Sie sind auf Seite 1von 6

How to Make Theories Untestable: A Guide to Theorists

Author(s): Clifford D. Shearing


Source: The American Sociologist, Vol. 8, No. 1 (Feb., 1973), pp. 33-37
Published by: American Sociological Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27702070
Accessed: 08-05-2017 15:58 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Sociologist

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HOW TO MAKE THEORIES UNTESTABLE:
A GUIDE TO THEORISTS*
CLIFFORD D. SHEARING

University of Toronto
The American Sociologist 1973, Vol. 8, (Feb.) : 33-37

A cursory glance at the development of so- ent-refer to what we call "the world"-and
ciological theory should indicate to any in- be ''capable of being tested by experience''
dependent observer that any theorist who (Popper, 1959 :40). Popper (1959 :40-42) has
seeks sociological fame must ensure that his argued that in view of the fact that scientific
theories are essentially untestable. Despite theories consist of universal statements relat-
this, to my knowledge, all writers who have ing at least two variables-a further criterion
addressed themselves to the question of theory of a scientific theory-testability means, in ef-
building-and this is, surprisingly, particu- fect, not that scientific theories must be veri-
larly true in explicitly pedagogical texts- fiable but rather that they must be '' falsifi-
have inexplicably concerned themselves exclu- able.'' A ''theory is empirical if it can, in
sively with the question of how to construct principle, be refuted by empirical observa-
testable theories. It is hoped that this paper tion. If it is irrefutable by observation, then it
may held redirect attention to what is clearly is not strictly empirical" (Cohen, 1968 :3).
the more sensible question : how does one con- This discussion provides for the general prin-
struct untestable theories? ciple that, if a theory is to be untestable, it
I propose here two methods for making a must be non-empirical.
theory untestable. To provide a rationale for Now, because scientific statements are uni-
these two methods, it is necessary to discuss versal, and empirical observations are of par-
briefly the nature of theory generally and sci- ticular events, if a theory is to be refutable
entific theory in particular. 1 The term theory, there must be some arrangement whereby
Kaplan (1964 :294) writes, "stands for the theoretical statements can be linked to ''or-
symbolic dimension of experience, as opposed dinary propositions'' about empirical parti-
to the apprehension of brute fact." However, culars (Zetterberg, 1965 :79-86). In short, we
as Cohen (1968 :102) notes, not only do must be able to ''deduce statements of par-
theories go beyond fact but they do so by ticular events from scientific theories, and to
virtue of their use of universal categories. check these by observation . . . '' (Cohen,
Scientific theories are a special type of theory 1968 :3). This does not mean that all state-
-Cohen (1968 :2) distinguishes three other ments must be capable of being tested in this
types-defined in terms of a set of normative manner but simply that one must be able
criteria to which scientists seek to conform to deduce some empirically testable proposi-
and in terms of which their theories are eval- tions.2
uated. Central among these is the principle We are now in a position to state our first
that scientific theories should be empirical. method for making sociological theory un-
That is, they should have an empirical refer- testable; that is, for making it unscientific:
make certain that no empirically refutable
statements can be deduced from the theory.
*I would like to thank Robin Gerrish, John Howe, In other words, ensure that no statement about
Peter MacnaughtonSmith, Mike Petrunik, Judy the relationship between particular events
Posner, Jim Turk, Irvin Waller and Kurt Weis for
their comments on this paper.
can be deduced from the theory (Bridgman,
1 Regretably, because of the total lack of literature
concerning how theories are to be made untestable, 2 The position taken here is explicitly rejected by
in this paper I have been forced, albeit reluctantly, Popper who argues that every scientific statement
in developing the argument, to refer to authors wlio "Must be capable of being tested . " (Popper,
are concerned with constructing testable theories. 1959 :47) ; but is supported by Nagel (1961: 101-102).
33

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
34 THE AMERICAN SociOLOGIST

1927: Chapter 1; Nagel, 1961 :90) .3 There are There are, of course, in the corpus of so-
several ways in which this can be done and ciological theory many examples of building
we will discuss a few of them : untestable theory that the novice can emulate:
(i) Provide no operational definitions for examples where it is not possible to provide
any of the terms in the theory. This means, in central concepts with empirical content and
effect, refusing to specify either the domain of where consequently, testing the theory be-
a concept (the "object" to which it applies) comes difficult and perhaps impossible. An
or the content of the concept in empirical area ripe with such example is structural-
terms (just what aspect of the "object" is functionalism. Philosophers of science, nota-
being referred to) or both. Zetterberg bly Hempel (in Gross, 1959 :271-307) and
(1965 :80) provides an excellent example of Nagel (1961: Chapter 12), have analyzed care-
what not to do in his discussion of how the fully the logic of functional analysis and have
empirical content of a theoretical proposition specified criteria which must be met if func-
is specified by the operational definition of its tional analysis is to qualify as scienitfic. Two
concepts. He illustrates the process by means of these are particularly relevant for this
of the theoretical proposition, "Persons tend paper: (a) one must specify the system in
to engage in actions that maintain the evalua- question, that is, the domain to which the
tions they receive from their associates.'' analysis refers and (b) the specific goal state
Zetterberg demonstrates, by the specification in question. Zetterberg, in considering these
of some of the concepts involved, how one criteria refers to the following statement by
moves from theoretical to ordinary proposi- Merton, "Functions are those observed con-
tions and hence towards testability. For ex- sequences which make for the adaptation or
ample, he suggests that one of the indices of adjustment of a given system; and dysfunc-
the concept ''evaluations'' is ''rank,'' where tions those observed consequences which lessen
" 'rank' is defined as an evaluation of a posi- the adaptation of the system" (quoted in
tion in a social structure'' and where there is Zetterberg, 1965 :74-75). Zetterberg (follow-
some means of operationally defining, by way ing and referring to Galtung's unpublished
of particular measurement procedures, this manuscript, no date) notes that the crucial
more specific concept ( 1965 :81). On the basis words in this statement are "adaptation" and
of this analysis it is possible to move towards "adjustment" and the crucial question is
a more testable proposition by rewriting the ''adaptation'' and ''adjustment'' to what?
above proposition as, ''Persons tend to engage In terms of the criteria of scientific functional
in actions that maintain the rank they enjoy analysis just given, this question can be con-
in their social structure'' ( 1965 :81) . See how sidered in two parts: (a) what is the system
dangerous a seemingly innocuous move to- or sub-system in question? and (b) how would
wards operational definition can be! If this "adaptation" or "adjustment" be recog-
process of operational definition of terms is nized? (That is, what criteria would we use
unwittingly continued the theorist will soon to identify them?) Merton, as a wise theorist
find himself in the disastrous position of hav- -whether this wisdom is manifest or latent
ing derived from his theory an empirically re- is not at issue here-does not provide a clearly
futable proposition (1965 :82). specified answer to either of these questions.
In the context of these two criteria of valid
functional analysis Talcott Parsons seems, at
a Note that failure to provide concepts of a theory first glance, to have blundered in developing
with an empirical referrent does not mean, as for
example Bridgman has maintained (1927:Chapter 1),
his theory of action. For, in this theory he
that these concepts have no meaning, or even that appears to have given considerable attention
they do not have a valid scientific meaning. For, to specifying systems and sub-systems of ac-
besides operational definitions, there are two other tion and to identifying the goal states of all
sources of meaning for scientific concepts: ''an ab-
stract calculus that is the logical skeleton of the systems of action. These goal states are con-
explanatory system, and that 'implicitly defines' the ceptualized as four system problems that must
basic notions of the system; ... and an interpretation be solved if the system is to continue to main-
or model for the abstract calculus which supplies tain its boundaries vis-a-vis the environment
some flesh for the skeletal structure in te-rms of more
or less familiar conceptual or visualizable materials" (Parsons, 1961 :38-41). However, once Par-
(Nagel, 1961:90). sons' theory is examined in detail it soon be-

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
How TO MAKE THEORIES UNTESTABLE 35
comes appart>nt that it is not at all clear how on Black's paper ''Some Questions About
one would know whether these problems were Parsons' Theories" (Black 1961 :268-288).
being solved independently of the mainte- Black, in his paper, attempts the difficult task
nance of boundaries (assuming for the mo- of formulating, in propositional form, the
ment that one could know when a system's basic assumptions underlying Parsons' theory.
boundaries were being maintained), so that In responding to Black's formulation, Par-
it is difficult to see how one would test propo- sons sets himsPlf the task of providing ''a new
sitions relating these two concepts. In his succinct statemt>nt'' of ''the frame of refer-
discussion of Parsons' four goal states, Zetter- ence'' for action theory which the reader can
berg notes that in order to test Parsons' theory compare with Black's. Parsons, in his response
it would be necessary to specify operationally to Black, despite statements to the contrary,
the nature of each goal state so that this state successfully foils Black's attempt to produce
could be reeognized. In order to allow his testable proposition by thoroughly and sys-
readtrs to conceive of what such a state of tematically muddying any clarity that Black
affairs would be like, Zetterberg invites them managed to produce. Parsons, thereby, deftly
to imagine that we ''can measure how well defends his theory by negating Black's at-
each rfunctional problem l is resolved in a tempt to move it towards testability.
social system by reading four master gauges, George C. Homans is very adept at using
and that all subsystems have similar gauges, this method for producing untestable theory.
and that we also can rate the subsystems ac- His particular forte lies in developing propo-
cording to the input and output they make sitions which, on first glance, appear the very
in these four quantities in the larger system" model of clarity and precision but which, as
( 1965 :77). Zetterberg 's point is that in order M:nris (1970) has recently shown, reveal a
to rigorously test this aspect of Parsons' subtle ambiguity when an attempt is made
theory one would have to be able to do some- to derive testable theories from them. One
thing like this and one simply can't imagine strategy used by Romans is the useful tech-
how one would do this. nique of leaving vague the conditions under
(ii) Prom:de no propositions in the theory. which a relationship holds. For example, in
Without propositions there clearly can be no Homans' second postulate he introduces the
possibility of testing one's theory. This is a temporal qualifiPr "within a given period of
particularly good method for one can create time'' and in his fourth postulnte he uses the
the illusion of testability by introducing con- qualifier ''in the recent past.'' 4 Both qunli-
cepts which can be clearly operationally de- fiers help to preserve an essential element of
fined. However, the theorist should be warned vagueness and ambiguity in seemingly very
that it is difficult in practice to develop a precise propositions (Maris, 1970 :1071-1072).
theoretical scheme which is no more than a Another strategy used by Homans is the
tnxonomy. Thus, I do not advise using this ''more than-less than'' technique. By in-
method alone, despite its intrinsic attractions. troducino- the terms more and less into one's
Notwithstanding its difficulty, however, many propositi~ns ( eg. the more X, the less Y), one
socologicnl theorists have used this method gives theoretical statements an undeniable
skillfully and have developed theories with propositional form. However, by not further
many more concepts than propositions. For qualifying such propositions and stating how
example, Romans (1967), Turk (1967) and much more or how much less, one makE's re-
Zetterberg (1965) have pointed to the fact futation more difficult (unfortunately, not
that Parsons' theory is fundamentally a tax- impossible and this is a clear defect in Ho-
onomy rathPr than a set of propositions.
(iii) If one finds one has included proposi-
4 The postulates in question are:
tions in a theory, a "second best" way to Postulate 2:
makP the theory untcstable is to ensure that ''The more often 'dthin a given period of time
the relationship between terms remains as un- a man's aetivity rewards the activity of any ot11er,
clear as possible. This method, of course, the more oftrn the other will emit the activity."
should be used in conjunction with ( i) above Postulate 4:
''The more often a man has in the recent past
for best results. I suggest that an excellent received a rewarding activity from another, the less
exmnple of an nttpmpt to usp just this method valuable any further unit of that activity becomes to
is Parsons' comment (in Black, 1961 :311-363) him." (Maris, 1970 :1071)

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
36 THE AMERICAN SociOLOGIST

mans' theory). Further, so long as no quali- untestable. Romans' theory probably comes
fying assumptions specifying the. degree of as close as any to achieving internal consis-
association between the variables are made, tency or logical closure but even here, as
logical deductions from propositions becomes Maris (1970) has shown, in its present form,
problematic (see Maris, 1970:1076; Duncan, assumptions still have to be added to Romans'
1963 :452) unless the stringent requirements theory if it is to be stated in axiomatic rather
that one's propositions are stated in asymme- than verbal form. Towards the other end of
tric causal form and logical closure can be the continuum is Parsons' theory of action,
assumed (Costner and Leik, 1964) . although Parsons, more than most other theor-
1 turn now from giving examples of the ists, works seriously at integrating the various
first method of making theories untestable to parts of his theory. For an example, see his
a statement of a second method for accom- Working Papers in the Theory of Action
plishing this end. In discussing the first (1953) and "Pattern Variables Revisited: A
method I have talked about testing theories Response to Dubin" ( 1960). Even further
by testing propositions which are deduced towards the inconsistency-end of the scale
from the theory. This method of theory testing are symbolic interactionists like Herbert
rests on the assumption that the theory in Blumer, who, in his use of the -Meadian con-
question is a logically closed system. In such cept of the "I," provides for a built-in inde-
a theory all the assumptions necessary to de- terminancy which prohibits the development
rive the empirical propositions are explicitly of a systematic set of propositions in deduc-
stated and, further, each proposition has iden- tive form.
tifiable implications for all the other proposi- In concluding this paper a w'ord of caution
tions in the theory. (For a discussion of the is necessary about the use of these methods.
concept of a closed theoretical system see Par- The methods just described assume a partic-
sons, 1968 :10.) Only under these conditions, ular frame of reference : the positivistic ontol-
as Popper (1959 :71-72) has indicated, is it ogy, in which an external and independent
possible, by testing specific empirical proposi- reality is postulated, and in which this postu-
tions, to provide a severe test of the theory late is used as the basis for the theory of evi-
as a whole. It is because of the importance dence which underlies the above discussion.
of this criterion of scientific theory that sim- However, as Lewis Carroll and others have re-
plicity and axiomatic formulation are stressed peatedly pointed out in both fairy tales and
by those naive theorists who stress the ip:l- philosophy, these common sense assumptions
portance of testability. The importance of about the nature of reality can be suspended.
axiomatic formulation follows from the fact Once this is done and one steps ''through the
that only under these conditions is it possible looking glass'' a new world is revealed : a
to assess whether or not a theory is closed, world with different questions, different en-
and, if it is not closed, to determine where terprises and different rules of evidence. So,
the logical gaps are. This criterion for scien- before using these methods to evaluate theory,
tific theory, that is, testable theory, is often be it one's own or others', be sure you know
referred to as the criterion of internal con- on which side of the "looking glass" the
sistency. From this it follows that a second theorist is working; for these methods, either
method for making theory untestable is to as standards or guides to action, are applic-
ensure that the theory is internally incon- able only on one side.
sistent. That is, take steps to ensure that one's
theory does not form a deductive system where
all the propositions of the theory can be de- REFERENCES
duced from a set of axioms. Under these con-
ditions, a test of any proposition, even if it Black, M. (ed.)
1961 The Social Theories of Talcott Parsons.
fulfills all the criteria of refutability (and Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
herein lies the beauty of this method), would Blau, P.
simply be a test of that particular proposition 1964 Exchange and Power in Social Life. New
and not the theory as a whole. In terms of this York: John Wiley and Sons.
Blumer, H.
criterion (and this is evidence of the wide- 1969 Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and
spread historical use of this method) prac- Method. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-
tically all major sociological theories remain Hall.

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
COMPUTER SIMULATION IN TEACHING 37
Bridgman, P. theory. '' American Sociological Review 35
1927 The Logic of Modern Physics. New York: (August): 1069-1081.
Macmillan. Nagel, E.
Cohen, P. (ed.) 1961 The Structure of Science. New York: Har-
1968 Modern Social Theory. London: Heinne court, Brace and World.
mann. Parsons, T ., et a!.
Costner, H. L. and R. K. Leik 1953 Working Papers in the Theory of Action.
1964 ''Deductions from 'axiomatic theory.' '' Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
American Sociological Review 29 (Decem- Parsons, T.
ber) :819-835. 1960 ''Pattern variables revisited: a response to
Duncan, 0. D. Dubin.'' American Sociological Review 25
1963 ''Axioms or correlations~'' American So- (August) :467-483.
ciological Review 28 (June) :452. 1961 Theories of Society. T. Parsons, et a!., eds.
Gross, L. ( ed.) New York: Free Press of Glencoe.
1959 Symposium on Sociological Theory. New 1968 The Structure of Social Action. New York:
York: Harper and Row. Free Press.
Romans, G. Popper, K.
1961 Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms. New 1959 The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London:
York: Harcourt, Brace and World. Hutchinson.
1967 The Nature of Social Science. New York: Turk, A.
Harcourt, Brace and World. 1967 ''On the Parsonian approach to theory
Kaplan, A. construction.'' Sociological Quarterly 8
1964 The Conduct of Inquiry. San Francisco: (Winter) :37-50.
Chandler. Zetterberg, H. L.
Maris, R. 1965 On Theory and Verification in Sociology.
1970 ''The logical adequacy of Romans' social Totowa, N.J.: Bedminster Press.

MANUSCRIPTS FOR THE


ASA ROSE SOCIOLOGY SERIES

Fellows and Active and Student members of the Association


may submit manuscripts of I00 to 300 typed pages for
publication in the ASA Arnold and Caroline Rose Mono-
graph Series in Sociology to the Series Editor, Sheldon
Stryker, Department of Sociology, Indiana University,
Bloomington, Indiana 47401.

This content downloaded from 148.202.10.146 on Mon, 08 May 2017 15:58:56 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen