Sie sind auf Seite 1von 7

THE

DEVELOPMENT
OF LOGIC
BY

WILLIAM KNEALE
F.8.A.,
white's professor of moral philosophy
IN THE OF

AND

MARTHA KNEALE
LADY HALL
OXFORD

OXFORD
AT THE CLARENDON PRESS
1962
"" W< lIWI II'PiP<apWI>I^IIIIUiI'II|Ji!pW'WWIWWII
II|'U^a^WWIJIWIIWW"I
M.W,"WmjJHI" '""WfWW 1' IUI' ' "Hl''rrwm*nr
.naSl

320 Logic after the renaissance THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 321


the details of their formal theory, e.g. their determination of the of Newton said that he had stolen the idea of the calculus from
valid moods of syllogism and their proofs of the special rules of their master, and the unmetaphysical minds of the eighteenth
the various figures. It is characteristic;, however, of Arnauld and century found his Theodicee and his Monadologie (published after
Nicole that before each of their passages dealing with details of his death) fantastic : he was the butt ofVoltaire's wit in Candide.
formal logic they tell the reader that he may omit what follows From short pieces published in journals,letters written to some of
since it is necessary only for pure theory. his many correspondents, and references scattered through his
A small point of some interest in their treatment of reason- Nouveaux Essais sur I'entendement humain (a detailed criticism of
ing is a remark that, when only one premiss of a valid syllogism Locke, first published in 1765) it became known that he claimed
is known to be true, the other premiss may be introduced as a to have made great discoveries in logic, but there was little avail-
condition to the conclusion. Given, for example, that no matter able to substantiate this claim. For years Leibniz had written
thinks, we may go on to infer that, if everything which feels pain copiously on his many projects, but in the form of notes or
'I
thinks, no matterfeels pain. And when neither premiss is known to memoranda, and most of what he had written remained un-
be true, we may even present them both as conditions in hypo- published in the library at Hanover, where he had served the
thetical statement.1 Here we have in effect a version of the prin- Elector as historian, scientific adviser, and expert on international
ciple of conditionalization (or 'deduction theorem') which was law. During the nineteenth century various selections from his
taken for granted by Aristotle and explicitly used by the Stoics. papers were published, but there was no complete (or nearly com-
Some features of the Port Royal Logic reflect special interests of plete) catalogue until 1895, 1 and even now there is no complete
Arnauld and Nicole which could not be expected to spread far text ; for the definitive edition in forty volumes projected by the
beyond their own circle ; but the general conception of logic Berlin Academy (of which he was the first president) has been
which they expounded in this book was widely accepted and con- delayed by anti-semitism and war.
tinued to dominate the treatment of logic by most philosophers There are many different facets to Leibniz's thought about
for the next 200 years. To follow in detail the transmission of logic. He was a man who took great delight in intellectual syn-
their influence would be tedious and not very profitable. In the thesis ; and just as he praised his metaphysical theory of monads
rest of this chapter we shall therefore consider instead another for connecting many things which would otherwise be discon-
1
it line of thought which has in the end proved much morefruitful, nected (e.g. teleology and mechanism, substance and energy,
though for a long time it produced little effect in the academic mind and matter, the infinitesimal calculus and microbiology),
teaching of logic. This is the line which Leibniz started as a boy, so too he valued his logic because it seemed to him like a jewel
a few years before the writing of the Port Royal Logic. that can throw light in many different directions. For an explana-
%: j
I' - tion of his thought it will therefore be necessary to consider a
2. The Interests of Leibniz number of his interests in turn, and we propose to treat briefly
of the following: (1) his respect for traditional logic, (2) his
Although, as we have seen, few famous thinkers of the seven- notion of an ars combinatorial or general theory of arrangements,
s
teenth and eighteenth centuries gave much attention to formal (3) his plans for an ideal language, (4) his scheme for the co-
logic, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who was born in 1646 and died ordination of knowledge in an encyclopaedia, and (5) his hope
hi
1 in 17 16, deserves to beranked among the greatest of all logicians.
1
for a general science of method. Each of these interests he shared
That his work on logic had little influence for nearly 200 years with some of his contemporaries, but the remarkable feature of
after he wrote was due in part to the dominance of other interests, his thought is the way in which he tried to relate them together.
connected with the rise of natural science, but also in part to the The order in which we shall deal with them is that which helps
II defects of his own character. He was a universal genius who con- most to an understanding of their connexions in Leibniz's mind.
It ceived many projects and made many beginnings but brought
little to fruition. When he died, his fame rested on his discovery
It corresponds in part to the order of development of his thought,
for (1) and (2) came very early and (5) later; but we do not
of the infinitesimal calculus and his defence of the metaphysical
; doctrine that this is the bestof all possible worlds. But the admirers
attach much importance to this, since it is not yet possible to trace
>i 1 E. Bodemann, Die
Leibniz-Handschriften der Koniglichen Offentlichen Bibliothek zu
1 Logiqtie, iii. 13. Hannover.
6341 V

