Sie sind auf Seite 1von 8

Politics (1999) 19(2) pp.

109±115

The Strategic-Relational
View of the State
Duncan Kelly

This paper seeks to highlight the main ele- Definitions ± What is the
ments of the `strategic-relational' approach to
(Marxist) state theory, developed particularly
State?
by Bob Jessop. The legacy of Nicos Poulantzas
Jessop locates his work within a broad Marx-
in particular is singled out for its importance
ist tradition. To what extent he accepts the
in laying the foundations for such an
normative implications of such a position is
approach. This is followed by a discussion of
discussed more below, but the terminology
Jessop and his development of many ideas
used, and the method of analysis provided,
bequeathed by Poulantzas, culminating in
evidently owes much to Marx (Jessop, 1990,
various moves toward a strategic-relational
pp. 196±8€.). However, Marxist theorists have
analysis. These moves are then critically
never agreed on a common de®nition or
assessed, with some wider thoughts on the
theory of the capitalist state. Famously, many
approach o€ered in conclusion
positions can be located on one or other side
of the `instrumentalist-structuralist' divide; or,
to use Jessop's terms, class or capital theore-
Introduction tic approaches. Generalising somewhat, the
idea that the state either acts in the (long-
Few areas in the study of politics have proved
term) interests of the ruling class, or in the
so elusive as that of `the state'. Within the
interests of capital, still provides the basis for
Marxist tradition especially, multiple theore-
much Marxist state theory, and one can see
tical positions have been outlined, all legiti-
this in Jessop's reluctance to provide a `®xed'
mately claiming some authority from Marx or
de®nition of the state. He argues that once a
Engels themselves (cf., Jessop, 1990, pp. 24±
de®nition is provided, it must immediately be
48; Hay, 1998). In developing and criticising
quali®ed to take account of the historical and
these approaches Bob Jessop has, over the
contingent circumstances of a state's exis-
past twenty years, attempted to rid state
tence and power. His tentative `cluster' de®ni-
theory of residual `essentialist' explanation,
tion suggests that:
o€ering instead what has been termed a `stra-
tegic-relational' analysis. This represents per-
haps the most theoretically sophisticated the core of the state apparatus comprises a
discussion of the state currently available, and distinct ensemble of institutions and orga-
it is the purpose of this short paper to pro- nisations whose socially accepted function
vide a critical introduction to the central ele- is to de®ne and enforce collectively binding
ments of such an approach. decisions on the members of a society in

Duncan Kelly, University of Sheeld.

# Political Studies Association 1999. Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK
and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. 109
Strategic-Relational View . Kelly Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115

the name of their general will (Jessop, the last analysis on political class domination'
1990, p. 341). (Poulantzas, 1973, p. 54). Taking this as a
general starting point, he emphasised that a
Immediately following this, Jessop suggests theory of the capitalist state was possible if
that such a near ideal-type model must be one can accept such an a priori assumption.
constantly re-de®ned to take account of the As his position developed, increasingly in¯u-
complexities of actual states. Thus, the means enced by the work of Foucault on the micro-
by which legitimacy is assured are historically physics of power, Poulantzas o€ered his most
speci®c; there is no strict separation between explicit theorisation of the state as a `social
state and society; coercion is not the only relation' in what was his ®nal major work,
sanction available to the state, and so on State, Power, Socialism (1978). Distinguishing
(Jessop, 1990, p. 342). Therefore, states are between any unity the state may have qua
never ®xed; rather, contradictions and move- institutional ensemble, and its more general
ment are their very essence (cf., Abrams, role as a factor of cohesion, Poulantzas
1988; Ho€mann, 1988; 1995). The resultant argued that state power is both relational and
assumption, that there cannot in fact be a selective. It is relational as state structures and
theory of the state, emerges as a direct result policies, for example, are historically con-
of Jessop's starting point, which is his tingent episodes in a dynamic process of evo-
engagement with Nicos Poulantzas' `elliptical lution. It is selective in terms of favouring the
proposition' that the state is a `social relation'. dominant class/class fraction of the particular
Background Gramsci and Poulantzas moment. Thus, class struggle traverses the
Within the Marxist tradition, Poulantzas' very `institutional materiality' of the state; its
work easily constitutes Jessop's major engage- mediation develops into policy, or `line[s] of
ment, alongside that of Gramsci (Jessop, force'. The state, therefore, becomes a strate-
1990, p. x). Inevitably, no claim to complete- gic terrain; it is `the material condensation of
ness can be made of the following thematic a relationship of forces, [and] we must grasp
discussion, but some relevant elements can it as a strategic ®eld and process of intersect-
be highlighted. The crucial point that both ing power networks' (Poulantzas, 1978, p.
highlight is the interdependence of state and 136€.; cf., Jessop, 1985, pp. 115±131; 1990,
society. For Gramsci, the state, ultimately, is pp. 220±248). Although there are many nuan-
`political society + civil society', or `hege- ces in Poulantzas' re¯ections, these are the
mony armoured by coercion' (cf., Gramsci, main insights that Jessop goes on to develop.
1977, pp. 243±246, 261±3€.; Anderson, 1977,
pp. 12±44). The concept of hegemony is uti-
lised to explain the continued reproduction Jessop's critique
of capitalist social relations in terms of the
moral, political, cultural and ideological lea- Unhappy with Poulantzas' ultimate equation
dership of the ruling class, maintained speci®- of class power and state power, Jessop has
cally in terms of a national-popular project attempted to reconcile what he sees as the
(Gramsci, 1971). This implies that the state problems of Poulantzas' account in the fol-
cannot be seen simply as an epiphenomenon lowing ways.
of an ultimately determining economic base;
rather, there is an autonomy of the political. (i) Critics quickly pointed out that Pou-
Adapting Gramsci's focus on hegemony, lantzas failed to specify any mechanisms
Poulantzas argued in his early work Political by which the state would, in the end, act
Power and Social Classes (1973) that the in the interests of the dominant class or
main role of the state was `the maintenance class fraction (Giddens, 1981). Jessop
of the unity of the social formation based in (1985, pp. 135±6) goes further, arguing

110 # Political Studies Association 1999


Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115 Strategic-Relational View . Kelly

that he failed to resolve a central para- accumulation in a given situation. It is


dox in his discussion of state power. At non-capitalist to the extent that these
the macro level, state power bene®ts the conditions are not realised. This view
dominant power bloc. At the micro level, radically displaces our theoretical
however, all sorts of struggles and strate- focus from the search for guarantees
gies, besides class interests, in¯uence that the state apparatus and its func-
state policies in various ways. tions are necessarily capitalist in all
Therefore, Jessop suggests that we can aspects to a concern with the many
make no macro, or general claim on the and varied contingent e€ects of state
nature of state power but he agrees that power on accumulation in speci®c
the state is a social relation. Accepting conjunctures (Jessop, 1990, p. 354).
that many other political strategies,
besides economic or class interests, One can think of further applications;
determine state policy, he makes the state power favours the ruling class to
more ¯exible pronouncement that the the extent that it maintains the condi-
state will be more responsive to parti- tions necessary for their continued dom-
cular strategies over others. What this inance, and so on. By abandoning the
fairly obvious point means, essentially, is `search for guarantees', theory should
that the theoretical or political primacy become more ¯exible and historically
of either class or capital in any account realistic.
is bypassed (Jessop, 1990, pp. 85±94€.). (iii) Any unity that the state may have, either
Nevertheless, the state remains both institutionally or in terms of the exercise
structurally and strategically selective; it of power, depends upon the relationship
has a `structurally mediated bias which in particular between what Jessop terms
means that particular forms of state pri- accumulation strategies, state forms and
vilege some strategies over others hegemonic projects (Jessop, 1990, pp.
(Jessop, cited in Hay, 1994, pp. 350±1). 196±220). This has been thoroughly
(ii) Given its anchoring in a dense network misunderstood by such scholars as
of social relations, does the state have a Hobson (1997, p. 242€.) who suggest
(relative) autonomy, and if so, how can that Jessop, in asserting that the state,
that be theorised? For Jessop, this ques- qua institutional ensemble, has no
tion is something of a chimera. He sug- power, denies any autonomy to the state
gests that no element in what we may, and suggests that it is a cipher for domi-
for the sake of simplicity, call the social nant economic interests. As should be
world, can count as in any way being clear, however, Jessop argues that on the
completely or even relatively determining one hand the state is a social relation,
in some a priori or given sense. This hence its power comes from the parti-
ascription of invalidity to any theoretical cular political structures and strategies
`prime-mover', so to speak, is the result that both shape, and which in turn are
of Jessop's critical engagement with shaped by the state. Correlatively, state
Marxist state theory. The exercise of power is not amenable to theorisation in
state power becomes the di€erentia spe- the manner that Hobson would wish;
ci®ca, which renders explicable state that is, the state is an, a priori, autono-
autonomy. Thus: mous actor (cf., Hobson, 1997; Mann,
1985). Rather, in terms of the capitalist
state power is capitalist to the extent type of state, policy is best understood
that it creates, maintains or restores as being moulded around particular
the conditions necessary for capital hegemonic projects, as expressed mainly

# Political Studies Association 1999 111


Strategic-Relational View . Kelly Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115

by dominant political parties, whose involve a `dual movement' between the


relationship to the dominant regime of abstract claim of, say, the state as social
accumulation is crucial. Therefore, the relation, and the complex empirical rea-
nature of the state form, its particular lity of the exercise of state power. There
structural and strategic selectivity, pro- are obviously close links to both Marx in
blematises its functions. Again, there are terms of `rising' from the abstract to the
no theoretical guarantees. Power and concrete, and also to Weber, in the con-
policy are executed through various, struction of quasi-ideal type models
contingent mechanisms that form part of which are then tested historically. How-
the dialectic of structure and strategy. ever, such a methodology means that
The dominant example utilised by there is no `best way' of developing
Jessop in discussing this approach is the theory. At the theoretical level, there is
case of the West-European `Keynesian indeterminacy; substantively, determi-
Welfare State[s]', whose origins in the nacy. Therefore, Jessop attempts to
post-war period centred around the `borrow' from other disciplines in order
development of mass welfare provision, to develop his approach.
underpinned by a new `Fordist' mode of
growth. The forms taken by particular
national states problematises their func- `External' influences
tionality for those processes that make
up the ideal type model, such as full (i) The `systems theory' of Niklas Luhmann
employment, state intervention and so o€ers one way of theorising the auton-
on; hence the vastly di€ering nature of omy of the political. For Luhmann, as
the national states subsumed under the the social system develops, ever increas-
general heading `Keynesian Welfare' type. ing amounts of specialisation and `func-
(iv) Such theoretical claims are premised on tional di€erentiation' occur (see
a particular methodology. Indeed, Jessop Luhmann, 1995). Thus, discrete sub-sys-
goes as far as to suggest that his work is, tems with their own areas of expertise
in part, a re¯ection on the methodology become increasingly important. He
of theory construction (Jessop, 1982, pp. adopts the biological metaphor of
213±220; 1990, pp. 10±12). The ideas autopoiesis to discuss the radical auton-
underpinning this `method of articula- omy of such systems. For Luhmann, sub-
tion' are captured by the couplet `con- systems are principally concerned with
tingent-necessity'. Such a counter maintaining conditions favourable to
intuitive description rests upon a parti- their continued reproduction. They will,
cular development of critical realist phi- therefore, be unwilling to co-operate
losophy of social science. At the level of with other sub-systems unless in their
ontology, all events are caused in some own interest. Nevertheless, they have
way; they are `necessary'. Accepting this, certain in¯uence upon other, dependent
Jessop's resultant epistemological claim sub-systems. Such is the `sel®sh' nature
is that the causal mechanisms necessary of autopoietic systems.
for an `event' to occur, come together in Jessop doesn't accept that such a total
a contingent, that is non-necessary way. degree of functional di€erentiation is a
Hence, the justi®cation for Jessop's theo- true representation of reality, but argues
retical moves away from Poulantzas in that theoretically, Luhmann's ideas o€er
particular, ®nd their ultimate basis in a novel general theory of systemic auton-
methodological considerations. An ade- omy (see Jessop, 1990, pp. 307±338). In
quate state theory would, for Jessop, fact, Luhmann himself argues that in

112 # Political Studies Association 1999


Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115 Strategic-Relational View . Kelly

developed societies, or systems, the mirrors his discussion of the partial unity
economy is the sub-system that has of the state at any time, constituted by
achieved the greatest degree of func- the con¯uence of various political strate-
tional di€erentiation, and whose impact gies and, again, the way that form pro-
is felt on the most other sub-systems. blematises function.
The problem then becomes one of
empirically proving both the pre-
ponderance of the economy, and also of Criticisms
assessing the autonomy of the state in
relation to it. These questions are dealt (i) Methodologically, to what extent is it
with in Jessop's engagement with regula- possible to theorise contingency as
tion theory. Jessop supposes? One particularly imma-
(ii) Examining regulation theory's focus on nent problem seems to be; how does
the importance of various non-economic empirical research actually alter theore-
elements that maintain conditions favour- tical concepts, as advocated in the dual
able to the continued reproduction of an movement between abstract and con-
inherently crisis prone capitalist econ- crete? It is not at all clear that the macro
omy, Jessop's state theory is easily inser- claims made by Jessop concerning state
ted (see e.g., Jessop, 1997b). In power, for example, can be veri®ed and
discussing the ways in which particular developed given that theoretical determi-
regimes of accumulation, for example, nants such as class are ruled out. When
require various norms, institutional med- undertaking substantive work, Jessop
iation etc. for their continuation, the state proceeds in more Weberian fashion, set-
obviously plays a central role. The main ting out at the beginning that the state
point for Jessop is that the state should has de®nite functions the maintenance of
be seen as an `object' of regulation in its conditions favourable to capital accumu-
own right, as are particular `modes of lation and the reproduction of labour
growth', for example. The state plays a power for instance, and subsequently
central role in methods of capitalist `soci- examining the changing `forms and func-
etalization'; that is, `the complex social tions' of the state in relation to these
processes in and through which speci®c ideal-typical initial suggestions (cf.,
institutional orders and their broader Jessop, 1994, pp. 102±3; 1997a). The
social preconditions are secured' (Jessop, contradiction between these proposi-
1990, pp. 5, 9). Again, there are no theo- tions, and the theory already discussed,
retical guarantees; instead, a focus on namely that there cannot be a theory of
particular `state e€ects'. the state, should be clear.
(iii) A third in¯uence has been Jessop's (ii) Theoretically, the seemingly ¯exible ana-
engagement with discourse theory, parti- lysis advocated concerning state power
cularly as applied in the study of Ernesto hides a rather more rigid basis. By
Laclau and Chantal Mou€e, Hegemony arguing that state power is capitalist to
and Socialist Strategy (1985). Utilising the extent that it maintains the condi-
the idea of `the social' as an open-ended tions favourable to capital accumulation,
arena, they discuss the methods through one must implicitly sanction a strict
which various hegemonic, or political separation of the political and economic
discourses are articulated to provide par- spheres. If the state is accepted as being
ticular points of reference in terms of a central arena in terms of shaping the
strategy. It is the always relative nature of nature of accumulation at a given time,
the discourse that Jessop focuses on; it then for state power to be non-capitalist

# Political Studies Association 1999 113


Strategic-Relational View . Kelly Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115

in the sense Jessop describes, it would (iv) The focus on `societalization' as the
surely have to sanction explicitly anti- mechanisms by which particular institu-
capitalist policies. That is, it would tional orders become routinised is also
represent a fundamental challenge to the problematic. Where is the role of
political order. Such an unlikely situation agency? For Jessop, agents have no `free
arises from what we might term Jessop's will'; actions are linked to structural
`theoretically anti-theoretical' approach. positions and capabilities (1990, p.
The interdependence between state and 266€.). However, when structures and
society, crucial given the state's anchor- systems are overturned, there is an
ing as a social relation, remains inade- obvious (historical) role for agency. To
quately mediated. Given the obvious tie action so closely to structural posi-
existence of what is commonly called tion limits the nature of individual
capitalist society, for state policies to be choice, but equally fails to discuss what
anti-capitalist, whilst still maintaining a is perhaps the dominant structural lim-
capitalist system, suggests a very limited itation placed upon agents, namely capi-
view of capitalism as a strictly economic talist social relations. Again, this can be
system. The implication, then, is that traced to methodological considerations.
either the state can be fully dissociated Theoretical indeterminacy and empirical
from the economy, or that it is fully determinacy results in diculty applying
functional for capital. Ironically, Jessop the theory.
appears to have inverted his own perti-
nent criticisms of Poulantzas back on to
himself. In abstract theory, no macro Conclusions
level claim on the state's capitalist or
otherwise `nature' can be made, yet in Nonetheless, Jessop's state theory has illumi-
more substantive discussion de®nite the- nated some of the major problems that arise
oretical propositions must be put for- in an attempt to move beyond one-sided the-
ward. This results in a confusion. oretical positions. His development is linked
(iii) Politically, Jessop acknowledges his debt to the perspicacious challenges to Marxist
to the Marxist tradition, and indeed still state theory that have come from, in parti-
utilises a Marxist critique of political cular, neo-Weberian and feminist camps (cf.,
economy as a starting point for his ana- Mann, 1993; Parkin, 1979; Allen, 1990).
lysis. The emancipatory political ideals of Equally however, and probably not least due
this tradition, however, are conspicuous to the style of presentation, his work has
by their absence in Jessop's work. This attracted numerous criticisms which seem to
is not to expect a detailed strategic blue- miss the mark. To suggest, as does Marsh
print, rather to highlight the lack of a (1994) for example, that Jessop's state theory
normative basis to work that sets itself cannot explain why the state will normally
up as being broadly Marxist. This is a intervene in times of economic crises is to
result of methodological considerations confuse levels of analysis. What seems more
obviously; borrowing from other tradi- problematic, it has been argued here, is in
tions to highlight the autonomy of the fact more immanent.
state, for example. But also at a more What is noticeable, however, is that there
`instinctual' level, Jessop's work seems to has been a convergence in state theory, lar-
lack any feeling that he is concerned gely unacknowledged, between writers like
with the possibility of political, or sys- Jessop and Mann, as both move towards an
temic transformation. Rather, these ideas open-ended theoretical approach, designed to
more easily theorise order. take account of the contingent processes of

114 # Political Studies Association 1999


Politics (1999) 19(2) pp. 109±115 Strategic-Relational View . Kelly

social and political change (see Mann, 1993, Hay, C. (1998), `Marxism and the State: Flogging a
pp. 44±92). This has certainly opened up Dead Horse?', in A. Gamble et al (eds.), Marx-
ism and Social Science Basingstoke: Macmillan,
state theory from traditionally more reduc- forthcoming.
tionist positions; however, the manner in Hobson, J. (1997), The Wealth of States, Cam-
which substantive work is carried out by bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jessop, outlining de®nite propositions about Ho€man, J. (1988), State, Power and Democracy,
the role of the state, contrasts markedly with Brighton: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Ho€man, J. (1995), Beyond the State, Oxford:
the more abstract discussion of state theory Polity.
he provides. This does justify his concern to Jessop, B. (1982), The Capitalist State: Marxist The-
provide a set of guidelines, or heuristics, ories and Methods, Oxford: Martin Robertson.
necessary for generating a theoretically Jessop, B. (1985), Nicos Poluantzas: Marxist
informed account of the state. Yet, it is not Theory and Political Strategy, Basingstoke: Mac-
millan.
certain that the tensions which remain either Jessop, B. (1990),State Theory : Putting the Capi-
have been, or indeed can be adequately talist State in its Place: Polity.
resolved. The attempt, though, should leave Jessop, B. (1994), `Changing Forms and Functions
few indi€erent to the problems involved. of the State in an Era of Globalization and
Regionalization', in R. Delorme and K. Dop¯er
(eds.), The Political Economy of Diversity, Alder-
shot: Edward Elgar.
Notes Jessop, B. (1997a), `Capitalism and its futures:
remarks on regulation, government and govern-
1 Thanks to Andrew Gamble, Colin Hay, Mike ance', Review of International Political Econ-
Kenny and two anonymous referees for their omy, 4(3), pp. 561±581.
comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Jessop, B. (1997b), `Twenty Years of the (Parisian)
Regulation Approach: The Paradox of Success
and Failure at Home and Abroad', New Political
Economy, 3(2), pp. 503±526.
References Laclau, E. and Mou€e, C. (1985), Hegemony and
Socialist Strategy, London: Verso.
Abrams, P. (1988), `Notes on the Diculty of Luhmann, N. (1995), Social Systems, Cambridge:
Studying the State', Journal of Historical Sociol- Cambridge University Press.
ogy, 1(1), pp. 58±89. Mann, M. (1985), `The Autonomous Power of the
Allen, J. (1990), `Does Feminism Need a Theory of State: its Origins and Mechanisms', in J. Hall
the State?', in S. Watson (ed.), Playing the State, (ed.), States in History, Oxford: Blackwell.
London: Verso. Mann, M. (1993), The Sources of Social Power ±
Anderson, P. (1977), `The Antinomies of Antonio The Rise of Lasses and Nation States 1760±
Gramsci', New Left Review, pp. 5±81. 1914, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Giddens, A. (1981), A Contemporary Critique of Marsh, D. (1994), `Explaining Thatcherism: Beyond
Historical Materialism, Basingstoke: Macmillan. Uni-Dimensional Explanation', in P. Dunleavy
Gramsci, A. (1971), Selections From the Prison and J. Stanyer (eds.), Contemporary Political
Notebooks, London: Lawrence and Wishart. Studies 1994 Political Studies Association.
Hay, C. (1994), `Werner in Wunderland, or notes Parkin, F. (1979), Marxism and Class Theory: A
on a marxism beyond pessimism and false opti- Bourgeois Critique, London: Tavistock.
mism', in F. SebaõÈ , and C. Vercellone, (eds.), Poulantzas, N. (1973), Political Power and Social
Ecole de la Regulation et Critique de la Raison Classes, London: NLB.
Economique, Special Issue of Futur Anterieur. Poulantzas, N. (1978), State, Power, Socialism,
Paris: Editions L'Harmattan, pp. 331±363. London: Verso.

# Political Studies Association 1999 115


Copyright of Politics is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to
multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users
may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen