Sie sind auf Seite 1von 5

All EHP content is accessible to individuals with disabilities.

A fully accessible (Section 508compliant)


HTML version of this article is available at http://dx.doi.org/10.1289/ehp.1408107. Commentary

Science, Policy, and the Transparency of Values


Kevin C. Elliott1 and David B. Resnik 2
1Lyman Briggs College, Department of Fisheries and Wildlife, and Department of Philosophy, Michigan State University, East Lansing,
Michigan, USA; 2National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences, National Institutes of Health, Department of Health and Human
Services, Research Triangle Park, North Carolina, USA

A Dispute about Science


Background: Opposing groups of scientists have recently engaged in a heated dispute over a Communication
preliminary European Commission (EC) report on its regulatory policy for endocrine-disrupting
A look beyond the scientific details of the
chemicals. In addition to the scientific issues at stake, a central question has been how scientists can
maintain their objectivity when informing policy makers. case shows that these and other editori-
als (Bergman etal. 2013; Gore etal. 2013;
Objectives: Drawing from current ethical, conceptual, and empirical studies of objectivity and con-
Grandjean and Ozonoff 2013; Horel and
flicts of interest in scientific research, we propose guiding principles for communicating scientific
findings in a manner that promotes objectivity, public trust, and policy relevance. Bienkowski 2013; Lehman-McKeeman and
Kaminski 2013) have raised significant issues
Discussion: Both conceptual and empirical studies of scientific reasoning have shown that it is
about how scientists can appropriately inform
unrealistic to prevent policy-relevant scientific research from being influenced by value judgments.
Conceptually, the current dispute over the EC report illustrates how scientists are forced to make public policy. The response in Environmental
value judgments about appropriate standards of evidence when informing public policy. Empirical Health states that [t]he most worrying aspect
studies provide further evidence that scientists are unavoidably influenced by a variety of potentially of the editorial by Dietrich etal. is the blur-
subconscious financial, social, political, and personal interests and values. ring of the border between what constitutes
Conclusions: When scientific evidence is inconclusive and major regulatory decisions are at stake, science and what belongs to the realm of
it is unrealistic to think that values can be excluded from scientific reasoning. Thus, efforts to sup- political, societal and democratic choices
press or hide interests or values may actually damage scientific objectivity and public trust, whereas (Bergman etal. 2013). This concern is clearly
a willingness to bring implicit interests and values into the open may be the best path to promoting expressed in the title of the editorial: Science
good science and policy. and policy on endocrine disrupters must
Citation: Elliott KC, Resnik DB. 2014. Science, policy, and the transparency of values. Environ not be mixed. Related to this worry about
Health Perspect 122:647650; http://dx.doi.org/10.1289/ehp.1408107 mixing policy with science, an editorial by
Grandjean and Ozonoff (2013) suggested
that a crucial flaw in the editorial by Dietrich
Introduction 2013). The editorial and an accompanying etal. (2013) was its failure to include a
A recent news story in Nature (Cressey 2013) letter (Dietrich etal. 2013) focused on two conflict-of-interest disclosure.According to
reported on a heated dispute between opposing issues: First, the authors of the editorial criti- Grandjean and Ozonoff, trust is necessary
groups of scientists in response to an alleged cized the EC for proposing a system in which among scientists, editors, publishers, and
but uncited draft report by the European evidence of endocrine disruption obtained in members of the public, and that trust is bro-
Commission (EC) on its proposed regulatory animals and various other experimental sys- ken when authors do not acknowledge their
policy concerning endocrine disrupting chemi- tems would be presumed to be relevant to competing interests.
cals (EDCs) (EC 2013; Horel and Bienkowski humans in the absence of evidence to the con- These editorials (Bergman etal. 2013;
2013). One of the participants in the dispute, trary. Second, the authors expressed the con- Grandjean and Ozonoff 2013) highlight the
Andrea Gore, a professor at the University cern that the EC would presume that EDCs worry that scientists are in danger of losing
of Texas at Austin and editor of the journal do not have a threshold dose below which their objectivity when they wade into the
Endocrinology, claimed that this was possibly they cease to induce adverse effects. policy domain. Because objectivity is one of
the most remarkable experience in my career In response to this initial editorial, several sciences most important goals, this concern
and that it was definitely more confronta- subsequent commentaries were published has considerable merit. Even when scientists
tional than most scientists are used to (Cressey (Bergman etal. 2013; Gore etal. 2013; do not actually compromise their objectiv-
2013). Although the details of the dispute Grandjean and Ozonoff 2013). An edito- ity, people may perceive that they have done
revolve around questions about how to identify rial signed by 41 scientists and published in so, which can undermine the publics trust in
and regulate EDCs, it also highlights broader Environmental Health (Bergman etal. 2013) science. Although engaging in policy-relevant
issues about how scientists should communi- questioned whether the EC actually envisioned research can threaten sciences objectivity, a
cate with policy makers in a manner that is a regulatory policy with the characteristics great deal would be lost if scientists refused
both policyrelevant and appropriately objec- described by Dietrich and his co-authors.
tive. Some of the participants in the dispute The editorial by Bergman etal. (2013) also Address correspondence to K.C. Elliott, Michigan
called for making a sharper distinction between pointed out that the International Programme State University, 35 East Holmes Hall, 919 E. Shaw
science and policy (Bergman etal. 2013), but on Chemical Safety (IPCS) Framework docu- Lane, East Lansing, MI 48825 USA. Telephone:
we argue here that society is better served when ment for risk assessment (IPCS 2002) adopts (937) 925-5997. E-mail: kce@msu.edu
This article is the work product of an employee
scientists strive to be as transparent as possible a default assumption that evidence of toxicity of the National Institute of Environmental Health
about the ways in which interests or values may in animals is relevant to humans. Moreover, Sciences (NIEHS), National Institutes of Health
influence their reasoning. the editorial argued that evidence for the (NIH). However, the statements, opinions, or con-
The conflict erupted when a group of existence of thresholds for EDCs, especially clusions contained therein do not necessarily rep-
18journal editors published an editorial in at the population level, remains inconclusive. resent the statements, opinions, or conclusions of
Food and Chemical Toxicology accusing the Another editorial, published in the journal NIEHS, NIH, or the United States government.
The authors declare they have no actual or potential
EC of preparing a regulatory system for EDCs Endocrinology (Gore etal. 2013), emphasized competing financial interests.
that is based on virtually complete ignorance that the assumption of no threshold for the Received: 10January 2014; Accepted: 24March
of all well-established and taught principles of adverse effects of EDCs is reasonable, given 2014; Advance Publication: 25March 2014; Final
pharmacology and toxicology (Dietrich etal. the evidence. Publication: 1July 2014.

Environmental Health Perspectives volume 122 | number 7 | July 2014 647


Elliott and Resnick

to enter these waters because public policies that evidence of toxicity in animals is relevant be based on this form of evidence, because it
should typically be informed by the best avail- to humans. The authors argue that the alterna- may be appropriate to use different standards
able scientific evidence (Pielke 2007; Resnik tive assumption (i.e., that effects in animals do of evidence to protect the public from risks. A
2009). In a commentary that cites Dietrich not provide evidence for effects in humans) continuum of different kinds and amounts of
etal. (2013) approvingly, Lehman-McKeeman would be unworkable (Bergman etal. 2013). evidence could be demanded for policy deci-
and Kaminski (2013) argued that the Society But this conclusion incorporates value judg- sions (Ashford 1988). Very high standards of
of Toxicology (SOT) must avoid playing it ments concerning the standards of evidence evidence are typically expected in order to infer
safe. In other words, they call for the mem- that are appropriate for regulating chemicals. causal relationships or to approve the market-
bers of the SOT to inform policy makers about Insisting that chemicals should be regulated ing of new drugs. In other social contexts, such
issues on which they have expertise. However, only in response to evidence from human as tort law and chemical regulation, weaker
if toxicologists and other scientists are to help studies would help to prevent false positive standards of evidence are sometimes accept-
inform policy, they face the question of how to conclusions about chemical toxicity, but it able to protect the public (Cranor 2008). To
do this without losing their objectivity or the would also prevent society from taking effec- demand the very highest standards of evidence
publics trust. tive action to minimize the risks of chemicals for chemical regulationincluding, for exam-
before they produce measurable adverse effects ple, human evidence, accompanying animal
Discussion in humans. Moreover, insisting on human data, mechanistic evidence, and clear exposure
In the past, scientists and philosophers have studies would result in failure to identify some datawould take very long periods of time
argued that the best way to maintain sciences human health risks because the diseases are and leave the publics health at risk. Thus, the
objectivity and the publics trust is to draw a rare, or the induction and latency periods are demand that regulators rely on the same stan-
sharp line between science and human val- long, or the effects are subtle (Cranor 2011). dards of evidence for toxicity as the scientific
ues or policy (Longino 1990). However, it is Similarly, Gore etal. (2013) argued that community uses in other contexts is itself a
not possible to maintain this distinction, both [t]he assumption of no threshold has been value-laden proposal.
because values are crucial for assessing what widely used, for many years, in the regulation The value-laden assumptions about stan-
counts as sufficient evidence and because ethi- of genotoxic carcinogens, often based upon dards of evidence in this dispute over endo-
cal, political, economic, cultural, and religious invitro data. We believe extending this prec- crine disruption are similar to broader social
factors unavoidably affect scientific judgment edent to EDCs is supported by the science. disputes over the precautionary principle
(Douglas 2009; Elliott 2011; Longino 1990; But the claim that the no-threshold hypothe (Kriebel etal. 2001; Martuzzi 2007; Miller and
Resnik 2007, 2009). Insisting that science is sis is supported by the science depends on Conko 2001; Sunstein 2005). Indeed, the title
value-free, when the arguments and evidence implicit assumptions about how much scien- of the editorial by Dietrich etal. (2013) begins
show that this is an unrealistic goal, perpetu- tific evidence is needed to justify formulat- with the claim, Scientifically unfounded pre-
ates a misunderstanding that interferes with the ing policy on this basis. And the question of caution drives European Commissions recom-
publics understanding of the scientific process how much evidence is needed should depend mendations on EDC regulation. Some critics
and may, paradoxically, undermine the pub- in part on value judgments about the relative of the precautionary principle, such as Dietrich
lics trust in science. We suggest that society is benefits and harms to society of assuming (or and his coauthors, argue that precaution runs
likely to be better served when scientists strive not assuming) a threshold when performing counter to scientific principles (Miller and
to be as transparent as possible about the ways risk assessments of EDCs. In this case, past Conko 2001). But decisions about how much
that interests and values may influence their toxicological experience may support the evidence to demand before taking regulatory
judgment and reasoning, while still striving for threshold hypothesis, whereas other lines of actions necessarily incorporate both scientific
objectivity. Transparency can promote public evidence (such as the proposed molecular judgments and value judgments. Because the
trust by helping laypeople understand how mechanisms by which EDCs could disrupt scientific conventions for inferring evidence
both empirical evidence and value assumptions development and generate irreversible effects of harm in some fields might require placing
enter into scientific decision making and policy on endocrine-sensitive organs) support the the public at risk for extended periods of time
formation. As the National Research Council no-threshold hypothesis. Thus, the dispute before the evidence could be accumulated, pre-
(NRC) report Understanding Risk (NRC 1996) between Gore etal. (2013) and Dietrich etal. cautionary decisions to engage in particular
emphasized, it is usually unrealistic to keep the (2013) regarding the adoption of thresholds forms of regulation may sometimes be appro-
process of risk characterization purely value- for EDCs could be clarified if the participants priate in response to more limited evidence
free. Instead, the report called for incorporat- were more forthcoming about their assump- (Cranor 2011; Martuzzi 2007).
ing broad-based deliberation about the values tions regarding the level and kind of evidence Financial, personal, and cultural influ-
that inform risk assessments in order to pro- needed to justify adopting or rejecting the ences. A second reason to avoid trying to
vide a context for the scientific analyses that are threshold hypothesis. maintain a sharp distinction between science
part of the assessment process. In their editorial, Lehman-McKeeman and values in the policy context is that per-
Standards of evidence. The first reason and Kaminski (2013) call for the members of sonal, ethical, political, and cultural values
it is problematic to draw a sharp separation the SOT to be strong advocates for applying unavoidably influence scientific reasoning.
between science and values is that values are the best science to policy issues and to craft This point is illustrated by recent concep-
necessary to decide what standards of evidence regulatory policies that are based on sound tual and empirical literature on the ways
to demand when informing policy decisions science. Even this seemingly innocuous advice that financial relationships can affect scien
(Ashford 1988; Cranor 1993; Douglas 2009; to promote decisions based on good science tific judgment and reasoning (Dana and
Elliott 2011). Several comments from the hides significant value judgments about the Loewenstein 2003; Elliott 2008; Resnik and
recent dispute about the proposed EC policy appropriate standards of evidence in policy Elliott 2013). An investigative report found
illustrate the difficulties of trying to ignore this contexts (Ashford 1988; Cranor 1993). If the that 17 of the 18 authors of the initial edito-
necessary role for values. First, as noted earlier, best science and sound science are inter- rial by Dietrich etal. (2013) had ties to regu-
the editorial that calls for science and policy on preted to mean science that meets the high- lated industries (Horel and Bienkowski 2013).
EDCs to remain unmixed (Bergman etal. est standards of scientific evidence, then it is In response to this investigation, Dietrich
2013) insists that it is reasonable to assume not clear that regulatory policy must always replied, [w]e do not believe the discussion

648 volume 122 | number 7 | July 2014 Environmental Health Perspectives


Science, policy, and the transparency of values

on the conflicts of interests will serve any- promoting transparency are also available. values may actually damage scientific objec-
body because it takes away the focus from the For example, efforts to incorporate scientists tivity and public trust, whereas a willingness
real issue (quoted by Horel and Bienkowski from a range of different stakeholder groups to bring implicit interests or values into the
2013). Bas Blaauboer, another co-author of on government advisory bodies can help to open may be the best path to promoting good
the editorial by Dietrich etal. (2013), insisted uncover and elucidate implicit value judg- science and policy.
that it was very stupid to think that his ments in science advice and promote demo-
industry involvement influenced his opinion cratic decision making (Resnik 2009). These References
(quoted by Horel and Bienkowski 2013). efforts to uncover implicit value judgments
But psychological studies have suggested that are important, given that values can influence Ashford N. 1988. Science and values in the regulatory process.
Stat Sci 3:377383.
financial interests can exert subconscious influ- subtle decisions about research questions, Babcock L, Loewenstein G, Issacharoff S. 1997. Creating
ences on human judgment even when indi- methodologies, terminology, and models convergence: debiasing biased litigants. Law Soc Inquiry
viduals are instructed about those potential (Ashford 1988; Douglas 2009; Elliott 2011; 22:401413.
Bergman , Andersson AM, Becher G, van den Berg M,
influences and motivated to remain objective Kriebel etal. 2001). Disclosures of competing BlumbergB, Bjerregaard P, etal. 2013. Science and policy
(Babcock etal. 1997; Dana and Loewenstein financial interests and nonfinancial interests on endocrine disrupters must not be mixed: a reply to a
2003; Orlowski and Wateska 1992). (such as professional or political allegiances) common sense intervention by toxicology journal editors
[Editorial]. Environ Health 12:69; doi:10.1186/1476-069X-12-69.
Importantly, people typically underestimate also provide opportunities for more transpar- Cranor CF. 1993. Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of
the strength of these influences (Dana and ent discussions of the impact of potentially Science and the Law. New York:Oxford University Press.
Loewenstein 2003; Katz etal. 2003). Some implicit and subconscious values (Resnik and Cranor CF. 2008. Toxic Torts: Science, Law, and the Possibility
of Justice. New York:Cambridge University Press.
commentators also worry that interest groups Elliott 2013). Cranor CF. 2011. Legally Poisoned: How the Law Puts Us at Risk
with deep pockets can use their financial When scientists are aware of important from Toxicants. Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press.
and political power to skew public debate by background assumptions or values that inform Cressey D. 2013. Journal editors trade blows over toxicology.
Nature; doi:10.1038/nature.2013.13787 [Online 20September
magnifying the influence of sympathetic sci- their work, it is valuable for them to make 2013].
entists through strategic funding efforts and these considerations explicit. They can also Dana J, Loewenstein G. 2003. A social science perspective on
public relations campaigns (McGarity and make their data publicly available and strive gifts to physicians from industry. JAMA 290:252255.
Wagner 2008; Michaels 2008). to acknowledge the range of plausible inter- Dietrich DR, von Aulock S, Marquardt H, Blaauboer B,
DekantW, KehrerJ, etal. 2013. Scientifically unfounded
Financial relationships are not the only pretations of available scientific information, precaution drives European Commissions recommenda-
factors that can influence scientists. Studies the limitations of their own conclusions, the tions on EDC regulation, while defying common sense,
of risk perception have found that even prevalence of various interpretations across the well-established science and risk assessment principles
[Editorial]. Food Chem Toxicol 62:A1A4.
among professional toxicologists, men tend scientific community, and the policy options Douglas HE. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal.
to have systematically lower perceptions supported by these different interpretations. Pittsburgh, PA:University of Pittsburgh Press.
of chemical risks than women, and those This approach has much in common with EC (European Commission). 2013. Commission Recommendation
of XXXX: Defining Criteria for Endocrine Disruptors.
employed by industry have lower perceptions Ashfords seminal call for scientists to be trans- Available: http://www.environmentalhealthnews.