f.
1
I

322 LOGIC AFTER THE RENAISSANCE THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 323


the history of his thought in detail, and it is1 clear in any case trine of twenty-four moods he committed himself quite explicitly
that he retained all these interests to the last. to the assumption of existential import for all universal state-
(1) According to his own statement Leibniz read Zabarella ments. We shall see that in spite of misgivings he never succeeded
with pleasure at the age of twelve and at the age offourteen had in freeing himselffrom this entanglement and that it was probably
the idea that all propositions might be arranged according to the one of the factors which prevented him from producing a really
order in which they gave matter for syllogisms, i.e. in a deductive satisfactory calculus of logic.
system like that which Euclid elaborated for geometry.2 This Thirdly, he preferred to reduce syllogisms to the first figure
enthusiasm for Aristotle's theory of the syllogism remained with per impossibile rather than by conversion, because he held that the
him still when he wrote the Nouveaux Essais. For he there describes method usually called indirect was really simpler. But he saw
Aristbtle's doctrine as 'one of the most beautiful discoveries of that syllogisms in the fourth figure could not be reduced at all
the human spirit', and says it is an 'art of infallibility'3 which can without principles of conversion (or at any rate without the prin-
be developed into 'a sort of universal mathematics'. These re- ciple of identity which he used for proofs of the principles of
marks are directed, of course, against Locke's depreciation of conversion in the second or third figures), and that in this respect
formal logic. In a note of 17 15, not intended for publication, he at least the tidinessof his scheme was compromised. 1 The remarks
was more outspoken: Lockius aliique gui spemunt non intelliguntA which he makes in this connexion show how carefully he had
But it is interesting to consider Leibniz's views on a number of studied the history of logic, and it is therefore rather strange that
points of syllogistic theory ; for he was by no means an Aris- he tries to justify indirect reduction by the principle of non-
totelian purist. contradiction alone, i.e. without the principle of primary logic
In the first place, he did not believe that all arguments could which the Stoics called the first thema.
be brought into syllogistic form. The examples of non-syllogistic Fourthly, he defended the view (which we have noticed already
reasoning which he liked to cite were the arguments by inversion in Wallis's work) that singular statements may be classed as
of relations and the arguments a recto ad obliquum discussed by universal for the purposes of syllogistic theory.2 If this were only
Junge in the Logica Hamburgensis. But he can scarcely have in- a dodgefor allowing us to treat arguments with singular premisses
tended to suggest that these were the only forms not covered by as though they were syllogisms, it would be harmless enough.
Aristotle's doctrine ; for he sometimes insisted that an enlarged For although these arguments are different in character from
theory of deduction would allow for many different calculi, and Aristotelian syllogisms, their rules have a similarity to those for
apart from that he was well aware of the impossibility ofreducing syllogistic reasoning which can be brought out by the device
conditional and disjunctive arguments to syllogistic form. He just mentioned. We think it is clear, however, that Leibniz went
held, nevertheless, that there is a common principle of all de- farther than this and accepted the assimilation of singular to
duction, namely, substitution of equivalents. s universal statements because it seemed to him there was no
Secondly, he maintained the existence of four figures of syl- fundamental difference between the two sorts. Such a conclusion
logism, each with six moods. This view appears already in his is implied by his often repeated assertion that in every true affir-
De Arte Combinatoria, written in 1666, when he was only nineteen mative proposition, whether universal or singular, necessary or
years of age, and it obviously attracted Leibniz because of its contingent, praedicatum inest subiecto, 3 and it is so important in his
tidy symmetry. He saw that the ordinary Aristotelian doctrine thought that it requires special notice.
offourteen moods, distributed between three figures, was due to Lord Russell argued in his book on The Philosophy of Leibniz
an arbitrary notion ofwhat was natural in reasoning, rather than that this principle was the chief source of the curious metaphysical
to any consistent theory of syllogistic form. In accepting the doc- doctrines to which Leibniz found himself committed. We can
now see that it was equallyfateful in the development ofLeibniz's
1 In giving references to works which have not been published separately we use logic. It may perhaps be paraphrased in English by the remark
*P' for Die philosophischen Schriften yon G. W. Leibniz and 'M' for Leibnizens mathe- 'Every true affirmative statement ascribes to the thing denoted
matische both edited by and '0' for Opuscules et fragments inidits
de Leibniz, edited by L. Couturat. The plan and much ofthe material ofthis section by its subject term an attribute which really inheres in that thing.
came from Couturat's Logique de Leibniz (1901)-
-3 Nouveaux Essais, iv. xvii.
4. We
2P> v> P- ia6
shall use 'ME.' for the title of this work.
5 Leibnitii Opera (cd. Dutens 1768), vi (i), p. 32.
- 3
1 #""" iv- ". 1. 2 K.E.
iv. xvii. 8.
0, p. 16; p. 51 0, pp. 518-19; Discours de metaphysique, 8; P, ii, p. 46.
* P, vii, p. 481.

I
I
\

324 LOGIC AFTER THE RENAISSANCE THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 325


Taken in this way, it would probably have been accepted by but he did a service to philosophy by trying to state it in un-
Aristotle ; for his account of general statementsisbased ona notion compromising form. The strenuousness of his efforts to preserve
of predication derived from consideration of singular statements. the old theory that every statement ascribes an attribute to a
But the application of the subject-predicate way of talking has subject shows his own uneasiness, and has stimulated later
usually tended to make philosophers think of general propositions logicians to shake themselves free from this part of the tradition.
The most fruitful idea that Leibniz derived from his study of
(
in a way appropriate only to singular propositions. In particular
they have assumed that the subject-term of a universal statement !
Aristotelian logic was the notion of formal proof. This is em-
must refer to something, and so have accepted without question
! phasized in the criticism of Locke noticed above, and it recurs
the doctrine of existential import. Leibniz sometimes followed again and again in his writings. He says, for example, that Des-
this line of thought, as we have noticed ; but the peculiarity of cartes's rules of method are psychological advice of no great
his philosophy is due in large part to the fact that he also fell into value, 1 and that Descartes's weakness as a writer on method2 was
the opposite mistake of trying to treat propositions about in- his failure to understand the importance of logical form. He
dividuals as though they were like the laws we express by recognized, of course, that the use of syllogisms in scholastic dis-
universal statements. When he used the phrase Praedicatum inest putations could degenerate into stupid pedantry; but he saw
subjecto, he thought not only ofthe sense in which wisdom may be also that there could be no rigour without formality, and he
said to inhere in Socrates, but also of the sense in which animality < insisted rightly on the importance of presenting new develop-
may be said to be contained in humanity ; and the second pre- ments of mathematics in such a way that their necessity could
dominated so far that he often talked as though there were a be seen to depend on their form. This interest of his was un-
concept or essence of each individual which necessarily involved fashionable when he wrote, and remained so for a long time
all the attributes predicable of that individual. This is the origin afterwards, but it has been amply justified in the past century.
of his principle ofthe identity of indiscernibles. Just as St. Thomas i (2) The theory of permutations and combinations was de-
Aquinas held that every angel was of a distinct species, because veloped first in the seventeenth century, primarily for its use in
they all lacked matter,by which ordinary things areindividuated, i connexion with the calculus of probabilities, and it attracted
so Leibniz maintained that every individual differedfrom every
i
Leibniz's attention while he was still in his teens. Indeed his
other in some attribute. 1 For him the distinction between history first considerable work was the De Arte Combinatorial mentioned
and science disappeared, and the assimilation of singular to '1
in an earlier paragraph. In later life he was annoyed by the
universal statements was no longer merely a dodge for economy of republication of this tract without his permission; the ground for
rules in the criticism of arguments, but the expression of a pro- his objection, however, was not that he had abandoned its theses,
found truth. but rather that he did not wish to have his immature work printed
His respect for the Aristotelian logic of subject and predicate as though it were a recent composition. 4 To the end of his life
had another unfortunate effect on Leibniz's thought, namely, he thought of the theory of combinations as something more
fundamental than ordinary logic ; but he meant by the phrase
f
that ofmaking him try to explain away propositions ofa relational
form. His mention of Junge's argument by inversion of relations ars combinatoria more than the rules for calculating the number of
(e.g. from 'Titus is bigger than Caius' to 'Caius is smaller than sub-sets of a certain constitution which may be formed from the
Titus') shows that he was aware of the need for an enlargement 1
members of a given set. In his teens he had conceived already
of logic by a theory of relations; but he was never able to admit ) the idea of an alphabet of human thought with which all possible
that the addition would be more than a gloss on the theory of thinkables might be constructed by suitable combinations and
attributes. According to him, 'Titus is bigger than Caius' means by which reasoning might be reduced to the quasi-mechanical
the same as 'Titus is big in as much as Caius is small', i.e. re- operation of going through a list. 5 His inspiration came from the
lational facts can be resolved into conjunctions of attributive Ars Magna of Raymond Lull and the Computatio sive Logica of
facts. 2 This doctrine is certainly untrue, and we shall see that it Hobbes (i.e. thefirst part ofDe Corpore).6 But he realized that in
hampered Leibniz seriously in the development ofhis own ideas ; 1 E. Bodemann, Die p. 82. 2 P, iv, p. 276.
1
2
Discours de metaphysique, 9.
0, p. 280. Cf. Fifth Letter to 47 (P, vii, p. 401).
3P, iv, p. 27.
-s P, vii, p. 185.
4
N-6E - - - -
IV m 18
P> iv, P- 64.

1
tfi

326 LOGIC AFTER THE RENAISSANCE THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 327

order to make the method useful two things were needed which express by putting together adjectives or common nouns, e.g. in
neither Lull nor Hobbes had provided : (a) an assurance that the the definition 'A triangle is a three-sided rectilinear figure', and
'alphabet' was really ultimate and complete, and (b) a procedure he failed to understand that the complexity of the world cannot
for making sure that all possible combinations were considered. be explained in this way alone. We shall have occasion to con-
In his early work so much space was given to the calculation of sider this point again, and we mention it here only because it is
the numbers ofcombinations permissible in certain circumstances interesting to notice that one of Leibniz's chief difficulties was
that these points were obscured ; but even there he made it clear implicit in his early treatment of the ars combinatoria.
that he was trying to work out a logic of discovery(logica inventiva), (3) Many writers of the seventeenth century put forward sug-
and he achieved at least one interesting result by showing that gestions for the construction of an artificial language ; in Leibniz's
there could be just twenty-four valid forms of syllogism. day such ideas flourished especially in England, where Wilkins
In the tract De Arte Combinatoria Leibniz tries to show how the and Dalgarno each advocated a system of his own. The chief
composition of complex geometrical notions could be exhibited arguments of the inventors were like those advanced in recent
concisely by a code in which integral numerals were made to times for Esperanto, namely, that communication would be
stand for termini primi (e.g. V for punctum and '2' for spatium) and much easier and the spread of ideas more rapid if all men, or at
fractional numerals for other terms which have been introduced least all learned men, had at their disposal a language con-
by definition and arranged in various classes (e.g. '|' for thefirst structed on simple principles and strictly regular in its grammar.
term of the second class, which happens to be quantitas). With Leibniz was not indifferent to such considerations. For he be-
this apparatus he produced such definitions as Circulus est lieved firmly in the importance of establishing peace and order
ab 18.21 habens rrjv i6.| rod 19 alicuius 1 ab 18.6. But he did not throughout the world, and he held that the advancement of
try to show how such a code might help in the enterprise with science depended on intellectual co-operation between men of
which he was mainly concerned, and thefact that he never made different nations. He therefore advocated at one time the use
any use of it in later works suggests that he soon realized its in- of a basicregular Latin (presumably something like theLatino sine
adequacy as an instrument oflogical analysis. It is in fact no more flexione used by Peano at the beginning of this century in his
philosophical than a telegraph code, and it is interesting chiefly Formulario Mathematico). 1 But his interest in the construction of an
because it shows in a clear light the difficulties of the project ideal language went much farther than this. He wanted a scien-
Leibniz had in mind. tific language which would help not merely in the com-
In the first place, Leibniz's list of twenty-seven termini primi munication of thoughts but also in thinking itself, 2and this he
for geometry is not compiled on any intelligible principle. Some called a lingua philosophica or characteristica universalis.
of the items, such as punctum and dimensio, seem to be peculiar The fundamental principle in Leibniz's theory of symbolism is
to geometry, while others, such as unum, possibile, and omne, have that our expressions should mirror the structure of the world.
application outside that study; and of the geometrical terms it is Although the basic signs which stand for simple elements may be
by no means clear that all are indispensable. Secondly, the need chosen arbitrarily, there must be an analogy, in the strict sense
for auxiliary expressions such as ab, habens, alicuius, and the in- of that word, between their relations and the relations of the
flected Greek articles in the formulation of definitions is a sign of elements they signifiy, 3 so that the name of each complex thing
the insufficiency of Leibniz's analysis. In order to carry out his is its definition and thekey to all its properties. 4 We cannot escape
programme satisfactorily it would be necessary (a) to distinguish from the use of signs in thinking, but our ordinary systems fall
sharply between the common signs of logical syntax and the short of the ideal, and this is the chief source of the difficulty of
peculiar signs of geometry and {b) to consider carefully what sorts intellectual work: Tn signis spectanda est commoditas ad in-
of complexity can occur in definitions, or, in other words, what veniendum, quae maxima est quoties rei naturam internam paucis
is to be understood by the 'combination' of simple geometrical exprimunt et velut pingunt ; ita enim mirifice imminuitur cogi-
notions. Leibniz's failure to produce a convincing example of his tandi labor. 5 In mathematics the importance of good symbolism
method was due mainly to his obsession with the idea that all is already established by the discoveries which it has made possible
complexity must arise from the conjunction of attributes. When 1 P, vii, p. 28. 2 P, vii, p.
184. 3 P, vii, p.
192.
he talked of combination he thought of such complexes as we 4 0, p. 152. 5 iv, p. 455-

!
TT

328 LOGIC AFTER THE RENAISSANCE THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 329


:!
(e.g. Leibniz's own discovery of the infinitesimal calculus), but There were two reasons why Leibniz never succeeded in pro-
we need a thread of Ariadne to guide us through the labyrinth of ducing a definite system. Thefirst was the impossibility of draw-
other studies, 1 and this we can get only from the characteristica ing up a dictionary for the new language until the work of
universalis. With such a help to thought we shall be free from the scientific research had been brought to completion, or at least
snares of the evil genius imagined by Descartes, because all will nearer to completion than itwas in Leibniz's own day. We cannot
be clear and there will be no danger offalse memory. provide an explanatory symbolism for chemistry until chemistry
In order to carry out Leibniz's programme, or any part of it, already exists as a science. Descartes had made this point earlier
we should have to provide (a) symbols for all the notions to be in the century against a proposal of Mersenne, and it did not
1

taken as ultimate or unanalysable, and (b) suitable devices for k escape the attention of Leibniz. His enthusiasm for the project
expressing such formal notions as predication, conjunction, dis- of an encyclopaedia was due in part to his hope that it would
junction,negation, conditional connexion, universality, and exis- help to make possible the production of'a characteristic^ universalis.
tence. In most ordinary languages there are special symbols But there was a second reason, unknown to Leibniz, why he
(called syncategorematic) to signify some of the formal notions, could make little progress in the construction of an ideal language,
but it is not essential that these should always be expressed by and that was his failure to shake himself free from the subject-
separate words. In ancient Greek, for example, the notion of pre- predicate dogma of traditional logic.
dication could be expressed by the placing of an adjective before I We have seen already how Leibniz failed in his early attempt
a noun with the definite article, as in 6 avrjp, and in English to apply the ars combinatoria to geometrical notions. The limitation
we can express conjunction by the simple juxtaposition of words, of his thought which made failure inevitable on thatoccasion was
as in the phrase 'a round red apple. Furthermore, even non- certain also to prevent him from working out a system of sym-
formal notions may sometimes be expressed by the arrangement bolism in which the name of each thing would be itsdefinition
of other symbols. This is most obvious in the making of maps, and thekey to all its properties. For the notion of complexity with
when the relative positions of the various natural features are which he worked was always that of the conjunction of attributes,
shown by therelative positions ofmarks associated with the names andthis is not sufficient to account for the diversity of thinkables.
of those features. But it can occur also in oral language, as when A typical suggestion to which he recurred on several occasions
Julius Caesar said Veni, vidi, vici, meaning that his arrival, his was that simple ideas might be expressed by different prime
inspection, and his conquest happened in the order of the verbs i
numbers and complex ideas by products of primes.2 Since there
he used to announce them. How exactly Leibniz wished to con- is only one way in which any given natural number can be de-
struct his characteristica universalis is not clear; for he never pro- composed into primes, this plan would enable a person who had
duced a detailed scheme or even discussed the alternatives noticed mastered the system to read off, or at least to work out in un-
above. But he probably thought of it most often as a script in ambiguous fashion, the definition ofeach derivative term ;Leibniz
which the non-formal notions would be represented by signs other was dissatisfied with it only because he hoped for some system in
than words. Sometimes he says that it would be like algebra, and ' which even the primitive terms would be intelligible without a
sometimes that it would be an improved version of the Chinese dictionary, i.e. a kind of picture writing which would be not only
ideographic system. 2 And he certainly intended it to exhibit the independent of the spoken language (as Chinese characters are)
logical form of propositions in a simple and more regular way than but also very easy to learn. 3 But such a system would not allow
any natural language. For he often asserts that a philosophically for the expression ofcomplexities outside a very restricted range.
y
constructed grammar will make formal reasoning easy by provid- Let us consider for an example the meaning of the common term
ing theframework for a calculusratiocinator (i.e. a quasi-mechanical 'grandparent. This is obviously complex, and Leibniz could
method of drawingconclusions) in which even the non-syllogistic scarcely wish to express it in his numerical system by a prime
arguments ofJungemaybe brought under afew simplerules ofpro- number; but it is not the notion of a thing with two or more
cedure. Andheprophesies that,when the new languageisperfected, attributes conjoined. When we say that X is a grandparent, we
men of good will desiring to settle a controversy on any subject mean that there are two persons V and Z such that X is a parent
whatsoever will take their pens in their hands and say Calculemus.3 1 Descartes, CEuvres (cd. Adam et Tannery), i, p.
76.
z 3 ME. m. i- 1 and iv. vi. 2.
1 0, p. 337. 0, p. 30. 3 P, vii, p. 200. 2 P, vii, p.
292.
T

330 LOGIC AFTER THE RENAISSANCE THE INTERESTS OF LEIBNIZ 331

of V and V a parent of Z. We have here what might be called him by some of the work which he did for his employer, the
a second power of an asymmetrical, intransitive, two-termed Elector of Hanover. But at a still later date he abandoned such
relation. Leibniz could not fit it into his scheme, because he never schemes in favour of a proposal that the encyclopaedia should
took relations seriously. include only the first principles of the various sciences, and to-
(4) We have seen that Leibniz was interested in the making wards the end of his life seems to have limited his project to the
of an encyclopaedia because he hoped that a systematic collection presentation of a unified world-view, at once scientific and
of knowledge would make it possible to construct a characteristica religious. His tract called Principes de la nature et de la grace and
universalis. But he had other reasons of a more obvious kind for his Monadologie were written for this purpose.
his interest. In the first place he was himself a polymath with a The planning of the encyclopaedia was usually linked in Leib-
strong desire to extend his learning yet farther and bring it all niz's thought with schemes for co-operative research in learned
into a single system. His works and his correspondence show the academies. At various times he sent proposals to the Royal
enormous range of his curiosity. Logic, mathematics, physics, Society of London, Louis XIV of France, Frederick I of Prussia,
engineering, biology, philology, history, politics, jurisprudence, and Peter the Great of Russia. With the King of Prussia he had
metaphysics, and theology were all for him congenial studies ; some success ; for his initiative led to the founding of the Prussian
and in nearly all of them his knowledge was at least equal to that Academy with himself as president for life. But in general the
of the most learned of the age. Since he died there has been no i response to his proposals was not encouraging, and the last years
man for whom the same distinction could be claimed ; and his of his life must have been a time of disappointment. He had hoped
writings show that his interest in the making of an encyclopaedia to accompany George I to England, but he was ordered to stay
was due in large part to his realization of a growing tendencyto the in Hanover, perhaps because of the dispute about the discovery
fragmentation ofknowledge. 1 Secondly, hebelieved that the safety of the differential calculus. When he died, there was little prospect
of all society depended on the maintenance of good order in the that science would be perfected and civilization made secure by
intellectual realm, and he sometimes thought of an encyclopaedia a college of illuminati.
as an instrument for uniting scholars of all groups. He was (5) Projects for an encyclopaedia contributed to the formation
especially interested in the reconciliation of the churches, and of Leibniz's logical theory only in so far as they led him to think
himself devoted much care to the exposition ofthe doctrines which about the possibility of organizing knowledge in a deductive
had to be brought into harmony. system. But his reflections on scientific method were ofthe greatest
Like his other leading ideas, the project of an encyclopaedia importance for his logic. Like Bacon and Descartes before him,
remained with Leibniz from his youth until his death, but it he thought it was possible to describe a procedure for the rapid
took somewhat different forms at different dates. When he was enlargement of knowledge, and he sometimes wrote as though
about twenty, he thought of it only as an opus Photianum, or series the work of research might be completed in his lifetime and made
of extracts from the best writers on all the various subjects. Thus available to all men by an order ofmissionaries (Ordo Pacidianorum
the logic would be taken mainly from Junge and the physics or Societas Theophilorum) devoted to that purpose. For there was
1

mainly from Hobbes. 2 At this date mathematics had no more than in his thinking an element of that mysticism which makes men
a minor place, in his scheme, because hehimself had not yet made look for the consummation of history in a millenium. When he
much progress in that science. But he insisted already that the wrote his De Arte Combinatoria, he had already the idea of a logic
material should be presented in a logical order of development. At of discovery, and in his later work this becomes the dominant
a later date the mathematical ideal became dominant in his theme under which his other interests can all be organized. We
thought, and he not only gave a bigger place to mathematics in can see this most clearly from a number of fragments about a
his scheme but wished to have the whole prepared in the demon- work on General Science, i.e. the science of method, which he
strative form of Euclid's Elements. When his plans were most planned to produce under the pseudonym 'Guilielmus Pacidius'.2
ambitious, he proposed to include the knowledge of nature which One of thesefragments, from which we reproduce selectionsbelow,
had been accumulated by craftsmen but not hitherto written is especially interesting because it mentions all the various interests
down for students to read. This idea may have been suggested to ofLeibniz and shows by its style what sort of man he was.
1 P, vii, p. 160. 2 La Logique de Leibniz, pp. 57_I - 1 0, pp.
3-8. 2 From Pax Dei : 0, p.
4.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen