Sie sind auf Seite 1von 6

About the Center | Staff

Search »
Search

Ethics Home Page


Focus Areas
Bioethics
Business Ethics
Campus Ethics
Character Education
Government Ethics
Leadership Ethics
More...
Publications
Ethics Articles
Ethics Cases
Ethical Decision Making
Ethics Blogs
Podcasts
Center News
E-letter/Subscribe
Events
Contact Us
Site Index

Of Headhunter s and Soldier s: Separ ating Cultur al and Ethical Relativism

By Renato Rosaldo

These days, cultural relativism has a bad reputation in many quarters. It conjures images of a world where
anything goes. According to this domino theory of norms, if people open themselves to the possibility that other
cultures may have valid, if different, ways of life, the next thing you know, they’ll be "doing it in the streets."

In academic debate, calling someone a relativist is a mild form of verbal abuse. When academic concepts
achieve such shorthand status (the refined grunt), it’s probably wise to unpack them—take them out and look at
them a little more carefully: shirts here, pants there, and so on.

In that spirit, I’d like to look at relativist and universalist traditions in my field, anthropology. I begin with the
relativist position, as it was defined by people like Franz Boas in the 1920s and ’30s. Relativism was formulated
in the context of ethical issues; it was meant to be an answer to the Nazis and their racism, anti-Semitism, and
eugenics. The idea was roughly this: Human differences, which ideologies such as
Nazism attributed to race, should be understood as cultural.

Behind this position was the idea of the plasticity of human nature, the ability of
humans to acquire any one or more of a vast array of languages and cultures. The
parable or metaphor the early relativists used was this: Except for the accidents of
history, we might well have all been born in Tibet. Our genetic makeup would be
the same, but we would speak a different language and adhere to a different
culture. In this view, culture is the stuff you learn after birth.

Ruth Benedict, a prominent anthropologist of the time, said all cultures are "coexisting and
equally valid patterns of life, which mankind has created for itself from the raw materials of
existence." In her view, and in the view of American anthropology of the time, each culture
is self-contained, autonomous, separate but equal. Each makes sense in its own context, and
all you have to do is know the context to understand what the people are doing and why
they’re doing it.

Today we might use the term incommensurable for the relativist view that all cultures are
equally valid. You can’t, they argued, have a scale of human cultures: excellent, good, not
so good, fair, medium, below medium. It’s just too complex a task.

Now let’s consider an anthropologist who is usually portrayed as a universalist, Clyde


Kluckhohn. Kluckhohn argued that ethical relativity is really a special case of cultural relativity. This being so,
he concluded that Benedict’s doctrine of cultural relativity—coexisting and equally valid patterns of life—
precludes moral criticism of any cultural practice, including slavery, cannibalism, Nazism, or communism. If
you adopt Benedict’s position, Kluckhohn suggested, then you can’t be critical of evil as you notice it in the
world around you, whatever your favorite examples of evil may be.

To replace Boas’ and Benedict’s relativism, Kluckhohn proposed a set of ethical and cultural universals that, to
my ear, are surprisingly void of content. He drew one example from Benedict’s book, Patterns of Culture, in
which she contrasts two Native American groups: the Kwakiutl of the Northwest Coast, whose culture
encourages exhibitionism and the Zuni of the Southwest, who by contrast prize restraint.

These are really different ways of giving meaning to one’s life, of displaying one’s identity, of being in the
world. To Kluckhohn, this vast difference revealed a universal–prizing the norms of one’s culture. But how
could that not be true? A people either prizes their own norms or they don’t have any norms.

Similarly Kluckhorn argued that the variety of human moral standards contains a universal. He said, "Morality is
as genuine a human universal as is language. All cultures have moral systems." I would think that’s fairly true,
except that I don’t feel especially enlightened. To say that we all have moral systems and then not to say what
the moral standards are is not very substantive. Thou shalt not kill—is that a universal? Addressing that question
would be getting into a more interesting and more difficult discussion—because I’m not sure what the universals
would be.

At the same time Kluckhohn was looking for cultural universals, he was also something of a relativist. He said
many different values in human cultures are not so much ethical as they are matters of taste. The fact that the
taste of other peoples does not coincide with our own does not make them stupid, ignorant, or evil. If somebody
speaks a different language than you do, if they button their shirts from the bottom up instead of the top down,
that doesn't mean they’re deranged. That, I think, is a key relativist tenet.

Kluckhohn even went so far as to say, "In a world society, each group can and must learn from other cultures,
can and must familiarize itself with divergent value systems even when it prefers, in the last analysis, to hold in
the main to its own traditional norms." That’s another clear relativist position: insisting on the imperative to
learn from other cultures. So although Kluckhohn held a brief for universals and argued against ethical
relativism, he also had a fairly strong need for relativity.
Kluckhohn was writing in the 1950s. What is happening to relativism in anthropology today? Here, my analysis
proceeds from an assumption of committed anthropology, of scholars working with a sense of ethics—of right
and wrong, or good and evil. This committed anthropology has disrupted the relativist notions inherited from the
1920s and '30s for two broad reasons.

First, the idea of separate but equal cultures no longer seems accurate. Cultures
are not separate; they are not confined to their own individual museum cases.
They exist side by side in the same space. Also, we’ve noticed that there are
inequalities between cultures—relations of dominance and subordination. Take,
for example, settler colonialism, the system we had in America. Relationships
formed in the colonial period and after created inequalities, which a committed
anthropologist would have to critique.

Second, in contrast with Kluckhohn, we see ethical relativism not as a special case of cultural relativism but as a
different notion. I, for one, would regard myself as a cultural relativist; I would not regard myself as an ethical
relativist.

To explain this distinction, we have to begin by returning cultural relativism to a rather modest doctrine. It’s
gotten inflated and become a kind of bogeyman. But the core notions of cultural relativism are the urgency of
studying and learning from other cultures and the belief that because somebody has a different form of life,
they’re not deranged, or evil.

Here, Clifford Geertz's recent work is instructive. Geertz calls a human being an "unfinished animal," by which
he means that humans are not genetically programmed to do what we do. He assumes that bees are genetically
programmed to make honey and birds are genetically programmed to make nests, but humans are genetically
programmed only to acquire language and culture. For example, we can look at plans and make a house, but
that’s something learned after we are born; it's not built in.

In this view, we are not fully human at birth. We haven't got all the stuff we need to cope in the world, to be
social, to be moral, to be thinking, to be creative. The crux of Geertz's argument is that human nature is realized
only in culture. Human nature is the capacity to become Javanese, for example. In Java, Geertz tells us, they
have a saying: "The person is not yet human." But the way they say it is: "The person is not yet Javanese."

The virtue of Geertz's position is its lack of parochialism. Relativism in this sense argues for engagement, for
dialogue between cultures. This is not the kind of easy cosmopolitanism that implies enormous privilege—the
capacity, for example, to spend three days in the Bali Hilton. It’s a deeper form of knowing that entails some
recognition that I am one among others. I'm not the center of the universe.

This argues against ethnocentrism, against what could be called cultural imperialism, (imposing a set of norms
on people who might not want to inhabit those norms), against projection (laying something you see inside
yourself on somebody else). The effort in relativism is to determine what that other person is actually thinking.

We can see the productiveness of relativism when we are trying to expand the discussion
of concepts we think are important—love, for example. We can look at other cultures and
ask, Do they have a notion of falling in love? When we do, we see that love is not a
universal; it’s not even widespread. But other cultures may have something that's kind of
like falling in love—romance, say. That’s probably one of the categories you could find to
look at.

Our own imagination is limited by the culture we have grown up in, but if we actually go
elsewhere and look at what other people do, we can expand our world and challenge our
own notions.

The caveat in all this is: To understand is not to forgive. Just because you come to terms with how something
works in another culture doesn't mean you have to agree with it; it means you have to engage it.
That's the sense in which I'd separate cultural and ethical relativism. I don't think that in order for me to hold a
position as ethical, it needs to be universal. In this way, the relativist position becomes emancipating. It means
I'm free to think what I think because I'm not going to wait for a consensus of the whole world, of every form of
life, every language, every culture. But I want to be challenged by what other people are doing, saying, thinking
—by their ethical systems.

To illustrate, in the late 1960s, I lived with a Filipino hill tribe called the Ilongots, who were headhunters. Do I
think headhunting is a good idea because I worked for years trying to understand it? No, I don’t. Am I horrified
by it? I used to be; it gave me lots of bad dreams, but then something happened.

One day, I went to Manila to get my mail, and I found I'd been called for the draft. I opposed the war in Vietnam,
so of course I was not thrilled by this news. When I went back to the Ilongots' household where I was living, I
told my hosts what had happened, partly because I needed somebody to talk to about it.

But I also had an ignoble motive. I imagined that maybe this situation would make the Ilongots think better of
me; maybe they would think, This guy has an opportunity to kill people, and that's great. I could not have been
further from the truth.

I mentioned the draft notice, and they said, "This is terrible. Don't worry. We'll take care of you. They'll never
find you here."

"Wait a minute," I said, "I thought you guys were in the business of killing."

"No, no," they answered, "we've seen soldiers." In June of 1945, they really saw soldiers when the Americans
drove Japanese troops into the hills where the Ilongots lived. The tribe lost a third of its population during that
time.

At first, I jumped to the conclusion that, having seen the carnage, they didn't approve of war. But when I talked
more with them, I came to realize that they were as horrified of modern warfare as most of us would be of
cannibalism or headhunting. It was a kind of moral horror.

Because I picked up this reaction, I kept pursuing the issue. Finally they said, "Well, what we saw was that one
soldier had the authority to order his brothers to sell their bodies." What they meant was that a commanding
officer could order his subordinates to move into the line of fire. That was absolutely inconceivable to them.
They said, "How can one person tell others to give up their lives, to put themselves so at risk that it's highly
likely they'll lose their lives?" That was their moral threshold.

That experience really knocked me off my moral-horror pedestal. So now, although I do not think headhunting is
a good idea, I no longer have the same horrified reaction to it I once did. I realize that some things we do and
take for granted can inspire other people's abhorrence.

This poem, which I wrote about my experience with the Ilongots, is another way of framing the issue:

Wild Men

A Filipino from the mountains

and I decide to call each other brother.

He asks how I can ask if he's taken a human head.

He's fed me, held my hand on treacherous trails.

I apologize, he's right, never believe war stories.

He pauses and recalls long ago, the time of the Japanese.


Yes, they beheaded some stragglers, helping us medikano.

Downstream, he reveals more recent deeds,

pointing to the house where he took a head, he says,

"Family deaths cling to me like vines to a tree.

Grief slows my steps, bleaches my cheeks.

Throwing away the victim's head

rids me of rage." I'm silent.

He takes my hand, a rough spot on the trail.

"Only red hornbill earrings, a sign

you've taken a head, will let your beauty shine."

I'm called to report for a physical.

He offers me protection.

Soldiers will never find me in these hills.

He shudders. He saw an American officer

order his men to move into the line of fire.

"It's not human, no man would command

his brother to sacrifice his body."

The Lucie Stern Professor in the Department of Cultural and Social Anthropology at
Stanford University, Renato Rosaldo is the author of the forthcoming book Cultural
Citizenship and Educational Democracy (Beacon Press).

Printer-Friendly Page
Return to Web format

Featured Materials
Issues in Ethics - V. 11, N. 1 Winter
2000
The views expressed on this site are the
issue abstr act
author's. The Markkula Center for
Arrow Is It All Relative? Applied Ethics does not advocate
thinking ethically particular positions but seeks to
Arrow Of Headhunters and Soldiers encourage dialogue on the ethical
features
dimensions of current issues. The
Arrow The Best Interests of the
Child
Center welcomes comments and
Arrow The Extra Mile alternative points of view.
Arrow Strangers Into Friends
a good read Ethics Home
Arrow Spiritual Machines Campus Map
at the center
Arrow Conference focusing on
About the Center
character in business and Site Index
education
Contact Us
Arrow Summer Ethics Camp
Program © 2014 Markkula Center for Applied Ethics
Arrow Markkula and Shanks on
Mercury millennium list
Arrow SCU honored for
encouraging character
development
Arrow Second Life in Ethics
to the editor
Arrow none in this issue
issues in ethics tools
Arrow Homepage Arrow Subscribe

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen