In A Secular Age, Charles Taylor poses the following question: “why was it virtually impossible
not to believe in God in, say, 1500 in our Western society, while in 2000 many of us find this not only
easy, but even inescapable?”1 His almost 800 page answer is an ambitious revision and retelling of the
process that we call secularization, and his intention is to demonstrate the inadequacy of mainstream
secularization theory (MST). The MST generally states that 1) in the modern period, beginning in the
17th century and increasingly in the 19th, the place of religion in public life declined and religious belief
and practice substantially decreased; 2) these changes are the result of something like industrialization,
urbanization, the differentiation of value spheres, or the progress of the natural sciences; and 3) that this
decline and decrease should be seen as a linear progression, was all but inevitable, and will almost
certainly continue. The MST is an example of what Taylor calls “subtraction stories,” the chief culprits in
Taylor’s account.
human beings having lost, or sloughed off, or liberated themselves from certain earlier,
human nature which were there all along, but had been impeded by what is now set
aside.2
Reason dispels Myth. Science supplants Religion. Darwin refutes the Bible. And so forth. These stories
are subtractive in two senses. First, the move to modernity is described as a skimming off of the dross of
religious belief, freeing up the underlying positum and essential kernel of human nature; fanciful
interpretations are dismissed, leaving pure, brute fact laying about for all and sundry to see. Second,
1
Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2007), 25.
2
Ibid., 22.
1
these stories are to Taylor’s eye far too simple and reductive; they either unduly prioritize one factor as
the major motor of secularization—e.g., economics, science, etc.—and/or drastically distort religious
belief, practice, and institutions in order to fit the bounds of their interpretative frame.
Taylor is convinced that MST is propped up by a cluster of thoroughly modern prejudices which
he yokes under the phrase “The Immanent Frame.” The gradual emergence and eventual victory of the
immanent frame involves a great many tectonic shifts in human thought, practice, and experience, such as
the disenchantment of the world, an ethic increasingly concentrated on discipline, rules, and norms, the
vision of nature as an impersonal order, and the rise of an “exclusive humanism,” 3 to name but a few; but
the upshot of these changes is the eclipse of any reference to a transcendent reality in general, or God in
particular. Human flourishing, moral life, and nature all come to be understood in a self-sufficient, “this-
Taylor’s alterative, the “Reform Master Narrative” (RMN), can be distilled into three claims. 4
(267-9) First, exclusive humanism and the modern moral order, the anthropocentric shift that rejects a
transcendent reality and refuses to acknowledge a good beyond natural human flourishing, arose mainly
as a result of pressures within Latin Christendom, pressures toward reform which collapses the long-
standing complementary between the higher spiritual vocations of the clergy and the more lax practices of
Taylor’s second claim is that exclusive humanism could not have arisen on any other basis. His
conviction is that it was the new ethical options opened up by exclusive humanism--not the cogency of its
arguments or the plausibility of its theories--that led (tempted?) larger segments of the population to drift
toward unbelief. A question Taylor poses well into his narrative crystallizes his convictions about this
issue: “How could the immense force of religion in human life [in pre-modern times] be countered,
3
By “exclusive,” Taylor means a view of human flourishing not grounded in a transcendent source, such as God or
the Tao, and without any good beyond “nature” or this life and world.
4
Ibid., 267-9.
2
except by using a modality of the most powerful ethical ideas, which this religion itself had helped to
entrench?” (267)
The third claim is that the secular age bears a constitutive reference to belief in God, albeit
usually negative, as something that has been overcome. This is the reason Taylor focuses so much on
narrative and historicity in his account of secularization. He detects a “double historicity” that determines
On the one hand, unbelief and exclusive humanism defined itself in relation to earlier
modes of belief, both orthodox theism and enchanted understandings of the world; and
this definition remains inseparable from unbelief today. On the other hand, later-arising
forms of unbelief, as well as attempts to redefine and recover belief, define themselves in
Taylor thinks that our present predicament must be seen not as a black and white tug of war between
belief and unbelief, Science vs. Religion, Intelligent Design vs. Evolution, etc.—but rather as a “three-
cornered affair” involving “those who acknowledge some good beyond life,” (traditional) “secular
humanists,” (modern) and “neo-Nietzscheans,” (postmodern). Taylor’s point is to show not only just how
“schizophrenic” the secular age really is, but to suggest that it opens up new possibilities for belief and
unbelief alike. Secularization should be seen as fundamentally ambivalent with regard to religion.
Taylor’s main objective, then, is to draw the immanent frame into focus, lay bare its origin and
development, and plead that an “open spin”—i.e., a strong sense of faith in a transcendent reality and the
pursuit and vision of a good that transcends human life--is not foreclosed, and a closed spin—i.e., “this is
all there is”--is not demanded, by the frame itself; his aim is to, as it were, rattle Webers’s “iron cage” by
giving a different account of what it is made of. Taylor’s remolding of Weber’s powerful image as a
frame, rather than a cage, is surely intentional, and probably meant to cast our condition less as a fateful
5
Ibid., 269.
3
fact, and more as a dominant frame of reference; as a social imaginary, not a solid reality. His main
quarrel with Weber—and others—is his characteristically modern tendency, set in motion most
powerfully by Nietzsche, to define religion as “man’s search for meaning”; this is what triggers the
closed spin on the immanent frame. There are alternatives, and merely recognizing this fact is, for Taylor,
an important and necessary step toward a rounder understanding of what it means to live in a secular age.
I will proceed as follows. First, I lay out Taylor’s methodology because it is it integral to his
account. His method is not just analytical but phenomenological and genealogical/historical. By
transcended a prior condition and undergone some process of development or maturation; he calls this our
“stadial consciousness.” Taylor’s methodology, in other words, reflects his third claim. Second, I sketch
some of the basic contours, pivotal concepts, and key constructions in Taylor’s story. Since his retelling
of the last five hundred years is far too rich and contains too many moving parts even to summarize in
such a short space, my aim here is to zero in on and connect a handful of the major themes in order to
illuminate the basic arc of the story, and suggest that his notion of “Reform” is the driving force of his
narrative. Finally, I break down his critique of MST and probe some of his conclusions about the place of
I. Taylor’s Methodology
phenomenological, and genealogical.6 Let us examine the second and third parts of this three-pronged
methodology in order to set the stage for Taylor’s account and thesis. The first is straightforward, is
obviously found in any secularization theory, and consists of a dissection of the salient factors
constituting and responsible for the emergence and process of secularization. The second and third,
however, are unique, and shed light on the novelty of Taylor’s approach.
6
Jose Casanova, “A Secular Age: Dawn or Twilight?” Varieties of Secularism in A Secular Age, Yale University, April 3-
5, 2008, 1.
4
A. Phenomenology
There are at least two reasons Taylor’s account can be classified as phenomenological: his unique
sense of “secularity,” and his notion of “fullness.” First, to see why Taylor makes recourse to
phenomenology, we must look at how he defines secularity. Taylor is not just concerned to offer another
make us think about what we mean when we claim to live in a secular world. As such, he tries to reframe
the debate by starting out from a different sense of secularity. The MST operates with two basic
definitions of secularity, which Taylor identifies as the decline of religion in public spaces (secularity 1)
and the waning of religious belief and practice in modern populations (secularity 2). Yet Taylor thinks
this leaves out something essential. He introduces a third category, which he calls “conditions of belief”
(secularity 3):
I want to talk about belief and unbelief, not as rival theories, that is, ways that people
account for existence…. Rather I what I want to do is focus attention on the different
kinds of lived experience involved in understanding your life in one way or the other, on
Taylor wants to focus, in other words, on what in phenomenology is commonly called “the lifeworld,” the
pre-reflective, pre-theoretical, everyday sense of the world that most people share yet rarely, if ever,
explicitly formulate. This is why he thinks we treat belief in God analytically--understood as a mere
theory or proposition about reality--at our peril; belief in God means different things in 1500 and 2000
because “all beliefs are held within a context or framework of the taken-for-granted, which usually
remains tacit, and may even be as yet unacknowledged by the agent, because never formulated.” 8 And it
is inattention to the “background” of the secular age—that is, the immanent frame—that Taylor sees as
the blind spot of MST. It results in an overly intellectualized reading of secularization that distorts the
7
Ibid., 4-5.
8
Ibid., 13.
5
experience of pre-modern societies by viewing them through the immanent frame, and misidentifies its
belief.
A second reason his account is phenomenological is his reliance on a general notion of human
experience,” which serves as the backbone for his analyses of the conditions of belief of people at various
points in history from 1500 to the present. One of Taylor’s crucial premises is that, whether we are
believers or unbelievers, nihilists, secular humanists, or Franciscans, we all have some general
understanding of human flourishing: “I am taking it as axiomatic that everyone, and hence all
philosophical positions, accepts some definition of greatness and fullness in human life.” 9 The way we
interpret this will differ—the monk may view fullness as the grace of God, the scientific materialist may
see it as a brain-bath of oxytocin, etc.—but, from an experiential standpoint, Taylor claims, we all see our
This basic understanding involves three points, which we can call fullness, emptiness, and
averageness. Fullness can be seen as the over-arching goal organizing our activities and primary good for
which we strive; it need not be something we explicitly formulate. It is something that can break through
in “limit experiences,” or can simply be the sense that “somewhere, in some activity, or condition, lies a
fullness, a richness; that is, in that place (activity or condition), life is fuller, richer, deeper, more worth
while, more admirable, more what it should be.”10 Emptiness or desolation is obviously the opposite,
while the third amounts to “some stable, even routine order in life, in which we are doing things which
have some meaning for us; for instance, which contribute to our ordinary happiness, or which are
9
Ibid., 597.
10
Ibid., 5.
11
Ibid., 7.
6
Now, what is distinctive about the immanent frame—as a theory—is that it has no place for a
robust sense of fullness, in the sense of flourishing grounded in a transcendent source; it eschews the
“transformation perspective.” As such, “par for the course,” succeeding on one or all of the above
middle-brow endeavors, becomes fullness itself; and indeed, questing after enlightenment, sanctity, or
salvation can distract from, and be destructive to, the sober pursuit of a human, all too human happiness. 12
In other words, the difference in the content and interpretations of the believer and the unbeliever may be
so great as to render Taylor’s scheme too narrow. Indeed, this is actually one of Taylor’s own critiques of
the modern approach to religion, namely, that it is watered down into a general search for “meaning”; he
considers this is a wet blanket prejudice, a non-starter that forecloses any serious, substantive discussion
of religion. Taylor insists, however, that even for the secular humanist who denies the existence of God
and an afterlife, “there is something he aspires to beyond where he’s at.” 13 Put differently, his ethical
aspirations are not congruent with his worldview. Taylor holds that the failure to appreciate the enduring
tension between a “transformation perspective” and the more modest view of flourishing--a tension
whose roots are, Taylor thinks, quite Christian—is a great problem with MST.
It is important for Taylor to validate this phenomenology of “fullness” and shore up this premise
in his argument because it is the wedge he will use later on in claiming that MST and the closed spin on
the immanent frame simply do not canvass the conditions of belief of the secular age; despite the iron grip
of the immanent frame of the present age, an aspiration for a higher-order fullness, Taylor thinks, still
flickers in even the staunchest materialist, and this is the clue to rattling the frame. This shows why
B. Genealogy
Turning to the genealogical aspect, Taylor unabashedly presents his account as a “master
narrative,” which he defines as a “broad framework [picture] of how history unfolds.” 14 He considers the
12
Ibid., 7.
13
Ibid., 7.
14
Ibid., 573.
7
post-modern dismissal of the latter as self-deceptive and disingenuous; we all need and use them,
“including those who claim to repudiate them,” he thinks, and the answer to a bad master narrative is not
a pox on any master narrative, but a better one. Taylor’s genealogy differs from others in that it is not
meant to “debunk.” The subtraction stories of secularization and MST tend to treat pre-modern peoples
as naïve and benighted, blind to the real motives for their beliefs in the transcendent; only the genealogist
can tell them what is actually going on “behind the back” of their consciousness, e.g., economic forces,
biological drives, political ideologies, etc. Once the cumbersome yokes of belief are fried by the sun of
Enlightenment—i.e., subtracted—then we have attained the normal, natural state. Taylor’s tack, however,
is different, because it is also phenomenological, in the sense that he brackets the truth and ontological
status of the world of, e.g., the 16th century Catholic worshipper, and simply tries to describe her world
“from the inside.” This interpretive charity enables Taylor to address the dizzying constellation of factors
driving the process of secularization, without settling for the soft sell of a subtraction story that privileges
The genealogical perspective is intimately tied to the third claim in Taylor’s thesis: namely, that
the secular age is “marked” by an “inescapable (though often negative) God reference,” in much the way
that a tattoo cleverly and carefully hidden by an adult is the unwanted sign of a wild youth he wishes he
could divorce, but cannot quite erase. Taylor is adamant that “it is a crucial fact of our present spiritual
predicament that it is historical; that is, our understanding of ourselves and where we stand is partly
defined by our sense of having come to where we are, of having overcome a previous condition.” 15 This
is why a purely analytical account will not do; the narrative is not an “optional extra for history buffs”
that can be cleanly separated from the mechanism of secularization. 16 We are studying not just factual
changes in the shape of Western societies—secularity 1 and 2—but we are also the heirs of and
participants in a conflict of interpretations, and that is why analysis and narrative must reflect one another.
15
Ibid., 29.
16
Ibid., 269.
8
So long as we fail to do justice to the variety of and connections between the narratives composing our
past and guiding our present, we will continue to misinterpret our own position.
Taylor also describes the modern historical self-understanding as a “stadial consciousness,” and
In virtually all pre-modern outlooks, the meaning of the repeated cycles of time was
found outside of time, or in higher time or eternity. What is peculiar to the modern world
is the rise of an outlook where the single reality giving meaning to the repeatable cycles
What is peculiar, that is, is the level of confidence and certainty that the pillars of the immanent frame are
obvious, self-evident, natural, etc., the sense that we have dispersed the childish clouds of myth-making
and come to take our stand on the sure ground of mature rationality. Once the immanent frame is set in
place, it comes to be seen as natural, as given, as the way things are. Taylor’s stresses that
the narrative dimension is extremely important, because the force of [the immanent
frame] comes less from the supposed detail of the argument (that science refutes religion,
or that Christianity is incompatible with human rights), an much more from the general
form of the narratives, to the effect that there was once a time when religion could
But the narrative dimension is either disavowed or whitewashed; this recalls Nietzsche’s observation that
democratic societies harbor a prejudice against origins. The birth certificate is burned; the mythos
masked; the origin obscured. Taylor’s twist is not to escape from the stadial consciousness—indeed, this
17
Ibid., 716.
18
Ibid., 590.
9
would be a very stadial thing to do!—but to tell a more adequate story and expand our frame of reference
so that we can see just how close the secular age remains to its late medieval roots in Latin Christendom,
to enrich the thin-soup conception of religion underwriting the MST and subtraction stories, and to
undermine the assumption that modernity entails secularity 2; this is how the shift to studying the
Lastly, Taylor relies on a construct he calls the “social imaginary.” This idea is a variation of the
notion of “background” mentioned above. For one, it is not a social theory, such as we might find in
sociology, i.e., an explanation of human motivation and behavior formulated in terms of laws. Second, it
is not equivalent to the idea of the “social construction of reality”; it is always based on and constrained
by an actual state of affairs and inflected through a cultural inheritance. Third, it mostly concerns “the
way ordinary people ‘imagine’ their surroundings, and this is often not expressed in theoretical terms, it is
carried in images, stories, legends, etc.”19 Fourth, its edges are intrinsically “ragged” and hazy; it cannot
be defined with analytical clarity and precision. Finally, it is a shared understanding that underwrites and
legitimizes common practices.20 As examples of social imaginaries, Taylor points to “the economy,” “the
public sphere” and “the sovereign people” as mainsprings of what he calls the “modern moral order” that,
he insists, must be seen as partly a social imaginary—an invention and construction—and not just as a
self-evident, factual, given state of affairs. With Taylor’s premises and methodology laid bare, we can
Taylor sets out to trace how the “bulwarks of belief” were gradually worn down, how a vision of
the world as enchanted, in which nature bore the mark of divine intention and agency, and in which God
was omnipresent in society and practically unavoidable—in which, moreover, there was no such
distinction between cosmos, nature, and society--how such an outlook came undone. 21 He posits that five
19
Ibid., 171-2.
20
Ibid., 172.
21
Ibid., 25.
10
major moves had to be made in order for this bubble to be burst. First, the cosmos had to be
disenchanted: the world must be drained of moral and spiritual forces, of demons, witches, sacred places,
etc., and reduced to brute facts, physical forces, mere matter and organisms. Second, society had to be re-
imagined as capable of being founded and existing independently of divine agency and oversight.
Taylor’s favorite example here is the doctrine of the King’s two bodies and the saying, “The King is dead.
Long live the King!” To modern ears, this either makes no logical sense, or has purely symbolic
meaning: let us keep the king alive in our collective memory and public rituals. For the pre-modern,
however, it is understood literally: the temporal, flesh and blood king is dead, but the eternal, spirit body
of the king will live on and inhabit another “vessel.” Third, the equilibrium or “hierarchical
complementarity” between “pre-Axial” forms of religion and “post-Axial” forms had to be disrupted.
Here, Taylor draws deeply on Karl Jaspers’ construct of the Axial Age, the period beginning around 500
B.C., in which numerous visionaries—e.g., Buddha, Confucius, and Socrates--proposed novel forms of
human flourishing beyond the natural, the this-worldly, the immanent, that broke with the morally
ambivalent “divine-in-nature” vision of magical and animistic worldviews and recognized a transcendent
and unambiguous good “beyond nature.” One of the constituent features of Latin Christendom, according
to Taylor, was its synthesis of magic and myth, a laity prone to a spirituality of enchantment—what we
today would call “superstition”—and a clergy bound by stricter codes of devotion and celibacy. This
equilibrium had to be punctuated in order for exclusive humanism to emerge on a collectively significant
scale. Fourth, time had to be homogenized and “flattened”; the social timeframe had to be modeled on a
“horizontal”, linear, unidirectional model unimpeded and uninterrupted by a vertical dimension of eternity
or cosmic cycles, by what Taylor terms “higher times.” What happens in time and history not only
matters—that is, in addition to and only on account of its grounding in, eternity—it is all that matters.
Fifth, the notion of the cosmos as a graduated “great chain of being,” as a hierarchy of meanings in which
all beings have their proper place, had to be collapsed into the “modern neutral universe.” 22
22
Ibid., 25.
11
I want to focus these vectors through the prism of Reform. The purpose of examining this facet
of Taylor’s story is twofold. First, the collapse of the bulwarks of belief, hastened by the spread of
Reform, is for him a necessary condition for the eventual rise of exclusive humanism. Second, this story
of Reform is where we find the basis for Taylor’s claim that the disenchantment of the world, the
disembedding of self from society and society cosmos, the rise of the disciplinary society, and the process
that he calls “excarnation”--the withdrawal of both spiritual and everyday life from the body and into the
mind--are, ironically, powered mainly by unresolved tensions within Latin Christendom. Though Taylor
gallantly resists the attempt to seize upon one factor as the Ur-cause of secularization—indeed, this is his
pet peeve about MST—I contend that Taylor’s reconstruction of Reform—the “rage for order” 23--is the
Since disenchantment is already a familiar trope in secularization theory, and since Taylor follows
others closely here,24 I will only refer to it as it relates to Taylor’s presentation of reform. As he sees it,
there are two long-term effects of disenchantment, one negative and one positive. The first is the crusade
to banish idolatry. All magic is branded black, all spirits are concentrated into the figure of the Devil, and
“Salem becomes possible.”25 The second effect pivots off the first. No longer assailed by invasive and
unpredictable spiritual forces, humans began to wield a new-found freedom to chart their own course and
determine their own destiny: “we can rationalize the world, expel the mystery from it (because it is all
now concentrated in the will of God). A great energy is released to re-order affairs in secular time.” 26
Disenchantment makes Reform not only possible, but plausible; recall that Taylor is trying to account for
how modern modes of belief and practice became available, acceptable, and sensible to society as a
whole.
23
Ibid., 63.
24
Taylor adverts to Gauchet’s work on the disenchantment of the world, noting how he too “gives a crucial
important to this long drive to Reform,” and adds that “I’m not sure if we don’t conceive it slightly differently,” but
does not explain his divergence in detail.
25
Ibid., 80.
26
Ibid., 80.
12
When Taylor discusses “Reform,” he is not merely referring to “The Reformation,” but to the
period roughly 1400-1650. Taylor clarifies his broad understanding of Reform thus:
Briefly summed up, Reform demanded that everyone be a real, 100 percent Christian.
Reform not only disenchants, but disciplines and re-orders life and society. Along with
civility, this makes for a notion of moral order which gives a new sense to Christianity,
and the demands of the faith. This collapses the distance of faith from Christendom. It
induces an anthropocentric shift, and hence a break-out from the monopoly of Christian
faith.27
By the “distance of faith,” Taylor is referring to the equilibrium or complementarity between spiritual
comportments of varying devotion, intensity, and stricture. Taylor recounts an old formula to illustrate
this form of life: “the clergy pray for all, the lords defend all, the peasants labor for all….” The key,
Taylor notes, is that these social functions—worshippers, warriors, and workers--are of “unequal
Taylor interjects an important point here about a common feature of pre-Axial societies: “rituals
of reversal,” the notion that “order binds a primitive chaos, which is both its enemy but also the source of
all energy, including that of order,” and that the order or structure of society must be periodically
suspended and overturned in a kind of cyclical purging. In other words, “all structure needs anti-
key is that such a ritual of reversal is carried out on a public scale: the personal, public, and cosmic are
The hierarchical structure entails that some are closer to God and are, in a sense, “more”
Christian. This stands in tension, however, with the “pull of ‘communitas’” associated with the Axial
27
Ibid., 774.
28
Ibid., 45.
29
Ibid., 47.
30
Ibid., 47.
13
aspect of Christianity, namely, its recognition of a good beyond this life, beyond normal human
flourishing and the social order: “the pull of communitas is potentially multi-valenced. It can not only
bring to the fore our community, but that of humankind.” 31 While the late medieval balance of pre-axial
and post-Axial spiritualities repeated the rituals of reversal and the cyclical play of structure/anti-
structure, it was nevertheless shot through with a universalist, egalitarian twist, a top-, or, depending on
how one sees it, bottom-heavy tilt that would enable it to tumble, first, into an “inclusive” humanism, in
which the sources of universal benevolence were located within human nature, with the latter created by
divine design and progressively carrying out the divine plan in history, and later, into a full-blown
“exclusive” humanism, in which the universalism is retained but the God-reference and super-human
What happens as a result of Reform is the almost total triumph of structure. Reform, Taylor says,
was originally meant to make the spirit of communitas—“which breaks out in moment of reversal or
transgression, and which gives legitimacy to the power of the weak”—a concrete social reality.
Communitas—the vision of the church as the body of Christ on earth—was supposed to replace the
parochial and exclusive social identities of pre-Axial societies, which were based on bloodlines, kinship,
tribal affiliations, etc.—with a universal and inclusive one; Taylor calls this the “Great Disembedding” of
self, society, and cosmos. The goal was to maintain the carnality of the relations, but expand their scope.
But the project misfired. The order that emerged from the spirit of reform was “not a network of agape,
but rather a disciplined society in which categorial relations have primacy, and therefore norms.” 32 That
is, the new social identity that takes hold is based on abstract categories drained of content and meaning;
more and more layers are padded on to the “buffered self,” 33 to the point that the original motivations for
31
Ibid., 50.
32
Ibid., 158.
33
The buffered self is Taylor’s construct of the modern subject that is self-reflective, uses instrumental reason to
order about itself and the world, and is disengaged from society and nature; this he opposes to the “porous self” of
the enchanted world, which is subject to the slings and arrows of magical forces, and cannot attain to full
“possession” of itself.
14
One of Taylor’s signature observations is his astonishment that the project of Reform got off the
ground at all. The creation of Weber’s “protestant work ethic,” suffused with an “inner-worldly
asceticism,” was to happen “very much through the active, reconstructive efforts of political authority.” 34
The goals were audacious: the eradication of violence and social anomie and the universal inculcation of
at least a modicum of the new “civility,” a project of social engineering simply unprecedented in human
history. Indeed, Taylor is convinced that the modern lack of astonishment at this fact is perhaps the
greatest testament of its near total success. But the basic shift in the social imaginary was the belief that,
as Raeff notes, “’human nature was essentially malleable, that it could be fashioned by will and external
circumstances.’”35 Locke’s epistemology of the tabula rasa is the perfect image of the new ethic; for
Taylor, its primary significance derives from its attraction as an ethical stance, not its plausibility as a
theory of knowledge.
The other key belief that made Reform possible, or that convinced people it was plausible—and
that would set the stage for exclusive humanism--was that “we don’t need to compromise, that we don’t
need complementarity, that the erecting of order doesn’t need to acknowledge limits in any opposing
principle of chaos.”36 The exhilaration of the new freedom and zeal for order, which was originally
intended to bring the Kingdom down to earth, would inadvertently power not just the decline of Hell, the
watering down of sin, the taming of violence—and its replacement by economic production as the highest
human activity--and so on, but eventually the exclusion of God. The irony is that the same forces that
drove the “sanctification of ordinary life” would produce the view that ordinary life was all there is.
Taylor yokes these various developments under the phrase “The Modern Moral Order” (MMO), which he
sums up thus:
the order of mutual benefit holds (1) between individuals…; the benefits (2) crucially
include life and the means of life, however securing these relates to the practice of virtue;
34
Ibid., 119.
35
Ibid., 121.
36
Ibid., 125.
15
it is meant (3) to secure freedom, and easily finds expressions in terms of rights…. (4)
these rights, this freedom, this mutual benefit is to be secured to all participants equally. 37
But how was this MMO shorn of its constitutive reference to God? How did the shift to
exclusive humanism occur? Recall Taylor’s first claim: the MMO was built on the back of Latin
Christendom, which we see in its “activist, interventionist stance, both towards nature and to human
society,” and in its appropriation of “universalism from its Christian sources.” 38 This latter is crucial: the
increasing and eventually all but universal recognition of “inner sources of benevolence,” whether “the
powers of disengaged reason” (neo-Stoicism), “a pure, universal will” (Kant), or “a sense of universal
sympathy” (Rousseau).39 Taylor urges that the paradox of these new views of human nature, fruits of an
“inward turn,” is that, on the one hand, “this inward turn is also evident in religious life; indeed, the whole
turn was largely driven by religious motives”40; on the other, these immanent sources of human goodness
are “the charter of modern unbelief.”41 So how did humanism become exclusive? How was the God
Because the very attempt to express what the Christian life means in terms of a code of
action in the saeculum opens the possibility of devising a code whose main aim is to
encompass the basic goods of life in the saeculum: life, prosperity, peace, mutual benefit.
In other words, it makes possible the anthropocentric shift. Once this happens then the
break-out is ready to occur. It just needs the step to holding that these ‘secular’ goods are
the point of the whole code. Pushed by annoyance at the ascetic demands of ultra-
37
Ibid., 171.
38
Ibid., 246.
39
Ibid., 150-1.
40
Ibid., 258.
41
Ibid., 257.
42
Ibid., 267.
16
Taylor’s second claim, recall, is that this step must be seen not as a giant, boot-strapping leap of mankind
out of myth and superstition, a heroic casting off of the yokes of belief, but as part of a “stairway” partly
composed of Christian materials. It is as though we climbed so high on the stairway that we can no
Taylor is at pains to convince us that this new order, the immanent frame, must be seen as an
invention, not a discovery; as a social imaginary, not just a social theory, or naturalistic reality. If not—in
other words, if we ignore the conditions of belief and our stadial consciousness—then we are apt to take it
as natural, given, obvious, self-evident, and will fail to appreciate just how much its erection was a “hard
slog.” It seems obvious and undeniable that the MMO is the “way things are” once the bogeymen of
the reverse is the case. Humans have lived for most of their history in modes of
surprising is that it was possible to win through to modern individualism; not just on the
level of theory, but also transforming and penetrating the social imaginary. Now that this
imagination has become linked with societies of unprecedented power in human history,
This is why he finds it simply inconceivable that exclusive humanism could have arisen on a non-
religious base. The modern attachment to the immanent frame is based on just such an inability—or
unwillingness—to divine the origins of its own historical, stadial consciousness. This modern mis-
identification of itself, its history, and of religion is of a piece with the MST and reductive construal of
secularity in terms of belief—in terms of the theoretical and the cognitive—rather than conditions of
43
Ibid., 169.
17
Taylor’s main points in expanding the sense of Reform and retelling the story of secularization
thus, are to show, first, that disenchantment, the dis-equilibrium of the hierarchical society/cosmos, the
disembedding of society, cosmos, and human good, and the project of Reform—in short, the invention of
the Modern Moral Order--are induced by Latin Christendom through its post-Axial sense of flourishing,
the pull of communitas, and the ardor to enact God’s plan in the world. And second, by casting the
Modern Moral Order as a social imaginary, he means to subvert the subtraction story of secularization
which holds that the truths we moderns hold to be self-evident are not, in fact, a-historical facts covered
for centuries by superstition and metaphysics and simply “discovered” by natural science and clear-eyed,
unbiased reason, but are in part social constructions based on—and unimaginable apart from--prior,
religious social imaginaries. Or, as Taylor puts it, “What happened here was not that one moral outlook
bowed to brute facts. Rather we might say that one moral outlook gave way to another.” 44 Viewed in this
broader context, first, religion is—or can be--a catalyst for the blossoming of reform and rationalization,
not always an impediment, as MST holds, and second, the latter holds moral stances that its naturalistic
With the broad beams of Taylor’s narrative in place, let us look more closely at his analysis and
critique of the MST, or “strong” secularization thesis. I want to address three questions here: First, what
does Taylor see as MST? Second, on what points does he agree with it? Third, what does he think is
senses of secularity: religion retreats from public spaces, and religious belief and practice dramatically
decline. Taylor sees the MST as a structure with three stories. The first floor can be seen as the fact—
which he does not dispute—of secularity 2. Almost everyone seems to agree that something like the
process we call secularity 2 has indeed happened; the differences have to do with how and why it
happened, and this corresponds to the “basement” of the MST, which comprises the various explanations
44
Ibid., 563.
18
proposed to account for the first floor, such as disenchantment, differentiation of social functions,
rationalization, and so forth. This is usually understood as a linear and all but inevitable process. The
third, upper floor consists of the state of belief and unbelief today; in other words, Taylor’s third sense of
secularity, the conditions of belief. In his view, the MST’s view of this upper floor is constrained by two
assumptions: the “disappearance thesis” and the “epiphenomenal thesis.” (433) The first holds that “the
independent motivation to religious belief and action (if, indeed, it hasn’t always been epiphenomenal)
tends to disappear in conditions of modernity.”45 The second maintains that “in conditions of modernity
(if not always), religious belief and action can only be epiphenomenal, that is, functional to some distinct
goals or purposes.”46
Taylor agrees with MST on the fact of secularity 2 (the ground floor). He allows that MST “is
right to this extent, that most of the changes [it identifies] (e.g., urbanization, industrialization, migration,
the fracturing of earlier communities) had a negative effect on the previously existing religious forms.
They often made some of their earlier practices impossible, while others lost their meaning or their
force.”47 Taylor concedes that these factors—the “basement--all played an important role in bringing
decline of one unchanging thing, over centuries, under the steady operation of a single set of causes.” 48
This is precisely why Taylor spends the first third of his book painstakingly retelling the history of pre-
Reformation Latin Christendom, namely, to show how complex and variegated it actually was.
Second, his third central claim about secularity leads him to reject the disappearance thesis. He
thinks that our modern consciousness is stadial, in that it defines itself as having overcome belief, and that
to move to a condition in which religious questions and motivations disappeared completely would be to
trade a fractured identity for no identity at all. He also feels this thesis has been dealt a serious blow by
the cultural revolution of the ‘60s, which saw the rise of new forms of spirituality and innovations of
45
Ibid., 443.
46
Ibid., 443.
47
Ibid., 436.
48
Ibid., 436.
19
religious traditions; indeed, this period plays an important role in Taylor’s reconstruction of our recent
crucial part of the current conditions of belief. The bulk of Taylor’s account of the process of
secularization, which I sketched above, is concerned with tracing the roots, emergence, and dissemination
of exclusive humanism. But the latter really only forms the first of what he sees as a three-stage process.
The second two stages, the “Nova Effect” and the “Super-Nova” are really just different degrees of the
same trend, and bear more upon the conditions of belief today. The Nova Effect—or what Taylor calls the
“Age of Mobilization”--comprises “the multiple critiques leveled at orthodox religion, Deism, and the
new humanism, and their cross-polemics.” These, he says, “end up generating a number of new
positions, including modes of unbelief which have broken out of the humanism of freedom and mutual
benefit (e.g., Nietzsche and his followers)—and lots else besides.” 49 The Nova picks up speed in the 19th
century and is still in full swing. The third stage, The Super-Nova—which Taylor also dubs “The Age of
Authenticity”, is merely the spread of the Nova to Western popular culture, which accelerates after the
second world war, and is powered by the “ethic of authenticity” or “expressive individualism,” “in which
people are encouraged to find their own way, discover their own fulfillment, “do their own thing.” 50
While there is not room to sufficiently sketch Taylor’s portrait of the contemporary scene, his intention in
narrating these two latter stages in the process of secularization, roughly from the middle of the 19 th
century to the present, is to underwrite his third central claim, namely, that the secular age bears a
constitutive reference to God. His conviction is that our age is deeply “cross-pressured”: “The salient
feature of Western societies is not so much a decline of religious faith and practice, though there has been
lots of that, more in some societies than in others, but rather a mutual fragilization of different religious
positiosn, as well as the outlooks of both belief and unbelief.” 51 This is what he means when he says that
belief in God does not mean the same thing in 2000 as it did in 1500, and why he questions “whether
49
Ibid., 299.
50
Ibid., 299.
51
Ibid., 595.
20
there could be unbelief without any sense of some religious view which is being negated.” 52 The MST
tends to answer this question in the affirmative, but Taylor thinks that such a response is predicated on a
Another of Taylor’s other main misgivings with MST—as well as modern theories of religion of,
e.g., Nietzsche, Weber, and Gauchet-- is its generalized view of religion. He believes this elides a tension
fundamental to our modern self-understanding. As noted above, MST tends to focus on belief, and
frames religion as mainly about belief in supernatural entities. But Taylor wants to both broaden and
specify the sense of religion, all while avoiding a universally applicable definition: “I want to focus not
only on beliefs and actions ‘predicated on the existence of supernatural entities,’ but also on the
understood as human flourishing….”53 He thinks that as far as secularization theory goes, we fudge the
facts when we talk about “religion in general,” rather than the specificity of belief as Christian, since the
ethical forms handed down to us by the latter have such a hand in shaping the very modern posture that
tries to analyze it! As he puts it, “In the Christian case, this means our participating in the love (agape) of
God for human beings, which is by definition a love which goes way beyond any possible mutuality, a
his lament at the over-reach of Reform—the “corruption of Christianity”—2) his conviction about
modernity’s self-misunderstanding; and 3) his claim that it is the ethical attraction of “debunking,” not the
theoretical plausibility or historical adequacy of the modern alternatives, that fuels the immanent frame
I have reservations about the idea that there is a demand for meaning as such, as it were,
any meaning, against something more specific. This…is rather endemic to our modern
humanist consciousness of religion and gives a particular (and I think dubious) twist to
52
Ibid., 269.
53
Ibid., 430.
54
Ibid., 430.
21
the hunger for religion in human beings. Nietzsche is followed in this, among others, by
Taylor also links this to what he sees as Weber’s and Gauchet’s occasional conflation of enchantment and
religion56; this is not consistent with their recognition, elsewhere, that “both Judaism and Christianity
have themselves at different times fostered various kinds of disenchantment.” 57 Taylor seems to think
that this inconsistency may derive from the ethical reaction in the face of the “loss of meaning,” the
defiant attitude of digging in one’s heels and facing the void pervasive in modernity. He dubs Weber “one
of the most influential proponents” of the view that we must “accept that this sense of loss is inevitable; it
is the price we pay for modernity and rationality, but we must courageously accept the bargain….” 58 The
debunker believes this because he is convinced that his position does not run ahead of reasons, that it is
yielding to his intellectual conscience. But Taylor holds that “both open and closed stances [on the
immanent frame] involve a step beyond available reasons into the realm of anticipatory confidence.” 59
His point is that there is belief involved here, aspiration to meet a high water mark, embody a set of
virtues—courage, intellectual honesty, living in touch with reality, etc.—not a mere recognition of and
capitulation to “the facts.” Here, Taylor turns the tables on the debunkers, who accuse all believers of
intellectual dishonesty--the “sacrifice of the intellect,” in Weber’s words-- and charges that the “closed
spin” “implies that one’s thinking is clouded or cramped by a powerful picture which prevents one seeing
important aspects of reality. I want to argue that those who think the closed reading of immanence is
‘natural’ and obvious are suffering from this kind of disability.” 60 The disabling prejudice is the watered-
down, hollowed out view of religion as an expression of man’s natural hunger for meaning as such. 61
55
Ibid., 318.
56
Ibid., 553: “Enchantment, [i.e., “the world of spirits and meaningful causal forces, of wood sprites and relics”], is
essential to some forms of religion; but other forms…have been built on its partial or total denial. We cannot just
equate the two.” He adds that “Even Weber seems to have fallen into this at times.”
57
Ibid., 426.
58
Ibid., 307.
59
Ibid., 551.
60
Ibid., 551.
61
Ibid., 717-18: “[Many modern] have seen the essence of religion in the answers it offers to the question of
meaning. I believe, as I argue above, that these theories are in an important way off the track. They imply that the
main point of religion is solving the human need for meaning. In taking this stance, they absolutize the modern
predicament….” This is one of the most important passages in the book.
22
This premise underwrites the disappearance and epiphenomenal theses, and suppresses the extant
tension between the two rival view of the human good. It is this essential tension between rival versions
of human flourishing—between the vertical, transformative perspective and the horizontal, MMO of
mutual benefit—that produces the preponderance of positions crowding the secular age, i.e., the current
conditions of belief. The MST is a subtraction story in this sense: by assuming that religion plays a
purely functional role, and ignoring the content of the specific religion that forms the backbone of the
story of secularization, it underestimates the persistence and power of the transformative perspective in
our own day. Contrary to MST, Taylor holds that “religious longing, the longing and response to a more-
modernity.”62
A Secular Age is not a Christian apologetic. Taylor is not making the case for faith per se.
Instead, he is using a careful re-reading of the late medieval and modern history of Christianity in order to
show the power that its (perhaps essential) tension between “this-worldly” and “other-worldly” ethical
postmoderns, the religious, the secular, and the “spiritual but not religious.” The constitutive God-
reference that “haunts” the secular age should to seen not as an empty vestige, but a sign that religion—
religion in Taylor’s strong sense, adherence to the transformation perspective (ethically), and openness to
a transcendent reality (ontological)—is not just here to stay, but destined to evolve; indeed, Taylor
assiduously avoids positing some “religious faculty” of the soul, some universal constant in human nature
that yearns for God but has been tamped down by modernity; as we saw, this is in fact the form of the
subtraction story he sets out to criticize. He appears committed to the hermeneutical principle that we
cannot speak of a bare human nature existing “in itself” apart from a network of historical prejudices and
social imaginaries. Taylor is equally suspicious of some “golden age” of religion marked by universal
62
Ibid., 531.
23
devotion. Taylor’s own spin on the “return of the religious” and “re-enchantment of the world” is an
argument for “re-incarnation,” which involves a more integral approach to religion that re-instates the
transformative perspective and recovers a richer relationship to tradition and a renewal of the constitutive
more accurate mirror to our present, bring the regnant narrative—the immanent frame—to light, and
show that the way we spin it—whether closed or open—is dictated not by the frame itself, but by the
sundry sources of our secular selves. The gates of the immanent frame are locked from the inside.
24