of risk than those in academic settings (Slovic parent about their values (Ashford 1988) and org/ehs/news/2013/pdf-links/2013.06.11%20EDC_
etal. 1997). Some of these employment with Pielkes vision of scientists as honest Recommendation%20Commission%20Draft.pdf [accessed
17March 2014].
effects may be caused or exacerbated by the brokers who open up discussions about the Elliott KC. 2008. Scientific judgment and the limits of conflict-of-
phenomenon of group polarization, whereby range of options available to decision makers interest policies. Account Res 15:129.
people exposed primarily to those who (Pielke 2007). It may even be valuable for Elliott KC. 2011. Is a Little Pollution Good for You? Incorporating
Societal Values in Environmental Research. New
share similar views ultimately adopt more scientists to reflect on how their work fits into York:Oxford University Press.
extreme positions (e.g., Sunstein 2005). Even broader social frames or narratives so that they Gore AC, Balthazart J, Bikle D, Carpenter DO, Crews D,
cultural valuesc oncerns about equality, can anticipate how their claims are likely to be Czernichow P, etal. 2013. Policy decisions on endorine
authority, individualism, and community misinterpreted or used to promote particular disruptors should be based on science across disciplines:
a response to Dietrich etal. [Editorial]. Endocrinology
can influence individuals risk perceptions political or economic agendas (McKaughan 154:39573960.
(Kahan 2010). This evidence from the social and Elliott 2013). Grandjean P, Ozonoff D. 2013. Transparency and translation of
sciences suggests that although scientists can Although scientists are rightly taught to science in a modern world [Editorial]. Environ Health 12:70;
doi:10.1186/1476-069X-12-70.
strive for objectivity, it is unrealistic to think strive for objectivity, efforts to maintain a Horel S, Bienkowski B. 2013. Special report: scientists critical
that they can provide policy advice without sharp distinction between science and policy of EU chemical policy have industry ties. Environ Health
being influenced by a variety of subconscious are likely to be counterproductive in such News. Available: http://www.environmentalhealthnews.
org/ehs/news/2013/eu-conflict [accessed 17March 2014].
factors, such as interests and values. cases as the recent dispute over EDCs. When IPCS (International Programme on Chemical Safety). 2002.
scientific evidence is disputed and major regu- Global Assessment of the State-of-the-Science of
Conclusions latory decisions are at stake, it is unrealistic to Endocrine Disruptors. Geneva:World Health Organization,
IPCS. Available: http://www.who.int/ipcs/publications/new_
Given both that values play a crucial role in think that scientists will not be influenced by issues/endocrine_disruptors/en/ [accessed 22May 2014].
choosing standards of evidence in the policy their financial, social, political, and personal Kahan D. 2010. Fixing the communications failure. Nature
context and that values have subconscious interests or values when they offer advice to 463:296297.
Katz D, Caplan A, Merz J. 2003. All gifts large and small: toward
influences on scientific judgment that are policy makers. Moreover, judgments about an understanding of the ethics of pharmaceutical industry
impossible to eliminate completely, we sug- whether EDCs exhibit thresholds or whether gift-giving. Am J Bioeth 3:3946.
gest that the best way to do policy-relevant an alleged EDC will have adverse effects in Kriebel D, Tickner J, Epstein P, Lemons J, Levins R, LoechlerEL,
research is for scientists to be as transparent humans rest not only on scientific evidence etal. 2001. The precautionary principle in environmental
science. Environ Health Perspect 109:871876.
as possible about the ways in which inter- but also on value-laden judgments about the Lehman-McKeeman L, Kaminski N. 2013. The hazards of play-
ests and values may influence their work appropriate standards of evidence. Even calls ing it safe: perspectives on how the Society of Toxicology
(Ashford 1988). The analyticdeliberative for decisions based on sound science incor- should contribute to discussions on timely issues of human
and environmental safety [Editorial]. Toxicol Sci 136:13.
approach to risk characterization described porate implicit value judgments about the Longino HE. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and
in Understanding Risk (NRC 1996) provides appropriate standards of evidence for drawing Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ:Princeton
one model for promoting this sort of trans- policy-relevant conclusions. In cases such as University Press.
Martuzzi M. 2007. The precautionary principle: in action for
parency, but a number of other strategies for these, efforts to suppress or hide interests or public health. Occup Environ Med 64:569570.

Environmental Health Perspectives volume 122 | number 7 | July 2014 649


Elliott and Resnick

McGarity TO, Wagner W. 2008. Bending Science: How Special NRC (National Research Council). 1996. Understanding Risk: Resnik DB. 2009. Playing Politics with Science: Balancing
Interests Corrupt Public Health Research. Cambridge, Informing Decisions in a Democratic Society. Washington, Scientific Independence and Government Oversight. New
MA:Harvard University Press. DC:National Academies Press. York:Oxford University Press.
McKaughan DJ, Elliott KC. 2013. Backtracking and the ethics of Orlowski J, Wateska L. 1992. The effects of pharmaceutical Resnik DB, Elliott KC. 2013. Taking financial relationships into
framing: lessons from voles and vasopressin. Account Res firm inticements on physician prescribing patterns. Chest account when assessing research. Account Res 20:184205.
20:206226. 102:270273. Slovic P, Malmfors T, Mertiz C, Neil N, Purchase I. 1997.
Michaels D. 2008. Doubt Is Their Product: How Industrys Pielke RA. 2007. The Honest Broker: Making Sense of Evaluating chemical risks: results of a survey of the British
Assault on Science Threatens Your Health. New Science in Policy and Politics. Cambridge, UK:Cambridge Toxicology Society. Hum Exp Toxicol 16:289304.
York:Oxford University Press. University Press. Sunstein C. 2005. Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary
Miller HI, Conko G. 2001. Precaution without principle. Nat Resnik DB. 2007. The Price of Truth: How Money Affects the Principle. New York:Cambridge University Press.
Biotechnol 19:302303. Norms of Science. New York:Oxford University Press.

650 volume 122 | number 7 | July 2014 Environmental Health Perspectives


Copyright of Environmental Health Perspectives is the property of Superintendent of
Documents and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a
listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print,
download, or email articles for individual use.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen