it that they are
goods in excess supply must, whatever the lag structure, serve to all the same. We are conccrned only with the excess-demand
Iower the utility of the fictionl household whose behavior we may vector of the present, which, as usual, we write as z, but it willnow
take as generating the actual excess demands we observe. There- depend not only on p, but al so on q: z(p,q) is the excess-demand
fore, we may take this household's utility function as our Lyapounov vector at p and q. It is homogeneous of degree zero in these argu-
function. Of course, the Hicksian case is exceptional. But the ments and W holds: pz(p,q) = O. We also take it to be differen-
argument showing that, for that case, stability is assured for a wide tiable where required. In Chapter 2 we discussed an economy of
variety of lag structures in the adjustment mechanism suggests that which the present one is a special instance. We showed that if we
!,
'~ '

,H:
11

'"
11
310 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 311

111, can take q to be a continuous function of p, there wou1d then exist Let
11!1
a p* such that the economy is in equilibrium in the present. We do V(p,q) = max z1(p,q),
:rl not enquire how it will fare in the future. We shall refer to this i
"' a function that is positive for all non-equilibrium p. We write
economy as the short-period economy (SP).
The auctioneer operates in the present on the basis of the excess Ztn+J = 8zf8q1 and take it for granted that all the partials are
demands observable to him in the present. This may cause a evaluated at (p,q). Also m is the set of i for which z1(p,q) = V(p,q),
conceptual difficulty. Is it possible to say that the auctioneer's rule and N is the set of i for which z1(p,q) < O. Then we have, for any i,
is stable, when that notion, seems to imply time going to infinity and
Z = L.
"'
zifp 1z 1 + L.
"'
z 1,n+Jq11p 1z1 W here q1 dq j
= T'
we are confining ourselves to a finite time interval? The answer is j 1 'Pi
that we have used time as an expository device so far; what is really Then for i E m, it must be that
at stake is that the number of steps-price changes undertaken by
the auctioneer-goes to infinity, and that is clearly possible in a
finite time interval. While in a formal way we can avoid being silly,
Z < L
1$N
ZtJPJZj + L
Jf;N
Zt,n+jqeZ ::;; V(p,q)(L
J<I;N
Zpj + L
Jrf;N
zl,n+Jqje),

it is true that in practice price adjustments do take time and that if


where the strict inequality follows from the fact that out of equilib-
the tatonnement is to be taken seriously as in sorne sense connected
rium, N cannot be empty in view of W and GS. Then, using H, it
with reality, then it must face the objection that even if the process
is surely true 1 that for all i E m, z < O, provided that
is stable it is only asymptotically that equilibrium is attained. We
shall take the formal way out of the difficulty and continue to use e1 ::;; 1 all j and all (p,q) O.
time differentials, although these must be taken to refer to steps. Thus, certainly V is declining for all non-equilibrium prices if that
Let us consider the simple adjustment process (II) and take all condition holds. We know that the path of p is bounded, so since
goods to be GS. Here "all goods" includes future goods . .We q is a continuous function ofp, it must be that q is also bounded and,
take p(O) O, and the usual argument will show that p(t) ' O all t hence, certainly V(p,q) is a Lyapounov function.
so that (II) does not run into difficulties. We also postulate the Since we may write q = q(p), we may also write z[p,q(p)] = Z(p),
following simple expectation formation mechanisms: say. But Z will have H in p if all e1 = 1 and it will have DD if
sorne e1 < 1 and no e1 > l. The reader should check this by
q1 >O whenp1 >O. (E) differentiating z and using the known property H for z(p,q) in (p,q).
Thus we make the price expected to rule for thejth good in the future Hence, for these cases, the economy has a unique equilibrium since
dependent only on the price called for that good by the auctioneer in our theorems on GS apply to Z(p) if it has H and our theorems on
the present. Here the word "rule" should be interpreted as the DD apply to Z(p) if it does not. We have therefore proved
expected equilibrium price of the future, that is, the price at which THEOREM 9. Let an SP economy have the expectation formation E
households expect to be able to transact then. The assumption with e1(p,q) ::;; 1, all (p,q). Then the economy has a unique short-
evidently has no very great appeal, but it will serve in allowing us to period equilibrium if all goods are GS. Por p(O) O, and the
learn sorne of the most important economic lessons that arise in auctioneer's rule (II), p* is globally stable. '
these constructions. We shall also be making use of the Hicksian 1
By H,
elasticity of expectations e, which, of course, is given by Zp L Zp + L Zt,n+lql
+ .;. = 0.
d !og q1 All the terms under the summation signs are positive by GS. Hence, since
e= dlogp ' N is not empty and ~ 1,
1

To be able to utilize this concept we take all the expectation forma- L Zpf + HN
ION
L Zt,n+fqEj < 0.
tion functions to be differentiable. But V(p,q) > O.
!,
'~ '

,H:
11

'"
11
310 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 311

111, can take q to be a continuous function of p, there wou1d then exist Let
11!1
a p* such that the economy is in equilibrium in the present. We do V(p,q) = max z1(p,q),
:rl not enquire how it will fare in the future. We shall refer to this i
"' a function that is positive for all non-equilibrium p. We write
economy as the short-period economy (SP).
The auctioneer operates in the present on the basis of the excess Ztn+J = 8zf8q1 and take it for granted that all the partials are
demands observable to him in the present. This may cause a evaluated at (p,q). Also m is the set of i for which z1(p,q) = V(p,q),
conceptual difficulty. Is it possible to say that the auctioneer's rule and N is the set of i for which z1(p,q) < O. Then we have, for any i,
is stable, when that notion, seems to imply time going to infinity and
Z = L.
"'
zifp 1z 1 + L.
"'
z 1,n+Jq11p 1z1 W here q1 dq j
= T'
we are confining ourselves to a finite time interval? The answer is j 1 'Pi
that we have used time as an expository device so far; what is really Then for i E m, it must be that
at stake is that the number of steps-price changes undertaken by
the auctioneer-goes to infinity, and that is clearly possible in a
finite time interval. While in a formal way we can avoid being silly,
Z < L
1$N
ZtJPJZj + L
Jf;N
Zt,n+jqeZ ::;; V(p,q)(L
J<I;N
Zpj + L
Jrf;N
zl,n+Jqje),

it is true that in practice price adjustments do take time and that if


where the strict inequality follows from the fact that out of equilib-
the tatonnement is to be taken seriously as in sorne sense connected
rium, N cannot be empty in view of W and GS. Then, using H, it
with reality, then it must face the objection that even if the process
is surely true 1 that for all i E m, z < O, provided that
is stable it is only asymptotically that equilibrium is attained. We
shall take the formal way out of the difficulty and continue to use e1 ::;; 1 all j and all (p,q) O.
time differentials, although these must be taken to refer to steps. Thus, certainly V is declining for all non-equilibrium prices if that
Let us consider the simple adjustment process (II) and take all condition holds. We know that the path of p is bounded, so since
goods to be GS. Here "all goods" includes future goods . .We q is a continuous function ofp, it must be that q is also bounded and,
take p(O) O, and the usual argument will show that p(t) ' O all t hence, certainly V(p,q) is a Lyapounov function.
so that (II) does not run into difficulties. We also postulate the Since we may write q = q(p), we may also write z[p,q(p)] = Z(p),
following simple expectation formation mechanisms: say. But Z will have H in p if all e1 = 1 and it will have DD if
sorne e1 < 1 and no e1 > l. The reader should check this by
q1 >O whenp1 >O. (E) differentiating z and using the known property H for z(p,q) in (p,q).
Thus we make the price expected to rule for thejth good in the future Hence, for these cases, the economy has a unique equilibrium since
dependent only on the price called for that good by the auctioneer in our theorems on GS apply to Z(p) if it has H and our theorems on
the present. Here the word "rule" should be interpreted as the DD apply to Z(p) if it does not. We have therefore proved
expected equilibrium price of the future, that is, the price at which THEOREM 9. Let an SP economy have the expectation formation E
households expect to be able to transact then. The assumption with e1(p,q) ::;; 1, all (p,q). Then the economy has a unique short-
evidently has no very great appeal, but it will serve in allowing us to period equilibrium if all goods are GS. Por p(O) O, and the
learn sorne of the most important economic lessons that arise in auctioneer's rule (II), p* is globally stable. '
these constructions. We shall also be making use of the Hicksian 1
By H,
elasticity of expectations e, which, of course, is given by Zp L Zp + L Zt,n+lql
+ .;. = 0.
d !og q1 All the terms under the summation signs are positive by GS. Hence, since
e= dlogp ' N is not empty and ~ 1,
1

To be able to utilize this concept we take all the expectation forma- L Zpf + HN
ION
L Zt,n+fqEj < 0.
tion functions to be differentiable. But V(p,q) > O.
312 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 313

It is quite easy to show that an exactly similar theorem can be functions and on the rule followed by the auctioneer. In particular,
established for the case of DD, provided this property holds for units "i :::; 1, all j, is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for
in which goods are measured that are independent of (p,q) and stability. That it is not sufficient follows from the fact that we can
provided we may take it that p(t) O, all t. This is just a simple easily construct an example for Z(p) with E/s obeying the restriction
exercise in the method just described and we shall not spell it out imposed, but nonetheless it is a case of instability. That it is not
beyond noting that the appropriate Vis then max ztfht where h; has necessary follows from our manner of proof of T.l2.9. If we had
the usual meaning. lt is also interesting to note that these results information on the upper bounds of the parta! coefficients of the
can still be shown to hold by exactly the same method of proof if we excess-demand function, then stability might be established for
replace (II) by logically possible cases with "i > 1, so me j. This is quite an
important point to understand since there is often talk in economics
of destabilizing expectations when all that is meant is that the
(II')
elasticity of expectation may somewhere exceed unity. After all, it
is common sense to enquire how expected prices enter into present
In that case the appropriate form of Vis max G;. Insofar as we take excess demands befo re assenting to the adjective "destabilizing."
' i
' 1 the auctioneer as imitating the market, it would seem that (II') has Indeed,. the SP economy is very rich in qualitative possibilities and
'1'
a good deal to recommend it. Curiously enough, it does not seem it seems rather doubtful that any either very simple or very general
possible to extend all these results to the Hicksian case. The stability propositions can be proved.
utility function ofthe fictional household with which we have worked Although we have determined not to examine a catalog of expecta-
in this case in the past will not do now as a Lyapounov function. tion hypotheses, there is one to which we must briefly pay some
The reason is simply that while the auctioneer's rule, as usual, serves attention because it is often used. We imagine the typical household
to make the fictional household worse off, the consequential adjust- to have a memory of all the prices that have been called by the
ment in expected price may make it better off. Thus, if the house- auctioneer and to formulate its expectations as to the prices that wiii
hold plans an excess demand for a good in the present and an excess rule in the future by taking an exponentially weighted average of past
supply of the good in the future, the rise in present price will make observed prices. In such an artificial setting, this assumption
it worse off, but the consequential rise in expected price will make it probably does not command much credence, but since matters are
better off. There may be a way of showing stability for the Hicksian otherwise in other settings, it is not without interest to consider it
case also, but we have not been able to find it. here. Accordingly, we postulate
Now it is not at all hard to think of alternative expectation forma-
tion hypotheses and no do u bt a good many "theorems" could be
fki o. (E')
generated. It does not seem appropriate to attempt a fuller catalog We refer to expectations formed according to (E') as adaptive. On
of possibilities here, especially since it seems Iikely that we already integrating this expression we find that the expected price is an
have sufficient to draw the qualitative moral that is likely to apply to exponentially weighted average of past prices. Note that .1 = oo
all cases. This moral is that, contrary to what was proposed in implies q1 = Pt> all t, a case often referred to as "stationary expecta-
Value and Capital, 1 we cannot draw any stability conclusions from tions." We, may interpret all this to mean that the price expected
knowledge of the expectation formation hypothesis alone. To do to rule in the future is the same as that expected to be called "next"
so we require information also on the form of the excess-demand by the auctioneer, so that if the actual price differs from the one
expected in the future, it also differs from the. one expected to be
1
"Technically, then, the case where elasticities of expectation are equal to called next. It is here that the artificiality of the construct is most
unity marks the dividing !in e between stability and instabi!ity." Hicks
[1939, p. 255]. Hicks, of course, was concerned with stability in a different apparent since, as a matter of plain common sense, no household can
sense than used here. have any interest in predicting what price will be called next by the
312 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
r STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 313

It is quite easy to show that an exactly similar theorem can be functions and on the rule followed by the auctioneer. In particular,
established for the case of DD, provided this property holds for units "i :::; 1, all j, is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for
in which goods are measured that are independent of (p,q) and stability. That it is not sufficient follows from the fact that we can
provided we may take it that p(t) O, all t. This is just a simple easily construct an example for Z(p) with E/s obeying the restriction
exercise in the method just described and we shall not spell it out imposed, but nonetheless it is a case of instability. That it is not
beyond noting that the appropriate Vis then max ztfht where h; has necessary follows from our manner of proof of T.l2.9. If we had
the usual meaning. lt is also interesting to note that these results information on the upper bounds of the parta! coefficients of the
can still be shown to hold by exactly the same method of proof if we excess-demand function, then stability might be established for
replace (II) by logically possible cases with "i > 1, so me j. This is quite an
important point to understand since there is often talk in economics
of destabilizing expectations when all that is meant is that the
(II')
elasticity of expectation may somewhere exceed unity. After all, it
is common sense to enquire how expected prices enter into present
In that case the appropriate form of Vis max G;. Insofar as we take excess demands befo re assenting to the adjective "destabilizing."
' i
' 1 the auctioneer as imitating the market, it would seem that (II') has Indeed,. the SP economy is very rich in qualitative possibilities and
'1'
a good deal to recommend it. Curiously enough, it does not seem it seems rather doubtful that any either very simple or very general
possible to extend all these results to the Hicksian case. The stability propositions can be proved.
utility function ofthe fictional household with which we have worked Although we have determined not to examine a catalog of expecta-
in this case in the past will not do now as a Lyapounov function. tion hypotheses, there is one to which we must briefly pay some
The reason is simply that while the auctioneer's rule, as usual, serves attention because it is often used. We imagine the typical household
to make the fictional household worse off, the consequential adjust- to have a memory of all the prices that have been called by the
ment in expected price may make it better off. Thus, if the house- auctioneer and to formulate its expectations as to the prices that wiii
hold plans an excess demand for a good in the present and an excess rule in the future by taking an exponentially weighted average of past
supply of the good in the future, the rise in present price will make observed prices. In such an artificial setting, this assumption
it worse off, but the consequential rise in expected price will make it probably does not command much credence, but since matters are
better off. There may be a way of showing stability for the Hicksian otherwise in other settings, it is not without interest to consider it
case also, but we have not been able to find it. here. Accordingly, we postulate
Now it is not at all hard to think of alternative expectation forma-
tion hypotheses and no do u bt a good many "theorems" could be
fki o. (E')
generated. It does not seem appropriate to attempt a fuller catalog We refer to expectations formed according to (E') as adaptive. On
of possibilities here, especially since it seems Iikely that we already integrating this expression we find that the expected price is an
have sufficient to draw the qualitative moral that is likely to apply to exponentially weighted average of past prices. Note that .1 = oo
all cases. This moral is that, contrary to what was proposed in implies q1 = Pt> all t, a case often referred to as "stationary expecta-
Value and Capital, 1 we cannot draw any stability conclusions from tions." We, may interpret all this to mean that the price expected
knowledge of the expectation formation hypothesis alone. To do to rule in the future is the same as that expected to be called "next"
so we require information also on the form of the excess-demand by the auctioneer, so that if the actual price differs from the one
expected in the future, it also differs from the. one expected to be
1
"Technically, then, the case where elasticities of expectation are equal to called next. It is here that the artificiality of the construct is most
unity marks the dividing !in e between stability and instabi!ity." Hicks
[1939, p. 255]. Hicks, of course, was concerned with stability in a different apparent since, as a matter of plain common sense, no household can
sense than used here. have any interest in predicting what price will be called next by the
l"

314 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 315
auctioneer. In any event, we note that equilibrium requires q = p. Let
Moreover, if we start in the vicinity of an equilibrium, then since .,1
Z
cannot exceed infinity, q can at most change in the same proportions -=V
as p, so that in the appropriate sense, the e1asticity of the previous Pi
discussion can never exceed unity. This is the important point to suppose that
remember when we show thaLin the GS case stability is assured to V(p,q) = Vr # O.
rule (1) whatever the precise value of .,1 may be. Adaptive expec-
By W, Vr > O. A1so
tations are conservative in the sense of Hicks, and in view of the
foregoing, the result should cause no surprise nor tempt us into un- V(p,q) = vr
necessarily and unjustifiably startling claims that expectations do
not matter for stability.
The proof of stability is very simple. We choose V(p,q) as
follows:
:::; Vr [2 ZrP + Zrn+}q] - v?
V(p,q) = max{zl, ... , Zn, f1-1(P1 - ql) .. .fl-n(Pn - Pn)} Pr
P1 Pn q1 qn <0 (7)
We first show that V(p,q) = O implies z(p,q) = O, p = q. If not, it where the first inequality follows from GS and the definition of Vr
follows from W that and the second inequality from H.
z(p,q) =O Next suppose that
p 1 - q1 :::; O all i
Pt - q < O sorne i. (6)
V(p,q) = W8 # O,
so
If we write Z(p) = z(p,p) and use the mapping 2.(4) we see that the
economy has an equilibrium (p*,q*) with p* = q*. By GS, p* O.
V (p,q) = Ws
= -fks ( PsVs - qsWs) - Ws2
Choose units such that p* = e = q*. Then, if for sorne current qs
price Pn Certainly ws >-O; if not, sin ce z(p,q) # O, W implies that z1 > O,
Pr :::; p 1 all i,
sorne i, contradicting V(p,q) = W8 , If V8 :::; O, then certainly
Pr :::; q all i,
V(p,q) < o. So suppose Vs < o. Then vs(ps - qs) ;:::.: (PsVs - qsws),
it follows from T.9.8 that zr(p,q) > O unless (p,q) is proportional to since W 8 ;:e: v., so
(e,e). This contradicts the hypothesis, but since (p,q) is not propor-
tional to (e,e), there must be an expected price q8 with
V(p,q) :::; VsWs - w; < o. (8)
Thus V(p,q) is declining for non-equilibrium (p,q). Since it is easy
qs :::; Pt all i,
to verify that the solution path of prices is bounded, we have pro ved
qs :::; q all i.
But q1 ;:e: p 1, all i, by assumption, so q8 = Ps and by the same argu- THEOREM 10. Let the SP economy have GS and the expectation
rule (E'). Then there is a unique equilibrium with p = q. More-
ment as before zs(p,q) > O. Hence (6) is impossible.
over, the auctioneer's rule (I) with all k 1 = 1 and p(O), q(O) O
11
Now consider (I) with k 1 = 1, all i. It is left to the reader to verify
makes this equilibrium globally stable.
that q(O) O, GS, and (E') ensure q(t) O, all t. We treat V(p,q)
1

1
as differentiable and note that by the same argunent as in the proof As we noted earlier, the theorem has nothing to say concerning
of T.12.6, we can easi1y modify the analysis when it is not differen- the size of fkJ As we also argued earlier, this should not be
tiable. surprising.
l"

314 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 315
auctioneer. In any event, we note that equilibrium requires q = p. Let
Moreover, if we start in the vicinity of an equilibrium, then since .,1
Z
cannot exceed infinity, q can at most change in the same proportions -=V
as p, so that in the appropriate sense, the e1asticity of the previous Pi
discussion can never exceed unity. This is the important point to suppose that
remember when we show thaLin the GS case stability is assured to V(p,q) = Vr # O.
rule (1) whatever the precise value of .,1 may be. Adaptive expec-
By W, Vr > O. A1so
tations are conservative in the sense of Hicks, and in view of the
foregoing, the result should cause no surprise nor tempt us into un- V(p,q) = vr
necessarily and unjustifiably startling claims that expectations do
not matter for stability.
The proof of stability is very simple. We choose V(p,q) as
follows:
:::; Vr [2 ZrP + Zrn+}q] - v?
V(p,q) = max{zl, ... , Zn, f1-1(P1 - ql) .. .fl-n(Pn - Pn)} Pr
P1 Pn q1 qn <0 (7)
We first show that V(p,q) = O implies z(p,q) = O, p = q. If not, it where the first inequality follows from GS and the definition of Vr
follows from W that and the second inequality from H.
z(p,q) =O Next suppose that
p 1 - q1 :::; O all i
Pt - q < O sorne i. (6)
V(p,q) = W8 # O,
so
If we write Z(p) = z(p,p) and use the mapping 2.(4) we see that the
economy has an equilibrium (p*,q*) with p* = q*. By GS, p* O.
V (p,q) = Ws
= -fks ( PsVs - qsWs) - Ws2
Choose units such that p* = e = q*. Then, if for sorne current qs
price Pn Certainly ws >-O; if not, sin ce z(p,q) # O, W implies that z1 > O,
Pr :::; p 1 all i,
sorne i, contradicting V(p,q) = W8 , If V8 :::; O, then certainly
Pr :::; q all i,
V(p,q) < o. So suppose Vs < o. Then vs(ps - qs) ;:::.: (PsVs - qsws),
it follows from T.9.8 that zr(p,q) > O unless (p,q) is proportional to since W 8 ;:e: v., so
(e,e). This contradicts the hypothesis, but since (p,q) is not propor-
tional to (e,e), there must be an expected price q8 with
V(p,q) :::; VsWs - w; < o. (8)
Thus V(p,q) is declining for non-equilibrium (p,q). Since it is easy
qs :::; Pt all i,
to verify that the solution path of prices is bounded, we have pro ved
qs :::; q all i.
But q1 ;:e: p 1, all i, by assumption, so q8 = Ps and by the same argu- THEOREM 10. Let the SP economy have GS and the expectation
rule (E'). Then there is a unique equilibrium with p = q. More-
ment as before zs(p,q) > O. Hence (6) is impossible.
over, the auctioneer's rule (I) with all k 1 = 1 and p(O), q(O) O
11
Now consider (I) with k 1 = 1, all i. It is left to the reader to verify
makes this equilibrium globally stable.
that q(O) O, GS, and (E') ensure q(t) O, all t. We treat V(p,q)
1

1
as differentiable and note that by the same argunent as in the proof As we noted earlier, the theorem has nothing to say concerning
of T.12.6, we can easi1y modify the analysis when it is not differen- the size of fkJ As we also argued earlier, this should not be
tiable. surprising.
T
'
316 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 317

10. The Constant-Returns Economy pendently of demand considerations and, therefore, we cannot
expect a p~1re cost-determined theory of price adjustment to prove
We now consideran economy in which production is everywhere
adequate. To see sorne of the difficulties that arise we now consider
carried out under constant returns to sca1e and in which there is on1y
an economy in which there are as many non-produced inputs as
one non-produced input. In particular, we shall take the economy
there are outputs and in which no intermediate goods are used in
to be connected and postulate A.2.10-A.2.13. The pricing rule is
production. It is the economy discussed in Section 10.4, and we
that given in A.11.5.
employ the same notation.
By our assumptions, it must be true that for all i and p > O, the
Since demand factors are now relevant to price formation and
mnimum unit cost of producing i, (Ct(P)), is strictly positive. It is
since we cannot employ supply functions under constant returns to
clear, therefore, that all solution paths generated by the pricing rule,
scale, we must somehow sidestep the difficulty this creates. We
starting with non-negative prices, will be bounded from below. We
propose to do this as follows. We know that if w is the vector of
also know (T.9.16) that the economy has a unique equilibrium,
input prices, we may solve for p, the vector of output prices at which
p* O. Let k(p) = PriP1 ::::: ptfpf, all i. Then, by the homo-
unit costs will be covered in alllines of production, from p = h(w).
geneity of the mnimum unit cost function and the definition of an
Ifthe production sets are strictly convex, then w determines the vector
equilibrium,
p uniquely. We now suppose that the auctioneer calls the prices of
Pr = k(p)p1 = Cr(k(p)p*). inputs, w, and simultaneously solves h(w) = p and calls the resulting
To pass from k(p)p* to p, at least one price, namely that of the prices of outputs. Since mnimum unit costs are exactly covered at
non-produced input, must be lowered, so certainly all times in all lines of production, producers stand ready to supply
whatever is demanded of the produced goods. We shall take it that
Cr(p) < Cr(k(p )p*) = Pr for all (w, h(w)), every produced good is demanded in positive
Thus, by A.11.5, A< O, unless p = p*, (i.e., k(p) = 1). It follows quantity by households. The consequence of these assumptions is
from all this that the solution path of prices is bounded also from that we can never observe anything but a zero excess demand for
above. Moreover, it is immediate that produced goods. On the other hand, it may not be feasible to
produce all the goods in the quantities in which they are demanded.
V(p) = maxl~t - 1[
This would be the case if, at the prices called and the consequential
supply plans to meet household demands, sorne input were to be in
will now serve as a Lyapounov function that is declining for all excess demand. Now the natural thing to assume is that the
non-equilibrium p. We have proved, therefore, auctioneer acts in the markets for inputs as we imagined him earlier
in this chapter acting in all markets: He raises the price of the input
THEOREM 11. The equilibrium of a connected constant-returns in excess demand and lowers it for that in excess supply. Thus the
economy satisfying A.2.10 to A.2.13 is globally stable for the rule of auctioneer's activity is responsive to demand considerations only
A.l1.5. insofar as they appear in the market for inputs. Let z1 be the excess-
This rather pleasing result is, unfortunately, very heavily de- demand vector for inputs. Then we may put what has just been
pendent on the supposition that there is only one non-produced said formally.
input, and therefore, it is not likely to find ready application in a
more realistic setting. lf it were not for this limitation, we would be ASSUMPTION 3. (a) For all t ::C: 0, p(t) = h(w(t)).
tempted to argue that we have here the beginnings, admittedly only (b) For any i E/, W = G(z), unless W = O and z < O when
rudimentary ones, of a mark-up theory of price formation. Wt =O.
If there are a number of non-produced inputs, then we know (e) The household (net) demand vector x(p,w) - x is strict1y
(Section 2.11) that we cannot determine equilibrium prices inde- positive for all (p,w).
T
'
316 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 317

10. The Constant-Returns Economy pendently of demand considerations and, therefore, we cannot
expect a p~1re cost-determined theory of price adjustment to prove
We now consideran economy in which production is everywhere
adequate. To see sorne of the difficulties that arise we now consider
carried out under constant returns to sca1e and in which there is on1y
an economy in which there are as many non-produced inputs as
one non-produced input. In particular, we shall take the economy
there are outputs and in which no intermediate goods are used in
to be connected and postulate A.2.10-A.2.13. The pricing rule is
production. It is the economy discussed in Section 10.4, and we
that given in A.11.5.
employ the same notation.
By our assumptions, it must be true that for all i and p > O, the
Since demand factors are now relevant to price formation and
mnimum unit cost of producing i, (Ct(P)), is strictly positive. It is
since we cannot employ supply functions under constant returns to
clear, therefore, that all solution paths generated by the pricing rule,
scale, we must somehow sidestep the difficulty this creates. We
starting with non-negative prices, will be bounded from below. We
propose to do this as follows. We know that if w is the vector of
also know (T.9.16) that the economy has a unique equilibrium,
input prices, we may solve for p, the vector of output prices at which
p* O. Let k(p) = PriP1 ::::: ptfpf, all i. Then, by the homo-
unit costs will be covered in alllines of production, from p = h(w).
geneity of the mnimum unit cost function and the definition of an
Ifthe production sets are strictly convex, then w determines the vector
equilibrium,
p uniquely. We now suppose that the auctioneer calls the prices of
Pr = k(p)p1 = Cr(k(p)p*). inputs, w, and simultaneously solves h(w) = p and calls the resulting
To pass from k(p)p* to p, at least one price, namely that of the prices of outputs. Since mnimum unit costs are exactly covered at
non-produced input, must be lowered, so certainly all times in all lines of production, producers stand ready to supply
whatever is demanded of the produced goods. We shall take it that
Cr(p) < Cr(k(p )p*) = Pr for all (w, h(w)), every produced good is demanded in positive
Thus, by A.11.5, A< O, unless p = p*, (i.e., k(p) = 1). It follows quantity by households. The consequence of these assumptions is
from all this that the solution path of prices is bounded also from that we can never observe anything but a zero excess demand for
above. Moreover, it is immediate that produced goods. On the other hand, it may not be feasible to
produce all the goods in the quantities in which they are demanded.
V(p) = maxl~t - 1[
This would be the case if, at the prices called and the consequential
supply plans to meet household demands, sorne input were to be in
will now serve as a Lyapounov function that is declining for all excess demand. Now the natural thing to assume is that the
non-equilibrium p. We have proved, therefore, auctioneer acts in the markets for inputs as we imagined him earlier
in this chapter acting in all markets: He raises the price of the input
THEOREM 11. The equilibrium of a connected constant-returns in excess demand and lowers it for that in excess supply. Thus the
economy satisfying A.2.10 to A.2.13 is globally stable for the rule of auctioneer's activity is responsive to demand considerations only
A.l1.5. insofar as they appear in the market for inputs. Let z1 be the excess-
This rather pleasing result is, unfortunately, very heavily de- demand vector for inputs. Then we may put what has just been
pendent on the supposition that there is only one non-produced said formally.
input, and therefore, it is not likely to find ready application in a
more realistic setting. lf it were not for this limitation, we would be ASSUMPTION 3. (a) For all t ::C: 0, p(t) = h(w(t)).
tempted to argue that we have here the beginnings, admittedly only (b) For any i E/, W = G(z), unless W = O and z < O when
rudimentary ones, of a mark-up theory of price formation. Wt =O.
If there are a number of non-produced inputs, then we know (e) The household (net) demand vector x(p,w) - x is strict1y
(Section 2.11) that we cannot determine equilibrium prices inde- positive for all (p,w).
318 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 319

Since we may write z1 = z1(p,w) = z{h(w),w) = Z(w), say, and at least will not lower it. Such a rise cannot lead to the reduction
since wZ1 = O, all w, we may think of the market for inputs as in the planned supply of the good if production sets are convex and
constituting a "reduced" general equilibrium system. 1 Stability it leaves the planned supplies of all other goods unchanged.
conclusions can be drawn by making assumptions about the reduced Accordingly, we should be justified in saying that the demand for no
excess demands, Z1 , so that we may appeal to our earlier results, in input is reduced. On the other hand, the rise in the price of the
which these properties were taken to hold for the non-reduced produced good will not increase the supply of any input either if the
system. The difficulty is simply that these postulates are now only latter is not subject to household choice or, if it is, if we may take it
. indirectly related to what might be the appropriate preferences of that leisure is not an inferior good. Thus, while sorne restrictions
households and the production sets of producers. Thus, for on the production sets and household preferences .re required, if we
instance, if Z 11 is the partial coefficient of Z 1 with respect to its jth want to be able to say that a rise in the price of good k does not
argument, reduce the excess demand for any input, these are far less "fine"
than needed in the constant-returns case. This is due to the
necessity of circumventing the absence of a supply "function" in
this case by stipulating that whatever is demanded is also supplied
We certainly may take 8P~c/Bw1 > O, all k, and it is easy to argue provided mnimum unit costs are covered.
for 8zj8w1 > O, i =1= O. It is much harder to postulate anything There is one case, however, for which we can be quite definite in
sensible concerning the (8zf8p 1,)'s. our conclusions; this arises when it is true that all households satisfy
If we suppose that from the point of view of households all goods the requirement that the economy be Hicksian, if all inputs are
are GS, then a rise, say, in the price of the produced good k will household services and households own no stocks of any good. If
reduce the demand for that good and increase the demand for other we write L as the supply vector of household services (taken to have
goocis. By our assumptions, the supply of good k will be lower and non-negative components) and x as the vector of household demand
that of others higher. This does not give us enough information to for produced goods, we may write the budget constraint of the
determine the final effect on the demand for any particular input; to fictional household that we always examine in the Hicksian case as
do that we need to know sorne ofthe finer properties ofthe household B = h(w)x - wL = O.
demand functions and of the production sets. This should come as
no surprise since we found this to be the case when we investigated Write h1t(w) = 8hf8w1 and differentiate the budget constraint with
the two-sector neoclassical model, which is similar to the present one respect to w1 to find, when x and L are held constant (denoted by an
in all respects except that it was restricted to the case of two inputs asterisk),
and outputs. Thus, while we may make such formal statements as, BB*' = ""
" L. h(W)X - L
uW i
"If Z 1 has GS, then the unique equilibrium of the economy will be
globally stable for the rule of A.l2~3," and while such results are not h1(w) is the amount of inputj employed per unit of output of good
without use, it must be admitted that they are not of very great i and so
interest. BB*
It is of sorne importance to understand why these difficulties are a Bw = Z(w)
peculiar feature of the present case. When constant returns are not since by assumption whatever is demanded of a produced good is
stipulated, we need only quite general restrictions on the production also supplied (ifunit costs are covered). Then, using the auctioneer's
sets and household preferences to enable us to say that the rise in the rule A.l2.3, we have
price of a produced good will raise the demand for a given input, or
dB*
dt = "" BB*
Bw w. 1 = "" Z(w)G(Z(w)),
1
This discussion partly recapitulates what was said in 9.12.
318 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 319

Since we may write z1 = z1(p,w) = z{h(w),w) = Z(w), say, and at least will not lower it. Such a rise cannot lead to the reduction
since wZ1 = O, all w, we may think of the market for inputs as in the planned supply of the good if production sets are convex and
constituting a "reduced" general equilibrium system. 1 Stability it leaves the planned supplies of all other goods unchanged.
conclusions can be drawn by making assumptions about the reduced Accordingly, we should be justified in saying that the demand for no
excess demands, Z1 , so that we may appeal to our earlier results, in input is reduced. On the other hand, the rise in the price of the
which these properties were taken to hold for the non-reduced produced good will not increase the supply of any input either if the
system. The difficulty is simply that these postulates are now only latter is not subject to household choice or, if it is, if we may take it
. indirectly related to what might be the appropriate preferences of that leisure is not an inferior good. Thus, while sorne restrictions
households and the production sets of producers. Thus, for on the production sets and household preferences .re required, if we
instance, if Z 11 is the partial coefficient of Z 1 with respect to its jth want to be able to say that a rise in the price of good k does not
argument, reduce the excess demand for any input, these are far less "fine"
than needed in the constant-returns case. This is due to the
necessity of circumventing the absence of a supply "function" in
this case by stipulating that whatever is demanded is also supplied
We certainly may take 8P~c/Bw1 > O, all k, and it is easy to argue provided mnimum unit costs are covered.
for 8zj8w1 > O, i =1= O. It is much harder to postulate anything There is one case, however, for which we can be quite definite in
sensible concerning the (8zf8p 1,)'s. our conclusions; this arises when it is true that all households satisfy
If we suppose that from the point of view of households all goods the requirement that the economy be Hicksian, if all inputs are
are GS, then a rise, say, in the price of the produced good k will household services and households own no stocks of any good. If
reduce the demand for that good and increase the demand for other we write L as the supply vector of household services (taken to have
goocis. By our assumptions, the supply of good k will be lower and non-negative components) and x as the vector of household demand
that of others higher. This does not give us enough information to for produced goods, we may write the budget constraint of the
determine the final effect on the demand for any particular input; to fictional household that we always examine in the Hicksian case as
do that we need to know sorne ofthe finer properties ofthe household B = h(w)x - wL = O.
demand functions and of the production sets. This should come as
no surprise since we found this to be the case when we investigated Write h1t(w) = 8hf8w1 and differentiate the budget constraint with
the two-sector neoclassical model, which is similar to the present one respect to w1 to find, when x and L are held constant (denoted by an
in all respects except that it was restricted to the case of two inputs asterisk),
and outputs. Thus, while we may make such formal statements as, BB*' = ""
" L. h(W)X - L
uW i
"If Z 1 has GS, then the unique equilibrium of the economy will be
globally stable for the rule of A.l2~3," and while such results are not h1(w) is the amount of inputj employed per unit of output of good
without use, it must be admitted that they are not of very great i and so
interest. BB*
It is of sorne importance to understand why these difficulties are a Bw = Z(w)
peculiar feature of the present case. When constant returns are not since by assumption whatever is demanded of a produced good is
stipulated, we need only quite general restrictions on the production also supplied (ifunit costs are covered). Then, using the auctioneer's
sets and household preferences to enable us to say that the rise in the rule A.l2.3, we have
price of a produced good will raise the demand for a given input, or
dB*
dt = "" BB*
Bw w. 1 = "" Z(w)G(Z(w)),
1
This discussion partly recapitulates what was said in 9.12.
,,

320 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 321

an expression that must always be positive out of equilibrium. lf P* is an equilibrium, we may be interested in the sign of dPf /dex,
However, dB*/dt > Omust mean that the fictional household is made which we go about determining from
worse off by each successive calling of prices of inputs. Provided
the rule gives rise toa bounded sequence, w(t) (as it will, for instance,
if G1(Z1) = Z 1), we may use the utility function of the fictional
household as a Lyapounov function, as usual. We have therefore
pro ved in our usual notation. If all goods are, say, GS, then we know that
it must be that dPf /da > O. It will be true also that for the usual
THEOREM 12. Let the constant-returns economy have as many non- auctioneer's rule, P* will be locally stable. But suppose that we are
produced inputs as it has produced outputs, there being no joint given only the latter information. We conclude from the require-
production. Let households own no stocks of any good and sup- ments of local stability that all the real parts of the roots of J(P *)
pose that A.l2.3 holds. Then, if the economy is Hicksian, the are positive. This is consistent with the determinant formed from
auctioneer's rule will be globally stable if the price path is bounded. J(P *) by deleting the first row and column having the same or the
We see that the Hicksian hypothesis is sufficiently powerful to opposite sign of the determinant of J(P*) itself. Hence, from the
allow us to deduce definite stability results without any further given info'rmation, we cannot deduce how the equilibrium price of
fine specification of the production sets and of household prefer- the first good will be changed as a result of a change in ex. The
ences; it seems to be the only such case. necessary conditions for local stability are too weak for the com-
parison task. This is even more striking, of course, when the num-
ber of goods is large and when glob.al stability is at stake.
11. The Correspondence Principie Thus what the "correspondence principie" amounts to is this:
In Section 1.6 we briefly mentioned the contention, due to Most of the restrictions on the form of the excess-demand functions
Samuelson, that the postulate that the economy was stable would that are at present known to be sufficient to ensure global stability
carry with it implications that would be helpful in the task of are also sufficient to allow certain exercises in comparing equilibria.
comparing equilibria. We are now in a better position to assess It should be added that these same conditions also turn up in the
this claim. discussion of the uniqueness of a competitive equilibrium. All
At first sight it would appear to be wholly justified, since it is true these restrictions share the characteristic that they are not necessary
that we ha ve been able to prove stability for just those cases for which for the task for which they were invented; they are only sufficient and
we also found it possible to reach certain conclusions as to the effects this explains why the correspondence principie "isn't."
of parameter changes on the economy's equilibrium. It is on such
grounds that an "intimate connection between stability and com-
12. Conclusions
parative statics" has been proposed. Yet the conclusion is too
hasty and the impression delusory, for we are asked to compare Although we set ourselves the task of investigating "the price
equilibria, not given the information that the economy has GS or is mechanism" in a highly simplified setting, it will probably be agreed
Hicksian, etc., but given the information that the equilibrium is that the task ls not simple, and that it has not bcen dcfinitivcly
locally or globally stable. The following example will make clear completed. There is a distressingly anecdotal air about our investi-
that this latter information is not enough. Consider an economy gation; case succeeds case, but it was not found possible to lay down
with four goods. Write the excess-demand function for good 1 as any general principies.
z1 (p,a), where a is a shift parameter such that z 1 a = oz 1 /8a > O. We Some of the difficulties we have encountered may be due to the
assume that ex enters into the excess-demand function of only the abstraction of a tatonnement; this will be discussed in the next
first and fourth goods and that the latter is the chosen numeraire. chapter. Even if it had been possible to show that in a perfectly
,,

320 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 321

an expression that must always be positive out of equilibrium. lf P* is an equilibrium, we may be interested in the sign of dPf /dex,
However, dB*/dt > Omust mean that the fictional household is made which we go about determining from
worse off by each successive calling of prices of inputs. Provided
the rule gives rise toa bounded sequence, w(t) (as it will, for instance,
if G1(Z1) = Z 1), we may use the utility function of the fictional
household as a Lyapounov function, as usual. We have therefore
pro ved in our usual notation. If all goods are, say, GS, then we know that
it must be that dPf /da > O. It will be true also that for the usual
THEOREM 12. Let the constant-returns economy have as many non- auctioneer's rule, P* will be locally stable. But suppose that we are
produced inputs as it has produced outputs, there being no joint given only the latter information. We conclude from the require-
production. Let households own no stocks of any good and sup- ments of local stability that all the real parts of the roots of J(P *)
pose that A.l2.3 holds. Then, if the economy is Hicksian, the are positive. This is consistent with the determinant formed from
auctioneer's rule will be globally stable if the price path is bounded. J(P *) by deleting the first row and column having the same or the
We see that the Hicksian hypothesis is sufficiently powerful to opposite sign of the determinant of J(P*) itself. Hence, from the
allow us to deduce definite stability results without any further given info'rmation, we cannot deduce how the equilibrium price of
fine specification of the production sets and of household prefer- the first good will be changed as a result of a change in ex. The
ences; it seems to be the only such case. necessary conditions for local stability are too weak for the com-
parison task. This is even more striking, of course, when the num-
ber of goods is large and when glob.al stability is at stake.
11. The Correspondence Principie Thus what the "correspondence principie" amounts to is this:
In Section 1.6 we briefly mentioned the contention, due to Most of the restrictions on the form of the excess-demand functions
Samuelson, that the postulate that the economy was stable would that are at present known to be sufficient to ensure global stability
carry with it implications that would be helpful in the task of are also sufficient to allow certain exercises in comparing equilibria.
comparing equilibria. We are now in a better position to assess It should be added that these same conditions also turn up in the
this claim. discussion of the uniqueness of a competitive equilibrium. All
At first sight it would appear to be wholly justified, since it is true these restrictions share the characteristic that they are not necessary
that we ha ve been able to prove stability for just those cases for which for the task for which they were invented; they are only sufficient and
we also found it possible to reach certain conclusions as to the effects this explains why the correspondence principie "isn't."
of parameter changes on the economy's equilibrium. It is on such
grounds that an "intimate connection between stability and com-
12. Conclusions
parative statics" has been proposed. Yet the conclusion is too
hasty and the impression delusory, for we are asked to compare Although we set ourselves the task of investigating "the price
equilibria, not given the information that the economy has GS or is mechanism" in a highly simplified setting, it will probably be agreed
Hicksian, etc., but given the information that the equilibrium is that the task ls not simple, and that it has not bcen dcfinitivcly
locally or globally stable. The following example will make clear completed. There is a distressingly anecdotal air about our investi-
that this latter information is not enough. Consider an economy gation; case succeeds case, but it was not found possible to lay down
with four goods. Write the excess-demand function for good 1 as any general principies.
z1 (p,a), where a is a shift parameter such that z 1 a = oz 1 /8a > O. We Some of the difficulties we have encountered may be due to the
assume that ex enters into the excess-demand function of only the abstraction of a tatonnement; this will be discussed in the next
first and fourth goods and that the latter is the chosen numeraire. chapter. Even if it had been possible to show that in a perfectly
322 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 323

competitive economy a tatonnement is always stable, it is not clear Uzawa [1959-60] formulated the discrete time process and proved the
that such a result could have been given much weight in forming a main results.
judgment of the performance of the price mechanism in actual Enthoven and Arrow [1956] and Arrow and Nerlove [1958] studied
local stability when expected prices enteted the excess-demand func-
1
1 economics. The fiction of an auctioneer is quite serious, since tions; global stability with adaptive expectations was studied by Arrow
~: 1
without it we would have to face the paradoxical problem that a and Hurwicz [1962].
perfect competitor changes prices that he is supposed to take as
given. In addition, the processes investigated in this chapter assume
that, disequilibrium notwithstanding, there is only a single pdce for
each good at any moment. It is also postulated that at each
moment, the plans of agents are their equilibrium plans. Lastly, of
course, there is no trade out of equilibrium. All of these postulates
are damaging to the tatonnement exercise. It may be that sorne of
the theorems and sorne of the insights gained will have application
when a more satisfactory theory of the price mechanism has been
developed. At the moment the main justification for the chapter is
that there are results to report on the tatonnement while there are no
results to report on what most economists would agree to be more
realistic constructions.

Notes

Walras [1874, 1877] first formulated the idea of a tatonnement


although in his more formal account of it he seemed to conceive of it as
the Gauss-Seidel process discussed in Section 12.8.
The modern concern with a rigorous analysis of the problem in a
general equilibrium context started with Hicks [1939], but the proper
dynamic formulation carne from Samuelson [1941-42; see also 1947].
A number of important local stability results were soon thereafter
proved. Global stability analysis was inaugurated by Arrow and
Hurwicz [1958] and notably contributed to by Uzawa [1961].
The gross-~ubstitute case (after the concept was first formulated by
Mosak [1944]) was analyzed by Metzler [1945], Hahn [1958], and
Negishi [1958] in the local context, and by Arrow and Hurwicz [1958]
and Arrow, Block, and Hurwicz [1959] in the global context. The weak
gross-substitute case has been studied by McKenzie [1960a] and Arrow
and Hurwicz [1960]. Diagonal Dominance was fully explored by
McKenzie [1960b] for local results and by Arrow, Block, and Hurwicz
[1959] for global ones. A number of other cases have been investigated
for local stability, notably by Morishima [1952], but we have not dis-
cussed them in this chapter.
The first example to show the possibility of global instability was that
of Scarf [1960]. The simpler case presented in Section 12.6 is due to
Gale [1963].
322 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS STABILITY WITH RECONTRACTING 323

competitive economy a tatonnement is always stable, it is not clear Uzawa [1959-60] formulated the discrete time process and proved the
that such a result could have been given much weight in forming a main results.
judgment of the performance of the price mechanism in actual Enthoven and Arrow [1956] and Arrow and Nerlove [1958] studied
local stability when expected prices enteted the excess-demand func-
1
1 economics. The fiction of an auctioneer is quite serious, since tions; global stability with adaptive expectations was studied by Arrow
~: 1
without it we would have to face the paradoxical problem that a and Hurwicz [1962].
perfect competitor changes prices that he is supposed to take as
given. In addition, the processes investigated in this chapter assume
that, disequilibrium notwithstanding, there is only a single pdce for
each good at any moment. It is also postulated that at each
moment, the plans of agents are their equilibrium plans. Lastly, of
course, there is no trade out of equilibrium. All of these postulates
are damaging to the tatonnement exercise. It may be that sorne of
the theorems and sorne of the insights gained will have application
when a more satisfactory theory of the price mechanism has been
developed. At the moment the main justification for the chapter is
that there are results to report on the tatonnement while there are no
results to report on what most economists would agree to be more
realistic constructions.

Notes

Walras [1874, 1877] first formulated the idea of a tatonnement


although in his more formal account of it he seemed to conceive of it as
the Gauss-Seidel process discussed in Section 12.8.
The modern concern with a rigorous analysis of the problem in a
general equilibrium context started with Hicks [1939], but the proper
dynamic formulation carne from Samuelson [1941-42; see also 1947].
A number of important local stability results were soon thereafter
proved. Global stability analysis was inaugurated by Arrow and
Hurwicz [1958] and notably contributed to by Uzawa [1961].
The gross-~ubstitute case (after the concept was first formulated by
Mosak [1944]) was analyzed by Metzler [1945], Hahn [1958], and
Negishi [1958] in the local context, and by Arrow and Hurwicz [1958]
and Arrow, Block, and Hurwicz [1959] in the global context. The weak
gross-substitute case has been studied by McKenzie [1960a] and Arrow
and Hurwicz [1960]. Diagonal Dominance was fully explored by
McKenzie [1960b] for local results and by Arrow, Block, and Hurwicz
[1959] for global ones. A number of other cases have been investigated
for local stability, notably by Morishima [1952], but we have not dis-
cussed them in this chapter.
The first example to show the possibility of global instability was that
of Scarf [1960]. The simpler case presented in Section 12.6 is due to
Gale [1963].
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 325
Chapter Thirteen
It is clear that the stipulation of a single rate of exchange between
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: any two goods at any one moment of time could itself be viewed as
A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY the outcome of sorne adjustment with sorne information process to
make participants aware of disparities in the terms of exchange.
Alternatively, we could decide to allow a variety of exchange rates
Pleasure or businesse, so, our soules between any two goods at every moment of time fqr :w.hich the
GRES E admit economy was out of equilibrium and considera sequerite ot" outco.m,~s .' ,
UNIVERSI~ 01: PAR/S l . PANTH~ON SO
For their first mover and are whirled that might result from a large nmn9tl1' af bilmteral-tiargains between
90 RBONNE
' rue de Tolbiac by it. a variety of individuals. In either case, our task w0uld ~e a. good
75634 PARIS CEOEX 13 -John Donne, Good Friday, deal more difficult. Although we shall r~turn.to this problem lafer,
1613, Riding Westward. the idealization of postulating an auctioneer is not an obviously
illegitimate shortcut through these problems, and the question, "How
1. The Problem do prices cometo change in the absence of an auctioneer?" is much
more difficult to deal with. lf we decide that the terms of exchange
. In the preceding chapter we concerned ourselves with the investiga- facing any unit of decision shall be independent of the cotlfSe of
twn of an extremely artificial formulation of the "price mechanism." action that unit might wish to pursue, it is decidedly odd to imagine
In particular, we insisted that no trade take place out of equilibrium. any one decision unit changing prices under "market pressure."
This restriction, strictly interpreted, is not only obviously nrealistic, Thus, for instance, in a production economy, if every firm faces a
but also seems to carry the logical implication that trade never takes horizontal demand curve (or thinks that it faces such a curve), it is
place. If the auctioneer's rule is not stable, trading is not permitted not easy to visualize any firm changing the price af which its product
afortiori, while ifit is, trading will be permitted only "in the limit" is sold. What is happening now is that, having decided on one ,
(i.e., as t approaches infinity), for it is only in the Iimit that equilibrium idealization (perfect competition), we run into what must be taken to 1

and "called" prices coincide.. Although there are obvious ways of be logical difficulties unless we import a further idealization: the
interpreting the process Iess strictly, it would be highly desirable auctioneer. It would be a vulgar mistake to suppose that this can
nonetheless to be able to do without the recontract assumption. be taken as evidence that the analysis has nothing to teach us about
Accordingly, in this chapter we shall remove the restriction ofno the world. The question really turns on the "mistakes" we can see
trade for non-equilibrium situations. In two important respects, ourselves making by adopting the perfectly competitive view. We
however, the analysis will continue to be both abstract and unrealis- cannot form any adequate judgment of these "mistakes" until we
tic: We shall continue to suppose that there is an auctioneer who have discovered where the idealization is taking us, and so we now
i calls prices and we shall assume that no productive activities are adoptit.
carried on in the economy. It is not uninstructive to consider why, The simplification that there is no production is of great impor-
as it were, we continue to tie our hands behind our backs. tance for the results to be established in this chapter and for an
The role of the auctioneer is twofold; at any moment of time he understanding of these results. We shall show that in the pure-
establishes unique and public terms on which goods may be traded, exchange economy with trade permitted at all times, relatively
and he adjusts these terms in the light of market observations by modest assumptions will allow us to deduce that the economy con-
sorne particular rule. If we did not stipulate the existence of such verges to an equilibrium. If, as in the theory of the trade cycle, we
an auctioneer, we would have to describe how it comes about that also wish to maintain that in many situations the process of decen-
at any moment of time two goods exchange on the same terms tralized decisions is not convergent, it is likely that we shall have to
wherever such exchange takes place and how these terms come to look for the causes on the "production side." This in itself is
change under market pressure. valuable information. lf we can also learn why the arguments to be

324
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 325
Chapter Thirteen
It is clear that the stipulation of a single rate of exchange between
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: any two goods at any one moment of time could itself be viewed as
A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY the outcome of sorne adjustment with sorne information process to
make participants aware of disparities in the terms of exchange.
Alternatively, we could decide to allow a variety of exchange rates
Pleasure or businesse, so, our soules between any two goods at every moment of time fqr :w.hich the
GRES E admit economy was out of equilibrium and considera sequerite ot" outco.m,~s .' ,
UNIVERSI~ 01: PAR/S l . PANTH~ON SO
For their first mover and are whirled that might result from a large nmn9tl1' af bilmteral-tiargains between
90 RBONNE
' rue de Tolbiac by it. a variety of individuals. In either case, our task w0uld ~e a. good
75634 PARIS CEOEX 13 -John Donne, Good Friday, deal more difficult. Although we shall r~turn.to this problem lafer,
1613, Riding Westward. the idealization of postulating an auctioneer is not an obviously
illegitimate shortcut through these problems, and the question, "How
1. The Problem do prices cometo change in the absence of an auctioneer?" is much
more difficult to deal with. lf we decide that the terms of exchange
. In the preceding chapter we concerned ourselves with the investiga- facing any unit of decision shall be independent of the cotlfSe of
twn of an extremely artificial formulation of the "price mechanism." action that unit might wish to pursue, it is decidedly odd to imagine
In particular, we insisted that no trade take place out of equilibrium. any one decision unit changing prices under "market pressure."
This restriction, strictly interpreted, is not only obviously nrealistic, Thus, for instance, in a production economy, if every firm faces a
but also seems to carry the logical implication that trade never takes horizontal demand curve (or thinks that it faces such a curve), it is
place. If the auctioneer's rule is not stable, trading is not permitted not easy to visualize any firm changing the price af which its product
afortiori, while ifit is, trading will be permitted only "in the limit" is sold. What is happening now is that, having decided on one ,
(i.e., as t approaches infinity), for it is only in the Iimit that equilibrium idealization (perfect competition), we run into what must be taken to 1

and "called" prices coincide.. Although there are obvious ways of be logical difficulties unless we import a further idealization: the
interpreting the process Iess strictly, it would be highly desirable auctioneer. It would be a vulgar mistake to suppose that this can
nonetheless to be able to do without the recontract assumption. be taken as evidence that the analysis has nothing to teach us about
Accordingly, in this chapter we shall remove the restriction ofno the world. The question really turns on the "mistakes" we can see
trade for non-equilibrium situations. In two important respects, ourselves making by adopting the perfectly competitive view. We
however, the analysis will continue to be both abstract and unrealis- cannot form any adequate judgment of these "mistakes" until we
tic: We shall continue to suppose that there is an auctioneer who have discovered where the idealization is taking us, and so we now
i calls prices and we shall assume that no productive activities are adoptit.
carried on in the economy. It is not uninstructive to consider why, The simplification that there is no production is of great impor-
as it were, we continue to tie our hands behind our backs. tance for the results to be established in this chapter and for an
The role of the auctioneer is twofold; at any moment of time he understanding of these results. We shall show that in the pure-
establishes unique and public terms on which goods may be traded, exchange economy with trade permitted at all times, relatively
and he adjusts these terms in the light of market observations by modest assumptions will allow us to deduce that the economy con-
sorne particular rule. If we did not stipulate the existence of such verges to an equilibrium. If, as in the theory of the trade cycle, we
an auctioneer, we would have to describe how it comes about that also wish to maintain that in many situations the process of decen-
at any moment of time two goods exchange on the same terms tralized decisions is not convergent, it is likely that we shall have to
wherever such exchange takes place and how these terms come to look for the causes on the "production side." This in itself is
change under market pressure. valuable information. lf we can also learn why the arguments to be

324
326 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM; A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 327

developed in this chapter would fail in an economy with production, where, as usual, xh1 is the utility-maximizing choice of good i of h
we may also be well on the way to understanding why such an at p, xh, and 311 = 1 if i = j, O if i # j. Then
economy may get into "difficulties."
1 :1
,,

!
2. The Relation to Stability with Recontract
by (1) and (2). So it follows that along any path of the economy,
Let there be H households, each endowed with a collection of
goods represented by the vector xh. Write X as the matrix with
columns xh. Then since we are proposing to treat X as variable (by
exchaijge), we write the excess-demand function as:
Z = Z(p,X) i = i, .. . , n. where
8z1
In general, we can expect the equilibrium prices to depend on X. Zj = -
i
8p
Suppose we continue to postulate a price adjustment mechanism
'1' ::
: !: given by Before we allowed exchange to take place, we were able to show
i1 (Chapter 12), that the pricing process was stable if all goods were
.i p = Z(p,X) i = i, .. . , n . gross substitutes, or if there was a dominant diagonal (with constant
i units of measurement), or if all households were "alike." The
In addition, there will be sorne process of exchange. This process
must satisfy two condition_jf it is to be feasible: striking point is this: If we are willing to postulate any of these
properties here and suppose these to hold for all X, then the pricing
P~h(t) =O all h, t 2: O (1) process is again stable. Therefore, it turns out' that for the cases
known, the assumption of recontract was not required for the desired
2 ~h(t) =o
h
all t 2: O. (2) result.
The reader can verify this for himself by the arguments of Chapter
The first of these establishes that no household can change its wealth 12. Here we take the gross-substitute case as an illustration. Let
- by exchange; the value of what it buys must clearly be equal to the - Z(p X)
value of what it sells. The second confirms that we are in a pure- V(p,X) = max -'-'-
i p
exchange economy without production. Let
(We can divide by p 1 because it can easily be shown that p(t) O, aH
X= G[X1p] t, if p(O) 0.) With the usual qualification (see proof of T.12.4),
V(p,X) is differentiable, and using the above results, we find
be a process of exchange that satisfies (1) and (2) (we shall discuss
an example in a subsequent section). . - 1 "' z z~
V(p,X) = - ~ ZrJPi-1 - 2
Given the mechanism of exchange and of price change, let us Pr i Pi Pr
calculate t 1 Let where
zr(p,X) 1 z (p,X)
w(t) = pxh(t). - - - = max---
Pr P1
Then, by elementary demand theory, By gross substitutability and the definition of V,
326 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM; A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 327

developed in this chapter would fail in an economy with production, where, as usual, xh1 is the utility-maximizing choice of good i of h
we may also be well on the way to understanding why such an at p, xh, and 311 = 1 if i = j, O if i # j. Then
economy may get into "difficulties."
1 :1
,,

!
2. The Relation to Stability with Recontract
by (1) and (2). So it follows that along any path of the economy,
Let there be H households, each endowed with a collection of
goods represented by the vector xh. Write X as the matrix with
columns xh. Then since we are proposing to treat X as variable (by
exchaijge), we write the excess-demand function as:
Z = Z(p,X) i = i, .. . , n. where
8z1
In general, we can expect the equilibrium prices to depend on X. Zj = -
i
8p
Suppose we continue to postulate a price adjustment mechanism
'1' ::
: !: given by Before we allowed exchange to take place, we were able to show
i1 (Chapter 12), that the pricing process was stable if all goods were
.i p = Z(p,X) i = i, .. . , n . gross substitutes, or if there was a dominant diagonal (with constant
i units of measurement), or if all households were "alike." The
In addition, there will be sorne process of exchange. This process
must satisfy two condition_jf it is to be feasible: striking point is this: If we are willing to postulate any of these
properties here and suppose these to hold for all X, then the pricing
P~h(t) =O all h, t 2: O (1) process is again stable. Therefore, it turns out' that for the cases
known, the assumption of recontract was not required for the desired
2 ~h(t) =o
h
all t 2: O. (2) result.
The reader can verify this for himself by the arguments of Chapter
The first of these establishes that no household can change its wealth 12. Here we take the gross-substitute case as an illustration. Let
- by exchange; the value of what it buys must clearly be equal to the - Z(p X)
value of what it sells. The second confirms that we are in a pure- V(p,X) = max -'-'-
i p
exchange economy without production. Let
(We can divide by p 1 because it can easily be shown that p(t) O, aH
X= G[X1p] t, if p(O) 0.) With the usual qualification (see proof of T.12.4),
V(p,X) is differentiable, and using the above results, we find
be a process of exchange that satisfies (1) and (2) (we shall discuss
an example in a subsequent section). . - 1 "' z z~
V(p,X) = - ~ ZrJPi-1 - 2
Given the mechanism of exchange and of price change, let us Pr i Pi Pr
calculate t 1 Let where
zr(p,X) 1 z (p,X)
w(t) = pxh(t). - - - = max---
Pr P1
Then, by elementary demand theory, By gross substitutability and the definition of V,
328 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 329
and so V< O if Vi= O. We may use the usual argument to show engage in speculative transactions that, while they imply a utility
that z(t)--+ O. Furthermore, if z(p,X) = O, then p = O, and we loss when they are made, are anticipated to yield a net gain even-
airead y know that z = O, so that any exchange that continues to take tually. Hence, if we are prepared to accept the proposed assump-
place must leave equilibrium prices unchanged. tion, we would be wise to think of households as having stationary
From all this we expect that as long as we continue to use the same expectations. We shall retum to this point later. Even so, we are
pricing rule, allowing exchange even out of equilibrium not only not yet out of the woods. If two individuals who can gain from
cannot deprive us of any existing stability results, but also may well exchange are actually to do so, it must be possible for them to find
give us stronger results. This, as we shall now see, is indeed the each other. Given enough time and a random search of households
case. for profitable exchanges, we could attempt to demonstrate that the
The reader should note, however, that the results just given show probability of the two households finding each other goes to one as
convergence to sorne equilibrium, which of cotme depends on X and time of search goes to infinity. However, since this procedure is no
,
p(O), and not to any arbitrarily preassigned equilibrium. This less unrealistic than the supposition that it is part of the auctioneer's
i'li means the process is stable, although no given equilibrium need be job to freely disseminate offers to buy and sell, we prefer to make the
1

' 1,11
stable. latter assumption. Once again, however, we are giving the auc-
1''
tioneer an uncomfortably large role. At the moment, our concern
11
3. Conditions for Trade is limited to dispelling the notion that A.l3.1 is innocuous.
One immediate consequence of A.l3.1 is that no exchange will
Let Bh(P) represent the collection of goods a household could take place if X is Pareto efticient. On the other hand, it is clear that
acquire at p without violating its budget constraint, that is, Bh(P) = X's being Pareto efticient does not imply that P is an equilibrium for
{x pxh :o:; pxh}, and let X be the matrix with columns xh. Write e
1
the economy in the sense that all excess demands are zero. Less
for the H-dimensional column vector with all elements equal to obvious, perhaps, is the fact that A.l3.1 might not permit trade to
unity. We propose to work with the following assumption. ' take place even though X is not Pareto efticient. Let us examine
AssuMPTION l. Exchange will take place at p O, if and only if this.
there is an X, with xh E B(p), all h, and Xe = Xe, such that Uh(xh) ;:o: It will be convenient to suppose that all utility functions are dif-
U(xh), all h, and Uh(xh) > Uh(xh), sorne h. ferentiable where required, and we write Uh 1(xh) = Dht as the partial
differential coefticient of Uh at x" with respect to its ith argument.
What this amounts to is an assertion that trade will take We take it, at least for the moment, that these marginal utilities are
place if and only if it is feasible for the households at p, everywhere positive and define
feasible for the economy, and leads to a Pareto-superior allocation.
(We are supposing that there is no consumption so that the total Rt
fl.-ht =-- 1, i = 1, ... , n - 1,
endowment of goods in the economy is the same before and after pi
trade; this assumption can be ignored at the cost of sorne complica- where P is the price vector in terms of good n. We also adopt the
tions.) At first sight, the assertion sounds extremely reasonable, but convention that two quantities, v and w, are of "the same sign" if
further thought quickly shows that, in fact, the proposed conditions they are both positive, or negative, or zero.
are quite restrictive. Thus we note that it is quite possible that an Now, if no trade is possible at X > O, it follows from A.13.1 that
individual who experiences a loss in utility from a given exchange f9r all i, fl.-ht must ha ve the same sign for all h. If not, since, say, the
may be prepared nonetheless to undertake it if he expects that the marginal rate of substitution between goods i and n would exceed
next p called by the auctioneer will put him in an advantageous their relative prices for sorne household, but not for some other
position to make large gains as a consequence of the exchanges he household, it is clear that the first household, could gain by ex-
has currently made. In other words, it is possible for households to changing i for n while the other household would not lose by this,
328 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 329
and so V< O if Vi= O. We may use the usual argument to show engage in speculative transactions that, while they imply a utility
that z(t)--+ O. Furthermore, if z(p,X) = O, then p = O, and we loss when they are made, are anticipated to yield a net gain even-
airead y know that z = O, so that any exchange that continues to take tually. Hence, if we are prepared to accept the proposed assump-
place must leave equilibrium prices unchanged. tion, we would be wise to think of households as having stationary
From all this we expect that as long as we continue to use the same expectations. We shall retum to this point later. Even so, we are
pricing rule, allowing exchange even out of equilibrium not only not yet out of the woods. If two individuals who can gain from
cannot deprive us of any existing stability results, but also may well exchange are actually to do so, it must be possible for them to find
give us stronger results. This, as we shall now see, is indeed the each other. Given enough time and a random search of households
case. for profitable exchanges, we could attempt to demonstrate that the
The reader should note, however, that the results just given show probability of the two households finding each other goes to one as
convergence to sorne equilibrium, which of cotme depends on X and time of search goes to infinity. However, since this procedure is no
,
p(O), and not to any arbitrarily preassigned equilibrium. This less unrealistic than the supposition that it is part of the auctioneer's
i'li means the process is stable, although no given equilibrium need be job to freely disseminate offers to buy and sell, we prefer to make the
1

' 1,11
stable. latter assumption. Once again, however, we are giving the auc-
1''
tioneer an uncomfortably large role. At the moment, our concern
11
3. Conditions for Trade is limited to dispelling the notion that A.l3.1 is innocuous.
One immediate consequence of A.l3.1 is that no exchange will
Let Bh(P) represent the collection of goods a household could take place if X is Pareto efticient. On the other hand, it is clear that
acquire at p without violating its budget constraint, that is, Bh(P) = X's being Pareto efticient does not imply that P is an equilibrium for
{x pxh :o:; pxh}, and let X be the matrix with columns xh. Write e
1
the economy in the sense that all excess demands are zero. Less
for the H-dimensional column vector with all elements equal to obvious, perhaps, is the fact that A.l3.1 might not permit trade to
unity. We propose to work with the following assumption. ' take place even though X is not Pareto efticient. Let us examine
AssuMPTION l. Exchange will take place at p O, if and only if this.
there is an X, with xh E B(p), all h, and Xe = Xe, such that Uh(xh) ;:o: It will be convenient to suppose that all utility functions are dif-
U(xh), all h, and Uh(xh) > Uh(xh), sorne h. ferentiable where required, and we write Uh 1(xh) = Dht as the partial
differential coefticient of Uh at x" with respect to its ith argument.
What this amounts to is an assertion that trade will take We take it, at least for the moment, that these marginal utilities are
place if and only if it is feasible for the households at p, everywhere positive and define
feasible for the economy, and leads to a Pareto-superior allocation.
(We are supposing that there is no consumption so that the total Rt
fl.-ht =-- 1, i = 1, ... , n - 1,
endowment of goods in the economy is the same before and after pi
trade; this assumption can be ignored at the cost of sorne complica- where P is the price vector in terms of good n. We also adopt the
tions.) At first sight, the assertion sounds extremely reasonable, but convention that two quantities, v and w, are of "the same sign" if
further thought quickly shows that, in fact, the proposed conditions they are both positive, or negative, or zero.
are quite restrictive. Thus we note that it is quite possible that an Now, if no trade is possible at X > O, it follows from A.13.1 that
individual who experiences a loss in utility from a given exchange f9r all i, fl.-ht must ha ve the same sign for all h. If not, since, say, the
may be prepared nonetheless to undertake it if he expects that the marginal rate of substitution between goods i and n would exceed
next p called by the auctioneer will put him in an advantageous their relative prices for sorne household, but not for some other
position to make large gains as a consequence of the exchanges he household, it is clear that the first household, could gain by ex-
has currently made. In other words, it is possible for households to changing i for n while the other household would not lose by this,
---------- ------~-~e~---~~~

T
330 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 331

provided'the exchange is made at the ruling prices. The condition Since we are permitting exchange, this assumption is equivalent to
that for all i, p,111 must be of the same sign for all h, is not enough to the assertion that conditions (a) and (b) of T.13.1 hold for X and
exclude the possibility of exchange in accordance with A.13.1 p(t), all t.
l)etween goods other than i and n. To ensure that, we must suppose Let us write Z(p,x11 ) as the excess-demand vector of household h;
that for all possible pairs i andj, p,111 - fhh! is of the same sign for all its components are xhl(p,x 11) - .X111 Then, if z11 # O, it must be,
h. Suppose, to take an example, that this difference is positive for assuming preferences strictly convex, that
h and zero for k. Then
U(X + Z) > U(X), (3)
and for any A, O < A : .:; 1, ., 1

1 ii
: 1
so that, evidently, h would gain by exchanging sorne of good i for U[A(X + Z) + (1 - A)x11 ] = U11 (Az11 + x 11) > U11(x11). '1
:1
1

,1
good j at the terms Pj/P1, while household k would be indifferent to Also for A small, !
such an exchange. On the other hand, if for all possible pairs i and '!

j, p,111 - fhh! is of the same sign for all h, then it must be that the
o< U(AZ + X) - U(X) ~ 2t
UAZ. (4)
'
marginal rate of substitution between any pair of goods bears the .. '',
,1 ' i_,',
;1
same relation (equal, greater than, less than) to the terms by which If P is the price vector in terms of good n (nth component = 1), 1

1
they can be exchanged, for all households, and thus exchange is not Pz11 = O, by the budget constraint for h. Subtracting APz11 from the 1

possible in accordance with A.13.1. We have established, therefore, right-hand side of (4) after dividing this by U11 n. we find

THEOREM l. A necessary condition for no exchange to be possible (5)


.1
in accordance with A.13.1 at X > O and p O is:
where aht = P 1p,111 , a 11 n = O, and sorne aht # O.
(a) Por all i, p,111 must be of the same sign for all h.
Now suppose x11 O, all h, and p O, and consider household k.
(b) Por all possible pairs i andj, p,111 - fhM must have the same
If this household were to satisfy the demand AZ11 of household h, the
sign, all h.
transaction would be feasible for A small enough (since xk 0).
Clearly, conditions (a) and (b) are not equivalent to the require- Moreover, px1, - pAz11 = pxk. Its utility change, then, is given by
ment that for all i, Rht must be of the same magnitude for all h, and Uk(x + A( -z11) } - Uk(x1,).
so even though X is not Pareto efficient, no trade is possible at
p o. This expression must be negative since we have postulated that no
exchange is possible. Then, certainly, for A small enough, it must
be that
4. Prices When No Trade Occurs
Consider the pricing rule
Pt = Z, i=1, ... ,n-1; and so proceeding as before,
(I)
Pn =O A 2
CXctZ > o.
where, as usual, z1 is the excess demand for good i and depends,
of course, on p and X. We wish to investigate the behavior of the Evidently, (6) must be true for all k # h, so letting
solution path of this rule on the assumption that X is constant for
all t, that is, that no exchange takes place even though it is permitted.
---------- ------~-~e~---~~~

T
330 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 331

provided'the exchange is made at the ruling prices. The condition Since we are permitting exchange, this assumption is equivalent to
that for all i, p,111 must be of the same sign for all h, is not enough to the assertion that conditions (a) and (b) of T.13.1 hold for X and
exclude the possibility of exchange in accordance with A.13.1 p(t), all t.
l)etween goods other than i and n. To ensure that, we must suppose Let us write Z(p,x11 ) as the excess-demand vector of household h;
that for all possible pairs i andj, p,111 - fhh! is of the same sign for all its components are xhl(p,x 11) - .X111 Then, if z11 # O, it must be,
h. Suppose, to take an example, that this difference is positive for assuming preferences strictly convex, that
h and zero for k. Then
U(X + Z) > U(X), (3)
and for any A, O < A : .:; 1, ., 1

1 ii
: 1
so that, evidently, h would gain by exchanging sorne of good i for U[A(X + Z) + (1 - A)x11 ] = U11 (Az11 + x 11) > U11(x11). '1
:1
1

,1
good j at the terms Pj/P1, while household k would be indifferent to Also for A small, !
such an exchange. On the other hand, if for all possible pairs i and '!

j, p,111 - fhh! is of the same sign for all h, then it must be that the
o< U(AZ + X) - U(X) ~ 2t
UAZ. (4)
'
marginal rate of substitution between any pair of goods bears the .. '',
,1 ' i_,',
;1
same relation (equal, greater than, less than) to the terms by which If P is the price vector in terms of good n (nth component = 1), 1

1
they can be exchanged, for all households, and thus exchange is not Pz11 = O, by the budget constraint for h. Subtracting APz11 from the 1

possible in accordance with A.13.1. We have established, therefore, right-hand side of (4) after dividing this by U11 n. we find

THEOREM l. A necessary condition for no exchange to be possible (5)


.1
in accordance with A.13.1 at X > O and p O is:
where aht = P 1p,111 , a 11 n = O, and sorne aht # O.
(a) Por all i, p,111 must be of the same sign for all h.
Now suppose x11 O, all h, and p O, and consider household k.
(b) Por all possible pairs i andj, p,111 - fhM must have the same
If this household were to satisfy the demand AZ11 of household h, the
sign, all h.
transaction would be feasible for A small enough (since xk 0).
Clearly, conditions (a) and (b) are not equivalent to the require- Moreover, px1, - pAz11 = pxk. Its utility change, then, is given by
ment that for all i, Rht must be of the same magnitude for all h, and Uk(x + A( -z11) } - Uk(x1,).
so even though X is not Pareto efficient, no trade is possible at
p o. This expression must be negative since we have postulated that no
exchange is possible. Then, certainly, for A small enough, it must
be that
4. Prices When No Trade Occurs
Consider the pricing rule
Pt = Z, i=1, ... ,n-1; and so proceeding as before,
(I)
Pn =O A 2
CXctZ > o.
where, as usual, z1 is the excess demand for good i and depends,
of course, on p and X. We wish to investigate the behavior of the Evidently, (6) must be true for all k # h, so letting
solution path of this rule on the assumption that X is constant for
all t, that is, that no exchange takes place even though it is permitted.
n
i
1
1.

1
1

1
T
: L 332 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
. 1 TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 333
1
1
summing (6) over k i= h, and adding (5) gives ensures that the solution paths of (1) are bounded. lf p* is a limit
i point of p(t), since for t large enough p(t) must be arbitrarily close
> 0. (7)
d A
j'
IXZhi
to p*, then by the usual argument (see the proof of T.ll.3), p* is an
equilibrium, and since by assumption p* O, it must be that
But (7) must hold for all h with z" i= O, so summing over h, we finally
11 z(p* ,X) = O. By T.13.2, X is Pareto efficient. From this it follows
have
that p(t) can have only one limit point, since a(p,X) = O, all i, can
,1
1
1
j
IXZ > 0 if z" i= O, some h. (8) have only one solution. This is enough to establish the global
stability of (1).
We may now prove We have shown, therefore, that the supposition implies that X is
THEOREM 2. Let X be strictly positive and p O. Then, if all Pareto efficient and that the latter property of the distribution matrix
utility functions are strictly quasi-concave and have positive partial implies, in turn, that (1) is globally stable. This result plays an
differential coefficients at x" and no exchange is possible at p, important role in the analysis that follows.
z(p,X) = Oimplies that X is Pareto efficient.
5. The Exchange Process
Proof. If not, then some z" i= O and so for some h and i, ahi i= O,
and from T.l3.1(a), ahi i= O and of the same sign, all h. But then, We shall now consider the story in which not only prices are
in view of z = O, we contradict (8)~ Hence z" = O, all h. changing in accordance with rule (1), but exchange also is taking
(
place whenever it is possible in accordance with A.l3.1.
We proceed to introduce
It is not easy to state a sensible rule for the rate at which exchange
AssuMPTION 2. Let p(i) be the price vector with zero in the ith is taking place between households at any on.e moment of time.
place. Then, for all feasible X and all p(i), z1[p(i),X] > O, all i. There may be a considerable variety of exchanges possible at any p
and X, and it is not clear .what simple rule of choice is appropriate.
The purpose of this assumption is to keep all prices positive and
We propose to ignore this difficulty at the moment and postulate the
to ensure that the path of prices is bounded (see below). We now
existence of a continuous function, T, that obeys the requirements of
pro ve
A.l3.1 and such that
THEOREM 3. If A.I3.2 and the assumptions of T.l3.1 hold, if no
exchange takes place anywhere on the path, and if p(O) O, then the X= T(p,X). (11)
adjustment rule is globally stable. Later we shall give an example of such a function. We shall
Proaf. Certainly, if pis notan equilibrium, (z(p,X) i= 0), it must suppose also that z( ) and T( ) satisfy a Lipschitz condition so that
be that some z" i= O, and so some a1(p,X) i= O. Let (1) and (11) combined give rise to solutions X(t) and p(t), which are
uniquely defined by the initial conditions X(O) and p(O) and are
V(p,X) = af = (R"t -
i i h
P) 2 continuous in these. Lastly, we shall suppose that for all t, p(t) O
and X(t) are positive. Of course, this implies certain restrictions on
Certainly, V(p,X) > O for all non-equilibrium P. Differentiating the utility functions of households.
V with respect to t gives, using (1), Consider the function W(p,X) defined by
V= -2 i
IXZ W(p,X) = u,(x").
and so, in view of (8), V < O for non-equilibrium P. V may be
"
By A.l3.1, it must be true that as long as exchange is going on,
taken as a Lyapounov function, since we know (12.(1)) that A.l3.2 W > O, and that in any case, W cannot decline. Therefore, we may
n
i
1
1.

1
1

1
T
: L 332 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
. 1 TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 333
1
1
summing (6) over k i= h, and adding (5) gives ensures that the solution paths of (1) are bounded. lf p* is a limit
i point of p(t), since for t large enough p(t) must be arbitrarily close
> 0. (7)
d A
j'
IXZhi
to p*, then by the usual argument (see the proof of T.ll.3), p* is an
equilibrium, and since by assumption p* O, it must be that
But (7) must hold for all h with z" i= O, so summing over h, we finally
11 z(p* ,X) = O. By T.13.2, X is Pareto efficient. From this it follows
have
that p(t) can have only one limit point, since a(p,X) = O, all i, can
,1
1
1
j
IXZ > 0 if z" i= O, some h. (8) have only one solution. This is enough to establish the global
stability of (1).
We may now prove We have shown, therefore, that the supposition implies that X is
THEOREM 2. Let X be strictly positive and p O. Then, if all Pareto efficient and that the latter property of the distribution matrix
utility functions are strictly quasi-concave and have positive partial implies, in turn, that (1) is globally stable. This result plays an
differential coefficients at x" and no exchange is possible at p, important role in the analysis that follows.
z(p,X) = Oimplies that X is Pareto efficient.
5. The Exchange Process
Proof. If not, then some z" i= O and so for some h and i, ahi i= O,
and from T.l3.1(a), ahi i= O and of the same sign, all h. But then, We shall now consider the story in which not only prices are
in view of z = O, we contradict (8)~ Hence z" = O, all h. changing in accordance with rule (1), but exchange also is taking
(
place whenever it is possible in accordance with A.l3.1.
We proceed to introduce
It is not easy to state a sensible rule for the rate at which exchange
AssuMPTION 2. Let p(i) be the price vector with zero in the ith is taking place between households at any on.e moment of time.
place. Then, for all feasible X and all p(i), z1[p(i),X] > O, all i. There may be a considerable variety of exchanges possible at any p
and X, and it is not clear .what simple rule of choice is appropriate.
The purpose of this assumption is to keep all prices positive and
We propose to ignore this difficulty at the moment and postulate the
to ensure that the path of prices is bounded (see below). We now
existence of a continuous function, T, that obeys the requirements of
pro ve
A.l3.1 and such that
THEOREM 3. If A.I3.2 and the assumptions of T.l3.1 hold, if no
exchange takes place anywhere on the path, and if p(O) O, then the X= T(p,X). (11)
adjustment rule is globally stable. Later we shall give an example of such a function. We shall
Proaf. Certainly, if pis notan equilibrium, (z(p,X) i= 0), it must suppose also that z( ) and T( ) satisfy a Lipschitz condition so that
be that some z" i= O, and so some a1(p,X) i= O. Let (1) and (11) combined give rise to solutions X(t) and p(t), which are
uniquely defined by the initial conditions X(O) and p(O) and are
V(p,X) = af = (R"t -
i i h
P) 2 continuous in these. Lastly, we shall suppose that for all t, p(t) O
and X(t) are positive. Of course, this implies certain restrictions on
Certainly, V(p,X) > O for all non-equilibrium P. Differentiating the utility functions of households.
V with respect to t gives, using (1), Consider the function W(p,X) defined by
V= -2 i
IXZ W(p,X) = u,(x").
and so, in view of (8), V < O for non-equilibrium P. V may be
"
By A.l3.1, it must be true that as long as exchange is going on,
taken as a Lyapounov function, since we know (12.(1)) that A.l3.2 W > O, and that in any case, W cannot decline. Therefore, we may
334 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 335

'i take W as a Lyapounov function, which, since p(t) and X(t) are Let S[U1 (x 1) UH(xH)] be a strictly quasi-concave social
r1
~1 bounded, approaches a limiting value W* as t approaches infinity. welfare function. Imagine it maxiinized for any p and X, subject to
1
1: In particular, the constraints that for all h,
. 1
1! Iim
t-> 00
; Uh(xh(t)) = L: u~,
1 and
since every Uh is non-decreasing (i.e., monotone), and therefore,
must approach a unique limit. Then let X* be any limit distrib::tion L: xh = L: xh.
h h
of X(t), p* any limit point of pQ) and .consi.d~r. the lim!tyaths X*(t)
and p*(t), generated by taking X* and p* as Imtial conditwns. Then, Elementary theory of such maximization assures us that, since the
certainly, individual utility functions are strictly quasi-concave, a unique
solution, which we write as the matrix X(p,X), can be found. lf we
u; = uh(x"t:) = uh(x"?:(t)) all h, imagine the household utility functions to be such that the marginal
utility of any good to any household becomes infinitely great as the
and so by A.l3.1 and strict convexity of preferences it must be that
quantity of that good goes to zero, we may take it that X(p,X) is a
x"t: = x"t:(t), all h and t; that is, X* = X*(t), ~~t. Then, on the
positive matrix. We also take X(O) to be positive. We may now
limit path p*(t), we may take X(t) constant at_X , all t, and so by
let T in (II) be given by
T.l3.3, p*(t) converges to p* such that z(p*,X*) = O. By T.l3.2,
it follows then that X* is Pareto optimal. Thus we have proved x= [X(p,X) - X].
THEOREM 4. Let X(t) and p(t) be strictly positive for all t. Let all Certainly, X(p,X) will be continuous in its arguments and the reader
utility functions be strictly quasi-concave and have partial difieren- should verify that by our assumptions, ih(t) > O, all t and h, if X(O)
tia! coefficients positive everywhere. Then the process (I) and (II) is positive.
is globally stable and. the limit is a competitive equilibrium of the W e cannot claim that this process has much to recommend it on
economy; that is, z(p,X) = O (and Pareto efficient). the grounds of realism; it is simply given to show that it is possible
to find processes such as (II). A more sensible procedure is the
It is important to recall that showing that a process is gl~bally
following, which we merely sketch. Given X(t) and p, we can define
stable is not the same thing as asserting that a particular
a small neighborhood of X(t) and note all the distribution matrices 1

equilibrium of the economy is globally stable. In particula.r,


in this small neighborhood that can be reached in accordance with
in the present case, while we can assert that the economy will
A.13.1. We could argue that the probability of any one of these
approach sorne equilibrium, we cannot. say which, until it has
matrices being reached is the same as that of reaching any other one.
approached it. Evidently, the exact nature of the exchanges under-
Thus the status of the economy at t + Eis given by p(t + E) and any
taken along any path determines which of the infinite number of
1 one of the admissible matrices. We do not knnw which of these
Pareto-efficient allocations the economy will approach. The out-
possible states actually will materialize, but for each such state, we
come here is not independent of the path. It was the desire to avoid
can calculate again a class of neighborhood matrices and the rate at
this, in part at least, that led to the development of the recontract which prices are changing. Thus we are involved in a branching
analysis. In that respect, ther~fore, recontract results are often
process. Along every branch the utilities of households are non-
stronger than our present one, since they may enable us to declare
diminishing, and as long as exchange is taking place, they are in-
one particular equilibrium globally (or locally) stable. creasing. We can be sure, then, that each branch terminates in sorne
Let us now return to the question of exchange processes that
distribution matrix since the attainable utilities are bounded above.
satisfy A.l3.1. It is not hard to construct one that, while not
For each of these "terminal" matrices we can use T.l3.2 and
necessarily sensible, is of the type (II) that we have used. T.l3.3 to show that the associated price process is now convergent
334 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 335

'i take W as a Lyapounov function, which, since p(t) and X(t) are Let S[U1 (x 1) UH(xH)] be a strictly quasi-concave social
r1
~1 bounded, approaches a limiting value W* as t approaches infinity. welfare function. Imagine it maxiinized for any p and X, subject to
1
1: In particular, the constraints that for all h,
. 1
1! Iim
t-> 00
; Uh(xh(t)) = L: u~,
1 and
since every Uh is non-decreasing (i.e., monotone), and therefore,
must approach a unique limit. Then let X* be any limit distrib::tion L: xh = L: xh.
h h
of X(t), p* any limit point of pQ) and .consi.d~r. the lim!tyaths X*(t)
and p*(t), generated by taking X* and p* as Imtial conditwns. Then, Elementary theory of such maximization assures us that, since the
certainly, individual utility functions are strictly quasi-concave, a unique
solution, which we write as the matrix X(p,X), can be found. lf we
u; = uh(x"t:) = uh(x"?:(t)) all h, imagine the household utility functions to be such that the marginal
utility of any good to any household becomes infinitely great as the
and so by A.l3.1 and strict convexity of preferences it must be that
quantity of that good goes to zero, we may take it that X(p,X) is a
x"t: = x"t:(t), all h and t; that is, X* = X*(t), ~~t. Then, on the
positive matrix. We also take X(O) to be positive. We may now
limit path p*(t), we may take X(t) constant at_X , all t, and so by
let T in (II) be given by
T.l3.3, p*(t) converges to p* such that z(p*,X*) = O. By T.l3.2,
it follows then that X* is Pareto optimal. Thus we have proved x= [X(p,X) - X].
THEOREM 4. Let X(t) and p(t) be strictly positive for all t. Let all Certainly, X(p,X) will be continuous in its arguments and the reader
utility functions be strictly quasi-concave and have partial difieren- should verify that by our assumptions, ih(t) > O, all t and h, if X(O)
tia! coefficients positive everywhere. Then the process (I) and (II) is positive.
is globally stable and. the limit is a competitive equilibrium of the W e cannot claim that this process has much to recommend it on
economy; that is, z(p,X) = O (and Pareto efficient). the grounds of realism; it is simply given to show that it is possible
to find processes such as (II). A more sensible procedure is the
It is important to recall that showing that a process is gl~bally
following, which we merely sketch. Given X(t) and p, we can define
stable is not the same thing as asserting that a particular
a small neighborhood of X(t) and note all the distribution matrices 1

equilibrium of the economy is globally stable. In particula.r,


in this small neighborhood that can be reached in accordance with
in the present case, while we can assert that the economy will
A.13.1. We could argue that the probability of any one of these
approach sorne equilibrium, we cannot. say which, until it has
matrices being reached is the same as that of reaching any other one.
approached it. Evidently, the exact nature of the exchanges under-
Thus the status of the economy at t + Eis given by p(t + E) and any
taken along any path determines which of the infinite number of
1 one of the admissible matrices. We do not knnw which of these
Pareto-efficient allocations the economy will approach. The out-
possible states actually will materialize, but for each such state, we
come here is not independent of the path. It was the desire to avoid
can calculate again a class of neighborhood matrices and the rate at
this, in part at least, that led to the development of the recontract which prices are changing. Thus we are involved in a branching
analysis. In that respect, ther~fore, recontract results are often
process. Along every branch the utilities of households are non-
stronger than our present one, since they may enable us to declare
diminishing, and as long as exchange is taking place, they are in-
one particular equilibrium globally (or locally) stable. creasing. We can be sure, then, that each branch terminates in sorne
Let us now return to the question of exchange processes that
distribution matrix since the attainable utilities are bounded above.
satisfy A.l3.1. It is not hard to construct one that, while not
For each of these "terminal" matrices we can use T.l3.2 and
necessarily sensible, is of the type (II) that we have used. T.l3.3 to show that the associated price process is now convergent
336 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 337
and that each terminal matrix is Pareto efficient. There are calcu- The assumption that p(t) O, all t, we can relax without serious
lable probabilities of the system converging on any one of these equi- difficulties. In the first place, we note that it is no longer true that
libria. Thus, while this is not a rigorous demonstration, it is not z" # O implies that U"(x" + z") > U,(x"), since it may happen that
likely that the conclusions of T.13.4 are vitally dependent on the the only non-zero component of z~~, is negative and its price is equal
existence of deterministic exchange processes such as (U). to zero, whence by free disposal, the household's utility cannot be
While it seems pretty safe to assert that our result is not very changed by disposing. On the other hand, (8) must still hold for all
sensitive to a change in the assumptions concerning the process of z" # O, zhi > O, sorne i. (We are again taking X* to be positive, of
exchange, it is not clear, unfortunately, that it is equally robust with course.) Now consider the proof of T.l3.2. From the fact that p*
respect to sorne of the other assumptions. Let us remove the is a limit point of p(t) we deduce that z(p* ,X*) ::; O. By the argu-
requirement that X(t) be positive for all t (but retain all other ment just given, it must be true that z"(p* ,x~) ::; O, all h, and so
postula tes). In other words, now we permit situations in which it may certainly X is Pareto efficient. It must be true, then, that for all
happen that at sorne point in the exchange process, individuals hold pt > O, ai(p*,X*) ::; O. But clearly there can be only one p*
zero quantities of sorne good or goods. Since the demonstration satisfying these conditions. Thus T.I3.2 and consequently T.l3.4
that the exchange process willlead X(t) to approach a distribution, are not at all dependent on the assumption that prices are strictly
X*, is not dependent on the hypothesis that X(t) are positive for all positive throughout, although the methods of proof originally
t, we can continue to use this result. However, X* may have sorne employed are. (We still require an equilibrium in which the
zero components. This has the unpleasant consequence that the exchange value of the numeraire is positive.)
inequality (8) of Section 13.4 can no longer be established. In the The assumption that the partial differential coefficients of the
notation of that section, consider the following possibility: utility functions are everywhere positive is closely related to the one
that insists that all households at all times ha ve positive quantities of
all goods. Should it be possible for the marginal utility of sorne
If h received ltz" from exchange with k, while the latter received good to be zero when none of that good is held, we will be back in
- ltz,, both would be better off, and we might conclude, therefore, the troubled waters that we ha ve already traversed. If the assump-
that exchange is possible at X*. This would be too hasty. We tion X(t) positive for all t can be maintained, however, the reader
must be sure that exchange is feasible. In particular, for sorne can check that all of our analysis will continue to hold, provided only
).. > O, it must be that x,, - )..zh has no negative components. We that we ma:y take it that the marginal utility of numeraire is nowhere
could be certain of this when x1, O. Now clearly we cannot, and zero.
so we cannot establish inequality (8) and the theorems dependent on We can sum up the state of affairs at this stage as follows. At no
it. This in turn means that we have lost the crucial information point will the exchange process fail to converge to an equilibrium if
that allowed us to declare the price path that results with the conditions are such that every recontract process is stable. On
limiting distribution X* to be stable. the other hand, to show the exchange process to be always
Since the assumption that every household always owns positive stable (whatever the form of the excess-demand functions might
stocks of every good is not a very happy one, we cannot really claim be) has required, so far, the assumption that every good is held in
very much for our results. On the other hand, it is clear that any positive quantity by every household and a restriction to the case of
of the assumptions leading to the stability of the recontract the pure-exchange economy.
process investigated in the last chapter will now serve to show that
the process that allows exchange in accordance with A.l3.1 is also
stable. Since to permit exchange during the process is more 6. A Monetary Economy
realistic than not doing so, we can claim to have improved to that The results of the last section depend entirely on the assump-
extent on the analysis, at least for a pure-exchange economy. tions that ensure that. at every stage of the process, the utilities of
336 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 337
and that each terminal matrix is Pareto efficient. There are calcu- The assumption that p(t) O, all t, we can relax without serious
lable probabilities of the system converging on any one of these equi- difficulties. In the first place, we note that it is no longer true that
libria. Thus, while this is not a rigorous demonstration, it is not z" # O implies that U"(x" + z") > U,(x"), since it may happen that
likely that the conclusions of T.13.4 are vitally dependent on the the only non-zero component of z~~, is negative and its price is equal
existence of deterministic exchange processes such as (U). to zero, whence by free disposal, the household's utility cannot be
While it seems pretty safe to assert that our result is not very changed by disposing. On the other hand, (8) must still hold for all
sensitive to a change in the assumptions concerning the process of z" # O, zhi > O, sorne i. (We are again taking X* to be positive, of
exchange, it is not clear, unfortunately, that it is equally robust with course.) Now consider the proof of T.l3.2. From the fact that p*
respect to sorne of the other assumptions. Let us remove the is a limit point of p(t) we deduce that z(p* ,X*) ::; O. By the argu-
requirement that X(t) be positive for all t (but retain all other ment just given, it must be true that z"(p* ,x~) ::; O, all h, and so
postula tes). In other words, now we permit situations in which it may certainly X is Pareto efficient. It must be true, then, that for all
happen that at sorne point in the exchange process, individuals hold pt > O, ai(p*,X*) ::; O. But clearly there can be only one p*
zero quantities of sorne good or goods. Since the demonstration satisfying these conditions. Thus T.I3.2 and consequently T.l3.4
that the exchange process willlead X(t) to approach a distribution, are not at all dependent on the assumption that prices are strictly
X*, is not dependent on the hypothesis that X(t) are positive for all positive throughout, although the methods of proof originally
t, we can continue to use this result. However, X* may have sorne employed are. (We still require an equilibrium in which the
zero components. This has the unpleasant consequence that the exchange value of the numeraire is positive.)
inequality (8) of Section 13.4 can no longer be established. In the The assumption that the partial differential coefficients of the
notation of that section, consider the following possibility: utility functions are everywhere positive is closely related to the one
that insists that all households at all times ha ve positive quantities of
all goods. Should it be possible for the marginal utility of sorne
If h received ltz" from exchange with k, while the latter received good to be zero when none of that good is held, we will be back in
- ltz,, both would be better off, and we might conclude, therefore, the troubled waters that we ha ve already traversed. If the assump-
that exchange is possible at X*. This would be too hasty. We tion X(t) positive for all t can be maintained, however, the reader
must be sure that exchange is feasible. In particular, for sorne can check that all of our analysis will continue to hold, provided only
).. > O, it must be that x,, - )..zh has no negative components. We that we ma:y take it that the marginal utility of numeraire is nowhere
could be certain of this when x1, O. Now clearly we cannot, and zero.
so we cannot establish inequality (8) and the theorems dependent on We can sum up the state of affairs at this stage as follows. At no
it. This in turn means that we have lost the crucial information point will the exchange process fail to converge to an equilibrium if
that allowed us to declare the price path that results with the conditions are such that every recontract process is stable. On
limiting distribution X* to be stable. the other hand, to show the exchange process to be always
Since the assumption that every household always owns positive stable (whatever the form of the excess-demand functions might
stocks of every good is not a very happy one, we cannot really claim be) has required, so far, the assumption that every good is held in
very much for our results. On the other hand, it is clear that any positive quantity by every household and a restriction to the case of
of the assumptions leading to the stability of the recontract the pure-exchange economy.
process investigated in the last chapter will now serve to show that
the process that allows exchange in accordance with A.l3.1 is also
stable. Since to permit exchange during the process is more 6. A Monetary Economy
realistic than not doing so, we can claim to have improved to that The results of the last section depend entirely on the assump-
extent on the analysis, at least for a pure-exchange economy. tions that ensure that. at every stage of the process, the utilities of
1
1
1,''
1'1

338 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PUREEXCHANGE ECONOMY 339

households are non-decreasing and those of sorne households are in- completion of all other transactions. Now we encounter difficulties
creasing, as long as equilibrium has not been attained. In fact, of exactly the sort we would ha ve encountered in our earlier analysis
the exchange economy may behave like a gradient process in the had we not stipulated that every household believed firmly that the
vector of household utilities. The economy we have been consider- present terms on which goods exchange would continue indefinitely.
ing, although it is one in which the auctioneer regulates the terms Of course, this picture could be somewhat modified if we made the
at which goods shall exchange, is essentially one of barter; all acts of further concession to reality of permitting lending and borrowing,
exchange are completed between two households exchanging one but we shall not do so here.
good for another. In the world in which we live, however, most acts Let us write m for the good that must mediate in exchange and
of exchange are exchanges of goods for money and money for goods, suppose that in other respects it is like other goods, in the sense that
and one feature of this arrangement is that it cannot sensibly be it yields its holder direct utility that does not depend on its exchange
argued that every such act of exchange increases the utility of at least value. In other words, at the end of the transaction process, house-
one of the participants and diminishes that of no participant. A holds plan to have a certain amount of m, which they determine in
real household, if constrained to the mediation of money, may be the same manner in which they determine the quantities of other
willing to exchange something of one good for money on the goods they plan to have (see below). Of course, this is bad mone-
supposition that the money so acquired will be 1J,Sed in exchange for tary theory, but our object here is not to examine a theory for which
sorne other good. Should the second leg of-'fhis transaction fail to the pure-exchange model is in any event peculiarly ill suited, but
materialize, then it may well be that had the household anticipated rather to concentrate on the single problem to which the necessity
this it would never have embarked on the first leg; in other words, of mediation gives rise in the analysis of such an exchange process.
the first transaction by itself leads to a fall in utility. Sorne rather (We shall assume that over the relevant range, the marginal utility of
perplexing problems now come up. m is positive for all h.)
Of course, our model is in no shape to give a satisfactory formal The amount of each good, including money, that the household
account of the role of money. In particular, it would be hard to plans to have when its transactions ha ve been completed is found by
"explain" the holding of money or why it media tes in most acts of maximizing Uh(xh,mh) subject to
exchange. For the moment, we sidestep these portentous issues by
making assumptions that, while hard to justify in the context of a Pzh + mh - ih = O.
simple pure-exchange economy, are not altogether off the mark in (P is now the price vector in terms of m.) The resulting excess
a more satisfactory and complicated world (see Chapter 14). demands we call target excess demands, and the resulting utility is
The first thing to notice is that if sorne commodity called money the target utility. By assumption, however, if the superscript "+" 1 1,

indeed must mediate in exchange, this in itself does not yet damage to a vector denotes that subvector whose components are non-
our conclusions of the previous section if we can take it that sales negative, at any moment t the household is further constrained by
and purchases are simultaneous. In this case, there is no "first leg"
and "second leg" of a transaction and we could continue to postu- (9)
late that every transaction is of a kind that does not decrease the (where we take the dimension of P from the context). If the
utility of the transactors. If this is the case, however, we certainly constraint is binding at t, then the household must plan a sequence
would be hard put to explainwhy any household should hold any of transactions in order to attain its target utility.
money at all (here, of course, we are abstracting from price uncer- Every household will be taken to believe that its transactions will
tainty). On the other hand, if we postulate that a purchase at any succeed. If we take the interval between transactions to be very
moment of time cannot be financed from the sales of that moment small, we may suppose that the household does not care by what
then every transaction of a household is speculative in the sense that sequence it attains its target. Accordingly, we shall stipulate a rule
the utility change from any one transaction is contingent on the of thumb that the household will be taken to follow. We write
1
1
1,''
1'1

338 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PUREEXCHANGE ECONOMY 339

households are non-decreasing and those of sorne households are in- completion of all other transactions. Now we encounter difficulties
creasing, as long as equilibrium has not been attained. In fact, of exactly the sort we would ha ve encountered in our earlier analysis
the exchange economy may behave like a gradient process in the had we not stipulated that every household believed firmly that the
vector of household utilities. The economy we have been consider- present terms on which goods exchange would continue indefinitely.
ing, although it is one in which the auctioneer regulates the terms Of course, this picture could be somewhat modified if we made the
at which goods shall exchange, is essentially one of barter; all acts of further concession to reality of permitting lending and borrowing,
exchange are completed between two households exchanging one but we shall not do so here.
good for another. In the world in which we live, however, most acts Let us write m for the good that must mediate in exchange and
of exchange are exchanges of goods for money and money for goods, suppose that in other respects it is like other goods, in the sense that
and one feature of this arrangement is that it cannot sensibly be it yields its holder direct utility that does not depend on its exchange
argued that every such act of exchange increases the utility of at least value. In other words, at the end of the transaction process, house-
one of the participants and diminishes that of no participant. A holds plan to have a certain amount of m, which they determine in
real household, if constrained to the mediation of money, may be the same manner in which they determine the quantities of other
willing to exchange something of one good for money on the goods they plan to have (see below). Of course, this is bad mone-
supposition that the money so acquired will be 1J,Sed in exchange for tary theory, but our object here is not to examine a theory for which
sorne other good. Should the second leg of-'fhis transaction fail to the pure-exchange model is in any event peculiarly ill suited, but
materialize, then it may well be that had the household anticipated rather to concentrate on the single problem to which the necessity
this it would never have embarked on the first leg; in other words, of mediation gives rise in the analysis of such an exchange process.
the first transaction by itself leads to a fall in utility. Sorne rather (We shall assume that over the relevant range, the marginal utility of
perplexing problems now come up. m is positive for all h.)
Of course, our model is in no shape to give a satisfactory formal The amount of each good, including money, that the household
account of the role of money. In particular, it would be hard to plans to have when its transactions ha ve been completed is found by
"explain" the holding of money or why it media tes in most acts of maximizing Uh(xh,mh) subject to
exchange. For the moment, we sidestep these portentous issues by
making assumptions that, while hard to justify in the context of a Pzh + mh - ih = O.
simple pure-exchange economy, are not altogether off the mark in (P is now the price vector in terms of m.) The resulting excess
a more satisfactory and complicated world (see Chapter 14). demands we call target excess demands, and the resulting utility is
The first thing to notice is that if sorne commodity called money the target utility. By assumption, however, if the superscript "+" 1 1,

indeed must mediate in exchange, this in itself does not yet damage to a vector denotes that subvector whose components are non-
our conclusions of the previous section if we can take it that sales negative, at any moment t the household is further constrained by
and purchases are simultaneous. In this case, there is no "first leg"
and "second leg" of a transaction and we could continue to postu- (9)
late that every transaction is of a kind that does not decrease the (where we take the dimension of P from the context). If the
utility of the transactors. If this is the case, however, we certainly constraint is binding at t, then the household must plan a sequence
would be hard put to explainwhy any household should hold any of transactions in order to attain its target utility.
money at all (here, of course, we are abstracting from price uncer- Every household will be taken to believe that its transactions will
tainty). On the other hand, if we postulate that a purchase at any succeed. If we take the interval between transactions to be very
moment of time cannot be financed from the sales of that moment small, we may suppose that the household does not care by what
then every transaction of a household is speculative in the sense that sequence it attains its target. Accordingly, we shall stipulate a rule
the utility change from any one transaction is contingent on the of thumb that the household will be taken to follow. We write
T
1

340 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS 1


TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 341

ahi(t) as the household's excess demand at moment t for good i and Let a(t) be the active excess demand for i by h at t and define
a(t) as the vector with these components. The latter is such to be a 1(t) similarly. Then
consistent with both the budget and the financia! constraint (9).
AsSUMPTION 5. Por any h and i,
ASSUMPTION 3. Por zhi(t) > 0,
a~ 1 (0) #- O implies a 111 (0)a1(0) > O.
m"(t) )
t = mm 1, Pzi(t)
1 ( ) (
K 11 Note that A.13.5 implies that a 1(0) = O if and only if a 111(0) = O,
all h.
Por z"(t) :::; O,
We would like the conditions of A.l3.5 to hold for all t ;:;:: O.
Let
X~ 1 (t) = a 111 (t) + X~{t),
This rule is arbitrary, of course. It supposes that when financia!
constraints are binding, target purchases all are reduced in the same so that X~t(t) is the stock ofthe ith good h would actively wish to have
proportion. Also, it assumes that the household is prepared to at t. Also let
spend all its money at t. Evidently, a number of alternative H(i,t) = {h 1 a(t)x~ 1 (t) < O, a(t) = O}
hypotheses are available. The important point to emphasize is that
the vector a~(t), which we shall call the active excess-demand vector and note that from A.13.3, if m11 (t) > O, then a" 1(t) =O, only
of household h, represents the actual transactions the household is if zhi(t) = O. Pinally let a superscript "+" denote a non-negative
willing to undertake at t. variable and a superscript "-" denote a negative variable. We now
In formulating the price adjustment rule we may take advantage introduce
of the ext.ra realism the present construction affords. Instead of ASSUMPTION 6. (a) Por i such that a 1(t) #- 0,
supposing that prices are moved by target excess demands, we now
ensure that active excess demands are responsible. This is sorne X(t) = X~(t) if h E H(i,t),
improvement since target excess demands are private to individuals
while active excess demands are public. X(t) = - a(t)
a(f)
_
I!EH (i,t)
x~1 (t) if h t/= H(i,t).

AsSUMPTION 4. Pt = O for i = m and for Pt = O, a1 ::::; O; Pt = at


(b) Por i such that a 1(t) =O,
otherwise, where a 1 = 2: a 111
/
x111 (t) = min[l,v(t)]x~ 1 (t) if x~ 1 (t) ;:;:: O
Since we are taking money as the numeraire we take A.13.2 to hold
for Zm- Since 2: Ptat ::::; 2: PtZt = - zm, we use an argument like that X(t) = min[l ,v 1- (t)]x~ 1 (t)
1
if x~1 (t) < O
employed in the proof of T.l2. 7 to show that prices will be bounded. where
We now turn to the process of exchange. Our concept of active
excess demands allows us to think of a proper market for a good i, V(t) =
one that brings together agents willing to exchange i for money and
vice-versa. We suppose that if there are willing sellers and willing
buyers, the two groups will transact. Should prices remain constant This assumption is pretty cumbersome, but it has a simple
for sorne time, we would expect a positive (negative) aggregate interpretation.
excess demand in market i to be possible only if no agent has a (a) The first part says that a household with zero excess demand
negative (positive) active excess demand for the good. It is at this can transact at the desired level if its excess demand is changing in a
point that we propose to start the story. direction opposite to the prevailing aggregate active excess demand.
T
1

340 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS 1


TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 341

ahi(t) as the household's excess demand at moment t for good i and Let a(t) be the active excess demand for i by h at t and define
a(t) as the vector with these components. The latter is such to be a 1(t) similarly. Then
consistent with both the budget and the financia! constraint (9).
AsSUMPTION 5. Por any h and i,
ASSUMPTION 3. Por zhi(t) > 0,
a~ 1 (0) #- O implies a 111 (0)a1(0) > O.
m"(t) )
t = mm 1, Pzi(t)
1 ( ) (
K 11 Note that A.13.5 implies that a 1(0) = O if and only if a 111(0) = O,
all h.
Por z"(t) :::; O,
We would like the conditions of A.l3.5 to hold for all t ;:;:: O.
Let
X~ 1 (t) = a 111 (t) + X~{t),
This rule is arbitrary, of course. It supposes that when financia!
constraints are binding, target purchases all are reduced in the same so that X~t(t) is the stock ofthe ith good h would actively wish to have
proportion. Also, it assumes that the household is prepared to at t. Also let
spend all its money at t. Evidently, a number of alternative H(i,t) = {h 1 a(t)x~ 1 (t) < O, a(t) = O}
hypotheses are available. The important point to emphasize is that
the vector a~(t), which we shall call the active excess-demand vector and note that from A.13.3, if m11 (t) > O, then a" 1(t) =O, only
of household h, represents the actual transactions the household is if zhi(t) = O. Pinally let a superscript "+" denote a non-negative
willing to undertake at t. variable and a superscript "-" denote a negative variable. We now
In formulating the price adjustment rule we may take advantage introduce
of the ext.ra realism the present construction affords. Instead of ASSUMPTION 6. (a) Por i such that a 1(t) #- 0,
supposing that prices are moved by target excess demands, we now
ensure that active excess demands are responsible. This is sorne X(t) = X~(t) if h E H(i,t),
improvement since target excess demands are private to individuals
while active excess demands are public. X(t) = - a(t)
a(f)
_
I!EH (i,t)
x~1 (t) if h t/= H(i,t).

AsSUMPTION 4. Pt = O for i = m and for Pt = O, a1 ::::; O; Pt = at


(b) Por i such that a 1(t) =O,
otherwise, where a 1 = 2: a 111
/
x111 (t) = min[l,v(t)]x~ 1 (t) if x~ 1 (t) ;:;:: O
Since we are taking money as the numeraire we take A.13.2 to hold
for Zm- Since 2: Ptat ::::; 2: PtZt = - zm, we use an argument like that X(t) = min[l ,v 1- (t)]x~ 1 (t)
1
if x~1 (t) < O
employed in the proof of T.l2. 7 to show that prices will be bounded. where
We now turn to the process of exchange. Our concept of active
excess demands allows us to think of a proper market for a good i, V(t) =
one that brings together agents willing to exchange i for money and
vice-versa. We suppose that if there are willing sellers and willing
buyers, the two groups will transact. Should prices remain constant This assumption is pretty cumbersome, but it has a simple
for sorne time, we would expect a positive (negative) aggregate interpretation.
excess demand in market i to be possible only if no agent has a (a) The first part says that a household with zero excess demand
negative (positive) active excess demand for the good. It is at this can transact at the desired level if its excess demand is changing in a
point that we propose to start the story. direction opposite to the prevailing aggregate active excess demand.
,,11'

342 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T
1
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 343

The second part states that there is a" rationing" of available "new" assume a(O) # O, all i, and
sales and purchases among unsatisfied buyers and sellers. -'- ( t ) = Xht t)
ah((
a ( t ) - - " xhl
a ( t ) .
Xnt ) L..,
(b) Suppose a1(t) = O does imply aht(t) = O, all h. Certainly this a1 t 1
is true at t = O, by A.l3.5. New transactions in this market depend Summing these equations over h and using the definition of x~1 (t)
on the excess demand of one h becoming positive and of sorne other gives
h negative. The assumptions ensure that not more can be bought
than is being newly supplied and no more can be sold than is being
newly demanded. Moreover, there is once again a rationing process W e can easily check
when not all new demands or supplies can be met.
We can easily verify that A.l3.6 ensures
2 xht(t) = o
h
all i.
Clearly, the preceding process preserves what we want-a1(t)ah1(t)
O, all h, i, or t-and no continuity problems arise. But it has less
:::=:

Moreover, in conjunction with A.l3.5 we now have, provided that to recommend it on economic grounds. In what follows we shall
for all h and all t ;:::: O, fn(t) > O, use A.13.6 with the premise of "sufficiently many agents," but the
reader can readily check that all our conclusions will hold also for
a,(t)a1(t) > O if ah 1(t) ., O, all h, i and t ;:::: O. (10) the above process.
Suppose that at T, two active excess demands, say aht(T) and Now we may easily establish the following preliminary results:
a1ct(T), become of opposite sign for the first time. One of them, at LEMMA l. Let H(t) = {h 1 fh(t) = 0}. Then, if H(t) = 0, all
least, must be zero at T, supposing a1ct(T) = O. Then k e H(i,T) and t ;:::: O, h(t) ::::; O, all h.
d,ct(T). = O, making it impossible that at T the two excess demands Proof From the budget constraint,
are becoming oppositely signed.
The reason the story seems a little strained is that we have chosen P(t)zh(t) + P(t)x~t(t) + rhh(t) - [P(t)~h(t) + n'i~t(t)] = O (11)
to work in continuous time. If we imagined an interval between Since H(t) = 0, all t ;:::: O, it follows from A.l3.3 that
each price change that is long enough to allow all transactions to be
Z~t(t)a~tt(t) ;:::: O all i.
completed, it would not be fanciful to suppose that there are no
willing sellers or buyers left in the same market at the end of the From (10), then,
interval. zh 1(t)a(t) ;:::: O all i,
There is one objection to A.l3.6(a). To ensure continuity in the and so by A.l3.4, the first term in (11) is non-negative. The last
transactions, we must suppose that there are very many agents. term in (11) is zero since a household cannot change its wealth by
Otherwise, the sum exchange. Hence
P(t)xn(t) + mh(t) ::::; O. (12)
But from target utility maximization,
may change discontinuously when a new agent enters the set H(i,t).
It is not clear how serious a problem this is for the analysis (Lip-
h(t) = 2 Uht(t)xht(t) + rhh(t)>.n(t)
t
schitz conditions are in danger of being violated), but the reader = >.n(t)[P(t)xh(t) + rhh(t)].
must suppose that there are sufficiently many agents.
8Uh(t) )
The above continuity difficulty can be avoided at the cost of ( !tit) = 8mh(t) > O.
economic realism. Por instance, we can assume that for a1 # O the
Using (12), then, proves the lemma.
ratio ahja1 is kept constant by transactions. Thus, for example,
,,11'

342 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T
1
TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 343

The second part states that there is a" rationing" of available "new" assume a(O) # O, all i, and
sales and purchases among unsatisfied buyers and sellers. -'- ( t ) = Xht t)
ah((
a ( t ) - - " xhl
a ( t ) .
Xnt ) L..,
(b) Suppose a1(t) = O does imply aht(t) = O, all h. Certainly this a1 t 1
is true at t = O, by A.l3.5. New transactions in this market depend Summing these equations over h and using the definition of x~1 (t)
on the excess demand of one h becoming positive and of sorne other gives
h negative. The assumptions ensure that not more can be bought
than is being newly supplied and no more can be sold than is being
newly demanded. Moreover, there is once again a rationing process W e can easily check
when not all new demands or supplies can be met.
We can easily verify that A.l3.6 ensures
2 xht(t) = o
h
all i.
Clearly, the preceding process preserves what we want-a1(t)ah1(t)
O, all h, i, or t-and no continuity problems arise. But it has less
:::=:

Moreover, in conjunction with A.l3.5 we now have, provided that to recommend it on economic grounds. In what follows we shall
for all h and all t ;:::: O, fn(t) > O, use A.13.6 with the premise of "sufficiently many agents," but the
reader can readily check that all our conclusions will hold also for
a,(t)a1(t) > O if ah 1(t) ., O, all h, i and t ;:::: O. (10) the above process.
Suppose that at T, two active excess demands, say aht(T) and Now we may easily establish the following preliminary results:
a1ct(T), become of opposite sign for the first time. One of them, at LEMMA l. Let H(t) = {h 1 fh(t) = 0}. Then, if H(t) = 0, all
least, must be zero at T, supposing a1ct(T) = O. Then k e H(i,T) and t ;:::: O, h(t) ::::; O, all h.
d,ct(T). = O, making it impossible that at T the two excess demands Proof From the budget constraint,
are becoming oppositely signed.
The reason the story seems a little strained is that we have chosen P(t)zh(t) + P(t)x~t(t) + rhh(t) - [P(t)~h(t) + n'i~t(t)] = O (11)
to work in continuous time. If we imagined an interval between Since H(t) = 0, all t ;:::: O, it follows from A.l3.3 that
each price change that is long enough to allow all transactions to be
Z~t(t)a~tt(t) ;:::: O all i.
completed, it would not be fanciful to suppose that there are no
willing sellers or buyers left in the same market at the end of the From (10), then,
interval. zh 1(t)a(t) ;:::: O all i,
There is one objection to A.l3.6(a). To ensure continuity in the and so by A.l3.4, the first term in (11) is non-negative. The last
transactions, we must suppose that there are very many agents. term in (11) is zero since a household cannot change its wealth by
Otherwise, the sum exchange. Hence
P(t)xn(t) + mh(t) ::::; O. (12)
But from target utility maximization,
may change discontinuously when a new agent enters the set H(i,t).
It is not clear how serious a problem this is for the analysis (Lip-
h(t) = 2 Uht(t)xht(t) + rhh(t)>.n(t)
t
schitz conditions are in danger of being violated), but the reader = >.n(t)[P(t)xh(t) + rhh(t)].
must suppose that there are sufficiently many agents.
8Uh(t) )
The above continuity difficulty can be avoided at the cost of ( !tit) = 8mh(t) > O.
economic realism. Por instance, we can assume that for a1 # O the
Using (12), then, proves the lemma.
ratio ahja1 is kept constant by transactions. Thus, for example,
! 1''
---------------1---------------------...
344 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 345

Corollary to Lemma l. If H(t) = 0, all t :::0: O, and a(t) "# O, comprise another possible set of limiting target demands. Then
sorne i, then h(t~ ~ O, all h, and h(t) < O, sorne h. U(x~,m~) =, U1{x~*,m~*) = U~ all h,
Proof. Evidentb the :first term in (11) must be strictly positive for and so, by the strict quasi-concavity of U,
sorne h and so (12) is strictly negative for sorne h. P*(x~ - x~*) + m~ - m~* < O all h.
i 1
These results suggest that we may be able to make the target Summing over h leads to a contradiction of :; x~ = :; :X" = :; x~*,
i, utilities serve the same role in the analysis of the present process as :;m'?; = m = :;m'?;*. Hence there is only one limiting set of target
li
did the actual utilities in the previous section. In the latter case the demands. But x't; = x't;, for if not, at "# O. Hence there is also a
lil,' actual utilities were never declining, while here, as long as H(t) is unique set of limit endowments: x't;,m't;. Evidently, then, P* is also
l :i il always empty, the target utilities are never increasing. Unfor- the limit point of the price sequence, and the process is globally
1 jl:l tunately there are no1 simple means by which we can ensure that stable.
1, 1
H(t) = 0, all t, and for the moment, we shall simply postulate that It is clear that this result is heavily dependent on the supposition
1
this is the case. that at all moments of time, households are in a position to purchase
1 THEOREM 5. If H(t) = \, all t > O, then the economy has a globally ifthey so desire. To use Keynesian language, we have assumed that
1

at least a part of every positive demand for a good can be translated,


11
1, stable adjustment process' under assumptions A. 13.3-A.13.6.
at all times, into "effective" demand. When this is not true, and
1:
Proof. (a) By de:finition, U[X(t),m(t)] :::0: [Uix")(t), m(t)]. there is nothing to ensure that it should be true, then we certainly
Moreover, we may take Uh[x"(t),mh(t)] as bounded from below. break the thread that links the analy,sis of the process to the behavior
(b) Let of utilities over time and it is clear that additional assumptions must
V(t) = U[X~t(t),m(t)].
h
be introduced in order to ensure that the process is stable. Evidently,
if a household's positive target excess demand fqr sorne good ca:nnot
,'1 Then, by the Corollary to Lemma 1, V(t) < O when a(t) "# O. On be translated into a positive active excess demand because of the
the other hand, a;(t) = O, all i, must mean a~tt(t) = O, all h and i, financia! restraint, it is quite possible that the active excess demand
and since H(t) = 0, Z~t;(t) = z(t) = O, all i and h. Then for this good in the economy as a whole is negative. In that case,
= 2 m"(t) = m 2 mh(t). the arguments of Lemma 1 no longer apply.
m(t) =
h h It is clear that there are other assumptions that could be invoked
to allow the exchange process to converge even if we cannot ensure
Hence V(t) = O if and only if the economy is in equilibrium, and that households ha ve positive stocks of money at every stage of the
so V(t) is a Lyapounov function, in view of (9). process. We have pursued this matter far enough to learn the main
(e) We now have, in view ofLemma 1 (which makes h(t) >O lessons, however. In a pure-exchange economy the necessity of
impossible), mediation of sorne good in exchange introduces a speculative element
lim Uh(t) = Uh[(x"(P*,x;i',m't;), m(P*,x't;,m't;)] = U~ (13) that, in itself, will not prevent convergence to an equilibrium pro-
t--+ 00
vided no household is prevented from an act of exchange by lack of
where P*, x't;, and m'?; are limit points of the path of prices and of the medium of exchange. When this is not the case-and a good
endowments. Let x~ = xh(P*,x't;,m;i'), m'?; = mh(P*,x;i',m'l;). It deal of modern analysis suggests that this is the more interesting
must be that :; x;i' = :; :X", :; m~ = m. 'If not, sorne aT "# O and hypothesis-convergence must be in doubt and, in any case, requires
't;(x't; ,m'?;) < O, sorne h, a contradiction of the de:finition of U*. further study. We shall return to this question in our examination
Then suppose that x;'* = xh(P**,x;i'*,m't;*) and of the Keynesian economy.
Lastly, the reader is reminded that the "monetary theory" of this
** -
mh m (P**'x-**
- h "'h m-**) section is extremely rudimentary.
! 1''
---------------1---------------------...
344 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS TRADING OUT OF EQUILIBRIUM: A PURE-EXCHANGE ECONOMY 345

Corollary to Lemma l. If H(t) = 0, all t :::0: O, and a(t) "# O, comprise another possible set of limiting target demands. Then
sorne i, then h(t~ ~ O, all h, and h(t) < O, sorne h. U(x~,m~) =, U1{x~*,m~*) = U~ all h,
Proof. Evidentb the :first term in (11) must be strictly positive for and so, by the strict quasi-concavity of U,
sorne h and so (12) is strictly negative for sorne h. P*(x~ - x~*) + m~ - m~* < O all h.
i 1
These results suggest that we may be able to make the target Summing over h leads to a contradiction of :; x~ = :; :X" = :; x~*,
i, utilities serve the same role in the analysis of the present process as :;m'?; = m = :;m'?;*. Hence there is only one limiting set of target
li
did the actual utilities in the previous section. In the latter case the demands. But x't; = x't;, for if not, at "# O. Hence there is also a
lil,' actual utilities were never declining, while here, as long as H(t) is unique set of limit endowments: x't;,m't;. Evidently, then, P* is also
l :i il always empty, the target utilities are never increasing. Unfor- the limit point of the price sequence, and the process is globally
1 jl:l tunately there are no1 simple means by which we can ensure that stable.
1, 1
H(t) = 0, all t, and for the moment, we shall simply postulate that It is clear that this result is heavily dependent on the supposition
1
this is the case. that at all moments of time, households are in a position to purchase
1 THEOREM 5. If H(t) = \, all t > O, then the economy has a globally ifthey so desire. To use Keynesian language, we have assumed that
1

at least a part of every positive demand for a good can be translated,


11
1, stable adjustment process' under assumptions A. 13.3-A.13.6.
at all times, into "effective" demand. When this is not true, and
1:
Proof. (a) By de:finition, U[X(t),m(t)] :::0: [Uix")(t), m(t)]. there is nothing to ensure that it should be true, then we certainly
Moreover, we may take Uh[x"(t),mh(t)] as bounded from below. break the thread that links the analy,sis of the process to the behavior
(b) Let of utilities over time and it is clear that additional assumptions must
V(t) = U[X~t(t),m(t)].
h
be introduced in order to ensure that the process is stable. Evidently,
if a household's positive target excess demand fqr sorne good ca:nnot
,'1 Then, by the Corollary to Lemma 1, V(t) < O when a(t) "# O. On be translated into a positive active excess demand because of the
the other hand, a;(t) = O, all i, must mean a~tt(t) = O, all h and i, financia! restraint, it is quite possible that the active excess demand
and since H(t) = 0, Z~t;(t) = z(t) = O, all i and h. Then for this good in the economy as a whole is negative. In that case,
= 2 m"(t) = m 2 mh(t). the arguments of Lemma 1 no longer apply.
m(t) =
h h It is clear that there are other assumptions that could be invoked
to allow the exchange process to converge even if we cannot ensure
Hence V(t) = O if and only if the economy is in equilibrium, and that households ha ve positive stocks of money at every stage of the
so V(t) is a Lyapounov function, in view of (9). process. We have pursued this matter far enough to learn the main
(e) We now have, in view ofLemma 1 (which makes h(t) >O lessons, however. In a pure-exchange economy the necessity of
impossible), mediation of sorne good in exchange introduces a speculative element
lim Uh(t) = Uh[(x"(P*,x;i',m't;), m(P*,x't;,m't;)] = U~ (13) that, in itself, will not prevent convergence to an equilibrium pro-
t--+ 00
vided no household is prevented from an act of exchange by lack of
where P*, x't;, and m'?; are limit points of the path of prices and of the medium of exchange. When this is not the case-and a good
endowments. Let x~ = xh(P*,x't;,m;i'), m'?; = mh(P*,x;i',m'l;). It deal of modern analysis suggests that this is the more interesting
must be that :; x;i' = :; :X", :; m~ = m. 'If not, sorne aT "# O and hypothesis-convergence must be in doubt and, in any case, requires
't;(x't; ,m'?;) < O, sorne h, a contradiction of the de:finition of U*. further study. We shall return to this question in our examination
Then suppose that x;'* = xh(P**,x;i'*,m't;*) and of the Keynesian economy.
Lastly, the reader is reminded that the "monetary theory" of this
** -
mh m (P**'x-**
- h "'h m-**) section is extremely rudimentary.
,l
T ji
1

346 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


Chapter Fourteen
7. Conclusions
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL
The economy in.vestigated in this chapter is still only a distant
relative of the economy we :know. Nevertheless we may claim to i!
1

have learned something. In particular, since A.l3.1 is not un- Things fall apart, the center does not
reasonable in its context and since T.13.4 is rather general in content, hold. i;.l
we must conclude that failure of the market mechanism to establish -W. 'B. Yeats, The Second Coming 1''
an equilibrium-if such failures are in fact observable-must be due li!
to the elements of the actual economy that the economy of Section
13.4 neglects. This information is worth having.
The most conspicuous neglects in the analysis up to Section 13.5
'i are speculative exchanges, mediation, and production. Of these, we
l. Introduction
1

1
have investigated only one. The conclusions that the necessity of
mediation itself introduces a "speculative" element into the proc- Keynes was concerned with what we have called temporary
ess of exchange and that general convergence results a la T.13.4 equilibrium (Sections 2.10 and 6.3). However, our previous
seem available only when rather strong special assumptions are made analysis requires sorne modification before it can be applied to the
are perhaps of interest. Speculation of the traditional kind, that is, Keynesian case. This is so for two reasons. In Section 6.3 we
purchases with a view to resale and vice versa, are best treated in a supposed that at the moment an equilibrium was to be shown to
model that includes consumption and production. We should not exist, economic agents had no cominitments left from the past, and
be surprised if we find, when we briefiy turn to this matter in Chapter secondly, the economy discussed was not explicitly a monetary one.
14, that stability may become problematical. In particular, the One of the questions we shall study in this chapter is whether the
absence of production in our analysis so far is significanL If we appropriate, required modifications may lead us to modify the
recall the "stock-fiow" problems associated with the existence of proposition that a temporary equilibrium always exists. This is a
durable purchases we may conjecture that we shall find it much matter of interest because Keynes has often been interpreted as
harder to ensure a "well-behaved" market mechanism in a claiming that, in fact, a temporary equilibrium (as we have defined
production economy. it) may not exist.
There is another, less formal possible interpretation of the
General Theory. In this view, Keynes was more concerned with
Notes demonstrating a "failure" of the price mechanism than arguing that
The first study of a process without recontract was reported by there exist no prices that make equilibrium possible. Considering
Negishi [1961]. He allowed endowments of households to vary out of the amount of attention he gave to matters such as expectations and
equilibrium in a continuous way and stipulated GS. The process of speculation, this is a very plausible interpretation. The out-of-
Section 13.1 was first studied by Uzawa [1962] and, in a somewhat equilibrium behavior of an economy in which transactions take place
different form, by Hahn [1962]. The assumption that the signs of
private and aggregate excess demands for each good were always the at all prices we know to be hard to analyze. We shall do no more
same was first investigated by Hahn and Negishi [1962] and further than consider a number of rather general problems raised by such
extended to include adaptive expectations by Negishi [1964]. The an undertaking.
discussion on the modification of the analysis when a medium of This chapter as a whole, of course, is not concerned with either a
exchange is present owes its point of departure to Clower [1965]. full exposition of Keynes or a detailed analysis of all the problems
raised. We are solely concerned with relating certain features of
this model to what has gone before in this book.
347
,l
T ji
1

346 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


Chapter Fourteen
7. Conclusions
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL
The economy in.vestigated in this chapter is still only a distant
relative of the economy we :know. Nevertheless we may claim to i!
1

have learned something. In particular, since A.l3.1 is not un- Things fall apart, the center does not
reasonable in its context and since T.13.4 is rather general in content, hold. i;.l
we must conclude that failure of the market mechanism to establish -W. 'B. Yeats, The Second Coming 1''
an equilibrium-if such failures are in fact observable-must be due li!
to the elements of the actual economy that the economy of Section
13.4 neglects. This information is worth having.
The most conspicuous neglects in the analysis up to Section 13.5
'i are speculative exchanges, mediation, and production. Of these, we
l. Introduction
1

1
have investigated only one. The conclusions that the necessity of
mediation itself introduces a "speculative" element into the proc- Keynes was concerned with what we have called temporary
ess of exchange and that general convergence results a la T.13.4 equilibrium (Sections 2.10 and 6.3). However, our previous
seem available only when rather strong special assumptions are made analysis requires sorne modification before it can be applied to the
are perhaps of interest. Speculation of the traditional kind, that is, Keynesian case. This is so for two reasons. In Section 6.3 we
purchases with a view to resale and vice versa, are best treated in a supposed that at the moment an equilibrium was to be shown to
model that includes consumption and production. We should not exist, economic agents had no cominitments left from the past, and
be surprised if we find, when we briefiy turn to this matter in Chapter secondly, the economy discussed was not explicitly a monetary one.
14, that stability may become problematical. In particular, the One of the questions we shall study in this chapter is whether the
absence of production in our analysis so far is significanL If we appropriate, required modifications may lead us to modify the
recall the "stock-fiow" problems associated with the existence of proposition that a temporary equilibrium always exists. This is a
durable purchases we may conjecture that we shall find it much matter of interest because Keynes has often been interpreted as
harder to ensure a "well-behaved" market mechanism in a claiming that, in fact, a temporary equilibrium (as we have defined
production economy. it) may not exist.
There is another, less formal possible interpretation of the
General Theory. In this view, Keynes was more concerned with
Notes demonstrating a "failure" of the price mechanism than arguing that
The first study of a process without recontract was reported by there exist no prices that make equilibrium possible. Considering
Negishi [1961]. He allowed endowments of households to vary out of the amount of attention he gave to matters such as expectations and
equilibrium in a continuous way and stipulated GS. The process of speculation, this is a very plausible interpretation. The out-of-
Section 13.1 was first studied by Uzawa [1962] and, in a somewhat equilibrium behavior of an economy in which transactions take place
different form, by Hahn [1962]. The assumption that the signs of
private and aggregate excess demands for each good were always the at all prices we know to be hard to analyze. We shall do no more
same was first investigated by Hahn and Negishi [1962] and further than consider a number of rather general problems raised by such
extended to include adaptive expectations by Negishi [1964]. The an undertaking.
discussion on the modification of the analysis when a medium of This chapter as a whole, of course, is not concerned with either a
exchange is present owes its point of departure to Clower [1965]. full exposition of Keynes or a detailed analysis of all the problems
raised. We are solely concerned with relating certain features of
this model to what has gone before in this book.
347
T
1

348 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 349

2. Sorne Preliminaries transactions such as the search for information, but who them-
selves do not perform costlessly. Moreover, most transactions take
We cannot here attempt a detailed and full analysis of a monetary
time and perhaps sorne effort, such as traveling.
economy. However, there are certain features that it is useful to
discuss before we proceed. From these considerations alone it is possible to construct an
explanation of why an economic agent should hold part of his wealth
Money. So far in this book, except in ehapter 8 and briefly in in a medium of exchange with zero rate of return even when there
ehapter 13, the existence of markets has been taken for granted. are other assets yielding a positive rate of return. Of course, insofar
Once economic agents know market prices they take it that they can as money is held (and here money is supposed to be intrinsically
transact to any extent on these terrns. The process of exchange is worthless), it is held for future transactions. This would not occur
entirely anonymous-no bargain need be struck between any two if there were in existence al! the futures markets discussed in Section
agents. It is pretty clear that this would be entirely unrealistic in an 2.9. The cost of organizing all these markets is one reason we do
economy with no medium of exchange. eonsider three individuals, not have them and, thus, one reason we use money. eosts also are
A, B, and e, where A has quantities of goods X and Y and derives responsible for the fact that sales and purchases do not always
no utility from good Z, B has quantities of goods Y and Z and coincide in time. Thus, for instance, if a household sells services to
derives no utility from good X, and e has quantities of Z and X and a firm, the latter will ha vean incentive to economize in the frequency
derives no utility from Y. It is perfectly clear that there are no of payment, that is, in the number of transactions. On the-other
terms on which any two of the agents could beneficially trade with hand, should the household buy only after it has actually sold (been
each other, although there may be available, at sorne terms of paid), it would be involved in storage costs.
exchange, triangular trades that are Pareto superior to the present Jt will be noted that so far we have not made the point that the
allocation. To make sure that the equilibriurn of this economy is future is uncertain and that in the absence of the requisite number
Pareto efficient we would have to assume that all possible triangular of contingent futures markets, well-known propositions in the theory
trades have been explored by the three households. It is easy to of choice under uncertainty can be invoked to explain why agents
construct exarnples in which chains of arbitrarily many links would should include money in their portfolio of assets. In this view, the
have to be taken as explored by each agent before the resulting rate of return foregone in holding money is a kind of insurance
equilibrium could be shown to be Pareto efficient. premium against the possibility that, in fact, the rate of return on
Such explorations ha ve two fea tu res: They are costly, and since other assets may turn out to be negative. Of course, if the "best
they may involve a household in an exchange that, as such, is not guess" is that the return on other assets will be negative, no further
"beneficia!," but is undertaken for the expectation of another that explanation for the holding of money is required. We shall not
is, they may involve speculation. Of course, one of the advantages pursue the uncertainty problern here.
of a rnonetary econorny is that it rnakes it possible to have anony- We can formalize sorne of the above arguments in the spirit of
mous rnarkets such that every agent need rnake, at most, two separa te Section 6.3, but it should be ernphasized that only the most primitive
transactions if he desires to exchange a given "non-money" good for monetary ideas are treated here.
another. We have seen (ehapter 13) that this does not entirely Let the subscript "m" stand for rnoney that we now regard as the
remove the speculative element from transactions, but it grcatly non-interest-paying debt of sorne agency outside our formal systern,
econornizes in the nurnber of such transactions. In particular, say the government. Household h, as in Section 6.3, has an antici-
only one transaction is needed in the exchange of money for any pated volurne of receipts given by xhb (For the moment we ignore
good. past debts.) Receipts are measured in unit of account, but not
While a monetary econorny greatly econornizes in the number of necessarily in terms of money. In addition, the household has a
transactions it does not make them costless; we still ha ve wholesalers, stock of rnoney, Xhm The anticipated receipts of period 2 do not
retailers, and brokers, whose function it is to reduce the costs of include the money stock transferred from period 1 to period 2. The
T
1

348 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 349

2. Sorne Preliminaries transactions such as the search for information, but who them-
selves do not perform costlessly. Moreover, most transactions take
We cannot here attempt a detailed and full analysis of a monetary
time and perhaps sorne effort, such as traveling.
economy. However, there are certain features that it is useful to
discuss before we proceed. From these considerations alone it is possible to construct an
explanation of why an economic agent should hold part of his wealth
Money. So far in this book, except in ehapter 8 and briefly in in a medium of exchange with zero rate of return even when there
ehapter 13, the existence of markets has been taken for granted. are other assets yielding a positive rate of return. Of course, insofar
Once economic agents know market prices they take it that they can as money is held (and here money is supposed to be intrinsically
transact to any extent on these terrns. The process of exchange is worthless), it is held for future transactions. This would not occur
entirely anonymous-no bargain need be struck between any two if there were in existence al! the futures markets discussed in Section
agents. It is pretty clear that this would be entirely unrealistic in an 2.9. The cost of organizing all these markets is one reason we do
economy with no medium of exchange. eonsider three individuals, not have them and, thus, one reason we use money. eosts also are
A, B, and e, where A has quantities of goods X and Y and derives responsible for the fact that sales and purchases do not always
no utility from good Z, B has quantities of goods Y and Z and coincide in time. Thus, for instance, if a household sells services to
derives no utility from good X, and e has quantities of Z and X and a firm, the latter will ha vean incentive to economize in the frequency
derives no utility from Y. It is perfectly clear that there are no of payment, that is, in the number of transactions. On the-other
terms on which any two of the agents could beneficially trade with hand, should the household buy only after it has actually sold (been
each other, although there may be available, at sorne terms of paid), it would be involved in storage costs.
exchange, triangular trades that are Pareto superior to the present Jt will be noted that so far we have not made the point that the
allocation. To make sure that the equilibriurn of this economy is future is uncertain and that in the absence of the requisite number
Pareto efficient we would have to assume that all possible triangular of contingent futures markets, well-known propositions in the theory
trades have been explored by the three households. It is easy to of choice under uncertainty can be invoked to explain why agents
construct exarnples in which chains of arbitrarily many links would should include money in their portfolio of assets. In this view, the
have to be taken as explored by each agent before the resulting rate of return foregone in holding money is a kind of insurance
equilibrium could be shown to be Pareto efficient. premium against the possibility that, in fact, the rate of return on
Such explorations ha ve two fea tu res: They are costly, and since other assets may turn out to be negative. Of course, if the "best
they may involve a household in an exchange that, as such, is not guess" is that the return on other assets will be negative, no further
"beneficia!," but is undertaken for the expectation of another that explanation for the holding of money is required. We shall not
is, they may involve speculation. Of course, one of the advantages pursue the uncertainty problern here.
of a rnonetary econorny is that it rnakes it possible to have anony- We can formalize sorne of the above arguments in the spirit of
mous rnarkets such that every agent need rnake, at most, two separa te Section 6.3, but it should be ernphasized that only the most primitive
transactions if he desires to exchange a given "non-money" good for monetary ideas are treated here.
another. We have seen (ehapter 13) that this does not entirely Let the subscript "m" stand for rnoney that we now regard as the
remove the speculative element from transactions, but it grcatly non-interest-paying debt of sorne agency outside our formal systern,
econornizes in the nurnber of such transactions. In particular, say the government. Household h, as in Section 6.3, has an antici-
only one transaction is needed in the exchange of money for any pated volurne of receipts given by xhb (For the moment we ignore
good. past debts.) Receipts are measured in unit of account, but not
While a monetary econorny greatly econornizes in the number of necessarily in terms of money. In addition, the household has a
transactions it does not make them costless; we still ha ve wholesalers, stock of rnoney, Xhm The anticipated receipts of period 2 do not
retailers, and brokers, whose function it is to reduce the costs of include the money stock transferred from period 1 to period 2. The
350 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 351
two budget constraints read: required.) If A.l4.1 holds, the proof of p.l44 can be used to
1
P Xk + Pb(xhb - Xhb) + Pm(Xhm - Xhm) :S: p X1 1
+ L dh1(py1)
f
establish that Uh(xh) is semi-strictly quasi-concave when xh =
(xk,xhb,Xhm) We need note only that xn,
as there defined, satisfies
+ L (d,1 - dh!)K1 , (1) the constraint (3).
f Lastly, it is easy to see that if J( ) becomes large enough as
P~X~ :S: Xhb + P~mXhm (2) Pnmxhm becomes small for xn,
p~ given, the household will always
transfer some money from period 1 to period 2.
. i
In addition to these budget constraints, the household is con-
1 strained by transaction costs, which depend on the money stocks it The Past. In Section 6.3 all households started period 1 with no
1
holds, prices, and the transactions it propases to carry out. Recall commitments from the past. This plainly is not .realistic since we
the time constraint on the amount of labor services supplied that was are not considering period 1 to be the beginning of the world.
introduced in Section 3.1. We shall now write Indeed, in the present context, history may have peculiar significance.
To examine the matter further we need a rather more elaborate
(3) structure than that of Section 6.3.
The left-hand side indicates the necessity of supplying some labor Let there be three time intervals: O, 1, and 2. If the agent is viewed
time for transactions in period 2. The amount required declines as acting in period O, then 1 is an interva1 ofthe future and 2 is the
with the money stock and increases with the value of transactions. remaining future. If the agent is acting in period 1, then O is the
We take J( ) to be continuous in its arguments. past and 2 is the future. We give a variable the superscript "OF"
Evidently, (3) is a pretty crude device to capture some of the to denote the expectation that was formed in O of the values to be
problems discussed in this section, but for our purposes it will serve. taken on by that variable from period 1 on, that is, in periods 1 and
Now, if X = (xk,xhb,Xhm), the first-period derived utility function, 2. We give a superscript "ij," j =1 F, to denote the expectation
D.6.18, is given by formed in i of the values of the variable in j. A single superscript
"i" denotes that we are dealing with the actual variable value in i.
s.t. (2) and (3). In this notation, for instance, p~Fx~F is what the agent h believes in
2
Note that the ." true" utility function, Uk ( ), depends only on con- periodO will be the present value of his endowment in period 1, that is,
sumption of goods and leisure, but that the derived function depends p~Fj~F = p~lj~l + p~l(p~2j~2).
on the money stock chosen for transfer to period (2). It is likely Similarly, p~FyJF is the present value of the profits in period 1 of
that more sophisticated versions of the demand for money also firm f on the expectations formed in period O.
would allow the construction of a derived utility function of which Let us now view period 1 as the present. We assume that the
the money stock is an argument.
bonds issued by firm fin period O are repaid in pericid 1, but that, as
In Section 6.3 we showed that our consumption assumptions before, the firm issues a quantity of new bonds, p} 2y} 2, equal to the
allowed us to deduce that U(X) was semi-strictly quasi-concave, profits it expects in 1 to make in 2. (The reader should note that
where xh did not include money. Here we may assume y} 2 now has quite a different meaning from that given it in Section
AssUMPTION , J(x~,p~,p~mXhm) is, for given p~, P~mXhm, a convex 6.3). We write xkb as the actual value of receipts in period 1 plus
function of x~. the present value of receipts expected then for period 2. By the
assumptions of Section 6.3,
This assumption can \:)e justified by arguing that there are ncreas-
ing time costs of transactions with a given stock of money. (Strictly xkb = plxk + p~(pkzxkz) + dk[ply} + p&(p}2y}2) - pJFyJFJ
f
speaking, a transaction takes place only when X~ =1 X~. We have
not thought it worthwhile to introduce the extra elaboration + p~ Ldk [max(pk2yj2) -
f
1
h
p} 2 y} 2 ] (4)

!1

,
350 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 351
two budget constraints read: required.) If A.l4.1 holds, the proof of p.l44 can be used to
1
P Xk + Pb(xhb - Xhb) + Pm(Xhm - Xhm) :S: p X1 1
+ L dh1(py1)
f
establish that Uh(xh) is semi-strictly quasi-concave when xh =
(xk,xhb,Xhm) We need note only that xn,
as there defined, satisfies
+ L (d,1 - dh!)K1 , (1) the constraint (3).
f Lastly, it is easy to see that if J( ) becomes large enough as
P~X~ :S: Xhb + P~mXhm (2) Pnmxhm becomes small for xn,
p~ given, the household will always
transfer some money from period 1 to period 2.
. i
In addition to these budget constraints, the household is con-
1 strained by transaction costs, which depend on the money stocks it The Past. In Section 6.3 all households started period 1 with no
1
holds, prices, and the transactions it propases to carry out. Recall commitments from the past. This plainly is not .realistic since we
the time constraint on the amount of labor services supplied that was are not considering period 1 to be the beginning of the world.
introduced in Section 3.1. We shall now write Indeed, in the present context, history may have peculiar significance.
To examine the matter further we need a rather more elaborate
(3) structure than that of Section 6.3.
The left-hand side indicates the necessity of supplying some labor Let there be three time intervals: O, 1, and 2. If the agent is viewed
time for transactions in period 2. The amount required declines as acting in period O, then 1 is an interva1 ofthe future and 2 is the
with the money stock and increases with the value of transactions. remaining future. If the agent is acting in period 1, then O is the
We take J( ) to be continuous in its arguments. past and 2 is the future. We give a variable the superscript "OF"
Evidently, (3) is a pretty crude device to capture some of the to denote the expectation that was formed in O of the values to be
problems discussed in this section, but for our purposes it will serve. taken on by that variable from period 1 on, that is, in periods 1 and
Now, if X = (xk,xhb,Xhm), the first-period derived utility function, 2. We give a superscript "ij," j =1 F, to denote the expectation
D.6.18, is given by formed in i of the values of the variable in j. A single superscript
"i" denotes that we are dealing with the actual variable value in i.
s.t. (2) and (3). In this notation, for instance, p~Fx~F is what the agent h believes in
2
Note that the ." true" utility function, Uk ( ), depends only on con- periodO will be the present value of his endowment in period 1, that is,
sumption of goods and leisure, but that the derived function depends p~Fj~F = p~lj~l + p~l(p~2j~2).
on the money stock chosen for transfer to period (2). It is likely Similarly, p~FyJF is the present value of the profits in period 1 of
that more sophisticated versions of the demand for money also firm f on the expectations formed in period O.
would allow the construction of a derived utility function of which Let us now view period 1 as the present. We assume that the
the money stock is an argument.
bonds issued by firm fin period O are repaid in pericid 1, but that, as
In Section 6.3 we showed that our consumption assumptions before, the firm issues a quantity of new bonds, p} 2y} 2, equal to the
allowed us to deduce that U(X) was semi-strictly quasi-concave, profits it expects in 1 to make in 2. (The reader should note that
where xh did not include money. Here we may assume y} 2 now has quite a different meaning from that given it in Section
AssUMPTION , J(x~,p~,p~mXhm) is, for given p~, P~mXhm, a convex 6.3). We write xkb as the actual value of receipts in period 1 plus
function of x~. the present value of receipts expected then for period 2. By the
assumptions of Section 6.3,
This assumption can \:)e justified by arguing that there are ncreas-
ing time costs of transactions with a given stock of money. (Strictly xkb = plxk + p~(pkzxkz) + dk[ply} + p&(p}2y}2) - pJFyJFJ
f
speaking, a transaction takes place only when X~ =1 X~. We have
not thought it worthwhile to introduce the extra elaboration + p~ Ldk [max(pk2yj2) -
f
1
h
p} 2 y} 2 ] (4)

!1

,
~j-

352 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 353

The first two terms are straightforward; they give the receipts The resources at the disposal of the household at the beginning of
from current endowment sale and the present expected value from period 1 are
future endowment sale. The first square bracket, for any j, gives the -oF) + PmXnm
net payment of fto shareholders after repayment of the bonds issued
-1
Xnb + ( Xnbo - Xhb 1 o

in O. The second square bracket gives the profit expected by the or, using (4) and (6),
most optimistic household in period 2 after repayment of the bonds
issued in period l. As before dkr = O if h is not the most optimistic
household.
[p 1xk + p&(pk 2 xk 2) - pJFx~F] + [ f (dkrK} - d~}KJ 1)J
If we write K} as the capital val ue of firm fin period 1, then it is - : (d~r -
f
dgl)KJ 1 + x~b + p~X~m (7)
given by the first square bracket plus p& times the second square
We refer to (7) as the wealth of h at the beginning of period 1 and
bracket for .f That is,
write it as wk. lf dkr = d~} = d~r' as we could take to be the case
(5) if all expectations are fulfilled and no one buys "short" in period O,
and if indeed all expectations are correct, then wk = x~b + p~x~m'
This should be compared with D.6. 15 and D.6. 16. Sin ce the which is. exactly (except for the monetary component) what we
economy now has a history, the firm has past commitments, that deduced to be the form of the wealth transferred to the "future" in
must be taken into account in the valuation placed on it in period 1. Section 6.3.
1t is plain that we now cannot assume K} ?: O. lf K} < O, then the Since households and firms ha ve different expectations in periodO,
household with a share dgr in the firm is responsible for dgK} of the it cannot be that all expectations are fulfilled in period l. Thus, in
net debt and cannot escape this obligation: general:

ASSUMPTION 2. K} < 0 implies dkr = d~r (a) The value of the endowment of a household in 1 will differ
from what was expected at O (the first square bracket in
Now we may write (4) also as (7)). If it is less, then the first term in (7) is negative.
(b) K} may be negative (and differ from K~ 1 ) because the value
xkb = p1 xk + p&(pk 2 xk 2 ) + : dkrK}. (4') of the firm's production plan in 1 is less than it was
f
expected to be in O. This may be so for three related
To (4') we add the net repayment of bonds to the household, reasons: First-period prices may be different than they had
(xgb - xg~), and the money stocks transferred to period one, been expected to be; the price expected in period 1 to rule
P~X~m- But in period 2 may be different than period 2 prices were
expected to be in period O; the production plan of the firm
xg~ = pJFx~F + : dg}K9
f
1
+ : (dgr -
f
dg})KJ 1 . (6) in period 1 may differ from what was expected in periodO.
(e) The actual share, dkr, in firmfmay differ from its planned
Here K9 1 is the capital value of firm fin period 1 as expected in value for all the reasons already given.
period O. Also, d~} are the planned holdings of h for period 1 of
the shares of firm .f Note that Now severa! situations that did not arise in our previous work are
possible. As before, let p = (p\pD.
KJl = [max (pgFyJF) _ pJFyJF]
h (a) Suppose p such that p 1y} + p&pj2y} 2 - pJFyJF < O. Then
= max(pg1yJ1 + pg1(p~zy~z) _ pJFyJF] the firm f cannot repay the debt of the previous period. We could
h
say that the firm is bankrupt. Since there may be shareholders more
so that, by the assumptions of Section 6.3, KJ 1 O. optimistic than the firm, however, we might wish to assume that they

,.
1

lj

l~-~ -- ~----- ------ -


~j-

352 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 353

The first two terms are straightforward; they give the receipts The resources at the disposal of the household at the beginning of
from current endowment sale and the present expected value from period 1 are
future endowment sale. The first square bracket, for any j, gives the -oF) + PmXnm
net payment of fto shareholders after repayment of the bonds issued
-1
Xnb + ( Xnbo - Xhb 1 o

in O. The second square bracket gives the profit expected by the or, using (4) and (6),
most optimistic household in period 2 after repayment of the bonds
issued in period l. As before dkr = O if h is not the most optimistic
household.
[p 1xk + p&(pk 2 xk 2) - pJFx~F] + [ f (dkrK} - d~}KJ 1)J
If we write K} as the capital val ue of firm fin period 1, then it is - : (d~r -
f
dgl)KJ 1 + x~b + p~X~m (7)
given by the first square bracket plus p& times the second square
We refer to (7) as the wealth of h at the beginning of period 1 and
bracket for .f That is,
write it as wk. lf dkr = d~} = d~r' as we could take to be the case
(5) if all expectations are fulfilled and no one buys "short" in period O,
and if indeed all expectations are correct, then wk = x~b + p~x~m'
This should be compared with D.6. 15 and D.6. 16. Sin ce the which is. exactly (except for the monetary component) what we
economy now has a history, the firm has past commitments, that deduced to be the form of the wealth transferred to the "future" in
must be taken into account in the valuation placed on it in period 1. Section 6.3.
1t is plain that we now cannot assume K} ?: O. lf K} < O, then the Since households and firms ha ve different expectations in periodO,
household with a share dgr in the firm is responsible for dgK} of the it cannot be that all expectations are fulfilled in period l. Thus, in
net debt and cannot escape this obligation: general:

ASSUMPTION 2. K} < 0 implies dkr = d~r (a) The value of the endowment of a household in 1 will differ
from what was expected at O (the first square bracket in
Now we may write (4) also as (7)). If it is less, then the first term in (7) is negative.
(b) K} may be negative (and differ from K~ 1 ) because the value
xkb = p1 xk + p&(pk 2 xk 2 ) + : dkrK}. (4') of the firm's production plan in 1 is less than it was
f
expected to be in O. This may be so for three related
To (4') we add the net repayment of bonds to the household, reasons: First-period prices may be different than they had
(xgb - xg~), and the money stocks transferred to period one, been expected to be; the price expected in period 1 to rule
P~X~m- But in period 2 may be different than period 2 prices were
expected to be in period O; the production plan of the firm
xg~ = pJFx~F + : dg}K9
f
1
+ : (dgr -
f
dg})KJ 1 . (6) in period 1 may differ from what was expected in periodO.
(e) The actual share, dkr, in firmfmay differ from its planned
Here K9 1 is the capital value of firm fin period 1 as expected in value for all the reasons already given.
period O. Also, d~} are the planned holdings of h for period 1 of
the shares of firm .f Note that Now severa! situations that did not arise in our previous work are
possible. As before, let p = (p\pD.
KJl = [max (pgFyJF) _ pJFyJF]
h (a) Suppose p such that p 1y} + p&pj2y} 2 - pJFyJF < O. Then
= max(pg1yJ1 + pg1(p~zy~z) _ pJFyJF] the firm f cannot repay the debt of the previous period. We could
h
say that the firm is bankrupt. Since there may be shareholders more
so that, by the assumptions of Section 6.3, KJ 1 O. optimistic than the firm, however, we might wish to assume that they

,.
1

lj

l~-~ -- ~----- ------ -


354 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 355

will repay the short-fall on the firm's debt as long as they are not with a zero real wage. This is not the only desideratum, however.
involved in loss. From this reasoning (b) follows. Keynes was concerned with a monetary economy, and in any case
(b) The firm is bankrupt when at sorne p, Kj < O. As long as we ha ve agreed that all of our constructions presuppose the absence
the present value ofprofits ofthe firm is positive, however, it evidently of barter. It is rather essential, then, that once money has been
pays to continue operating. introduced explicitly as the means of effecting exchanges, we should
(e) If at p, K} is sufficiently negative to cause wk < O, the bank- not finish up with an equilibrium in which money has zero exchange
ruptcy point of household h has been passed. We must suppose value, that is, one in which p~ = O, in the notation of the previous
that, in fact, the household hands over to its creditors all its assets, section. In other words, we must show the existence of an equi-
including the present val u e of its wages and its share in the firm. The librium restrained furtlier by the requirement that p~ > O.
creditors may value the future profits of the firm, the debtor's share Our procedure will be to assume first that if an equilibrium exists
of which they claim, quite differently than the debtor did, so it will satisfy p~ > O. This allows us to take money as the
they (the creditors) might experience a discontinuous change in wealth. numeraire. Later we shall re-examine this matter.
(d) To be even remotely realistic, we must add that the manage- From what we have .learned already we know that we must be
ment of the firm and thus 'its production plans may change at any able to establish the appropriate continuity properties of the
stage in (a), (b), or (e). In (a) the shareholders may install new behavioral function or correspondences and of those constructed
management, in (b) the creditors may demanda change, and in (e) from them in order to demonstrate that an equilibrium exists. The
the creditors own a fraction of the firm. Any such change in the possibility that at sorne point in the price space the entire resources
identity of the management, since it will be accompanied by a change of one agent become the property of other agents, in the present
in the expectations, will generally lead to a discontinuous change of context, is associated in general with a discontinuity, so the existence
production plans. proof is endangered.
Clearly, the actual bankruptcy procedure is at least partly a Suppose that household e is the so le creditor of firm/from period
matter oflaw, but it seems plain that the history ofthe economy may O and that household h owns all the shares of firm f Then house-
make it impossible to guarantee the continuity properties of the hold e includes among the resources available to it in period 1
various functions and correspondences and this is bad for existence p~Fy~F, the repayment of its loan to firm/, made in periodO. If at
proofs. It is to this, one of our main concerns in this chapter, that p, however, household h has wk = O, then it cannot borrow and
we now turn. transfers all its resources to c. As far as h is concerned they are just
equal in value to its debt of p~Fy?F. But household h expected to
3. The Existence of Keynesian Temporary Equilibrium receive pk 2 y} 2 in period 2, while household e expects p; 2 y} 2 and the
There are two, rather distinct questions that we must investigate. two amounts may differ. Al so, of course, the future "earning
The first, straightforward question is whether it can be argued that power" of h from its own resources was pk 2 x~, while household e
Keynes discovered features of an economy that lead to the failure of values them at p~ 2 x~. Hence, at the bankruptcy point, e may ex-
one or the other of our assumptions of Section 6.3 and thus make it perience a discontinuous change in wealth.
impossible to establish the existence of a temporary equilibrium. To this must be added the equally important difficulty caused
(It should be emphasized that for our purposes temporary equi- by a change in managemcnt resulting from the bankruptcy of the
librium implies the clearing of all markets including that for labor. firm.
The next section looks at a different kind of equilibrium.) The In addition to all this another problem arises. It will be recalled
second question is whether such an equilibrium, even if it can be that the strategy of our existence proofs was to establish the existence
shown to exist, is "sensible." of a compensated equilibrium and then to show that it was, in fact,
By "sensible," of course, we can mean all sorts of things. Cer- a competitive equilibrium. For this last step we needed to ensure 1,
tainly, though, we should not be much interested in an equilibrium that in the compensated equilibrium every household disposed of a 1 !
1
11

' '11.

'~ 1"

11
ll],,

i
354 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 355

will repay the short-fall on the firm's debt as long as they are not with a zero real wage. This is not the only desideratum, however.
involved in loss. From this reasoning (b) follows. Keynes was concerned with a monetary economy, and in any case
(b) The firm is bankrupt when at sorne p, Kj < O. As long as we ha ve agreed that all of our constructions presuppose the absence
the present value ofprofits ofthe firm is positive, however, it evidently of barter. It is rather essential, then, that once money has been
pays to continue operating. introduced explicitly as the means of effecting exchanges, we should
(e) If at p, K} is sufficiently negative to cause wk < O, the bank- not finish up with an equilibrium in which money has zero exchange
ruptcy point of household h has been passed. We must suppose value, that is, one in which p~ = O, in the notation of the previous
that, in fact, the household hands over to its creditors all its assets, section. In other words, we must show the existence of an equi-
including the present val u e of its wages and its share in the firm. The librium restrained furtlier by the requirement that p~ > O.
creditors may value the future profits of the firm, the debtor's share Our procedure will be to assume first that if an equilibrium exists
of which they claim, quite differently than the debtor did, so it will satisfy p~ > O. This allows us to take money as the
they (the creditors) might experience a discontinuous change in wealth. numeraire. Later we shall re-examine this matter.
(d) To be even remotely realistic, we must add that the manage- From what we have .learned already we know that we must be
ment of the firm and thus 'its production plans may change at any able to establish the appropriate continuity properties of the
stage in (a), (b), or (e). In (a) the shareholders may install new behavioral function or correspondences and of those constructed
management, in (b) the creditors may demanda change, and in (e) from them in order to demonstrate that an equilibrium exists. The
the creditors own a fraction of the firm. Any such change in the possibility that at sorne point in the price space the entire resources
identity of the management, since it will be accompanied by a change of one agent become the property of other agents, in the present
in the expectations, will generally lead to a discontinuous change of context, is associated in general with a discontinuity, so the existence
production plans. proof is endangered.
Clearly, the actual bankruptcy procedure is at least partly a Suppose that household e is the so le creditor of firm/from period
matter oflaw, but it seems plain that the history ofthe economy may O and that household h owns all the shares of firm f Then house-
make it impossible to guarantee the continuity properties of the hold e includes among the resources available to it in period 1
various functions and correspondences and this is bad for existence p~Fy~F, the repayment of its loan to firm/, made in periodO. If at
proofs. It is to this, one of our main concerns in this chapter, that p, however, household h has wk = O, then it cannot borrow and
we now turn. transfers all its resources to c. As far as h is concerned they are just
equal in value to its debt of p~Fy?F. But household h expected to
3. The Existence of Keynesian Temporary Equilibrium receive pk 2 y} 2 in period 2, while household e expects p; 2 y} 2 and the
There are two, rather distinct questions that we must investigate. two amounts may differ. Al so, of course, the future "earning
The first, straightforward question is whether it can be argued that power" of h from its own resources was pk 2 x~, while household e
Keynes discovered features of an economy that lead to the failure of values them at p~ 2 x~. Hence, at the bankruptcy point, e may ex-
one or the other of our assumptions of Section 6.3 and thus make it perience a discontinuous change in wealth.
impossible to establish the existence of a temporary equilibrium. To this must be added the equally important difficulty caused
(It should be emphasized that for our purposes temporary equi- by a change in managemcnt resulting from the bankruptcy of the
librium implies the clearing of all markets including that for labor. firm.
The next section looks at a different kind of equilibrium.) The In addition to all this another problem arises. It will be recalled
second question is whether such an equilibrium, even if it can be that the strategy of our existence proofs was to establish the existence
shown to exist, is "sensible." of a compensated equilibrium and then to show that it was, in fact,
By "sensible," of course, we can mean all sorts of things. Cer- a competitive equilibrium. For this last step we needed to ensure 1,
tainly, though, we should not be much interested in an equilibrium that in the compensated equilibrium every household disposed of a 1 !
1
11

' '11.

'~ 1"

11
ll],,

i
TI-lE KEYNESIAN MODEL 357
356 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

v.alue of resources that exceeded the value of its minimum consump- important also because it is a link between the past and the present.
twn vector. It is plain that this last step may not be possible now If a serious monetary theory comes to be written, the fact that
even: if the existence of a compensated equilibrium could be demon~ contracts are indeed made in terms of money will be of considerable
st.rated. In a compensated equilibrium, if a household is bankrupt it importance.
d1sposes of no resources, and we cannot use our assumption of We now have a great deal of evidence that establishing the exist-
resource relatedness to reach the desired conclusion. The fact that ence of a temporary equilibrium for the economy we are now
sorne household has an "effective" demand for the resources of the considering m ay not be smooth sailing. Of course, general "non-
bankrupt household does not help the latter to any "disposable" existence" theorems are not to be sought. Therefore it may be
resources. helpful to sketch an example.
In his Chapter 19, "Changes in Money-Wages," Keynes really To avoid aggregation problems, Jet us suppose that the economy
addressed himself to the problems of this section, although he was is capable of producing a single good. For the purpose of this
example only, we write yt as the output ofthe good at time t (not to be
not concerned with a formal existence analysis. He argued that
lower money wages might not reduce unemployment. He adduced confused with the vector y 1)'. The good may be consumed or used
various well-known reasons, including one not yet mentioned here, in subsequent production. Let S1 be the amount of the good
namely the possibility that expected prices may not be continuous available at the end of period t for production at t + 1 and Jet Lt be
the amount of the single kind of labor service used in production
functions of current price. This is not unimportant if we consider,
for instance, the likelihood that the bankruptcy of firms and house- at t. Then the production function is
holds is information separate from current price information, which y 1 = Sf_ 1 Lr a> 0,(3 >O, a+ (3 <l. (8)
may influence agents' views of the future. But Keynes also wrote, Note tha:t there are diminishing returns to scale and that only
"Indeed if the fall in wages and prices goes far, the embarrassment stocks set aside in the previous period are availab1e for production.
of those entrepreneurs who are heavily indebted may soon reach the It will be convenient to take units such that
point of insolvency-with severely adverse effects on Investment "
(p. 264). ' So = l.
This Ieads us to another point of sorne importance: The problem Let p be the actual price of the good in period 1 (i.e., we omit the
of bankruptcy is not unrelated to the good or goods in terms of superscript), pJ the price expected by the firm for period 2. Simi- !:
which debts are contracted. Keynes realistically took it that they Iarly w is the current wage and WJ the wage expected by the firm for .!!:
' ',11
1

were contracted in terms of money. We have hitherto taken them period 2. All prices are measured in terms of rnoney. Then,
as contracted in abstract unit of account. Consider again the assuming that the present value of profits are maximized, routine
cr~ditor household c. If it has a contract to receive money, then it calculations give
wlll receive p~(pJFyJF)p~1 , and this is the amount of money the debtor - fi/b(l- a)

household also is contracted to deliver. Evidently then, the set of TT = p(ar)a(l - a) + pb(pJ) 11 bb(l - a)(arJ)u ( ~ ) (9)

P at which wk = O when debt is fixed in unit of account will not


where Trr is the present value of profits as seen by the firm and
coincide, in general, with the set of p at which wk = O when debt is
present in terms of money. The terms in which contracts are made PJ p
matter. In particular, if money is the good in terms of which
r = !!..,
w
ry = w' q = ~,
contracts are made, then the prices of goods in terms of money are a
of special significance. This is not the case if we consider an a =_a_, b = 1- (a+ (3), u=-
1-a 1-a b
economy without a past and without a future. Keynes wrote that
"the importance of money essentially flows from it being a link Al so
(10)
between the present and the future," to which we may add that it is
TI-lE KEYNESIAN MODEL 357
356 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

v.alue of resources that exceeded the value of its minimum consump- important also because it is a link between the past and the present.
twn vector. It is plain that this last step may not be possible now If a serious monetary theory comes to be written, the fact that
even: if the existence of a compensated equilibrium could be demon~ contracts are indeed made in terms of money will be of considerable
st.rated. In a compensated equilibrium, if a household is bankrupt it importance.
d1sposes of no resources, and we cannot use our assumption of We now have a great deal of evidence that establishing the exist-
resource relatedness to reach the desired conclusion. The fact that ence of a temporary equilibrium for the economy we are now
sorne household has an "effective" demand for the resources of the considering m ay not be smooth sailing. Of course, general "non-
bankrupt household does not help the latter to any "disposable" existence" theorems are not to be sought. Therefore it may be
resources. helpful to sketch an example.
In his Chapter 19, "Changes in Money-Wages," Keynes really To avoid aggregation problems, Jet us suppose that the economy
addressed himself to the problems of this section, although he was is capable of producing a single good. For the purpose of this
example only, we write yt as the output ofthe good at time t (not to be
not concerned with a formal existence analysis. He argued that
lower money wages might not reduce unemployment. He adduced confused with the vector y 1)'. The good may be consumed or used
various well-known reasons, including one not yet mentioned here, in subsequent production. Let S1 be the amount of the good
namely the possibility that expected prices may not be continuous available at the end of period t for production at t + 1 and Jet Lt be
the amount of the single kind of labor service used in production
functions of current price. This is not unimportant if we consider,
for instance, the likelihood that the bankruptcy of firms and house- at t. Then the production function is
holds is information separate from current price information, which y 1 = Sf_ 1 Lr a> 0,(3 >O, a+ (3 <l. (8)
may influence agents' views of the future. But Keynes also wrote, Note tha:t there are diminishing returns to scale and that only
"Indeed if the fall in wages and prices goes far, the embarrassment stocks set aside in the previous period are availab1e for production.
of those entrepreneurs who are heavily indebted may soon reach the It will be convenient to take units such that
point of insolvency-with severely adverse effects on Investment "
(p. 264). ' So = l.
This Ieads us to another point of sorne importance: The problem Let p be the actual price of the good in period 1 (i.e., we omit the
of bankruptcy is not unrelated to the good or goods in terms of superscript), pJ the price expected by the firm for period 2. Simi- !:
which debts are contracted. Keynes realistically took it that they Iarly w is the current wage and WJ the wage expected by the firm for .!!:
' ',11
1

were contracted in terms of money. We have hitherto taken them period 2. All prices are measured in terms of rnoney. Then,
as contracted in abstract unit of account. Consider again the assuming that the present value of profits are maximized, routine
cr~ditor household c. If it has a contract to receive money, then it calculations give
wlll receive p~(pJFyJF)p~1 , and this is the amount of money the debtor - fi/b(l- a)

household also is contracted to deliver. Evidently then, the set of TT = p(ar)a(l - a) + pb(pJ) 11 bb(l - a)(arJ)u ( ~ ) (9)

P at which wk = O when debt is fixed in unit of account will not


where Trr is the present value of profits as seen by the firm and
coincide, in general, with the set of p at which wk = O when debt is
present in terms of money. The terms in which contracts are made PJ p
matter. In particular, if money is the good in terms of which
r = !!..,
w
ry = w' q = ~,
contracts are made, then the prices of goods in terms of money are a
of special significance. This is not the case if we consider an a =_a_, b = 1- (a+ (3), u=-
1-a 1-a b
economy without a past and without a future. Keynes wrote that
"the importance of money essentially flows from it being a link Al so
(10)
between the present and the future," to which we may add that it is
358 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1
1

THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 359

Next let us consider households. We shall assume that they Next we want
have identical utility functions, although they may have different
expectations. For reasons we will not examine, a household will 2, mk = i,
,
(16)
always deliver one unit of labor in each period. (This assumption
makes the example easier, but is in no way essential.) The maxi- where i is the total stock of money in the economy. Also Jet
mum amount of leisure it can have in each period is also one unit.
I = S1;
Part of the leisure, however, may have to be used in transactions
JI
(see (3)). To make this precise, Jet e!, be the amount of the good then we require '
bought by h in period t and Jet mi,- 1 be the amount of money trans- I + 2, e~ = y 1
= (ar*)a. (17)
11

'1
ferred from period (t - 1) to period t. Then, if Al. is the leisure ,
:!
consumed by hin period t, we postulate
Since the debt of a firm is really the debt of the households that '!i.
own its shares, we find, on the assumption that w~ > O, all h, l[
m~~
1

Al.= min(1,
p eh
) (ll)
2, w~ = w 1
= 2, m~ + p + 2, wk + Pb 2, w~ + py} -
, , ,
wLj
The idea behind (11) is sufficiently obvious, as is the amount of
simplification involved. lt is worth noting that 1 - A!,, the amount + Pb[max(p~yJ -- wf.LJ)] (18)
of leisure used for transaction purposes, is indeed a convex function (where it should be recalled that S0 = 1 so that pS0 = p). Also,
of the transactions to be made in the range in which Al. :s; l.
The utility function we shall use is /',,
1'
(19) 11,

(v log ek + , log Ak) + 8(v log ef. + , !og A~) '"


11',!

11!
and
where 8 > O and v > , > O. The constraint on the household,
besides (ll), is: YJ = (arJ)a(I + 1)P/(1- ). (20)

(12) From (19), we may write

where wk is the total present wealth, including "human wealth," of h. I = I(q).


Proceeding in the usual way we find
Also, if
Pe1 8. v-.
mk = ~ 1"'
11
g- -- g=--, forh < - - (13) 1
1 - Pb v-. v W =- L, W,,
p ,

- 1 then from ( 18), ( 19), and (20),


pel, = cwk e o=: 1 + 8 + g' (14)
w = w(p,q).
If there are H households, the labor supply in period 1 is equal to
H. The demand for labor is (ar)a/a and so, neglecting the case If wv = owfop' and so on, we find wv < O, Wq < O, and in similar
w = O, a condition of equilibrium is notation, lq < O.
We may now write (16) and (17) as
= (ar)a,
i
''
1

:
H
a
(15) gcw(p,q) + (q- 1 - r 1
)i = 0,} (v- .)
Pb < - - -
(16')

and this uniquely determines r*. J(q) + CW(p,q) - (ar*)a = 0, V (17')

,l
358 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
1
1

THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 359

Next let us consider households. We shall assume that they Next we want
have identical utility functions, although they may have different
expectations. For reasons we will not examine, a household will 2, mk = i,
,
(16)
always deliver one unit of labor in each period. (This assumption
makes the example easier, but is in no way essential.) The maxi- where i is the total stock of money in the economy. Also Jet
mum amount of leisure it can have in each period is also one unit.
I = S1;
Part of the leisure, however, may have to be used in transactions
JI
(see (3)). To make this precise, Jet e!, be the amount of the good then we require '
bought by h in period t and Jet mi,- 1 be the amount of money trans- I + 2, e~ = y 1
= (ar*)a. (17)
11

'1
ferred from period (t - 1) to period t. Then, if Al. is the leisure ,
:!
consumed by hin period t, we postulate
Since the debt of a firm is really the debt of the households that '!i.
own its shares, we find, on the assumption that w~ > O, all h, l[
m~~
1

Al.= min(1,
p eh
) (ll)
2, w~ = w 1
= 2, m~ + p + 2, wk + Pb 2, w~ + py} -
, , ,
wLj
The idea behind (11) is sufficiently obvious, as is the amount of
simplification involved. lt is worth noting that 1 - A!,, the amount + Pb[max(p~yJ -- wf.LJ)] (18)
of leisure used for transaction purposes, is indeed a convex function (where it should be recalled that S0 = 1 so that pS0 = p). Also,
of the transactions to be made in the range in which Al. :s; l.
The utility function we shall use is /',,
1'
(19) 11,

(v log ek + , log Ak) + 8(v log ef. + , !og A~) '"


11',!

11!
and
where 8 > O and v > , > O. The constraint on the household,
besides (ll), is: YJ = (arJ)a(I + 1)P/(1- ). (20)

(12) From (19), we may write

where wk is the total present wealth, including "human wealth," of h. I = I(q).


Proceeding in the usual way we find
Also, if
Pe1 8. v-.
mk = ~ 1"'
11
g- -- g=--, forh < - - (13) 1
1 - Pb v-. v W =- L, W,,
p ,

- 1 then from ( 18), ( 19), and (20),


pel, = cwk e o=: 1 + 8 + g' (14)
w = w(p,q).
If there are H households, the labor supply in period 1 is equal to
H. The demand for labor is (ar)a/a and so, neglecting the case If wv = owfop' and so on, we find wv < O, Wq < O, and in similar
w = O, a condition of equilibrium is notation, lq < O.
We may now write (16) and (17) as
= (ar)a,
i
''
1

:
H
a
(15) gcw(p,q) + (q- 1 - r 1
)i = 0,} (v- .)
Pb < - - -
(16')

and this uniquely determines r*. J(q) + CW(p,q) - (ar*)a = 0, V (17')

,l
360 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS

When fJb ;:: (v - p,)jv, then (13) is not appropriate, since in that
T q
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 361
,
.,i
case A~ = l. Also, it has been supposed that m~ has a value that 'o
li

allows the solution A~ < l. For the purpose of this example we ;i


:,1
suppose that the economy finds an equilibrium in the range for
il l
which A~ < 1 andA~ < l. In Figure 14-1, OA has slope v/(v- 0 ) so ,1

that every point above OA satisfies Pb < (v - .t)jv, since qjp = 1/Pb B

1
1
q ',i
:1
1
OL---------------------------p

Figure 142

''1' At al! points to the left of B and on B, the debtor is bankrupt.


'1
The dashed part of (16') and (17') are the continuations of Figure
14-1 if bankruptcy had not occurred. The discontinuity caused by
Figure 14-1 bankruptcy means that no equilibrium exists. It should be noted
.. '

''
1
that the construction takes full account of cash balance effects.
Indeed, if it did not, (17') would be an equation in q only. Note
We ha ve also plotted equations (1 6') and (17'), and the signs of their also that when the debtor is bankrupt, equilibrium in the money
slopes can be checked from what has gone before. The intersection market implies an excess demand for goods, while if he is not bank-
of the two curves gives the unique equilibrium of the economy. It rupt, it implies an excess supply of goods, where these are "fuii
should be noted that as p varies, so does w0 (the money wage) in the employment" excess demands.
same proportion, since r is fixed at r*. As usual, it is not possible to prove for the general case that no
However, we have supposed in deriving these curves that w~ > O equilibrium exists. The example is sufficient, however, to show that
throughout. Now suppose that there are only two households: the if we take the Keynesian construction seriously, that is, as of a world
creditor household and the debtor household, so-called according with a past as weii as a future and in which contracts are made in
to their respective commitments in period O. In Figure 14-2 the terms of money, no equilibrium may exist.
curve Bis the bankruptcy locus of the debtor. If (p,q) lies on this Let us now turn to the second problem we ha ve set ourselves: 1f
curve, then the debtor hands his assets (in the sense of the previous an equilibrium exists, is it one in which money has a positive exchange
section) to the creditor. If the creditor has a less sanguine expectation value?
of future profits than did the debtor, there will be a discontinuous faii Before answering this question it is worthwhilc drawing attention
in the creditor's wealth. Hence, in order that ti-ie demand for output to a paradox that m ay arise from an ill-form ulated monetary theory.
should equal its supply, at any p, Pb will have to be higher than it By this we may mean a theory in which the demand for money is
would have been otherwise. For the same reason, and because the simply derived by putting "real cash balances" into the utility
creditor must now demand al! the money there is, at any p, Pb will function, not as a proxy for something else, but to account for con-
have to be higher than it would have been otherwise if the demand venience and the like. lf nothing else is said, and if the usual
for money is to equal what is available. continuity properties are taken to hold, then we can argue as follows:

'i.
'11

li

'1

1
360 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS

When fJb ;:: (v - p,)jv, then (13) is not appropriate, since in that
T q
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 361
,
.,i
case A~ = l. Also, it has been supposed that m~ has a value that 'o
li

allows the solution A~ < l. For the purpose of this example we ;i


:,1
suppose that the economy finds an equilibrium in the range for
il l
which A~ < 1 andA~ < l. In Figure 14-1, OA has slope v/(v- 0 ) so ,1

that every point above OA satisfies Pb < (v - .t)jv, since qjp = 1/Pb B

1
1
q ',i
:1
1
OL---------------------------p

Figure 142

''1' At al! points to the left of B and on B, the debtor is bankrupt.


'1
The dashed part of (16') and (17') are the continuations of Figure
14-1 if bankruptcy had not occurred. The discontinuity caused by
Figure 14-1 bankruptcy means that no equilibrium exists. It should be noted
.. '

''
1
that the construction takes full account of cash balance effects.
Indeed, if it did not, (17') would be an equation in q only. Note
We ha ve also plotted equations (1 6') and (17'), and the signs of their also that when the debtor is bankrupt, equilibrium in the money
slopes can be checked from what has gone before. The intersection market implies an excess demand for goods, while if he is not bank-
of the two curves gives the unique equilibrium of the economy. It rupt, it implies an excess supply of goods, where these are "fuii
should be noted that as p varies, so does w0 (the money wage) in the employment" excess demands.
same proportion, since r is fixed at r*. As usual, it is not possible to prove for the general case that no
However, we have supposed in deriving these curves that w~ > O equilibrium exists. The example is sufficient, however, to show that
throughout. Now suppose that there are only two households: the if we take the Keynesian construction seriously, that is, as of a world
creditor household and the debtor household, so-called according with a past as weii as a future and in which contracts are made in
to their respective commitments in period O. In Figure 14-2 the terms of money, no equilibrium may exist.
curve Bis the bankruptcy locus of the debtor. If (p,q) lies on this Let us now turn to the second problem we ha ve set ourselves: 1f
curve, then the debtor hands his assets (in the sense of the previous an equilibrium exists, is it one in which money has a positive exchange
section) to the creditor. If the creditor has a less sanguine expectation value?
of future profits than did the debtor, there will be a discontinuous faii Before answering this question it is worthwhilc drawing attention
in the creditor's wealth. Hence, in order that ti-ie demand for output to a paradox that m ay arise from an ill-form ulated monetary theory.
should equal its supply, at any p, Pb will have to be higher than it By this we may mean a theory in which the demand for money is
would have been otherwise. For the same reason, and because the simply derived by putting "real cash balances" into the utility
creditor must now demand al! the money there is, at any p, Pb will function, not as a proxy for something else, but to account for con-
have to be higher than it would have been otherwise if the demand venience and the like. lf nothing else is said, and if the usual
for money is to equal what is available. continuity properties are taken to hold, then we can argue as follows:

'i.
'11

li

'1

1
362 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
!
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 363

Consider the case in which the price of money is made identically with p given its present definition and x, = (xk,x,b,xkm) As before,
equal to zero. Ignoring the supply and demand for money alto- for any Pareto-efficient utility allocation we can find a set of p that
gether, we have an economy in which there is one less good. Of support it and penalize households who "overspend" at p, in the
course, Walras' law and the other usual assumptions hold. The same way as before. It does not seem worthwhile going through
economy has an equilibrium. Yet there must be an equilibrium also this again step by step.
for the "full" economy with money, since at a zero price no one will We know that there exists p0 , a competitive equilibrium. Since
wish to hold money and it will be in excess supply. Thus a Pm = 1, we know that there will be sorne demand for money and so
"monetary economy" so loosely specified always has an equilibrium k 0 = O is impossible. Hence k 0 > O. Set p~ = k 0 and we have
in which money plays no part. This result, of cotll'Se, is due entirely found the actual equilibrium price of money. Therefore, if the
i
;1 to the fact that a proper function for money has not been formulated, assumptions made here and in Section 6.3 hold, an equilibrium
i
' so that when money is worthless, transactions can be carried out as always exists for a monetary economy. It is worth noting that
befo re. k 0 > Oimplies pg < 1, so that the equilibrium is reached ata positive
To avoid such nonsense it is best to regard the model as defined, "interest rate."
or viable, only for the c.ase p~ > O. This becomes an additional
constraint. We may assume more sensibly that the demand for
4. Target and Active Excess Demands
money will always be positive-say, by the kind of argument used
in the example. In the previous chapter, where we assumed that money was
Since we are now concerned specifically with the problems arising required for every act of exchange, we found it necessary to dis-
from requiring p~ > O, it is best to return to the construction of tinguish between target and active excess demands. The distinction
Section 6.3, that is, to a world without a past and, therefore, one in is quite similar to the Keynesian distinction between desired pur-
which bankruptcy difficulties cannot occur. We shall consider the chase and effective demand. Strictly speaking, this distinction
case of fixed expected prices only. arises also in a barter economy: A household may have to acquire
Let sorne one good before it can exchange it for the desired one. Still,
it is best to stick to the economy we know, that is, a monetary one.
!(a scalar
We wish to extend the analysis of Chapter 13 to include a pro-
be the initial endowment vector of household money balances. Set duction vector. Also, we shall be concerned with temporary
p~ = 1 and consider p = (p\pb,k), where k is a scalar by which we equilibrium.
propose to multiply Xm, k ~ O. Then, if p is a temporary price As before, we shall write
equilibrium, so is hp, h > O, if we make the following assumption:
The utility of every household is unchanged if the quantity of money
it can hold and all money prices are changed in the same proportion.
This is a sufficiently well-known postulate that does not require as the current production vector that would maximize profits-call
elaboration; it is in accordance with what we said concerning the it the target production vector. Also, xko is the stock of leisure
derived utility function in Section 14.2 (Money). It should be noted (there is on1y one kind) available to h in period 1 and xfi 0 is jts
that changing Pb to hpb is equivalent to multiplying the present prices demand for leisure. Write
of all future goods by h. Also, the amount of money each household
transfers to period 2 from period 1 is multiplied by h. Certainly,
therefore, we may normalize p to lie in the unit simplex.
Now the method of proof of the existence of a temporary equi- l_'V 1
Iibrium, with rather obvious modifications, can proceed as before
Xo - L., Xno Y6 = 2Ylo
" f
362 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
T
!
THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 363

Consider the case in which the price of money is made identically with p given its present definition and x, = (xk,x,b,xkm) As before,
equal to zero. Ignoring the supply and demand for money alto- for any Pareto-efficient utility allocation we can find a set of p that
gether, we have an economy in which there is one less good. Of support it and penalize households who "overspend" at p, in the
course, Walras' law and the other usual assumptions hold. The same way as before. It does not seem worthwhile going through
economy has an equilibrium. Yet there must be an equilibrium also this again step by step.
for the "full" economy with money, since at a zero price no one will We know that there exists p0 , a competitive equilibrium. Since
wish to hold money and it will be in excess supply. Thus a Pm = 1, we know that there will be sorne demand for money and so
"monetary economy" so loosely specified always has an equilibrium k 0 = O is impossible. Hence k 0 > O. Set p~ = k 0 and we have
in which money plays no part. This result, of cotll'Se, is due entirely found the actual equilibrium price of money. Therefore, if the
i
;1 to the fact that a proper function for money has not been formulated, assumptions made here and in Section 6.3 hold, an equilibrium
i
' so that when money is worthless, transactions can be carried out as always exists for a monetary economy. It is worth noting that
befo re. k 0 > Oimplies pg < 1, so that the equilibrium is reached ata positive
To avoid such nonsense it is best to regard the model as defined, "interest rate."
or viable, only for the c.ase p~ > O. This becomes an additional
constraint. We may assume more sensibly that the demand for
4. Target and Active Excess Demands
money will always be positive-say, by the kind of argument used
in the example. In the previous chapter, where we assumed that money was
Since we are now concerned specifically with the problems arising required for every act of exchange, we found it necessary to dis-
from requiring p~ > O, it is best to return to the construction of tinguish between target and active excess demands. The distinction
Section 6.3, that is, to a world without a past and, therefore, one in is quite similar to the Keynesian distinction between desired pur-
which bankruptcy difficulties cannot occur. We shall consider the chase and effective demand. Strictly speaking, this distinction
case of fixed expected prices only. arises also in a barter economy: A household may have to acquire
Let sorne one good before it can exchange it for the desired one. Still,
it is best to stick to the economy we know, that is, a monetary one.
!(a scalar
We wish to extend the analysis of Chapter 13 to include a pro-
be the initial endowment vector of household money balances. Set duction vector. Also, we shall be concerned with temporary
p~ = 1 and consider p = (p\pb,k), where k is a scalar by which we equilibrium.
propose to multiply Xm, k ~ O. Then, if p is a temporary price As before, we shall write
equilibrium, so is hp, h > O, if we make the following assumption:
The utility of every household is unchanged if the quantity of money
it can hold and all money prices are changed in the same proportion.
This is a sufficiently well-known postulate that does not require as the current production vector that would maximize profits-call
elaboration; it is in accordance with what we said concerning the it the target production vector. Also, xko is the stock of leisure
derived utility function in Section 14.2 (Money). It should be noted (there is on1y one kind) available to h in period 1 and xfi 0 is jts
that changing Pb to hpb is equivalent to multiplying the present prices demand for leisure. Write
of all future goods by h. Also, the amount of money each household
transfers to period 2 from period 1 is multiplied by h. Certainly,
therefore, we may normalize p to lie in the unit simplex.
Now the method of proof of the existence of a temporary equi- l_'V 1
Iibrium, with rather obvious modifications, can proceed as before
Xo - L., Xno Y6 = 2Ylo
" f
364 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS

We shall take firms as sufficiently integrated so as to be able to


1 THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 365

So, if z 1 a+ # z 1 +, we ha ve
ignore intermediate goods. This is not a good assumption, but it
is quite harmless to the main point of this section. It means that L pfzla+ + pbzsa+ + x~,a - .\'~,
we take y6 as the only non-positive component of y}. It is also h'O

supposed that firms can always "finance" their demands. Then, if Or, if Zf = z[a+ - yf,
y 1 a is the actual production vector we have
AssuMPTION 3. y1 a # y 1 if and only if y6 + (x6 - x6) < O.
L p[zt + pbz&a+
ti' O
+ x~,a - .\'~, = O, (21)

That is, actual and target production fail to coincide only if firms which is Walras' law for active excess demands. It is different from
cannot get all the labor they want. Let z0 = x6 - x6 - y6, the the usual (target) form; in particular, the excess supply of labor
target excess demand for labor. makes no appearance. Hence, as far as active excess demands are
The money available to households consists of the following: the concerned, active attempts to sell more labor are not mirrored in
stock transferred from the previous period, the receipts from all active attempts to buy more than is being offered for sale.
actual sales, including that of bonds (since firms do not buy bonds, 1t is irnportant not to misunderstand (2 1). lt is not being pro-
households as a whole have no net receipts from bonds), and posed that sornetirnes the usual (target) Walras' law holds and so me-
receipts of profits from the firms. These consist of current profits times it does not. It a!ways holds. What is being arguedis that for
only, since firms finance the payment currently of the present value certain purposes of analysis it is not the most appropriate accounting
of future profits out of the sale of bonds (see Section 6.3). Thus identity. Thus if, as we have irnplicitly been doing, we think of a
households as a group can augment their inherited money stock only two-stage analysis in which households first se!! to firrns and then
by sales of labor and receipts of profits. buy, (2 1) easily emerges. It is a rnuch too tidy affair, of course, as
Let x 1 a be the veGtor of active demands by households taken can be seen from the assumptions. But it makes again the impor-
together and 5P the stock of goods they hold, where both: vectors tant point that in a monetary economy intentions to buy become
exclude money and labor. Write z1 a = (x 1 a - x1). Correspond- relevant signals only when coupled with both the willingness and
ing to these definitions Jet z 1 be the target value of z, that is, when it ability to pay in money. Lastly, the reader familiar with the
is derived without the constraint, no purchase without money. Keynesian literature will recognize (2 1) as the accounting identity
Then we postulate used there. In particular, note that :: depends on what has been
sold, that is, on incorne as well as on prices.
AssuMPTION 4. z1 a + # z 1 + implies y 1 a = y\ where the superscript A certain difficulty with (21) must now be noted. In deriving this
"+" denotes a vector with non-negative components. relation we supposed that households actually receive what are in
What this means is that if households fail to achieve their targets, fact the target profits of period 1, p 1 y 1 If targets cannot be met,
they have not sold their target amount of labor to firms. Then, by actual profits rnay differ from target profits. There are two ways in
A.l4.3, firms cannot ha ve failed to buy the target quantity of labor. which actual profs and target profits m ay differ: Active demand for
The assumption thus excludes the possibility of households selling goods may be less than actual supply; target production may differ
their target quantity of labor, but failing to achieve their target from actual production for the reasons already given. To overcome
borrowing. Once again the main point of the discussion is not this complication we suppose that firms actually pay households the
vitally affected by this. target profits for period 1 out of their cash balances, so that a dis-
From what has already been said, the available monetary resources crepancy between target and actual profits is reflected in the firms'
of the households are second-period assets and so in the valuation of households of their
next period's profit. This way we can keep the accounting straight
although an obvious simplification of reality is involved.
364 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS

We shall take firms as sufficiently integrated so as to be able to


1 THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 365

So, if z 1 a+ # z 1 +, we ha ve
ignore intermediate goods. This is not a good assumption, but it
is quite harmless to the main point of this section. It means that L pfzla+ + pbzsa+ + x~,a - .\'~,
we take y6 as the only non-positive component of y}. It is also h'O

supposed that firms can always "finance" their demands. Then, if Or, if Zf = z[a+ - yf,
y 1 a is the actual production vector we have
AssuMPTION 3. y1 a # y 1 if and only if y6 + (x6 - x6) < O.
L p[zt + pbz&a+
ti' O
+ x~,a - .\'~, = O, (21)

That is, actual and target production fail to coincide only if firms which is Walras' law for active excess demands. It is different from
cannot get all the labor they want. Let z0 = x6 - x6 - y6, the the usual (target) form; in particular, the excess supply of labor
target excess demand for labor. makes no appearance. Hence, as far as active excess demands are
The money available to households consists of the following: the concerned, active attempts to sell more labor are not mirrored in
stock transferred from the previous period, the receipts from all active attempts to buy more than is being offered for sale.
actual sales, including that of bonds (since firms do not buy bonds, 1t is irnportant not to misunderstand (2 1). lt is not being pro-
households as a whole have no net receipts from bonds), and posed that sornetirnes the usual (target) Walras' law holds and so me-
receipts of profits from the firms. These consist of current profits times it does not. It a!ways holds. What is being arguedis that for
only, since firms finance the payment currently of the present value certain purposes of analysis it is not the most appropriate accounting
of future profits out of the sale of bonds (see Section 6.3). Thus identity. Thus if, as we have irnplicitly been doing, we think of a
households as a group can augment their inherited money stock only two-stage analysis in which households first se!! to firrns and then
by sales of labor and receipts of profits. buy, (2 1) easily emerges. It is a rnuch too tidy affair, of course, as
Let x 1 a be the veGtor of active demands by households taken can be seen from the assumptions. But it makes again the impor-
together and 5P the stock of goods they hold, where both: vectors tant point that in a monetary economy intentions to buy become
exclude money and labor. Write z1 a = (x 1 a - x1). Correspond- relevant signals only when coupled with both the willingness and
ing to these definitions Jet z 1 be the target value of z, that is, when it ability to pay in money. Lastly, the reader familiar with the
is derived without the constraint, no purchase without money. Keynesian literature will recognize (2 1) as the accounting identity
Then we postulate used there. In particular, note that :: depends on what has been
sold, that is, on incorne as well as on prices.
AssuMPTION 4. z1 a + # z 1 + implies y 1 a = y\ where the superscript A certain difficulty with (21) must now be noted. In deriving this
"+" denotes a vector with non-negative components. relation we supposed that households actually receive what are in
What this means is that if households fail to achieve their targets, fact the target profits of period 1, p 1 y 1 If targets cannot be met,
they have not sold their target amount of labor to firms. Then, by actual profits rnay differ from target profits. There are two ways in
A.l4.3, firms cannot ha ve failed to buy the target quantity of labor. which actual profs and target profits m ay differ: Active demand for
The assumption thus excludes the possibility of households selling goods may be less than actual supply; target production may differ
their target quantity of labor, but failing to achieve their target from actual production for the reasons already given. To overcome
borrowing. Once again the main point of the discussion is not this complication we suppose that firms actually pay households the
vitally affected by this. target profits for period 1 out of their cash balances, so that a dis-
From what has already been said, the available monetary resources crepancy between target and actual profits is reflected in the firms'
of the households are second-period assets and so in the valuation of households of their
next period's profit. This way we can keep the accounting straight
although an obvious simplification of reality is involved.
L
1
1
1

366 GENERAL COM.PETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 367

Tn view of what has just been said we can easily check that the actual behavior of an economy out of equilibrium as he was with the
appropriate accounting identity when z 0 ~ O is the usual Walras' description of an equilibrium or quasi-equilibrium. Tndeed the idea
law. Households receive target profits and target receipts from the of a q uasi-equilibrium is rather closely connected with the postulated
sale of labor. The discrepancy between y 1 and y 1 a is reflected in the behavior of the economy (in particular, of coLme, the labor market)
expected future receipts from firms, that is, in the stock of bonds. out of equilibrium.
i'
r'
Now consider the possibility, much discussed in recent years (e.g., We shall discuss briefly the Keynesian view of the economy when
by Phillips), that changes in money wages obey the law it is not in quasi-equilibrium. Consider the following quotations
from the General Theory:
Po = F(z 0 + B) B >O,
... if labor were to respond to conditions of gradually diminishing
where F is a sign-possessing function, F(O) = O. Then it is possible employment by offering its services ata gradually diminishing money
that at sorne set of prices - Zo = B, z1 = O, z~a + = O, z~a = o. wage, this would not, as a rl.rie, have the effect of reducing real wages
This suggests p; = O, all i, and we call the situation a quasi-equi- and might even have the effect of increasing them. . . . The chief
librium. Clower has argued that there is good reason to suppose result of this policy would be to cause a great instability of prices, so
violent perhaps as to make business calculations futile .... , To sup-
that this corresponds to Keynes' unemployment eq uilibrium. Of
pose that a flexible wage policy is a right and proper adjunct of a
cotJrSe, it is notan equilibrium in any of the sen ses used in this book; system which on the whole is one of laissez faire, is the opposite of
it is consistent with target excess supply in one market and it is not the truth. (p. 269)
Pareto efficien t.
For if competition between unemployed workers always led toa very
Tt is not at all clear that, for arbitrary B, such an equilibrium need great reduction in the money wage there would be violen! instability
exist. Sometimes, however, the Keynesian wage mechanism is in thc price level. Moreover there might be no position of stable
interpreted as equilibrium except in conditions consisten! with full employment.
(p. 253)
Po = F[max(O,zo)]
In particular it is an, outstanding characteristic of the economic
so that money wages can rise, but not fall. A quasi-equilibrium is system in which we live that, whilst it is subject to severe fluctuations
now any set of prices at which active excess de'mands are zero, but in respect of output and employment, it is not violently unstable.
(p. 249)
z 0 < O. In certain circumstances we can show that either a quasi-
equilibrium in this sense or a proper temporary equilibrium exists. Keynes in fact takes the evidence of the third statement to imply
To do so we cannot use a procedure that depends on the fixed point that the contingencies considered in the first and second do not
being Pareto efficient. Tf we are willing to deal with functions rather occur; that is, wages do not fall, in particular they do not fall very
than corresponden ces, however, we can use the method of Chapter 2, much in response to a target excess supply of labor. On the other
provided the required continuity properties hold. We replace z 0 by hand, the end of statement 2 seems to entail the possibility that if
max(O,z 0 ) = z0 and use (21). We must suppose that there are no wages fell rapidly enough, full eq uilibrium could possibly be estab-
discontinuities at the point at which households cease to be able to lished. In view of statement 1, however, we must take this as not
meet their targets. likely.
It is plain that it will not be easy to make any simple connection
between the adjustment process so far discussed and the kind of
5. Sorne Concluding Remarks
forces Keynes thought to be important. This is partly due to the
So far we ha ve been concerned with the modification of our earlier fact that he was quite imprecise in these matters, but largely because
discussion of temporary equilibrium to make it possible to include a precise formulation would be extremely complex. For instance,
sorne of the features of an economy stressed by Keynes. It is part of an argument designed to show the possible inefficacy of
arguable, however, that Keynes was as much concerned with the falling money wages is to say that they may induce the expectation
L
1
1
1

366 GENERAL COM.PETITIVE ANAL YSIS THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 367

Tn view of what has just been said we can easily check that the actual behavior of an economy out of equilibrium as he was with the
appropriate accounting identity when z 0 ~ O is the usual Walras' description of an equilibrium or quasi-equilibrium. Tndeed the idea
law. Households receive target profits and target receipts from the of a q uasi-equilibrium is rather closely connected with the postulated
sale of labor. The discrepancy between y 1 and y 1 a is reflected in the behavior of the economy (in particular, of coLme, the labor market)
expected future receipts from firms, that is, in the stock of bonds. out of equilibrium.
i'
r'
Now consider the possibility, much discussed in recent years (e.g., We shall discuss briefly the Keynesian view of the economy when
by Phillips), that changes in money wages obey the law it is not in quasi-equilibrium. Consider the following quotations
from the General Theory:
Po = F(z 0 + B) B >O,
... if labor were to respond to conditions of gradually diminishing
where F is a sign-possessing function, F(O) = O. Then it is possible employment by offering its services ata gradually diminishing money
that at sorne set of prices - Zo = B, z1 = O, z~a + = O, z~a = o. wage, this would not, as a rl.rie, have the effect of reducing real wages
This suggests p; = O, all i, and we call the situation a quasi-equi- and might even have the effect of increasing them. . . . The chief
librium. Clower has argued that there is good reason to suppose result of this policy would be to cause a great instability of prices, so
violent perhaps as to make business calculations futile .... , To sup-
that this corresponds to Keynes' unemployment eq uilibrium. Of
pose that a flexible wage policy is a right and proper adjunct of a
cotJrSe, it is notan equilibrium in any of the sen ses used in this book; system which on the whole is one of laissez faire, is the opposite of
it is consistent with target excess supply in one market and it is not the truth. (p. 269)
Pareto efficien t.
For if competition between unemployed workers always led toa very
Tt is not at all clear that, for arbitrary B, such an equilibrium need great reduction in the money wage there would be violen! instability
exist. Sometimes, however, the Keynesian wage mechanism is in thc price level. Moreover there might be no position of stable
interpreted as equilibrium except in conditions consisten! with full employment.
(p. 253)
Po = F[max(O,zo)]
In particular it is an, outstanding characteristic of the economic
so that money wages can rise, but not fall. A quasi-equilibrium is system in which we live that, whilst it is subject to severe fluctuations
now any set of prices at which active excess de'mands are zero, but in respect of output and employment, it is not violently unstable.
(p. 249)
z 0 < O. In certain circumstances we can show that either a quasi-
equilibrium in this sense or a proper temporary equilibrium exists. Keynes in fact takes the evidence of the third statement to imply
To do so we cannot use a procedure that depends on the fixed point that the contingencies considered in the first and second do not
being Pareto efficient. Tf we are willing to deal with functions rather occur; that is, wages do not fall, in particular they do not fall very
than corresponden ces, however, we can use the method of Chapter 2, much in response to a target excess supply of labor. On the other
provided the required continuity properties hold. We replace z 0 by hand, the end of statement 2 seems to entail the possibility that if
max(O,z 0 ) = z0 and use (21). We must suppose that there are no wages fell rapidly enough, full eq uilibrium could possibly be estab-
discontinuities at the point at which households cease to be able to lished. In view of statement 1, however, we must take this as not
meet their targets. likely.
It is plain that it will not be easy to make any simple connection
between the adjustment process so far discussed and the kind of
5. Sorne Concluding Remarks
forces Keynes thought to be important. This is partly due to the
So far we ha ve been concerned with the modification of our earlier fact that he was quite imprecise in these matters, but largely because
discussion of temporary equilibrium to make it possible to include a precise formulation would be extremely complex. For instance,
sorne of the features of an economy stressed by Keynes. It is part of an argument designed to show the possible inefficacy of
arguable, however, that Keynes was as much concerned with the falling money wages is to say that they may induce the expectation
368 GENERAL COMPETITIYE ANAL YSIS
1 THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 369

of falling money prices. Just how large such an expectation must Then, whether the economy may move to a full equilibrium depends,
1
be, in absolute magnitude, to give the predicted "violent instability" of course, on whether it exists and on the global properties of z 9
in any moderately realistic model would be fairly hard to calculate. Certainly we may interpret what Keynes says in quotation 2 in this
Moreover, since the whole process, unlike a tatonnement, takes Iight. (We have taken Pb as fixed and relied on the cash balance
place in real time, the consequences of disequilibrium transactions effect to do the work Keynes ascribes to changing interest rates. A
at one moment in the behavior of the economy in a subsequent full analysis would have todo without this simplification.) It is even
moment would be very difficult to trace. In addition, the actual possible to imagine a case in which oz 9 jop < O and oz9 jow > O, in
path may be strewn with bankruptcies. which case the economy would exhibit oscillatory behavior, which
We cannot attempt to pursue these difficult matters here. It is may or may not be damped. The faster wages change in this case,
certainly sufficiently clear that models constructed to discuss Keynes' the less likly is it that oscillations will be damped.
view, that is, models that pay no attention to expectations, cannot From all this, as well as from our existence discussions, we con-
illuminate or enable us to criticize this view. Suppose we return to elude that the Keynesian revolution cannot be understood if proper
the simple model ofSection 14.3. Let :: 9 be the active excess demand account is not taken of the powerful influence exerted by the future
for output and z 0 the target excess demand for labor. Suppose that and past on the present and by the large modifications that must be
for sorne B, there are prices such that -:: 0 = B, :: 9 = O, that is, that introduced into both value theory and stability analysis, if the
a quasi-equilibrium exists. requisite futures markets are missing. Clearly, it is not possible, on
If we calculate fJz 9 jop and z 9 j;v on the assumption of fixed the basis of this single example, to judge whether Keynes was right
expectations, we find the first term negative and the second term or wrong in his view that a price mechanism confined mainly to
positive. Since oz 0 /8w < O, 8z 0 /p > O, the process j = z9 , w = current markets for current goods is likely to go astray. He was
F(z 0 + B) will be stable since it is a gross-substitute case. certainly right in arguing that the theoretical evidence to be adduced
Now suppose that all agents have the same expectations and that from constructions in which these problems did not arise is not
!'
expected prices are the same as current prices. (Keynes would never relevant. Indeed it could be argued that much of the Iiterature
have denied that lower money wages, say, are good for emplyment devoted to explaining Keynes has really not concerned itself with this
1
if they and prices are lower relative to their future expected value.) central point. This chapter can be taken as no more than a begin-
We find ning of taking seriously the Keynes of the chapters on expectations
OZg - .,n a and the functions of money.
p 8p = cpby = [acx + _(3 c.!.J - e - - sy 1 acx + (I + 1) -b'
1 - (X b p

where Notes
The Jiterature on this subject is vast, and this chapter has been
s = 1 -e w OZg
-e- =
- 111 OZg
-e- - p - . influenced by many writers. The problems of proving the existence of
aw p ap an equilibrium in a monetary economy were first discussed by Hahn
[1965] and Jater by Glustoff [1968]. The distinction between target and
Simple though the construction is, it can now accommodate so me active excess demands is that of Clower [1965], and it has been exten-
of the more important Keynesian points. Certainly, in the vicinity sively discussed by Leijonhufvud [1968].
of quasi-equilibrium we may have oz 9 /p > O. For instance, since
expected prices are al so lower, lower prices will red uce investment
and expected future incomes. This reduction in demand may more
than offset the reduction in current output, even allowing for the rise
in real cash balances. Moreover, if this is the case, !z 9 /w < O and
the reader can easily find the quasi-equilibrium totally unstable.
368 GENERAL COMPETITIYE ANAL YSIS
1 THE KEYNESIAN MODEL 369

of falling money prices. Just how large such an expectation must Then, whether the economy may move to a full equilibrium depends,
1
be, in absolute magnitude, to give the predicted "violent instability" of course, on whether it exists and on the global properties of z 9
in any moderately realistic model would be fairly hard to calculate. Certainly we may interpret what Keynes says in quotation 2 in this
Moreover, since the whole process, unlike a tatonnement, takes Iight. (We have taken Pb as fixed and relied on the cash balance
place in real time, the consequences of disequilibrium transactions effect to do the work Keynes ascribes to changing interest rates. A
at one moment in the behavior of the economy in a subsequent full analysis would have todo without this simplification.) It is even
moment would be very difficult to trace. In addition, the actual possible to imagine a case in which oz 9 jop < O and oz9 jow > O, in
path may be strewn with bankruptcies. which case the economy would exhibit oscillatory behavior, which
We cannot attempt to pursue these difficult matters here. It is may or may not be damped. The faster wages change in this case,
certainly sufficiently clear that models constructed to discuss Keynes' the less likly is it that oscillations will be damped.
view, that is, models that pay no attention to expectations, cannot From all this, as well as from our existence discussions, we con-
illuminate or enable us to criticize this view. Suppose we return to elude that the Keynesian revolution cannot be understood if proper
the simple model ofSection 14.3. Let :: 9 be the active excess demand account is not taken of the powerful influence exerted by the future
for output and z 0 the target excess demand for labor. Suppose that and past on the present and by the large modifications that must be
for sorne B, there are prices such that -:: 0 = B, :: 9 = O, that is, that introduced into both value theory and stability analysis, if the
a quasi-equilibrium exists. requisite futures markets are missing. Clearly, it is not possible, on
If we calculate fJz 9 jop and z 9 j;v on the assumption of fixed the basis of this single example, to judge whether Keynes was right
expectations, we find the first term negative and the second term or wrong in his view that a price mechanism confined mainly to
positive. Since oz 0 /8w < O, 8z 0 /p > O, the process j = z9 , w = current markets for current goods is likely to go astray. He was
F(z 0 + B) will be stable since it is a gross-substitute case. certainly right in arguing that the theoretical evidence to be adduced
Now suppose that all agents have the same expectations and that from constructions in which these problems did not arise is not
!'
expected prices are the same as current prices. (Keynes would never relevant. Indeed it could be argued that much of the Iiterature
have denied that lower money wages, say, are good for emplyment devoted to explaining Keynes has really not concerned itself with this
1
if they and prices are lower relative to their future expected value.) central point. This chapter can be taken as no more than a begin-
We find ning of taking seriously the Keynes of the chapters on expectations
OZg - .,n a and the functions of money.
p 8p = cpby = [acx + _(3 c.!.J - e - - sy 1 acx + (I + 1) -b'
1 - (X b p

where Notes
The Jiterature on this subject is vast, and this chapter has been
s = 1 -e w OZg
-e- =
- 111 OZg
-e- - p - . influenced by many writers. The problems of proving the existence of
aw p ap an equilibrium in a monetary economy were first discussed by Hahn
[1965] and Jater by Glustoff [1968]. The distinction between target and
Simple though the construction is, it can now accommodate so me active excess demands is that of Clower [1965], and it has been exten-
of the more important Keynesian points. Certainly, in the vicinity sively discussed by Leijonhufvud [1968].
of quasi-equilibrium we may have oz 9 /p > O. For instance, since
expected prices are al so lower, lower prices will red uce investment
and expected future incomes. This reduction in demand may more
than offset the reduction in current output, even allowing for the rise
in real cash balances. Moreover, if this is the case, !z 9 /w < O and
the reader can easily find the quasi-equilibrium totally unstable.
~
'

T
1'
1
!
'1

11
.1.:

Appendix A POSITIVE MATRICES 371


1

THEOREM 1 (Perron). Let A 0. Then


POSITIVE MATRICES
(a) there exists x 0 O sueh that x 0 A = ,\0 x 0 ,
(b) ,\ 0 exceeds the moduli of all other characteristic roots x
of A.
(It is clear that lt 0 > 0.)
Proof (a) There is sorne x 0 > O such that x 0 A lt0 x 0 Let
y = x 0 A. Then y O (since A O and x 0 > 0). Then, unless
x 0 A = ,\ 0 x 0 (in which case x 0 0), we have y > lt 0 x 0 or y -
,\ 0 x
0
> O, so that (y - lt 0 x 0 )A O or yA lt0 y. In that case,
however, for sorne E > O,
This appendix proves the theorems on positive matrices that are yA (,\ 0 + E)y.
used in this book. It is not an exhaustive treatment.
Since y O, ye > O (where it will be recalled that e is the. vector all
Notation. Let A be n x n, with elements a. If a11 > O, all i,j, of whose components are 1). If z = yf(ye), then z E Sn. and
write A O. If a11 O, all i,j, and a > O, sorne i,j, write A > O
If a11 O, all i,j, write A O. As usual, Sn is the unit simplex in zA 2: (,\ 0 + E)Z,
n space. Also, let a contradiction of the definition of lt 0 This proves (a).
A = {,\ 1 xA ,\x for sorne x E Sn, ,\ 0}. (b) Let ,\ i= ,\ 0 be a characteristic root of A, and z the correspond-
ing characteristic vector, zA = Az. Let z+ be the vector in which all
Remark l. For any matrix A, A is compact, that is, closed and elements of z are replaced by their moduli; since z i= O, z+ > O.
bounded. For any ,\ E A, let x be the vector for which xA ,\x, Since the modulus of a sum does not exceed the sum of the moduli
x E Sn, and let x 1 be the largest component of x. Then certainly andA O, z+A 2: J!tJz+. From the construction ofIta, J!tl:::; Ita.
x 1 1fn. Furthermore, since Sn is compact, the range of xA 'as x Suppose !ti = lt 0 Let o > Oand small enough so that A - O! O.
1

ranges over Sn is bounded so that, for sorne M, (xA) 1 :::; M for all Evidently, ,\0 - ois the largest positive characteristic root of A - O!
x E Sn and all i. Then and bounds in absolute value all other roots of this matrix. But
,\ :::; nltx1 .:::; n(xA)1 :::; nM, since 1!tJ = ,\ 0 and ,\ i= lt 0 , the imaginary part of ,\ is non-zero. An
easy calculation shows that J!t - oJ > ,\ 0 - o, a contradiction.
so that A is bounded. Now let .vE A, all v, ,\V--+ ,\ 0, and by Hence lt 0 > 1!tJ.
definition, choose xv E Sn such that
THEOREM 2. Let A > 0. Then
xvA 2: ,\vxv.
(a) there exists x 0 > O such that x 0 A = lt 0 x 0 ,
Since Sn is compact, the sequence {xv} has a limit point, say x 0 , in
(b) if ,\ is a characteristic root of A, then !tJ :::; Ita.
1
Sn. Then x 0 A lt 0 x 0 so that ,\ 0 E A, and A is closed as well as
bounded. Note also that for A > O, A is non-null (put ,\ = 0). Proof Let U be the matrix all of whose elements are l. Then
Let for all o > O, A + oU O. Thus, T.A.l holds for this matrix for
lt 0 = max lt;
1\EA
all o > O. By an immediate limiting argument on o, T.A.2 is
established.
the maximum is attained for compact and non-null A. From the
definition of ,\0 , it is clearly real and is non-negative if A > O. DEFINITION l. A matrix, A, is said to be decomposable if there

370

_l
~
'

T
1'
1
!
'1

11
.1.:

Appendix A POSITIVE MATRICES 371


1

THEOREM 1 (Perron). Let A 0. Then


POSITIVE MATRICES
(a) there exists x 0 O sueh that x 0 A = ,\0 x 0 ,
(b) ,\ 0 exceeds the moduli of all other characteristic roots x
of A.
(It is clear that lt 0 > 0.)
Proof (a) There is sorne x 0 > O such that x 0 A lt0 x 0 Let
y = x 0 A. Then y O (since A O and x 0 > 0). Then, unless
x 0 A = ,\ 0 x 0 (in which case x 0 0), we have y > lt 0 x 0 or y -
,\ 0 x
0
> O, so that (y - lt 0 x 0 )A O or yA lt0 y. In that case,
however, for sorne E > O,
This appendix proves the theorems on positive matrices that are yA (,\ 0 + E)y.
used in this book. It is not an exhaustive treatment.
Since y O, ye > O (where it will be recalled that e is the. vector all
Notation. Let A be n x n, with elements a. If a11 > O, all i,j, of whose components are 1). If z = yf(ye), then z E Sn. and
write A O. If a11 O, all i,j, and a > O, sorne i,j, write A > O
If a11 O, all i,j, write A O. As usual, Sn is the unit simplex in zA 2: (,\ 0 + E)Z,
n space. Also, let a contradiction of the definition of lt 0 This proves (a).
A = {,\ 1 xA ,\x for sorne x E Sn, ,\ 0}. (b) Let ,\ i= ,\ 0 be a characteristic root of A, and z the correspond-
ing characteristic vector, zA = Az. Let z+ be the vector in which all
Remark l. For any matrix A, A is compact, that is, closed and elements of z are replaced by their moduli; since z i= O, z+ > O.
bounded. For any ,\ E A, let x be the vector for which xA ,\x, Since the modulus of a sum does not exceed the sum of the moduli
x E Sn, and let x 1 be the largest component of x. Then certainly andA O, z+A 2: J!tJz+. From the construction ofIta, J!tl:::; Ita.
x 1 1fn. Furthermore, since Sn is compact, the range of xA 'as x Suppose !ti = lt 0 Let o > Oand small enough so that A - O! O.
1

ranges over Sn is bounded so that, for sorne M, (xA) 1 :::; M for all Evidently, ,\0 - ois the largest positive characteristic root of A - O!
x E Sn and all i. Then and bounds in absolute value all other roots of this matrix. But
,\ :::; nltx1 .:::; n(xA)1 :::; nM, since 1!tJ = ,\ 0 and ,\ i= lt 0 , the imaginary part of ,\ is non-zero. An
easy calculation shows that J!t - oJ > ,\ 0 - o, a contradiction.
so that A is bounded. Now let .vE A, all v, ,\V--+ ,\ 0, and by Hence lt 0 > 1!tJ.
definition, choose xv E Sn such that
THEOREM 2. Let A > 0. Then
xvA 2: ,\vxv.
(a) there exists x 0 > O such that x 0 A = lt 0 x 0 ,
Since Sn is compact, the sequence {xv} has a limit point, say x 0 , in
(b) if ,\ is a characteristic root of A, then !tJ :::; Ita.
1
Sn. Then x 0 A lt 0 x 0 so that ,\ 0 E A, and A is closed as well as
bounded. Note also that for A > O, A is non-null (put ,\ = 0). Proof Let U be the matrix all of whose elements are l. Then
Let for all o > O, A + oU O. Thus, T.A.l holds for this matrix for
lt 0 = max lt;
1\EA
all o > O. By an immediate limiting argument on o, T.A.2 is
established.
the maximum is attained for compact and non-null A. From the
definition of ,\0 , it is clearly real and is non-negative if A > O. DEFINITION l. A matrix, A, is said to be decomposable if there

370

_l
r'

372 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T POSITIVE MATRICES 373

exists a perrnutation that, when applied sirnultaneously to the rows since z :2: O and A > O. For the rth cornponent this inequality
1

and colurnns, puts A in the forrn: 1


becornes
O= SZr :2: - ey?,
and since y? > o, e :2: o. By definition of e, X :2: o, but since
x i= O (otherwise y = 0), x > O.
If A is not decornposable, it is said to be indecomposable. (e) We show that, in fact, x O. Suppose not. Let x = (x\x 2),
THEOREM 3. Let A > O and indecornposable. Then there exists where x 1 O and x 2 = O. Partition (si - A) conforrnably, and
x 0 O such that x 0A = il 0 A, where !1 0 is the root described in consider
l. '1::
T.A.2.
'1
(x\x 2 )(si - A1 - A 2 ) > O.
Proof Suppose x , as described in T.A.2, has zero cornponents.
0
-A 3 si- A 4
Let x 0 = (x 01 ,x02 ), where x 01 O and x 02 = O. Partition A con-
forrnably, and consider the equation Then O s x 1( -A 2) + x 2(si- A 4) = -x 1A 2, and since x 1 O and
A 2 :2: O, this is possible only if A2 = O, which contradicts the
1.
hypothesis of indecornposability. Hence x O.
Remark 2. If A > O, but decornposable, and we know that for
sorne u O, u(si- A) O, then we rnay proceed as in (a) and (b)
Then x 01 A2 + x 02 A 4 = il 0x 02 or, since x 02 = O, x 01 A2 = O. Since
of the preceding proof to show that (si - A) - l > O.
A2 ;;:: O and x 01 O, this is possible only if A2 = O. Then. A is
decornposable, contrary to hypothesis. THEOREM 5. Let A > O and indecornposable,
THEOREM 4. Let A > O and indecornposable, and s > !10 Then
si - A is non-singular and B = (si - A) - l O.
Proof. (a) Suppose si - A singular. Then there exists x i= O so Then
that xA = sx. Then s > !1 0 would be a characteristic root of A, rnin r s !1 0 s rnax r.
contrary to T.A.2. i i

=
(b) Frorn T.A.3 and hypothesis, y 0 x 0 (si- A) = (s - !1 0)x 0 Proof. (a) Let B > O be a rnatrix of the sarne order as A, such
O. Now consider x(si - A) = y, with y > O. The assertion
that A - B ;;:: O. Let ;, be a characteristic root of B, and y the
B O is equivalent to the staternent x O for each such y. First
associated right characteristic vector. We show that J;,J s !10. We
it is shown that x > O. have By= ;,y and x 0 A = il 0x 0. Let y+ have cornponents Jy;J.
Let Then J;,Jy+ s By+ s Ay+, and hence
e= rnin X
JLJx 0y+ s x 0 Ay+ il 0x 0y+.
x? =

Then z :2: O, Zr = O for sorne r. But x 0 O, y+ > O, so that x 0y+ > O and J;,J s !1 0.
(b) Let B be derived frorn A by rnultiplying every elernent in the
z(si- A)= y- ey 0 > -eyo, jth row of A by
or
for eachj.
sz > zA - Oy 0 ;;:: - Oy 0
r'

372 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T POSITIVE MATRICES 373

exists a perrnutation that, when applied sirnultaneously to the rows since z :2: O and A > O. For the rth cornponent this inequality
1

and colurnns, puts A in the forrn: 1


becornes
O= SZr :2: - ey?,
and since y? > o, e :2: o. By definition of e, X :2: o, but since
x i= O (otherwise y = 0), x > O.
If A is not decornposable, it is said to be indecomposable. (e) We show that, in fact, x O. Suppose not. Let x = (x\x 2),
THEOREM 3. Let A > O and indecornposable. Then there exists where x 1 O and x 2 = O. Partition (si - A) conforrnably, and
x 0 O such that x 0A = il 0 A, where !1 0 is the root described in consider
l. '1::
T.A.2.
'1
(x\x 2 )(si - A1 - A 2 ) > O.
Proof Suppose x , as described in T.A.2, has zero cornponents.
0
-A 3 si- A 4
Let x 0 = (x 01 ,x02 ), where x 01 O and x 02 = O. Partition A con-
forrnably, and consider the equation Then O s x 1( -A 2) + x 2(si- A 4) = -x 1A 2, and since x 1 O and
A 2 :2: O, this is possible only if A2 = O, which contradicts the
1.
hypothesis of indecornposability. Hence x O.
Remark 2. If A > O, but decornposable, and we know that for
sorne u O, u(si- A) O, then we rnay proceed as in (a) and (b)
Then x 01 A2 + x 02 A 4 = il 0x 02 or, since x 02 = O, x 01 A2 = O. Since
of the preceding proof to show that (si - A) - l > O.
A2 ;;:: O and x 01 O, this is possible only if A2 = O. Then. A is
decornposable, contrary to hypothesis. THEOREM 5. Let A > O and indecornposable,
THEOREM 4. Let A > O and indecornposable, and s > !10 Then
si - A is non-singular and B = (si - A) - l O.
Proof. (a) Suppose si - A singular. Then there exists x i= O so Then
that xA = sx. Then s > !1 0 would be a characteristic root of A, rnin r s !1 0 s rnax r.
contrary to T.A.2. i i

=
(b) Frorn T.A.3 and hypothesis, y 0 x 0 (si- A) = (s - !1 0)x 0 Proof. (a) Let B > O be a rnatrix of the sarne order as A, such
O. Now consider x(si - A) = y, with y > O. The assertion
that A - B ;;:: O. Let ;, be a characteristic root of B, and y the
B O is equivalent to the staternent x O for each such y. First
associated right characteristic vector. We show that J;,J s !10. We
it is shown that x > O. have By= ;,y and x 0 A = il 0x 0. Let y+ have cornponents Jy;J.
Let Then J;,Jy+ s By+ s Ay+, and hence
e= rnin X
JLJx 0y+ s x 0 Ay+ il 0x 0y+.
x? =

Then z :2: O, Zr = O for sorne r. But x 0 O, y+ > O, so that x 0y+ > O and J;,J s !1 0.
(b) Let B be derived frorn A by rnultiplying every elernent in the
z(si- A)= y- ey 0 > -eyo, jth row of A by
or
for eachj.
sz > zA - Oy 0 ;;:: - Oy 0
!Ir
1 .

i,
;1
1
1
374 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
Appendix B
Then every row sum of B is
CONVEX AND RELATED SETS
mio r 1,

B > O and indecomposable. Let .0 be the dominant root of B as


defined by T.A.2 and T.A.3 and y the associated right characteristic
1
vector. By T.A.3, y O. From (a), .\0 y :2::: .0 y = By. Let
11

11
Yr = miny1
1

Then

l. Basic Definitions
Most of the concepts to be introduced in this section need little
which, since Yr > O, establishes elaboration.
DEFINITION l. A linear space, L, is a set of vectors such that
mio r1 :::; .\ 0
1
(a) if x EL, then tx EL for any real t;
It is left to the reader to establish the second part of the inequality. (b) if x 1 EL and x 2 EL, then x 1 + x 2 E L.
Remark 3. By considering A', T.A.5 establishes also that Sets are partially ordered by set inclusion. Hence, for any given
family of sets, we can speak of a minimal member of the family,
mio c1 :::; .\ 0 :::; max c1, meaning a set in the family such that no other member is a subset of
j j
it. Similarly, a maximal member of the family is one that is not
where included in any other member.
Any set, S, may be included in a linear space modified by having
the origin displaced to another point, that is, a set of the form
L + {a}, for sorne a. Then for any x E S, x = x' + a, for sorne
x' EL, or equivalently, x - a E L. Take any fixed x 0 E S, so that
x 0 - a E L. Since L is a linear space, a - x0 = (-l)(x0 - a) EL,
and so does x - x 0 = (x - a) + (a - x 0). Hence, if S eL +
{a} for sorne a, S e L + {x0 } for any fixed x 0 E S. Then Jet S e
L + {a} and also S e L' + {a'}, where L and L' are linear spaces.
" "
,, 11

Choose any x 0 E S; then S eL + {x0 }, S e L' + {x0 }, or x - x 0


i'
belongs to both L and L', and therefore, to their intersection. Thus,
if L" is the intersection of alllinear spaces L such that S e L + {a}
for sorne a, it is also true that S e L" + {x0 }. Since the intersection
of any family of linear spaces is again a linear space, L" must be the
minimallinear space with the property S e L + {a} for sorne {a}.
DEFINITION 2. The linear space of S, L(S), is the mnima! linear
space with the property S e L + {a} for sorne a. By the dimension
of S, dim S, is meant the dimension of L(S).

375
!Ir
1 .

i,
;1
1
1
374 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
Appendix B
Then every row sum of B is
CONVEX AND RELATED SETS
mio r 1,

B > O and indecomposable. Let .0 be the dominant root of B as


defined by T.A.2 and T.A.3 and y the associated right characteristic
1
vector. By T.A.3, y O. From (a), .\0 y :2::: .0 y = By. Let
11

11
Yr = miny1
1

Then

l. Basic Definitions
Most of the concepts to be introduced in this section need little
which, since Yr > O, establishes elaboration.
DEFINITION l. A linear space, L, is a set of vectors such that
mio r1 :::; .\ 0
1
(a) if x EL, then tx EL for any real t;
It is left to the reader to establish the second part of the inequality. (b) if x 1 EL and x 2 EL, then x 1 + x 2 E L.
Remark 3. By considering A', T.A.5 establishes also that Sets are partially ordered by set inclusion. Hence, for any given
family of sets, we can speak of a minimal member of the family,
mio c1 :::; .\ 0 :::; max c1, meaning a set in the family such that no other member is a subset of
j j
it. Similarly, a maximal member of the family is one that is not
where included in any other member.
Any set, S, may be included in a linear space modified by having
the origin displaced to another point, that is, a set of the form
L + {a}, for sorne a. Then for any x E S, x = x' + a, for sorne
x' EL, or equivalently, x - a E L. Take any fixed x 0 E S, so that
x 0 - a E L. Since L is a linear space, a - x0 = (-l)(x0 - a) EL,
and so does x - x 0 = (x - a) + (a - x 0). Hence, if S eL +
{a} for sorne a, S e L + {x0 } for any fixed x 0 E S. Then Jet S e
L + {a} and also S e L' + {a'}, where L and L' are linear spaces.
" "
,, 11

Choose any x 0 E S; then S eL + {x0 }, S e L' + {x0 }, or x - x 0


i'
belongs to both L and L', and therefore, to their intersection. Thus,
if L" is the intersection of alllinear spaces L such that S e L + {a}
for sorne a, it is also true that S e L" + {x0 }. Since the intersection
of any family of linear spaces is again a linear space, L" must be the
minimallinear space with the property S e L + {a} for sorne {a}.
DEFINITION 2. The linear space of S, L(S), is the mnima! linear
space with the property S e L + {a} for sorne a. By the dimension
of S, dim S, is meant the dimension of L(S).

375
376 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS
T

CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 377

In what follows, a relative neighborhood of a point x 0 E S is defined convex combination of the points xl (i = O, ... , r). Now any point
to be the intersection of a neighborhood of x 0 with L(S) + {x0 }. in S can be written uniquely as
Then x 0 is a relative interior point of S if it possesses a relative r r r
neighborhood entirely contained in S; x 0 is a relative boundary point x = x0 + : ,\(xl - x 0) = : AX with : A = l.
of S if every relative neighborhood of x 0 contains points of both S l= 1 l=O t=O

and S (the complement of S).


If we write
DEFINITION 3. Por any finite set T, x' is said to be a convex combina- r
tion of T if there exists a real-valued function, cx(x), defined on T, such where > O, : = 1
l=O
that
we see that for any x in a sufficiently small relative neighborhood of
cx(x) ;:::: O aii x E T,
i, the corresponding A's must be non-negative, so that x is a convex
: cx(x) = 1,
XET
combination of the points x 1 (i = O, ... , r) and, therefore, belongs
to S. Since S is convex, every point of S is visible from every point
in this neighborhood.
x' = . cx(x)x.
xeT

We will also say that T spans x' under the same circumstances. The
2. Gauge Functions
point x' will be said to be a proper convex combination of T if, in Por any set, S, anda given point, x 0 , we can define a function over
addition to the above, cx(x) > O, aii x E T. A fine segment [x\x 2 ] is L(S) that in effect indicates how far along a Iine segment starting at
the set of convex combinations of the set containing just the two x 0 the set S extends.
elements x 1 and x 2
DEFINITION 8. The gauge function p(x x 0 ,S) for a given set S and
1

DEFINITION 4. Por any set S and any two points, x 1 and x 2 , x 1 is point x 0 in the relative interior of S is defined for aii x E L(S) as
visible in S from x 2 if [x\x 2 ] e S.

DEFINITION 5. S is star shaped (with center x 0 ) if every point of S


is visible from x 0

DEFINITION 6. S is strictly star shaped (with center x 0 ) if there is a Since x 0 is a relative interior point, there will always exist sorne
relative neighborhood N of x 0 such that every point of S is visible p > O for which x 0 + (x/p) E S for any x E L(S), so that the gauge
from every point of N. function is always defined.
Where the context makes the designation of x 0 and S clear or
DEFINITION 7. S is convex if every point of S is visible from any unnecessary, the gauge function will be referred to simply as p(x).
other. To state someproperties of gauge functions, we define two properties
of real-valued functions.
LEMMA l. If S is convex, then it is strictly star shaped for some
center. DEFINITION 9. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said
to be positive homogeneous if f(tx) = tf(x) for aii x and al! t > O.
Proof Take any x 0 E S. Then, if r = dim S, it follows from
D.B.2 that there exist r elements of S, xt (i = 1, ... , r) such that the DEFINITION 10. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said
vectors xt - x 0 are Iinearly independent. Let x be any proper to be subadditive if for every x 1 and x 2 , f(x 1 + x 2 ) s f(x 1 ) + f(x 2 ).
376 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS
T

CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 377

In what follows, a relative neighborhood of a point x 0 E S is defined convex combination of the points xl (i = O, ... , r). Now any point
to be the intersection of a neighborhood of x 0 with L(S) + {x0 }. in S can be written uniquely as
Then x 0 is a relative interior point of S if it possesses a relative r r r
neighborhood entirely contained in S; x 0 is a relative boundary point x = x0 + : ,\(xl - x 0) = : AX with : A = l.
of S if every relative neighborhood of x 0 contains points of both S l= 1 l=O t=O

and S (the complement of S).


If we write
DEFINITION 3. Por any finite set T, x' is said to be a convex combina- r
tion of T if there exists a real-valued function, cx(x), defined on T, such where > O, : = 1
l=O
that
we see that for any x in a sufficiently small relative neighborhood of
cx(x) ;:::: O aii x E T,
i, the corresponding A's must be non-negative, so that x is a convex
: cx(x) = 1,
XET
combination of the points x 1 (i = O, ... , r) and, therefore, belongs
to S. Since S is convex, every point of S is visible from every point
in this neighborhood.
x' = . cx(x)x.
xeT

We will also say that T spans x' under the same circumstances. The
2. Gauge Functions
point x' will be said to be a proper convex combination of T if, in Por any set, S, anda given point, x 0 , we can define a function over
addition to the above, cx(x) > O, aii x E T. A fine segment [x\x 2 ] is L(S) that in effect indicates how far along a Iine segment starting at
the set of convex combinations of the set containing just the two x 0 the set S extends.
elements x 1 and x 2
DEFINITION 8. The gauge function p(x x 0 ,S) for a given set S and
1

DEFINITION 4. Por any set S and any two points, x 1 and x 2 , x 1 is point x 0 in the relative interior of S is defined for aii x E L(S) as
visible in S from x 2 if [x\x 2 ] e S.

DEFINITION 5. S is star shaped (with center x 0 ) if every point of S


is visible from x 0

DEFINITION 6. S is strictly star shaped (with center x 0 ) if there is a Since x 0 is a relative interior point, there will always exist sorne
relative neighborhood N of x 0 such that every point of S is visible p > O for which x 0 + (x/p) E S for any x E L(S), so that the gauge
from every point of N. function is always defined.
Where the context makes the designation of x 0 and S clear or
DEFINITION 7. S is convex if every point of S is visible from any unnecessary, the gauge function will be referred to simply as p(x).
other. To state someproperties of gauge functions, we define two properties
of real-valued functions.
LEMMA l. If S is convex, then it is strictly star shaped for some
center. DEFINITION 9. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said
to be positive homogeneous if f(tx) = tf(x) for aii x and al! t > O.
Proof Take any x 0 E S. Then, if r = dim S, it follows from
D.B.2 that there exist r elements of S, xt (i = 1, ... , r) such that the DEFINITION 10. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said
vectors xt - x 0 are Iinearly independent. Let x be any proper to be subadditive if for every x 1 and x 2 , f(x 1 + x 2 ) s f(x 1 ) + f(x 2 ).
- '1
T
1
1

1
1
li

378 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 379

THEOREM l. The following properties hold for gauge functions: can be chosen arbitrarily clase to p(x1), so it must be that
p(xl + x2) ~ p(xl) + p(x2).
(a) p(O) = O; In Section 6.4, it turned out to be useful to show that a strictly
(b) p(x) is positive homogeneous;
star-shaped set is equivalent in certain essential ways to a compact
(e) if S is bounded, then p(x 1 x 0 ,S) > O for all x =1= O;
convex set; more exactly, it is a continuous image of such a set.
(d) if p(x x 0 ,S) > p, then x 0 + (xfp) ~S;
1
This follows easily from the continuity of the gauge function for such
(e) if S is star shaped with center x 0 and p(x 1 x 0 ,S) < p, then sets.
x 0 + (xfp) E S;
(f) if p(x- x 0 1 x 0 ,S) > 1, then x ~S; THEOREM 2. If S is strictly star shaped with center x 0 then the
(g) if S is star shaped with center x 0 and p(x - x 0 1 x 0 ,S) < 1, gauge function for the point x 0 and S is continuous. '
then x E S;
(h) if S is closed and star shaped with center x 0 , then x E S if Prooj. Let {x"} be a sequence such that x"-+ x. By T.B.l(i),
and only if p(x - x 0 x 0 ,S) ~ 1;
1
then, the sequence {p(x")} is bounded. Let p* be any limit point;
(i) p(x) is bounded on every bounded subset of the linear we seek to prove that p* = p(x).
space on which it is defined; For notational convenience let x 0 = O; there is clearly no Ioss of
(j) if S is convex, then p(x x 0 ,S) is subadditive.
1
generality.
Let {Ev} be a sequence of positive real numbers converging to O,
Prooj. Parts (a)-(d) follow immediately from the definitions. Pv = p~x") : E"v By T.B.l(e), x"fPv E S, all v. By the hypothesis
Suppose the hypothesis of (e) holds. Then, by D.B.8, there exists that S 1s stnctly star shaped, it is possible to choose E" > O such that
p' < p such that x 0 + (x/p') E S. But ever~ element of S is visible from every x for which fxl ~ E". In
particular, therefore, x"fPv is visible from E(x- x")/fx- x"f, all v.
1'
xo + ~ = %(xo + (?)) + (1 - %) xo. Let
1 i

Since x 0 + (x/p') is visible from x 0 by hypothesis, and p' < p by x'" = x


construction, x 0 + (xfp) E S, as claimed. Parts (f) and (g) follow Pv~+-(;-;-1x---x""'I/,...,..E")

from (d) and (e), respectively, if x is replaced by x - x 0 and p set


E"Pv ~ + fx - x"f E(X - x")
equal to l. In view of (f) and (g) it is :mfficient to show that
E"Pv + fx - x"l Pv E"Pv + fx - x"f fx - x"f ;
p(x - x 0 ) = 1 implies that x E S to prove (h). For such x, x 0 +
(x- x 0 )/p E S for all p > 1, by (e); for closed S, then x = x 0 + then x'" must lie in S; by the definition of a gauge function, then,
(x - x 0)/1 E S.
If (i) did not hold, then there would be a bounded sequence {x"} p(x) ~ Pv + (fx- x"I/E").
for which p(x")-+ oo. Then we could certainly choose a sequence
By letting v approach infinity, we see that p(x) ~ p*. The argument
{p"} such that p" < p(x"), p"-+ oo. By (d), x 0 + (x"/p") ~S. But
is illustrated in Figure B-la.
this sequence approaches x 0 , in contradiction to D.B.8, which
. It remai.ns ~o show that p(x) :=::: p*; this part of the proof is
requires that x 0 be a relative interior point of S.
Illustrated m.F1gure B-lb. Note thatp(x) = fxfp(x/fxl) ifx =1= O by
Finally, to prove (j), we can choose p 1 > p(x1), i = 1,2, so that
T.B.l(b). S1nce p(x/fxf) is bounded, by T.B.I(i), it easily follows
x + (x1/p1) E S by (e). Since S is convex, the point
0
that
xo + xl + x2 = P1 (xo + xl) + P2 (xo + x2) lim p(x) = O = p(O),
x->0
P1 + P2 P1 + P2 P1 P1 + P2 P2
also belongs to S. By definition, p(x 1 + x 2) ~ P1 + p 2, but p 1 by T.B.l(a). Furthermore, if x =!= O, then it follows also that it
- '1
T
1
1

1
1
li

378 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 379

THEOREM l. The following properties hold for gauge functions: can be chosen arbitrarily clase to p(x1), so it must be that
p(xl + x2) ~ p(xl) + p(x2).
(a) p(O) = O; In Section 6.4, it turned out to be useful to show that a strictly
(b) p(x) is positive homogeneous;
star-shaped set is equivalent in certain essential ways to a compact
(e) if S is bounded, then p(x 1 x 0 ,S) > O for all x =1= O;
convex set; more exactly, it is a continuous image of such a set.
(d) if p(x x 0 ,S) > p, then x 0 + (xfp) ~S;
1
This follows easily from the continuity of the gauge function for such
(e) if S is star shaped with center x 0 and p(x 1 x 0 ,S) < p, then sets.
x 0 + (xfp) E S;
(f) if p(x- x 0 1 x 0 ,S) > 1, then x ~S; THEOREM 2. If S is strictly star shaped with center x 0 then the
(g) if S is star shaped with center x 0 and p(x - x 0 1 x 0 ,S) < 1, gauge function for the point x 0 and S is continuous. '
then x E S;
(h) if S is closed and star shaped with center x 0 , then x E S if Prooj. Let {x"} be a sequence such that x"-+ x. By T.B.l(i),
and only if p(x - x 0 x 0 ,S) ~ 1;
1
then, the sequence {p(x")} is bounded. Let p* be any limit point;
(i) p(x) is bounded on every bounded subset of the linear we seek to prove that p* = p(x).
space on which it is defined; For notational convenience let x 0 = O; there is clearly no Ioss of
(j) if S is convex, then p(x x 0 ,S) is subadditive.
1
generality.
Let {Ev} be a sequence of positive real numbers converging to O,
Prooj. Parts (a)-(d) follow immediately from the definitions. Pv = p~x") : E"v By T.B.l(e), x"fPv E S, all v. By the hypothesis
Suppose the hypothesis of (e) holds. Then, by D.B.8, there exists that S 1s stnctly star shaped, it is possible to choose E" > O such that
p' < p such that x 0 + (x/p') E S. But ever~ element of S is visible from every x for which fxl ~ E". In
particular, therefore, x"fPv is visible from E(x- x")/fx- x"f, all v.
1'
xo + ~ = %(xo + (?)) + (1 - %) xo. Let
1 i

Since x 0 + (x/p') is visible from x 0 by hypothesis, and p' < p by x'" = x


construction, x 0 + (xfp) E S, as claimed. Parts (f) and (g) follow Pv~+-(;-;-1x---x""'I/,...,..E")

from (d) and (e), respectively, if x is replaced by x - x 0 and p set


E"Pv ~ + fx - x"f E(X - x")
equal to l. In view of (f) and (g) it is :mfficient to show that
E"Pv + fx - x"l Pv E"Pv + fx - x"f fx - x"f ;
p(x - x 0 ) = 1 implies that x E S to prove (h). For such x, x 0 +
(x- x 0 )/p E S for all p > 1, by (e); for closed S, then x = x 0 + then x'" must lie in S; by the definition of a gauge function, then,
(x - x 0)/1 E S.
If (i) did not hold, then there would be a bounded sequence {x"} p(x) ~ Pv + (fx- x"I/E").
for which p(x")-+ oo. Then we could certainly choose a sequence
By letting v approach infinity, we see that p(x) ~ p*. The argument
{p"} such that p" < p(x"), p"-+ oo. By (d), x 0 + (x"/p") ~S. But
is illustrated in Figure B-la.
this sequence approaches x 0 , in contradiction to D.B.8, which
. It remai.ns ~o show that p(x) :=::: p*; this part of the proof is
requires that x 0 be a relative interior point of S.
Illustrated m.F1gure B-lb. Note thatp(x) = fxfp(x/fxl) ifx =1= O by
Finally, to prove (j), we can choose p 1 > p(x1), i = 1,2, so that
T.B.l(b). S1nce p(x/fxf) is bounded, by T.B.I(i), it easily follows
x + (x1/p1) E S by (e). Since S is convex, the point
0
that
xo + xl + x2 = P1 (xo + xl) + P2 (xo + x2) lim p(x) = O = p(O),
x->0
P1 + P2 P1 + P2 P1 P1 + P2 P2
also belongs to S. By definition, p(x 1 + x 2) ~ P1 + p 2, but p 1 by T.B.l(a). Furthermore, if x =!= O, then it follows also that it
T -T
1

380 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 381

suffices to prove continuity for all x such that lxl = l. Choose p > p(x), so that xfp E S, by T.B.l(e). Then xfp is
denote the usual inner product of x 1 and x 2, that is, visible from y', all v. By construction,
x D,
x' = (x'x )1fJ - + - y'.
p E

Since D,/E ;::: O while (x'x)p -7- p > O, it follows that for v large,
x'
, xv IPv .z v = 7
( x-:-:'x----;):-'P-+-,---;(D--;:;--;v/"E)
f4Jv .... ,
x,fxvf x
.1.-~1
/ xjp~ / ',, is a convex combination of xfp and y' and therefore belongs to S,
., ..., 1 1'' 11 ,~-~ r\.,,, \ by hypothesis. Therefore, p(x') ::::; (xvx)p + (Dv/E). Let Jl approach
//
1
11
11
',
\ 1 1 1 lzv'~' \ infinity; then p* ::::; p. Since p was any number exceeding p(x),
11 11 1 f 1 1/ \\ '
11
1
\
..
11 1uo /
1
\ ~yV 1
(
p* ::::; p(x), as was to be proved.
1 1
\ \'jE Coro!lary 2. If S is convex, then for sorne x 0 , the gauge function,
..... ""'
\ E 1
\1
' .... J--- "' / \ ', ~-- 1 p(x 1 x 0 ,S) is continuous ..
', ,.,.1
.............. ____ ..,., Proof T.B.2, Lemma B. l .
THEOREM 3. For any compact, strictly star shaped set S, there is a
(a) (b) compact convex set C and a continuous function T(x) that maps C
into S and whose unique inverse maps S into C.
LEGEND: 1/ Two lines so marked are parallel
Proof Take C to b the unit sphere, {x llxl ::::; 1}. Let X 0 be a
_j Right angle
center of the strictly star shaped set S as defined in D.B.6. Let the
mapping be defined by
Figure B-r
xlxl
0
X +- if X i= 0,
T(x) = p(x)
{
By a well-known inequality, x if X= O.
(x'x)2 ::::; lx'l21xl2 = l. Here p(x) is the gauge function for S from x 0 Note that T(x) is
well defined since p(x) > O for x i= O by T.B.l(c). From T.B.2,
Then we can define D, = V1 - (x'x) 2; clearly D, -7- O. Also,
T(x) is clearly continuous for x i= O. Also, for x i= O, it follows
lx'- (x'x)xl 2 = lx'l 2 - 2(x'x) 2 + (x'x)21xl 2 from the positive homogeneity of p(x) that
= 1 - (x'x) 2 = D~, X
T(x) = xo + p(x/lxl).
or lx' - (x'x)xl = D,. For all v for which D, > O, let
Let B be the boundary of the unit sphere; sin ce p is continuous
y' = _:_ [x' - (x'x)x]. and positive there, p(x) is bounded away from O for x E B. If x i= O,
D,
xflxl E B, so that p(x/lxl) is bounded away from O for x i= O.
Then IY'I = E for all v for which D, > O; choose y' arbitrarily Hence, as x approaches O, x/p(x/lxl) approaches O, so that T(x)
subject to the condition IY'I = E for all v for which D, = O. approaches x 0 and is continuous.
T -T
1

380 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 381

suffices to prove continuity for all x such that lxl = l. Choose p > p(x), so that xfp E S, by T.B.l(e). Then xfp is
denote the usual inner product of x 1 and x 2, that is, visible from y', all v. By construction,
x D,
x' = (x'x )1fJ - + - y'.
p E

Since D,/E ;::: O while (x'x)p -7- p > O, it follows that for v large,
x'
, xv IPv .z v = 7
( x-:-:'x----;):-'P-+-,---;(D--;:;--;v/"E)
f4Jv .... ,
x,fxvf x
.1.-~1
/ xjp~ / ',, is a convex combination of xfp and y' and therefore belongs to S,
., ..., 1 1'' 11 ,~-~ r\.,,, \ by hypothesis. Therefore, p(x') ::::; (xvx)p + (Dv/E). Let Jl approach
//
1
11
11
',
\ 1 1 1 lzv'~' \ infinity; then p* ::::; p. Since p was any number exceeding p(x),
11 11 1 f 1 1/ \\ '
11
1
\
..
11 1uo /
1
\ ~yV 1
(
p* ::::; p(x), as was to be proved.
1 1
\ \'jE Coro!lary 2. If S is convex, then for sorne x 0 , the gauge function,
..... ""'
\ E 1
\1
' .... J--- "' / \ ', ~-- 1 p(x 1 x 0 ,S) is continuous ..
', ,.,.1
.............. ____ ..,., Proof T.B.2, Lemma B. l .
THEOREM 3. For any compact, strictly star shaped set S, there is a
(a) (b) compact convex set C and a continuous function T(x) that maps C
into S and whose unique inverse maps S into C.
LEGEND: 1/ Two lines so marked are parallel
Proof Take C to b the unit sphere, {x llxl ::::; 1}. Let X 0 be a
_j Right angle
center of the strictly star shaped set S as defined in D.B.6. Let the
mapping be defined by
Figure B-r
xlxl
0
X +- if X i= 0,
T(x) = p(x)
{
By a well-known inequality, x if X= O.
(x'x)2 ::::; lx'l21xl2 = l. Here p(x) is the gauge function for S from x 0 Note that T(x) is
well defined since p(x) > O for x i= O by T.B.l(c). From T.B.2,
Then we can define D, = V1 - (x'x) 2; clearly D, -7- O. Also,
T(x) is clearly continuous for x i= O. Also, for x i= O, it follows
lx'- (x'x)xl 2 = lx'l 2 - 2(x'x) 2 + (x'x)21xl 2 from the positive homogeneity of p(x) that
= 1 - (x'x) 2 = D~, X
T(x) = xo + p(x/lxl).
or lx' - (x'x)xl = D,. For all v for which D, > O, let
Let B be the boundary of the unit sphere; sin ce p is continuous
y' = _:_ [x' - (x'x)x]. and positive there, p(x) is bounded away from O for x E B. If x i= O,
D,
xflxl E B, so that p(x/lxl) is bounded away from O for x i= O.
Then IY'I = E for all v for which D, > O; choose y' arbitrarily Hence, as x approaches O, x/p(x/lxl) approaches O, so that T(x)
subject to the condition IY'I = E for all v for which D, = O. approaches x 0 and is continuous.
----']'
'1
T
1
'

1,
!:
382 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 383

Again using the positive homogeneity of the gauge function, Since the left-hand side depends only on x 1 and the right-hand side
on x 2 and these two variables are independent, there must be a
p[T(x) - xo] = p (xlxl) =
p(x) p(x)
M
p(x) = lxl. scalar a such that

From T.B.1 (h), T(x) E S if and only if xl s 1, so that S is indeed


1 f(xl) - p(xl - uo) s a s - f(x2) + p(xz + uo),
the image of C under the mapping T(x). It is easy to see that T(x) allx\x 2 EL'. (1)
has a unique inverse.
Then we define F(x) = f(x') + at when x = x' + tu 0 , x' EL'.
Clearly, F(x) is a linear function, and it coincides withf(x) for x EL',
3. Support and Separation Theorems
that is, when t = p. It remains to show that F(x' + tu 0 ) s
i Consider a convex set C and the linear space L( C). A hyperplane p(x' + tu 0 ) for x EL', t =1= O. First assume t >'O. Then use the
1 in L( C) defines two half-spaces, the sets of points not abo ve and not second inequality in (1) with x 2 = x'ft.
below the hyperplane. A separating hyperplane for two disjoint sets,
C1 and C2, is one such that C1 is contained in one and C2 in the other F(x' + tu 0 ) = f(x') + at s f(x') - if (~') + tp(~' + u0 )
of the half-spaces.
In establishing the existence of separating hyperplanes, we shall = f(x') - f(x') + p(x' + tu 0 ) = p(x' + tu 0 ),
make use of the gauge function and .of the Hahn-Banach theorem where use has been made of the properties tf(x') = f(tx'), all t,
for finite-dimensional spaces. tp(x) = p(tx) for t > O.
DEFINITION 11. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said For the case t < O, use the first inequality in (1), and let x 1 =
to be linear if f(tx) = tf(x) for all real t and f(x 1 + x 2) = f(x 1) + -x'ft; positive homogeneity of p(x) implies -tp(x) = p(-tx).
/(x 2) for al! x 1 and x 2.
THEOREM 4. Let p(x) be a positive homogeneous, sul;:>additive F(x' + tu 0 ) =f(x') + at sf(x') + tf(-tx')- tp(-tx'- u0 )
function defined on a linear space L andf(x) a linear function defined
on a linear space L' contained in L. If f(x) s p(x) for al! x EL', = p(x' + tu 0),
then there exists a linear function F(x) defined on L such that
as was to be proved.
(a) F(x) = f(x) for all x EL',
(b) F(x) s p(x) for all x E L. THEOREM 5 (First Separation Theorem). Let C be a convex set, x 1
belong to L(C), but not to C. Then there exists a point x 0 in the
Proof It suffices to establish the theorem for the case in which
relative interior of C and a linear function, F(x), defined on L( C),
the dimension of Lis one greater than that of L', for then the general such that for all x E C, F(x - x 0 ) s F(x 1 - x 0), with F(x) not
case follows by straightforward induction. identically o. If e is closed, then there is a constant e < F(x 1 - x 0 )
In that case, let u0 be any element of L not in L'. Then obviously
such that F(x - x 0 ) s e for all x E C.
any x EL can be written x = x' + tu 0 , where x' EL', and this in only
one way. Proof Choose x 0 in the relative interior of e, and let p(x) =
Now take any xt EL' (i = 1,2). By hypothesis and the definitions, p(x 1 x 0 ,C) be the gauge function. Let L' be the one-dimensional
f(xl) + f(xz) = f(xl + xz) s p(xl + xz) space consisting of all points x = t(x 1 - x 0) for all t. On L',
= p[(xl - uo) + (xz + uo)] define f(x) = tp(x 1 - x 0); it is certainly a linear function. For
s p(x 1 - u0 ) + p(x 2 + u 0 ), t > O, f(x) = p[t(x 1 - x 0)] = p(x), by the homogeneity of p; for
t s O, f(x) s O s p(x), so that f(x) s p(x), all x EL'. By T.B.4,
the last by the subadditivity of p(x). Equivalently, there exists a linear function F(x) on L(C) such thatf(x) = F(x) for
f(x 1) - p(x 1 - u0) s - f(x 2) + p(x 2 + u0 ) all x\ x 2 EL'. x EL', F(x) s p(x) for all x EL( C). From T.B.l(f), p(x - x 0 ) s 1
----']'
'1
T
1
'

1,
!:
382 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 383

Again using the positive homogeneity of the gauge function, Since the left-hand side depends only on x 1 and the right-hand side
on x 2 and these two variables are independent, there must be a
p[T(x) - xo] = p (xlxl) =
p(x) p(x)
M
p(x) = lxl. scalar a such that

From T.B.1 (h), T(x) E S if and only if xl s 1, so that S is indeed


1 f(xl) - p(xl - uo) s a s - f(x2) + p(xz + uo),
the image of C under the mapping T(x). It is easy to see that T(x) allx\x 2 EL'. (1)
has a unique inverse.
Then we define F(x) = f(x') + at when x = x' + tu 0 , x' EL'.
Clearly, F(x) is a linear function, and it coincides withf(x) for x EL',
3. Support and Separation Theorems
that is, when t = p. It remains to show that F(x' + tu 0 ) s
i Consider a convex set C and the linear space L( C). A hyperplane p(x' + tu 0 ) for x EL', t =1= O. First assume t >'O. Then use the
1 in L( C) defines two half-spaces, the sets of points not abo ve and not second inequality in (1) with x 2 = x'ft.
below the hyperplane. A separating hyperplane for two disjoint sets,
C1 and C2, is one such that C1 is contained in one and C2 in the other F(x' + tu 0 ) = f(x') + at s f(x') - if (~') + tp(~' + u0 )
of the half-spaces.
In establishing the existence of separating hyperplanes, we shall = f(x') - f(x') + p(x' + tu 0 ) = p(x' + tu 0 ),
make use of the gauge function and .of the Hahn-Banach theorem where use has been made of the properties tf(x') = f(tx'), all t,
for finite-dimensional spaces. tp(x) = p(tx) for t > O.
DEFINITION 11. The functionf(x) defined over a linear space is said For the case t < O, use the first inequality in (1), and let x 1 =
to be linear if f(tx) = tf(x) for all real t and f(x 1 + x 2) = f(x 1) + -x'ft; positive homogeneity of p(x) implies -tp(x) = p(-tx).
/(x 2) for al! x 1 and x 2.
THEOREM 4. Let p(x) be a positive homogeneous, sul;:>additive F(x' + tu 0 ) =f(x') + at sf(x') + tf(-tx')- tp(-tx'- u0 )
function defined on a linear space L andf(x) a linear function defined
on a linear space L' contained in L. If f(x) s p(x) for al! x EL', = p(x' + tu 0),
then there exists a linear function F(x) defined on L such that
as was to be proved.
(a) F(x) = f(x) for all x EL',
(b) F(x) s p(x) for all x E L. THEOREM 5 (First Separation Theorem). Let C be a convex set, x 1
belong to L(C), but not to C. Then there exists a point x 0 in the
Proof It suffices to establish the theorem for the case in which
relative interior of C and a linear function, F(x), defined on L( C),
the dimension of Lis one greater than that of L', for then the general such that for all x E C, F(x - x 0 ) s F(x 1 - x 0), with F(x) not
case follows by straightforward induction. identically o. If e is closed, then there is a constant e < F(x 1 - x 0 )
In that case, let u0 be any element of L not in L'. Then obviously
such that F(x - x 0 ) s e for all x E C.
any x EL can be written x = x' + tu 0 , where x' EL', and this in only
one way. Proof Choose x 0 in the relative interior of e, and let p(x) =
Now take any xt EL' (i = 1,2). By hypothesis and the definitions, p(x 1 x 0 ,C) be the gauge function. Let L' be the one-dimensional
f(xl) + f(xz) = f(xl + xz) s p(xl + xz) space consisting of all points x = t(x 1 - x 0) for all t. On L',
= p[(xl - uo) + (xz + uo)] define f(x) = tp(x 1 - x 0); it is certainly a linear function. For
s p(x 1 - u0 ) + p(x 2 + u 0 ), t > O, f(x) = p[t(x 1 - x 0)] = p(x), by the homogeneity of p; for
t s O, f(x) s O s p(x), so that f(x) s p(x), all x EL'. By T.B.4,
the last by the subadditivity of p(x). Equivalently, there exists a linear function F(x) on L(C) such thatf(x) = F(x) for
f(x 1) - p(x 1 - u0) s - f(x 2) + p(x 2 + u0 ) all x\ x 2 EL'. x EL', F(x) s p(x) for all x EL( C). From T.B.l(f), p(x - x 0 ) s 1
Tl :r

384 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 385

for x EC. Let e = 1; then F(x - x 0 ) :::; p(x - x 0 ) :::; e for all 4. Convex Hulls and Vector Sums
1: X E c. Sin ce x 1 $ e, it follows from T.B.l (g) that p(x 1 - x 0 ) :::::: 1 =
'1 DEFINITION 12. The eonvex hu/! of a set S, con S, is the minimal 1

,,
1
e, while if C is closed, we must have p(x 1 - x 0 ) > e by T.B.l(h). ,
convex set that includes S.
Finally, by construction, F(x 1 - x 0) = f(xl - xo) = p(xl _ xo).
1'

That every set possesses a convex hull can easily be seen. First, 1!
Corollary 5. Let C be a convex set of the full dimensionality of note that the intersection of the members of any family of sets con- 1
the space, X 1 $ C. Then there exists a row vector y =1= O such that taining S must itself contain S. Now consider the intersection of i
yx ;:>: yx 1 for all X E c. If e is closed, there is a constant e > yx 1 any family of convex sets. If x 1 and x 2 are any two members of the ,il
such that yx : : : e for all x E C. 1:
intersection, they belong to all members of the family. Since each ri

Proof Let F(x) have the properties specified in T.B.5. Then is convex, each contains the line segment [x\:x-2], which by the
F(x) is a linear function over the entire space. Let ei be the ith unit preceding remarl<, must a1so be contained in the intersection. Thus,
vector (with 1 in the ith place and O elsewhere); then any vector x the intersection of a family of convex sets is also convex. From
these remarks, it follows that the intersection of all convex sets
1

' can be written as


1

1
containing S is a convex set containing S; by construction, this
intersection is included in any convex set containing S and is there-
fore the minima1 set of this type. We note an obvious charac-
Then
terization of convex lmlls.

-F(x) = -F(L xiei) =


i
-2: xiF(ei) = L
' i
yixi = yx, THEOREM 7. (a) If S is finite, con S is the set of all convex combina-
tions of S.
where y is the rciw vector with components Yi = - F(ei). Since (b) For any S, con S = {x 1 T spans x for some finite subset T of
F(x) is not identically zero, y =1= O. Then by T.B.5, y(x ~ xo) ;:::: S with at most n + 1 elements}, where n is the dimensionality of the
y(x 1 - X 0), aiJ X E C, or, equiva1elitJy, yx ;:::: yx 1 space.
Proof It is obvious that if T e S, then con T e con S, and we
THEOREM 6 (Second Separation Theorem). Let el be a convex
shall use this fact repeatedly. First, we note that if T is a finite
set of the full dimensionality of the space, C2 a convex set disjoint
subset of a convex set C and T spans x, then x E C. We prove this
from C1. Then there exists y =!= O and scalar e such that yx ;:::: e, all
by induction on the number of elements of T. If T contains two
X E el, yx :::; e, all X E C2.
elements, this statement is just the definition of convexity. Suppose
:roof Let C = C1 - C 2 If x 1 is an interior point of C 1 (one true when T has m members, and let T with m + 1 members span x.
eXJStS by hypothesis) and X 2 any eJement of C 2 , then x 1 + U E C1 for Then there is a real-va1ued function a(x') defined on T, with
all u sufficiently small in abso1ute value, so that, by definition,
1
X + u - X = (x - X ) + u E el - c2 for all such u.
2 1 2
By defini-
x = L a(x')x'
X'ET
L a(x') = 1,
X'ET
1 2
tion, X - X is an interior point of C 1 - C2 , which must therefore
a(x') ;:::: O, all x' E T.
ha ve the full dimensionality of the space. Also, since C and C are
disjoint, it is impossible that x 1 - x 2 = O for any x 1 E ~ , x 2 : C 2 ;
1 Choose x E T so that a(x ) < 1, and let T' = T ~ {x 0}; T' has m
0 0
hence, O $ C1 - C2. Then Corollary 5 implies that for some members. Let f3(x') = a(x')/[1 - a(x 0)] for x' E T'. Then
y =!= O, yx : : : o for all X E el - c2, or by definition, yx 1 :::::: yx 2 for x = [1 - a(x 0)]x 1 + a(x 0)x 0,
all X 1 E C1, X 2 E C 2 . Since the two variables are independent, there
where
must be a constant e such that
x1 = L
X'ET'
f3(x')x'.
Tl :r

384 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 385

for x EC. Let e = 1; then F(x - x 0 ) :::; p(x - x 0 ) :::; e for all 4. Convex Hulls and Vector Sums
1: X E c. Sin ce x 1 $ e, it follows from T.B.l (g) that p(x 1 - x 0 ) :::::: 1 =
'1 DEFINITION 12. The eonvex hu/! of a set S, con S, is the minimal 1

,,
1
e, while if C is closed, we must have p(x 1 - x 0 ) > e by T.B.l(h). ,
convex set that includes S.
Finally, by construction, F(x 1 - x 0) = f(xl - xo) = p(xl _ xo).
1'

That every set possesses a convex hull can easily be seen. First, 1!
Corollary 5. Let C be a convex set of the full dimensionality of note that the intersection of the members of any family of sets con- 1
the space, X 1 $ C. Then there exists a row vector y =1= O such that taining S must itself contain S. Now consider the intersection of i
yx ;:>: yx 1 for all X E c. If e is closed, there is a constant e > yx 1 any family of convex sets. If x 1 and x 2 are any two members of the ,il
such that yx : : : e for all x E C. 1:
intersection, they belong to all members of the family. Since each ri

Proof Let F(x) have the properties specified in T.B.5. Then is convex, each contains the line segment [x\:x-2], which by the
F(x) is a linear function over the entire space. Let ei be the ith unit preceding remarl<, must a1so be contained in the intersection. Thus,
vector (with 1 in the ith place and O elsewhere); then any vector x the intersection of a family of convex sets is also convex. From
these remarks, it follows that the intersection of all convex sets
1

' can be written as


1

1
containing S is a convex set containing S; by construction, this
intersection is included in any convex set containing S and is there-
fore the minima1 set of this type. We note an obvious charac-
Then
terization of convex lmlls.

-F(x) = -F(L xiei) =


i
-2: xiF(ei) = L
' i
yixi = yx, THEOREM 7. (a) If S is finite, con S is the set of all convex combina-
tions of S.
where y is the rciw vector with components Yi = - F(ei). Since (b) For any S, con S = {x 1 T spans x for some finite subset T of
F(x) is not identically zero, y =1= O. Then by T.B.5, y(x ~ xo) ;:::: S with at most n + 1 elements}, where n is the dimensionality of the
y(x 1 - X 0), aiJ X E C, or, equiva1elitJy, yx ;:::: yx 1 space.
Proof It is obvious that if T e S, then con T e con S, and we
THEOREM 6 (Second Separation Theorem). Let el be a convex
shall use this fact repeatedly. First, we note that if T is a finite
set of the full dimensionality of the space, C2 a convex set disjoint
subset of a convex set C and T spans x, then x E C. We prove this
from C1. Then there exists y =!= O and scalar e such that yx ;:::: e, all
by induction on the number of elements of T. If T contains two
X E el, yx :::; e, all X E C2.
elements, this statement is just the definition of convexity. Suppose
:roof Let C = C1 - C 2 If x 1 is an interior point of C 1 (one true when T has m members, and let T with m + 1 members span x.
eXJStS by hypothesis) and X 2 any eJement of C 2 , then x 1 + U E C1 for Then there is a real-va1ued function a(x') defined on T, with
all u sufficiently small in abso1ute value, so that, by definition,
1
X + u - X = (x - X ) + u E el - c2 for all such u.
2 1 2
By defini-
x = L a(x')x'
X'ET
L a(x') = 1,
X'ET
1 2
tion, X - X is an interior point of C 1 - C2 , which must therefore
a(x') ;:::: O, all x' E T.
ha ve the full dimensionality of the space. Also, since C and C are
disjoint, it is impossible that x 1 - x 2 = O for any x 1 E ~ , x 2 : C 2 ;
1 Choose x E T so that a(x ) < 1, and let T' = T ~ {x 0}; T' has m
0 0
hence, O $ C1 - C2. Then Corollary 5 implies that for some members. Let f3(x') = a(x')/[1 - a(x 0)] for x' E T'. Then
y =!= O, yx : : : o for all X E el - c2, or by definition, yx 1 :::::: yx 2 for x = [1 - a(x 0)]x 1 + a(x 0)x 0,
all X 1 E C1, X 2 E C 2 . Since the two variables are independent, there
where
must be a constant e such that
x1 = L
X'ET'
f3(x')x'.
T
386 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 387

Since x 1 is spanned by T', x 1 E e by the induction hypothesis; there are more than n + 1 of them, they are linear!y dependen t. We
x 0 E C by hypothesis; hence x E C by the definition of convexity. can find a real function c(x') defined for x' E T such that
L c(x')(x',1) = O c(x') =f. Ofor sorne x' E T. i',,
lf C is convex and T a finite subset of C, 1
X'ET
then every convex combination of T belongs to C. (2)
Then
(a) In (2) if we replace T by S and C by any convex set containing
S, then we can see that every convex combination of S belongs to L c(x')x' = O
X'ET
L
X'ET
c(x') =O.
every convex set cont~ining S. But the set of convex combinations
of S is easily seen to be itself convex. Hence the set of convex
Let f3(x') = a(x') + tc(x'); then
combinations of S must be the convex hull of S by D.B.12, since it .L f3(x') = 1
x'eT
L f3(x')x' = x .
is a convex set containing S and contained in every convex set X'ET

containing S. Sin ce - c(x') satisfies the same conditions as c(x'), we can assume
(b) For general S, con Te con S, for T a finite subset of S. Let without loss of generality that c(x') < O for sorne x' E T. Then
1
S* = {x 1 T spans x for sorne finite subset T of S}. Then clearly f3(x') > O .for all x' E T when t = O, {3(x') < O for so me x' for t
S* e con S. By consi,dering the one-element subsets of S, in par- sufficiently large. There is, then, a largest t = i for which f3(x') ;::: O,
ticular, it is obvious that S e S* and therefore con S e con S*. all x' E T. For this value, f3(x') = Ofor sorne x', so that x is spanned
Hence it is necessary only to show that S* is convex. If x is spanned by a smaller set, contrary to hypothesis. Hence T contains, at most,
by T, it is certainly spanned by any finite set containing T; we need n + 1 elements.
Ot?-lY extend the definition of a(x) by letting a(x) = O for x ~ T.
The operation of taking a convex hull commutes with that of
Then, if x 1 and x 2 E S*, they are spanned by finite subsets T1 and
forming a vector sum.
T2, respectively. Then both are spanned by the finite subset
T1 u T 2 , and hence any convex combination of them is span~ed by LEMMA 2. For any sets S1 (i = 1, ... , m),
T1 u T 2 and therefore belongs toS*. m m

It remains to show that if x E S*, x is spanned by a finite subset of


con L S = L con S
i= 1
1
1= 1
1

S with no more than n + 1 elements. For any x E S*, let T be the Proof It suffices to consider the case m = 2; the general case
spanning set with the least number of members. If follows by an obvious induction.
First, let x E con(S1 + S 2). Then x can be written
x = L a(x')x',

where
XET
x = "'a
L.;
1 '
x'
1

where X1 E sl + S2. Then x1 = xil + x 12 , where x11 S, x12 s2.


a(x') :?: O L a(x') = 1,
x'eT
Hence,
E E

then it must be that a(x') > O for all x' E T; otherwise such an x' X = Lj
aXil + L j
a,xt2'

could be deleted and the remainder of the set would still span x,
whereas we have chosen T to have the least possible number of and is therefore the sum of a vector in con S 1 and of one in con S 2.
members. Suppose, then, a(x') > O, all x' E T, and T has more than Now let x E con S 1 + con S 2. Then x = x 1 + x 2, where
n + 1 members. Associate with each member of T the correspond- x1 = Lax 1
11

ing (n + !)-dimensional vector obtained by adding 1 as the (n + l)st 1

component. Write such a vector as (x',1), where x' E T. Since where x 11 E S, all i, x 2 j E s2, all j.
T
386 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 387

Since x 1 is spanned by T', x 1 E e by the induction hypothesis; there are more than n + 1 of them, they are linear!y dependen t. We
x 0 E C by hypothesis; hence x E C by the definition of convexity. can find a real function c(x') defined for x' E T such that
L c(x')(x',1) = O c(x') =f. Ofor sorne x' E T. i',,
lf C is convex and T a finite subset of C, 1
X'ET
then every convex combination of T belongs to C. (2)
Then
(a) In (2) if we replace T by S and C by any convex set containing
S, then we can see that every convex combination of S belongs to L c(x')x' = O
X'ET
L
X'ET
c(x') =O.
every convex set cont~ining S. But the set of convex combinations
of S is easily seen to be itself convex. Hence the set of convex
Let f3(x') = a(x') + tc(x'); then
combinations of S must be the convex hull of S by D.B.12, since it .L f3(x') = 1
x'eT
L f3(x')x' = x .
is a convex set containing S and contained in every convex set X'ET

containing S. Sin ce - c(x') satisfies the same conditions as c(x'), we can assume
(b) For general S, con Te con S, for T a finite subset of S. Let without loss of generality that c(x') < O for sorne x' E T. Then
1
S* = {x 1 T spans x for sorne finite subset T of S}. Then clearly f3(x') > O .for all x' E T when t = O, {3(x') < O for so me x' for t
S* e con S. By consi,dering the one-element subsets of S, in par- sufficiently large. There is, then, a largest t = i for which f3(x') ;::: O,
ticular, it is obvious that S e S* and therefore con S e con S*. all x' E T. For this value, f3(x') = Ofor sorne x', so that x is spanned
Hence it is necessary only to show that S* is convex. If x is spanned by a smaller set, contrary to hypothesis. Hence T contains, at most,
by T, it is certainly spanned by any finite set containing T; we need n + 1 elements.
Ot?-lY extend the definition of a(x) by letting a(x) = O for x ~ T.
The operation of taking a convex hull commutes with that of
Then, if x 1 and x 2 E S*, they are spanned by finite subsets T1 and
forming a vector sum.
T2, respectively. Then both are spanned by the finite subset
T1 u T 2 , and hence any convex combination of them is span~ed by LEMMA 2. For any sets S1 (i = 1, ... , m),
T1 u T 2 and therefore belongs toS*. m m

It remains to show that if x E S*, x is spanned by a finite subset of


con L S = L con S
i= 1
1
1= 1
1

S with no more than n + 1 elements. For any x E S*, let T be the Proof It suffices to consider the case m = 2; the general case
spanning set with the least number of members. If follows by an obvious induction.
First, let x E con(S1 + S 2). Then x can be written
x = L a(x')x',

where
XET
x = "'a
L.;
1 '
x'
1

where X1 E sl + S2. Then x1 = xil + x 12 , where x11 S, x12 s2.


a(x') :?: O L a(x') = 1,
x'eT
Hence,
E E

then it must be that a(x') > O for all x' E T; otherwise such an x' X = Lj
aXil + L j
a,xt2'

could be deleted and the remainder of the set would still span x,
whereas we have chosen T to have the least possible number of and is therefore the sum of a vector in con S 1 and of one in con S 2.
members. Suppose, then, a(x') > O, all x' E T, and T has more than Now let x E con S 1 + con S 2. Then x = x 1 + x 2, where
n + 1 members. Associate with each member of T the correspond- x1 = Lax 1
11

ing (n + !)-dimensional vector obtained by adding 1 as the (n + l)st 1

component. Write such a vector as (x',1), where x' E T. Since where x 11 E S, all i, x 2 j E s2, all j.
l'! ~r

388 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 389

Then it is easily calculated that as the Cartesian product of compact sets, it is itself compact. Hence,
by choice of a suitable subsequence, we can find vectors cx E Sn,
i
x = rxf3ix1t + x2'),
t j
x' 1 E S (each i) such that a.v-+ cx, x'tv :-7- x' 1 along the subsequence.
Then
1'
!1
and since x 11
+x 21
E S1 + S 2 for every pair i andj, x E con(S1 + S 2). n+1
,1, X = dX'i,
Another elementary consequence ofthe definitions is the following. t=1
'1!1,
! LEMMA 3. The convex hull of a compact set is compact. so that x E con S.
1~
Proof If S is bounded, then lxl ::;; M for all x E S, for sorne We now cometo the main point of this section for our purposes,
suitably chosen M. Then, if x E con S, we can find a finite subset a theorem due to L. Shapley and J. H. Folkman (unpublished but
T of S and a real non-negative function rx(x') defined on T such that reported by Starr [1969, pp. 35-37]) of the extent to which vector
11 sums of bounded sets are approximately convex. We first need the

1

x'eT
rx(x') = x =
x'eT
rx(x')x'. concept of the "facial dimension" of a point in a convex set, that is,
the dimension of the face on which it lies (note that convex hulls
By the triangle inequality, typically ha ve flat sections on their boundary); this theory is due to
Karlin and Shapley [1953, pp. 6-7].
lxl ::;;
x'eT
rx(x')lx'l :S:
x' e T
rx(x')M = M,
DEFINITION 13. The vector y is a facial direction at X in C if X +
ty E C for all t sufficiently small. The set of all facial directions at
1 1

so that con S is bounded.


X in C is called the facial Space at X in C.
Now let {xv} be a sequence in con S, with xv-+ x. We seek to
show that x E con 3. For each v we can find a set rv e S with not If C is convex, the facial space, after displacement of the origin to
more than n + 1 elements anda non-negative function rxv(x'j defined x, is the hyperplane of highest dimension such that x lies in the
on rv such that relative interior of the intersection of C with that hyperplane. In
Figure B-2, y is a facial direction at X in e, and L is the facial space

X'ET
rxv(x') = 1 rxv(x')x' = xv.
x'eT
there. At x 1 or x 2 , the only facial direction is O.

Without loss of generality we can suppose that rv contains n +

cV:x'
elements, each v; we need only add elements for which we define L
rxv(x') = O. For each v enumerate the elements of rv in sorne
\
arbitrary order; call them x'iv (i = 1, ... , n + 1). Let rxi =
i - xx+ty
1 i rxv(x' 1v). Then y
X - ty
n+1 n+1
:L af = rxix'tv = xv. x2
t= 1 t= 1
o
The numbers rxJ' can be considered components of a vector a.v, which
belongs to the unit simplex Sn Then the vectors x' 1v, cxv taken
together belong to the Cartesian product x2 - x

Figure B-2

':
l'! ~r

388 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 389

Then it is easily calculated that as the Cartesian product of compact sets, it is itself compact. Hence,
by choice of a suitable subsequence, we can find vectors cx E Sn,
i
x = rxf3ix1t + x2'),
t j
x' 1 E S (each i) such that a.v-+ cx, x'tv :-7- x' 1 along the subsequence.
Then
1'
!1
and since x 11
+x 21
E S1 + S 2 for every pair i andj, x E con(S1 + S 2). n+1
,1, X = dX'i,
Another elementary consequence ofthe definitions is the following. t=1
'1!1,
! LEMMA 3. The convex hull of a compact set is compact. so that x E con S.
1~
Proof If S is bounded, then lxl ::;; M for all x E S, for sorne We now cometo the main point of this section for our purposes,
suitably chosen M. Then, if x E con S, we can find a finite subset a theorem due to L. Shapley and J. H. Folkman (unpublished but
T of S and a real non-negative function rx(x') defined on T such that reported by Starr [1969, pp. 35-37]) of the extent to which vector
11 sums of bounded sets are approximately convex. We first need the

1

x'eT
rx(x') = x =
x'eT
rx(x')x'. concept of the "facial dimension" of a point in a convex set, that is,
the dimension of the face on which it lies (note that convex hulls
By the triangle inequality, typically ha ve flat sections on their boundary); this theory is due to
Karlin and Shapley [1953, pp. 6-7].
lxl ::;;
x'eT
rx(x')lx'l :S:
x' e T
rx(x')M = M,
DEFINITION 13. The vector y is a facial direction at X in C if X +
ty E C for all t sufficiently small. The set of all facial directions at
1 1

so that con S is bounded.


X in C is called the facial Space at X in C.
Now let {xv} be a sequence in con S, with xv-+ x. We seek to
show that x E con 3. For each v we can find a set rv e S with not If C is convex, the facial space, after displacement of the origin to
more than n + 1 elements anda non-negative function rxv(x'j defined x, is the hyperplane of highest dimension such that x lies in the
on rv such that relative interior of the intersection of C with that hyperplane. In
Figure B-2, y is a facial direction at X in e, and L is the facial space

X'ET
rxv(x') = 1 rxv(x')x' = xv.
x'eT
there. At x 1 or x 2 , the only facial direction is O.

Without loss of generality we can suppose that rv contains n +

cV:x'
elements, each v; we need only add elements for which we define L
rxv(x') = O. For each v enumerate the elements of rv in sorne
\
arbitrary order; call them x'iv (i = 1, ... , n + 1). Let rxi =
i - xx+ty
1 i rxv(x' 1v). Then y
X - ty
n+1 n+1
:L af = rxix'tv = xv. x2
t= 1 t= 1
o
The numbers rxJ' can be considered components of a vector a.v, which
belongs to the unit simplex Sn Then the vectors x' 1v, cxv taken
together belong to the Cartesian product x2 - x

Figure B-2

':
1 1
1

390 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 391


Frorn this definition, it is obvious that if y is a facial direction, Hence, interchanging x and x\ the weak inequality holds also in
then sois ty for any scalar t. Now suppose C is convex and y 1 and the reverse direction, so equality holds. If x 1 - x is not a facial
2
y are both facial directions at sorne point x in C. By definition, direction at x\ then, by Lernma B.5, the set of facial directions at
x + ty 1 E C for 1td srnall (i = 1,2). Sin ce C is convex, x 1 is a proper subset of that at x; but since both are linear spaces,
by Lemrna B.4, the facial space at x 1 rnust have a lower dirnension
X + __!t2 y1 + __gt2 y2 E C than that at x.
We now consider faces formed when the convex hull of a set is
for [t1[, [t 2[ sufficiently srnall, so that x + t(y 1 + y2) E C for [t[ taken. A point in the convex hull of a set is spanned by a finite
sufficiently srnall, and therefore, y 1 + y 2 is a facial direction also. subset of the convex hui!. We show that the difference between the
point and any elernent of the spanning set is a facial direction in the
LEMMA 4. If C is convex and X E C, then the facial space at X in C convex hui!. In Figure B-3, x 1 - x and x 2 - x are facial directions
is a linear space.
at x in the convex hull of the illustrated set.
DEFINITION 14. The facial dimension of X in C, d(x f C), is the
dirnension of the facial space at x in C.

1
In Figure B-2, the facial dirnension of X in e is 1, while that of x 1
is O. x'
Suppose x and x 1 both belong to a convex set C and also suppose
that the rnovernent frorn x to x 1 lies on a face; that is, x 1 - x is a
facial direction at x in C. Then any facial direction at x 1 rnust also
be a facial direction at x; the converse willnot hold if x 1 is at the
edge of the face, as can be seen fforn Figure B-2.
Figure B-3
LEMMA 5. lf x and x 1 belong to the convex set C and x 1 - x is a
facial direction at X in C, then every facial direction at X 1 is also a
facial direction at x. LEMMA 7. If x E con S, then there is a finite subset T of S such that
T spans x and x' - x is a facial direction at x in con S for all x' E T.
Proof. Since x 1 - x is a facial direction at x, x 0 = x + t(x 1 - x)
Proof By T.B.7(b), there is a finite subset T of S anda function
E C for SOrne f < 0, SO that X = (J - a)x 0 + ax\ Where a =
a(x') defined on T such that
- t/(1 - t), and therefore, O < a < l. Let y be a facial direction
e
at x 1 ; then x 1 + ty E for 1t 1 sufficiently small. Then X + aty = L a(x') = 1,
(1 - a)x 0 + a(x 1 + ty) E C for all [t [ sufficiently srnall and therefore X;ET

for all [at [ sufficiently srnall. Hence, by definition, y is a facial a(x') ;:::: O all x' E T, ,:
direction at x. il'

LEMMA 6. If x and x 1 both belong to a convex set C and if x 1 - x


x = : a(x')x'. i',
,
X'ET
'i'
is a facial direction at x in C, then d(x 1 C) :<::; d(x C). The
f f
If we delete all elernents of T for which a(x') = O, obviously the sarne
equality holds if and only if x 1 - x is also a facial direction at x 1 Ir:
relations hold. Hence we can assurne a(x') > O for all x' E T. 11!
in C. Choose any fixed x" E T, and let ,!.1!

:
1
Proof The weak inequality follows frorn Lernrna B.5. If x 1 - x
is also a facial direction at xl, then so is x - x 1 = ( -l)(x 1 - x).
x 1 = (1 - t)x + tx" = tx" + (1 - t)
1
a(x')x'. '1:
,1
X E 1' !
11

,,
1:11

l'..i''
l
1 :1
lli.l
1

i1
1
1 1
1

390 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 391


Frorn this definition, it is obvious that if y is a facial direction, Hence, interchanging x and x\ the weak inequality holds also in
then sois ty for any scalar t. Now suppose C is convex and y 1 and the reverse direction, so equality holds. If x 1 - x is not a facial
2
y are both facial directions at sorne point x in C. By definition, direction at x\ then, by Lernma B.5, the set of facial directions at
x + ty 1 E C for 1td srnall (i = 1,2). Sin ce C is convex, x 1 is a proper subset of that at x; but since both are linear spaces,
by Lemrna B.4, the facial space at x 1 rnust have a lower dirnension
X + __!t2 y1 + __gt2 y2 E C than that at x.
We now consider faces formed when the convex hull of a set is
for [t1[, [t 2[ sufficiently srnall, so that x + t(y 1 + y2) E C for [t[ taken. A point in the convex hull of a set is spanned by a finite
sufficiently srnall, and therefore, y 1 + y 2 is a facial direction also. subset of the convex hui!. We show that the difference between the
point and any elernent of the spanning set is a facial direction in the
LEMMA 4. If C is convex and X E C, then the facial space at X in C convex hui!. In Figure B-3, x 1 - x and x 2 - x are facial directions
is a linear space.
at x in the convex hull of the illustrated set.
DEFINITION 14. The facial dimension of X in C, d(x f C), is the
dirnension of the facial space at x in C.

1
In Figure B-2, the facial dirnension of X in e is 1, while that of x 1
is O. x'
Suppose x and x 1 both belong to a convex set C and also suppose
that the rnovernent frorn x to x 1 lies on a face; that is, x 1 - x is a
facial direction at x in C. Then any facial direction at x 1 rnust also
be a facial direction at x; the converse willnot hold if x 1 is at the
edge of the face, as can be seen fforn Figure B-2.
Figure B-3
LEMMA 5. lf x and x 1 belong to the convex set C and x 1 - x is a
facial direction at X in C, then every facial direction at X 1 is also a
facial direction at x. LEMMA 7. If x E con S, then there is a finite subset T of S such that
T spans x and x' - x is a facial direction at x in con S for all x' E T.
Proof. Since x 1 - x is a facial direction at x, x 0 = x + t(x 1 - x)
Proof By T.B.7(b), there is a finite subset T of S anda function
E C for SOrne f < 0, SO that X = (J - a)x 0 + ax\ Where a =
a(x') defined on T such that
- t/(1 - t), and therefore, O < a < l. Let y be a facial direction
e
at x 1 ; then x 1 + ty E for 1t 1 sufficiently small. Then X + aty = L a(x') = 1,
(1 - a)x 0 + a(x 1 + ty) E C for all [t [ sufficiently srnall and therefore X;ET

for all [at [ sufficiently srnall. Hence, by definition, y is a facial a(x') ;:::: O all x' E T, ,:
direction at x. il'

LEMMA 6. If x and x 1 both belong to a convex set C and if x 1 - x


x = : a(x')x'. i',
,
X'ET
'i'
is a facial direction at x in C, then d(x 1 C) :<::; d(x C). The
f f
If we delete all elernents of T for which a(x') = O, obviously the sarne
equality holds if and only if x 1 - x is also a facial direction at x 1 Ir:
relations hold. Hence we can assurne a(x') > O for all x' E T. 11!
in C. Choose any fixed x" E T, and let ,!.1!

:
1
Proof The weak inequality follows frorn Lernrna B.5. If x 1 - x
is also a facial direction at xl, then so is x - x 1 = ( -l)(x 1 - x).
x 1 = (1 - t)x + tx" = tx" + (1 - t)
1
a(x')x'. '1:
,1
X E 1' !
11

,,
1:11

l'..i''
l
1 :1
lli.l
1

i1
1
------------------------~0/F
'!i'1
1

392 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 393


Let f3(x') 7~ (1 - t)o:(x') when x' =? x", f3(x") = (1 - t)o:(x") + t. is the closed interval <O,m), and con S1 is the interval <O,l). For

1
.1
il
Then each i, x 1 has facial dimension 1 in con S1 if O < x 1 < 1 and facial
'1
:
x1 =
X 1
ET
f3(x')x', dimension O if x 1 = O or l. If x is any real number between O and
m, it can be written in many ways as

X

1
E T
f3(x') = t + (1 - t) 'L;
X' ET
o:(x') = t + (1 - t).
X= X,
m

t= 1
Finally, since o:(x') > O, all x' E T, we can ensure f3(x') ;e: O, all
where O :::; x 1 :::; 1, but among these ways there is at least one for
x' E T, by making t sufficiently small. Hence x 1 E con T e con S
1 1
which x 1 is either O or 1 except, at most, for one value of i.
for such t. If we write x 1 = x + t(x" - x), we see, by D.B.13, that
Specifically, if x = r, an integer, then we can let x 1 = 1 (i = 1, ... , r),
x" - x is a facial direction at x in con S, and this for any x" E T.
x 1 = O (i = r + 1, ... , m), while if x is notan integer and r is the
We now state the first theorem that shows that, in one sense, the
largest integer less than x, let x 1 = 1 (i = 1, ... , r), x 1 = O (i = r +
vector sum of a large number of sets is approximately convex.
1, . .. , m - 1), Xm = x - r. Although in this case the result is
Consider any point in the convex lmll of the vector sum. By
obvious, we can also prove it by a method that generalizes. Among 1

Lemma B.2, the point can be written as a vector sum of points in the
the many solutions to the equations and inequalities ! l.
convex hulls ofthe individual sets. This representation is, in general, 1'
m 'i
not unique; it will be shown that the points can be chosen so that all
X= X 0:0:: X :0:: 1, [1
but a fixed number (equal to the dimensionality of the space) are i= 1
i:

actually in the individual sets and not merely in their convex hulls.
choose the one that minimizes the sum of the facial dimensions of
THEOREM 8. Let F be a finite family of compact sets, x 1 in con S 1 If this solution has more than one x 1 satisfying
O < x 1 < 1, suppose this holds for i = 1,2. Let x 1(t) = X1 + t,
x E con S. x 2 (t) = x 2 - t, x 1(t) = x 1 (i > 2). Increase t from O until either
SEF
x 1(t) reaches 1 or x 2(t) reaches O; that is, let t = min(I - x1>x2).
Then F can be divided into two subfami1ies, F 1 and F 2 , where F 1 has Note that
at most n members (where n is the dimensionality of the space) such m
that X(t) =X 0 :0:: X(t) :0:: l.
x E con S + S. i= 1
SE F S E F2
Further, the facial dimension of x 1(t) in con S 1 remains unchanged
Before proceeding to the general proof, we shall illustrate the for each i except for the one that reaches 1 orO, respectively, for which
theorem and the method of proof in a very simple case. Let the the facial dimension drops from 1 to O, in contradiction to the choice
space be the set of real numbers, therefore of dimension 1, and let of the x's. Hence the solution in question can have, at most, one
the family F consist of m sets, each of which consists of the numbers x 1 that is neither O nor l.
O and l. Call the sets S 1 , , Sm. Then
Proof. By Lemma B.2,
x = x(S),
SEF

consists of the integers O, ... , m, where x(S) E con S. Among all choices of x(S) satisfying these
m
conditions, choose the one that minimizes
con S1 d[x(S) 1 con S];
i= 1
SEF
------------------------~0/F
'!i'1
1

392 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 393


Let f3(x') 7~ (1 - t)o:(x') when x' =? x", f3(x") = (1 - t)o:(x") + t. is the closed interval <O,m), and con S1 is the interval <O,l). For

1
.1
il
Then each i, x 1 has facial dimension 1 in con S1 if O < x 1 < 1 and facial
'1
:
x1 =
X 1
ET
f3(x')x', dimension O if x 1 = O or l. If x is any real number between O and
m, it can be written in many ways as

X

1
E T
f3(x') = t + (1 - t) 'L;
X' ET
o:(x') = t + (1 - t).
X= X,
m

t= 1
Finally, since o:(x') > O, all x' E T, we can ensure f3(x') ;e: O, all
where O :::; x 1 :::; 1, but among these ways there is at least one for
x' E T, by making t sufficiently small. Hence x 1 E con T e con S
1 1
which x 1 is either O or 1 except, at most, for one value of i.
for such t. If we write x 1 = x + t(x" - x), we see, by D.B.13, that
Specifically, if x = r, an integer, then we can let x 1 = 1 (i = 1, ... , r),
x" - x is a facial direction at x in con S, and this for any x" E T.
x 1 = O (i = r + 1, ... , m), while if x is notan integer and r is the
We now state the first theorem that shows that, in one sense, the
largest integer less than x, let x 1 = 1 (i = 1, ... , r), x 1 = O (i = r +
vector sum of a large number of sets is approximately convex.
1, . .. , m - 1), Xm = x - r. Although in this case the result is
Consider any point in the convex lmll of the vector sum. By
obvious, we can also prove it by a method that generalizes. Among 1

Lemma B.2, the point can be written as a vector sum of points in the
the many solutions to the equations and inequalities ! l.
convex hulls ofthe individual sets. This representation is, in general, 1'
m 'i
not unique; it will be shown that the points can be chosen so that all
X= X 0:0:: X :0:: 1, [1
but a fixed number (equal to the dimensionality of the space) are i= 1
i:

actually in the individual sets and not merely in their convex hulls.
choose the one that minimizes the sum of the facial dimensions of
THEOREM 8. Let F be a finite family of compact sets, x 1 in con S 1 If this solution has more than one x 1 satisfying
O < x 1 < 1, suppose this holds for i = 1,2. Let x 1(t) = X1 + t,
x E con S. x 2 (t) = x 2 - t, x 1(t) = x 1 (i > 2). Increase t from O until either
SEF
x 1(t) reaches 1 or x 2(t) reaches O; that is, let t = min(I - x1>x2).
Then F can be divided into two subfami1ies, F 1 and F 2 , where F 1 has Note that
at most n members (where n is the dimensionality of the space) such m
that X(t) =X 0 :0:: X(t) :0:: l.
x E con S + S. i= 1
SE F S E F2
Further, the facial dimension of x 1(t) in con S 1 remains unchanged
Before proceeding to the general proof, we shall illustrate the for each i except for the one that reaches 1 orO, respectively, for which
theorem and the method of proof in a very simple case. Let the the facial dimension drops from 1 to O, in contradiction to the choice
space be the set of real numbers, therefore of dimension 1, and let of the x's. Hence the solution in question can have, at most, one
the family F consist of m sets, each of which consists of the numbers x 1 that is neither O nor l.
O and l. Call the sets S 1 , , Sm. Then
Proof. By Lemma B.2,
x = x(S),
SEF

consists of the integers O, ... , m, where x(S) E con S. Among all choices of x(S) satisfying these
m
conditions, choose the one that minimizes
con S1 d[x(S) 1 con S];
i= 1
SEF
T
1F
,.,
,,,
,,1'
;,
',

1 i 394 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 395


! ~ since the function to be minimized takes on only non-negative if x(t 1 S) E con S for all S E F 1 Let A = {t 1 t ;::: O, x(t 1 S) E
integer values, it must have a minimum. By Lemma B.7, we must con S for all S E F1 }. Obviously, A is a closed interval containing
have, for each S, a point x'(S) such that x'(S) E S and x'(S) - x(S) O. Furthermore, since x'(S) - x(S) is a facial direction at x(S) in
is a facial direction at x(S) in con S. Let F1 = {S x'(S) =!= x(S)}, 1 con S for each S, x(t 1 S) E con S for 1tc(S)I sufficiently small and,
F2 = {S 1 x'(S) = x(S)}. For S E F2, x(S) E S; hence therefore, for all 1t 1 sufficiently small, so that A contains a positive
value of t. Suppose A were unbounded. Since x'(S) - x(S) =!= O
x = x(S)
S e F
x(S) +
S e F2
E
S E F
con S +
S 6 F2
S for S E F1 , it follows that the range of x(t 1 S) as t vades over A is
unbounded also if c(S) =1= O, which must be true for at least one
=con 2 S+ S, S E F 1 . For tE A, x(t 1 S) E con S; since S is compact by hypoth-
F2 SeF Se
esis, so is con S, by Lemma B.3, a contradiction. Hence (3) can be
by Lemma B.2. written
It remains to show that F 1 has, at most, n members. Suppose it
had more. Then the vectors x'(S) - x(S), S E Fb would be 2 d[x(t
SEF
1 S) 1 con S] ;:::
Se F
d[x(S) 1 con S] for tE A, (4)
linearly dependent; that is, there would exist real numbers c(S), not
all O, such that and A is a closed bounded non-degnerate interval with lower
bound O.

SeF1
c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)] = O. Since x'(S) - x(S) is a facial direction at x(S) in con S, so is
c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)]t; by Lemma B.6,
For each S in Fb let
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] :::; d[x(S) 1 con S]
x(t 1 S) = x(S) + c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)]t.
for all S E F1 From (4),
By construction,
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] = d[x(S) 1 con S] for all S E F 1 if t E A.

SEF1
x(t S) =1
SEF1
x(S),
Again from Lemma B.6, it must be that x(t 1 S) - x(S) is a facial
so that direction at x(t 1 S). Then, by definition,

x = x(t 1 S) + x(S). x(t 1 S) + u[x(t 1 S) - x(S)] E con S


for lul sufficiently small if tE A. In particular, take u > O. Since
SEF SEF2

Hence, if x(t S) E con S, all S E Fb it follows from the choice of


1
x(t 1 S) + u[x(t 1 S) - x(S)] = x(S) + c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)](l + u)t,
x(S) as minimizing it follows that if tE A, so does (1 + u)t for someu > O. Thus there
is no largest positive element of A, in contradiction to its being a
d[x(S)
SeF
1 con S]
closed bounded non-degenerate interval. It has been shown, there-
fore, that the elements of F 1 cannot be linearly dependent and
that therefore there are no more than n of them.

SeF
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] +
SeJ? 2
d[x(S) 1 con S] ;:::
SeF
d[x(S) 1 con S], We now proceed to state the fundamental result of Shapley and
Folkman, which gives a bound on the degree to which the vector
or sum of a large number of uniformly bounded sets can differ from its "'


SEF
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] ;:::
SeF
d[x(S) 1 con S] (3)
convex hull. We define the radius of any compact setas that of the
smallest sphere that includes it. ,
1111
ll

lti
ill!
11
111
'11
:h

1'
::"'
T
1F
,.,
,,,
,,1'
;,
',

1 i 394 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 395


! ~ since the function to be minimized takes on only non-negative if x(t 1 S) E con S for all S E F 1 Let A = {t 1 t ;::: O, x(t 1 S) E
integer values, it must have a minimum. By Lemma B.7, we must con S for all S E F1 }. Obviously, A is a closed interval containing
have, for each S, a point x'(S) such that x'(S) E S and x'(S) - x(S) O. Furthermore, since x'(S) - x(S) is a facial direction at x(S) in
is a facial direction at x(S) in con S. Let F1 = {S x'(S) =!= x(S)}, 1 con S for each S, x(t 1 S) E con S for 1tc(S)I sufficiently small and,
F2 = {S 1 x'(S) = x(S)}. For S E F2, x(S) E S; hence therefore, for all 1t 1 sufficiently small, so that A contains a positive
value of t. Suppose A were unbounded. Since x'(S) - x(S) =!= O
x = x(S)
S e F
x(S) +
S e F2
E
S E F
con S +
S 6 F2
S for S E F1 , it follows that the range of x(t 1 S) as t vades over A is
unbounded also if c(S) =1= O, which must be true for at least one
=con 2 S+ S, S E F 1 . For tE A, x(t 1 S) E con S; since S is compact by hypoth-
F2 SeF Se
esis, so is con S, by Lemma B.3, a contradiction. Hence (3) can be
by Lemma B.2. written
It remains to show that F 1 has, at most, n members. Suppose it
had more. Then the vectors x'(S) - x(S), S E Fb would be 2 d[x(t
SEF
1 S) 1 con S] ;:::
Se F
d[x(S) 1 con S] for tE A, (4)
linearly dependent; that is, there would exist real numbers c(S), not
all O, such that and A is a closed bounded non-degnerate interval with lower
bound O.

SeF1
c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)] = O. Since x'(S) - x(S) is a facial direction at x(S) in con S, so is
c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)]t; by Lemma B.6,
For each S in Fb let
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] :::; d[x(S) 1 con S]
x(t 1 S) = x(S) + c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)]t.
for all S E F1 From (4),
By construction,
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] = d[x(S) 1 con S] for all S E F 1 if t E A.

SEF1
x(t S) =1
SEF1
x(S),
Again from Lemma B.6, it must be that x(t 1 S) - x(S) is a facial
so that direction at x(t 1 S). Then, by definition,

x = x(t 1 S) + x(S). x(t 1 S) + u[x(t 1 S) - x(S)] E con S


for lul sufficiently small if tE A. In particular, take u > O. Since
SEF SEF2

Hence, if x(t S) E con S, all S E Fb it follows from the choice of


1
x(t 1 S) + u[x(t 1 S) - x(S)] = x(S) + c(S)[x'(S) - x(S)](l + u)t,
x(S) as minimizing it follows that if tE A, so does (1 + u)t for someu > O. Thus there
is no largest positive element of A, in contradiction to its being a
d[x(S)
SeF
1 con S]
closed bounded non-degenerate interval. It has been shown, there-
fore, that the elements of F 1 cannot be linearly dependent and
that therefore there are no more than n of them.

SeF
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] +
SeJ? 2
d[x(S) 1 con S] ;:::
SeF
d[x(S) 1 con S], We now proceed to state the fundamental result of Shapley and
Folkman, which gives a bound on the degree to which the vector
or sum of a large number of uniformly bounded sets can differ from its "'


SEF
d[x(t 1 S) 1 con S] ;:::
SeF
d[x(S) 1 con S] (3)
convex hull. We define the radius of any compact setas that of the
smallest sphere that includes it. ,
1111
ll

lti
ill!
11
111
'11
:h

1'
::"'
\1
' T 1

396 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 397

DEFINITION 15. The radius of a cornpact set is defined by It rernains to prove (5); we proceed byinduction on m, the nurnber
of rnernbers ofF. First, suppose m = l. Then
rad(S) = rnin rnaxlx- Yl
X

THEOREM 9 (Shapley-Folkrnan). Let F be a farnily (not necessarily


YES
X= L a(y)y,
ye T
finite) of cornpact sets S such that, for sorne nurnber L, rad(S) :S: L
for sorne finite T e S and sorne function a(y) with a(y) ~ O, all y,
for all S E F. Then
and
for any finite subfarnily F' e F and any x E con L S,
SeF'
L
a(y) = l.
yeT
there is a y E L
SeF'
S such that lx - Yl :S: LVn,
Let x* rninirnize
where n is the dirnensionality of the space. rnaxlx- y,
y eS ''
Proof We will establish: so that
'
1

For any finite farnily F of cornpact sets and any


rad(S) = rnaxlx* - Yl
x E con S, there exists y E S such that YES
SeF SEF
lx - Yl :S:2
SeF
2: [rad(S)]2. (5) O= x - X = x - 2 a(y)y = 2 a(y)(x -
yeT yeT
y).

Suppose (5) has been established. Let F' be any finite subfarnily Take the inner product of both sides with x - x*.
ofF satisfying the hypotheses of the theorern. Let m be the nurnber
of rnernbers ofF'. If m :S: n, then frorn (5), O= 2 a(y)(x -
yeT
x*)(x - y).

lx- YI 2
.:S:
SeF'
2 [rad(S)] 2 :S: 2 V= mV :S: nV.
SEF'
It is elearly irnpossible that (x - x*)(x - y) > O for all y m T.
Therefore, (x - x*)(x - y) :S: O for sorne y E S. But
Suppose then m > n. By T.B.8, x = x1 + x2, where
[rad(S)J2 ~ lx* - Yl 2 = l(x - x*) - (x - y)l 2
1
x E con 2S x 2
E 2 S, = lx - Yl 2 + lx - x*l 2 - 2(x - x*)(x - y) ~ lx - yl 2 ,
SeFi SeF~
as was to be proved.
F~ and F~ .constitute a partition of F' into two disjoint subfarnilies
and F~ has, at rnost, n elernents. Then Now suppose that (5) holds for m; we seek to prove it when F has
+ 1 rnernbers. Let S' be any set in the farnily F, and let F' be
x- x 2 Econ 2 S; m
the family of rernaining rnernbers of which there are m. Then, if
SeFi

since F~ has, at rnost, n elernents, .it follows frorn what has already x E con 2S = con 2 S + con S'
been established that there exists SeF SeF

y 1E S
(by Lernrna B.2), we can write x = x 1 + x 2 , where
SeFi
x 1 E con 2 S x 2 E con S'.
such that lx - x 2 - y 1 1 :S: LVn. But if y = y 1 + x2 , then $EF'

By the induction hypothesis, we can find


YE 2 S,

and the theorern is established.


SeF'
ylE 2S
SeF'
,

''
\1
' T 1

396 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 397

DEFINITION 15. The radius of a cornpact set is defined by It rernains to prove (5); we proceed byinduction on m, the nurnber
of rnernbers ofF. First, suppose m = l. Then
rad(S) = rnin rnaxlx- Yl
X

THEOREM 9 (Shapley-Folkrnan). Let F be a farnily (not necessarily


YES
X= L a(y)y,
ye T
finite) of cornpact sets S such that, for sorne nurnber L, rad(S) :S: L
for sorne finite T e S and sorne function a(y) with a(y) ~ O, all y,
for all S E F. Then
and
for any finite subfarnily F' e F and any x E con L S,
SeF'
L
a(y) = l.
yeT
there is a y E L
SeF'
S such that lx - Yl :S: LVn,
Let x* rninirnize
where n is the dirnensionality of the space. rnaxlx- y,
y eS ''
Proof We will establish: so that
'
1

For any finite farnily F of cornpact sets and any


rad(S) = rnaxlx* - Yl
x E con S, there exists y E S such that YES
SeF SEF
lx - Yl :S:2
SeF
2: [rad(S)]2. (5) O= x - X = x - 2 a(y)y = 2 a(y)(x -
yeT yeT
y).

Suppose (5) has been established. Let F' be any finite subfarnily Take the inner product of both sides with x - x*.
ofF satisfying the hypotheses of the theorern. Let m be the nurnber
of rnernbers ofF'. If m :S: n, then frorn (5), O= 2 a(y)(x -
yeT
x*)(x - y).

lx- YI 2
.:S:
SeF'
2 [rad(S)] 2 :S: 2 V= mV :S: nV.
SEF'
It is elearly irnpossible that (x - x*)(x - y) > O for all y m T.
Therefore, (x - x*)(x - y) :S: O for sorne y E S. But
Suppose then m > n. By T.B.8, x = x1 + x2, where
[rad(S)J2 ~ lx* - Yl 2 = l(x - x*) - (x - y)l 2
1
x E con 2S x 2
E 2 S, = lx - Yl 2 + lx - x*l 2 - 2(x - x*)(x - y) ~ lx - yl 2 ,
SeFi SeF~
as was to be proved.
F~ and F~ .constitute a partition of F' into two disjoint subfarnilies
and F~ has, at rnost, n elernents. Then Now suppose that (5) holds for m; we seek to prove it when F has
+ 1 rnernbers. Let S' be any set in the farnily F, and let F' be
x- x 2 Econ 2 S; m
the family of rernaining rnernbers of which there are m. Then, if
SeFi

since F~ has, at rnost, n elernents, .it follows frorn what has already x E con 2S = con 2 S + con S'
been established that there exists SeF SeF

y 1E S
(by Lernrna B.2), we can write x = x 1 + x 2 , where
SeFi
x 1 E con 2 S x 2 E con S'.
such that lx - x 2 - y 1 1 :S: LVn. But if y = y 1 + x2 , then $EF'

By the induction hypothesis, we can find


YE 2 S,

and the theorern is established.


SeF'
ylE 2S
SeF'
,

''
1

1
1

1 398 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


1 CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 399
such that Important as this theorem is, it can be usefully strengthened. For
lxl - yll2 ~ 2
SeF'
[rad(S)]2. example, consider the case in which all the sets in the family F are
0
themselves convex. Then the vector sum is convex and coincides
Now choose z to minimize lx - y 1 - zl for z E con S'. Since
with its convex hull, so that the upper bound given above is too
S' is compact, sois con S', by Lemma B.3, so the mnimum exists.
weak. Starr [1969, p. 37] extended the Shapley-Folkman theorem
Since x 2 E con S', we have, in particular,
by measuring the non-convexity of the sets in F. For each point
lx _ yl _ zo12 ~ lx _ yl _ x212 = lxl _ yll2 in the convex hull of a set S, we can find all the finite subsets of S
~ 2
SeF'
[rad(S)] 2. (6) that span it and choose among them the one having the smallest
radius (which will be zero if the point belongs toS). The mnimum
For any z E con S', tz + (1 - t)z 0 E con S' forO < t ~ l. Then,, radius of spanning set, in general, will vary as x vares over con S;
the maximum attained is a measure of the non-convexity of the set,
lx- yl - zol2 ~ lx- yl - [tz + (1 - t)zoJI2
sin ce it will certainly be zero if every point of the convex hull belongs
= lx - yl - zo - t(z - zo)l2
to S itself.
= lx - y 1 - z 0 l2 - 2t(x - y 1 - z 0 )(z - z 0 )
+ t21z - zol2 DEFINITION 16. The inner radius of S is defined by
1 0 0 1 0 2
Add 2t(x - y - z )(z - z ) - lx - y - z l to both sides, divide r(S) = sup inf rad(T).
xe con S T spans x
by 2t (with t > 0), and then let t approach O. TeS
(x - y 1 - z 0)(z - z 0 ) ~ O for all z E con S'. (7) THEOREM 10 (Starr). Let F be a family (not necessarily finite) of
According to Lemma B.7, we can find a finite subset T of S' that compact sets S such that, for sorne number L, r(S) ~ L for all S E F.
spans z 0 , since z 0 E con S'. Since z 0 E con T, it follows by (5) for Then for every finite subfamily F' and any ,
m = 1 that we can choose y 2 E T e S' such that
X E COn 2 S,
IY 2 - z 0 l2 ~ [rad(T)] 2 ~ [rad(S')J2. (8) SE F'

2 0
Since it is also true, by Lemma B.7, that y - z is a facial direction there is a
at z 0 in con S', z 0 + t(y 2 - z 0 ) E con S' for ltl sufficiently small. If YE LS
SeF'
we substitute for z in (7), we see that
t(x - y 1 - z0 )(y 2 - z0 ) .~ O such that lx - Yl ~ LV, where n is the dimensionality of the
space.
for all 1t 1 sufficiently small. Since t can be of either sign, we must
have Proof If
(x - yl - zo)(y2 - zo) = O. (9) x E con L
SEF'
S,
Let y= y + y ; then
1 2
then
YE 2 S.
SEF
x = L x(S),
SeF'
From (6), (8), and (9), where x(S) E con S. By D.B.16, we canrfind T(S) e S, where T(S)
lx - Yl2 = lx - yl - y212 = l(x - yl - zo) - (y2 - zo)l2 spans x(S) and rad[T(S)] ~ r(S) + E, for any given E > O. Then
= lx _ yl _ zo12 _ 2(x _ yl _ zo)(y2 _ zo) + IY2 _ zol2 x(S) E con T(S), and
~ 2 [rad(S)] 2.
SEF
x E L con T(S) = con 2 T(S).
SeF' SEF'
1

1
1

1 398 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


1 CONVEX ANO RELATED SETS 399
such that Important as this theorem is, it can be usefully strengthened. For
lxl - yll2 ~ 2
SeF'
[rad(S)]2. example, consider the case in which all the sets in the family F are
0
themselves convex. Then the vector sum is convex and coincides
Now choose z to minimize lx - y 1 - zl for z E con S'. Since
with its convex hull, so that the upper bound given above is too
S' is compact, sois con S', by Lemma B.3, so the mnimum exists.
weak. Starr [1969, p. 37] extended the Shapley-Folkman theorem
Since x 2 E con S', we have, in particular,
by measuring the non-convexity of the sets in F. For each point
lx _ yl _ zo12 ~ lx _ yl _ x212 = lxl _ yll2 in the convex hull of a set S, we can find all the finite subsets of S
~ 2
SeF'
[rad(S)] 2. (6) that span it and choose among them the one having the smallest
radius (which will be zero if the point belongs toS). The mnimum
For any z E con S', tz + (1 - t)z 0 E con S' forO < t ~ l. Then,, radius of spanning set, in general, will vary as x vares over con S;
the maximum attained is a measure of the non-convexity of the set,
lx- yl - zol2 ~ lx- yl - [tz + (1 - t)zoJI2
sin ce it will certainly be zero if every point of the convex hull belongs
= lx - yl - zo - t(z - zo)l2
to S itself.
= lx - y 1 - z 0 l2 - 2t(x - y 1 - z 0 )(z - z 0 )
+ t21z - zol2 DEFINITION 16. The inner radius of S is defined by
1 0 0 1 0 2
Add 2t(x - y - z )(z - z ) - lx - y - z l to both sides, divide r(S) = sup inf rad(T).
xe con S T spans x
by 2t (with t > 0), and then let t approach O. TeS
(x - y 1 - z 0)(z - z 0 ) ~ O for all z E con S'. (7) THEOREM 10 (Starr). Let F be a family (not necessarily finite) of
According to Lemma B.7, we can find a finite subset T of S' that compact sets S such that, for sorne number L, r(S) ~ L for all S E F.
spans z 0 , since z 0 E con S'. Since z 0 E con T, it follows by (5) for Then for every finite subfamily F' and any ,
m = 1 that we can choose y 2 E T e S' such that
X E COn 2 S,
IY 2 - z 0 l2 ~ [rad(T)] 2 ~ [rad(S')J2. (8) SE F'

2 0
Since it is also true, by Lemma B.7, that y - z is a facial direction there is a
at z 0 in con S', z 0 + t(y 2 - z 0 ) E con S' for ltl sufficiently small. If YE LS
SeF'
we substitute for z in (7), we see that
t(x - y 1 - z0 )(y 2 - z0 ) .~ O such that lx - Yl ~ LV, where n is the dimensionality of the
space.
for all 1t 1 sufficiently small. Since t can be of either sign, we must
have Proof If
(x - yl - zo)(y2 - zo) = O. (9) x E con L
SEF'
S,
Let y= y + y ; then
1 2
then
YE 2 S.
SEF
x = L x(S),
SeF'
From (6), (8), and (9), where x(S) E con S. By D.B.16, we canrfind T(S) e S, where T(S)
lx - Yl2 = lx - yl - y212 = l(x - yl - zo) - (y2 - zo)l2 spans x(S) and rad[T(S)] ~ r(S) + E, for any given E > O. Then
= lx _ yl _ zo12 _ 2(x _ yl _ zo)(y2 _ zo) + IY2 _ zol2 x(S) E con T(S), and
~ 2 [rad(S)] 2.
SEF
x E L con T(S) = con 2 T(S).
SeF' SEF'
T 1'

400 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 401
Consider the family of all finite subsets T of any S in F for which DEFINITION 19. S is connected if it has no components.
rad(T) :::; L + E. The family of sets T(S) for S E F' is certainly a
finite subfamily of this family, and we can use T.B.9. Then there LEMMA 8. S is connected if and only if it is not the union of two or
is a point, more, but finitely many disjoint non-null sets each closed in S.

y E 2
SeF'
T(S), Proof Suppose S is not connected. Then it has a component
C; by D.B.18, S is the union of C and S"' C, both non-null and
closed in S. Conversely, suppose S is the union of C, ... , Cm,
such thatlx - Yl :S: (L + E)Vn. Note that
mutually disjoint and each non-null and closed in S, with m > l.
YE 2 S. Then S "' C1 is the union of C2 , . . . , Cm and, therefore, is non-null
SEF' and el o sed in S, sin ce the union of finitely many el o sed sets is el o sed.
The chosen y may vary with E, but since it lies in a cmpact set, Then C1 is a component of S, which therefore is not connected.
by choosing a suitable sequence of E's approaching O, we can Another rendering of the intuitive concept of connectedness,
approach a point, appropriate to vector spaces, is that any two points in the set can be
joined by a cbntinuous path or are lying entirely in the set.
YE 2
SEF
S,
DEFINITION 20. S is arcwise connected if, for every x 0 , x 1 E S, there
such that lx - Yl :::: Lv. is a continuous vector-valued function, x(t), defined for O :::; t :::; 1,
such that x(O) = x 0 , x(l) = xl, and x(t) E S, all t, O ::;; t :::; l.

5. The Connectedness of Convex Sets THEOREM 11. Every arcwise connected set is connected.
Proof Suppose S arcwise connected, but not connected. Let C
We shall prove here that a closed convex set cannot be expressed
be any component. Choose x 0 E e, x 1 E S "' e, and Jet x(t) be the
as the union oftwo or more (but finitely many) closed sets; this result
are joining them, as defined in D.B.20. Let
was used in the proof of T.l1.5. To accord with the formulations of
textbooks in analysis, we will state definitions and results slightly C' = {t 1 x(t) E C'} C" = {t 1 x(t) E S "' C}. '',
,
more generally than actually employed. Sorne of these definitions 1

Since C and S "' C are closed in S and x(t) is continuous, C' and
have found other uses in mathematical economics.
C" are disjoint closed sets whose union is the unit interval. By
DEFINITION 17. The set e is closed in the set S if any limit point construction, O E C', 1 E C"; hence neither is null. Since C" is
of C that is in S is also in C. closed and bounded from below, it must have a minimum element,
!, which must be positive since O E C'. Then tE C' for all t < !, by
Note that if C is closed in the usual sense, that is, in its natural definition of a mnimum; but this statement implies that ! is a limit
space, then C is closed in S for any S. We actually need only this point of C', a contradiction to either the disjointness of C' and C"
case. or the closedness of C'.
DEFINITION 18. lf e is a non-null proper subset of S and both e Corol!ary 11. No convex set is the union of two or more, but
and S "' C are closed in S, then e is a component of S. finitely many disjoint non-null closed sets.
Intuitively, C is isolated from the rest of S, for no sequence of Proof Every pair of points in a convex set is joined in the set
points in S ,..., e can approach a point in e, and no sequence of by the !in e segment defined by them; hence every convex set is
points of e can approach a point in S "' C. Of course, if C is a arcwise connected and, therefore, connected so that Lemma B.8
component, so is S "' C. applies.
T 1'

400 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS CONVEX AND RELATED SETS 401
Consider the family of all finite subsets T of any S in F for which DEFINITION 19. S is connected if it has no components.
rad(T) :::; L + E. The family of sets T(S) for S E F' is certainly a
finite subfamily of this family, and we can use T.B.9. Then there LEMMA 8. S is connected if and only if it is not the union of two or
is a point, more, but finitely many disjoint non-null sets each closed in S.

y E 2
SeF'
T(S), Proof Suppose S is not connected. Then it has a component
C; by D.B.18, S is the union of C and S"' C, both non-null and
closed in S. Conversely, suppose S is the union of C, ... , Cm,
such thatlx - Yl :S: (L + E)Vn. Note that
mutually disjoint and each non-null and closed in S, with m > l.
YE 2 S. Then S "' C1 is the union of C2 , . . . , Cm and, therefore, is non-null
SEF' and el o sed in S, sin ce the union of finitely many el o sed sets is el o sed.
The chosen y may vary with E, but since it lies in a cmpact set, Then C1 is a component of S, which therefore is not connected.
by choosing a suitable sequence of E's approaching O, we can Another rendering of the intuitive concept of connectedness,
approach a point, appropriate to vector spaces, is that any two points in the set can be
joined by a cbntinuous path or are lying entirely in the set.
YE 2
SEF
S,
DEFINITION 20. S is arcwise connected if, for every x 0 , x 1 E S, there
such that lx - Yl :::: Lv. is a continuous vector-valued function, x(t), defined for O :::; t :::; 1,
such that x(O) = x 0 , x(l) = xl, and x(t) E S, all t, O ::;; t :::; l.

5. The Connectedness of Convex Sets THEOREM 11. Every arcwise connected set is connected.
Proof Suppose S arcwise connected, but not connected. Let C
We shall prove here that a closed convex set cannot be expressed
be any component. Choose x 0 E e, x 1 E S "' e, and Jet x(t) be the
as the union oftwo or more (but finitely many) closed sets; this result
are joining them, as defined in D.B.20. Let
was used in the proof of T.l1.5. To accord with the formulations of
textbooks in analysis, we will state definitions and results slightly C' = {t 1 x(t) E C'} C" = {t 1 x(t) E S "' C}. '',
,
more generally than actually employed. Sorne of these definitions 1

Since C and S "' C are closed in S and x(t) is continuous, C' and
have found other uses in mathematical economics.
C" are disjoint closed sets whose union is the unit interval. By
DEFINITION 17. The set e is closed in the set S if any limit point construction, O E C', 1 E C"; hence neither is null. Since C" is
of C that is in S is also in C. closed and bounded from below, it must have a minimum element,
!, which must be positive since O E C'. Then tE C' for all t < !, by
Note that if C is closed in the usual sense, that is, in its natural definition of a mnimum; but this statement implies that ! is a limit
space, then C is closed in S for any S. We actually need only this point of C', a contradiction to either the disjointness of C' and C"
case. or the closedness of C'.
DEFINITION 18. lf e is a non-null proper subset of S and both e Corol!ary 11. No convex set is the union of two or more, but
and S "' C are closed in S, then e is a component of S. finitely many disjoint non-null closed sets.
Intuitively, C is isolated from the rest of S, for no sequence of Proof Every pair of points in a convex set is joined in the set
points in S ,..., e can approach a point in e, and no sequence of by the !in e segment defined by them; hence every convex set is
points of e can approach a point in S "' C. Of course, if C is a arcwise connected and, therefore, connected so that Lemma B.8
component, so is S "' C. applies.
i ,'

(
1
Appendix C FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 403

DEFINITION l. A simplex is the convex hull of a finite set of linearly


FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND independent vectors.
RELATED COMBINATORIAL A particular simplex has been used repeatedly in Chapters 2-5:
ALGORITHMS
DEFINITION 2. The fundamental simplex in n space is the set of n
vectors,
Sn = {x j X ~ 0, i
1=1
X1 = 1}
It is e~sy to verify that Sn is the convex hull of the unit n vectors
e1 (i = 1, ... , n), where e1 is a vector with 1 in the ith place and O
elsewhere.
The basic fixed-point theorem for the fundamental simplex is
l. Preliminary Remarks
THEOREM 1 (Brouwer's Fixed-Point Theorem). If f(x) is a con-
A basic role in the proofs of the existence theorems in competitive tinuous mapping of the fundamental simplex, Sn, into itself, then
equilibrium has been played by fixed-point theorems. In each case, there exists x* E Sn such that f(x*) = x*.
there is sorne kind of continuous mapping of a set into itself, and the
aim is to demonstrate that at least one point of the set remains Proofs of this theorem can be found in many books on topology.
invariant under the mapping. For our purposes, it suffices to con- It is possible to give proofs that do not depend on other topological
fine attention to domains that are subsets of finite-dimensional vector theorems; for excellent self-contained presentations see Tompkins
spaces. [1964] or Burger [1963, Appendix]. In the following sections,
The nature of the domain over which the mapping is defined is however, we presenta new theory, dueto Scarf [1967; a, b, e], of a
crucial to the validity of a fixed-point theorem. Thus, if w~ consider general combinatoria! algorithm that yields not only a proof of
the set defined by the circumference of a circle, a 45 rotation is a Brouwer's theorem, but a method of computing the fixed point, at "1
"!
continuous transformation that has no fixed point; on the other least to any desired degree of approximation. The algorithm
hand, if we consider the entire circle, interior and circumference, actually does a great deal more; it proves the more general Kakutani
such a rotation leaves the center invariant. Though more general fixed-point theorem (see Section B.4), which, as we have seen, is
theorems are known, it will suffice to assume the domain to be a essential to provingthe existence of equilibrium in the general model
convex set, a condition that eliminates the first counter-example. of Chapters 3-5, and it enables us to calcula te the core in market and
It is obviously necessary also to restrict attention to sets that are more general games. This appendix is based on the exposition in
el osed and bounded. Thus, map the open interval, (0, 1), into itself Hansen and Scarf [1969]; see also Kuhn [1968], who has related
by moving each point halfway to the upper boundary, that is, Scarf's theory to earlier proofs of fixed-point theorems.
mapping x into (x + 1)/2. This mapping has no fixed point in the First, since the following account is fairly difficult, we shall
open interval; on the other hand, if it is closed by adding the end- discuss the method somewhat intuitively befare working it precisely.
points, then 1 is a fixed point. Boundedness is also essential: The We shall need sorne well-known results from the theorem on linear
mapping x into x + 1 maps the entire realline into itself, but has no programming so we recapitulate.
fixed point. Let Y be an m-element set of n-dimensional vectors, where m > n
We thus restrict ourselves to mappings of compact convex sets and Y is taken to include the n vectors e1 If b ~ O is any given
11

into themselves. The basic theory can be worked out for a special vector, we are interested in the fundamental solution of
case, in which the domain is a simplex, and then easily extended to
the general case of a compact convex set.
L yw(y)
YE Y.
= b w(y) ~ O. (1)
11'

402
i ,'

(
1
Appendix C FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 403

DEFINITION l. A simplex is the convex hull of a finite set of linearly


FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND independent vectors.
RELATED COMBINATORIAL A particular simplex has been used repeatedly in Chapters 2-5:
ALGORITHMS
DEFINITION 2. The fundamental simplex in n space is the set of n
vectors,
Sn = {x j X ~ 0, i
1=1
X1 = 1}
It is e~sy to verify that Sn is the convex hull of the unit n vectors
e1 (i = 1, ... , n), where e1 is a vector with 1 in the ith place and O
elsewhere.
The basic fixed-point theorem for the fundamental simplex is
l. Preliminary Remarks
THEOREM 1 (Brouwer's Fixed-Point Theorem). If f(x) is a con-
A basic role in the proofs of the existence theorems in competitive tinuous mapping of the fundamental simplex, Sn, into itself, then
equilibrium has been played by fixed-point theorems. In each case, there exists x* E Sn such that f(x*) = x*.
there is sorne kind of continuous mapping of a set into itself, and the
aim is to demonstrate that at least one point of the set remains Proofs of this theorem can be found in many books on topology.
invariant under the mapping. For our purposes, it suffices to con- It is possible to give proofs that do not depend on other topological
fine attention to domains that are subsets of finite-dimensional vector theorems; for excellent self-contained presentations see Tompkins
spaces. [1964] or Burger [1963, Appendix]. In the following sections,
The nature of the domain over which the mapping is defined is however, we presenta new theory, dueto Scarf [1967; a, b, e], of a
crucial to the validity of a fixed-point theorem. Thus, if w~ consider general combinatoria! algorithm that yields not only a proof of
the set defined by the circumference of a circle, a 45 rotation is a Brouwer's theorem, but a method of computing the fixed point, at "1
"!
continuous transformation that has no fixed point; on the other least to any desired degree of approximation. The algorithm
hand, if we consider the entire circle, interior and circumference, actually does a great deal more; it proves the more general Kakutani
such a rotation leaves the center invariant. Though more general fixed-point theorem (see Section B.4), which, as we have seen, is
theorems are known, it will suffice to assume the domain to be a essential to provingthe existence of equilibrium in the general model
convex set, a condition that eliminates the first counter-example. of Chapters 3-5, and it enables us to calcula te the core in market and
It is obviously necessary also to restrict attention to sets that are more general games. This appendix is based on the exposition in
el osed and bounded. Thus, map the open interval, (0, 1), into itself Hansen and Scarf [1969]; see also Kuhn [1968], who has related
by moving each point halfway to the upper boundary, that is, Scarf's theory to earlier proofs of fixed-point theorems.
mapping x into (x + 1)/2. This mapping has no fixed point in the First, since the following account is fairly difficult, we shall
open interval; on the other hand, if it is closed by adding the end- discuss the method somewhat intuitively befare working it precisely.
points, then 1 is a fixed point. Boundedness is also essential: The We shall need sorne well-known results from the theorem on linear
mapping x into x + 1 maps the entire realline into itself, but has no programming so we recapitulate.
fixed point. Let Y be an m-element set of n-dimensional vectors, where m > n
We thus restrict ourselves to mappings of compact convex sets and Y is taken to include the n vectors e1 If b ~ O is any given
11

into themselves. The basic theory can be worked out for a special vector, we are interested in the fundamental solution of
case, in which the domain is a simplex, and then easily extended to
the general case of a compact convex set.
L yw(y)
YE Y.
= b w(y) ~ O. (1)
11'

402
1 r
'
;
i
,i
404 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 405 ,,1

(a) In Y there is at least one subset, B, (a basis) of n linearly w1 is lexicographically greater than the vector w2 if w} > wy when
independent vectors such that (1) holds with w(y) = O for y E Y "' B. j = min{i J w!- # wt}. We write this as w1 > L w 2 .
To see this, let B = !, the unit matrix. Now let w(y) be (n + !)-dimensional with the coordinates in-
(b) Suppose y' E Y"' B for sorne basis B. We ask whether there dexed (0, ... , n), and consider the equation and inequalities:
is anothr basis, B', that includes y' and all but one element of B
such that (1) can be satisfied with w(y) = O, all y E Y"' B'.
yw(y) = (b,J),
yeB
w(y) >LO all y E B, (3)
Note that B "' {y"} = B' "' {y'}, where y" is the element in B"' B'.
where Bis a basis. If (3) can be satisfied, we say that Bis a feasible
DEFINITION 3. B' is said to be the insertion of y' in B if B and B' are basis and note that the solution of (3) contains as the coordinate
both feasible bases for (1) and B' "' B = {y'}. labeled "O" the solution to problem (!).
Now suppose that y' E Y "' B and that there is a new feasible
By the definition of B there are numbers r(y) so that
basis B' where B "' {y"} = B' "' {y'}. Then there is a vector v such
y'= yr(y).
yeB
(2) that

Let 8 ;:::: O be a scalar and write (1) as


yw(y) -
yeB
y'v + y'v = y[w(y) -
YEB
vr(y)] + yv = (b,J) (3')

yw(y) -
y eB
By' + By' = b. (1') and
w(y")
V=--
Substitute from (2) into (1'): r(y")

y[w(y) -
yeB
Br(y)] + By' = b. (1") Certainly v >LO. So we need show only that y".is the only element
removed from B, that is, that
Let w(y,B) = w(y) - Br(y) for y E B, = 8 for y= y', and =O other- min w(y)
wise. yeB r(y)
r(y)>O
Suppose r(y) .::; O, all y E B. Then (1) would be satisfied for 8
arbitrarily Iarge with w(y) = w(y,B). We exclude this possibility by is unique.
supposing that the set of solutions of (1) is bounded so that r(y) > O If not, then w(y") = [r(y")]/[r(y 1)]w(y 1), for y 1 1= y". Let W be
sorne y E B. Let the n x n matrix, the rows of which are the n-dimensional vectors
0
w(y) formed from w(y) by deleting the first element. Let [y]s be
B* - min w(y) - w(y") the matrix formed for y E B. Then, by (3), [y]s W = J. Post-
- y~B r(y) - r(y")
r(y)>O multiply both sides of the equation by the vector k and note Wk = O
lf this minimum is unique with w(y) > O, then setting 8 = 8* in (1") implies k = O, so W is non-singular. Then it is impossible for two
gives us a new solution of (1): rows, 0 w(y"), 0 w(y 1 ) of W to be proportional and so the minimum
must be unique.
yw'(y) =
yEB
b w'(y) = w(y) - B*r(y) The Scarf algorithm requires us to consider another set, which for
the moment we write as Z, and, also for the moment, take to have
y E B, w(y') = 8* as its elements n-dimensional vectors z. In Z we are interested in
If the minimum is not unique and/or w(y) = O, there is said to be certain subsets with the property that all of its elements are "el ose"
degeneracy. to each other. Such a set will be called a primitive set of Z. We
(e) We deal with degeneracy in the following way (see Dantzig shall consider a one-to-one mapping from subsets of Z to subsets
[1951, pp. 365-367]; Charnes [1952]). Let us say that the vector of Y.
1 r
'
;
i
,i
404 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 405 ,,1

(a) In Y there is at least one subset, B, (a basis) of n linearly w1 is lexicographically greater than the vector w2 if w} > wy when
independent vectors such that (1) holds with w(y) = O for y E Y "' B. j = min{i J w!- # wt}. We write this as w1 > L w 2 .
To see this, let B = !, the unit matrix. Now let w(y) be (n + !)-dimensional with the coordinates in-
(b) Suppose y' E Y"' B for sorne basis B. We ask whether there dexed (0, ... , n), and consider the equation and inequalities:
is anothr basis, B', that includes y' and all but one element of B
such that (1) can be satisfied with w(y) = O, all y E Y"' B'.
yw(y) = (b,J),
yeB
w(y) >LO all y E B, (3)
Note that B "' {y"} = B' "' {y'}, where y" is the element in B"' B'.
where Bis a basis. If (3) can be satisfied, we say that Bis a feasible
DEFINITION 3. B' is said to be the insertion of y' in B if B and B' are basis and note that the solution of (3) contains as the coordinate
both feasible bases for (1) and B' "' B = {y'}. labeled "O" the solution to problem (!).
Now suppose that y' E Y "' B and that there is a new feasible
By the definition of B there are numbers r(y) so that
basis B' where B "' {y"} = B' "' {y'}. Then there is a vector v such
y'= yr(y).
yeB
(2) that

Let 8 ;:::: O be a scalar and write (1) as


yw(y) -
yeB
y'v + y'v = y[w(y) -
YEB
vr(y)] + yv = (b,J) (3')

yw(y) -
y eB
By' + By' = b. (1') and
w(y")
V=--
Substitute from (2) into (1'): r(y")

y[w(y) -
yeB
Br(y)] + By' = b. (1") Certainly v >LO. So we need show only that y".is the only element
removed from B, that is, that
Let w(y,B) = w(y) - Br(y) for y E B, = 8 for y= y', and =O other- min w(y)
wise. yeB r(y)
r(y)>O
Suppose r(y) .::; O, all y E B. Then (1) would be satisfied for 8
arbitrarily Iarge with w(y) = w(y,B). We exclude this possibility by is unique.
supposing that the set of solutions of (1) is bounded so that r(y) > O If not, then w(y") = [r(y")]/[r(y 1)]w(y 1), for y 1 1= y". Let W be
sorne y E B. Let the n x n matrix, the rows of which are the n-dimensional vectors
0
w(y) formed from w(y) by deleting the first element. Let [y]s be
B* - min w(y) - w(y") the matrix formed for y E B. Then, by (3), [y]s W = J. Post-
- y~B r(y) - r(y")
r(y)>O multiply both sides of the equation by the vector k and note Wk = O
lf this minimum is unique with w(y) > O, then setting 8 = 8* in (1") implies k = O, so W is non-singular. Then it is impossible for two
gives us a new solution of (1): rows, 0 w(y"), 0 w(y 1 ) of W to be proportional and so the minimum
must be unique.
yw'(y) =
yEB
b w'(y) = w(y) - B*r(y) The Scarf algorithm requires us to consider another set, which for
the moment we write as Z, and, also for the moment, take to have
y E B, w(y') = 8* as its elements n-dimensional vectors z. In Z we are interested in
If the minimum is not unique and/or w(y) = O, there is said to be certain subsets with the property that all of its elements are "el ose"
degeneracy. to each other. Such a set will be called a primitive set of Z. We
(e) We deal with degeneracy in the following way (see Dantzig shall consider a one-to-one mapping from subsets of Z to subsets
[1951, pp. 365-367]; Charnes [1952]). Let us say that the vector of Y.
)
'u

'['

406 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 407

Suppose there is D e Z such that the mapping takes D into a While these remarks may serve to motvate the discussion that
basis B in Y, whereB is feasiblefor problem (l). Suppose also that D follows, there are a good many complications that we have neglected
can be chosen so that all but one of its elements are the same as that and that account for sorne of the special procedures we adapt.
of a primitive set in Z. We could try to bring the two sets into (a) We can define a primitive set of Z as follows. Let P be an
"agreement" (have them contain the same elements) by either z
n-element subset of Z. Let be the vector formed by making each
removing the non-agreeing element from the primitive set and of its components equal to the smallest corresponding component of
finding another one to replace it, or inserting the element of the any vector in P. Consider the set z E Z such that z ;::: z. Then we
primitive set that is not in D into D and, accordingly, removing one can say that P is primitive if the set just defined has an empty
element from D. The latter operation, given the mapping, involves interior. If so, there are no elements of Z that can be expressed as
finding a new feasible basis for problem (1); the first operation convex mixtures of elements in P and so there are no elements of Z
hwolves finding a new primitive set from a given primitive set. If that lie "between" the elements' of P in that case.
it is the case that there is always a unique way of performing these However, difficulties similar to those discussed under the heading
operations (as we already know to be the case with changes in feasible of degeneracy in linear programming arise if there are elements in P
base) and if the steps never cycle, we can show that the attempt to with zero coordinates and if there is more than one vector in P that
bring D into agreement with a primitive set of Z will eventually be has a given smallest coordinate. The algorithm requires us to
accomplished. remove one element from P and uniquely replace it by another in
To see why this algorithm can lead to a fixed-point theorem, let order to form a new primitive set.
b = e' in (1), where e' is the n-dimensional row vector with one in (b) It will be recalled that Y contains the n vectors et and that we
every place. Let Z be a finite subset of the n-dimensional simplex concern ourselves with mapping points from another set into Y. It
and f(z) a single-valued continuous map of the simplex into itself. will be convenient to replace Z by the set X UJ where X is a set of
Let y(z) be the mapping from Z to Y referred to above and write n-dimensional vectors and J the set of integers 1, ... , n. In our
mapping we shall associate with any j E J the vector e1 in Y.
y(z) = f(z) - z + e'. To form a primitive set in X U J to allow us to pass from one such
Suppose that when the algorithm terminates we have set to another, we must induce an order on the elements of X U J.
L y(z)w(z) = L [f(z) -
ZE P ZE P
z + e']w(z) = e', (4)
To avoid degeneracy we wish to avoid "ties." This we can accom-
plish by a cyclic permutation of the series 1, ... , n. The formal
theory follows in the next section, but we shall consider an
where Pis the primitive set in Z with which the algorithm termina tes.
Since ef(z) = ez = 1, we have e[f(z) - z + e'] = n whence pre- illustration here.
Let the vectors in X be three-dimensional and J = 1, 2, 3. Con-
multiplying (4) by e gives
sider a cyclic permutation of the indexes, 2, 3, 1, which we might call
n L w(z) = n
ZEP
a "2-ordering" since 2 is now the leading term. Then in this order-
ing 1 > 3, since 1 comes after 3. Also, of course, 1 > 2.
or Now consider a 2-ordering of the coordinates of elements in
L w(z) = l.
ZEP
(5) X. That is, the coordinate 1abeled "2" is the first entry of each
vector, the coordinate labeled 3 is the second, and that labeled 1 is
Now suppose that the elements of Pare so ''el ose" that we may take the third. Consider in the ordering two elements x, x' in X, x =? x'.
them as identical. Here we are thinking of a limiting operation that Certainly they must differ in at least one coordinate. Find the
of course will require Z to be suitably dense (see Lemmas C.1 and 2-smallest such coordinate, that is, the first coordinate in the
C.2). Then, in view of (5), (4) becomes f(z) - z = O, which is the 2-ordering in which they differ. Suppose it has the label "3."
Brouwer fixed point. Then we shall say x > 2 x' if x 3 > x~ and x < 2 x' if X 3 < x;.
)
'u

'['

406 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS


T FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 407

Suppose there is D e Z such that the mapping takes D into a While these remarks may serve to motvate the discussion that
basis B in Y, whereB is feasiblefor problem (l). Suppose also that D follows, there are a good many complications that we have neglected
can be chosen so that all but one of its elements are the same as that and that account for sorne of the special procedures we adapt.
of a primitive set in Z. We could try to bring the two sets into (a) We can define a primitive set of Z as follows. Let P be an
"agreement" (have them contain the same elements) by either z
n-element subset of Z. Let be the vector formed by making each
removing the non-agreeing element from the primitive set and of its components equal to the smallest corresponding component of
finding another one to replace it, or inserting the element of the any vector in P. Consider the set z E Z such that z ;::: z. Then we
primitive set that is not in D into D and, accordingly, removing one can say that P is primitive if the set just defined has an empty
element from D. The latter operation, given the mapping, involves interior. If so, there are no elements of Z that can be expressed as
finding a new feasible basis for problem (1); the first operation convex mixtures of elements in P and so there are no elements of Z
hwolves finding a new primitive set from a given primitive set. If that lie "between" the elements' of P in that case.
it is the case that there is always a unique way of performing these However, difficulties similar to those discussed under the heading
operations (as we already know to be the case with changes in feasible of degeneracy in linear programming arise if there are elements in P
base) and if the steps never cycle, we can show that the attempt to with zero coordinates and if there is more than one vector in P that
bring D into agreement with a primitive set of Z will eventually be has a given smallest coordinate. The algorithm requires us to
accomplished. remove one element from P and uniquely replace it by another in
To see why this algorithm can lead to a fixed-point theorem, let order to form a new primitive set.
b = e' in (1), where e' is the n-dimensional row vector with one in (b) It will be recalled that Y contains the n vectors et and that we
every place. Let Z be a finite subset of the n-dimensional simplex concern ourselves with mapping points from another set into Y. It
and f(z) a single-valued continuous map of the simplex into itself. will be convenient to replace Z by the set X UJ where X is a set of
Let y(z) be the mapping from Z to Y referred to above and write n-dimensional vectors and J the set of integers 1, ... , n. In our
mapping we shall associate with any j E J the vector e1 in Y.
y(z) = f(z) - z + e'. To form a primitive set in X U J to allow us to pass from one such
Suppose that when the algorithm terminates we have set to another, we must induce an order on the elements of X U J.
L y(z)w(z) = L [f(z) -
ZE P ZE P
z + e']w(z) = e', (4)
To avoid degeneracy we wish to avoid "ties." This we can accom-
plish by a cyclic permutation of the series 1, ... , n. The formal
theory follows in the next section, but we shall consider an
where Pis the primitive set in Z with which the algorithm termina tes.
Since ef(z) = ez = 1, we have e[f(z) - z + e'] = n whence pre- illustration here.
Let the vectors in X be three-dimensional and J = 1, 2, 3. Con-
multiplying (4) by e gives
sider a cyclic permutation of the indexes, 2, 3, 1, which we might call
n L w(z) = n
ZEP
a "2-ordering" since 2 is now the leading term. Then in this order-
ing 1 > 3, since 1 comes after 3. Also, of course, 1 > 2.
or Now consider a 2-ordering of the coordinates of elements in
L w(z) = l.
ZEP
(5) X. That is, the coordinate 1abeled "2" is the first entry of each
vector, the coordinate labeled 3 is the second, and that labeled 1 is
Now suppose that the elements of Pare so ''el ose" that we may take the third. Consider in the ordering two elements x, x' in X, x =? x'.
them as identical. Here we are thinking of a limiting operation that Certainly they must differ in at least one coordinate. Find the
of course will require Z to be suitably dense (see Lemmas C.1 and 2-smallest such coordinate, that is, the first coordinate in the
C.2). Then, in view of (5), (4) becomes f(z) - z = O, which is the 2-ordering in which they differ. Suppose it has the label "3."
Brouwer fixed point. Then we shall say x > 2 x' if x 3 > x~ and x < 2 x' if X 3 < x;.
'1
1'
1

408 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 409

To compare an element of J with an element of X requires a con- But also x" o;6 x 4 so either x" > 1 x 4 or :X" < 1 x 4 In the first case,
vention and we chose the following. In a 2-order, we regard 2 < 2 x, since x" > 2 x 1 and x" > 3 x 6 , x" would dominate Q, contradicting
all x E X, and all other integers, that is, 1 or 3, are 2-greater than that it is primitive. In the second c.ase x 4 > 2 x\ x 4 > 3 x 6 , and
every element of X. x 4 > 1 x" = x 1 (Q'), contradicting that Q' is primitive. Hence
It is plain that in this illustration the choice of a 2-order was x" # x1 (Q').
arbitrary-we could have taken instead a 3-order or, indeed, a (b) Then x1 (Q') = x 1 or x 6 But x 6 > x, al! x E X, i o;6 3, and
1-order. so x1 (Q') = x 1 . (This shows that if we had removed x 1 from Q
We note that for unequal vectors in X either x > 2 x' or x' > 2 x no new primitive set could have been found. For x 1 is 2-minimum
so that they are strictly ordered. Moreover, there is a complete and neither x 4 nor x 6 could be 2-minimum in Q'. That is, we cannot
2-order of ail elements in X UJ, and since it is strict, there is a unique proceed with the algorithm if, after the removal of an element from
2-minimum element. Q, we are left with only elements in J. Not only is x 1 the 1-minimum
With these conventions, Iet Q be an n-element subset of X uJ. element in Q', but clearly it is also the 1-minimum element in
Let xi(Q) be the i-minimum element in Q. Then we say that Q is Q ~ {x4 } = (x\x 6).)
primitive if there is no x in X uJ su eh that x > i X.i( Q), all i. If there (e) Since we have shown that x 1 is 1-minimum in Q' and we
is such an x we say that it dominates Q. In our example i takes on know that x 6 is 3-minimum in Q', it must be that x" is 2-minimum in
the values 1, 2, 3. Q'. To find x" consider the set R of elements of X UJ that are
To illustrate, Iet X be the set of three vectors: x 1 = (3, 7,6), x 2 = 1-greater than x 1 and 3-greater than x 6 . Certainly this set has at
(3,5, 1), x 3 = (5,4, 1). Also Iet x 4 = 1, x 5 = 2, x 6 = 3. Suppose Q least one member since x 5 satisfies the criteria. Also, of course, x"
has the elements x\ x 2, and x 4 . Then x1 (Q) = x\ x2(Q) = x2, must be a member of this set, bein'g the 2-minimum element of Q'
x3 ( Q) = x 2. Then certainly x 1 > i x.i( Q), al! i, and the set cannot be and not i-minimum for i o;6 2. Find the 2-maximum element of the
primitive. set we ha ve defined and cal! it x**. Then x** > 1 x 1 , x** > 3 x 6
Next Iet Q have the elements x\ x\ and x 6 Then x1 (Q) = x\ If x** > 2 x", then x** would domina te Q' = (x\x 6 ,x 4 ), so x** = x".
x (Q) = x\ x3 (Q) = x 6 It is plain that no element of Q dominates
2
Since x 2 < 1 x 1 in our example, x 2 is not a candidate for x". But
Q. Also, we have x 5 <2 x 2(Q), x 2 < 2 x 2(Q), and x 3 < 2 x 2(Q), so x > 1 x 1 and x 3 > 3 x 6 , so x 3 as well as x 5 is a candidate. But
3

no element outside Q dominates Q. Hence (x 1 ,x 4 ,x 6 ) is a primitive se t. x 5 < 2 x, all x in X, so x 5 < 2 x 3 , x 3 = x", or Q' = (x\x 6 ,x3 ). Tt is
Notice that when we were considering the set (x\x 2 ,x 4), we had easily checked directly that Q' is indeed primitive. But we can also
x = xi(Q) for more than one i and found that the set was not argue a.s follows. Suppose there is an x that dominates Q'. Then
primitive. Indeed, it is easy to show (see (17)) that if Q is primitive, certainly x must be 1-greater than x 1 and 3-greater than x 6 and thus
x = X.i(Q) for exactly one i. Also note that a primitive set cannot x E R. But al so of course x > 2 x", and this contradicts the definition
consist of elements of J only, since by definition, x > i i, if x E X. of x" as the 2-maximum element of R.
Suppose we start with the primitive set Q: (x\x\x 6 ) and are told Hopefully these samples will make it easier to understand the
to remove x 4 from it. The problem is to find a replacement for this formal presentation that follows.
element so that a new primitive set Q' will be formed. Cal! this
element x"-we still have to find it, but first assumc that indeed a
2. Primitive Sets and Replacements
new primitive set Q' can be formed. We proceed by steps.
(a) x 4 is 1-minimum in Q. We show that x" cannot be 1-mini- Severa! new concepts will be introduced as part of Scarf's proof;
mum in Q'. This is easy, for the sets Q ~ {x 4 } and Q' ~ {x"} are the more traditional proofs of fixed-point theorems also require the
the same. Hence, if x" is 1-minimum in Q', we have introduction of concepts peculiar to them, though different from
Scarf's.
Let X be a set of non-negative vectors and J the set of integers
'1
1'
1

408 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 409

To compare an element of J with an element of X requires a con- But also x" o;6 x 4 so either x" > 1 x 4 or :X" < 1 x 4 In the first case,
vention and we chose the following. In a 2-order, we regard 2 < 2 x, since x" > 2 x 1 and x" > 3 x 6 , x" would dominate Q, contradicting
all x E X, and all other integers, that is, 1 or 3, are 2-greater than that it is primitive. In the second c.ase x 4 > 2 x\ x 4 > 3 x 6 , and
every element of X. x 4 > 1 x" = x 1 (Q'), contradicting that Q' is primitive. Hence
It is plain that in this illustration the choice of a 2-order was x" # x1 (Q').
arbitrary-we could have taken instead a 3-order or, indeed, a (b) Then x1 (Q') = x 1 or x 6 But x 6 > x, al! x E X, i o;6 3, and
1-order. so x1 (Q') = x 1 . (This shows that if we had removed x 1 from Q
We note that for unequal vectors in X either x > 2 x' or x' > 2 x no new primitive set could have been found. For x 1 is 2-minimum
so that they are strictly ordered. Moreover, there is a complete and neither x 4 nor x 6 could be 2-minimum in Q'. That is, we cannot
2-order of ail elements in X UJ, and since it is strict, there is a unique proceed with the algorithm if, after the removal of an element from
2-minimum element. Q, we are left with only elements in J. Not only is x 1 the 1-minimum
With these conventions, Iet Q be an n-element subset of X uJ. element in Q', but clearly it is also the 1-minimum element in
Let xi(Q) be the i-minimum element in Q. Then we say that Q is Q ~ {x4 } = (x\x 6).)
primitive if there is no x in X uJ su eh that x > i X.i( Q), all i. If there (e) Since we have shown that x 1 is 1-minimum in Q' and we
is such an x we say that it dominates Q. In our example i takes on know that x 6 is 3-minimum in Q', it must be that x" is 2-minimum in
the values 1, 2, 3. Q'. To find x" consider the set R of elements of X UJ that are
To illustrate, Iet X be the set of three vectors: x 1 = (3, 7,6), x 2 = 1-greater than x 1 and 3-greater than x 6 . Certainly this set has at
(3,5, 1), x 3 = (5,4, 1). Also Iet x 4 = 1, x 5 = 2, x 6 = 3. Suppose Q least one member since x 5 satisfies the criteria. Also, of course, x"
has the elements x\ x 2, and x 4 . Then x1 (Q) = x\ x2(Q) = x2, must be a member of this set, bein'g the 2-minimum element of Q'
x3 ( Q) = x 2. Then certainly x 1 > i x.i( Q), al! i, and the set cannot be and not i-minimum for i o;6 2. Find the 2-maximum element of the
primitive. set we ha ve defined and cal! it x**. Then x** > 1 x 1 , x** > 3 x 6
Next Iet Q have the elements x\ x\ and x 6 Then x1 (Q) = x\ If x** > 2 x", then x** would domina te Q' = (x\x 6 ,x 4 ), so x** = x".
x (Q) = x\ x3 (Q) = x 6 It is plain that no element of Q dominates
2
Since x 2 < 1 x 1 in our example, x 2 is not a candidate for x". But
Q. Also, we have x 5 <2 x 2(Q), x 2 < 2 x 2(Q), and x 3 < 2 x 2(Q), so x > 1 x 1 and x 3 > 3 x 6 , so x 3 as well as x 5 is a candidate. But
3

no element outside Q dominates Q. Hence (x 1 ,x 4 ,x 6 ) is a primitive se t. x 5 < 2 x, all x in X, so x 5 < 2 x 3 , x 3 = x", or Q' = (x\x 6 ,x3 ). Tt is
Notice that when we were considering the set (x\x 2 ,x 4), we had easily checked directly that Q' is indeed primitive. But we can also
x = xi(Q) for more than one i and found that the set was not argue a.s follows. Suppose there is an x that dominates Q'. Then
primitive. Indeed, it is easy to show (see (17)) that if Q is primitive, certainly x must be 1-greater than x 1 and 3-greater than x 6 and thus
x = X.i(Q) for exactly one i. Also note that a primitive set cannot x E R. But al so of course x > 2 x", and this contradicts the definition
consist of elements of J only, since by definition, x > i i, if x E X. of x" as the 2-maximum element of R.
Suppose we start with the primitive set Q: (x\x\x 6 ) and are told Hopefully these samples will make it easier to understand the
to remove x 4 from it. The problem is to find a replacement for this formal presentation that follows.
element so that a new primitive set Q' will be formed. Cal! this
element x"-we still have to find it, but first assumc that indeed a
2. Primitive Sets and Replacements
new primitive set Q' can be formed. We proceed by steps.
(a) x 4 is 1-minimum in Q. We show that x" cannot be 1-mini- Severa! new concepts will be introduced as part of Scarf's proof;
mum in Q'. This is easy, for the sets Q ~ {x 4 } and Q' ~ {x"} are the more traditional proofs of fixed-point theorems also require the
the same. Hence, if x" is 1-minimum in Q', we have introduction of concepts peculiar to them, though different from
Scarf's.
Let X be a set of non-negative vectors and J the set of integers
r

410 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 411

1, ... , n. The set X UJ, is then a well-defined, though somewhat W e complete the definition of the i-ordering to permit comparisons
strange, set composed of n vectors and integers. We are interested of elements of J with elements of X.
in sets Q that are n-element subsets of X U J. The idea is that the
i <X for all x in X; (8)
integer elements of Q, that is, the set J n Q, designate certain dimen-
sions that are treated in a special manner. Then, since Q has n X<} for all x in X and all j =1= i, j E J. (9)
elements, there are exactly as many members of J "' Q as there are
of X n Q, and they will be put into one-to-one correspondence in It can easily be verified that the i-ordering is an ordering, that is,
appropriate ways. transitive and connected, and indeed a strict ordering, so that for
We want to rank elements of X according to their ith coordinate, x =1= x' one and only one of the relations x < 1 x' and x' <; x holds.
but analogous to our treatment of the degeneracy in Section C.1, It follows that for any subset of X U J there is a unique i-minimum.
we shall supplement the rules so as to avoid ti es; that is, if the ith Specifically, for any n-element subset, Q, of X U J, let
coordinates are equal, they will rank one element above another x1(Q) be the i-minimum element of Q. (10)
according to the relative values of sorne other coordinates. Also,
we want to rank elements of X relative to those of J; we agree that We note sorne e1ementary consequences of these definitions.
i itself is "smaller in the ith coordina te" than any element of X, but From (8) and (9), if i E J n Q, then x1(Q) = i. If i ~ J n Q, so that
that an integer j =!= ns "larger in the ith coordina te" than any i E J "' Q, then J n Q has at most n - 1 members, so that Q contains
element of X. at least one member of X. Hence, from (9), it is impossible that
Although there are severa! ways ofintroducing the desired ranking, x1(Q) = j forjE J, j =/= i.
it will be most. convenient, both theoretically and computationally, Jf i EJn Q, then x1(Q) = i;
to order the integers according to a cyclic permutation with the
if E J "' Q, then x1(Q) Ex n Q. (11)
integer i placed first; then we order the elements of X according to
the lowest-ranking tie-breaking component, where the components lf xl(Q) > x 1 for sorne x in X n Q, it certainly could not be true
are ordered according to this cyclic permutation. Specifically, we that xi(Q) is the i-minimum element.
introduce an i-ordering on J,
If i E J "' Q, then x(Q) = min x1 (12)
xeYnQ
j < }' if i :o; j < j' or i :o; j, j' < i or j < j' < i. (6)
We will associate with Q a cone contained in the non-negative
This amounts to putting the integers i, ... , n before the integers orthant. Define a vector 1;( Q) by the coordina te relations:
1, ... , i - 1 and then ordering them. The relation "j < 1 ) ' " will be
nQ
{~i(Q)
read, ''j is i-smaller thanj'." if i E J
g(Q) =
(13)
We now order the elements of X according to the ith coordinate if i E J "-' Q
if possible; if not, beca use of a ti e, we order them according to the
first unequal coordinate in the i-ordering of coordinates. Then dertne a convex cone,
For two e1ements, x,x' in X, let J(x,x') be the set of coordinates i
for which X; =!= x;, and Jet j be the i-minimum element of J(x,x'). T(Q) = {x 1 X ~ l;(Q)}. (14)
Then we define The above definitions amount to saying that we choose m :0:: n
x < 1 x' to mean that x1 < xj. (7) elements of X and a corresponding number of coordina te directions;
then T(Q) is the smallest cone similar to the non-negative orthant
Note that if x1 =1= x;, then i itself is the i-minimum element of containing these points and unrestricted in all other coordinate
J(x,x') and x < 1x' or x' <; x according as X < x; or x; < x 1. directions.
r

410 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 411

1, ... , n. The set X UJ, is then a well-defined, though somewhat W e complete the definition of the i-ordering to permit comparisons
strange, set composed of n vectors and integers. We are interested of elements of J with elements of X.
in sets Q that are n-element subsets of X U J. The idea is that the
i <X for all x in X; (8)
integer elements of Q, that is, the set J n Q, designate certain dimen-
sions that are treated in a special manner. Then, since Q has n X<} for all x in X and all j =1= i, j E J. (9)
elements, there are exactly as many members of J "' Q as there are
of X n Q, and they will be put into one-to-one correspondence in It can easily be verified that the i-ordering is an ordering, that is,
appropriate ways. transitive and connected, and indeed a strict ordering, so that for
We want to rank elements of X according to their ith coordinate, x =1= x' one and only one of the relations x < 1 x' and x' <; x holds.
but analogous to our treatment of the degeneracy in Section C.1, It follows that for any subset of X U J there is a unique i-minimum.
we shall supplement the rules so as to avoid ti es; that is, if the ith Specifically, for any n-element subset, Q, of X U J, let
coordinates are equal, they will rank one element above another x1(Q) be the i-minimum element of Q. (10)
according to the relative values of sorne other coordinates. Also,
we want to rank elements of X relative to those of J; we agree that We note sorne e1ementary consequences of these definitions.
i itself is "smaller in the ith coordina te" than any element of X, but From (8) and (9), if i E J n Q, then x1(Q) = i. If i ~ J n Q, so that
that an integer j =!= ns "larger in the ith coordina te" than any i E J "' Q, then J n Q has at most n - 1 members, so that Q contains
element of X. at least one member of X. Hence, from (9), it is impossible that
Although there are severa! ways ofintroducing the desired ranking, x1(Q) = j forjE J, j =/= i.
it will be most. convenient, both theoretically and computationally, Jf i EJn Q, then x1(Q) = i;
to order the integers according to a cyclic permutation with the
if E J "' Q, then x1(Q) Ex n Q. (11)
integer i placed first; then we order the elements of X according to
the lowest-ranking tie-breaking component, where the components lf xl(Q) > x 1 for sorne x in X n Q, it certainly could not be true
are ordered according to this cyclic permutation. Specifically, we that xi(Q) is the i-minimum element.
introduce an i-ordering on J,
If i E J "' Q, then x(Q) = min x1 (12)
xeYnQ
j < }' if i :o; j < j' or i :o; j, j' < i or j < j' < i. (6)
We will associate with Q a cone contained in the non-negative
This amounts to putting the integers i, ... , n before the integers orthant. Define a vector 1;( Q) by the coordina te relations:
1, ... , i - 1 and then ordering them. The relation "j < 1 ) ' " will be
nQ
{~i(Q)
read, ''j is i-smaller thanj'." if i E J
g(Q) =
(13)
We now order the elements of X according to the ith coordinate if i E J "-' Q
if possible; if not, beca use of a ti e, we order them according to the
first unequal coordinate in the i-ordering of coordinates. Then dertne a convex cone,
For two e1ements, x,x' in X, let J(x,x') be the set of coordinates i
for which X; =!= x;, and Jet j be the i-minimum element of J(x,x'). T(Q) = {x 1 X ~ l;(Q)}. (14)
Then we define The above definitions amount to saying that we choose m :0:: n
x < 1 x' to mean that x1 < xj. (7) elements of X and a corresponding number of coordina te directions;
then T(Q) is the smallest cone similar to the non-negative orthant
Note that if x1 =1= x;, then i itself is the i-minimum element of containing these points and unrestricted in all other coordinate
J(x,x') and x < 1x' or x' <; x according as X < x; or x; < x 1. directions.
T
,1
'/

1
412 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 413

Now define, DEFINITION 5. Q' is said to be a replacement ofx' in Q if Q and Q'


are primitive sets and Q ~ Q' = {x'}.
DEFINITION 4. An element x in X dominates an n-element subset,
Q, of X uJ, x dom Q, if and only if x >; x1(Q), all i. Q is said to In other words, x' is removed from the primitive set Q and replaced
be primitive if it is undominated by any element of X. by another element of X U J, say x", in such a way that the new set,
If T(Q) had an element of X in its interior, then it would certainly
Q', is also primitive.
be dominated. TI-IEOREM 2. If Q is primitive and x' E Q, then there is no replace-
ment of x' in Q if Q ~ {x'} e J and exactly one replacement
If Q is primitive, then the interior of T(Q)
is disjoint from X. (15) otherwise.

The converse is not quite true, because of the possibility of ties Proo.f We suppose that such a replacement exists and find
in any one coordinate that are broken by looking at another necessary conditions. Let x" be the sole element of Q' ~ Q, that
coordinate. is, the new element in Q'. From (17), we can assume, without loss
We first note sorne elementary properties of primitive sets. of generality, that
Suppose Q contained no elements of X, that is, Q e J. Since Q
and J both have n elements, Q = J. Then x1(Q) = i, all i; but, by
(8), x dom Q for any x E X. First, suppose that x" = x1 (Q'); we show that this is impossible.
From (17), we would have, for i > 1, xi(Q) E Q ~ {x}, x 1(Q') E Q' ~
Jf Q is primitive, X n Q is non-null. (16) {x"}. Since x1(Q) is i-minimum in Q, it is certainly i-minimum in the
Suppose X E Q, X -1= x 1(Q). By (10), then, X > i xi(Q). Hence, if subset, Q ~ {x'}, and similarly, x1(Q') is i-minimum in Q' ~ {x"},
Q is primiti\:e, for all x E Q, x = x1(Q) for sorne i, for otherwise which, however, is the same set.
x dom Q. Since both J and Q ha ven elements, it is impossible that
for i > l.
x = x1(Q) for more than one i, since then there would be sorne
x' -1= xi( Q), all i. From (JO) and (17), x' >; xi(Q) = xi(Q') for i > 1, and similarly
x" >; xi(Q) for i > l. Since x' -1= x", either x' > 1 x" or x" > 1 x'.
If Q is primitive, then for all x E Q,
Since x' = x1 (Q), x" = x1 (Q'), we have in the first case that x'
x = xi(Q) for exactly one i. (17)
dom Q' and in the second that x" dom Q, both of which contradict
Jf x E Xn Q, f;(Q) >X;, then f;(Q) > O; from (13), i El~ Q, the assumed primitivity of Q and Q'. Thus the supposition x" =
and then there is a contradiction from (13) and (12). Therefore, x1( Q') leads to a contradiction.
Then, x1 (Q') must belong to Q' ~ {x"} = Q ~ {x'}. Let
X;~ f;(Q) for x E Xn Q, all i.
(19)
lt follows from (16) that
T(Q) n X is non-mili. (18) Since x* E Q, x* = x1(Q), sorne i, but x* -1= x' = x1(Q), so that
i > l. Without loss of generality, we may suppose
A primitive set is, in sorne suggestive ways, analogous to a basis
in linear programming; the set J n Q is analogous to the set of slack (20)
vectors. A key step in linear programming is the pivota! trans- Jf x* El, then we have to have, by (11), x* = 1, from (19), and
formation by which one element is removed from a basis and x* = 2, from (20), a contradiction.
replaced by another. In general, this replacement is unique. The
following definition introduces an analogous step. x* E xn [Q ~ {x'}]. (21)
T
,1
'/

1
412 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 413

Now define, DEFINITION 5. Q' is said to be a replacement ofx' in Q if Q and Q'


are primitive sets and Q ~ Q' = {x'}.
DEFINITION 4. An element x in X dominates an n-element subset,
Q, of X uJ, x dom Q, if and only if x >; x1(Q), all i. Q is said to In other words, x' is removed from the primitive set Q and replaced
be primitive if it is undominated by any element of X. by another element of X U J, say x", in such a way that the new set,
If T(Q) had an element of X in its interior, then it would certainly
Q', is also primitive.
be dominated. TI-IEOREM 2. If Q is primitive and x' E Q, then there is no replace-
ment of x' in Q if Q ~ {x'} e J and exactly one replacement
If Q is primitive, then the interior of T(Q)
is disjoint from X. (15) otherwise.

The converse is not quite true, because of the possibility of ties Proo.f We suppose that such a replacement exists and find
in any one coordinate that are broken by looking at another necessary conditions. Let x" be the sole element of Q' ~ Q, that
coordinate. is, the new element in Q'. From (17), we can assume, without loss
We first note sorne elementary properties of primitive sets. of generality, that
Suppose Q contained no elements of X, that is, Q e J. Since Q
and J both have n elements, Q = J. Then x1(Q) = i, all i; but, by
(8), x dom Q for any x E X. First, suppose that x" = x1 (Q'); we show that this is impossible.
From (17), we would have, for i > 1, xi(Q) E Q ~ {x}, x 1(Q') E Q' ~
Jf Q is primitive, X n Q is non-null. (16) {x"}. Since x1(Q) is i-minimum in Q, it is certainly i-minimum in the
Suppose X E Q, X -1= x 1(Q). By (10), then, X > i xi(Q). Hence, if subset, Q ~ {x'}, and similarly, x1(Q') is i-minimum in Q' ~ {x"},
Q is primiti\:e, for all x E Q, x = x1(Q) for sorne i, for otherwise which, however, is the same set.
x dom Q. Since both J and Q ha ven elements, it is impossible that
for i > l.
x = x1(Q) for more than one i, since then there would be sorne
x' -1= xi( Q), all i. From (JO) and (17), x' >; xi(Q) = xi(Q') for i > 1, and similarly
x" >; xi(Q) for i > l. Since x' -1= x", either x' > 1 x" or x" > 1 x'.
If Q is primitive, then for all x E Q,
Since x' = x1 (Q), x" = x1 (Q'), we have in the first case that x'
x = xi(Q) for exactly one i. (17)
dom Q' and in the second that x" dom Q, both of which contradict
Jf x E Xn Q, f;(Q) >X;, then f;(Q) > O; from (13), i El~ Q, the assumed primitivity of Q and Q'. Thus the supposition x" =
and then there is a contradiction from (13) and (12). Therefore, x1( Q') leads to a contradiction.
Then, x1 (Q') must belong to Q' ~ {x"} = Q ~ {x'}. Let
X;~ f;(Q) for x E Xn Q, all i.
(19)
lt follows from (16) that
T(Q) n X is non-mili. (18) Since x* E Q, x* = x1(Q), sorne i, but x* -1= x' = x1(Q), so that
i > l. Without loss of generality, we may suppose
A primitive set is, in sorne suggestive ways, analogous to a basis
in linear programming; the set J n Q is analogous to the set of slack (20)
vectors. A key step in linear programming is the pivota! trans- Jf x* El, then we have to have, by (11), x* = 1, from (19), and
formation by which one element is removed from a basis and x* = 2, from (20), a contradiction.
replaced by another. In general, this replacement is unique. The
following definition introduces an analogous step. x* E xn [Q ~ {x'}]. (21)
li
1

414 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT TI-IEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORi'I'HMS 415
This statement a1ready shows that it is necessary for the existence of Pro m (25), x* does not belong to R. Suppose that x" > 2 x*.
a replacement of x' in Q that X n [Q "' {x'}] be non-mll. Hence, Since x* = x2 (Q), from (20), we ha ve, from (25), x" > t xi(Q) for
if Q "' {x'} e J, then there is no such replacement, so the first part i > l. Since x* > 1 x1 (Q), from (20), and x" > 1 x*, by definition
of T.C.2 is confirmed. of R, we have, by transitivity, that x" > 1 x1 (Q), so that x" dom Q,
Prom (10), x* is 1-minimum in Q'; from (21), contrary to hypothesis. Hence, x* > 2 x". Again from (20), x* is :1
2-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}, so that (23) i
x* is 1-minimum in Xn [Q' "'{x"}] = Xn [Q "'{x'}], (22) .'i'
must hold.
so that x* is uniquely defined and by a constructive procedure.
It is now easy to show that Q' is primitive. If x dom Q', it
Prom (19) and (17), x* is not 2-minimum in Q'. Prom (20), x*
follows from (19), (24), and (25) that x E R, while also x > 2 i 2 (Q'),
is 2-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}; hence
a contradiction to (26). This completes the proof of the theorem.
x" = x2(Q'). (23)
Corollary 2. If Q' is the replacement of x' in Q and x" is the so le
Now Q "' [{x'} u{x*}] = Q' "' [{x"} u {x*}]. Por i > 2, xt(Q) is element of Q' "' Q, then Q is the replacement of x" in Q.
i-minimum in the first of these sets and xt(Q') in the second.
This follows immediately from the uniqueness of the replacement
for i > 2. (24) and its definition.
We seek a characterization of x". Define the set Remark. It has been shown that the unique replacement of x' in
Q can be achieved in a finite number of steps, by (22), (25), and (26).
R = {x 1 X E X uJ, X > 1 x*' X > i xi( Q) for i > 2}. (25)
The determination of x* in (22) involves a search among, at most,
Pirst, note that R is necessarily non-null, for 2 E R; from (9), n - 1 alternatives, and n usually will be taken in application to be
2 > t x for al! x E X if i i= 2, while from (6), 2 > i i for al! i E J, a fixed number (for example, the number of commodities). How-
i i= 2. Also, we note that, from (23) and (17), x" E R. Let x:* be ever, the set X will be taken to be very large; indeed, in the deter-
the 2-maximum element of R .. Prom (19) and (24), it fol!ows from mination of a fixed point, the larger the set X, the better the approxi-
the definition of R that, mation. It would appear on the face of it that the determination of
x** >t xi(Q') for i i= 2. the set R requires searching through the en tire X U J, which is not
very appealing. In general, this is true, but it is possib1e to reduce
If x** > 2 x", then, from (23), x** dom Q', contrary to assumption. the calculation to a minor exercise if X happens to be the set of
Therefore, x** = X 1', by definition of a 2-maximum element. elements of Sn with rational coordinates and a fixed denominator,
x" is the 2-maximum element of R. (26) that is,
Prom (22), x* is uniquely defined, and therefore, so is x", by (25)
and (26). Thus, there is, at most, one replacement of x' in Q. It
XN = {x 1 Xt = %' at non-negative integers, f Xt = 1}
remains to show that these conditions are sufficient for a replacement. Por details, see Hansen and Scarf [1969, Section IV] and Kuhn
Since Q', defined as [Q "' {x'}] U {x"}, has n elements, it suffices to [1968, pp. 1240-1242].
show that it is primitive. Pirst, we will show that xi(Q') are indeed
as given in (19), (23), and (24). If 1 E Q, then x' = 1, so that, in 3. Scarf's Theorem
any case, 1 ~ Q "' {x'}. It then follows from (22) and (9) that x* THEOREM 3. Let X be a set of n vectors, y(x) a function mapping
is 1-minimum in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}. Prom (25) and (26), X into a set Y of n vectors, 1 the set of unit vectors and J the set of
x" > 1 x*, so that (19) is confirmed. Similarly, for i > 2, x1(Q) is integers 1, ... , n. If b ;::: O and if the set of inequalities,
i-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}, while

.. 1

X > i xi( Q), so that (24) holds.


11 yw(y) = b w(y) ;::: O,
yEYul
li
1

414 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT TI-IEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORi'I'HMS 415
This statement a1ready shows that it is necessary for the existence of Pro m (25), x* does not belong to R. Suppose that x" > 2 x*.
a replacement of x' in Q that X n [Q "' {x'}] be non-mll. Hence, Since x* = x2 (Q), from (20), we ha ve, from (25), x" > t xi(Q) for
if Q "' {x'} e J, then there is no such replacement, so the first part i > l. Since x* > 1 x1 (Q), from (20), and x" > 1 x*, by definition
of T.C.2 is confirmed. of R, we have, by transitivity, that x" > 1 x1 (Q), so that x" dom Q,
Prom (10), x* is 1-minimum in Q'; from (21), contrary to hypothesis. Hence, x* > 2 x". Again from (20), x* is :1
2-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}, so that (23) i
x* is 1-minimum in Xn [Q' "'{x"}] = Xn [Q "'{x'}], (22) .'i'
must hold.
so that x* is uniquely defined and by a constructive procedure.
It is now easy to show that Q' is primitive. If x dom Q', it
Prom (19) and (17), x* is not 2-minimum in Q'. Prom (20), x*
follows from (19), (24), and (25) that x E R, while also x > 2 i 2 (Q'),
is 2-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}; hence
a contradiction to (26). This completes the proof of the theorem.
x" = x2(Q'). (23)
Corollary 2. If Q' is the replacement of x' in Q and x" is the so le
Now Q "' [{x'} u{x*}] = Q' "' [{x"} u {x*}]. Por i > 2, xt(Q) is element of Q' "' Q, then Q is the replacement of x" in Q.
i-minimum in the first of these sets and xt(Q') in the second.
This follows immediately from the uniqueness of the replacement
for i > 2. (24) and its definition.
We seek a characterization of x". Define the set Remark. It has been shown that the unique replacement of x' in
Q can be achieved in a finite number of steps, by (22), (25), and (26).
R = {x 1 X E X uJ, X > 1 x*' X > i xi( Q) for i > 2}. (25)
The determination of x* in (22) involves a search among, at most,
Pirst, note that R is necessarily non-null, for 2 E R; from (9), n - 1 alternatives, and n usually will be taken in application to be
2 > t x for al! x E X if i i= 2, while from (6), 2 > i i for al! i E J, a fixed number (for example, the number of commodities). How-
i i= 2. Also, we note that, from (23) and (17), x" E R. Let x:* be ever, the set X will be taken to be very large; indeed, in the deter-
the 2-maximum element of R .. Prom (19) and (24), it fol!ows from mination of a fixed point, the larger the set X, the better the approxi-
the definition of R that, mation. It would appear on the face of it that the determination of
x** >t xi(Q') for i i= 2. the set R requires searching through the en tire X U J, which is not
very appealing. In general, this is true, but it is possib1e to reduce
If x** > 2 x", then, from (23), x** dom Q', contrary to assumption. the calculation to a minor exercise if X happens to be the set of
Therefore, x** = X 1', by definition of a 2-maximum element. elements of Sn with rational coordinates and a fixed denominator,
x" is the 2-maximum element of R. (26) that is,
Prom (22), x* is uniquely defined, and therefore, so is x", by (25)
and (26). Thus, there is, at most, one replacement of x' in Q. It
XN = {x 1 Xt = %' at non-negative integers, f Xt = 1}
remains to show that these conditions are sufficient for a replacement. Por details, see Hansen and Scarf [1969, Section IV] and Kuhn
Since Q', defined as [Q "' {x'}] U {x"}, has n elements, it suffices to [1968, pp. 1240-1242].
show that it is primitive. Pirst, we will show that xi(Q') are indeed
as given in (19), (23), and (24). If 1 E Q, then x' = 1, so that, in 3. Scarf's Theorem
any case, 1 ~ Q "' {x'}. It then follows from (22) and (9) that x* THEOREM 3. Let X be a set of n vectors, y(x) a function mapping
is 1-minimum in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}. Prom (25) and (26), X into a set Y of n vectors, 1 the set of unit vectors and J the set of
x" > 1 x*, so that (19) is confirmed. Similarly, for i > 2, x1(Q) is integers 1, ... , n. If b ;::: O and if the set of inequalities,
i-minimum in Q and therefore in Q "' {x'} = Q' "' {x"}, while

.. 1

X > i xi( Q), so that (24) holds.


11 yw(y) = b w(y) ;::: O,
yEYul
1 i

416 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-l>OINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 417
has a bounded set of solutions, then there exists a feasible basis B 1
distinct. The insertion of y(x in y( C) has no meaning in this case,
)

for the system of inequalities anda primitive set Q for the set X uJ or more precisely, the "insertion" simply leaves the basis unchanged,
such that B is the image of Q under the mapping y(x), where it is but we can still define C 1 in exactly the same way, and C 1 is different
understood that y(j) = e1 for j E J. from C.
If C almost agrees with Q, we say that the pair (C ,Q is adjacent
1 1
)
Proof The ingenious combinatoria! argument parallels one
to (e, Q) if either of the following is possible.
introduced by Lemke and Howson [1964] for finding the equilibrium
points of a two-person non-zero sum game with finitely many (a) C = C ,Q is the replacement ofx(C,Q) in Q;
1 1

strategies for each player; for excellent expositions and greatly (b) Q = Q C is the insertion of x( C, Q) in C.
1
,
1

widened range of applications, see Lemke ['1968] and Dantzig and


From li~ear programming theory, the transformation (b) is always
Cottle [1968].
possible. We show that the transformation (a) is possible if and
For the purposes of this proof, an n-element subset C of X uJ will
only if C =f. J. First, suppose C = J. Then C n Q must consist of
be termed a feasible basis if its image under the mapping y(x),
the integers 2, ... , n. Sin ce C and Q do not agree, x( C, Q) must be
,,,
i ;,1
denoted by y( C), is a feasible basis. A feasible basis C is said to i 1!1

an element of. X. Thus, Q ~ {x(C,Q)} e J, and by T.C.2, no


agree with a primitive set Q if Q = C. We seek to show that there
replacement is possible.
exists a pair (C,Q) such that C agrees with Q. A feasible basis C is
Now suppose C =1- J. Then C contains an element, x, of X.
said to almost agree with a primitive set Q if C ~ Q = {1}; that is,
Since e~ Q = {1}, X E Q. But X =1- x(C,Q), from (27), so that
n - 1 elements of B = y(C) correspond to elements of Q, but B
Q ~ {x(C,Q)} contains an element of X, and a replacement is
also contains the first unit vector.
possible. We have shown that if e =1- J, both transformations (a)
This method of proof is to begin with a pair (Ca, Qa) that almost
and (b) are possible, while if C = J, only (b) is possible.
agrees and then continue with a series of transformations that take
an almost agreeing pair into either an almost agreeing pair or an (e, Q) has one adjacent pair if e = J,
agreeing pair. 1t will be shown that the sequence can never repeat; two adjacent pai~s otherwise. (28)
since there are only finitely many possible pairs, the process must
If (e , Q ) is adjacent to (e, Q) and e almost agrees with Q , then
1 1 1 1

eventually termina te in an agreeing pair, which not only demonstrates


it follows from Corollary 2 that (C,Q) is adjacent to (C ,Q 1 1
).
the theorem, but exhibits a finite algorithm for arriving at a basis
We also observe that if C = J, there is only one possible Q that
that is both feasible and primitive.
almost agrees with C. As already seen, Q must contain 2, ... , n.
If C almost agrees with Q, Q ~ C must contain exactly one
Then x1(Q) = i, i > 1, while x1 (Q) E X. Let x* be the 1-maximum
element; define
element of X. Then x* > 1 i (i > 1); if al so x* > 1 x1 ( Q), then x*
x( C, Q) is the sol e e1ement of Q ~ C. (27) dominates Q, and Q wou1d not be primitive. Hence, if C = J and
C almost agrees with Q, then Q consists of x* and the integers
If C is a feasible basis, then y( C) is a feasible basis in its appro- 2, ... , n; call this set Qa.
priate set Y u/. Since both sets ha ve n elements, the mapping y(x) We now generate a sequence of pairs, (Cv,Qv), as follows. Let
has a unique inverse for X E C. If X 11$ e, we define el to be the Ca = J and Qa be as just specified. Then there is precisely one pair
1
insertion of x' in C essentially if C is the inverse of the insertion of adjacent to (Ca,Qa); call it (C1 ,Q 1 ). In general, if Cv =1- J, there are
y(x') in y(C). In more detail, if y" is the eliminated element in this two pairs adjacent to (Cv,Qv); Jet (Cv+l,Qv+l) be adjacent to
insertion, then y" = y(x") for some unique x", and we define C' as (Cv,Qv) and distinct from (Cv_ 1 ,Qv_ 1). By induction, it is imme-
[C ~ {x"}] u{x'}. 1t can happen that y(x') is in fact already an diately verified that if Cv almost agrees with Qv, then (Cv -1> Qv -1) is
element of y( C); that is, y(x = y(x") for so me x" E C. There
1
)
adjacent to (Cv, Qv), so that ( Cv+ 1 , QV+ 1 ) is uniquely specified.
cannot be more than one such x", since the elements of y(C) are Note also that, from the definition of adjacency, if C almost
1 i

416 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-l>OINT THEOREMS ANO COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 417
has a bounded set of solutions, then there exists a feasible basis B 1
distinct. The insertion of y(x in y( C) has no meaning in this case,
)

for the system of inequalities anda primitive set Q for the set X uJ or more precisely, the "insertion" simply leaves the basis unchanged,
such that B is the image of Q under the mapping y(x), where it is but we can still define C 1 in exactly the same way, and C 1 is different
understood that y(j) = e1 for j E J. from C.
If C almost agrees with Q, we say that the pair (C ,Q is adjacent
1 1
)
Proof The ingenious combinatoria! argument parallels one
to (e, Q) if either of the following is possible.
introduced by Lemke and Howson [1964] for finding the equilibrium
points of a two-person non-zero sum game with finitely many (a) C = C ,Q is the replacement ofx(C,Q) in Q;
1 1

strategies for each player; for excellent expositions and greatly (b) Q = Q C is the insertion of x( C, Q) in C.
1
,
1

widened range of applications, see Lemke ['1968] and Dantzig and


From li~ear programming theory, the transformation (b) is always
Cottle [1968].
possible. We show that the transformation (a) is possible if and
For the purposes of this proof, an n-element subset C of X uJ will
only if C =f. J. First, suppose C = J. Then C n Q must consist of
be termed a feasible basis if its image under the mapping y(x),
the integers 2, ... , n. Sin ce C and Q do not agree, x( C, Q) must be
,,,
i ;,1
denoted by y( C), is a feasible basis. A feasible basis C is said to i 1!1

an element of. X. Thus, Q ~ {x(C,Q)} e J, and by T.C.2, no


agree with a primitive set Q if Q = C. We seek to show that there
replacement is possible.
exists a pair (C,Q) such that C agrees with Q. A feasible basis C is
Now suppose C =1- J. Then C contains an element, x, of X.
said to almost agree with a primitive set Q if C ~ Q = {1}; that is,
Since e~ Q = {1}, X E Q. But X =1- x(C,Q), from (27), so that
n - 1 elements of B = y(C) correspond to elements of Q, but B
Q ~ {x(C,Q)} contains an element of X, and a replacement is
also contains the first unit vector.
possible. We have shown that if e =1- J, both transformations (a)
This method of proof is to begin with a pair (Ca, Qa) that almost
and (b) are possible, while if C = J, only (b) is possible.
agrees and then continue with a series of transformations that take
an almost agreeing pair into either an almost agreeing pair or an (e, Q) has one adjacent pair if e = J,
agreeing pair. 1t will be shown that the sequence can never repeat; two adjacent pai~s otherwise. (28)
since there are only finitely many possible pairs, the process must
If (e , Q ) is adjacent to (e, Q) and e almost agrees with Q , then
1 1 1 1

eventually termina te in an agreeing pair, which not only demonstrates


it follows from Corollary 2 that (C,Q) is adjacent to (C ,Q 1 1
).
the theorem, but exhibits a finite algorithm for arriving at a basis
We also observe that if C = J, there is only one possible Q that
that is both feasible and primitive.
almost agrees with C. As already seen, Q must contain 2, ... , n.
If C almost agrees with Q, Q ~ C must contain exactly one
Then x1(Q) = i, i > 1, while x1 (Q) E X. Let x* be the 1-maximum
element; define
element of X. Then x* > 1 i (i > 1); if al so x* > 1 x1 ( Q), then x*
x( C, Q) is the sol e e1ement of Q ~ C. (27) dominates Q, and Q wou1d not be primitive. Hence, if C = J and
C almost agrees with Q, then Q consists of x* and the integers
If C is a feasible basis, then y( C) is a feasible basis in its appro- 2, ... , n; call this set Qa.
priate set Y u/. Since both sets ha ve n elements, the mapping y(x) We now generate a sequence of pairs, (Cv,Qv), as follows. Let
has a unique inverse for X E C. If X 11$ e, we define el to be the Ca = J and Qa be as just specified. Then there is precisely one pair
1
insertion of x' in C essentially if C is the inverse of the insertion of adjacent to (Ca,Qa); call it (C1 ,Q 1 ). In general, if Cv =1- J, there are
y(x') in y(C). In more detail, if y" is the eliminated element in this two pairs adjacent to (Cv,Qv); Jet (Cv+l,Qv+l) be adjacent to
insertion, then y" = y(x") for some unique x", and we define C' as (Cv,Qv) and distinct from (Cv_ 1 ,Qv_ 1). By induction, it is imme-
[C ~ {x"}] u{x'}. 1t can happen that y(x') is in fact already an diately verified that if Cv almost agrees with Qv, then (Cv -1> Qv -1) is
element of y( C); that is, y(x = y(x") for so me x" E C. There
1
)
adjacent to (Cv, Qv), so that ( Cv+ 1 , QV+ 1 ) is uniquely specified.
cannot be more than one such x", since the elements of y(C) are Note also that, from the definition of adjacency, if C almost
418 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 419

agrees with Q and (C',Q') is adjacent to (C,Q), then C' either agrees Then ex = 1 and, from (14),
or almost agrees with Q'.
el;(QN) :S: l. (29)
Now we demonstrate that the sequence never repeats; that is, it is
impossible that (C,"'Q,_.) = (Cv+ 1,Qv+ 1) for p, :S: v. Otherwise, pick L()t U be the subset of the non-negative orthant consisting of all
the smallest such v. Since two adjacent pairs are never equal, it is points on or below the fundamental simplex, that is,
impossible that p, = v, and by the construction, it is impossible that
p, = v - l. Hence p, < v - l. U= {x 1 x ;::: O, ex :S: 1}.
Suppose p, = O. Then (Cv, Qv) would be adjacent to ( C0 , Q0 ) as
The set T(QN) is geometrically similar to the non-negative orthant,
would ( Cl> Q1). But there is only one pair adjacent to ( C0 , Q0 );
and therefore the set Un T(QN) is similar to the set U, with all
hence (Cl> Q1) = (Cv, Qv) Since v > 1, as just seen, this contradicts
dimensions reduced in the proportion 1: 1 - el;(QN) Consider, in
the choice of v as the smallest val ue for which ( C11 , Q11 ) =
particular, the radius of the largest neighborhood contained in
(Cv+l>Qv+ 1), for sorne p, :S: v.
T(QN) n S 71 , where the neighborhood is taken relative to Sn; this
Suppose fL > O. Then (C-1,Q 11 - 1), (Cfl+1,Qfl+1), and (Cv,Qv)
radius is proportional to 1 - el;(QN). For N large, the set XN can
would all be adjacent to (C11 ,Q11). In view of (28) two would have
be made as dense as desired in S71 , so that the radius of the largest
to be equal; but such equality contradicts the choice of v.
neighborhood relative to Sn that is disjoint from XN approaches O
Therefore, all the elements of the sequence (Cv, Qv) are distinct.
as N approaches infinity. Since, by (15), the interior of T(QN) is
The sequence can be continued as long as Cv almost agrees with Qv;
disjoint from XN, the same is true of any neighborhood contained in
on the other hand, there are only finitely many possible bases and,
T(QN) n S 71 From all this, it follows that
afortiori, only finitely many pairs (C,Q) that almost agree. Hence,
since all elements of the sequence either agree or almost agree, and lim el;(QN)
N-+oo
= l. (30)
the sequence terminates in the first case, it follows that in finitely
many steps the algorithm reaches an agreeing pair. ' For each N, J n QN is a proper subset of J; since there are only
finitely many such sets, there must be at least one set, J*, such that
J n QN = J* for infinitely many N. From now on, consider only
4. Brouwer's and Kakutani's Fixed-Point Theorems such N. The sequence l;(QN) is bounded; hence we can choose
Scarf's theorem yields a remarkably rapid proof of Brouwer's another subsequence such that
fixed-point theorem, T.C.l. For any given integer, N, we consider (31)
the set X to be the set XN defined in the Remark to T.C.2 and then
make a suitable choice of y(x). The theorem follows by a limiting From the definition of l;(Q) in (13), g1(QN) = O for i E J*, so that
argument. certainly xf = Ofor i E J*, as claimed. Finally, since xN E XN n QN,
we have both xN E S71 and xN E T(QN), so that
LEMMA l. Let QN be any primitive set for XN UJ, and let xN be any
element of XN n QN. By choosing an appropriate subsequence, we
can find a proper subset, J*, of J, anda point, x*, su eh that J n QN =
Then it follows from (29)-(31) that xN--+ x* along the subsequence.
J* and xN--+ x* along the subsequence, and xf = O for all i E J*.
We now state a lemma that exhibits, in general, the manner of
The subsequence and the limit point x* are independent of the man-
ner of choosing xN from XN n QN. going to a limit in the application of Scarf's theorem; this lemma is
used not only to prove Brouwer's and Kakutani's fixed-point
Proof Recall the definition of T(QN) in (14). Since XN e 8 71 , it theorems, but also to prove a large variety of other results (for
follows from (18) that T(QN) n S71 is non-null; let x be an element. example, see Section C.5).
418 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 419

agrees with Q and (C',Q') is adjacent to (C,Q), then C' either agrees Then ex = 1 and, from (14),
or almost agrees with Q'.
el;(QN) :S: l. (29)
Now we demonstrate that the sequence never repeats; that is, it is
impossible that (C,"'Q,_.) = (Cv+ 1,Qv+ 1) for p, :S: v. Otherwise, pick L()t U be the subset of the non-negative orthant consisting of all
the smallest such v. Since two adjacent pairs are never equal, it is points on or below the fundamental simplex, that is,
impossible that p, = v, and by the construction, it is impossible that
p, = v - l. Hence p, < v - l. U= {x 1 x ;::: O, ex :S: 1}.
Suppose p, = O. Then (Cv, Qv) would be adjacent to ( C0 , Q0 ) as
The set T(QN) is geometrically similar to the non-negative orthant,
would ( Cl> Q1). But there is only one pair adjacent to ( C0 , Q0 );
and therefore the set Un T(QN) is similar to the set U, with all
hence (Cl> Q1) = (Cv, Qv) Since v > 1, as just seen, this contradicts
dimensions reduced in the proportion 1: 1 - el;(QN) Consider, in
the choice of v as the smallest val ue for which ( C11 , Q11 ) =
particular, the radius of the largest neighborhood contained in
(Cv+l>Qv+ 1), for sorne p, :S: v.
T(QN) n S 71 , where the neighborhood is taken relative to Sn; this
Suppose fL > O. Then (C-1,Q 11 - 1), (Cfl+1,Qfl+1), and (Cv,Qv)
radius is proportional to 1 - el;(QN). For N large, the set XN can
would all be adjacent to (C11 ,Q11). In view of (28) two would have
be made as dense as desired in S71 , so that the radius of the largest
to be equal; but such equality contradicts the choice of v.
neighborhood relative to Sn that is disjoint from XN approaches O
Therefore, all the elements of the sequence (Cv, Qv) are distinct.
as N approaches infinity. Since, by (15), the interior of T(QN) is
The sequence can be continued as long as Cv almost agrees with Qv;
disjoint from XN, the same is true of any neighborhood contained in
on the other hand, there are only finitely many possible bases and,
T(QN) n S 71 From all this, it follows that
afortiori, only finitely many pairs (C,Q) that almost agree. Hence,
since all elements of the sequence either agree or almost agree, and lim el;(QN)
N-+oo
= l. (30)
the sequence terminates in the first case, it follows that in finitely
many steps the algorithm reaches an agreeing pair. ' For each N, J n QN is a proper subset of J; since there are only
finitely many such sets, there must be at least one set, J*, such that
J n QN = J* for infinitely many N. From now on, consider only
4. Brouwer's and Kakutani's Fixed-Point Theorems such N. The sequence l;(QN) is bounded; hence we can choose
Scarf's theorem yields a remarkably rapid proof of Brouwer's another subsequence such that
fixed-point theorem, T.C.l. For any given integer, N, we consider (31)
the set X to be the set XN defined in the Remark to T.C.2 and then
make a suitable choice of y(x). The theorem follows by a limiting From the definition of l;(Q) in (13), g1(QN) = O for i E J*, so that
argument. certainly xf = Ofor i E J*, as claimed. Finally, since xN E XN n QN,
we have both xN E S71 and xN E T(QN), so that
LEMMA l. Let QN be any primitive set for XN UJ, and let xN be any
element of XN n QN. By choosing an appropriate subsequence, we
can find a proper subset, J*, of J, anda point, x*, su eh that J n QN =
Then it follows from (29)-(31) that xN--+ x* along the subsequence.
J* and xN--+ x* along the subsequence, and xf = O for all i E J*.
We now state a lemma that exhibits, in general, the manner of
The subsequence and the limit point x* are independent of the man-
ner of choosing xN from XN n QN. going to a limit in the application of Scarf's theorem; this lemma is
used not only to prove Brouwer's and Kakutani's fixed-point
Proof Recall the definition of T(QN) in (14). Since XN e 8 71 , it theorems, but also to prove a large variety of other results (for
follows from (18) that T(QN) n S71 is non-null; let x be an element. example, see Section C.5).
420 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 421

LEMMA 2. If y(x) is a bounded mapping from Sn to n space, b ;:o: O, so that (a) and (b) hold; that ut
= O for i E J "' J* follows from the
and the sets of solutions to the inequalities fact that uf = O for those i for all N.

2 y(x)w(x) = b w(x) ;:o: O Proof of T. C. J. We now apply Lemma C.2 with an appropriate
XEXUJ
choice of y(x) and b. Brouwer's theorem assumes tha:t f(x) is a
for all finite subsets X of Sn are bounded uniformly, then there exists continuous mapping of Sn into itself. Hence ef(x) = 1 = ex, for
a proper subset, J*, of J, u* ;:o: O, vj ;:o: O (j = 1, ... , m), where m all X E Sn-
is the numbcr of clemcnts in J "' J*, x* in sn> and y1 (j = 1' ... , m), Define now
where, for each j, y1 is a limit point of y(x) as x approaches x*, such
that y(x) = f(x) - x + e', b = e', for X E Sn, (33)

m where e' is the column vector all of whose components are l. First,
(a) u* + 2: vjy1 = b,
we verify that the boundedness hypotheses are verified. Obviously,
J= 1

(b) ut =O for i E J "' J*, y(x) is a bounded function. Let X be any finite subset of Sn. and
xt =O for i El*. consider the equations and inequalities

Proof By T.C.3, for each N, there exists QN, which is both a 2 y(x)~(x) = e' w(x) ;:o: O.
primitive set and a feasible basis for the inequalities XEXUJ

2 y(x)w(x) =b w(x) ;:o: O. Since y(i) = e1 for i E J, by letting u1 = w(i) and u be the vector
XEXNU]
with components u1, we can write this system as
Then, by definition of a feasible basis, we can find wN(x) ;:o: O, x E QN,
such that u + 2 y(x)w(x) = e'
XEX
u ;:o: O, w(x) ;:o: O, all x E X. (34) l.
XEQN
2 y(x)wN(x) = b. (32)
From (33), it is obvious that ey(x) = ef(x) - ex + ee' = ee' = n,
Choose the subsequence of Lemma C.l and the corresponding J*. all x E X. Also, eu ;:o: O, eu = O if and only if u = O. If we mul-
Let uf = wN(i) for i E J*, uf = O for i E J "' J*. Sin ce y(i) = e1, tiply through in (34) on the left by e,

2 y(x)w(x) = 2 ufe 1
=
n
2 ufe 1
= uN, eu +n 2 w(x) = n,
xeX
xeJ* teJ* i=l

where uN is the vector with components uf. Enumerate the m so that


elements of QN "' J* arbitrarily as x 1N, ... , xmN, and Jet wN(x1N) =
vf. Then (32) can be written
2 w(x) :::; 1
XEX
w(x) ;:o: O, all x E X;
(35)
m
uN + 2 vfy(xiN) = b,
}=1
2 w(x) = 1
XEX
if and only if u = O,

where uN ;:o: O, vf ;:o: O, uf = O for i E J "' J*. From Lemma C.l and the solutions for w(x) (x E X) are, in particular, bounded; from
there exists x* such that x 1N -> x* for allj on a suitable subsequence, (34), the same must hold for u.
and xt = O for i E J*. From the boundedness hypothesis of the We can therefore apply Lemma C.2 so that
lemma, the sequences uN, vf, and y(x1N) are all bounded; hence, by
m
choosing a further subsequence, we can ensure that
u* + 2 vjy 1
= e', (36)
uN--+ u* vf--+ vj y(xiN) -> yi, }=1
420 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 421

LEMMA 2. If y(x) is a bounded mapping from Sn to n space, b ;:o: O, so that (a) and (b) hold; that ut
= O for i E J "' J* follows from the
and the sets of solutions to the inequalities fact that uf = O for those i for all N.

2 y(x)w(x) = b w(x) ;:o: O Proof of T. C. J. We now apply Lemma C.2 with an appropriate
XEXUJ
choice of y(x) and b. Brouwer's theorem assumes tha:t f(x) is a
for all finite subsets X of Sn are bounded uniformly, then there exists continuous mapping of Sn into itself. Hence ef(x) = 1 = ex, for
a proper subset, J*, of J, u* ;:o: O, vj ;:o: O (j = 1, ... , m), where m all X E Sn-
is the numbcr of clemcnts in J "' J*, x* in sn> and y1 (j = 1' ... , m), Define now
where, for each j, y1 is a limit point of y(x) as x approaches x*, such
that y(x) = f(x) - x + e', b = e', for X E Sn, (33)

m where e' is the column vector all of whose components are l. First,
(a) u* + 2: vjy1 = b,
we verify that the boundedness hypotheses are verified. Obviously,
J= 1

(b) ut =O for i E J "' J*, y(x) is a bounded function. Let X be any finite subset of Sn. and
xt =O for i El*. consider the equations and inequalities

Proof By T.C.3, for each N, there exists QN, which is both a 2 y(x)~(x) = e' w(x) ;:o: O.
primitive set and a feasible basis for the inequalities XEXUJ

2 y(x)w(x) =b w(x) ;:o: O. Since y(i) = e1 for i E J, by letting u1 = w(i) and u be the vector
XEXNU]
with components u1, we can write this system as
Then, by definition of a feasible basis, we can find wN(x) ;:o: O, x E QN,
such that u + 2 y(x)w(x) = e'
XEX
u ;:o: O, w(x) ;:o: O, all x E X. (34) l.
XEQN
2 y(x)wN(x) = b. (32)
From (33), it is obvious that ey(x) = ef(x) - ex + ee' = ee' = n,
Choose the subsequence of Lemma C.l and the corresponding J*. all x E X. Also, eu ;:o: O, eu = O if and only if u = O. If we mul-
Let uf = wN(i) for i E J*, uf = O for i E J "' J*. Sin ce y(i) = e1, tiply through in (34) on the left by e,

2 y(x)w(x) = 2 ufe 1
=
n
2 ufe 1
= uN, eu +n 2 w(x) = n,
xeX
xeJ* teJ* i=l

where uN is the vector with components uf. Enumerate the m so that


elements of QN "' J* arbitrarily as x 1N, ... , xmN, and Jet wN(x1N) =
vf. Then (32) can be written
2 w(x) :::; 1
XEX
w(x) ;:o: O, all x E X;
(35)
m
uN + 2 vfy(xiN) = b,
}=1
2 w(x) = 1
XEX
if and only if u = O,

where uN ;:o: O, vf ;:o: O, uf = O for i E J "' J*. From Lemma C.l and the solutions for w(x) (x E X) are, in particular, bounded; from
there exists x* such that x 1N -> x* for allj on a suitable subsequence, (34), the same must hold for u.
and xt = O for i E J*. From the boundedness hypothesis of the We can therefore apply Lemma C.2 so that
lemma, the sequences uN, vf, and y(x1N) are all bounded; hence, by
m
choosing a further subsequence, we can ensure that
u* + 2 vjy 1
= e', (36)
uN--+ u* vf--+ vj y(xiN) -> yi, }=1
422 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 423

where also Lemma C.2(b) holds, and from (35), DEFINITION 6. A correspondence is a mapping of points into sets.
m A correspondence, <I>(x), is said to be upper semi-continuous if for

J= 1
vj :s; 1 and equality implies that u* = O. (37) any sequences {xv}, {yv}, the conditions xv __,. x, yv __,.y, yv E cD(xv), all
v, imply that y E cD(x).
Here, y1 is a limit point of y(x) as x approaches x*. From (33) then
THEOREM 4 (Kakutani's Fixed-Point Theorem). Let be a compact e
1
y + x* - e' is a limit point of f(x) as x approaches x*. (38) convex set and cD(x) an upper semi-continuous correspondence
defined on C SUCh that cD(x) C e, cD(x) COnVeX, for each X E C.
Since f(x) is assumed continuous,
e
Then there exists x* E such that x* E Cl)(x*).
y1 + x* - e' = f(x*) allj. (39) Note that if cD(x) consists of a single point for each x, this reduces
N ow let d be the row vector, with dt = O for i E J*, dt = 1 for to Brouwer's theorem for a general compact convex domain.
i E J"' J*. From Lemma C.2(b), du* = O. Also, dt # et only for Proof The above proof of Brouwer's theorem suffices, with
i E J* and therefore only if xt
= O, by Lemma C.2(b); hence dx* = slight modifications, to establish Kakutani's theorem for the case in
ex* = l. Finally, d :s; e, so that df(x) :s; ef(x) = l. From (38) which e is the fundamental simplex, Sn. Then the general case can
or (39),
be handled simply.
d(y1 + x* - e') :s; 1 eachj. For each x E Sn, choose f(x) to be an arbitrary element of cD(x).
Then define y(x) as befare. The entire argument through (38) makes
Since dx* = 1, this statement can be written dyi :s; de'. If we
no use of the continuity of f(x) and so remains valid; also, (40) still
premultiply (36) by d, then we find
holds. Since f(x) E cD(x), which is upper semi-continuous, it follows
m from (38) and D.C.6 that
(de') L vj 2 de'.
J=l yi + x* - e' E cD(x*), eachj.
In conjunction with (37), we see that Since, from (40),
' ~,'
',

m vj 2 O, eachj, 1

L vj = 1
J=l
u*= O.
and
1

m
If we substitute into (36), then we have
m
L vj = 1
J=l
y* = e' where y* = L vjyi and and since cD(x*) is convex by hypothesis,
J=l
m
m
L vj = 1, vj 2 O, allj. (40)
vj(yi + x* - e') E cD(x*),
J=l
i=l
which can be written,
If we multiply (39) by vj and then sum over j, we have
y* + x* - e' E <I>(x*).
y* + x* - e' = f(x*),
From (40), this establishes Kakutani's theorem.
which, in view of (40) establishes Brouwer's theorem.
To extend this to the case in which the domain is a general compact
We now state and prove Kakutani's generalization of Brouwer's convex set, first note that there is really no loss of generality in
theorem. We first repeat the definition already given in Chapter 4. assuming that e is a subset of a fundamental simplex. Suppose that
422 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 423

where also Lemma C.2(b) holds, and from (35), DEFINITION 6. A correspondence is a mapping of points into sets.
m A correspondence, <I>(x), is said to be upper semi-continuous if for

J= 1
vj :s; 1 and equality implies that u* = O. (37) any sequences {xv}, {yv}, the conditions xv __,. x, yv __,.y, yv E cD(xv), all
v, imply that y E cD(x).
Here, y1 is a limit point of y(x) as x approaches x*. From (33) then
THEOREM 4 (Kakutani's Fixed-Point Theorem). Let be a compact e
1
y + x* - e' is a limit point of f(x) as x approaches x*. (38) convex set and cD(x) an upper semi-continuous correspondence
defined on C SUCh that cD(x) C e, cD(x) COnVeX, for each X E C.
Since f(x) is assumed continuous,
e
Then there exists x* E such that x* E Cl)(x*).
y1 + x* - e' = f(x*) allj. (39) Note that if cD(x) consists of a single point for each x, this reduces
N ow let d be the row vector, with dt = O for i E J*, dt = 1 for to Brouwer's theorem for a general compact convex domain.
i E J"' J*. From Lemma C.2(b), du* = O. Also, dt # et only for Proof The above proof of Brouwer's theorem suffices, with
i E J* and therefore only if xt
= O, by Lemma C.2(b); hence dx* = slight modifications, to establish Kakutani's theorem for the case in
ex* = l. Finally, d :s; e, so that df(x) :s; ef(x) = l. From (38) which e is the fundamental simplex, Sn. Then the general case can
or (39),
be handled simply.
d(y1 + x* - e') :s; 1 eachj. For each x E Sn, choose f(x) to be an arbitrary element of cD(x).
Then define y(x) as befare. The entire argument through (38) makes
Since dx* = 1, this statement can be written dyi :s; de'. If we
no use of the continuity of f(x) and so remains valid; also, (40) still
premultiply (36) by d, then we find
holds. Since f(x) E cD(x), which is upper semi-continuous, it follows
m from (38) and D.C.6 that
(de') L vj 2 de'.
J=l yi + x* - e' E cD(x*), eachj.
In conjunction with (37), we see that Since, from (40),
' ~,'
',

m vj 2 O, eachj, 1

L vj = 1
J=l
u*= O.
and
1

m
If we substitute into (36), then we have
m
L vj = 1
J=l
y* = e' where y* = L vjyi and and since cD(x*) is convex by hypothesis,
J=l
m
m
L vj = 1, vj 2 O, allj. (40)
vj(yi + x* - e') E cD(x*),
J=l
i=l
which can be written,
If we multiply (39) by vj and then sum over j, we have
y* + x* - e' E <I>(x*).
y* + x* - e' = f(x*),
From (40), this establishes Kakutani's theorem.
which, in view of (40) establishes Brouwer's theorem.
To extend this to the case in which the domain is a general compact
We now state and prove Kakutani's generalization of Brouwer's convex set, first note that there is really no loss of generality in
theorem. We first repeat the definition already given in Chapter 4. assuming that e is a subset of a fundamental simplex. Suppose that
424 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 425

the dimensionality of e is n - 1 ; this is the dimensionality of the 5. A Direct Computation of Equilibrium in a Simple Model
smallest linear space containing C. Choose a coordinate system
in this space of n - 1 dimensions; this can be taken to be a linear We conclude this appendix by presenting Scarf's [1967c] algorithm
transformation of the original variables. By shifting origin, we can for computing equilibrium in a simple model involving both produc-
1

assume that C is contained in the non-negative orthant. Since C is tion and exchange. Although, in principie, all equilibrium com-
bounded, ex is bounded on C; by another simple transformation we putations can be done by using the general reduction to a fixed-point
can assume that ex ::;; l. Finally, we map C Iinearly into a subset problem, as in Chapter 5, it is frequently preferable from the view-
of ~n by adding an nth coordinate, 1 - ex. Thus, C is Iinearly point of computational simplicity to use Scarf's theorem directly
eqmvalent to a compact convex subset of Sn and has the same with a new interpretation of y(x).
dimensionality. Since all transformations are linear, the hypotheses In the present section, the symbols have economic interpretations
of Kakutani's theorem remain valid. and therefore the notation of the text will be used. The underlying
variable is the price vector, p, which ranges over Sn. Household
Now choose X 0 to be any point of C that is interna! relative to the
demand, x(p), is assumed single valued, continuous, and non-
linear space defined by the equation, ex = 1, and Jet p(x) be the gauge
negative, over Sn. The social production possibility set is taken to
function of C relative to this space (see D.B.8, T.B.l(h)). Then
p(x) is continuous, and p(x - x 0) ::;; 1 if and only if x E C, for x in be a closed convex cone, Y, which satisfies the conditions of Chapter
this space and in particular for x E Sno Let q(x) = max[p(x - x 0 ), 1]
4, in particular, A.4.4, so that production without inputs and
so that x E C if and only if q(x) = l. Define a mapping, reversibility are both ruled out. Then T.4.2 holds, so that the set
of feasible production vectors,
X- X 0
T(x) = x 0 + -q(x)
- ' Y= Yn{y['y+x;:o:O},
l this
.
maps an element of e into itself and an element X of Sn ~ e is compact, where x is the vector of initial endowments. Since
mto that e]ement of C that is closest to X on the line segment joining profits at equilibrium are O for Y, a cone, we can assume
x 0 to x. Since q(x) is bounded away from O, T(x) is continuous. px(p) = px forallp; (41)
Finally, define the correspondence
more precisely, we define x(p) to be household demand from an
ci\(x) = c])[T(x)] for all x E Sn in come generated so le! y by sale of household possessions. To avoid
For.x in C, this is simply the original correspondence. (]) 1 is upper difficult cases, we assume that x O, so that px > O, all p E Sn.
sem1-continuous, since e]) is upper semi-continuous and T(x) is con- Equilibrium, allowing for inequalities, can be defined by the
tinuous; c])l(x) = c])[T(x)], where T(x) E e for all X E Sn, so that for relations
eac.h such x, c]) 1(x) is convex and c]) 1(x) e C e Sn. Hence c]) 1(x)
u* + x(p*) = y* + x, u* ;:: O, p*u* =O, y* E Y,
satisfies all the hypotheses of Kakutani's theorem for the fundamental
simplex, and there is a point, x* E Sn, such that x* E c]) 1(x*). Since, p*y* =o, p*y::;; o, allyEY. (42)
by construction, c])l(x) e e for all X E sn> x* E C; then T(x*) = x*
If we define
and cD1(x*) = cD(x*), so that Kakutani's theorem holds for the set C.
Remark. From the computational view, the extension of Y- = {p 1 py ::;; O for aii y E Y} (43)
Kakutani's theorem to a general compact convex set creates only one the last condition can be written p* E y-. (y- 1s frequently
possible difficulty, 11amely, the mapping, T(x) ofthe simplex onto the referred to as the polar cone to Y.)
se~. Although the definition is very simple in principie, computation Now we use again Lemma C.2. With the present notation, we
m1ght turn out to be very difficult if the set C is not defined in sorne re place y(x) by q(p). To define this, note that if p $ Y-, then
simple way. py > O for sorne y E Y; since Y is a cone, we have, for all ,\ > O,
424 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 425

the dimensionality of e is n - 1 ; this is the dimensionality of the 5. A Direct Computation of Equilibrium in a Simple Model
smallest linear space containing C. Choose a coordinate system
in this space of n - 1 dimensions; this can be taken to be a linear We conclude this appendix by presenting Scarf's [1967c] algorithm
transformation of the original variables. By shifting origin, we can for computing equilibrium in a simple model involving both produc-
1

assume that C is contained in the non-negative orthant. Since C is tion and exchange. Although, in principie, all equilibrium com-
bounded, ex is bounded on C; by another simple transformation we putations can be done by using the general reduction to a fixed-point
can assume that ex ::;; l. Finally, we map C Iinearly into a subset problem, as in Chapter 5, it is frequently preferable from the view-
of ~n by adding an nth coordinate, 1 - ex. Thus, C is Iinearly point of computational simplicity to use Scarf's theorem directly
eqmvalent to a compact convex subset of Sn and has the same with a new interpretation of y(x).
dimensionality. Since all transformations are linear, the hypotheses In the present section, the symbols have economic interpretations
of Kakutani's theorem remain valid. and therefore the notation of the text will be used. The underlying
variable is the price vector, p, which ranges over Sn. Household
Now choose X 0 to be any point of C that is interna! relative to the
demand, x(p), is assumed single valued, continuous, and non-
linear space defined by the equation, ex = 1, and Jet p(x) be the gauge
negative, over Sn. The social production possibility set is taken to
function of C relative to this space (see D.B.8, T.B.l(h)). Then
p(x) is continuous, and p(x - x 0) ::;; 1 if and only if x E C, for x in be a closed convex cone, Y, which satisfies the conditions of Chapter
this space and in particular for x E Sno Let q(x) = max[p(x - x 0 ), 1]
4, in particular, A.4.4, so that production without inputs and
so that x E C if and only if q(x) = l. Define a mapping, reversibility are both ruled out. Then T.4.2 holds, so that the set
of feasible production vectors,
X- X 0
T(x) = x 0 + -q(x)
- ' Y= Yn{y['y+x;:o:O},
l this
.
maps an element of e into itself and an element X of Sn ~ e is compact, where x is the vector of initial endowments. Since
mto that e]ement of C that is closest to X on the line segment joining profits at equilibrium are O for Y, a cone, we can assume
x 0 to x. Since q(x) is bounded away from O, T(x) is continuous. px(p) = px forallp; (41)
Finally, define the correspondence
more precisely, we define x(p) to be household demand from an
ci\(x) = c])[T(x)] for all x E Sn in come generated so le! y by sale of household possessions. To avoid
For.x in C, this is simply the original correspondence. (]) 1 is upper difficult cases, we assume that x O, so that px > O, all p E Sn.
sem1-continuous, since e]) is upper semi-continuous and T(x) is con- Equilibrium, allowing for inequalities, can be defined by the
tinuous; c])l(x) = c])[T(x)], where T(x) E e for all X E Sn, so that for relations
eac.h such x, c]) 1(x) is convex and c]) 1(x) e C e Sn. Hence c]) 1(x)
u* + x(p*) = y* + x, u* ;:: O, p*u* =O, y* E Y,
satisfies all the hypotheses of Kakutani's theorem for the fundamental
simplex, and there is a point, x* E Sn, such that x* E c]) 1(x*). Since, p*y* =o, p*y::;; o, allyEY. (42)
by construction, c])l(x) e e for all X E sn> x* E C; then T(x*) = x*
If we define
and cD1(x*) = cD(x*), so that Kakutani's theorem holds for the set C.
Remark. From the computational view, the extension of Y- = {p 1 py ::;; O for aii y E Y} (43)
Kakutani's theorem to a general compact convex set creates only one the last condition can be written p* E y-. (y- 1s frequently
possible difficulty, 11amely, the mapping, T(x) ofthe simplex onto the referred to as the polar cone to Y.)
se~. Although the definition is very simple in principie, computation Now we use again Lemma C.2. With the present notation, we
m1ght turn out to be very difficult if the set C is not defined in sorne re place y(x) by q(p). To define this, note that if p $ Y-, then
simple way. py > O for sorne y E Y; since Y is a cone, we have, for all ,\ > O,
426 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 427

.\y E Y and p(.\y) > O. Therefore, for two arbitrary numbers, and, for eachj = 1, ... , m, q1 is a limit point of q(p) as p approaches
O < M<! M, we can require M :o; JyJ ::::; M. Then choose q(p) so p*. Then let
that qi = lirn q(piv) where lirn p1v = p*.
v-+oo v-..oo
q(p) = -y, (44)
We can classify the in dices j into two sets according as the sequence
wherepy >O, y E Y, M :o; JyJ :o; M, forp<t' y-, and {piv} does or does not have infinitely rnany rnembers in y-. Let the
q(p) = x(p) for pE Y-. (45) in dices in the second set be nurnbered 1, ... , r, and in the first,
r + 1, ... , m: It still has to be shown that r < m, that is, that for
Let P be any finite subset of Sn. We first establish that the sorne j, piv E y- for infinitely many v. For j > r, then, q(p1v) =
solutions of the inequalities,
x(p 1v) for infinitely many v, and p* is the limit of a sequence in y-;
u + .2; q(p)w(p) = x u :2: O, w(p) :2: O, since x(p) is continuous and y- is closed,
pEP
qi = x(p*) for j > r; p* E y- if r < m. (50)
are bounded uniformly in the choice of P. From (44) and (45), these
can be written, For j :o; r, -q(piv) E Y and p1v[-q(p1v)] > O, all v. Since Y is
el o sed,
u + .2; x(p)w(p) = .2; [-q(p)]w(p) + x. (46) -qiE Y, -p*qi ;:o: O forj :Sir. (51)
pePnY- peP~y-

Since -q(p) E Yfor p EP ~ y-, w(p) :2: O, all p, and Yis a convex Frorn (50) and (51), (48) can be rewritten
cone, u* + v*x(p*) = y* + x, (52)
2: (-q(p)]w(p) =y E Y. (47)
where
m
J>EP~Y
v* = .2; vj
Since the left-hand side of (46) is certainly non-negative, y E Y and 1= r+ 1

therefore is bounded. Then, since /-q(p)/ :2: M for pE P ~ y-, and


r
it follows from (47) that w(p) is uniformly bounded for such p. y* = .2; vj( -qi).
Also, frorn (41), x(p) 1= o for any pE sn> so that Jx(p)/ is bounded 1=1
away from O on Sn. since it is a continuous function. Since the Since Y is a convex cone, it follows from (51) that 1'
1

right-hand side of (46) is bounded, the left-hand side must be; thus,
both u and y* E Y p*y* :2: 0.
Premultiply both sides of (52) by p* and use (49) and (41):
.2; x(p)w(p)
pePnY (v* - 1)p*x = p*y*.
are bounded. But since Jx(p)J s bounded uniformly from below, it Then v* ;:o: 1, v* = 1 if p*y* = O. But v* > O certainly implies
must be that w(p) is bounded from abo ve for p E P n Y-. that r < m; from (50) and the definition of Y-, 1
Frorn the definitions (44) and (45), the function q(p) is certainly
bounded. Hence Lernma C.2 is applicable. p*y :Si o all y E Y,
m and certainly p*y* = Oand therefore v* = 1, so that (42) is satisfied. 1 ,1!1
11':

u* + .2; vjq1 = x u* :2: O, vj :2: O; (48) 1 Attention should be drawn to another algorithm for finding a competitive
1
,,
1

1= 1
equilibrium, dueto Cottle [1966]; it is applicable to economies in which a ~lig~1tly
for sorne set J*, uf = O for i E J ~ J*, pf = O for i E J*, so that stronger version of the GaJe property holds, specifically, where all the pnnc1paj 1

minors of the Jacobian of excess supplies are positive and bounded away from 1

p*u* =O, (49) zero and infinity.


426 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS FIXED-POINT THEOREMS AND COMBINATORIAL ALGORITHMS 427

.\y E Y and p(.\y) > O. Therefore, for two arbitrary numbers, and, for eachj = 1, ... , m, q1 is a limit point of q(p) as p approaches
O < M<! M, we can require M :o; JyJ ::::; M. Then choose q(p) so p*. Then let
that qi = lirn q(piv) where lirn p1v = p*.
v-+oo v-..oo
q(p) = -y, (44)
We can classify the in dices j into two sets according as the sequence
wherepy >O, y E Y, M :o; JyJ :o; M, forp<t' y-, and {piv} does or does not have infinitely rnany rnembers in y-. Let the
q(p) = x(p) for pE Y-. (45) in dices in the second set be nurnbered 1, ... , r, and in the first,
r + 1, ... , m: It still has to be shown that r < m, that is, that for
Let P be any finite subset of Sn. We first establish that the sorne j, piv E y- for infinitely many v. For j > r, then, q(p1v) =
solutions of the inequalities,
x(p 1v) for infinitely many v, and p* is the limit of a sequence in y-;
u + .2; q(p)w(p) = x u :2: O, w(p) :2: O, since x(p) is continuous and y- is closed,
pEP
qi = x(p*) for j > r; p* E y- if r < m. (50)
are bounded uniformly in the choice of P. From (44) and (45), these
can be written, For j :o; r, -q(piv) E Y and p1v[-q(p1v)] > O, all v. Since Y is
el o sed,
u + .2; x(p)w(p) = .2; [-q(p)]w(p) + x. (46) -qiE Y, -p*qi ;:o: O forj :Sir. (51)
pePnY- peP~y-

Since -q(p) E Yfor p EP ~ y-, w(p) :2: O, all p, and Yis a convex Frorn (50) and (51), (48) can be rewritten
cone, u* + v*x(p*) = y* + x, (52)
2: (-q(p)]w(p) =y E Y. (47)
where
m
J>EP~Y
v* = .2; vj
Since the left-hand side of (46) is certainly non-negative, y E Y and 1= r+ 1

therefore is bounded. Then, since /-q(p)/ :2: M for pE P ~ y-, and


r
it follows from (47) that w(p) is uniformly bounded for such p. y* = .2; vj( -qi).
Also, frorn (41), x(p) 1= o for any pE sn> so that Jx(p)/ is bounded 1=1
away from O on Sn. since it is a continuous function. Since the Since Y is a convex cone, it follows from (51) that 1'
1

right-hand side of (46) is bounded, the left-hand side must be; thus,
both u and y* E Y p*y* :2: 0.
Premultiply both sides of (52) by p* and use (49) and (41):
.2; x(p)w(p)
pePnY (v* - 1)p*x = p*y*.
are bounded. But since Jx(p)J s bounded uniformly from below, it Then v* ;:o: 1, v* = 1 if p*y* = O. But v* > O certainly implies
must be that w(p) is bounded from abo ve for p E P n Y-. that r < m; from (50) and the definition of Y-, 1
Frorn the definitions (44) and (45), the function q(p) is certainly
bounded. Hence Lernma C.2 is applicable. p*y :Si o all y E Y,
m and certainly p*y* = Oand therefore v* = 1, so that (42) is satisfied. 1 ,1!1
11':

u* + .2; vjq1 = x u* :2: O, vj :2: O; (48) 1 Attention should be drawn to another algorithm for finding a competitive
1
,,
1

1= 1
equilibrium, dueto Cottle [1966]; it is applicable to economies in which a ~lig~1tly
for sorne set J*, uf = O for i E J ~ J*, pf = O for i E J*, so that stronger version of the GaJe property holds, specifically, where all the pnnc1paj 1

minors of the Jacobian of excess supplies are positive and bounded away from 1

p*u* =O, (49) zero and infinity.


BIBLIOGRAPHY 429
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arrow, K. J., and L. Hurwicz [1960]. "Competitive stability under
weak gross substitutability: the 'Euclidean distance' approach,"
International Economic Review, 1, 38-49.
Arrow, K. J., and L. Hurwicz [1962]. "Competitive equilibrium under
weak gross substitutability: non-linear price adjustment and
adaptive expectation," International Economic Review, 3, 233-
255.
Arrow, K. J., and M. Nerlove [1958]. "A note on expectations and
stability " Econometrica, 26, 297-305.
Aumann, R. J. [1964]. "Markets with a continuum of traders,"
Econometrica, 32, 39-50.
Aumann, R. J. [1966]. "Existence of competitive equilibria in markets
with a continuum of traders," Econometrica, 34, 1-17.
American Mathematical Society [1968]. The Mathematics of the
Bator, F. M. [1961]. "Convexity, efficiency, and markets," Journal of
Decision Sciences. Providence, Rhode Island: The American
Mathematical Society, 2 vols. Political Economy, 69, 480-483.
Becker, G. [1965]. "A theory of the allocation of time," Economic
Arrow, K. J. [1951]. "An extension of the basic theorems of classical
welfare economics," in J. Neyman (ed.), Proceedings of the Journal, 75, 495-517.
Bernoulli, D. [1738]. "Spe'cimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis,"
Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperiales Petropolitanae, 5,
Probability. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 507-
532. 175-192.
Bernoulli, D. [ 1954]. "Exposition of a new theory of the measurement
Arrow, K. J. [1953]. "Le role des valeurs boursieres pour la rpar-
of risk," Econometrica, 12, 23-36. English translation by L.
tition la meilleure des risques," Econometrie. Pars: Centre
National de la recherche scientifique, pp. 41-48. Sommer of Bernoulli [1738].
Bohm, P. [1963]. Externa! Economies in Pro~uction .. Stockholm:
Arrow, K. J. [1963]. "Uncertainty and the welfare economics of
Almqvist & Wiksell. Stockholm Econom1c Studies, Pamphlet
medica! care," American Economic Review, 53, 941-973. Re-
printed in Arrow [ 1970, pp. 177-219]. Series 3.
Bowen, R. [1968]. "A new proof of a tbeorem in utility theory,"
Arrow, K. J. [1963-1964]. "The role of securities in the optimal
International Economic Review, 9, 374.
allocation of risk-bearing," Review of Economic Studies, 31,
Burger, E. [1963]. Introduction to the Theory of Games. Englewood
91-96. English translation of Arrow [1953]. Reprinted in
Arrow [1970, 121-133]. Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Bushaw, D. W., and R. W. Clower [1957]. I~troduction to Mathe-
Arrow, K. J. [1965]. Aspects of the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Helsinki: matical Economics. Homewood, Ill.: Irwm.
Academic Bookstore. Reprinted in Arrow [1970, 44-120, Cassel, G. [1924]. The Theory of Social Economy. New York:
134-143]. Harcourt, Brace.
Arrow, K. J. [1968]. "Economic equilibrium," in International Encyclo- Chamberlin, E. H. [1948]. "Proportionality, divisibility, and econo-
pedia of the Social Sciences. Macmillan and the Free Press, 4, mies of scale," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 62, 229-262.
376-386. Chamberlin, E. H. [1949]. "Proportionality, divisibil~ty, and econo-
Arrow, K. J. [1970]. Essays in the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Chicago: mies of scale: reply," Quarterly Journal of Econom1cs, 63, 137-143.
Markham; London: North-Holland. Chamberlin, E. H. [1956]. The Theory of Monopolistic Competition, 7th
Arrow, K. J. [1971]. "The firm in general equilibrium theory," in Edition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
R. Marris andA. Wood (eds.), The Corporate Economy: Growth, Charnes, A. [1952]. "Optimality and degeneracy in linear program-
Competition, and Innovative Potential. London: Macmillan; ming," Econometrica, 17, 160-170. ..
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 68-110. Chipman, J. S. [ 1970]. "Externa] economies of scale and competitive
Arrow, K. J., H. D. Block, and L. Hurwicz [1959]. "On the stability equilibria," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 3~7-385. .
of the competitive equilibrium II," Econometrica, 27, 82-109. Clower, R. W. [1965]. "The Keynesian counterrevoluti~n: a tbeoreti-
Arrow, K. J., and G. Debreu [1954]. "Existence of equilibrium for a cal appraisal," in F. H. Hahn and F. P. R. Brecbhng (eds.), The
competitive economy," Econometrica, 22, 265-290. Theory of Interest Rates. London: Macmillan; New York: St.
Arrow, K. J. and L. Hurwicz [1958]. "On the stability of the competitive Martin's Press.
equilibrium I," Econometrica, 26, 522-552.

428
BIBLIOGRAPHY 429
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arrow, K. J., and L. Hurwicz [1960]. "Competitive stability under
weak gross substitutability: the 'Euclidean distance' approach,"
International Economic Review, 1, 38-49.
Arrow, K. J., and L. Hurwicz [1962]. "Competitive equilibrium under
weak gross substitutability: non-linear price adjustment and
adaptive expectation," International Economic Review, 3, 233-
255.
Arrow, K. J., and M. Nerlove [1958]. "A note on expectations and
stability " Econometrica, 26, 297-305.
Aumann, R. J. [1964]. "Markets with a continuum of traders,"
Econometrica, 32, 39-50.
Aumann, R. J. [1966]. "Existence of competitive equilibria in markets
with a continuum of traders," Econometrica, 34, 1-17.
American Mathematical Society [1968]. The Mathematics of the
Bator, F. M. [1961]. "Convexity, efficiency, and markets," Journal of
Decision Sciences. Providence, Rhode Island: The American
Mathematical Society, 2 vols. Political Economy, 69, 480-483.
Becker, G. [1965]. "A theory of the allocation of time," Economic
Arrow, K. J. [1951]. "An extension of the basic theorems of classical
welfare economics," in J. Neyman (ed.), Proceedings of the Journal, 75, 495-517.
Bernoulli, D. [1738]. "Spe'cimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis,"
Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperiales Petropolitanae, 5,
Probability. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 507-
532. 175-192.
Bernoulli, D. [ 1954]. "Exposition of a new theory of the measurement
Arrow, K. J. [1953]. "Le role des valeurs boursieres pour la rpar-
of risk," Econometrica, 12, 23-36. English translation by L.
tition la meilleure des risques," Econometrie. Pars: Centre
National de la recherche scientifique, pp. 41-48. Sommer of Bernoulli [1738].
Bohm, P. [1963]. Externa! Economies in Pro~uction .. Stockholm:
Arrow, K. J. [1963]. "Uncertainty and the welfare economics of
Almqvist & Wiksell. Stockholm Econom1c Studies, Pamphlet
medica! care," American Economic Review, 53, 941-973. Re-
printed in Arrow [ 1970, pp. 177-219]. Series 3.
Bowen, R. [1968]. "A new proof of a tbeorem in utility theory,"
Arrow, K. J. [1963-1964]. "The role of securities in the optimal
International Economic Review, 9, 374.
allocation of risk-bearing," Review of Economic Studies, 31,
Burger, E. [1963]. Introduction to the Theory of Games. Englewood
91-96. English translation of Arrow [1953]. Reprinted in
Arrow [1970, 121-133]. Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Bushaw, D. W., and R. W. Clower [1957]. I~troduction to Mathe-
Arrow, K. J. [1965]. Aspects of the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Helsinki: matical Economics. Homewood, Ill.: Irwm.
Academic Bookstore. Reprinted in Arrow [1970, 44-120, Cassel, G. [1924]. The Theory of Social Economy. New York:
134-143]. Harcourt, Brace.
Arrow, K. J. [1968]. "Economic equilibrium," in International Encyclo- Chamberlin, E. H. [1948]. "Proportionality, divisibility, and econo-
pedia of the Social Sciences. Macmillan and the Free Press, 4, mies of scale," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 62, 229-262.
376-386. Chamberlin, E. H. [1949]. "Proportionality, divisibil~ty, and econo-
Arrow, K. J. [1970]. Essays in the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Chicago: mies of scale: reply," Quarterly Journal of Econom1cs, 63, 137-143.
Markham; London: North-Holland. Chamberlin, E. H. [1956]. The Theory of Monopolistic Competition, 7th
Arrow, K. J. [1971]. "The firm in general equilibrium theory," in Edition. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
R. Marris andA. Wood (eds.), The Corporate Economy: Growth, Charnes, A. [1952]. "Optimality and degeneracy in linear program-
Competition, and Innovative Potential. London: Macmillan; ming," Econometrica, 17, 160-170. ..
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 68-110. Chipman, J. S. [ 1970]. "Externa] economies of scale and competitive
Arrow, K. J., H. D. Block, and L. Hurwicz [1959]. "On the stability equilibria," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 84, 3~7-385. .
of the competitive equilibrium II," Econometrica, 27, 82-109. Clower, R. W. [1965]. "The Keynesian counterrevoluti~n: a tbeoreti-
Arrow, K. J., and G. Debreu [1954]. "Existence of equilibrium for a cal appraisal," in F. H. Hahn and F. P. R. Brecbhng (eds.), The
competitive economy," Econometrica, 22, 265-290. Theory of Interest Rates. London: Macmillan; New York: St.
Arrow, K. J. and L. Hurwicz [1958]. "On the stability of the competitive Martin's Press.
equilibrium I," Econometrica, 26, 522-552.

428
430 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Coddington, E. A., and N. Levinson [1955]. Theory of Ordinary


l BIBLIOGRAPHY

Georgescu-Roegen, N. [1951]. "Sorne properties of a generalized


431

Differential Equations. New York: McGraw-Hill. Leontief model," in Koopmans [1951a, Chapter X, 165-173].
Cottle, R. W. [1966]. "Nonlinear programs with positively bounded Reprinted in enlarged form in N. Georgescu-Roegen [1966].
Jacobians," SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 14, 147-158. Analytical Economics. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Cottle, R. W., and G. B. Dantzig [1968]. "Complementary pivot Press, Chapter 9, pp. 316-337.
theory o{ mathematical programming," in American Mathe- Gillies, O. B. [1953]. "Sorne theorems on n-person games." Ph.D.
matical Society [1968, I: 115-136]. thesis, Princeton University.
Cournot, A. A. [1838]. Reherches sur les prncipes mathmatiques de Glustoff, E. [1968]. "On the existence of a Keynesian equilibrium,"
la thorie des richesses. Paris: Librairie des sciences poli tiques Review of Economic Studies, 35, 327-334.
et sociales, ,M. Riviere & cie. Translated by Nathaniel T. Bacon Gorman, W. M. [1953]. "Community preference fields," Econometrica,
[1897]. Researches into the Mathematical Principies ofthe Theory 21, 63-80.
of Wealth. New York: Macmillan. Gorman, W. M. [1964]. "More scope for qualitative economics,"
!
Dantzig, G. B. [1951]. "Application of the simplex method to a Review of Economic Studies, 31, 65-68 .
. 1
transportation problem," in Koopmans [1951a], Chapter XXIII, Hahn, F. H. [1949]. "Proportionality, divisibility, and economies of
11
1' pp. 359-373. scale: comment," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 63, 131-137.
Dantzig, G. B., A. Orden, and P. Wolfe [1955]. "The generalized Hahn, F. H. [1958]. "Gross substitutes and the dynamic. stability of
simplex method for minimizing a linear form under inequality general equilibrium," Econometrica, 26, 169-170.
restraints," Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 5, 183-195. Hahn, F. H. [1962]. "On the stability of pure exchange equilibrium,"
Debreu, G. [1951]. "The coeflicient of resource utilization," Econo- International Economic Review, 3, 206-213.
metrica, 19, 273-292. Hahn, F. H. [1965]. "On sorne problems in proving the existence of
Debreu, G. [1954]. "Representation of a preference ordering by a equilibrium in a monetary economy," in F. H. Hahn and F. P. R.
numerical function," in R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, and R. L. Brechling (eds.), The Theory of Interest Rates. London: Mac-
Davis (eds.), Decision Processes. New York: Wiley; London: millan; New York: St. Martin's Press.
Chapman & Hall, Chapter XI, pp. 159-166. Hahn, F. H., and T. Negishi [1962]. "A theorem on non-tatonnement
Debreu, G. [1959]. Theory of Value. New York: Wiley. stability," Econometrica, 30, 463-469.
Debreu, G. [1962]. "New concepts and techniques for equilibrium Hahn, W. [1959]. Theorie und Anwendung der direkten Methoden von
analysis," International Economic Review, 3, 257-273. Lyapunov. Berlin: Springer.
Debreu, G. [1964]. "Continuity properties of Paretian utility," Hansen, T., and H. Scarf [1969]. ''On the applications of a recent
Interna.tional Economic Review, 5, 285-293. combinatoria) algorithm." Cowles Foundation Discussion
Debreu, G. [ 1970]. "Economies with a finite set of equilibria," Paper, No. 272.
Econometrica, 38, 387-392. Hawkins, D., and H. Simon [1949]. "Note: sorne conditions of
Debreu, G., and H. Scarf [1963]. "A Iimit theorem on the core of an macroeconomic stability," Econometrica, 17, 245-248.
economy," International Economic Review, 4, 235-246. Hicks, J. R. [1939]. Value and Capital. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Edgeworth, F. Y. [1881]. Mathematical Psychics. London: C. Kegan Hicks, J. R. [1965]. Capital and Growth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Paul. Hildenbrand, W. [1970]. "On economies with many agents," Journal
Eilenberg, S. [1941]. "Ordered topological spaces," American Journal of Economic Theory, 2, 161-188.
of Mathematics, 63, 37-45. Hotelling, H. [1932]. "Edgeworth's taxation paradox and the nature
Enthoven, A. C., and K. J. Arrow [1956]. "A theorem on expectations of demand and supply functions," Journal of Political Economy,
and the stability of equilibrium," Econometrica, 24, 288-293. 40, 571-616.
Farrell, M. J. [1959]. "The convexity assumption in the theory of lsnard, A. N. [1781]. Trait des richesses. London.
competitive markets," Journal of Political Economy, 61, 377-391. Jenkin, F. [1870]. "The graphic representation of the laws of supply
de Finetti, B. [1937]. "La prvision: ses lois logiques, ses sources and demand, and other essays on political economy," in Sir
subjectives," Annales de l'lnstitut Henri Poincar, 1, 1-68. Alexander Grant (ed.), Recess Studies, pp. 76-106. Edinburgh.
English translation by H. E. Kyburg in Kyburg and Smokler Reprinted in 1931. No. 9 in series of Reprints of Scarce Tracts
[1964, 95-158]. in Economic and Political Science. London: London School of
Gale, D. [ 1957]. "General equilibrium for linear models." Unpublished. Economics.
Gale, D., and H. Nikaido [1965]. "The Jacobian matrix and global Kakutani, S. [1941]. "A generalization of Brouwer's fixed-point
univalence of mappings," Mathematische Annalen, 159, 81-93. theorem," Duke Mathematical Journal, 8, 451--459.
430 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS

Coddington, E. A., and N. Levinson [1955]. Theory of Ordinary


l BIBLIOGRAPHY

Georgescu-Roegen, N. [1951]. "Sorne properties of a generalized


431

Differential Equations. New York: McGraw-Hill. Leontief model," in Koopmans [1951a, Chapter X, 165-173].
Cottle, R. W. [1966]. "Nonlinear programs with positively bounded Reprinted in enlarged form in N. Georgescu-Roegen [1966].
Jacobians," SIAM Journal of Applied Mathematics, 14, 147-158. Analytical Economics. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Cottle, R. W., and G. B. Dantzig [1968]. "Complementary pivot Press, Chapter 9, pp. 316-337.
theory o{ mathematical programming," in American Mathe- Gillies, O. B. [1953]. "Sorne theorems on n-person games." Ph.D.
matical Society [1968, I: 115-136]. thesis, Princeton University.
Cournot, A. A. [1838]. Reherches sur les prncipes mathmatiques de Glustoff, E. [1968]. "On the existence of a Keynesian equilibrium,"
la thorie des richesses. Paris: Librairie des sciences poli tiques Review of Economic Studies, 35, 327-334.
et sociales, ,M. Riviere & cie. Translated by Nathaniel T. Bacon Gorman, W. M. [1953]. "Community preference fields," Econometrica,
[1897]. Researches into the Mathematical Principies ofthe Theory 21, 63-80.
of Wealth. New York: Macmillan. Gorman, W. M. [1964]. "More scope for qualitative economics,"
!
Dantzig, G. B. [1951]. "Application of the simplex method to a Review of Economic Studies, 31, 65-68 .
. 1
transportation problem," in Koopmans [1951a], Chapter XXIII, Hahn, F. H. [1949]. "Proportionality, divisibility, and economies of
11
1' pp. 359-373. scale: comment," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 63, 131-137.
Dantzig, G. B., A. Orden, and P. Wolfe [1955]. "The generalized Hahn, F. H. [1958]. "Gross substitutes and the dynamic. stability of
simplex method for minimizing a linear form under inequality general equilibrium," Econometrica, 26, 169-170.
restraints," Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 5, 183-195. Hahn, F. H. [1962]. "On the stability of pure exchange equilibrium,"
Debreu, G. [1951]. "The coeflicient of resource utilization," Econo- International Economic Review, 3, 206-213.
metrica, 19, 273-292. Hahn, F. H. [1965]. "On sorne problems in proving the existence of
Debreu, G. [1954]. "Representation of a preference ordering by a equilibrium in a monetary economy," in F. H. Hahn and F. P. R.
numerical function," in R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, and R. L. Brechling (eds.), The Theory of Interest Rates. London: Mac-
Davis (eds.), Decision Processes. New York: Wiley; London: millan; New York: St. Martin's Press.
Chapman & Hall, Chapter XI, pp. 159-166. Hahn, F. H., and T. Negishi [1962]. "A theorem on non-tatonnement
Debreu, G. [1959]. Theory of Value. New York: Wiley. stability," Econometrica, 30, 463-469.
Debreu, G. [1962]. "New concepts and techniques for equilibrium Hahn, W. [1959]. Theorie und Anwendung der direkten Methoden von
analysis," International Economic Review, 3, 257-273. Lyapunov. Berlin: Springer.
Debreu, G. [1964]. "Continuity properties of Paretian utility," Hansen, T., and H. Scarf [1969]. ''On the applications of a recent
Interna.tional Economic Review, 5, 285-293. combinatoria) algorithm." Cowles Foundation Discussion
Debreu, G. [ 1970]. "Economies with a finite set of equilibria," Paper, No. 272.
Econometrica, 38, 387-392. Hawkins, D., and H. Simon [1949]. "Note: sorne conditions of
Debreu, G., and H. Scarf [1963]. "A Iimit theorem on the core of an macroeconomic stability," Econometrica, 17, 245-248.
economy," International Economic Review, 4, 235-246. Hicks, J. R. [1939]. Value and Capital. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Edgeworth, F. Y. [1881]. Mathematical Psychics. London: C. Kegan Hicks, J. R. [1965]. Capital and Growth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Paul. Hildenbrand, W. [1970]. "On economies with many agents," Journal
Eilenberg, S. [1941]. "Ordered topological spaces," American Journal of Economic Theory, 2, 161-188.
of Mathematics, 63, 37-45. Hotelling, H. [1932]. "Edgeworth's taxation paradox and the nature
Enthoven, A. C., and K. J. Arrow [1956]. "A theorem on expectations of demand and supply functions," Journal of Political Economy,
and the stability of equilibrium," Econometrica, 24, 288-293. 40, 571-616.
Farrell, M. J. [1959]. "The convexity assumption in the theory of lsnard, A. N. [1781]. Trait des richesses. London.
competitive markets," Journal of Political Economy, 61, 377-391. Jenkin, F. [1870]. "The graphic representation of the laws of supply
de Finetti, B. [1937]. "La prvision: ses lois logiques, ses sources and demand, and other essays on political economy," in Sir
subjectives," Annales de l'lnstitut Henri Poincar, 1, 1-68. Alexander Grant (ed.), Recess Studies, pp. 76-106. Edinburgh.
English translation by H. E. Kyburg in Kyburg and Smokler Reprinted in 1931. No. 9 in series of Reprints of Scarce Tracts
[1964, 95-158]. in Economic and Political Science. London: London School of
Gale, D. [ 1957]. "General equilibrium for linear models." Unpublished. Economics.
Gale, D., and H. Nikaido [1965]. "The Jacobian matrix and global Kakutani, S. [1941]. "A generalization of Brouwer's fixed-point
univalence of mappings," Mathematische Annalen, 159, 81-93. theorem," Duke Mathematical Journal, 8, 451--459.
1 1
!

1
432 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
BIBLIOGRAPHY 433
Kaldor, N. [1935]. "Market imperfection and excess capacity," McKenzie, L. [1954]. "On equilibrium in Graham's model of world
Economica N.S., 2, 33-50.
trade and other competitive systems," Econometrica, 22, 147-161.
Karlin, S. [1959]. Mathematical Methods and Theory in Games,
McKenzie, L. [1955a]. "Equality of factor prices in world trade,"
Programming, and Economics. Reading, Mass.: Addison-
Wesley, 2 vols. Econometrica, 23, 239-257.
McKenzie, L. [1955b]. "Competitive equilibrium with dependent
Karlin, S., and L. S. Shapley [1953]. "Geometry of moment spaces"
consumer preferences," in National Bureau of Standards and
Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, 12. '
Department of the Air Force, The Second Symposium on Linear
Keynes, J. M. [1936]. The General Theory of Employment Interest and
Money. New York: Harcourt, Brace. Programming. Washington, D.C.
McKenzie, L. [1956-57]. "Demand theory without a utility index,"
Knight, F. H. [1935]. "The Ricardian theory of production and
distribution," Canadian Journal of Economic and Po!itical Review of Economic Studies, 24, 185-189.
McKenzie, L. [1959]. "On the existence of general equilibrium for
Science, 1, 3-25, 171-196. Reprinted in Frank H. Knight
a competitive market," Econometrica, 27, 54-71.
[ 1956]. On the History and Method of Economics. Chicago:
McKenzie, L. [ 1960a]. "Stability of equilibrium and the val u e of
University of Chicago Press, pp. 37-88.
positive excess demand," Econometrica, 28, 606-617.
Koopmans, T. C. (ed.) [1951a]. Activity Analysis of Allocation and
McKenzie, L. [1960b]. "Matrices with dominant diagonal and
Production. New York: Wiley.
economic theory," in K. J. Arrow, S. Karlin, and P. Suppes
Koopmans, T. C. [1951b]. "Analysis of production asan effident
(eds.), Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, 1959.
combination of activities," in Koopmans [1951a], Chapter III,
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, Chapter 4, pp. 47-62.
pp, 33-97.
McKenzie, L. [1961]. "On the existence of general equilibrium: sorne
Kuhn, H. W .. [1968]. "Simplicial approximation of fixed points,"
corrections," Econometrica, 29, 247-248.
Proceedmgs of the National Academy of Sciences, 61, 1238-1242.
Menger, K. [1954]. "The laws of return; a study in metaeconomics,"
Kyburg, H. E., Jr., and H. E. Smokler (eds.) [1964]. Studies in Sub-
in O. Morgenstern (ed.), Economic Activlty Analysis. New
jective Probabi!ity. New York: Wiley.
York: Wiley, pp. 419-481.
Lancaster, K. [1 961-62]. "The scope of qualitative economics,"
Metzler, L. [1945]. "The stability of multiple markets: the Hicks
Review of Economic Studies, 29, 99-123.
conditions," Econometrica, 13, 277-292.
Lancaster, K. [1964]. "Partitionable systems and qualitative eco-
Morishima, M. [1952]. "On the Jaw of change of price-system in an
nomics," Review of Economic Studies, 31, 69-72.
economy which contains complementary commodities," Osaka
Lancaster, K. [1965]. "The theory of qualitative linear systems"
Econometrica, 33, 395-408. ' Economic Papers, 1, 101-113.
Morishima, M. [1959]. "Gross substitutability, homogeneity, and the
La Salle, J., and S. Lefschetz [1961]. Stability by Lyapounov's Direct
Walras' Law." Unpublished manuscript.
Method with Applications. New York: Academic Press.
Morishima, M. [ 1959-60]. "On the three Hicksian Iaws of compara-
Leijonhufvud, A. [1968]. On Keynesian Economics and the Economics
tive statics," Review of Economic Studies, 27, 195-201.
of Keynes: A Study of Monetary Theory. New York: Oxford
Morishima, M, [1964]. Equilibrium, Stability, and Growth. Oxford:
University Press.
Lemke, C. [1968]. "On complementary pivot theory," in American Clarendon Press.
Mosak, Jacob L. [1944]. General Equilibrium Theory in International
Mathematical Society [1968, 1: 95-1 14].
Trade. Bloomington, Indiana: Principia Press.
Lemke, C., and J. T. Howson, Jr. [1964]. "Equilibrium points of
Nash, J. F., Jr. [1950]. "Equilibrium in N-person games," Proceedings
bimatrix games," Journal of the Society for Industrial and Applied
of the National Academy of Sciences, 36, 48-49.
Mathematics, 12, 412-423.
Nataf, A. [1953]. "Possibilit d'agrgation dans le cadre de la thorie
Leontief, W. W. [1936]. "Composite commodities and the problem
of indcx numbers," Econometrica, 4, 39-59. des choix," Metroeconomica, 5, 22-30.
Negishi, T. [1958]. "A note on the stability of an economy where all
Leontief, W. W. [194~1: The Structure ofthe American Economy, 1919-
goods are gross substitutes," Econometrica, 26, 445-447.
1939, F1rst Edltwn. New York: Oxford University Press.
Negishi, T. [1960]. "Welfare economics and existence of an equi-
Lyapounov, A. [1947]. Probleme gnral de la stabilit du mouvement;
librium for a competitive economy," Metroeconomica, 12, 92-97.
Annals of Mathematics Study 17. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
Negishi, T. [1960-61]. "Monopolistic competition and general
University Press.
equilibrium," Review of Economic Studies, 28, 196-201.
Marris, R. [1964]. The Economic Theory of"Managerial" Capitalism.
Negishi, T. [1961]. "On the formation of prices," International
New York: Free Press.
Economic Review, 2, 122-126.
1 1
!

1
432 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS
BIBLIOGRAPHY 433
Kaldor, N. [1935]. "Market imperfection and excess capacity," McKenzie, L. [1954]. "On equilibrium in Graham's model of world
Economica N.S., 2, 33-50.
trade and other competitive systems," Econometrica, 22, 147-161.
Karlin, S. [1959]. Mathematical Methods and Theory in Games,
McKenzie, L. [1955a]. "Equality of factor prices in world trade,"
Programming, and Economics. Reading, Mass.: Addison-
Wesley, 2 vols. Econometrica, 23, 239-257.
McKenzie, L. [1955b]. "Competitive equilibrium with dependent
Karlin, S., and L. S. Shapley [1953]. "Geometry of moment spaces"
consumer preferences," in National Bureau of Standards and
Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, 12. '
Department of the Air Force, The Second Symposium on Linear
Keynes, J. M. [1936]. The General Theory of Employment Interest and
Money. New York: Harcourt, Brace. Programming. Washington, D.C.
McKenzie, L. [1956-57]. "Demand theory without a utility index,"
Knight, F. H. [1935]. "The Ricardian theory of production and
distribution," Canadian Journal of Economic and Po!itical Review of Economic Studies, 24, 185-189.
McKenzie, L. [1959]. "On the existence of general equilibrium for
Science, 1, 3-25, 171-196. Reprinted in Frank H. Knight
a competitive market," Econometrica, 27, 54-71.
[ 1956]. On the History and Method of Economics. Chicago:
McKenzie, L. [ 1960a]. "Stability of equilibrium and the val u e of
University of Chicago Press, pp. 37-88.
positive excess demand," Econometrica, 28, 606-617.
Koopmans, T. C. (ed.) [1951a]. Activity Analysis of Allocation and
McKenzie, L. [1960b]. "Matrices with dominant diagonal and
Production. New York: Wiley.
economic theory," in K. J. Arrow, S. Karlin, and P. Suppes
Koopmans, T. C. [1951b]. "Analysis of production asan effident
(eds.), Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, 1959.
combination of activities," in Koopmans [1951a], Chapter III,
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, Chapter 4, pp. 47-62.
pp, 33-97.
McKenzie, L. [1961]. "On the existence of general equilibrium: sorne
Kuhn, H. W .. [1968]. "Simplicial approximation of fixed points,"
corrections," Econometrica, 29, 247-248.
Proceedmgs of the National Academy of Sciences, 61, 1238-1242.
Menger, K. [1954]. "The laws of return; a study in metaeconomics,"
Kyburg, H. E., Jr., and H. E. Smokler (eds.) [1964]. Studies in Sub-
in O. Morgenstern (ed.), Economic Activlty Analysis. New
jective Probabi!ity. New York: Wiley.
York: Wiley, pp. 419-481.
Lancaster, K. [1 961-62]. "The scope of qualitative economics,"
Metzler, L. [1945]. "The stability of multiple markets: the Hicks
Review of Economic Studies, 29, 99-123.
conditions," Econometrica, 13, 277-292.
Lancaster, K. [1964]. "Partitionable systems and qualitative eco-
Morishima, M. [1952]. "On the Jaw of change of price-system in an
nomics," Review of Economic Studies, 31, 69-72.
economy which contains complementary commodities," Osaka
Lancaster, K. [1965]. "The theory of qualitative linear systems"
Econometrica, 33, 395-408. ' Economic Papers, 1, 101-113.
Morishima, M. [1959]. "Gross substitutability, homogeneity, and the
La Salle, J., and S. Lefschetz [1961]. Stability by Lyapounov's Direct
Walras' Law." Unpublished manuscript.
Method with Applications. New York: Academic Press.
Morishima, M. [ 1959-60]. "On the three Hicksian Iaws of compara-
Leijonhufvud, A. [1968]. On Keynesian Economics and the Economics
tive statics," Review of Economic Studies, 27, 195-201.
of Keynes: A Study of Monetary Theory. New York: Oxford
Morishima, M, [1964]. Equilibrium, Stability, and Growth. Oxford:
University Press.
Lemke, C. [1968]. "On complementary pivot theory," in American Clarendon Press.
Mosak, Jacob L. [1944]. General Equilibrium Theory in International
Mathematical Society [1968, 1: 95-1 14].
Trade. Bloomington, Indiana: Principia Press.
Lemke, C., and J. T. Howson, Jr. [1964]. "Equilibrium points of
Nash, J. F., Jr. [1950]. "Equilibrium in N-person games," Proceedings
bimatrix games," Journal of the Society for Industrial and Applied
of the National Academy of Sciences, 36, 48-49.
Mathematics, 12, 412-423.
Nataf, A. [1953]. "Possibilit d'agrgation dans le cadre de la thorie
Leontief, W. W. [1936]. "Composite commodities and the problem
of indcx numbers," Econometrica, 4, 39-59. des choix," Metroeconomica, 5, 22-30.
Negishi, T. [1958]. "A note on the stability of an economy where all
Leontief, W. W. [194~1: The Structure ofthe American Economy, 1919-
goods are gross substitutes," Econometrica, 26, 445-447.
1939, F1rst Edltwn. New York: Oxford University Press.
Negishi, T. [1960]. "Welfare economics and existence of an equi-
Lyapounov, A. [1947]. Probleme gnral de la stabilit du mouvement;
librium for a competitive economy," Metroeconomica, 12, 92-97.
Annals of Mathematics Study 17. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
Negishi, T. [1960-61]. "Monopolistic competition and general
University Press.
equilibrium," Review of Economic Studies, 28, 196-201.
Marris, R. [1964]. The Economic Theory of"Managerial" Capitalism.
Negishi, T. [1961]. "On the formation of prices," International
New York: Free Press.
Economic Review, 2, 122-126.
l
434 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS BIBLIOGRAPHY 435

Negishi, T. [1964]. "Stability of exchange and adaptive expectations," Samuelson, P. A. [1941, 1942]. "The stability of equilibrium,"
International Economic Review, 5, 104-111. Econometrica, 9, 97-120; 10, 1-25. Reprinted in Samuelson
Neisser, H. [1932]. "Lohnhohe und Beschaftigungsgrad im Markt- [1966, 1: 539-562, 565-589].
gleichgewicht," Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 36, 415-455. Samuelson, P. A. [1947]. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cam-
von Neumann, J. [1937]. "ber ein okonomisches Gleichungssystem bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
und eine Verallgemeinerung des Brouwerschen Fixpunktsatzes," Samuelson, P. A. [1948]. "International trade and the equalisation of
Ergebnisse eines Mathematischen Kolloquiums, 8, 73-83. factor prices," Economic Journal, 58, 163-184. Reprinted in
von Neumann, J. [1945]. "A model of general'economic equilibrium," Samuelson [1966, 11: 847-868].
Review of Economic Studies, 13, 1-9. English translation of Samuelson, P. A. [1951]. "Abstract of a theorem concerning sub-
von Neumann [1937]. stitutability in open Leontief Models," in Koopmans [1951a,
von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern [1944]. TAeory of Games and Chapter VII, 142-146]. Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, 1:
Economic Behavior. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. 515-519]. .
von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern [1947]. Theory of Games and Samuelson, P. A. [1953-54]. "Prices of factors and goods in general
Economic Behavior, Second Edition. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton equilibriurr\," Review of Economic Studies, 21, 1-20. Reprinted
University Press. in Samuelson [1966, 11: 888-908].
Nikaido, H. [1956]. "On the classical multilateral exchange problem," Sarnuelson, P. A. [1957]. "Wages and interest: a modern dissection of
Metroeconomica, S, 135-145. Marxian economic models," American Economic Review, 47,
Nikaido, H., and H. Uzawa [1960]. "Stability and non-negativity in a 884~912. Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, 1: 341-369].
Walrasian tatonnement process," lnternational Economic Review, Samuelson, P. A. [1959]. "A modern treatment of the Ricardian
1, 50-59. economy," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 73, 1-35, 217-231.
Nishino, H. [1970]. "Kokan-keisai no Core to sono Kyokugenteiri" Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, I: 373-421].
(The cores of exchange economies and the Iimit theorems), in Samuelson, P. A. [1966]. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
M. Suzuki (ed.), Kyoso-shakai no Game no Riron (Theory of Samuelson. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 2 vols.
Games in Competitive Society). Tokyo: Keiso-shobo, pp. 131- Samuelson, p, A., and W. F. Stolper [1941-42]. "Protection and real
168. wages," Review of Economic Studies, 9, 58-73. Reprinted in
Pareto, V. [1909]. Manueld'conomiepolitique. Pars: Girard &Briere. Samuelson [1966, 11: 831-846].
Pearce, I. F. [1967]. "More about factor price equalization," Inter- Savage, L. J. [1954]. TheFoundationsofStatistics. NewYork: Wiley.
national Economic Review, S, 255-270. Scarf, H. [1962]. "An analysis of markets with a large number of
Pearce, I. F., and J. Wise [forthcoming]. "On the uniqueness of com- participants," Recent Advances in Game Theory. Princeton,
petitive equilibrium." N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Quirk, J. P. [1968]. "Comparative statics under Walras' law: the case Scarf, H. [1967a]. "The core of an N-person game," Econometrica,
of strong dependence," Review of Economic Studies, 35, 11-21. 35, 50-69.
Rader, J. T. [1963]. "The existence of a utility function to represent Scarf, H. [1967b]. "On the approximation of fixed points of a con-
preferences," Review of Economic Studies, 30, 229-232. tinuous mapping," SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 15,
Radner, R. [1968]. "Competitive equilibrium under uncertainty," 1328-1343.
Econometrica, 36, 31-58. Scarf, H. [1967c]. "On the computation of equilibrium prices," in W.
Ramsey, F. P. [1926]. "Truth and Probability," in F. P. Ramsey Fellner et al., Ten Economic Studies .in the Tradition of Irving
[1931]. The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Fisher. New York: Wiley, Chapter 8.
Essays. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., pp. 156- Schelling, T. C. [1960]. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, Mass.:
198. Reprinted in Kyburg and Smokler [1964, 63-92]. Harvard University Press.
Robinson, J. [1933]. The Economics of lmperfect Competition. Schlesinger, K, [1933-34]. "ber die Produktionsgleichungen der
London: Macmillan. okonomische Wertlehre," Ergebnisse eines mathematischen
Rothenberg, J. [1960]. "Non-convexity, aggregation, and Pareto Kolloquiums, 6, 10-11.
optimality," Journal of Political Economy, 68, 435-468. Scitovsky, T. [1944-45]. "Sorne consequences of the ha bit of judging
Rybczynski, T. M. [1955]. "Factor endowment and relative com- quality by price," Review of Economic Studies, 12, 100-105.
modity prices," Economica N.S., 22, 336-341. Shubik, M. [1959]. "Edgeworth market games," in A. W. Tucker and
Saito, M. [1961]. "Professor Debreu on 'Theory of Value'; a review R. D. Luce (eds.), Contributions to the Theory of Games, IV.
article," International Economic Review, 2, 231-237. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
l
434 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANALYSIS BIBLIOGRAPHY 435

Negishi, T. [1964]. "Stability of exchange and adaptive expectations," Samuelson, P. A. [1941, 1942]. "The stability of equilibrium,"
International Economic Review, 5, 104-111. Econometrica, 9, 97-120; 10, 1-25. Reprinted in Samuelson
Neisser, H. [1932]. "Lohnhohe und Beschaftigungsgrad im Markt- [1966, 1: 539-562, 565-589].
gleichgewicht," Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 36, 415-455. Samuelson, P. A. [1947]. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Cam-
von Neumann, J. [1937]. "ber ein okonomisches Gleichungssystem bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
und eine Verallgemeinerung des Brouwerschen Fixpunktsatzes," Samuelson, P. A. [1948]. "International trade and the equalisation of
Ergebnisse eines Mathematischen Kolloquiums, 8, 73-83. factor prices," Economic Journal, 58, 163-184. Reprinted in
von Neumann, J. [1945]. "A model of general'economic equilibrium," Samuelson [1966, 11: 847-868].
Review of Economic Studies, 13, 1-9. English translation of Samuelson, P. A. [1951]. "Abstract of a theorem concerning sub-
von Neumann [1937]. stitutability in open Leontief Models," in Koopmans [1951a,
von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern [1944]. TAeory of Games and Chapter VII, 142-146]. Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, 1:
Economic Behavior. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. 515-519]. .
von Neumann, J., and O. Morgenstern [1947]. Theory of Games and Samuelson, P. A. [1953-54]. "Prices of factors and goods in general
Economic Behavior, Second Edition. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton equilibriurr\," Review of Economic Studies, 21, 1-20. Reprinted
University Press. in Samuelson [1966, 11: 888-908].
Nikaido, H. [1956]. "On the classical multilateral exchange problem," Sarnuelson, P. A. [1957]. "Wages and interest: a modern dissection of
Metroeconomica, S, 135-145. Marxian economic models," American Economic Review, 47,
Nikaido, H., and H. Uzawa [1960]. "Stability and non-negativity in a 884~912. Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, 1: 341-369].
Walrasian tatonnement process," lnternational Economic Review, Samuelson, P. A. [1959]. "A modern treatment of the Ricardian
1, 50-59. economy," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 73, 1-35, 217-231.
Nishino, H. [1970]. "Kokan-keisai no Core to sono Kyokugenteiri" Reprinted in Samuelson [1966, I: 373-421].
(The cores of exchange economies and the Iimit theorems), in Samuelson, P. A. [1966]. The Collected Scientific Papers of Paul A.
M. Suzuki (ed.), Kyoso-shakai no Game no Riron (Theory of Samuelson. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 2 vols.
Games in Competitive Society). Tokyo: Keiso-shobo, pp. 131- Samuelson, p, A., and W. F. Stolper [1941-42]. "Protection and real
168. wages," Review of Economic Studies, 9, 58-73. Reprinted in
Pareto, V. [1909]. Manueld'conomiepolitique. Pars: Girard &Briere. Samuelson [1966, 11: 831-846].
Pearce, I. F. [1967]. "More about factor price equalization," Inter- Savage, L. J. [1954]. TheFoundationsofStatistics. NewYork: Wiley.
national Economic Review, S, 255-270. Scarf, H. [1962]. "An analysis of markets with a large number of
Pearce, I. F., and J. Wise [forthcoming]. "On the uniqueness of com- participants," Recent Advances in Game Theory. Princeton,
petitive equilibrium." N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Quirk, J. P. [1968]. "Comparative statics under Walras' law: the case Scarf, H. [1967a]. "The core of an N-person game," Econometrica,
of strong dependence," Review of Economic Studies, 35, 11-21. 35, 50-69.
Rader, J. T. [1963]. "The existence of a utility function to represent Scarf, H. [1967b]. "On the approximation of fixed points of a con-
preferences," Review of Economic Studies, 30, 229-232. tinuous mapping," SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 15,
Radner, R. [1968]. "Competitive equilibrium under uncertainty," 1328-1343.
Econometrica, 36, 31-58. Scarf, H. [1967c]. "On the computation of equilibrium prices," in W.
Ramsey, F. P. [1926]. "Truth and Probability," in F. P. Ramsey Fellner et al., Ten Economic Studies .in the Tradition of Irving
[1931]. The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Fisher. New York: Wiley, Chapter 8.
Essays. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., pp. 156- Schelling, T. C. [1960]. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, Mass.:
198. Reprinted in Kyburg and Smokler [1964, 63-92]. Harvard University Press.
Robinson, J. [1933]. The Economics of lmperfect Competition. Schlesinger, K, [1933-34]. "ber die Produktionsgleichungen der
London: Macmillan. okonomische Wertlehre," Ergebnisse eines mathematischen
Rothenberg, J. [1960]. "Non-convexity, aggregation, and Pareto Kolloquiums, 6, 10-11.
optimality," Journal of Political Economy, 68, 435-468. Scitovsky, T. [1944-45]. "Sorne consequences of the ha bit of judging
Rybczynski, T. M. [1955]. "Factor endowment and relative com- quality by price," Review of Economic Studies, 12, 100-105.
modity prices," Economica N.S., 22, 336-341. Shubik, M. [1959]. "Edgeworth market games," in A. W. Tucker and
Saito, M. [1961]. "Professor Debreu on 'Theory of Value'; a review R. D. Luce (eds.), Contributions to the Theory of Games, IV.
article," International Economic Review, 2, 231-237. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
ri
T
436 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS BIBLIOGRAPHY 437

Slutzky, E. [1915]. "Suiia teoria del bilancio del consumatore," Wold, H. [1943-44]. "A synthesis of pure demand analysis," I-III,
Giornale degli Economisti, 51, 19-23. Skandinavisk Aktuarietidskrift, 26, 85-118, 220-263; 27, 69-120.
von Stackelberg, H. [1933]. "Zwei Kritische bemerkungen zur preis- Zeuthen, F. [1932]. "Das Prinzip der Knappheit, technische Kom-
theorie Gustav Cassels," Zeitschrift fr Nationalokonomie, 4, bination und i:ikonomische Quiilitat," Zeitschrift fr National-
456-472. okonomie, 4, 1-24.
Starr, R. [1969]. "Quasi-equilibria in markets with nonconvex
preferences," Econometrica, 37, 25-38.
Theocharis, R. [1961]. Early Developments in Mathematical Economics.
London: Macmillan.
Tompkins, C. B. [ 1964 ]. "Sperner's lemma and sorne extensions," in
li
E. F. Beckenbach (ed.), Applied Combinatoria! Mathematics.
New York: Wiley, Chapter 15. ',,
1

Triffin, R. [1940]. Monopolistic Competition and General Equilibrium


Theory. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Uzawa, H. [1958]. "Gradient method for concave programming, II:
global stability in the strictly concave case," in K. J. Arrow, L.
Hurwicz, and H. Uzawa, Studies in Linear and Non-Linear
Programming. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press,
Chapter 7, pp. 127-132.
Uzawa, H. [1959-60]. "Walras' tatonnement in the theory of ex-
change," Review of Economic Studies, 27, 182-194.
Uzawa, H. [1961]. "The stability of dynamic processes," Econometrica,
29, 617-631.
Uzawa, H. [1962]. "On the stability of Edgeworth's barter process,"
International Economic Review, 3, 218-232.
Veblen, T. [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. New York:
Macmiiian.
Wald, A. [1933-34]. "ber die eindeutige positive Li:isbarkeit der
ii neuen Produktions-gleichungen," Ergebnisse eines mathema-
tischen Ko/loquiums, 6, 12-20.
Wald, A. [1934-35]. "ber die Produktionsgleichungen der i:ikono-
: 1
mische Wertlehre," Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums,
1

7, 1-6.
Wald, A. [1936]. "ber einige Gleichungssysteme der mathematischen
Okonomie," Zeitschrift fr Nationa!Okonomie, 7, 637-670.
Wald, A. [1951]. "On sorne systems of equations of mathematical
economics," Econometrica, 19, 368-403. English translation of
Wald [1936].
Walras, L. [1874, 1877]. Elments d'conomie politique pure. Lau-
sanne: L. Corbaz. English translation of the definitive edition
by William Jaff [1954]. Elements of Pure Economics. London:
AIIen and Unwin.
Whitin, T. M., and M. H. Peston [1954]. "Random variations, risk,
and returns to scale," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 68,
603-612.
Williamson, O. E. [1964]. The Economics of Discretionary Behavior:
Managerial Objectives in a Theory of the Firm. Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
ri
T
436 GENERAL COMPETITIVE ANAL YSIS BIBLIOGRAPHY 437

Slutzky, E. [1915]. "Suiia teoria del bilancio del consumatore," Wold, H. [1943-44]. "A synthesis of pure demand analysis," I-III,
Giornale degli Economisti, 51, 19-23. Skandinavisk Aktuarietidskrift, 26, 85-118, 220-263; 27, 69-120.
von Stackelberg, H. [1933]. "Zwei Kritische bemerkungen zur preis- Zeuthen, F. [1932]. "Das Prinzip der Knappheit, technische Kom-
theorie Gustav Cassels," Zeitschrift fr Nationalokonomie, 4, bination und i:ikonomische Quiilitat," Zeitschrift fr National-
456-472. okonomie, 4, 1-24.
Starr, R. [1969]. "Quasi-equilibria in markets with nonconvex
preferences," Econometrica, 37, 25-38.
Theocharis, R. [1961]. Early Developments in Mathematical Economics.
London: Macmillan.
Tompkins, C. B. [ 1964 ]. "Sperner's lemma and sorne extensions," in
li
E. F. Beckenbach (ed.), Applied Combinatoria! Mathematics.
New York: Wiley, Chapter 15. ',,
1

Triffin, R. [1940]. Monopolistic Competition and General Equilibrium


Theory. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Uzawa, H. [1958]. "Gradient method for concave programming, II:
global stability in the strictly concave case," in K. J. Arrow, L.
Hurwicz, and H. Uzawa, Studies in Linear and Non-Linear
Programming. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press,
Chapter 7, pp. 127-132.
Uzawa, H. [1959-60]. "Walras' tatonnement in the theory of ex-
change," Review of Economic Studies, 27, 182-194.
Uzawa, H. [1961]. "The stability of dynamic processes," Econometrica,
29, 617-631.
Uzawa, H. [1962]. "On the stability of Edgeworth's barter process,"
International Economic Review, 3, 218-232.
Veblen, T. [1899]. The Theory of the Leisure Class. New York:
Macmiiian.
Wald, A. [1933-34]. "ber die eindeutige positive Li:isbarkeit der
ii neuen Produktions-gleichungen," Ergebnisse eines mathema-
tischen Ko/loquiums, 6, 12-20.
Wald, A. [1934-35]. "ber die Produktionsgleichungen der i:ikono-
: 1
mische Wertlehre," Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums,
1

7, 1-6.
Wald, A. [1936]. "ber einige Gleichungssysteme der mathematischen
Okonomie," Zeitschrift fr Nationa!Okonomie, 7, 637-670.
Wald, A. [1951]. "On sorne systems of equations of mathematical
economics," Econometrica, 19, 368-403. English translation of
Wald [1936].
Walras, L. [1874, 1877]. Elments d'conomie politique pure. Lau-
sanne: L. Corbaz. English translation of the definitive edition
by William Jaff [1954]. Elements of Pure Economics. London:
AIIen and Unwin.
Whitin, T. M., and M. H. Peston [1954]. "Random variations, risk,
and returns to scale," Quarterly Journal of Economics, 68,
603-612.
Williamson, O. E. [1964]. The Economics of Discretionary Behavior:
Managerial Objectives in a Theory of the Firm. Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
INDEXES INDEX 439

Hicks, J. R., 7, 11, 12, 167n, 209, Mil ton, J., 169
262n,312n,314,321n,431 Mirrlees, J., 106n, 168n
Hildenbrand, W., 206n, 431 Morgenstern, O., 9, 10, 124, 205n,
Hotelling, H., 11, 74n, 431 434
Howson, J. T., Jr., 416, 432 Morishima, M., 243n, 262n, 321n,
Hurwicz, L., 243n, 292, 321n, 433
323n,428,429 Mosak,J.L., 12,262n,321n,433

Ichiishi, T., 168n Nash, J. F., Jr., lln, 127n, 433


Isnard, A. N., 3n, 431 Nataf, A., 220, 433
Negishi, T., 127n, 167n, 168n,
Jenkin, F., 6, 431 321n,346n,431,433,434
Jevons, W. S., 3 Neisser, H., 8, 434
Author lndex Nerlove, M., 323n, 429
Allen, R.G.D., 11 Kakutani, S., 10,431 Neumann, J. von, 10, 74n, 124,
Debreu, G., 11, 74n, 106n, 127n, Kaldor, N., 166,432 205n,434
Arrow, K. J., 11, 106n, 127n, 128n,206n,243n,428,430 Karlin, S., 14, 74n, 389, 432 Nikaid, H., 11, 15, 127n, 243n,
128n, 167n, 168n,243n,292, de Finetti, B., 124, 430 Keynes, J. M., 151, 345, 347, 354, 270,430,434
321n, 323n, 428, 429, 430
Aumann, R. J., 182n, 429 355,356,363,366,367,368, Nishino, H., 206n, 434
Edgeworth, F. Y., 5, 6, 10, 205n 369,432
430 '
Bacon, F., 173 Knight, F. H., 3n, 432 Pareto, V., 5, 6, 106n, 434
Bator, F. M., 182n, 429 Eilenberg, S., 106n, 430 Koopmans, T. C., 11n, 74n, 432 Pearce, l. F., 241, 243n, 434
Becker, G. S., 106n, 429 Enthoven, A. C., 323n 430 Kuhn, H. W., 11n, 403,415,432 Perron, 0., 14, 371
' '

Bernoulli, D., 123,429 Kyburg, H. E., 432 Phillips, A. W., 366


Farrell, M. J., 182n, 430
Block, H. D., 243n, 321n, 428
Fisher, I., 106n
Bohm, P., 167,429 Lancaster, K., 262n, 432 Quirk, J. P., 262n, 434
Folkman, J. H., 182n, 188, 389,
Bowen, R., 106n, 429 La Salle, J., 281n, 432
395,396
Brouwer, L. E. J., 10 Lefschetz, S., 281n, 432 Rader, J. T., 106n, 128n, 434
Frobenius, G., 14
Burger, E., 403,429 Leijonhufvud, A., 369n, 432 Radner, R., 128, 434
Bushaw, D. W., 167n, 429 Lemke, C., 416,432 Ramsey, F.' P., 124, 434
Gale, D., 15, 127n, 243n, 300,
Leontief, W. W., 7, 13, 51n, 432 Ricardo, D., 2
Cassel, G., 8, 9, 51n, 429 321n,430
Levinson, N., 281n, 430 Robinson, J., 166, 434
Chamberlin, E. H., 74n, 166, Georgescu-Roegen, N., 14, 51 11 ,
Lyapunov, A., 281n, 432 Rothenberg, J., 182n, 434
167n, 429 431
Rybczynski, T. M., 261,434
Charnes, A., 404, 429 Gillies, D. B., 10, 205n, 431
McKenzie, L., 11, 51n, 74n, 127n,
Chipman, J. S., 167n, 429 Glustoff, E., 369n, 431
167n, 243n, 321n, 433 SaitQ, M., 167n, 434
Clark, J. B., 4 Gorman, W. M., 220, 262n, 431
Malthus, T. R., 2, 3 Samuelson, P. A., 2n, 11, 12, 14,
Clower, R. W., 167n, 346, 366, Marris, R., 150, 432 15, 51n, 242n, 243n, 262n,
369n,429 Hahn, F. H., 74n, 243n, 321n,
346n,369n,431 Marshall, A., 15, 263, 280, 281n 320,321n,435
Coddington, E. A., 28n, 430 Marx, K., 2 Savage, L. J., 124,435
Cottle, R. W., 416, 427n, 430 Hahn, W., 281n, 431
Menger, C., 3, 9, 74n, 433 Scarf, H., 10, 206n, 300, 321n,
Cournot, A. A., 6, 430 Hansen, T., 403,415,431
Hawkins, D., 51n, 431 Metzler, L., 12, 321n, 433 403,409,415,425,431,435
Dantzig, G. B., lln, 404, 416 Henry, C., 281n Mili, J. S., 2, 4 Schelling, T. C., 187, 435

438
INDEXES INDEX 439

Hicks, J. R., 7, 11, 12, 167n, 209, Mil ton, J., 169
262n,312n,314,321n,431 Mirrlees, J., 106n, 168n
Hildenbrand, W., 206n, 431 Morgenstern, O., 9, 10, 124, 205n,
Hotelling, H., 11, 74n, 431 434
Howson, J. T., Jr., 416, 432 Morishima, M., 243n, 262n, 321n,
Hurwicz, L., 243n, 292, 321n, 433
323n,428,429 Mosak,J.L., 12,262n,321n,433

Ichiishi, T., 168n Nash, J. F., Jr., lln, 127n, 433


Isnard, A. N., 3n, 431 Nataf, A., 220, 433
Negishi, T., 127n, 167n, 168n,
Jenkin, F., 6, 431 321n,346n,431,433,434
Jevons, W. S., 3 Neisser, H., 8, 434
Author lndex Nerlove, M., 323n, 429
Allen, R.G.D., 11 Kakutani, S., 10,431 Neumann, J. von, 10, 74n, 124,
Debreu, G., 11, 74n, 106n, 127n, Kaldor, N., 166,432 205n,434
Arrow, K. J., 11, 106n, 127n, 128n,206n,243n,428,430 Karlin, S., 14, 74n, 389, 432 Nikaid, H., 11, 15, 127n, 243n,
128n, 167n, 168n,243n,292, de Finetti, B., 124, 430 Keynes, J. M., 151, 345, 347, 354, 270,430,434
321n, 323n, 428, 429, 430
Aumann, R. J., 182n, 429 355,356,363,366,367,368, Nishino, H., 206n, 434
Edgeworth, F. Y., 5, 6, 10, 205n 369,432
430 '
Bacon, F., 173 Knight, F. H., 3n, 432 Pareto, V., 5, 6, 106n, 434
Bator, F. M., 182n, 429 Eilenberg, S., 106n, 430 Koopmans, T. C., 11n, 74n, 432 Pearce, l. F., 241, 243n, 434
Becker, G. S., 106n, 429 Enthoven, A. C., 323n 430 Kuhn, H. W., 11n, 403,415,432 Perron, 0., 14, 371
' '

Bernoulli, D., 123,429 Kyburg, H. E., 432 Phillips, A. W., 366


Farrell, M. J., 182n, 430
Block, H. D., 243n, 321n, 428
Fisher, I., 106n
Bohm, P., 167,429 Lancaster, K., 262n, 432 Quirk, J. P., 262n, 434
Folkman, J. H., 182n, 188, 389,
Bowen, R., 106n, 429 La Salle, J., 281n, 432
395,396
Brouwer, L. E. J., 10 Lefschetz, S., 281n, 432 Rader, J. T., 106n, 128n, 434
Frobenius, G., 14
Burger, E., 403,429 Leijonhufvud, A., 369n, 432 Radner, R., 128, 434
Bushaw, D. W., 167n, 429 Lemke, C., 416,432 Ramsey, F.' P., 124, 434
Gale, D., 15, 127n, 243n, 300,
Leontief, W. W., 7, 13, 51n, 432 Ricardo, D., 2
Cassel, G., 8, 9, 51n, 429 321n,430
Levinson, N., 281n, 430 Robinson, J., 166, 434
Chamberlin, E. H., 74n, 166, Georgescu-Roegen, N., 14, 51 11 ,
Lyapunov, A., 281n, 432 Rothenberg, J., 182n, 434
167n, 429 431
Rybczynski, T. M., 261,434
Charnes, A., 404, 429 Gillies, D. B., 10, 205n, 431
McKenzie, L., 11, 51n, 74n, 127n,
Chipman, J. S., 167n, 429 Glustoff, E., 369n, 431
167n, 243n, 321n, 433 SaitQ, M., 167n, 434
Clark, J. B., 4 Gorman, W. M., 220, 262n, 431
Malthus, T. R., 2, 3 Samuelson, P. A., 2n, 11, 12, 14,
Clower, R. W., 167n, 346, 366, Marris, R., 150, 432 15, 51n, 242n, 243n, 262n,
369n,429 Hahn, F. H., 74n, 243n, 321n,
346n,369n,431 Marshall, A., 15, 263, 280, 281n 320,321n,435
Coddington, E. A., 28n, 430 Marx, K., 2 Savage, L. J., 124,435
Cottle, R. W., 416, 427n, 430 Hahn, W., 281n, 431
Menger, C., 3, 9, 74n, 433 Scarf, H., 10, 206n, 300, 321n,
Cournot, A. A., 6, 430 Hansen, T., 403,415,431
Hawkins, D., 51n, 431 Metzler, L., 12, 321n, 433 403,409,415,425,431,435
Dantzig, G. B., lln, 404, 416 Henry, C., 281n Mili, J. S., 2, 4 Schelling, T. C., 187, 435

438
440 INDEX INDEX 441

Schlesinger, K., 9, 435 Tucker, A. W., 11n Basis, 404, 405, 412 Compara ti ve statics, 5, 11-12, 245
Scitovsky, T., 129,435 feasible, 405, 406, 416 Compensated demand function, 80
Shapley, L. S., 182n, 188, 205n, Uzawa, H., 11, 243n, 270, 281n, Binary change, 245-252 Compensated equilibrium, 95, 109,
389,395,396,432 321n, 323n, 346n, 434, 436 Blocking, 184 131, 135, 149, 150, 191, 196,
Shubik, M., 10, 205n, 435 weak, 196 205, 355
Simon, H., 51n, 431 Veblen, T., 129,436 Bonds, 136, 138, 139, 141, 143, definition of, 108
Slutzky, E., 74n, 436 146, 351, 352, 364, 366 existence of, 114, 356
Smith, A., 1, 2, 5, 186 Wald, A., 9, 10, 11, 15, 51n, 127n, Borrowing, 21, 339, 355 with externalities, 135
Smokler, H. E., 432 243n, 436 Boundedness individual approximate, 179,
Stackelberg, H. von, 8, 9, 436 Walras, L., 3-5, 8, 12, 264n, 305, of demand for free goods, 29 180
Starr, R., 182n, 188,389, 399,436 322n,436 of excess cemands from below, social approximate, 177
Starrett, D., 167n Wicksteed, P. H., 4 31 Competitive allocation, Pareto
Stolper, W. F., 262n, 435 Branching process, 335 efficiency of, 159
Williamson, O. E., 150, 436
Broker, 348 Co'mpetitive equilibrium, 5, 6, 9,
Wise, J., 243n, 434
Theocharis, R., 3n, 436 Wold, H., 106n, 437 Budget constraint, 350 94, 95, 131, 135, 184, 185,
Tompkins, C. B., 403, 436 186, 190, 355
Triffin, R., 167n, 436 C ( continuity of excess-demand definition of, 107
Zeuthen, F., 8, 9, 10, 437
function) , 21 existen ce of, 116
Capital, 2 with externalities, 133, 135
Subject Index Capital markets, perfect, 151 general, 52
Accounting identity, 365, 366 Capital value of firm, ~52 monopolistic, 160, 161, 165
production, 88
Active demand, 364 Cash balance effects, 361 static, 146
two-period, 146
Active excess demand, 340, 341, Cash balances, 365 unblocked, 187
u-feasible, 90, 99
345, 363-366, 369n Characteristic root, 371, 372, 373 Complementary slackness, 9
unblocked, 184,185,186,195
Activity, 52, 53, 74n Characteristic vector, 371, 373, 374 Composite commodity, 7, 253
Allocation to types, 195
Adaptive expectation, 313, 314, Classical economics, supply- Computation of equilibrium, 425
Arcwise connected set, 401
323n oriented, 2 Cone, 60
Auctioneer, 264, 268, 276, 303,
Additivity, 59-61 Classical economists, 1-3, 5 convex, 61, 198
306, 308, 312, 313, 314, 322,
Adjustment, 332 Classical saving, 239 Connected economy, 227, 249,
324,325,328,329,338
Adjustment rule, 292, 308 Coalition 289, 316
Auctioneer's rule, 266-270, 278,
Aggregation problem, 357 cost of forming, 186 Connected set, 401
286,290,302-309,310
definition of, 184 Connexity, 78, 83, 176
Aggregation theorem, Hicks- monotonicity of, 288
Leontief, 7 feasibility for, 184 Constant returns, 319
Average cost, 22
Algorithm, 403 Commodity, 8 and auctioneer's rule, 280
Allocation, 5, 88 current, 146 and comparing equilibria,
Bankruptcy, 119, 120, 121, 151,
blocked, 199, 203 first-period, 146 254--261
353,.354, 361, 362
competitive (see Competitive marketed (see Marketed economy, 316, 320
of household, 356, 368
allocation) commodity) in an L-economy (see
Bankruptcy point of households,
consumption, 88 monopolized, 153 L-economy)
354,355
current, 147 Commodity prices, 13, 14, 238 Consumer choice, 75-82
Bargaining, 5-6
feasible, 89 Community indifference curve, Consumption, 75, 76
equilibrium in, 183-187
feasible current, 147 221 current, 143, 144
Barriers to entry, 166
Pareto-efficient, 94, 130 Comparative dynamics, 245 two-period, 140
Barter,338,355, 363
440 INDEX INDEX 441

Schlesinger, K., 9, 435 Tucker, A. W., 11n Basis, 404, 405, 412 Compara ti ve statics, 5, 11-12, 245
Scitovsky, T., 129,435 feasible, 405, 406, 416 Compensated demand function, 80
Shapley, L. S., 182n, 188, 205n, Uzawa, H., 11, 243n, 270, 281n, Binary change, 245-252 Compensated equilibrium, 95, 109,
389,395,396,432 321n, 323n, 346n, 434, 436 Blocking, 184 131, 135, 149, 150, 191, 196,
Shubik, M., 10, 205n, 435 weak, 196 205, 355
Simon, H., 51n, 431 Veblen, T., 129,436 Bonds, 136, 138, 139, 141, 143, definition of, 108
Slutzky, E., 74n, 436 146, 351, 352, 364, 366 existence of, 114, 356
Smith, A., 1, 2, 5, 186 Wald, A., 9, 10, 11, 15, 51n, 127n, Borrowing, 21, 339, 355 with externalities, 135
Smokler, H. E., 432 243n, 436 Boundedness individual approximate, 179,
Stackelberg, H. von, 8, 9, 436 Walras, L., 3-5, 8, 12, 264n, 305, of demand for free goods, 29 180
Starr, R., 182n, 188,389, 399,436 322n,436 of excess cemands from below, social approximate, 177
Starrett, D., 167n Wicksteed, P. H., 4 31 Competitive allocation, Pareto
Stolper, W. F., 262n, 435 Branching process, 335 efficiency of, 159
Williamson, O. E., 150, 436
Broker, 348 Co'mpetitive equilibrium, 5, 6, 9,
Wise, J., 243n, 434
Theocharis, R., 3n, 436 Wold, H., 106n, 437 Budget constraint, 350 94, 95, 131, 135, 184, 185,
Tompkins, C. B., 403, 436 186, 190, 355
Triffin, R., 167n, 436 C ( continuity of excess-demand definition of, 107
Zeuthen, F., 8, 9, 10, 437
function) , 21 existen ce of, 116
Capital, 2 with externalities, 133, 135
Subject Index Capital markets, perfect, 151 general, 52
Accounting identity, 365, 366 Capital value of firm, ~52 monopolistic, 160, 161, 165
production, 88
Active demand, 364 Cash balance effects, 361 static, 146
two-period, 146
Active excess demand, 340, 341, Cash balances, 365 unblocked, 187
u-feasible, 90, 99
345, 363-366, 369n Characteristic root, 371, 372, 373 Complementary slackness, 9
unblocked, 184,185,186,195
Activity, 52, 53, 74n Characteristic vector, 371, 373, 374 Composite commodity, 7, 253
Allocation to types, 195
Adaptive expectation, 313, 314, Classical economics, supply- Computation of equilibrium, 425
Arcwise connected set, 401
323n oriented, 2 Cone, 60
Auctioneer, 264, 268, 276, 303,
Additivity, 59-61 Classical economists, 1-3, 5 convex, 61, 198
306, 308, 312, 313, 314, 322,
Adjustment, 332 Classical saving, 239 Connected economy, 227, 249,
324,325,328,329,338
Adjustment rule, 292, 308 Coalition 289, 316
Auctioneer's rule, 266-270, 278,
Aggregation problem, 357 cost of forming, 186 Connected set, 401
286,290,302-309,310
definition of, 184 Connexity, 78, 83, 176
Aggregation theorem, Hicks- monotonicity of, 288
Leontief, 7 feasibility for, 184 Constant returns, 319
Average cost, 22
Algorithm, 403 Commodity, 8 and auctioneer's rule, 280
Allocation, 5, 88 current, 146 and comparing equilibria,
Bankruptcy, 119, 120, 121, 151,
blocked, 199, 203 first-period, 146 254--261
353,.354, 361, 362
competitive (see Competitive marketed (see Marketed economy, 316, 320
of household, 356, 368
allocation) commodity) in an L-economy (see
Bankruptcy point of households,
consumption, 88 monopolized, 153 L-economy)
354,355
current, 147 Commodity prices, 13, 14, 238 Consumer choice, 75-82
Bargaining, 5-6
feasible, 89 Community indifference curve, Consumption, 75, 76
equilibrium in, 183-187
feasible current, 147 221 current, 143, 144
Barriers to entry, 166
Pareto-efficient, 94, 130 Comparative dynamics, 245 two-period, 140
Barter,338,355, 363
442 INDEX INDEX 443

Consumption possibility set, 76, non-convexity (see Non- Demand continued Double-tangency solution, 166
77, 78, 175 convexity) excess, 88 Durable goods
1:
Contingent commodities, 124, 125 of orderings, 95 for money, 361 in an L-economy, 46
l! Contingent futures market, 349 of preferences, 169 neglect of in classical production, 40
Continuity, 21, 71,78 of preferences under economics, 2 services of, 36
and equilibrium, 354, 355, 361, uncertainty, 128n for resources, 4 and short period, 35
366 of production possibility set, 95, Demand correspondence,
of monopolistic behavior, 158, 168n, 169, 287, 319 compensated, 81 Earning power, 355
166 semi-strict, 78 Demand function, 8, 10, 16, 18, Economic growth, 74n, 239
of ordering, 82 of simplex, 28 54, 100 balanced, 1O
of preferences, 84 Core, 1O, 183-206, 403 compensated, 80, 81, 104 Economy, one-household, 217
of preferences, strict, 334 approximation to competitive discontinuity of, 109, 127n Edgeworth box, 185
of solutions, 269 equilibrium, 188 domain of definition, 101 Effective demancl, 345, 356, 363
of sum of excess demands, 30 with a continuum of households, not defined on simplex, 29 Elasticity
weakened condition, 31 206n perceived 152, 167 of demand, 226
weakened condition and with finitely many types, 195- uncompensated, 80, 100 of expectation, 313, 314
equilibrium, 29 198 Demand J acobian, 298 Hicksian, 3 1O
Continuity theorems, 97-99 non-empty, 190 Derived utility function, 137, 350 Elasticity formula, 285
Continuous time, 266, 268, 305, of productive economy, 198- Desired purchase, 363 Endowment, 75, 94, 353
308, 342 205,206n Deterministic exchange processes, current, 352
Continuum of households, 151 in a sequence of economies, 336 future, 352
Contract, 356, 357, 361 206n Diagonal dominance, 233-235, positive, 336, 337, 344, 345
Contract curve, 6, 1O Correspondence prin~iple, 12, 242,249,250,251,292-296, Entrepreneur, indebted, 356
Convenience, 361 320-321 297,298,301,305,306,311, Equal treatment in the core, 196
Converging subsequence, 272 Correspondences, 16, 81, 97, 127n, 312,321n,327 Equality of equations and
Convex combination, 174, 376, 385 423 Difference equations, 50 unknowns, 4, 8
proper, 70, 376-377 continuity of, 97, 201 Differential equation, 268 Equilibrium, 4, 22-24
Convex corre, 61, 198 ,Cost curve, U-shaped, 182n Dimension, 375 compensated (see Compensated
Convex function, 350, 358 Cost function, mnimum unit, 73, Discontinuities equilibrium)
Convex hull, 153, 174, 175, 176, 280,316,317 and bankruptcy, 361 compensated and competitive,
385,387,388,391,392,393, Cost minimization in an L-econ- and existence of equilibrium, 107-111
394,395,396,399 omy, unique, 47 355 competitive (see Competitive
Convex set, 59, 375-401 Creditor, 354, 360 in wealth, 355, 360 equilibrium)
connectedness of, 400-401 Cuisine, 173 Discrete time, 266, 268, 305, 307 computation of (see Computa-
strictly, 70 Cyclic permutation, 407, 410 Disequilibrium, 263 tion of equilibrium)
vector sum of, 188 Dishoarding, unintended, 50 on current market, 136
Convexification of preference Debt, 119, 120, 121, 151,359 Distance, measure of, 278 with debt and bankruptcy, 119-
ordering, 176 Debtor, 356, 360, 361 Divisibility, 59-62, 74n 122
Convexified economy, 174, 176, Decomposable mat:ix, 371 Dominance, 9), 183 definition of, 23
177, 178. Degeneracy, 404, 407, 410 of uti!ity allocations, 96 existence of (see Existence of
Convexity, 186 Demand, 3, 80 Dominan! diagonal (see Diagonal equilibrium)
and existence of equilibrium, for consumer goods, 4 dominance) withexternalities, 132-136, 167n
170 elasticity of, 226 Dominant root, 374 flow, 49
442 INDEX INDEX 443

Consumption possibility set, 76, non-convexity (see Non- Demand continued Double-tangency solution, 166
77, 78, 175 convexity) excess, 88 Durable goods
1:
Contingent commodities, 124, 125 of orderings, 95 for money, 361 in an L-economy, 46
l! Contingent futures market, 349 of preferences, 169 neglect of in classical production, 40
Continuity, 21, 71,78 of preferences under economics, 2 services of, 36
and equilibrium, 354, 355, 361, uncertainty, 128n for resources, 4 and short period, 35
366 of production possibility set, 95, Demand correspondence,
of monopolistic behavior, 158, 168n, 169, 287, 319 compensated, 81 Earning power, 355
166 semi-strict, 78 Demand function, 8, 10, 16, 18, Economic growth, 74n, 239
of ordering, 82 of simplex, 28 54, 100 balanced, 1O
of preferences, 84 Core, 1O, 183-206, 403 compensated, 80, 81, 104 Economy, one-household, 217
of preferences, strict, 334 approximation to competitive discontinuity of, 109, 127n Edgeworth box, 185
of solutions, 269 equilibrium, 188 domain of definition, 101 Effective demancl, 345, 356, 363
of sum of excess demands, 30 with a continuum of households, not defined on simplex, 29 Elasticity
weakened condition, 31 206n perceived 152, 167 of demand, 226
weakened condition and with finitely many types, 195- uncompensated, 80, 100 of expectation, 313, 314
equilibrium, 29 198 Demand J acobian, 298 Hicksian, 3 1O
Continuity theorems, 97-99 non-empty, 190 Derived utility function, 137, 350 Elasticity formula, 285
Continuous time, 266, 268, 305, of productive economy, 198- Desired purchase, 363 Endowment, 75, 94, 353
308, 342 205,206n Deterministic exchange processes, current, 352
Continuum of households, 151 in a sequence of economies, 336 future, 352
Contract, 356, 357, 361 206n Diagonal dominance, 233-235, positive, 336, 337, 344, 345
Contract curve, 6, 1O Correspondence prin~iple, 12, 242,249,250,251,292-296, Entrepreneur, indebted, 356
Convenience, 361 320-321 297,298,301,305,306,311, Equal treatment in the core, 196
Converging subsequence, 272 Correspondences, 16, 81, 97, 127n, 312,321n,327 Equality of equations and
Convex combination, 174, 376, 385 423 Difference equations, 50 unknowns, 4, 8
proper, 70, 376-377 continuity of, 97, 201 Differential equation, 268 Equilibrium, 4, 22-24
Convex corre, 61, 198 ,Cost curve, U-shaped, 182n Dimension, 375 compensated (see Compensated
Convex function, 350, 358 Cost function, mnimum unit, 73, Discontinuities equilibrium)
Convex hull, 153, 174, 175, 176, 280,316,317 and bankruptcy, 361 compensated and competitive,
385,387,388,391,392,393, Cost minimization in an L-econ- and existence of equilibrium, 107-111
394,395,396,399 omy, unique, 47 355 competitive (see Competitive
Convex set, 59, 375-401 Creditor, 354, 360 in wealth, 355, 360 equilibrium)
connectedness of, 400-401 Cuisine, 173 Discrete time, 266, 268, 305, 307 computation of (see Computa-
strictly, 70 Cyclic permutation, 407, 410 Disequilibrium, 263 tion of equilibrium)
vector sum of, 188 Dishoarding, unintended, 50 on current market, 136
Convexification of preference Debt, 119, 120, 121, 151,359 Distance, measure of, 278 with debt and bankruptcy, 119-
ordering, 176 Debtor, 356, 360, 361 Divisibility, 59-62, 74n 122
Convexified economy, 174, 176, Decomposable mat:ix, 371 Dominance, 9), 183 definition of, 23
177, 178. Degeneracy, 404, 407, 410 of uti!ity allocations, 96 existence of (see Existence of
Convexity, 186 Demand, 3, 80 Dominan! diagonal (see Diagonal equilibrium)
and existence of equilibrium, for consumer goods, 4 dominance) withexternalities, 132-136, 167n
170 elasticity of, 226 Dominant root, 374 flow, 49
,1
'1

444 INDEX
INDEX 445
Equilibrium continued Excess-demand Jacobian, 303 O ames
Factor income, 256, 258
general (see General Excess supply, 18 non-zero-sum, 205n
Factor price equalization, 237, 240
equilibrium) of labor, 365 theory of, 1O, 403
Factor prices, 13, 14, 238
isolated (see Isolated Excess-supply function, 207 Gauge function, 377-382, 383
Feasibility, 52, 88, 89
equilibria) Excess-supply Jacobian, 210, 214, Gauss-Seidel method, 306, 321n
for coalitions, 198, 203
in an L-economy, 73 295, 296 General equilibrium, 2, 3, 6, 7
for production, 64-65
long-run, 49 non-vanishing, 236 Fictional household, 308, 312, competitive, 52
market, 18 positive quasi-definite, 235 General Theory, 347, 367
319,320
under monopolistic competition, Exchange, 324-331, 334-336, Finance, 364 Giffen paradox, 300
151-167 338-340, 348, 355, 363 Financia! constraint, 340, 345 Global instability, 295, 299-301
partial, 6-8 Exchange process, 333-337, 340, Firm, 3, 17, 52, 63, 74n Global stability, 321, 332, 333,
probability of convergence to, 345,348 capital value of, 141 334, 345
336 Existence of equilibrium, 8-11, integrated, 364 of auctioneer's rule, 271, 272,
relation of competitive to 25-29, 127n market capital value of, 150 279
compensated, 108 in a monetary economy, 369n Firm's debt, 354 of equilibrium, 272
short-period (see Short-period in a two-good economy, 24-25 Fixed coefficients of production, (see also Quasi~global stability)
equilibrium) Existence proof, 354, 355 2,4,8, 12,74n Global quasi-stability, 289
short-run, 49, 278 Expectations, 278, 309, 347, 351, Fixed point, 28, 307, 366 GP (see Gale property)
stability of (see Stability of 353,354,358,360,367,368, as an equilibrium, 28 Gradient method, 275-278
equilibrium) 369 of mapping for L-economy, 42 Gradient process, 289, 338
stationary, 10 destabilizing, 313 Fixed-point theorem, 402, 406, Gross subst,itutes, 15, 221-227,
stock, 49 formation of, 312 409,415 247,251,269,286,288,289,
stock and flow, 48-50 stationary, 329 Brouwer's, 10, 28,403,418,419 297,298,301,305-308,310,
strictly positive, 292 Expected prices, 36, 31 O, 357, 362 proof of, 421 311, 314, 315, 318, 320, 321,
temporary (see Temporary and current prices, 39 Kakutani's, 10, 163, 403, 419, 321n,327,346n,368
equilibrium) discontinuous functions of 422,423 and equilibrium prices, 222
under uncertainty, 122-126, current prices, 356 proof of, 423 in production, 226
172n of firms, 37 Fluctuations, 367 and unbounded demand, 29
uniqueness of (see Uniqueness Expected wage, 357 Foreign trade, 3, 4 weak (see Weak gross
of equilibrium) Externa! economies, 133 Free disposal, 20, 23, 71, 337 substitutes)
when utility is affected by prices, Externalities, 95, 132-136, 167n Free entry, 166 Group rationality, 5
129-131 absence of, 186 Free trade, 258 GS (see Gross substitutes)
Equilibrium price of money, 363 Full employment, 361, 367
Equilibrium set, convex, 289, 292 F ( existence of excess-demand Future, 356, 357, 361 H (homogeneity), 19
Esthetic valuation, 173 function), 18 Future income, 368 Hahn-Banach theorem, 382
ex ante, 19 Facial dimcnsion, 389, 390, 393, Future profits, 354 Hicksian economy, 217-221, 239,
Excess demand, 18, 88 395 Futures contracts, 34 247,275,278,286-289,297,
single-valued, 99-105 Facial direction, 389, 390, 391, Futures markets, 122, 245, 309, 298,301,306,308,309,312,
social, 191 394,395 349, 369 319, 320
u-possible, 90, 99 Facial space, 3 89, 390, 391 restricted, 33-34 Hicksian elasticity of expectation,
Excess-demand function, 17-19 Factor, 8 310
boundedness of, 21 free, 9 Gains from trade, 185 Hicksian matrix, 209
continuity of, 20 scarce, 9 GaJe property, 208, 250, 427n and GaJe property, 209
,1
'1

444 INDEX
INDEX 445
Equilibrium continued Excess-demand Jacobian, 303 O ames
Factor income, 256, 258
general (see General Excess supply, 18 non-zero-sum, 205n
Factor price equalization, 237, 240
equilibrium) of labor, 365 theory of, 1O, 403
Factor prices, 13, 14, 238
isolated (see Isolated Excess-supply function, 207 Gauge function, 377-382, 383
Feasibility, 52, 88, 89
equilibria) Excess-supply Jacobian, 210, 214, Gauss-Seidel method, 306, 321n
for coalitions, 198, 203
in an L-economy, 73 295, 296 General equilibrium, 2, 3, 6, 7
for production, 64-65
long-run, 49 non-vanishing, 236 Fictional household, 308, 312, competitive, 52
market, 18 positive quasi-definite, 235 General Theory, 347, 367
319,320
under monopolistic competition, Exchange, 324-331, 334-336, Finance, 364 Giffen paradox, 300
151-167 338-340, 348, 355, 363 Financia! constraint, 340, 345 Global instability, 295, 299-301
partial, 6-8 Exchange process, 333-337, 340, Firm, 3, 17, 52, 63, 74n Global stability, 321, 332, 333,
probability of convergence to, 345,348 capital value of, 141 334, 345
336 Existence of equilibrium, 8-11, integrated, 364 of auctioneer's rule, 271, 272,
relation of competitive to 25-29, 127n market capital value of, 150 279
compensated, 108 in a monetary economy, 369n Firm's debt, 354 of equilibrium, 272
short-period (see Short-period in a two-good economy, 24-25 Fixed coefficients of production, (see also Quasi~global stability)
equilibrium) Existence proof, 354, 355 2,4,8, 12,74n Global quasi-stability, 289
short-run, 49, 278 Expectations, 278, 309, 347, 351, Fixed point, 28, 307, 366 GP (see Gale property)
stability of (see Stability of 353,354,358,360,367,368, as an equilibrium, 28 Gradient method, 275-278
equilibrium) 369 of mapping for L-economy, 42 Gradient process, 289, 338
stationary, 10 destabilizing, 313 Fixed-point theorem, 402, 406, Gross subst,itutes, 15, 221-227,
stock, 49 formation of, 312 409,415 247,251,269,286,288,289,
stock and flow, 48-50 stationary, 329 Brouwer's, 10, 28,403,418,419 297,298,301,305-308,310,
strictly positive, 292 Expected prices, 36, 31 O, 357, 362 proof of, 421 311, 314, 315, 318, 320, 321,
temporary (see Temporary and current prices, 39 Kakutani's, 10, 163, 403, 419, 321n,327,346n,368
equilibrium) discontinuous functions of 422,423 and equilibrium prices, 222
under uncertainty, 122-126, current prices, 356 proof of, 423 in production, 226
172n of firms, 37 Fluctuations, 367 and unbounded demand, 29
uniqueness of (see Uniqueness Expected wage, 357 Foreign trade, 3, 4 weak (see Weak gross
of equilibrium) Externa! economies, 133 Free disposal, 20, 23, 71, 337 substitutes)
when utility is affected by prices, Externalities, 95, 132-136, 167n Free entry, 166 Group rationality, 5
129-131 absence of, 186 Free trade, 258 GS (see Gross substitutes)
Equilibrium price of money, 363 Full employment, 361, 367
Equilibrium set, convex, 289, 292 F ( existence of excess-demand Future, 356, 357, 361 H (homogeneity), 19
Esthetic valuation, 173 function), 18 Future income, 368 Hahn-Banach theorem, 382
ex ante, 19 Facial dimcnsion, 389, 390, 393, Future profits, 354 Hicksian economy, 217-221, 239,
Excess demand, 18, 88 395 Futures contracts, 34 247,275,278,286-289,297,
single-valued, 99-105 Facial direction, 389, 390, 391, Futures markets, 122, 245, 309, 298,301,306,308,309,312,
social, 191 394,395 349, 369 319, 320
u-possible, 90, 99 Facial space, 3 89, 390, 391 restricted, 33-34 Hicksian elasticity of expectation,
Excess-demand function, 17-19 Factor, 8 310
boundedness of, 21 free, 9 Gains from trade, 185 Hicksian matrix, 209
continuity of, 20 scarce, 9 GaJe property, 208, 250, 427n and GaJe property, 209
446 INDEX INDEX 447
Hoarding, unintended, 50 Irrational actions, rationalty of, Limit path, 272, 290, 334 Mnimum consumption vector,
Homogeneity, 4, 7, 71 186 Limit point, 271, 333, 334, 344 356
of degree zero, 19 Irreversibility, 64, 74n unique, 334 Mnimum expenditure function,
Household, 3, 17 Isolated equilibria, 274, 283, 289 Linear function, 382, 383 104
endowments of, 300 Isolated limit points, 275 Linear programming, 9, 11, 403, Mnimum unit cost, 73, 280, 316,
most optimistic, 352 407,412 317
Household preference, 319,320 Jacobian Linearspace, 375,382,390,391 Monetary economy, 337-345,
Horizontal demand curve, 325 sign pattern of, 262n Lipschitz condition, 269, 304, 348, 355, 357, 362, 363, 365
Human wealth, 358 trace of, 300, 302 333,342 Monetary theory, 339, 345, 361
uniformly bounded, 305 Local stability, 278-280, 284-285, Money, 268, 302, 338-340, 348,
i-minimum, 408-411, 413-415 ioint production, absence of, 12, 296-299, 321 349,351,355-357,359,360,
definition of, 410-411 14,40,320 Lower semi-continuity, 97 362-365, 369
i-ordering, 407, 408, 409, 413, Lyapunov function, 273, 276, 284, Money market, 361
414 Keynesian revolution, 369 286, 288-291, 293-298, 304, Money prices, 368
definition of, 410-411 Keynesian temporary equilibrum, 306-309, 311, 312, 316, 320, Money stocks, 350, 352
Imaginary root, 371 354-363, '365 332,334,344 Money wages, 356, 366, 367
Immigration, 352 differentiabilty of, 288 Monopolistic competition, 165,
Income, 3, 77, 365 L-economy monotonicity of, 286 167n
Income terms, 105, 234, 297-299 assumptions discussed, 45
covarance of, 298-300 Monopolst's supply curve, 157
equilbrium, 73 Management, 354, 355
Indecomposable matrix, 372-374 Monopoly, 15~
uniqueness of, 236-237 Managerial theory of the firm, 150
Indifference, 78 Monopsony, 153
equilbrium of economic agents, Many agents, 342, 343
Indivisibility, 61, 62, 155, 171, 173 Moral hazard, 6, 128n
41 Mapping, 307
Inferior good, 300, 319 and household demand, 47 continuous, 26
Information, 128n, 349, 356 Neoclassical economics, 73n
with many factors, 237-242 of simplex into itself, 26, 28
Information and equilibrium, 126, Neoclassical economists, 6
productive, 41, 46, 51 n Marginal productivity, 4
127n profits in, 41 Net debt, 352
Marginal propensity to buy goods,
Initial condition, 268, 273, 333, short-perod equilibrium in, Net input, 67
225
334 40-48 Net output, 58, 62
Marginal propensity to consume,
Inner radius, 175, 206n, 399 Labor, 2, 3, 64 Newton's method, 303
298, 300
Input, 66, 67 Labor market, 367 Marginal rate of substitution, 329, Non-convexity, 62, 152, 155, 399
net, 67 Labor services, 75, 357 degree of, 173, 174
330
non-produced,41,316,317,320 Lag structure, 308 Marginal utilty, 335, 337 and equilbrium, 62
Insertion, 404, 416, 417 Laissez /aire, 367 Market, 348 inner radius as a measure of,
Insolvency, 356 Land, 2,3 current, 146 188
Insurance premium, 349 Law of supply and demand, 22, Market capital, value of, 141 measures of, 399
Interest rate, 363, 369 265, 267 Market value of firm, 137 inproduction, 171,175
Interior point, 384 Leisure, 75, 76, 319, 358, 363 Marketed commodity, 61 Non-produced good, 281
Intermedia te goods, 13, 260, 317, Lending, 21, 339 Marshallian parta! analysis, 254 Non-produced input, 41, 316, 317,
364 Leontief economy (see L-econ- Mediation, 338, 339, 346 320
International trade, 247, 282 omy) Medium of exchange, 19, 35, 302, Non-satiation, 78
Investment, 356, 368 Lexicographic ordering, 405 339,345,346,349 Non-singular matrix, 372
Invisible hand, 1, 5, 304 Limit distribution, 334 marignal utility of, 339 Nuclear strategy, 186
446 INDEX INDEX 447
Hoarding, unintended, 50 Irrational actions, rationalty of, Limit path, 272, 290, 334 Mnimum consumption vector,
Homogeneity, 4, 7, 71 186 Limit point, 271, 333, 334, 344 356
of degree zero, 19 Irreversibility, 64, 74n unique, 334 Mnimum expenditure function,
Household, 3, 17 Isolated equilibria, 274, 283, 289 Linear function, 382, 383 104
endowments of, 300 Isolated limit points, 275 Linear programming, 9, 11, 403, Mnimum unit cost, 73, 280, 316,
most optimistic, 352 407,412 317
Household preference, 319,320 Jacobian Linearspace, 375,382,390,391 Monetary economy, 337-345,
Horizontal demand curve, 325 sign pattern of, 262n Lipschitz condition, 269, 304, 348, 355, 357, 362, 363, 365
Human wealth, 358 trace of, 300, 302 333,342 Monetary theory, 339, 345, 361
uniformly bounded, 305 Local stability, 278-280, 284-285, Money, 268, 302, 338-340, 348,
i-minimum, 408-411, 413-415 ioint production, absence of, 12, 296-299, 321 349,351,355-357,359,360,
definition of, 410-411 14,40,320 Lower semi-continuity, 97 362-365, 369
i-ordering, 407, 408, 409, 413, Lyapunov function, 273, 276, 284, Money market, 361
414 Keynesian revolution, 369 286, 288-291, 293-298, 304, Money prices, 368
definition of, 410-411 Keynesian temporary equilibrum, 306-309, 311, 312, 316, 320, Money stocks, 350, 352
Imaginary root, 371 354-363, '365 332,334,344 Money wages, 356, 366, 367
Immigration, 352 differentiabilty of, 288 Monopolistic competition, 165,
Income, 3, 77, 365 L-economy monotonicity of, 286 167n
Income terms, 105, 234, 297-299 assumptions discussed, 45
covarance of, 298-300 Monopolst's supply curve, 157
equilbrium, 73 Management, 354, 355
Indecomposable matrix, 372-374 Monopoly, 15~
uniqueness of, 236-237 Managerial theory of the firm, 150
Indifference, 78 Monopsony, 153
equilbrium of economic agents, Many agents, 342, 343
Indivisibility, 61, 62, 155, 171, 173 Moral hazard, 6, 128n
41 Mapping, 307
Inferior good, 300, 319 and household demand, 47 continuous, 26
Information, 128n, 349, 356 Neoclassical economics, 73n
with many factors, 237-242 of simplex into itself, 26, 28
Information and equilibrium, 126, Neoclassical economists, 6
productive, 41, 46, 51 n Marginal productivity, 4
127n profits in, 41 Net debt, 352
Marginal propensity to buy goods,
Initial condition, 268, 273, 333, short-perod equilibrium in, Net input, 67
225
334 40-48 Net output, 58, 62
Marginal propensity to consume,
Inner radius, 175, 206n, 399 Labor, 2, 3, 64 Newton's method, 303
298, 300
Input, 66, 67 Labor market, 367 Marginal rate of substitution, 329, Non-convexity, 62, 152, 155, 399
net, 67 Labor services, 75, 357 degree of, 173, 174
330
non-produced,41,316,317,320 Lag structure, 308 Marginal utilty, 335, 337 and equilbrium, 62
Insertion, 404, 416, 417 Laissez /aire, 367 Market, 348 inner radius as a measure of,
Insolvency, 356 Land, 2,3 current, 146 188
Insurance premium, 349 Law of supply and demand, 22, Market capital, value of, 141 measures of, 399
Interest rate, 363, 369 265, 267 Market value of firm, 137 inproduction, 171,175
Interior point, 384 Leisure, 75, 76, 319, 358, 363 Marketed commodity, 61 Non-produced good, 281
Intermedia te goods, 13, 260, 317, Lending, 21, 339 Marshallian parta! analysis, 254 Non-produced input, 41, 316, 317,
364 Leontief economy (see L-econ- Mediation, 338, 339, 346 320
International trade, 247, 282 omy) Medium of exchange, 19, 35, 302, Non-satiation, 78
Investment, 356, 368 Lexicographic ordering, 405 339,345,346,349 Non-singular matrix, 372
Invisible hand, 1, 5, 304 Limit distribution, 334 marignal utility of, 339 Nuclear strategy, 186
448 INDEX INDEX 449

Numeraire, 4, 7, 208, 268, 289, Preference ordering, 87, 174 Principal minors and GaJe Profit function, 69, 71, 72
294, 299, 301-302, 304, 320, convexification of, 176 property, 208 unit, 73
337, 340 non-convex, 190 Prvate commodity, 53, 61 Profit maximization, 52
Preferences, 75, 77, 78 Probability Pure exchange, 9
Oligopoly, 167 convexity of, under uncertainty, personal, 124 Pure-exchange economy, 17 5, 180,
Ordering, 77, 78 124 subjective, 124 183, 185, 275, 292-294, 297,
complete, 16 non-convexity of, 172, 173 Product differcntiation, 165 309,326,336-339,345
Oscillatory behavior, 369 Preferred consumption vectors, 79 Production, 52-74, 325, 326, 346
Output, 66, 67 Present wealth, 358 alternative methods of, 14 Quasi-equilibrium, 366, 367, 368
net, 58, 62 Present expected value, 352 current, 139 Quasi-global stability, 274, 292
Present val u e of profits, 357, 364 non-convexity in, 171, 17 5
Parameter change, general, 252- Price determination, structure of, two-period, 138 Radius, 175, 395, 396, 399
254 12 Production allocation, 63 Rationing, 342
Pareto efficiency, 91, 183-185, Price expectations, 137 feasible, 66 Real cash balances, 361,368
329,330,332-334,336,337, differences in, 137, 141 Production coefficients, fixed, 2, 4, Recontract, 324, 326, 334, 336,
348,363,366 elastic, 149 8, 12,74n 346n
compensated eqtiilibrium Price mechanism, 265, 266, 278, Production connected economy, Recontract process, 337
sufficient for, 11 O 282,321,322,324,347,369 254 Redistribution of initial assets, 95
conditional, 130, 135, 149 Price of money, 362 Production cost, 41 Reduced economy, variety of, 215
and redistribution, 121 Price set, 96 Production function, 4, 74n Reduced general equilibrium, 318
Pareto frontier, 96 Prices, 17, 35 Production plan, 354 Reduced system, 211
homeomorphic to a simplex, boundedness of, 340 of firm, 353 Relative boundary point, 376
111 of commodities and factors, 238 Production possibility, 59 Relative interior point, 376, 377,
non-negative, 112 commodity (see Comrpodity Production possibility set, 52, 60, 378, 383, 389
Pareto-superior allocation, 328, prices) 138, 174, 320 Relative neighborhood, 376
348 current, 141 for a coalition, 201 Relative utilities, 1 12, 114
equilibrium, 22 convexity of, 95, 168n, 169, Repayment of bonds, 352
Partial equilibrium, 6-8
equilibriuin, and gross 287,319 Repayment of loans, 355
Past, 351, 356, 357, 361, 362
substitutes, 222 differentiability of, 287 Replacement, 409-415, 417
Past commitments, 351, 352
expected (see Expected prices) firm, 64 definition of, 413
Perfect competition, 53, 182n,
factor (see Factor prices) and inherited equipment, 38 Resource relatedness, 117, 127n,
266,325
of goods in terms of money, 356 monopolistic, 152, 154 131, 150, 161, 356
Perfect stability, 209,216
independent of demand, 45 non-convexity, degree of, 175 indirect, 118, 127n, 131, 135
Period analysis, 50 instability of, 367 Resources, optimal allocation of, 5
social, 62, 64, 96
Perishable good, 265 negative, 20 Retailer, 348
strictly convex, 317
Permutation, 372 non-negative, 307 Returns to scale
Production possibility vector,
Polar cone, 425 positive, 332 social, 65 constant, 19, 40, 60, 69
Positive definite matrix, 235 second-period, 141 Productive economy (see (see a/so Constant returns)
Positive homogeneous function, set of equilibrium vectors, 24 L-economy, productive) diminishing, 56, 57, 71
377,378,382,383 under uncertainty, 125 Productivity, 51n increasing, 57, 58, 133, 152,
Positive matrices, 253, 370-374 zero (see Zero prices) Profit, 53, 352, 364 153,263
Positive prices, 332 Primitive set, 409-416 equaliza tion of, 1, 2, 4, 13 social-increasing, 133, 167n
Positive quasi-definite matrix, 235 definition of, 412 positive, 56 Revealed preference, 1O1
448 INDEX INDEX 449

Numeraire, 4, 7, 208, 268, 289, Preference ordering, 87, 174 Principal minors and GaJe Profit function, 69, 71, 72
294, 299, 301-302, 304, 320, convexification of, 176 property, 208 unit, 73
337, 340 non-convex, 190 Prvate commodity, 53, 61 Profit maximization, 52
Preferences, 75, 77, 78 Probability Pure exchange, 9
Oligopoly, 167 convexity of, under uncertainty, personal, 124 Pure-exchange economy, 17 5, 180,
Ordering, 77, 78 124 subjective, 124 183, 185, 275, 292-294, 297,
complete, 16 non-convexity of, 172, 173 Product differcntiation, 165 309,326,336-339,345
Oscillatory behavior, 369 Preferred consumption vectors, 79 Production, 52-74, 325, 326, 346
Output, 66, 67 Present wealth, 358 alternative methods of, 14 Quasi-equilibrium, 366, 367, 368
net, 58, 62 Present expected value, 352 current, 139 Quasi-global stability, 274, 292
Present val u e of profits, 357, 364 non-convexity in, 171, 17 5
Parameter change, general, 252- Price determination, structure of, two-period, 138 Radius, 175, 395, 396, 399
254 12 Production allocation, 63 Rationing, 342
Pareto efficiency, 91, 183-185, Price expectations, 137 feasible, 66 Real cash balances, 361,368
329,330,332-334,336,337, differences in, 137, 141 Production coefficients, fixed, 2, 4, Recontract, 324, 326, 334, 336,
348,363,366 elastic, 149 8, 12,74n 346n
compensated eqtiilibrium Price mechanism, 265, 266, 278, Production connected economy, Recontract process, 337
sufficient for, 11 O 282,321,322,324,347,369 254 Redistribution of initial assets, 95
conditional, 130, 135, 149 Price of money, 362 Production cost, 41 Reduced economy, variety of, 215
and redistribution, 121 Price set, 96 Production function, 4, 74n Reduced general equilibrium, 318
Pareto frontier, 96 Prices, 17, 35 Production plan, 354 Reduced system, 211
homeomorphic to a simplex, boundedness of, 340 of firm, 353 Relative boundary point, 376
111 of commodities and factors, 238 Production possibility, 59 Relative interior point, 376, 377,
non-negative, 112 commodity (see Comrpodity Production possibility set, 52, 60, 378, 383, 389
Pareto-superior allocation, 328, prices) 138, 174, 320 Relative neighborhood, 376
348 current, 141 for a coalition, 201 Relative utilities, 1 12, 114
equilibrium, 22 convexity of, 95, 168n, 169, Repayment of bonds, 352
Partial equilibrium, 6-8
equilibriuin, and gross 287,319 Repayment of loans, 355
Past, 351, 356, 357, 361, 362
substitutes, 222 differentiability of, 287 Replacement, 409-415, 417
Past commitments, 351, 352
expected (see Expected prices) firm, 64 definition of, 413
Perfect competition, 53, 182n,
factor (see Factor prices) and inherited equipment, 38 Resource relatedness, 117, 127n,
266,325
of goods in terms of money, 356 monopolistic, 152, 154 131, 150, 161, 356
Perfect stability, 209,216
independent of demand, 45 non-convexity, degree of, 175 indirect, 118, 127n, 131, 135
Period analysis, 50 instability of, 367 Resources, optimal allocation of, 5
social, 62, 64, 96
Perishable good, 265 negative, 20 Retailer, 348
strictly convex, 317
Permutation, 372 non-negative, 307 Returns to scale
Production possibility vector,
Polar cone, 425 positive, 332 social, 65 constant, 19, 40, 60, 69
Positive definite matrix, 235 second-period, 141 Productive economy (see (see a/so Constant returns)
Positive homogeneous function, set of equilibrium vectors, 24 L-economy, productive) diminishing, 56, 57, 71
377,378,382,383 under uncertainty, 125 Productivity, 51n increasing, 57, 58, 133, 152,
Positive matrices, 253, 370-374 zero (see Zero prices) Profit, 53, 352, 364 153,263
Positive prices, 332 Primitive set, 409-416 equaliza tion of, 1, 2, 4, 13 social-increasing, 133, 167n
Positive quasi-definite matrix, 235 definition of, 412 positive, 56 Revealed preference, 1O1
450 INDEX INDEX 451
Revealed preference continued 290,292,293,294,304,307, Target amount of labor, 364 Two-stage analysis, 365
weak axiom of, 15, 218, 249, 316, 332 Target borrowing, 364 Types, 6, io5
261,262n Solution of simultaneous Target demand, 345 productive, 200, 205
weak axiom of, and gross differential equations, 269 Target excess demand, 339, 340,
substitutes, 225 boundedness of, 270, 306 345, 363-366, 369n Unblocked allocation, strongly,
Risk aversion, 124, 128n continuity of, 209 Target excess demand for labor, 196
Risk bearing, 125 Spanning set, 174, 175, 376,385, 364 Uncertainty, 151, 302, 349
Rule of thumb, 339 386, 391' 399 Target excess supply, 366 equilibrium under, 122-126,
Speculation, 151, 346, 34 7, 348 Target excess supply of labor, 367 172n
Saddle point, 1O, 11 Speculative element, 345 Target production, 363, 365 and futures markets, 33
Satiation, 21 Speculative exchange, 346 Target profits, 365, 366 prices under, 125
Scarf's algorithm, 403, 405 Speculative transaction, 329 Target purchases, 340 Unemployment, 356
Scarf's theorem, 415-418,.419,425 Stability of adjustment rule, 284 Target receipts, 366
Unemployment equilibrium, 366
Second-order conditions for Stability of equilibrium, 11-12, 326 Target utility, 339, 344
maximization, 11 Uniqueness
global (see Global stability) Tariff, 258, 259
Semi-strict quasi-concavity, 87, of equilibrium, 8-11, 12, 14, 15
local (see Local stability) Taste, change of, 245
350, 351 locally asymptotic, 279 in the case of two primary
Tatonnement, 4, 264-266, 282,
Separating hyperplane, 382 factors, 238
in the sense of Lyapunov, 279 285, 293, 302, 306, 310, 321,
Separation theorem for convex (see also Uniqueness of 322, 368 and a class of reduced
sets, 92, 93, 382-384 equilibrium and Stability of Tay1or expansion, 296. economies, 215-217
Sequential price adjustment, 305 equilibrium) Technica1 progress, 255, 256 in a constant returns
Shapley-Folkman theorem, 396, Star-shaped set, 376, 378 Temporary equilibrium, 136-151, economy, 318
399 strictly, 154, 376, 379, 381 167n, 347, 362, 366 and correspondence principie,
Share of profits, 77, 198, 204 State of the world, 122, 123, 125 compensated, 147 321
Shareholder, 352, 353, 354 Stationary equilibrium, 10 competitive, 147, 150 and diagonal dominance, 301
Shares, 359 Stationary expectations, 313 definition of, 37 and Gale property, 211-214
ownership of, 94 Stock market, 141, 142, 146 existence of, 38, 362 in a Hicksian economy, 221,
Short-period economy, 310, 311, Storage, 35 Terms of trade, 284 286,287
313,315 Strictly concave function, 277 Trade, 324, 328, 330 in a Keynesian economy, 360
Short-period equilibrium, 35-40, Strictly positive equilibrium, 292 Trade cycle, 325 in an L-economy, 236-237
'
309-315 Strictly quasi-concave function, l. Transaction, 264, 280, 302, 309, and non-singularity of
Short-run equilibrium, 49, 278 277 l, Jacobian, 304
331,338,339,340,341,342,
Sign-preserving function, 266 Subadditive function, 377, 378, 347, 349, 350, 362, 368 in a one-household economy,
Simplex, 21,402,403,424 382, 383 continuity of, 342 218
fundamental, 403, 423 Sub~equence, convergent, 271 intertemporal, 309 in a short-period economy,
n-dimensional, 20 Substitution tcrms, 105, 225, 234, l Transaction costs, 35, 350 311, 315
Singular matrix, 372 297,298,299 Transitivity, 78, 83 and stability of equilibrium,
Slack vector, 412 Super additivity, 201 r! Triangular trade, 348 272,275,277,279,280,
Slutzky relations, 105 Supply, multi-valued, 55, 58, 59 Two-good economy, 246, 282, 283 283,284,285,286,287,
Social welfare function, strictly Supply correspondence, 70 Two-good, two-factor economy, 288,294,296,301,304,
quasi-concave, 335 Supply function, 16, 18, 54 259 305,311,315,318
Solution path, 330 perceived, 152 Two-sector model, 237, 247, 318 and stability of tatonnement
boundedness of, 285,.286, 287, Support theorem, 382-384 and gross substitutes, 240 rule, 293
450 INDEX INDEX 451
Revealed preference continued 290,292,293,294,304,307, Target amount of labor, 364 Two-stage analysis, 365
weak axiom of, 15, 218, 249, 316, 332 Target borrowing, 364 Types, 6, io5
261,262n Solution of simultaneous Target demand, 345 productive, 200, 205
weak axiom of, and gross differential equations, 269 Target excess demand, 339, 340,
substitutes, 225 boundedness of, 270, 306 345, 363-366, 369n Unblocked allocation, strongly,
Risk aversion, 124, 128n continuity of, 209 Target excess demand for labor, 196
Risk bearing, 125 Spanning set, 174, 175, 376,385, 364 Uncertainty, 151, 302, 349
Rule of thumb, 339 386, 391' 399 Target excess supply, 366 equilibrium under, 122-126,
Speculation, 151, 346, 34 7, 348 Target excess supply of labor, 367 172n
Saddle point, 1O, 11 Speculative element, 345 Target production, 363, 365 and futures markets, 33
Satiation, 21 Speculative exchange, 346 Target profits, 365, 366 prices under, 125
Scarf's algorithm, 403, 405 Speculative transaction, 329 Target purchases, 340 Unemployment, 356
Scarf's theorem, 415-418,.419,425 Stability of adjustment rule, 284 Target receipts, 366
Unemployment equilibrium, 366
Second-order conditions for Stability of equilibrium, 11-12, 326 Target utility, 339, 344
maximization, 11 Uniqueness
global (see Global stability) Tariff, 258, 259
Semi-strict quasi-concavity, 87, of equilibrium, 8-11, 12, 14, 15
local (see Local stability) Taste, change of, 245
350, 351 locally asymptotic, 279 in the case of two primary
Tatonnement, 4, 264-266, 282,
Separating hyperplane, 382 factors, 238
in the sense of Lyapunov, 279 285, 293, 302, 306, 310, 321,
Separation theorem for convex (see also Uniqueness of 322, 368 and a class of reduced
sets, 92, 93, 382-384 equilibrium and Stability of Tay1or expansion, 296. economies, 215-217
Sequential price adjustment, 305 equilibrium) Technica1 progress, 255, 256 in a constant returns
Shapley-Folkman theorem, 396, Star-shaped set, 376, 378 Temporary equilibrium, 136-151, economy, 318
399 strictly, 154, 376, 379, 381 167n, 347, 362, 366 and correspondence principie,
Share of profits, 77, 198, 204 State of the world, 122, 123, 125 compensated, 147 321
Shareholder, 352, 353, 354 Stationary equilibrium, 10 competitive, 147, 150 and diagonal dominance, 301
Shares, 359 Stationary expectations, 313 definition of, 37 and Gale property, 211-214
ownership of, 94 Stock market, 141, 142, 146 existence of, 38, 362 in a Hicksian economy, 221,
Short-period economy, 310, 311, Storage, 35 Terms of trade, 284 286,287
313,315 Strictly concave function, 277 Trade, 324, 328, 330 in a Keynesian economy, 360
Short-period equilibrium, 35-40, Strictly positive equilibrium, 292 Trade cycle, 325 in an L-economy, 236-237
'
309-315 Strictly quasi-concave function, l. Transaction, 264, 280, 302, 309, and non-singularity of
Short-run equilibrium, 49, 278 277 l, Jacobian, 304
331,338,339,340,341,342,
Sign-preserving function, 266 Subadditive function, 377, 378, 347, 349, 350, 362, 368 in a one-household economy,
Simplex, 21,402,403,424 382, 383 continuity of, 342 218
fundamental, 403, 423 Sub~equence, convergent, 271 intertemporal, 309 in a short-period economy,
n-dimensional, 20 Substitution tcrms, 105, 225, 234, l Transaction costs, 35, 350 311, 315
Singular matrix, 372 297,298,299 Transitivity, 78, 83 and stability of equilibrium,
Slack vector, 412 Super additivity, 201 r! Triangular trade, 348 272,275,277,279,280,
Slutzky relations, 105 Supply, multi-valued, 55, 58, 59 Two-good economy, 246, 282, 283 283,284,285,286,287,
Social welfare function, strictly Supply correspondence, 70 Two-good, two-factor economy, 288,294,296,301,304,
quasi-concave, 335 Supply function, 16, 18, 54 259 305,311,315,318
Solution path, 330 perceived, 152 Two-sector model, 237, 247, 318 and stability of tatonnement
boundedness of, 285,.286, 287, Support theorem, 382-384 and gross substitutes, 240 rule, 293
452 INDEX

Uniqueness continued . Vector average, convex hu]] of,


in a two-goods economy, 283, 189
284,285 Vector sum, 387, 399
and weak gross substitutes, approximated by a convex set, lllON- SOFlE
286 188,399 biac
perfect, 216 approximately convex, 392 'EX 13
Unit of account, 17, 19,268,356 convex hull of, 189
Upper contour set, 175, 190
Upper semi-continuity, 81,423 W (Walras' Iaw), 21
Utility Walras' law, 4, 7, 21, 29, 71,366
affected by prices, 129 for active excess demands, 365
first period derived, 144, 146 and satiation, 29
non-negative, 159 W AR ( weak axiom of revealed
non-transferable, 206n preference), 218
transferable, 205n Weak gross substitutes, 227-233,
Utility allocation, 96 249,286,289-292,296,298,
efficient, 159 32In
'easible, 91 and set of equilibrium prices,
feasible and efficient, 90-97 232 i
Pareto.-efficient, 95, 97 and weak axiom of revealed 1

Utility functions, 82-87, 358 preference, 230 ~


boundedness of, 335 Wealth, 353
continuity of, 84, 87 discontinuous change in, 354,
derived, 137, 350 355,360
differentiability of, 329 Welfare economics, 94, 106n
monotonicity of, 334 WGS (see Weak gross substitutes)
strict quasi-concavity of, 275, Wholesaler, 348
277, 332, 334
Zero exchange value of money,
Value and Capital, 312 355
Value of resources, 356 Zero prices, 20, 23, 29
Value theory, 369 Zero real wage, 355
452 INDEX

Uniqueness continued . Vector average, convex hu]] of,


in a two-goods economy, 283, 189
284,285 Vector sum, 387, 399
and weak gross substitutes, approximated by a convex set, lllON- SOFlE
286 188,399 biac
perfect, 216 approximately convex, 392 'EX 13
Unit of account, 17, 19,268,356 convex hull of, 189
Upper contour set, 175, 190
Upper semi-continuity, 81,423 W (Walras' Iaw), 21
Utility Walras' law, 4, 7, 21, 29, 71,366
affected by prices, 129 for active excess demands, 365
first period derived, 144, 146 and satiation, 29
non-negative, 159 W AR ( weak axiom of revealed
non-transferable, 206n preference), 218
transferable, 205n Weak gross substitutes, 227-233,
Utility allocation, 96 249,286,289-292,296,298,
efficient, 159 32In
'easible, 91 and set of equilibrium prices,
feasible and efficient, 90-97 232 i
Pareto.-efficient, 95, 97 and weak axiom of revealed 1

Utility functions, 82-87, 358 preference, 230 ~


boundedness of, 335 Wealth, 353
continuity of, 84, 87 discontinuous change in, 354,
derived, 137, 350 355,360
differentiability of, 329 Welfare economics, 94, 106n
monotonicity of, 334 WGS (see Weak gross substitutes)
strict quasi-concavity of, 275, Wholesaler, 348
277, 332, 334
Zero exchange value of money,
Value and Capital, 312 355
Value of resources, 356 Zero prices, 20, 23, 29
Value theory, 369 Zero real wage, 355

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen