Sie sind auf Seite 1von 5

American Economic Association

The Case against Intellectual Property


Author(s): Michele Boldrin and David Levine
Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 92, No. 2, Papers and Proceedings of the One
Hundred Fourteenth Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association (May, 2002), pp.
209-212
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3083403 .
Accessed: 01/08/2013 19:56

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
American Economic Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 152.14.136.96 on Thu, 1 Aug 2013 19:56:17 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
The Case Against IntellectualProperty

By MICHELEBOLDRINAND DAVID LEVINE*

According to a common argument,the pres- worthy commercial idea..."'' abound in the


ence of strong intellectualpropertyrights spurs business, legal, and economic press. In arguing
innovation leading to higher economic growth the case against "intellectual monopoly" we
and increasing benefits for all. The argument will examine this argumentwith care.
seems coherent. No economic agent exercises
productive effort without the certainty of con- I. Downstream Licensing
trollingits fruits.Whatis truefor physical effort
must be true for the intellectual one: if strong Intellectual property has two components.
propertyrights provide good incentives for the One is the rightto own and sell ideas. The other
productionof potatoes, they must also provide is the rightto controlthe use of those ideas after
good incentives for the productionof ideas. sale. The first,sometimes called the rightof first
Why then do we argue a "case against intel- sale, we view as essential. The second, which
lectual property?"Are we arguing that, while we referto as downstreamlicensing, we view as
stealing potatoes is bad, stealing ideas is good? economically dangerous. All producers would
We are not. Economic efficiency and common impose downstream-licensing agreementsif they
sense argue that ideas should be protected and could: producersprefer not to compete against
available for sale, just like any other commod- their customers. But the absence of competi-
ity. But "intellectual property" has come to tion leads to monopoly. That the downstream-
mean not only the right to own and sell ideas, licensing provisions of patent, copyright, and
but also the right to regulate their use. This otherprivatecontractslead to monopoly is well
creates a socially inefficient monopoly, and understood. Among economists, the argument
what is commonly called intellectual property has been that it is only throughmonopoly that it
might be better called "intellectualmonopoly." is possible to rewardinventive activity. There is
When you buy a potato you can eat it, throw it a seemingly compelling logic: the cost of inno-
away, plant it, or make it into a sculpture.Cur- vation is a fixed cost, and ideas are distributedat
rent law allows producersof CDs and books to zero, or at least constant, marginalcost. Since
take this freedom away from you. When you perfect competitionprices at marginalcost, the
buy a potato you can use the "idea"of a potato fixed cost cannot be recouped.Consequently,if
embodied in it to make better potatoes or to producersof intellectual propertyare forced to
invent french fries. Currentlaw allows produc- compete with their customers, they will not be
ers of computer software or medical drugs to able to recoup the cost of creation.This point is
take this freedom away from you. It is against forcefully made, for example, in Paul Romer
this distortedextension of intellectual property (1990).
rights that we argue. In other work (Boldrin and Levine, 2001) we
It is a long jump from the assertion that have pointed out that creationis not a fixed, but
inventorsdeserve the fruitsof theirefforts to the a sunk, cost. Since only ideas embodied in peo-
conclusion that current patent and copyright ple or productsmatter,the cost of creationis the
protection are the best way of providing such cost of producing the first unit. Such a "sunk
reward.Statementssuch as "A patentis the way cost" is very ordinaryin economics and poses
of rewarding somebody for coming up with a no particular threat to perfect competition.
As far as we know there is no organizedmove-
ment to provide producersof potatoes, or any
* Departmentof Economics, University of Minnesota,
other commodity involving sunk costs, with a
Minneapolis, MN 55455, and Departmentof Economics,
University of California, Los Angeles, CA 90024. Our
thanks to the NSF and the University of Minnesota Grants
in Aid programfor financial support. 1 The Economist, 23 June 2001, p. 42; italics added.
209

This content downloaded from 152.14.136.96 on Thu, 1 Aug 2013 19:56:17 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
210 AEA PAPERSAND PROCEEDINGS MAY2002

governmentmonopoly. What is different about ital audiotaperecordersthat do not work very


creative activity is the indivisibility involved in well do not pose much of an economic threat.
producingthe firstunit:two half-bakedideas do However, the same computersthat play music,
not equal one fully baked idea. also hold financial records, creative work,
The theory of competition with indivisibili- e-mail records,and much of economic value. A
ties is not yet fully worked out. In Boldrin and malfunctioningcopy-protectionsystem that de-
Levine (2001) we show that competition often stroys files, causes computersto crash,or causes
yields the first best: that diminishing costs of otherforms of collateraldamagecan easily have
replication can increase, rather than decrease, an economic cost far exceeding the value of all
the incentive for creative activity; and that recordedmusic.
downstream licensing may hurt, rather than The inability to reverse-engineer software
help, innovation. We illustrate these ideas be- that enforces copy protection has other collat-
low by means of a simple example. eral costs. If copy-protection software is se-
Nevertheless, there is an expectation, which cretly phoning home to provide its issuers with
we share, that there are cases where ordinary private information about users, this flagrant
competitive rents will be insufficientrewardto violation of privacy is difficult or even illegal to
induce socially desirablecreativeactivity. In the prevent.Thereis also an importantcommitment
rest of this essay, we also argue that the mo- problem with copy-protectedideas: if the pro-
nopoly power in downstream licensing has ducer goes out of business, the copy-protected
costs that vastly exceed the usual "welfare tri- products may lose their value. Unfortunately
angle," and that creative competitive mecha- there does not seem to be a crediblemechanism
nisms can providethe rightrewardfor inventive by which producerscan commit to puttingtheir
activity, even where monopoly fails. software into the public domain if they go
bankrupt.
II. CollateralCosts Suppressionof ideas throughthe legal system
creates other collateral problems through the
Like all property, intellectual property is impact on researchand development.Although
expensive to protect. However, downstream- laws are designed in an effort to minimize this
licensing agreements are especially costly to impact, it is a fact that research and develop-
enforce because they requireeitherthe producer ment under the watchful eye of a regulatory
or the governmentto tightly supervisethe use of agent is going to be greatly inhibited. Similar
ideas. Of course, there are the direct costs of conflicting goals arise in the protection of the
writing laws, catching lawbreakers,and bring- freedom of speech and of political discourse.
ing legal action against them. However, there The same technology used to track"musicfree-
are many other forms of "collateraldamage"to loaders" can be used to track individuals who
economic welfare. Here we focus on ideas that express unpopularopinions, for example.
can be embodied in digital form, such as com- On the patent front, more time and energy
puter programs,music, books, and movies. To seems to be spent on nuisance and defensive
superviseusage of these productsrequirescopy- patenting of the obvious than on innovation.
protection technology. Copy protection man- Individualsexploit the ignorance of patent ex-
dated by law is especially pernicious because aminers by patenting ideas already in wide-
the potential economic damage (think of abol- spreaduse in hopes of collecting licensing fees
ishing all computersbecause they can be used to from a few large companies;large corporations
piratemusic) bears no relationshipto the under- patent and cross-license everythingimaginable,
lying value that is being protected. both to protect themselves against greenmail
Unless mandated by law, few people will and to suppress entry into their industry. That
choose to install software that enforces copy cross-licensing and "protection of intellectual
protection instead of software that does not. property"can be instrumentalin promotingcol-
This was recognized,for example, in the case of lusion within an industryseems transparent.On
digital audiotape,where copy protectionwas le- the empiricalside, JoshuaS. Gans et al. (2000 p.
gally mandated. Unfortunately,copy-protection 29) provide evidence from a 1999 survey of
technology often does not work very well. Dig- high-tech start-upsthat "stronger[intellectual]

This content downloaded from 152.14.136.96 on Thu, 1 Aug 2013 19:56:17 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
VOL 92 NO. 2 PROPERTY:DO WENEED IT?
INTELLECTUAL 211

property protection is associated with higher, We are interested in two questions. Is the
ratherthan lower levels of cooperationbetween price of the very first copy enough to compen-
incumbentsand start-upinnovatorentrant." sate the producer for its sunk cost? Does the
Ultimately, the case against monopoly rests price of the firstcopy increase or decreasewhen
less upon the welfare triangle from monopoly new technologies increase ,B?
pricing than upon the rent-seekingactivity used According to standardcompetitive theory the
to get and keep a monopoly. In the brief exam- sale price of an MP3 is just the presentvalue of
ple of Section IV we show how, with govern- the rental rates. A simple calculation2 shows
ment enforced monopoly, the incentives for that
rent-seeking lead to large welfare costs in the
productionof ideas. (1 + a/3
t - 61/t3(iI)/
)

III. Competition Without Po= -1


Downstream Licensing

We provide an example to illustrate the For finite values of po,Po is a positive and finite
idea in Boldrin and Levine (2001) that inno- number.Since po is what the producercan earn
vation can thrive in a competitive economy from the first sale when he has no downstream
even in the face of indivisibility. In this econ- protectionat all (in practicehe should be able to
omy, individuals live forever. There are many do better than this), there is money to be made
consumers, indexed by c < 0. In each period, for producersof intellectual products.
consumers either consume one unit of the Is this competitive value of intellectualprod-
good, or not. The benefit to consumer c of ucts enough to motivate the producersto spend
consuming a unit of the good is c - + with q > the effort and time required?We do not know.
0. Consumers also prefer to consume early To answer this question one needs to know the
rather than later: a unit of good consumed particularopportunitycost of time of the par-
today is worth 6 < 1 of a unit of the same ticularcreator,which clearly varies from case to
good consumed next period. case. It seems to us, though,thatthereis no hard
Initially, there is a single prototype of a du- empiricalevidence supportingthe view that this
rable commoditythat generatesthe flow of con- value would not be enough.
sumption service. The inventor or producer We also want to understandthe social impact
owns this prototype.Once sold, no downstream of a technology that facilitates the reproduction
licensing is possible. At each moment of time of "idea-goods." Does it increase or decrease
the prototype can either be used to generate a the value of intellectual productsin a competi-
flow of consumptionor be reproduced.To make tive market?Basically, received wisdom argues
things less abstract,let us imagine that the new that cheap copying makes it impossible for in-
good is a recordingof a new musical piece that novatorsto earn back their productioncosts. If,
is embodied in an MP3 file. Copying takes one in a competitive setting, increasing /3lowered
period, and each MP3 that is copied produces po, received wisdom would be correct:without
, > 1 additionalMP3's. A technology such as downstream protection, fewer "idea-goods"
Napster increases ,B. would be createdas a result of the adventof the
Under competitive conditions, in the tth pe- new technology.
riod each MP3 sells for a marketpricePt or may What does happen to po as /3grows larger?
be rented for one period at a rental rate rt. The answer depends on 4'.If 4'< 1, demandis
Notice that consumers for whom c-+q > rt elastic. This is the empirically interestingcase.
value the song more highly than the rental cost As /3grows larger, it is easy to check from the
and will choose to listen to an MP3 that period; equation above that the price of the initial copy
consumersfor whom c - ' < rt will choose not
to listen to the MP3: if they have a copy, they
preferrentingout theircopy to someone else. In 2 Details on this and other calculations in this papercan
a competitive environment,everyone is poten- be found online at (http://Mevine.sscnet.ucla.edu) or (http://
tially a buyer and a seller. www.econ.umn.edu/-mboldrin).

This content downloaded from 152.14.136.96 on Thu, 1 Aug 2013 19:56:17 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
212 AEA PAPERSAND PROCEEDINGS MAY2002

goes to infinity as more of it is allocated to difference to consumers. When there are many
reproduction. In fact, this happens as ,B ap- firms competing for monopoly rents, and mar-
proaches a finite value, but this is a special ket conditions are such that rents can be ob-
implicationof the analytic forms we are using. tained even with some degree of competition,
Notice that, in all cases, the rate at which the the rent-seekingbehaviorof competing monop-
price falls over time is proportionalto ,B.Nev- olists dissipates the social surplus by overpro-
ertheless, with elastic demand and large (3,the duction of too many similar items. When we
increase in the rate with which price falls over allow for creativity in the use of markets by
time is associatedwith a higher initial price and having consumers submit contingent bids, then
greaterrent for the innovator. no copyright is unambiguously better than
In summary, under competition and in the copyright.
empirically interesting case where demand is Suppose in particular that firms are identi-
elastic, improvingthe technology for reproduc- cal, face a fixed cost, and produce at zero
tion increases the first sale price withoutbound. marginal cost. Suppose also that there are H
The improvedtechnology makes it much easier identical risk-neutral customers with fixed
for a producerto recover sunk costs in a com- reservation price who may reproduce the
petitive market. This does not mean that the good at marginal cost ( ' 0. When intellec-
producerwill argue against downstreamlicens- tual monopoly is legally enforced through
ing and in favor of increased competition. She copyright, we assume that the post-entry price
will still be able to earn more revenues with a lies between the price needed to recover costs
monopoly than under competition. However, it (for each firm) and the monopoly price in a
is a good argument for not giving in to the way that depends on the number of firms and
producersand grantingthem the monopoly: the consumers. This particular form of market
social benefit of the monopoly (the ability to arrangement(call it "copyright-inducedcom-
cover sunk costs and produce a socially desir- petition for niches") results in what we de-
able good) is reduced by the new technology. scribe as the Pareto worst outcome.
This establishes competitive marketsas a vi- Withoutcopyrighttherewill be no outputand
able institutionalsetting for fosteringinnovative no social surplusonly if (H < FN; otherwise,
activity.3 We move now to consider the viabil- social surplus will be higher than under copy-
ity of alternativeinstitutionalsettings. right. This, however, does not do justice to the
competitive instinct: we have excluded the im-
IV. The Hidden Costs of Imperfect Monopoly portantpossibility that consumers may submit
contingent bids prior to production.In a sym-
What happens when competitive rent is in- metric equilibrium of a contingent-bidding
sufficientto cover the cost of producingthe first model, with copyright, the Pareto worst out-
unit? Let us considerthe starkcase traditionally come is still an equilibrium, while without
consideredin economic theoryin which thereis copyright, the first best is obtained.
a fixed cost that must be recovered, and in
which the marginalcost of productionis zero. REFERENCES
With demand that is perfectly elastic up to an
upper bound, there is no cost of monopoly, so Boldrin, Michele and Levine, David K. "Perfectly
this would seem the ideal environmentto im- CompetitiveInnovation."Mimeo, University
pose downstream-licensingrestrictions. of Minnesota, 2001.
This is correct only if it is not possible to Gans, Joshua S.; Hsu, David H. and Stern, Scott.
produce similar items. In the case of textbooks, "When Does Start-up Innovation Spur the
for example, it is easy to producebooks that are Gale of Creative Destruction?"National Bu-
sufficientlydifferentto be entitled to a separate reau of Economic Research (Cambridge,
copyright,but sufficientlysimilaras to make no MA) Working Paper No. W85 1, 2000.
Romer, Paul. "Are Nonconvexities Important
for UnderstandingGrowth?"American Eco-
'In Boldrin and Levine (2001) we develop a more nomic Review, May 1990 (Papers and Pro-
general version of this argument. ceedings), 80(2), pp. 97-103.

This content downloaded from 152.14.136.96 on Thu, 1 Aug 2013 19:56:17 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen