Sie sind auf Seite 1von 58

1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.

4: Conclusions

Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

George Pennacchi

University of Illinois

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 1/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Introduction

Expected utility is the standard framework for modeling investor


choices. The following topics will be covered:

1 Analyze conditions on individual preferences that lead to an


expected utility function.
2 Consider the link between utility, risk aversion, and risk premia
for particular assets.
3 Examine how risk aversion aects an individuals portfolio
choice between a risky and riskfree asset.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 2/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Preferences when Returns are Uncertain

Economists typically analyze the price of a good using supply


and demand. We can do the same for assets.

The main distinction between assets is their future payos:


Risky assets have uncertain payos, so a theory of asset
demands must specify investor preferences over dierent,
uncertain payos.

Consider relevant criteria for ranking preferences. One


possible measure is the assets average payo.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 3/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Criterion: Expected Payo

Suppose an asset oers a single random payo at a particular


future date, and this payo has a discrete distribution with n
possible outcomes P (x1 ; :::; xn ) and corresponding probabilities
(p1 ; :::; pn ), where ni=1 pi = 1 and pi 0.

Then the expected value of the payo


P (or, more simply, the
expected payo) is x E [e x ] = ni=1 pi xi .

Is an assets expected value a suitable criterion for


determining an individuals demand for the asset?

Consider how much Paul would pay Peter to play the


following coin ipping game.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 4/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

St. Petersburg Paradox, Nicholas Bernoulli, 1713

Peter continues to toss a coin until it lands heads. He


agrees to give Paul one ducat if he gets heads on the very rst
throw, two ducats if he gets it on the second, four if on the
third, eight if on the fourth, and so on.

If the number of coin ips taken to rst obtain heads is i, then


i
pi = 21 and xi = 2i 1 : Thus, Pauls expected payo equals
P1 1 1 1 1
x = i =1 pi xi = 2 1 + 4 2 + 8 4 + 16 8 + ::: (1)
1
= 2 (1 + 12 2 + 14 4 + 18 8 + :::
1
= 2 (1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + ::: = 1

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 5/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

St. Petersburg Paradox

What is the paradox?

Daniel Bernoulli (1738) explained it using expected utility.

His insight was that an individuals utility from receiving a


payo diered from the size of the payo.
P
Instead of valuing an asset as x = ni=1 pi xi , its value, V ,
would be Xn
V E [U (e x )] = pi Ui
i =1
where Ui is the utility associated with payo xi .

He hypothesized that Ui is diminishingly increasing in wealth.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 6/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Criterion: Expected Utility

Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) derived conditions on


an individuals preferences that, if satised, would make them
consistent with an expected utility function.
Dene a lottery as an asset that has a risky payo and
consider an individuals optimal choice of a lottery from a
given set of dierent lotteries. The possible payos of all
lotteries are contained in the set fx1 ; :::; xn g.
A lottery is characterized by an ordered set of probabilities
P
n
P = fp1 ; :::; pn g, where of course, pi = 1 and pi 0. Let a
i =1
dierent lottery be P = fp1 ; :::; pn g. Let , , and
denote preference and indierence between lotteries.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 7/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Preferences Over Dierent Random Payos

Specically, if an individual prefers lottery P to lottery P,


this can be denoted as P P or P P .

When the individual is indierent between the two lotteries,


this is written as P P.

If an individual prefers lottery P to lottery P or she is


indierent between lotteries P and P, this is written as
P P or P P .

N.B.: all lotteries have the same payo set fx1 ; :::; xn g, so we
focus on the (dierent) probability sets P and P .

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 8/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Expected Utility Axioms 1-3

Theorem: There exists an expected utility function


V (p1 ; :::; pn ) if the following axioms hold:
Axioms:
1) Completeness
For any two lotteries P and P, either P P, or P P, or
P P.
2) Transitivity
If P P and P P, then P P.
3) Continuity
If P P P, there exists some 2 [0; 1] such that
P P + (1 )P, where P + (1 )P denotes a
compound lottery; namely, with probability one receives the
lottery P and with probability (1 ) one receives the lottery P.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 9/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Expected Utility Axioms 4-5


4) Independence
For any two lotteries P and P , P P if and only if for all 2
(0,1] and all P :

P + (1 )P P + (1 )P

Moreover, for any two lotteries P and P y , P P y if and only if for


all 2(0,1] and all P :

P + (1 )P P y + (1 )P

5) Dominance
Let P 1 be the compound lottery 1 P z + (1 y
1 )P and P
2 be the
compound lottery 2 P z + (1 y
2 )P . If P
z P y , then P 1 P 2 if
and only if 1 > 2 .
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 10/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Discussion: Machina (1987)

The rst three axioms are analogous to those used to establish


a real-valued utility function in consumer choice theory.

Axiom 4 (Independence) is novel, but its linearity property is


critical for preferences to be consistent with expected utility.

To understand its meaning, suppose an individual chooses P


P. By Axiom 4, the choice between P + (1 )P and
P + (1 )P is equivalent to tossing a coin that with
probability (1 ) lands tails, in which both lotteries pay
P , and with probability lands heads, in which case the
individual should prefer P to P.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 11/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Allais Paradox

But, there is some experimental evidence counter to this


axiom.

Consider lotteries over fx1 ; x2 ; x3 g = f$0; $1m; $5mg and two


lottery choices:
C1: P 1 = f0; 1; 0g vs P 2 = f:01; :89; :1g
C2: P 3 = f:9; 0; :1g vs P 4 = f:89; :11; 0g

Which do you choose in C1? In C2?

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 12/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Allais Paradox

Experimental evidence suggests most people prefer P 1 P2


and P 3 P4.

But this violates Axiom 4. Why?

Dene P 5 = f1=11; 0; 10=11g and let = 0:11. Note that P 2


is equivalent to the compound lottery:

P2 P 5 + (1 ) P1
0:11f1=11; 0; 10=11g + 0:89f0; 1; 0g
f:01; :89; :1g

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 13/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Allais Paradox
Note also that P 1 is trivially the compound lottery
P 1 + (1 ) P 1 . Hence, if P 1 P 2 , the independence
axiom implies P 1 P 5 .
Now also dene P 6 = f1; 0; 0g, and note that P 3 equals the
following compound lottery:
P3 P 5 + (1 ) P6
0:11f1=11; 0; 10=11g + 0:89f1; 0; 0g
f:9; 0; :1g
while P4 is equivalent to the compound lottery
P4 P 1 + (1 ) P6
0:11f0; 1; 0g + 0:89f1; 0; 0g
f:89; 0:11; 0g
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 14/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Allais Paradox

But if P 3 P 4 , the independence axiom implies P 5 P 1 ,


which contradicts the choice of P 1 P 2 that implies
P1 P5.

Despite the sometimes contradictory experimental evidence,


expected utility is still the dominant paradigm.

However, we will consider dierent models of utility at a later


date, including those that reect psychological biases.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 15/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Deriving Expected Utility: Axiom 1

We now prove the theorem by showing that if an individuals


preferences over lotteries satisfy the preceding axioms, these
preferences can be ranked by the individuals expected utility
of the lotteries.

Dene an elementary or primitive lottery, ei , which


returns outcome xi with probability 1 and all other outcomes
with probability zero, that is, ei = fp1 ; :::pi 1 ;pi ;pi +1 :::;pn g =
f0; :::0; 1; 0; :::0g where pi = 1 and pj = 0 8j 6= i.

Without loss of generality, assume that the outcomes are


ordered such that en en 1 ::: e1 . This follows from the
completeness axiom for this case of n elementary lotteries

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 16/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Deriving Expected Utility: Axiom 3, Axiom 4

From the continuity axiom, for each ei , there exists a


Ui 2 [0; 1] such that

ei Ui en + (1 Ui )e1 (2)

and for i = 1, this implies U1 = 0 and for i = n, this implies


Un = 1.
Now a given arbitrary lottery, P = fp1 ; :::; pn g, can be viewed
as a compound lottery over the n elementary lotteries, where
elementary lottery ei is obtained with probability pi .

P p1 e1 + ::: + pn en

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 17/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Deriving Expected Utility: Axiom 4

By the independence axiom, and equation (2), the individual


is indierent between lottery, P, and the following lottery:

p1 e1 + ::: + pn en p1 e1 + ::: + pi 1 ei 1 + pi [Ui en + (1 Ui )e1 ]


+pi +1 ei +1 + ::: + pn en (3)

where the indierence relation in equation (2) substitutes for


ei on the right-hand side of (3).
By repeating this substitution for all i, i = 1; :::; n, the
individual will be indierent between P and
n
! n
!
X X
p1 e1 + ::: + pn en pi Ui en + 1 pi Ui e1 (4)
i =1 i =1

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 18/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Deriving Expected Utility: Axiom 5


P
n
Now dene pi Ui . Thus, P en + (1 )e1
i =1
Similarly, we can show that any other arbitrary lottery
Pn
P = fp1 ; :::; pn g en + (1 )e1 , where pi Ui .
i =1
We know from the dominance axiom that P P i > ,
P
n P
n
implying pi Ui > pi Ui .
i =1 i =1
So we can dene the function
n
X
V (p1 ; :::; pn ) = pi Ui (5)
i =1

which implies that P P i V (p1 ; :::; pn ) > V (p1 ; :::; pn ).


George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 19/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Deriving Expected Utility: The End

The function in (5) is known as von Neumann-Morgenstern


expected utility. It is linear in the probabilities and is unique
up to a linear monotonic transformation.
The intuition for why expected utility is unique up to a linear
transformation comes from equation (2). Here we express
elementary lottery i in terms of the least and most preferred
elementary lotteries. However, other bases for ranking a given
lottery are possible.
For Ui = U(xi ), an individuals choice over lotteries is the
same under the transformation aU(xi ) + b, but not a
nonlinear transformation that changes the shape of U(xi ).

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 20/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

St. Petersburg Paradox Revisited


p
Suppose Ui = U(xi ) = xi . Then the expected utility of the
St. Petersburg payo is
n
X 1
X 1
X 1
X
1p 1
(i +1) i
V = pi Ui = 2i 1 = 2 2 = 2 2
2i
i =1 i =1 i =1 i =2
2 3
= 2 + 2 + :::2 2

X 1
1 i 1 1 1
= p 1 p = 1 p
i =0
2 2 1 p12 2
1
= p = 1:707
2 2
A certain payment of 1:7072 = 2:914 ducats has the same
expected utility as playing the St. Petersburg game.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 21/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Super St. Petersburg


The St. Petersburg game has innite expected payo because
the probability of winning declines at rate 2i , while the
winning payo increases at rate 2i .
In a super St. Petersburg paradox, we can make the
winning payo increase at a rate xi = U 1 (2i 1 ) to cause
expected utility to increase at 2i . For square-root utility,
xi = (2i 2)2 = 22i 2 ; that is, x1 = 1, x2 = 4, x3 = 16, and so
on. The expected utility of super St. Petersburg is
Xn X1 1
1 p 2i 2 X 1 i 1
V = pi Ui = 2 = 2 =1 (6)
2i 2i
i =1 i =1 i =1
Should we be concerned that if prizes grow quickly enough,
we can get innite expected utility (and valuations) for any
chosen form of expected utility function?
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 22/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Von Neumann-Morgenstern Utility

The von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility can be


generalized to a continuum of outcomes and lotteries with
continuous probability distributions. Analogous to equation
(5) is
Z Z
V (F ) = E [U (e
x )] = U (x) dF (x) = U (x) f (x) dx (7)

where F (x) is the lotterys cumulative distribution function


over the payos, x. V can be written in terms of the
probability density, f (x), when F (x) is absolutely continuous.
This is analogous to our previous lottery represented by the
discrete probabilities P = fp1 ; :::; pn g.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 23/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion

Diminishing marginal utility results in risk aversion: being


unwilling to accept a fair lottery. Why?
Let there be a lottery that has a random payo, e ", where
"1 with probability p
e
"= (8)
"2 with probability 1 p
The requirement that it be a fair lottery restricts its
expected value to equal zero:

E [e
"] = p"1 + (1 p)"2 = 0 (9)

which implies "1 ="2 = (1 p) =p, or solving for p,


p = "2 = ("1 "2 ). Since 0 < p < 1, "1 and "2 are of
opposite signs.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 24/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion and Concave Utility


Suppose a vN-M maximizer with current wealth W is oered
a fair lottery. Would he accept it?
With the lottery, expected utility is E [U (W + e")]. Without
it, expected utility is E [U (W )] = U (W ). Rejecting it implies
U (W ) > E [U (W + e
")] = pU (W + "1 ) + (1 p)U (W + "2 )
(10)
U (W ) can be written as
U(W ) = U (W + p"1 + (1 p)"2 ) (11)
Substituting into (10), we have
U (W + p"1 + (1 p)"2 ) > pU (W + "1 )+(1 p)U (W + "2 )
(12)
which is the denition of U being a concave function.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 25/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion , Concavity


A function is concave if a line joining any two points lies
entirely below the function. When U(W ) is a continuous,
second dierentiable function, concavity implies U 00 (W ) < 0.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 26/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion , Concavity

To show that concave utility implies rejecting a fair lottery, we


can use Jensens inequality which says that for concave U( )

E [U(~
x )] < U(E [~
x ]) (13)

Therefore, substituting x~ = W + e
" with E [e
"] = 0, we have

E [U(W + e
")] < U (E [W + e
"]) = U(W ) (14)

which is the desired result.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 27/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion and Risk Premium


How might aversion to risk be quantied? One way is to
dene a risk premium as the amount that an individual is
willing to pay to avoid a risk.
Let denote the individuals risk premium for a lottery, e
".
is the maximum insurance payment an individual would pay to
avoid the lottery risk:
U(W ) = E [U(W + e
")] (15)
W is dened as the certainty equivalent level of wealth
associated with the lottery, e
".
For concave utility, Jensens inequality implies > 0 when e " is
fair: the individual would accept wealth lower than her
expected wealth following the lottery, E [W + e "], to avoid the
lottery.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 28/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Premium

For small e
" we can take a Taylor approximation of equation
(15) around e" = 0 and = 0.
Expanding the left-hand side about = 0 gives

U(W ) = U(W ) U 0 (W ) (16)

and expanding the right-hand side about e


" gives

E [U(W + e
")] = E U(W ) + e "2 U 00 (W )
"U 0 (W ) + 12 e (17)
2
= U(W ) + 0 + 1
2 U 00 (W )
where 2 "2 is the lotterys variance.
E e

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 29/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Premium contd

Equating the results in (16) and (17) gives


00 (W )
1 2U 1 2
= 2 2 R(W ) (18)
U 0 (W )

where R(W ) U 00 (W )=U 0 (W ) is the Pratt (1964)-Arrow


(1971) measure of absolute risk aversion.
Since 2 > 0, U 0 (W ) > 0, and U 00 (W ) < 0, concavity of the
utility function ensures that must be positive
An individual may be very risk averse ( U 00 (W ) is large), but
may be unwilling to pay a large risk premium if he is poor
since his marginal utility U 0 (W ) is high.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 30/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

U 00 (W ) and U 0 (W )
Consider the following negative exponential utility function:
bW
U(W ) = e ;b > 0 (19)

Note that U 0 (W ) = be bW > 0 and


U 00 (W ) = b 2 e bW < 0.
Consider the behavior of a very wealthy individual whose
wealth approaches innity

lim U 0 (W ) = lim U 00 (W ) = 0 (20)


W !1 W !1

Theres no concavity, so is there no risk aversion?


b2 e bW
R(W ) = bW
=b (21)
be
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 31/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Absolute Risk Aversion: Dollar Payment for Risk

We see that negative exponential utility, U(W ) = e bW ,

has constant absolute risk aversion.

If, instead, we want absolute risk aversion to decline in wealth,


a necessary condition is that the utility function must have a
positive third derivative:
00
@R(W ) @ UU 0 (W
(W )
) U 000 (W )U 0 (W ) [U 00 (W )]2
= =
@W @W [U 0 (W )]2
(22)

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 32/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

R(W ) ) U(W )

The coe cient of risk aversion contains all relevant


information about the individuals risk preferences. Note that
U 00 (W ) @ (ln [U 0 (W )])
R(W ) = = (23)
U 0 (W ) @W

Integrating both sides of (23), we have


Z
R(W )dW = ln[U 0 (W )] + c1 (24)

where c1 is an arbitrary constant. Taking the exponential


function of (24) gives
R
R (W )dW
e = U 0 (W )e c1 (25)

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 33/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

R(W ) ) U(W ) contd

Integrating once again, we obtain


Z R
e R (W )dW dW = e c1 U(W ) + c2 (26)

where c2 is another arbitrary constant.

Because vN-M expected utility functions are unique up to a


linear transformation, e c1 U(W ) + c2 reects the same risk
preferences as U(W ).

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 34/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is another frequently used measure


dened as
Rr (W ) = WR(W ) (27)
Consider risk aversion for some utility functions often used in
models of portfolio choice and asset pricing. Power utility can
be written as
U(W ) = 1 W ; < 1 (28)
( 1)W 2 (1 )
implying that R(W ) = W 1
= W and, therefore,
Rr (W ) = 1 .
Hence, it displays constant relative risk aversion.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 35/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Logarithmic Utility: Constant Relative Risk Aversion


Logarithmic utility is a limiting case of power utility. Since
utility functions are unique up to a linear transformation, write
the power utility function as
1 1 W 1
W =

Next take its limit as ! 0. Do so by rewriting the


numerator and applying LHpitals rule:
W 1 e ln(W ) 1 ln(W )W
lim = lim = lim = ln(W )
!0 !0 !0 1
(29)
Thus, logarithmic utility is power utility with coe cient of
2
relative risk aversion (1 ) = 1 since R(W ) = W W 1
= W1
and Rr (W ) = 1.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 36/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

HARA: Power, Log, Quadratic

Hyperbolic absolute-risk-aversion (HARA) utility generalizes


all of the previous utility functions:

1 W
U(W ) = + (30)
1
W
s:t: 6= 1, > 0, 1 + > 0, and = 1 if = 1.
1
W
Thus, R(W ) = 1 + . Since R(W ) must be > 0, it
1
W
implies > 0 when > 1. Rr (W ) = W 1 + .
HARA utility nests constant absolute risk aversion ( = 1,
= 1), constant relative risk aversion ( < 1, = 0), and
quadratic ( = 2) utility functions.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 37/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Another Look at the Risk Premium

A premium to avoid risk is ne for insurance, but we may also


be interested in a premium to bear risk.
This alternative concept of a risk premium was used by Arrow
(1971), identical to the earlier one by Pratt (1964).
Suppose that a fair lottery e
", has the following payos and
probabilities:
1
+ with probability 2
e
"= 1 (31)
with probability 2

How much do we need to deviate from fairness to make a


risk-averse individual indierent to this lottery?

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 38/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Premium v2

Lets dene a risk premium, , in terms of probability of


winning p:

= Prob(win) Prob(lose) = p (1 p) = 2p 1 (32)

Therefore, from (32) we have

Prob(win) p = 12 (1 + )
Prob(lose) = 1 p = 12 (1 )

We want that equalizes the utilities of taking and not taking


the lottery:
1 1
U(W ) = (1 + )U(W + ) + (1 )U(W ) (33)
2 2
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 39/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion (again)

Lets again take a Taylor approximation of the right side,


around = 0
1
U(W ) = (1 + ) U(W ) + U 0 (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W ) (34)
2
1
+ (1 ) U(W ) U 0 (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W )
2
= U(W ) + U 0 (W ) + 12 2 U 00 (W )

Rearranging (34) implies


1
= 2 R(W ) (35)

which, as before, is a function of the coe cient of absolute


risk aversion.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 40/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk Aversion (again)

Note that the Arrow premium, , is in terms of a probability,


while the Pratt measure, , is in units of a monetary payment.
If we multiply by the monetary payment received, , then
equation (35) becomes
1 2
= 2 R(W ) (36)

Since 2 is the variance of the random payo, e ", equation (36)


shows that the Pratt and Arrow risk premia are equivalent.
Both were obtained as a linearization of the true function
around e
" = 0.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 41/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

A Simple Portfolio Choice Problem

Lets consider the relation between risk aversion and an


individuals portfolio choice in a single period context.
Assume there is a riskless security that pays a rate of return
equal to rf and just one risky security that pays a stochastic
rate of return equal to er.
Also, let W0 be the individuals initial wealth, and let A be the
dollar amount that the individual invests in the risky asset at
the beginning of the period. Thus, W0 A is the initial
investment in the riskless security.
Denote the individuals end-of-period wealth as W ~:

~
W = (W0 A)(1 + rf ) + A(1 + ~r ) (37)
= W0 (1 + rf ) + A(~r rf )

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 42/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Single Period Utility Maximization

A vN-M expected utility maximizer chooses her portfolio by


maximizing the expected utility of end-of-period wealth:
~ )] = maxE [U (W0 (1 + rf ) + A(~r
maxE [U(W rf ))] (38)
A A

Maximization satises the rst-order condition wrt. A:


h i
E U0 W ~ (~r rf ) = 0 (39)

Note that the second order condition


h i
E U 00 W~ (~r rf )2 0 (40)

~
is satised because U 00 W 0 from concavity.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 43/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Obtaining A from FOC

If E [~r rf ] = 0, i.e., E [~r ] = rf , then we can show A=0 is the


solution.
When A=0, W ~ = W0 (1 + rf ) and, therefore,
U0 W ~ = U 0 (W0 (1 + rf )) is nonstochastic. Hence,
h i
E U0 W ~ (~r rf ) = U 0 (W0 (1 + rf )) E [~r rf ] = 0.

Next, suppose E [~r rf ] > 0.


A h= 0 is not a solution
i because
E U0 W ~ (~r rf ) = U 0 (W0 (1 + rf )) E [~r rf ] > 0 when
A = 0.
Thus, when E [~r ] rf > 0, lets show that A > 0.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 44/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Why must A > 0?

Let r h denote a realization of ~r > rf , and let W h be the


corresponding level of W ~
Also, let r l denote a realization of ~r < rf , and let W l be the
corresponding level of W ~.
Then U 0 (W h )(r h rf ) > 0 and U 0 (W l )(r l rf ) < 0.
~ (~r
For U 0 W rf ) to average to zero for all realizations of
~r , it must be that W h > W l so that U 0 W h < U 0 W l due
to the concavity of the utility function.
Why? Since E [~r ] rf > 0, the average r h is farther above rf
than the average r l is below rf . To preserve (39), the
multipliers must satisfy U 0 W h < U 0 W l to compensate,
which occurs when W h > W l and which requires that A > 0.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 45/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

How does A change wrt W0 ?


dA(W 0 )
Well use implicit dierentiation to obtain dW 0 :
h i
Dene f (A; W0 ) E U W f and let
v (W0 ) = maxf (A; W0 ) be the maximized value of expected
A
utility when A, is optimally chosen.
Also dene A (W0 ) as the value of A that maximizes f for a
given value of the initial wealth parameter W0 .
Now take the total derivative of v (W0 ) with respect to W0 by
applying the chain rule:
dv (W 0 ) @f (A;W 0 ) dA(W 0 ) @f (A(W 0 );W 0 )
dW 0 = @A dW 0 + @W 0 .
However, @f (A;W
@A
0)
= 0 since it is the rst-order condition for a
maximum.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 46/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

How does A change wrt W0 contd

dv (W 0 ) @f (A(W 0 );W 0 )
The total derivative simplies to dW 0 = @W 0 :
Thus, the derivative of the maximized value of the objective
function with respect to a parameter is just the partial
derivative with respect to that parameter.
Second, consider how the optimal value of the control
variable, A (W0 ), changes when the parameter W0 changes.
We can derive this relationship by taking the total derivative
of the (39) @f (A (W0 ) ; W0 ) =@A = 0 with respect to W0 :
@(@f (A(W 0 );W 0 )=@A) 2f (A(W 0 );W 0 ) dA(W 0 ) @ 2 f (A(W 0 );W 0 )
@W 0 = 0 =@ @A 2 dW 0 + @A@W 0

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 47/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

How does A change wrt W0 contd

Rearranging the above gives us

dA (W0 ) @ 2 f (A (W0 ) ; W0 ) @ 2 f (A (W0 ) ; W0 )


= = (41)
dW0 @A@W0 @A2
We can then evaluate it to obtain
h i
(1 + rf )E U ~
00 (W )(~
r rf )
dA
= h i (42)
dW0 E U 00 (W ~ )(~r rf )2

The denominator of (42) is positive because of concavity.


dA
Therefore, the sign of dW 0
depends on the numerator.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 48/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

dA
Implications for dW0 with DARA

Consider an individual with absolute risk aversion that is


decreasing in wealth. Assuming E [~r ] > rf so that A > 0:

R W h < R (W0 (1 + rf )) (43)

where, as before, R(W ) = U 00 (W )=U 0 (W ).


Multiplying both terms of (43) by U 0 (W h )(r h rf ), which is
a negative quantity, the inequality sign changes:
U 00 (W h )(r h rf ) > U 0 (W h )(r h rf )R (W0 (1 + rf )) (44)
Then for A > 0, we have W l < W0 (1 + rf ). If absolute risk
aversion is decreasing in wealth, this implies
R(W l ) > R (W0 (1 + rf )) (45)
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 49/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

dA
Implications for dW0 with DARA

Multiplying (45) by U 0 (W l )(r l rf ), which is positive, so


that the sign of (45) remains the same, we obtain

U 00 (W l )(r l rf ) > U 0 (W l )(r l rf )R (W0 (1 + rf )) (46)

Inequalities (44) and (46) are the same whether the


realization is ~r = r h or ~r = r l .
Therefore, if we take expectations over all realizations of ~r , we
obtain
h i h i
~ )(~r rf ) > E U 0 (W
E U 00 (W ~ )(~r rf ) R (W0 (1 + rf ))
(47)
The rst term on the right-hand side is just the FOC.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 50/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with ARA/RRA


Inequality (47) reduces to
h i
~ )(~r
E U 00 (W rf ) > 0 (48)

Thus, DARA ) dA=dW0 > 0: amount invested A increases in


initial wealth.
What about the proportion of initial wealth? To analyze this,
dene
dA
dW 0 dA W0
A
= (49)
W
dW0 A
0

which is the elasticity measuring the proportional increase in


the risky asset for an increase in initial wealth.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 51/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with RRA

A
Adding 1 A to the right-hand side of (49) gives

(dA=dW0 )W0 A
=1+ (50)
A
Substituting dA=dW0 from equation (42), we have
h i h i
~ )(~r rf ) + AE U 00 (W
W0 (1 + rf )E U 00 (W ~ )(~r rf )2
= 1+ h i
~ )(~r rf )2
AE U 00 (W
(51)
Collecting terms in ~ )(~r
U 00 (W rf ), this can be rewritten as

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 52/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with RRA

h i
~ )(~r
E U 00 (W
rf )fW0 (1 + rf ) + A(~r rf )g
= 1+ h i (52)
AE U 00 (W ~ )(~r rf )2
h i
~ )(~r rf )W
E U 00 (W ~
= 1+ h i (53)
AE U 00 (W~ )(~r rf )2

The denominator in (53) is positive for A > 0 by concavity.


Therefore, > 1, so that the individual invests proportionally
more
h in the risky asseti with an increase in wealth, if
00
E U (W ~ )(~r rf )W
~ > 0.
Can we relate this to the individuals risk aversion?
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 53/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with DRRA

Consider an individual whose relative risk aversion is


decreasing in wealth.
Then for A > 0, we again have W h > W0 (1 + rf ). When
Rr (W ) WR(W ) is decreasing in wealth, this implies

W h R(W h ) < W0 (1 + rf )R (W0 (1 + rf )) (54)

Multiplying both terms of (54) by U 0 (W h )(r h rf ), which is


a negative quantity, the inequality sign changes:

W h U 00 (W h )(r h rf ) > U 0 (W h )(r h rf )W0 (1+rf )R (W0 (1 + rf ))


(55)

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 54/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with DRRA

For A > 0, we have W l < W0 (1 + rf ). If relative risk aversion


is decreasing in wealth, this implies

W l R(W l ) > W0 (1 + rf )R (W0 (1 + rf )) (56)

Multiplying (56) by U 0 (W l )(r l rf ), which is positive, so


that the sign of (56) remains the same, we obtain

W l U 00 (W l )(r l rf ) > U 0 (W l )(r l rf )W0 (1+rf )R (W0 (1 + rf ))


(57)
Inequalities (55) and (57) are the same whether the
realization is ~r = r h or ~r = r l .
Therefore, taking expectations over all realizations of ~r yields

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 55/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Implications for risk-taking with DRRA

h i h i
E W~ U 00 (W
~ )(~r rf ) > ~ )(~r
E U 0 (W rf ) W0 (1+rf )R(W0 (1+rf ))
(58)
The rst term on the right-hand side is just the FOC, so
inequality (58) reduces to
h i
E W ~ U 00 (W
~ )(~r rf ) > 0 (59)

Hence, decreasing relative risk aversion implies > 1 so an


individual invests proportionally more in the risky asset as
wealth increases.
The opposite is true for increasing relative risk aversion: < 1
so that this individual invests proportionally less in the risky
asset as wealth increases.
George Pennacchi University of Illinois
Expected utility and risk aversion 56/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Risk-taking with ARA/RRA

The main results of this section can be summarized as:

Risk Aversion Investment Behavior


@A
Decreasing Absolute @W 0 > 0
@A
Constant Absolute @W 0 = 0
@A
Increasing Absolute @W 0 < 0
@A A
Decreasing Relative @W 0 > W 0
@A A
Constant Relative @W 0 = W 0
@A A
Increasing Relative @W 0 < W 0

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 57/ 58
1.1: Preferences 1.2: Risk Premia 1.3: Portfolio Choice 1.4: Conclusions

Conclusions

We have shown:

Why expected utility, rather than expected value, is a better


criterion for choosing and valuing assets.
What conditions preferences can satisfy to be represented by
an expected utility function.
How relationship between utility functions, U(W ); and risk
aversion.
How ARA/RRA aect the choice between risky and risk-free
assets.

George Pennacchi University of Illinois


Expected utility and risk aversion 58/ 58

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen