Sie sind auf Seite 1von 15

Society for Music Theory

Method and Motivation in Hugo Riemann's History of Harmonic Theory


Author(s): Scott Burnham
Source: Music Theory Spectrum, Vol. 14, No. 1 (Spring, 1992), pp. 1-14
Published by: University of California Press on behalf of the Society for Music Theory
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/746078
Accessed: 23/01/2010 09:01

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucal.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

University of California Press and Society for Music Theory are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve
and extend access to Music Theory Spectrum.

http://www.jstor.org
Method and Motivation in Hugo Riemann's
History of Harmonic Theory

Scott Burnham

Concerning the enthusiasm for the natural sciences so For Riemann is quite explicit about his allegiance to the
characteristicof late nineteenth-centurythought, the German methods and viewpoints of naturalscience. His earliest work
philosopher Wilhelm Wundt once quipped: "In the seven- eagerly takes up the physiological orientation of Helmholtz;
teenth century God gave the laws of nature, in the eighteenth somewhat later he comes to share the excitement generated
nature did it herself, and in the nineteenth the individual by the claims to science of the field of psychology.3But Rie-
scientists take care of that task."' And, we might add, they mann's engagement with natural science was to extend be-
were taking care of it with such apodictic aplomb that it is yond the hunger pangs of methodological acquisition to the
hardly a surprise to see a young music theorist like Hugo satiety of an epistemological standpoint:the understandingof
Riemann set his course as a musical thinker by the lights of art involves the discovery of underlyingnaturallaws that are
the natural scientists of his generation. Nor is it surprisingto consciously or unconsciously obeyed by artists.4 Riemann
find that this is how Riemann is most often and most eco- conceives of harmony as forming the natural law-governed
nomically portrayed by latter-day historians of theory.2 basis of music; harmony provides the terms of what he calls
"musical logic."5 Such logic is said to underlie the natural
The author is indebted to Ivan Waldbauer, whose panel on Riemann at
the 1990 AMS/SMT/SEMnational conference in Oakland, Californiamade
possible the original version of this paper. 3For an interestingperspective on the role of psychology and physiology
'Cited in Alexander Gode-von Aesch, Natural Science in German Ro- in Riemann's work see Peter Rummenholler, MusiktheoretischesDenken im
manticism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1941), 24. 19. Jahrhundert,Studien zur Musikgeschichtedes 19. Jahrhunderts,vol. 12
2Forexample: "Riemann'saesthetic is rooted in the discoveries and pro- (Regensburg: Gustav Bosse Verlag, 1967), 100ff.
cedural assumptionsof physiology, psychology, and acoustical physics, all of 4Riemannspecificallychargesart theory with the duty of uncoveringthese
which he considered to be equal partnerswith theoretical speculation in the laws. See Riemann, Geschichteder Musiktheorieim IX.-XIX. Jahrhundert,
study of music" (Ruth Solie, review of William C. Mickelsen's Hugo Rie- 2d ed. (Berlin: Max Hesse Verlag, 1921), 470. (This edition was reprinted
mann's Theory of Harmony, in Nineteenth-CenturyMusic 2, no. 2 [1978]: in 1961 by the Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlungin Hildesheim.) The chap-
179). See also Hellmuth Christian Wolff's spirited encomium "Hugo Rie- ters of the second edition that are cited in the present article are identical
mann, der Begriinderder systematischenMusikbetrachtung,"FestschriftMax to those of the initial 1898 edition.
Schneiderzum Achtzigsten Geburtstage,ed. Walther Vetter (Leipzig: Deu- 5Inhis sturdyaccount of the development of Riemann'sharmonictheory,
tscher Verlag fur Musik, 1955), 265-70. Elmar Seidel refers to Riemann's notion of musical logic as a "roter Faden"
2 MusicTheory Spectrum

coherence of all music: if one discovers the truth about har- vertretungto provide as secure a foundation for further sys-
monic logic, one discovers the truth about Music. From this tematic expansion as would a purely scientific basis.8
fundamental assumption, Riemann can make the claim that The appropriationon the part of the human sciences of
even the melodies of musical antiquityrest on the foundation some of the methods and much of the confidence of the nat-
of harmony, and that it took the entire development of poly- ural sciences had a broad influence on the writing of art his-
phonic music, from its crudest beginningsto its full harmonic tories and intellectual histories.9Such histories could now be
glory, to reveal completely the theoretical (that is, harmonic) recast as histories of human development, understood as the
underpinnings of monody.6 The idea that tonal harmonic gradualrealization of an innate human entelechy. The shape
logic acts as a universal musical attribute informs much of of these narrativeswas controlled by the resilient prevalence
Riemann's work from the 1880s and 1890s; only in the last of organicistthought:earlierstages of development were seen
decade of his life would he start to consider the autonomous as the primitiveyet fundamentalseeds from which later stages
viability of other musical systems.7 could grow and develop.10As we shall see, these are precisely
It may seem paradoxical that Riemann, who so vocifer- the terms in which Hugo Riemann cast his views on the
ously rejected acoustics and mathematics as the absolute history of harmonic theory.
foundation of musical understanding, should attach the va- In 1898, Riemann completed and published his History of
lidity and essential timelessness of natural law to his theo- Music Theory, an ambitious digest of a thousand years of
retical conception of harmonic logic, which he increasingly theory, from the ninth throughthe nineteenth centuries. Rie-
based on human psychology. He thus appears to replace one mann himself admits, in the foreword to the firstedition, that
set of a priori suppositions with another, distinctly less ver- his expansive constructionis in fact the result of two separate
ifiable, set. Yet this sort of transactionwas quite simply the projects. He originallyintended to restricthis researchto the
privilege of his age. Just as naturalist authors, especially in early history of music theory, extending no furtherthan Tinc-
Germany, sought to demonstratethat human psychology was toris. Some twenty years of interveningwork on the practical
a determinable affair, subject to the indifferent control of and speculative aspects of harmonic theory then led to a
natural laws, so too did thinkers like Riemann place confi-
dence in the hard validity and causal consistency of so-called 8Riemann, "Die Natur der Harmonik," Sammlung MusikalischerVor-
"psychologicalfacts." One need only point out that Riemann trdge, ed. Paul Graf Waldersee (Leipzig: Breitkopf and Hirtel, 1882), 185.
considered the psychological basis of his principle of Klang- The relevant passage is cited and discussed by Rummenholler, 102, as well
as by Seidel, 54. I am grateful to Brian Hyer for sending me a copy of the
Riemann essay.
9Gode-von Aesch discusses some of the more extreme manifestationsof
this confidence in Natural Science, 26.
which runs through all the different periods of his theoretical work. See "lThe force of this narrativepremise is what compels Riemann to posit
Seidel, "Die HarmonielehreHugo Riemanns," Beitrdgezur Musiktheoriedes a harmonicbasis for early Western monody: if harmony is indeed a funda-
19. Jahrhunderts,ed. Martin Vogel, Studien zur Musikgeschichte des 19. mental and universal aspect of music it must have been there near the start
Jahrhunderts,vol. 4 (Regensburg: Gustav Bosse Verlag, 1966), 47. of music's evolution-it could not have arisen as a later development. Allan
6Riemann, Geschichte, 471. Keiler makes this point in connection with HeinrichSchenker'searly writings
7See, for example, his monograph entitled FolkloristischeTonalitdtsstu- in "The Origins of Schenker's Thought: How Man is Musical," Journal of
dien (Leipzig, 1916). Riemann'schange of position is discussedby Wolff, 267. Music Theory 33 (1989): 281f.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 3

desire to ground modern harmonic theory with a thorough works which have a palpable significance, either positive or
study of its origins; to this end, Riemann worked back from negative, for what he calls the developmental history (Ent-
the present until he found himself in the sixteenth century, wicklungsgeschichte)of the theory of Tonsatz. 2 And he only
facing the furthest extent of his previous work. He then de- discusses those aspects of the included theoretical works
cided to publish both studies as a history of theory reaching which seem to him to impinge upon this history. Moreover,
all the way to his own age. Riemann'scriteriafor determiningthese aspects as well as the
This article is concerned with the latter half of this positive or negative significance they hold for the develop-
work-in which Riemann traces the development of har- ment of harmonic theory are drawn entirely from the con-
monic theory from Zarlino to himself-and begins with an clusions of his own theoretical work. The ramifications of
attempt to describe what it is that Riemann is actually doing such a method of historical investigation loom large; we will
when he purports to write the history of harmonic theory. probe some of them after a more focused look at some of the
This will entail both a broad overview of his historicalschema particularsof Riemann's history.
and a much closer reading of his criticalengagement with one Each theorist that Riemann discusses is analyzed for as-
particulartheorist, in this case Rameau. His motives for writ- pects which further the development of harmonictheory and
ing such a history in the first place will then be examined. aspects which hinder that development. Thus, for example,
Finally, his enterprise will be characterized in terms of the Zarlino is lauded for his recognition of the primacy of the
conflicting currents of methodology and motivation in the triad and for his alleged emphasis on harmonicdualism, that
Geisteswissenschaftenof the late nineteenth century and in is to say, on the isolation of major and minor triads as the
terms of an ideological position which had become funda- "two possible forms of harmony."'3The concept of dualism
mental to the formative stages of German musicology. was to become, of course, the central axiom of Riemann's
How does Riemann conceive of the history of harmonic own harmonic theory. On the other hand, Zarlino's adher-
theory? Near the beginning of the final chapter of his book, ence to the contrapuntalstricturesof the old school have, for
Riemann presents a brief summaryof this history in explicitly Riemann, a retarding effect on his more speculative notions
developmental terms: theoretical understanding grows out- about harmony.14
ward from the establishment of the consonant chord to the Riemann claims that Zarlino's discovery of harmonic du-
recognition that whole groups of chord formations can have ality was eclipsed in the generations that followed, especially
the same harmonic significance (as inversions of the same by adherents to the figured-bassschool of theory. This claim
basic chord), then to an understandingof cadence formations is based on a dichotomy which remains decisive throughout
and, finally, to a complete doctrine of the immanent logic of Riemann's history: speculative advances in harmonic theory
harmonic progressions, a doctrine of the natural and law- are countered by pragmaticadvances. Thus for Riemann, the
governed coherence of harmonic motion.1' His decision to figured-bassschool, while revolutionizingthe practicalart of
interpret the history of theory in this way provides him with accompaniment, completely obscured Zarlino's discovery of
a clear strategy for choosing and arrangingthe facts of that
history: he states that he has included only those theoretical 12Ibid.,506.
'3Ibid., 389ff.
1Riemann, Geschichte, 473. '4Ibid., 425.
4 MusicTheory Spectrum

dualism, leaving it to be rediscovered with consequence only took no account of the coherent logical and hierarchicalcon-
in the nineteenth century. Despite his generally antagonistic nections in tonal harmony.18
attitudetowardthe figured-bassera, Riemann admitsthat the Another speculative swing of the pendulumtakes place for
treatises generated therein served to extend the growth of Riemann in the nineteenth century, setting the stage for his
theoretical knowledge. Advances included the continued and own ideas. Moritz Hauptmann was the first to realize that
enhanced recognition of the triad, as well as the incipient apparently consonant chords could actually have dissonant
recognition of inversions.15 But the main purpose of the harmonic significance.19Although Hauptmann's discovery
figured-bassera in music theory is conceived negatively by falls in the province of acoustics (specifically, the acoustical
Riemann. After reviewing some of the contradictory and dissonance of the ii chord), Riemann was to develop from it
variant methods of figured-bassnumbering prevalent in the a complete system of hierarchicalharmonicsignificance,rest-
early eighteenth century, Riemann claims that this confused ing on the assertion that secondarytriads are only apparently
situation was instrumental in encouraging Jean-Philippe consonant and are to be theoretically construed as dissonant
Rameau to make the first attempt at replacing figured bass variants of the three main harmonic functions (tonic, dom-
with a new type of designation which would reveal the roles inant, and subdominant).
of harmonies within a central key.16 Two other discoveries led directly to Riemann's own the-
Thus it is Rameau who initiates the next speculative ad- oretical work. The first was the re-discovery of harmonic
vance in Riemann's history. According to Riemann, the dualism, posited by Hauptmann in 1853 and supported by
French theorist developed a "doctrine of the significance of Arthur von Ottingen's 1866 treatise Harmoniesystemin du-
harmonies for the logic of musical composition."'7 But this aler Entwickelung,in which Ottingen construes harmonicdu-
advance, like that of Zarlino, is countered by a pragmatic alism as the tonic and phonic derivationsof major and minor
reaction, in this case triggeredby an aspect of Rameau's own respectively.20 The second decisive discovery was Karl
system. The concept felt by Riemann to harbor the most Stumpf'srecognitionthat harmonicsignificanceis a fact more
disastrousconsequences for Rameau and the reception of his psychological than acoustical.21This led to Riemann's life-
work is that of chord structure by thirds. The next few gen- long preoccupationwith what he called Tonvorstellung,or the
erations of harmonic theorists took Rameau's idea of chord mental representationof sound, construed as a logically con-
structureby thirds and made it the basis of a proliferationof sistent cognitive activity.
pragmatically oriented chord-classification schemes which It should be sufficiently clear that Riemann reads earlier
theorists from the standpoint of his own views about the
primacy of harmony and the nature of tonal harmonic logic.
'5Riemann realizes some of the theoretical implications of figured-bass If we return to his reading of Rameau, we can do a closer
notation-for example, the very fact that the triad may remain unmarkedin analysisof what Riemann sees and what he chooses to ignore.
this notationreveals an underlyingassumptionabout its primacy,its normality
(ibid., 435-36). He also claims that figured-basstheorists such as Gottfried '8But Riemann disassociatesfrom this prevailingtrend the "enlightened"
Keller were led to an enhanced recognition of inversions when searchingfor work of Daube and Tartini, who both recognized, in differing ways, the
practical ways to simplify the role of the accompanist. Ibid., 453. primacy of tonic, subdominant, and dominant harmony. Ibid., 486-93.
'6Ibid., 469. 19Ibid.,515f.
x7"Lehrevon der Bedeutung der Harmonienfur die Logik des Tonsatzes" 20Ibid., 519f.
(ibid., 474). 21Ibid., 522.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 5

We will then be in a better position to access the assumptions Example 1. Rameau'ssixte ajoutee
which underlie his theoretical constructionof tonal music and
which greatly influence his understandingof history and the "
0
writing of history. Added sixth Major third
As mentioned above, Riemann sees Rameau's chief virtue 6
in his conception of harmonic significance based on tonal
coherence. Accordingly, Riemann emphasizes everything in
Rameau's various treatises which supports the hierarchical Fifth
# " *
and logically coherent conception of a tonal center and its 5
subservient harmonies. This includes Rameau's position on
the primacy of the dominant-tonic relationship, his estab-
lishment of tonic, subdominant, and dominant as the "triple
proportion," his alleged recognition that the vi chord acts as
a tonic substitute in the deceptive cadence, and his concept
of "characteristicdissonance" and modulation.22 Fourth note 0
Fundamentalbass V: Tonic note
Yet Rameau is characterizedas havingfailed to bringthese 6
ideas to term, simply because he was more fundamentally 5

committed to building chords by thirds. Riemann claims that


this was the principle from which Rameau derived all har- In Riemann's view, the latter interpretation, that of the su-
mony, a principle that was furthered by later generations of pertonic seventh chord in inversion, betrays Rameau's fun-
theorists, thus deterring the true development of harmonic damentalinsight about the subdominantand its characteristic
theory. Not only does Riemann assert that third-structuring dissonance. Riemann argues that Rameau was swayed by his
rules Rameau's derivation of harmony; he also states that principle of third-structuringwhen he "all too frequently"
Rameau's rules for the progression of the fundamental bass interprets this chord as a ii7.24 But it is of course Rameau's
grow out of the same unhappy idea.23 theory of the double emploi that stands behind the possibility
There is an importantaspect of Rameau's theory that Rie- for two differinginterpretationsof the same harmonicentity:
mann cannot, or will not, see. To uncover that aspect it is the analyticaldecision to regard the sixte ajoutee as a seventh
necessary to examine those passages in which Riemann dis- chord on the supertonic is based on Rameau's stricturesfor
cusses Rameau's notion of third-structuring.Riemann is trou- the motion of the fundamental bass. The fundamental bass
bled by Rameau's ambivalence about the subdominant and cannot normativelyprogress by a second upwards;therefore,
its characteristicdissonance, the sixte ajoutee (see Example when the chord structurein Example 1 (with or without the
1). At times Rameau interprets this harmonic structure as a added sixth) is followed by a dominant chord, as it so often
subdominant with the added sixth, at times as the inverted is in practice, the analystmust perforce interpretit as a chord
form of a seventh chord built from the second scale degree. based on the second scale degree, a fifth away from the dom-

22Ibid., 479-83. 24Ibid., 488. Example 1 is taken from Jean-Philippe Rameau, Treatise on
23Ibid., 490. Harmony, ed. and trans. Philip Gossett (New York: Dover, 1971), 74.
6 MusicTheory Spectrum

inant. Rameau's admittedly strong claims about the primacy Riemann prefers to read this as a statement to the effect
of third-structuring allow him to make this analytical choice, that the fundamental bass can only move in intervals of a third
but they do not dictate such a choice, as Riemann asserts. The or its compounds, the fifth and the seventh. His interpretation
choice is instead dictated by Rameau's conception of how the is supported by some tendentious editing of the above quote.
fundamental bass must move, which in turn is based on the For example, the clause before Riemann's excerpted version
primacy of the interval of a fifth. reads: "The fifth, however, should be considered the interval
That Riemann cannot see this aspect of Rameau's work best suited for the bass. ..." In view of the reconstituted
is obvious from his own interpretation of the basis of version of this quotation as well as what we know about
Rameau's rules for the progression of the fundamental bass. Rameau's harmonic derivation, it is clear that Rameau con-
According to Riemann, the motion of the fundamental bass siders the interval of the fifth, and not the third, to be the
is governed by Rameau's principle of third-structuring. He progenitor of harmonic motion.
quotes the following passage from the 1722 Traite in support Why does Riemann thus misread Rameau? Why will he
of his claim: not admit the primacy of the fifth for the motion of the fun-
damental bass? I would argue, first, that Riemann needed to
In fact, we never hear a final cadence or the end of a piece in which
use the idea of third-structuring as a kind of scapegoat prin-
this progression [the falling fifth] is not the primary element....
Since the fifth is constructedof two thirds, the bass, in order to hold ciple, one which could account for those aspects of Rameau's
the listener in an agreeable state of suspense, may be made to pro- theories that do not correspond with Riemann's own ideas.
ceed by one or several thirds .... Dissonance may sometimes oblige For example, Riemann could not understand why Rameau
us to make the bass ascend only a tone or a semitone. In addition would undermine the singularity of the subdominant by oc-
to the fact that this arises from a license introducedby the deceptive casionally interpreting the sixte ajoutee as a supertonic sev-
cadence . . . we may note that this ascending (but not descending) enth, thus substituting functional variant for functional pro-
tone or semitone is the inversion of the seventh.... 2 totype.26 Additionally, when Rameau prohibits the root
motion of a second in the fundamental bass (in favor of root
2SIbid., 490. I have condensed the passage. Riemann quotes Rameau in motion by fifth or third), he precludes what is for Riemann
the original French (introducinghis own elisions, interjections, and italics),
as follows: "En effet on n'entendjamaisde cadencesfinalesou de conclusions
the basic dialectical progression of subdominant moving to
de chants, que cette progression(de quinte descendante) n'en soit le premier
objet ... et ce que nous disons de la Quinte doit s'entendreaussi de la Quarte
(ascendante)qui la represente toujours ... ensuite pour tenir l'auditeurdans Treatiseon Harmony, 60. Interested readers should also consult the original
une suspension agr6ablecomme la Quinte est composee de deux tierces l'on context of the passage in Rameau's Traitede l'harmonie (1722), 50-51.
peut faire proc6derla Basse par une ou plusieurstierces, reservanttoutes les 26CarlDahlhaus explores in variouspublicationsthe tension in Riemann's
cadences a la Quinte seule et a la Quarte qui la repr6sente,de sorte que toute function theory between prototype and variant. See, for example, Dahlhaus,
la progression de la Basse fondamentale doit etre renfermeedans ces conso- Untersuchungenuber die Entstehung der harmonischen Tonalitat (Kassel:
nances. Et si la dissonance nous oblige quelquefois a ne faire monter cette Barenreiter, 1968), 42, or "Terminologischeszum Begriff der harmonischen
Basse que d'un Ton ou d'un semi-Ton, outre que cela provient d'une licence Funktion," Die Musikforschung28, no. 2 (1975): 197-202. In "The Concept
introduitepar la cadence rompue . . . I'on peut remarquerque ce Ton ou ce of Function in Riemann," a paper delivered at the 1990 AMS/SMT/SEM
semi-Tonen montantet non pas en descendant(!) sont renversezde la Septieme national conference in Oakland, California, Brian Hyer critically engages
(!) que se fait entendre pour lors entre ces deux sons qui forment ou Ton ou Dahlhaus's interpretationwhile offering his own "deconstruction"of Rie-
semi-Ton." (Several accents have been added in accordance with modern mann'sconcept of function. Hyer argues that while Riemann describes func-
usage.) I am using Philip Gossett's rendering of the passage; see Rameau, tion as an object, the concept he has in mind really denotes a relation.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 7

dominant. Third-structuringcan be invoked as a rationale for (except the subdominant) are referred to as simple domi-
both of these alleged deviations, and Riemann obviously nants, understood as analogues to the so-called dominant-
needed to find an idea in Rameau's work which could be held tonic.27What is importantto rememberhere is that the actual
accountable for the perception that Rameau and his direct content of harmonic progression remains open-ended for
descendants were blocked in pursuing those elements of Rameau. That is to say, the necessary components of any
Rameau's system that were to be fundamentalto Riemann's given chord progressionare not generalized by Rameau; only
own system. The promotion of the principle of third- the nature in which the chords move is defined and under-
structuringfrom an a posteriori to an a priori condition of stood in terms of the prototypicalmodel of dominant-seventh
Rameau's theory accords with Riemann's fashioning of the leading to tonic triad.
history of harmonictheory as the conflict between the forces Now let us consider the nature of harmonicprogressionin
of theoretical advancementand those of theoretical entrench- Riemann's function theory. He posits a prototypical har-
ment: as was the case with the aftermathof Zarlino, Rameau monic progression consisting of the sequence of functions
and his followers allegedly failed to realize the more spec- tonic, subdominant, dominant, and tonic-or T, S, D, and
ulative advances in his work, preferring to treat as funda- T. The members of any given chord progression are under-
mental those aspects which could be turned to the pragmatic stood to represent one (and sometimes two) of these three
ends of constructivist theory. Yet I believe that Riemann's underlying functions. Here the generalized aspect of har-
misreading of Rameau runs deeper than an attempt to seize monic progressioninvolves the actual harmoniccomponents:
upon the most readily available scapegoat principle; Rie- chord progressions are made up of T functions, S functions,
mann's deprecatory fixation on the idea of third-structuring and D functions.
is not so much a matter of willful reinterpretation after the Riemann does not, like Rameau, postulate a prototypical
fact as it is the result of a blind spot. To trace the shape of mode of harmonic motion; he instead postulates a proto-
this blind spot is to reconstruct in part Riemann's field of typically complete harmonic motion, a dialectical process
vision, to reanimate, however imperfectly, his understanding leading from initial tonic to final tonic. The emphasis is
of how music works. switched from the type of motion to the product, or content,
What Riemann fails to see in Rameau is the prototypical of motion, from an open-ended temporal process to a closed
nature of the perfect cadence for harmonicmotion. The law- harmonicstructure.This fundamentallyspatial conception of
ful movement of the fundamental bass is founded on the harmonic logic allows Riemann to construct an underlying
imitation of this cadence. Root motion by fifth drives network of possible harmonicrelations by means of which he
Rameau's system, and Rameau understandssuch motion to classifies and labels actual harmonic moves. (A representa-
be a logical deduction from the properties of the fifth as they tion of this type of network is shown in Figure 1.) Analysis
were themselves deduced from the principe sonore. A dia-
tonic chord progression is normatively analyzed by Rameau
as a series of imitated or avoided cadences, culminating on
the tonic sonority. Every chord in the series is considered
27Rameau,Treatiseon Harmony, trans. Gossett, 83. Even the subdom-
dissonant, in potentia if not in actu, until the final consonant inant is in a sense defined by the dominant, in that Rameau designates its
tonic. The final cadence is markedby a chord of the dominant cadentialmove to tonic as "irregular"over and againstthe "perfect"cadence
seventh progressing to a perfect triad. All other chords of dominant to tonic.
8 Music Theory Spectrum

becomes a taxonomic operation of labeling harmonies in tonal system as utilized in music ranging from Bach to Wag-
terms of a coherent system of tonal function, and tonality is ner.28
thus conceived in hierarchical and spatial terms. The pride
of his system is for Riemann the fact that he could map
28Figure1 is taken from Renate Imig, Systemeder Funktionsbezeichnung
virtually any harmonic move onto his underlying network, in den Harmonielehrenseit Hugo Riemann (Dusseldorf: Gesellschaft zur
thus demonstrating the inherent logical coherence of the Forderungder systematischen Musikwissenschaft,1970), 258.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 9

Such an emphasis is incompatible with Rameau's agenda. far too limiting terms (the structureof a simple chord rather
Rameau conceives of harmonic motion temporally, as the than the more comprehensive harmonic structure of a key
result of the dissonance treatment and voice-leading char- center) .29
acteristics of a prototypical progression from dominant sev- The opposition between Riemann's understandingof har-
enth to tonic. Riemann conceives of harmonic motion spa- mony and that of Rameau may be less a function of their
tially, as the filling in of possible spaces in a coherently respective scientific pretensions (the inductive taxonomies of
arrangedunderlyingnetwork. In Rameau's system harmonic natural science vs. the deductive constructions of Cartesian
content is interpreted in terms of a prototypical harmonic science) than a comment on the musics they were most di-
motion; for Riemann, harmonic motion is interpreted in rectly challenged to account for theoretically. Jacques Hand-
terms of prototypical harmonic content. We are now in a schin has suggested that Riemann'sfunctionaltheory is based
position to understand why Riemann picks the concept of on a prominent harmonic tendency of classical and romantic
third-structuringand not some other aspect of Rameau's the- music of the Germanic tradition.30Much of the harmonic
ory to act as his scapegoat. Riemann's critique of Rameau syntax and phraseology of this music is based on repeated
posits third-structuringas fundamental because he himself reformulations and variations of tonic, subdominant, dom-
sees the essence of harmonicprogressionas contingent on the inant, and tonic. Rameau's more temporal conception is
structureof actual harmonic components-and he simply as- based, conversely, on the prevailing harmonic tendencies of
sumes that Rameau understood it in the same way, only in Baroque music-a rhetoric of Fortspinnung, sequence, and
elided cadences.31
This article has concentrated on Riemann's discussion of
UnderstandingRiemann's harmonictheory as a spatial conception allows
us to see his much disputed notion of harmonic dualism in a new light, not Rameau simply for the sake of convenience; the type of se-
as a contradictionto the rest of his functional theory but as its fundamental lective reading that Riemann indulges in vis-a-vis Rameau
condition. The concept of dualism allows Riemann to establish the two- could be demonstrated with any of the other theorists Rie-
dimensionalityof his underlying network of harmonic logic; dualism serves mann discusses (and already has been in the case of
Riemann not just as an ad hoc explanation for the minor mode, but rather
as the foundationof his theory of "apparentconsonance" (Scheinkonsonanz)
and, therefore, tonal logic. Only by assuming opposite principles for major
and minor could Riemann theoretically distinguish between the major pri-
mary chords of any given major key and the minor secondary chords, con- 29Jacques Handschin explains Riemann's antipathy toward third-
ceiving the latter as dissonant variants of the former. In other words, seen structuringas the resistanceof one schematicviewpointto another. See Hand-
from the perspective of major, the minor triad is dissonant and vice versa. schin, Der Toncharakter:Eine Einfiihrung in die Tonpsychologie (Zurich:
The concept of dualism is the conditio sine qua non of his two-dimensional Atlantis Verlag, 1948), 278f.
harmonic universe, and it is no coincidence that Riemann tenaciously de- 30Ibid., 268.
fended this concept throughout his career. 31CarlDahlhaus makes a similar point when he contrasts Stufentheorie
Nor is it any accident that Riemann reads the concept of dualisminto the with function theory. He links the former with the harmonic tendencies of
work of Zarlino. As mentioned above, the organicist presuppositionof de- Baroque music and the latter with the music of Beethoven. Dahlhaus, "Har-
velopmental historyrequiresthat fundamentalaspects of any historicallycon- mony," New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians, ed. Stanley Sadie,
ditioned development arise at the outset of the evolutionaryprocess:Riemann 1980. See also CharlesRosen, The ClassicalStyle(New York: W. W. Norton,
was no doubt determined to find the seeds of dualism in the work of Zarlino, 1972), 48-49, on the difference between Baroque and Classical harmonic
the theorist who forms the starting point of his history of harmonic theory. tendencies.
10 Music TheorySpectrum

Zarlino).32Riemann quite clearly assesses past theorists by historicalprocess is understood as the gradualuncovering of
asking them the same questions his own work answers so natural truth.
elegantly. He is not interested in uncovering the questions Considering Riemann's application of an underlying and
that their work provides answers to because he is convinced axiomatic network of natural laws to the history of music
that they are attempting to answer the same questions, that, theory, a consistencyof method may be discernedthroughout
in fact, the entire history of theory has been devoted to an- the expansiverange of his musicalthought. Both his harmonic
swering these same questions. And the answers have been and rhythmic theories seek to classify musical content in
there from the start, just waiting to be discovered. terms of an underlyingand quasi-abstract,spatiallyconceived
For Riemann, these answers form a network of assump- network. As already discussed, Riemann's function theory
tions about the nature of harmonic logic, assumptionswhich provides labels for harmonies in accordance with three pro-
he characterizesas natural laws and treats as axioms for the totypical functions. And his rhythmicanalyses are supported
constructionof his harmonictheory. The history of theory is by the underlyingprototype of the eight-barperiod. Concrete
then read against these underlyingaxioms, so that the work content, whether harmonic, rhythmic, or historical, is taxo-
of any given theorist or school is analyzed in terms either of nomicallyclassifiedaccordingto some abstractaxiomaticnet-
discovering or obscuring that which Riemann called, in an- work. Riemann's work as a historian of theory thus operates
other context, "das Urgesetzliche."33Thus the internal co- within the same methodological frameworkas his theoretical
herence of a past theorist's work is downplayed in favor of work: not only do the terms of his own theory provide a ready
its relationship to Riemann's axiomatic system; each theo- means for assessing earlier theories, but the procedures and
rist's position can be analyzed as a series of right or wrong suppositions of his theory guide the entire enterprise of con-
moves on a network of underlyingtruths, denying any inkling structing a history of theory.34
of coherence as a system in and of itself, not to mention as Although Riemann's history of harmonic theory may be
a document of the intellectual and cultural tenor of the age characterizedas the outline of an alleged historical process
in which it was conceived. The facts of history are instead that graduallydiscoversthe naturallaws governing the innate
arrangedaccordingto that which is regardedas naturaltruth. capacity of humans to understandand use musical language,
And history is thus involved in the gradual discovery of that his motivation to undertake such an investigation in the first
truth. Despite Riemann's framing of his history of harmonic place and then to cast it as a development history has not yet
theory as a development history, he has in fact constructed entirely been explored. Why could he not just unabashedly
an Entdeckungsgeschichte,or discovery history, wherein the report on earlier manifestationsof his own ideas, in the man-
ner, say, of Noam Chomsky's Cartesian Linguistics, a work
which does not seek to dissemble its basicallysynchronicsam-
32RuthSolie documents the criticalreactionsto Riemann'smisattribution
of dualism to Zarlino in her review of Riemann's Harmony, 184. 34Riemann'staxonomic enterpriseextends to his aesthetic speculationsas
33"Ist doch der eigentliche Zweck der historischenForschung, das allen well, particularlyin the pseudo-scientificcodification of melodic behaviors
Zeiten gemeinsame Urgesetzliche, das alles Empfinden und kiinstlerische which he formulatedin MusikalischeDynamikundAgogik (1884). This aspect
Gestalten beherrscht, erkennbar zu machen" (from the foreword to his of Riemann'swork was broughtto my attentionby Ian Bent within the course
Musikgeschichtein Beispielen [1912], as cited by Dahlhaus in Entstehungder of a richly informative paper entitled "The Aesthetics of Hugo Riemann,"
Tonalitit, 51). read at the 1990AMS/SMT/SEMnationalconference in Oakland, California.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 11

pling of intellectual history?35The closing peroration of Ri- that reason has been said to stand as a basic intellectual
emann's History of Theory provides some clues: premise spanningthe entire nineteenth century.38But equally
Of greatimportancefor me is the proofthatthoughtswhichharbor important is the implication that history can validate one's
some truthwill continueto flare up until they can no longerbe ideas; by demonstratingthat his theory is the result of a long
historical development-that is, by giving his theory a
repressed.Maythis historicalworkthusbe additionallyconsidered
... as an account of the origins of my ideas about music theory, history-Riemann is in fact seeking to create a credible basis
through which . . . much that seems to so many to be new in my for the ideological (and hardly defensible) position that his
booksstandsrevealedas somethingtriedandtrue,and,conjointly, particularsystem is axiomatic for all of music. He treats the
the positionI hold obtainsan unshakablefoundation.36 history of music theory in the same manner as the traditional
This paragraphemphasizes Riemann'sbelief in the validity conception of the history of natural science, that is, as the
of his axioms-his ideas are characterizedas having the stay- gradual development of a theoretical language adequate to
naturalreality. Music, like Nature, must then be assumed to
ing power of great truths.37And he states explicitly that his have an unchangingessence for which there is only one true
history is to be understood as a report on the origins of his
own theories. By writing a history of music theory, Riemann description, and Riemann applies history to the task of sup-
can show how his ideas evolved naturally;he can demonstrate porting this particularideological standpointabout the nature
of music.
that they didn'tjust springup ex nihilo. History is thus treated
And what motivates Riemann's ideology? Is it indeed the
as a method of explanation: one can only understand some-
ethos of natural science? There is certainly some compelling
thing thoroughly by knowing its history, its evolution. This evidence for this view. In the absence of the type of tran-
is an idea fundamental to both Hegel and Darwin, and for
scendence which functioned as a lodestar for romantic aes-
thetics, the laws of nature become an absolute norm in the
latter years of the nineteenth century; this shift stems in part
from the so-called "anthropologicalturn" undertaken by so
35InChomsky'swords: "Questions of currentinterest will . . . determine
the general form of this sketch; that is, I will make no attempt to characterize many thinkers in the Geisteswissenschaftenbetween the ro-
Cartesian linguistics as it saw itself, but rather will concentrate on the de- mantic age and the age of naturalism.39The unlimited and
velopment of ideas that have reemerged, quite independently, in current transcendentspiritinformingmusical works of the earlier age
work" (CartesianLinguistics:A Chapterin the Historyof RationalistThought becomes a limited naturalsystem as it is transformedinto the
[New York, 1966], 2). musical faculty of humankind,conceived as a kind of musical
36"[F]ir hochst wichtig halte ich den Nachweis, dass Gedanken, denen
eine Wahrheit innewohnt, immer wieder aufflammen, bis sie endlich nicht
mehr niederzuhalten sind. Moge man deshalb diese historische Arbeit . . .
zugleich als einen Rechenschaftsberichtiber die Herkunftmeiner Ideen zur
Theorieder Musik ansehen, durchwelchen zwar bis auf weniges Nebensich- 38CompareErnst Cassirer, The Problem of Knowledge (New Haven,
liche das vielen neuscheinende in meinen Bucher sich als ein langst beste- 1950), 171.
hendesAlte herausstellt,zugleich aber der Standpunkt,auf dem ich stehe, ein 390n the generalinfluenceof the Hegelian Left in Germanintellectuallife
felsenfestes Fundament erhalt" (Riemann, Geschichte, 529). of the nineteenth century, see Michael Ermarth, WilhelmDilthey: The Cri-
37CompareWilliam C. Mickelsen, Hugo Riemann's Theory of Harmony tique of HistoricalReason (Chicago, 1978), 52ff. Specificallyrelatingto music
(Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1977), 5. history in this regard is a study by John Deathridge (see footnote 47).
12 MusicTheory Spectrum

competence.40Riemann's allegiance to this new way of think- cated on the Viennese classicalstyle.42Riemann hypostasizes
ing is clear, for he increasingly applied his theoretical de- this style as the natural and essential basis of musical un-
scriptions of music to the operations of human cognition. In derstanding. In so doing, he invests a basically Germanic
fact, his portrayalof the cognitive psychology of the listener Kulturgutwith universal validity. He maintains this ideolog-
sounds strikinglylike his own methodological enterprise as a ical position throughthe variousembassies of naturalscience,
theorist: musical cognition is understood as an active process including developmental history and cognitive psychology.
of classification according to a simplifying network of hier- It is instructive in this regard to compare the views of
archicallyrelated categories which insure logical coherence.41 Riemann to those of a real naturalscientist, namely Hermann
By transferringthe logical operations of music from the mu- von Helmholtz. In his justly famous Lehre von den Tonemp-
sical objects themselves into human cognition, and thus into findungen (1863), Helmholtz emphaticallycircumscribesthe
the favored realm of naturalscience, Riemann was convinced limits of a scientific investigation of music, relinquishingthe
that he was demonstrating natural laws. In his view, music analysis of actual musical practice to the realm of aesthetics.
is not based on the physical nature of sound, as it was for The fundamentalprinciplesof any given musical style or era
Rameau, nor is it conceived as the concretization of some are, for Helmholtz, culturally and historically determined;
transcendentidea. It is rather construed as the product of an they are indeed conditioned by the nature of the materials
innate cognitive network of logical relations, a network con- but are not to be considered as natural products in and of
forming to natural law. themselves. Scales and tonal systems are thus already the
But Riemann'sideology runs deeper than the assumptions result of the artistic invention.43Positing one specific system
of natural science. That is to say, he appropriates natural as the naturalbasis for all of music would be as wrongheaded
science (the favored methodological standpointof the age) in as insisting that the Gothic cathedral be considered the es-
the service of something else; it is not an end in itself. For sential prototype of architecturalbeauty and the Greek tem-
what is preserved by Riemann's so-called natural law? What ple as merely a ratherimperfect adumbration.44It seems safe
lies behind the nomothetic prototypical structures of the for us to consider Helmholtz's self-imposed limit on the ex-
eight-barperiod and the T-S-D-T harmonicformula?These planatory extent of science in things musical as representing
manifestations of Riemann's natural law are clearly predi- something of a benchmark for the role of natural science in

42RuthSolie also relates Riemann's"universalprinciplesof musicalstruc-


ture" with the stylistic norms of the Viennese classical style in her excellent
4'As Allan Keiler has recently pointed out, this type of endeavor was precis of Riemann's historical significance; see Solie, 181. See also H. C.
prevalent in German musical thought of the late nineteenth century, notably Wolff's article on Riemann in Musik in Geschichte und Gegenwart, ed.
including the early work of Heinrich Schenker. See Keiler, 291-92. FriedrichBlume (1963).
41"[D]asMusikhoren [ist] ein Auswvdhle/n aus dem zu Gehor gebrachten 43Hermannvon Helmholtz, Die Lehre von den Tonempfindungenals
Klanigmaterial nach einfachen, naherdarzulegendenGesichtspunkten. ... Es PhysiologischeGrundlagefiir die Theorieder Musik, 4th ed. (Braunschweig,
ist eben ein Vorstellen,ein vereinen, trennen, vergleichen, aufeinanderbe- 1877), 389, 588.
ziehen von Vorstellungen . . ." (Riemann, MusikalischeSyntaxis [Leipzig, 44Ibid.,389. For an illuminatingcomparisonof Riemann and Helmholtz
1877], viii). The taxonomist's agenda could hardly be more succinctly re- on the relation of musical systems and history see Dahlhaus, Entstehungder
vealed. Tonalitit, 51ff.
Methodand Motivationin Historyof HarmonicTheory 13

nineteenth-century musical thought. That Riemann refused classical style represented a foundation for an ongoing Ger-
to acknowledge this limitation is less the result of an ambition man tradition of musical universality. Franz Brendel's 1859
to extend the frontiers of natural science in the arts than it unveiling of the New German School (notably including the
is the telltale sign that he never fundamentallyoperated from foreigners Berlioz and Liszt) provided perhaps the premier
the standpointof naturalscience in the first place, despite the expression of just this idea of the continuing universalityof
range, and even depth, of his attachmentto those disciplines. German music, a universalitycharteredby the Viennese clas-
Riemann's history of theory is emblematic of the con- sical style.45For Brendel, Germany had become the spiritual
flicting concerns of late nineteenth-centuryGerman intellec- fatherlandof talented composers from other European coun-
tuals involved in the human sciences-a generally facile ap- tries who had transcended the limits of their own national-
propriation of the methods and assumptions of the natural ities.46 The pervasive force of this view of Germanic music
sciences is curiously conflated with idealist notions about the also found expression in the world of music publishing.Breit-
importance of history and origins. In the case of Riemann, kopf and Hartel's extensive publication of "collected works"
the taxonomic methodology of natural science and the trap- editions in the latter half of the nineteenth century served to
pings of developmental history are paradoxicallyemployed to canonize those composers who were seen as fundamentalto
reach a conclusion redolent of idealist teleology: Germany's the Germanic tradition.47
Golden Age is fixed as both the essential basis and culmi- Hugo Riemann's contribution to this enterprise was the
nating telos of the rest of musical art. Music comes to know formulationof a theory of music which covertly embodied as
itself through the Viennese classical style. its fundamental assumption the ideological premise that the
And Riemann is not alone in this: a growing perception underlying syntax of the Viennese classical style could serve
of the classical style as the consummate stage of musical his- as the universal basis of music. But lest we characterizeRie-
tory is reflected in much of the theoretical and historicalwrit-
45BrendelunderstoodMozartas the Germaniccomposer who synthesized
ing of the period, attaining its most magisterial rhetoric in several national styles (particularlythe Italian and German styles) within a
Guido Adler's 1924 monograph on the Viennese school and
single style, thus forming "the first all-comprehensive,universal apex of the
its most potent theoretical expression in the canonic pre- entire European evolution" (Geschichte der Musik in Italien, Deutschland,
scriptionsof Heinrich Schenker. This ideological position was und Frankreich,6th ed. [Leipzig, 1878], 329). Beethoven, on the other hand,
clearly one of the galvanizing forces behind the burgeoning achieved a more specificallyGermandepth of spirit that reached back to J. S.
self-awarenessof German Musikwissenschaftin the late nine- Bach and forwardto the musicof the New GermanSchool. See Brendel, "Zur
teenth century. For a sense of mission coalesced around the Anbahnung einer Verstandigung," Neue Zeitschriftfur Musik 50, no. 24
(1859): 272. I am indebted to John Deathridge for making me aware of both
music of Haydn, Mozart, and Beethoven, as Germany's in- the central importance of Brendel's views for musical thought in late
veterate urge for unification encouraged the systematized nineteenth-centuryGermanyand the influenceof the Hegelian Left on Bren-
protection and promotion of this living symbol of the glory del's conception of musical history.
of the German spirit. Even music historians who were to 46Brendel,"Anbahnung," 272.
47JohnDeathridge provides a detailed discussion of the musical conse-
revise their notion of history in accordancewith the Hegelian
quences and ideological implications of German universality in his study
Left, thus refusing to see the Viennese or any other period "
"Germany:The 'Special Path.' in The Late RomanticEra: From the Mid-
as the teleological culminationof musical history, based their Nineteenth Century to World War I, ed. J. Samson (London: Macmillan,
hopes for the future of music on the assumption that the 1991), 50-73.
14 Music Theory Spectrum

mann as ideologically inflexible we must remember that, near ABSTRACT


the end of his life, he relaxed his conception of one set of Book III of Hugo Riemann's 1898 History of Music Theory is dis-
natural laws for all of music, broadening his theoretical base cussed from the point of view of historical method and underlying
in order to validate a wider range of musical practice.48 Oth- motivation. Although he casts his history of harmonic theory as a
ers, as we know, could not make this turn, with the result that developmental history, Riemann is shown to have constructed a
the ideology which preserves German hegemony within the discovery history, in which a set of unchangingnaturaltruths about
harmoniclogic are graduallydiscovered by generations of theorists
very definition of universal musical art is still very much with who are understood to be asking the same questions. Riemann's
us today.
methodology as a historianof theory is seen as embodying the same
taxonomic impulse that informs his theoretical work. There follows
an investigationof the claimsof naturalscience, idealist thought, and
nationalistpride on Riemann's motivation for writing his history of
48See footnote 7. harmonic theory.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen