Sie sind auf Seite 1von 14

Macroeconomic Priorities†

By ROBERT E. LUCAS , JR.*

Macroeconomics was born as a distinct Ž eld to give up in return? About one-half of one-
in the 1940’s, as a part of the intellectual re- tenth of a percent, I calculate. I will defend this
sponse to the Great Depression. The term then estimate as giving the right order of magnitude
referred to the body of knowledge and expertise of the potential gain to society from improved
that we hoped would prevent the recurrence of stabilization policies, but to do this, many ques-
that economic disaster. My thesis in this lecture tions need to be addressed.
is that macroeconomics in this original sense How much of aggregate consumption vari-
has succeeded: Its central problem of depression ability should be viewed as pathological? How
prevention has been solved, for all practical much can or should be removed by monetary
purposes, and has in fact been solved for many and Ž scal means? Section III reviews evidence
decades. There remain important gains in wel- bearing on these questions. Section IV consid-
fare from better Ž scal policies, but I argue that ers attitudes toward risk: How much do people
these are gains from providing people with bet- dislike consumption uncertainty? How much
ter incentives to work and to save, not from would they pay to have it reduced? We also
better Ž ne-tuning of spending  ows. Taking know that business-cycle risk is not evenly dis-
U.S. performance over the past 50 years as a tributed or easily diversiŽ ed, so welfare cost
benchmark, the potential for welfare gains from estimates that ignore this fact may badly under-
better long-run, supply-side policies exceeds by state the costs of  uctuations. Section V reviews
far the potential from further improvements in recently developed models that let us explore
short-run demand management. this possibility systematically. These are hard
My plan is to review the theory and evidence questions, and deŽ nitive answers are too much
leading to this conclusion. Section I outlines the to ask for. But I argue in the end that, based on
general logic of quantitative welfare analysis, in what we know now, it is unrealistic to hope for
which policy comparisons are reduced to differ- gains larger than a tenth of a percent from better
ences perceived and valued by individuals. It countercyclical policies.
also provides a brief review of some exam-
ples—examples that will be familiar to I. Welfare Analysis of Public Policies:
many— of changes in long-run monetary and Logic and Results
Ž scal policies that consumers would view as
equivalent to increases of 5–15 percent in their Suppose we want to compare the effects of
overall consumption levels. two policies, A and B say, on a single consumer.
Section II describes a thought-experiment in Under policy A the consumer’s welfare is
which a single consumer is magically relieved U(c A), where c A is the consumption level he
of all consumption variability about trend. How enjoys under that policy, and under policy B it
much average consumption would he be willing is U(c B). Suppose that he prefers c B: U(c A) ,
U(c B). Let l . 0 solve

Presidential Address delivered at the one-hundred Ž f- U~~1 1 l !c A ! 5 U~c B !.
teenth meeting of the American Economic Association,
January 4, 2003, Washington, DC.
* Department of Economics, University of Chicago, We call this number l—in units of a percentage
1126 East 59th Street, Chicago, IL 60637. I am grateful for of all consumption goods—the welfare gain of
discussions with Fernando Alvarez, Gadi Barlevy, Lars a change in policy from A to B. To evaluate the
Hansen, Per Krusell, Ellen McGrattan, Chris Phelan, effects of policy change on many different con-
Edward Prescott, Esteban Rossi-Hansberg, Tom Sargent,
Matthew Shapiro, Tony Smith, Nancy Stokey, Kjetil Stores-
sumers, we can calculate welfare gains (perhaps
letten, and Tom Tallarini, and for the able assistance of losses, for some) for all of them, one at a time,
Adrian Kats and Mikhail Golosov. and add the needed compensations to obtain the
1
2 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

welfare gain for the group. We can also specify details, but all were variations on a one-good
the compensation in terms of one or a subset growth model in which consumers (either an
of goods, rather than all of them: There is no inŽ nitely lived dynasty or a succession of gen-
single, right way to carry these comparisons out. erations) maximize the utility of consumption
However it is done, we obtain a method for and leisure over time, Ž rms maximize proŽ t,
evaluating policies that has comprehensible units and markets are continuously cleared.
and is built up from individual preferences. In general, these studies found that reducing
There is a great tradition of quantitative pub- capital income taxation from its current U.S.
lic Ž nance that applies this general framework level to zero (using other taxes to support an
using well-chosen Taylor expansions to calcu- unchanged rate of government spending) would
late estimates of the compensation parameter l, increase the balanced-growth capital stock by
“welfare triangles” as Arnold C. Harberger 30 to 60 percent. With a capital share of around
called them. Today we use numerical simula- 0.3, these numbers imply an increase of con-
tion of general-equilibrium models, often dy- sumption along a balanced growth path of 7.5 to
namic and subject to unpredictable shocks, to 15 percent. Of course, reaching such a balanced
carry out welfare analysis with the general logic path involves a period of high investment rates
that I have just sketched. Some examples will, I and low consumption. Taking these transition
hope, convey the applicability of this approach costs into account, overall welfare gains amount
and some of the estimates that have emerged. to perhaps 2 to 4 percent of annual consump-
Martin J. Bailey’s (1956) thought-experiment tion, in perpetuity.
of a perfectly predictable in ation at a constant Production per adult in France is about 70
rate, induced by sustained growth in the money percent of production per adult in the United
supply, was a pioneering example of the quan- States. Edward C. Prescott (2002) observes that
titative evaluation of policy. In a replication of hours worked per adult in France, measured as
the Bailey study, I estimated the welfare gain a fraction of available hours, are also about 70
from reducing the annual in ation rate from 10 percent of the comparable U.S. Ž gure. Using
to 0 percent to be a perpetual consumption  ow estimates for France and the United States of the
of 1 percent of income.1 Some economists take ratio (1 1 t c)/(1 2 t h) that equals the mar-
estimates like this to imply that in ation is a ginal rate of substitution between consumption
relatively modest problem, but 1 percent of in- and leisure in the neoclassical growth model, he
come is a serious amount of money, and in any shows that tax differences can account for the
case, the gain depends on how much in ation entire difference in hours worked and, ampliŽ ed
there is. The gain from eliminating a 200- by the indirect effect on capital accumulation,
percent annual in ation—well within the range for the entire difference in production. The
of recent experience in several South American steady-state welfare gain to French households
economies—is about 7 percent of income. of adopting American tax rates on labor and
The development of growth theory, in which consumption would be the equivalent of a con-
the evolution of an economy over time is traced sumption increase of about 20 percent. The con-
to its sources in consumer preferences, technol- clusion is not simply that if the French were to
ogy, and government policies, opened the way work American hours, they could produce as
for extending general-equilibrium policy analy- much as Americans do. It is that the utility
sis to a much wider class of dynamic settings. In consequences of doing so would be equivalent
the 1980’s, a number of economists used ver- to a 20-percent increase in consumption with no
sions of neoclassical growth theory to examine increase in work effort!
the effects of taxation on the total stock of The gain from reducing French taxes to U.S.
capital, not just the composition of that stock.2 levels can in part be viewed as the gain from
The models used in these studies differ in their adopting a  at tax on incomes,3 but it is doubt-

1
Lucas (2000). My estimates are based on the money
demand estimates in Allan H. Meltzer (1963). rence H. Summers (1981), Alan J. Auerbach and Laurence
2
For example, William A. Brock and Stephen J. J. Kotlikoff (1987), and Kenneth L. Judd (1987).
3
Turnovsky (1981), Christophe P. Chamley (1981), Law- See also Robert E. Hall and Alvin Rabushka (1995).
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 3

ful that all of it can be obtained simply by something other than mere units changes. Then
rearranging the tax structure. It entails a reduc- it must also be the case that these same rigidities
tion in government spending as well, which prevent the economy from responding efŽ -
Prescott interprets as a reduction in the level of ciently to real shocks, raising the possibility that
transfer payments, or in the government provi- a monetary policy that reacts to real shocks in
sion of goods that most people would buy any- some way can improve efŽ ciency.
way, Ž nanced by distorting taxes. Think of If we had a theory that could let us sort these
elementary schooling or day care. The gains issues out, we could use it to work out the
from eliminating such Ž scal “cross-hauling” (as details of an ideal stabilization policy and to
Sherwin Rosen [1996] called the Swedish day- evaluate the effects on welfare of adopting it.
care system) involve more than eliminating “ex- This seems to me an entirely reasonable re-
cess burden,” but they may well be large. search goal—I have been thinking success is
The stakes in choosing the right monetary just around the corner for 30 years— but it has
and Ž scal policies are high. Sustained in ation, not yet been attained. In lieu of such a theory, I
tax structures that penalize capital accumulation will try to get quantitative sense of the answer to
and work effort, and tax-Ž nanced government the thought-experiment I have posed by study-
provision of private goods all have uncompen- ing a series of simpler thought-experiments.
sated costs amounting to sizeable fractions of In the rest of this section, I ask what the effect
income. We can see these costs in differences in on welfare would be if all consumption vari-
economic performance across different countries ability could be eliminated.4 To this end, con-
and time periods. Even in the United States, sider a single consumer, endowed with the
which visibly beneŽ ts from the lowest excess stochastic consumption stream
burdens in the modern world, economic analy-
2
sis has identiŽ ed large potential gains from fur- (1) c t 5 Ae mte 2~ 1/2!s « t ,
ther improvements in long-run Ž scal policy.
where log(« t) is a normally distributed random
II. Gains from Stabilization: variable with mean 0 and variance s 2. Under
A Baseline Calculation these assumptions
2
In the rest of the lecture, I want to apply the E~e 2~1 /2 !s « t ! 5 1
public Ž nance framework just outlined to the
assessment of gains from improved stabilization and mean consumption at t is Ae m t. Preferences
policy. Such an exercise presupposes a view of over such consumption paths are assumed to be

5 X D 6
the workings of the economy in which short-run
t
monetary and Ž scal policies affect resource al-
O
`
1 c 1t 2 g
location in ways that are different from the (2) E ,
supply side effects I have just been discussing. t50
11r 12g
One possibility is that instability in the quan-
tity of money or its rate of growth, arising from where r is a subjective discount rate, g is the
government or private sources, induces inefŽ - coefŽ cient of risk aversion, and the expectation
cient real variability. If that were all there was is taken with respect to the common distribution
to it, the ideal stabilization policy would be to of the shocks «0 , «1 , ... .
Ž x the money growth rate. (Of course, such a Such a risk-averse consumer would obvi-
policy would require the Federal Reserve to ously prefer a deterministic consumption path
take an active role in preventing or offsetting to a risky path with the same mean. We quantify
instabilities in the private banking system.) But this utility difference by multiplying the risky
this cannot be all there is to it, because an path by the constant factor 1 1 l in all dates
economy in which monetary  uctuations induce and states, choosing l so that the household is
real inefŽ ciencies—indeed, any economy in
which money has value—must be one that op-
erates under missing markets and nominal ri- 4
This calculation replicates the one I carried out in
gidities that make changes in money into Lucas (1987, Ch. III).
4 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

indifferent between the deterministic stream Many questions have been raised about this
and the compensated, risky stream. That is, l is estimate, and subsequent research on this issue
chosen to solve has pursued many of them, taking the discus-
sion deep into new scientiŽ c territory. In the

5 6
next four sections, I will review some of the
O b ~~1 11 l2!cg !
` 12g
t t main Ž ndings.
(3) E
t50
III. Removeable Variance: Two Estimates

O b ~Ae1 2! g
`
t
mt 1 2 g
Even if we do not know exactly how much
5 , consumption risk would be removed by an op-
t50 timal monetary and Ž scal policy, it is clear that
it would fall far short of the removal of all
where c t is given by (1). Canceling, taking logs, variability. The major empirical Ž nding in mac-
and collecting terms gives roeconomics over the past 25 years was the
demonstration by Finn E. Kydland and Prescott
1 (1982), replicated and reŽ ned by Gary D.
(4) l gs 2 .
2 Hansen (1985) and by many others since then,
that technology shocks measured by the method
This compensation parameter l—the welfare of Robert M. Solow (1957) can induce a rea-
gain from eliminating consumption risk— sonably parameterized stochastic growth model
depends, naturally enough, on the amount of to exhibit nearly the same variability in produc-
risk that is present, s2, and the aversion people tion and consumption as we see in postwar U.S.
have for this risk, g. time series. In the basic growth model, equilib-
We can get an initial idea of the value to the rium and optimal growth are equivalent, so that
economy as a whole of removing aggregate risk if technology shocks are all there is to postwar
by viewing this agent as representative of U.S. business cycles, resources are already being al-
consumers in general. In this case, to estimate l located efŽ ciently and a variance-reducing
we need estimates of the variance s2 of the log monetary-Ž scal policy would be welfare reduc-
of consumption about its trend, and of the co- ing. Even if the equilibrium is inefŽ cient, due to
efŽ cient g of risk aversion. Using annual U.S. distorting taxes, missing markets or the like, in
data for the period 1947–2001, the standard the face of unavoidable technology and prefer-
deviation of the log of real, per capita consump- ence shocks an optimal monetary and Ž scal
tion about a linear trend is 0.032.5 Estimates of the policy will surely be associated with a positive
parameter g in use in macroeconomics and pub- level of consumption variance. We need to es-
lic Ž nance applications today range from 1 (log timate the size of that part and remove it from
utility) to 4. Using log utility, for example, the the estimate of s2 used in (4).
formula (4) yields the welfare cost estimate Matthew D. Shapiro and Mark W. Watson’s
(1988) study is one of several relatively atheo-
1 retical attempts to break down the variance of
(5) l 5 2 ~0.032! 2 5 0.0005,
production and other variables into a fraction
due to what these authors call “demand” shocks
about one-twentieth of 1 percent of consumption. (and which I will call “nominal” shocks) and
Compared to the examples of welfare gains fractions due to technology and other sources.
from Ž scal and monetary policy changes that I Their study represents quarterly U.S. time series
cited above, this estimate seems trivially small: over the period 1951–1985 as distributed lags of
more than an order of magnitude smaller than serially independent shocks. The observables
the gain from ending a 10-percent in ation! include Ž rst differences of a measure of hours
worked, a log real GDP measure, and the cor-
responding implicit price de ator. To these
5
The comparable Ž gure using a Hodrick-Prescott trend three rates of change are added an ex post real
with the smoothing parameter 400 is 0.022. interest rate (the three-month Treasury bill rate
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 5

minus the in ation rate) and the change in the TABLE 1—PERCENTAGE OF VARIANCE DUE TO NOMINAL
relative price of oil. The coefŽ cients of an in- SHOCKS AT DIFFERENT FORECAST H ORIZONS
vertible vector autoregression are estimated,
Quarter Output Hours In ation Interest rate
subject to several restrictions. This procedure
yields time series of estimated shocks «ˆ t and 1 28 36 89 83
4 28 40 82 71
decompositions of the variance of each of the 8 20 31 82 72
Ž ve variables into the fractions “explained” by 12 17 27 84 74
the most recent k values of each of the Ž ve 20 12 20 86 79
shocks. 36 8 12 89 85
Shapiro and Watson apply a variety of the- ` 0 0 94 94
oretical principles to the interpretation of
their estimates. They do not consistently fol-
low the general-equilibrium practice of inter- Shapiro and Watson do with the two nominal
preting all shocks as shifts in preferences, shocks, and interpret their paper as partitioning
technologies, or the behavior of policy vari- the variance of output and hours into nominal
ables, but they have in mind some kind of and real sources. The resulting Table 1 is a
monetary growth model that does not have a condensation of their Table 2.
long-run Phillips curve.6 Real variables, in The two zeroes for output and hours in the
the long run, are determined by real factors last, long-run, row of Table 1 are there by the
only. Nominal shocks can affect real variables deŽ nition of a nominal shock. But the two 94-
and relative prices in the short run but not in percent entries in this row for in ation and the
the long run. This idea is not tested: Long-run nominal interest rate could have come out any
neutrality is imposed on the statistical model. way. I take the fact that these values are so close
In return it becomes possible to estimate sep- to 1 as a conŽ rmation of Shapiro and Watson’s
arately the importance of nominal shocks to procedure for identifying nominal shocks. Ac-
the short- and medium-run variability of out- cording to Table 1, these nominal shocks have
put, hours, and real interest rates. 7 accounted for something less than 30 percent of
In the Ž ve-variable scheme that Shapiro and short-run production variability in the postwar
Watson use, there are two nominal variables— United States. This effect decays slowly, with
the in ation rate and the nominal interest rate— no change after one year, a reduction to 20
and three real ones—output, hours, and the percent after two years, and so on.
relative price of oil. They assume as well Ž ve One can ask whether a better estimate of the
shocks, two of which are nominal in the sense importance of nominal shocks could have ob-
of having no effect on real variables in the long tained by using M1 or some other observable
run. They are not able to measure the effects of measure of monetary shocks. Many studies
the two dimensions of nominal instability sep- have proceeded in this more direct way,8 and
arately. The other three shocks are taken to be much has been learned, but in the end one does
real. The assumed exogeneity of oil price not know whether the importance of monetary
shocks plus a long-run neutrality hypothesis on shocks has been estimated or just the impor-
hours are used to estimate the importance of tance of a particular, possibly very defective,
three distinct real shocks. This aspect of their measure of them. Information on future prices is
identiŽ cation seems to me questionable, and in conveyed to people by changes in monetary
any case it is of an entirely different nature from aggregates, of course, but it is also conveyed by
the neutrality of nominal shocks. I will just interest-rate and exchange-rate movements, by
lump the effects of the real shocks together, as changes in the Ž scal situation that may lead to
tighter or easier money later on, by changes in
Ž nancial regulations, by statements of in uen-
6
To remove any doubt on the latter point, they quote tial people, and by many other factors. Shapiro
from Milton Friedman’s (1968) Presidential Address. and Watson’s method bypasses these hard
7
A similar, and similarly motivated, identiŽ cation pro-
cedure was used in Olivier J. Blanchard and Danny Quah
(1989). Thomas J. Sargent and Christopher A. Sims (1977)
8
is a predecessor in spirit, if not in detail. For example, Lawrence J. Christiano, et al. (1996).
6 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

measurement questions and goes directly to an technology shocks, based on comovements of


estimation of the importance of nominal shocks production and labor input over the cycle.
in general, those we know how to measure and Shapiro and Watson Ž nd that at most 30
those we do not, whatever they may be. percent of cyclical output variability can be
A second reason for preferring the procedure attributed to nominal shocks. Working from the
Shapiro and Watson used is that the effects of opposite direction, Prescott and Aiyagari con-
nominal shocks as they estimate them include clude that at least 75 percent of cyclical output
the effects of real shocks that could have been variability must be due to technology shocks.
offset by monetary policy but were not. What- These Ž ndings are not as consistent as they may
ever it is that keeps prices from rising in pro- appear, because there are important real factors
portion to a given increase in money must also besides technological shocks—shocks to the tax
keep relative prices from adjusting as neoclas- system, to the terms of trade, to household tech-
sical theory would predict they should to, say, nology, or to preferences—that are cyclically
an increase in the OPEC-set price of oil. Effects important but not captured in either of the cat-
of either kind—those initiated by monetary egories I have considered so far. 10 Even so, on
changes and those initiated by real shocks—will the basis of this evidence I Ž nd it hard to imag-
last only as long as the rigidity or glitch that ine that more than 30 percent of the cyclical
gives rise to them lasts, vanishing in the long variability observed in the postwar United
run, and will be identiŽ ed as arising from the States could or should be removed by changes
“nominal,” or “demand,” shock under the Sha- in the way monetary and Ž scal policy is
piro and Watson identiŽ cation procedure. Thus conducted.
I want to interpret the estimates in columns 2
and 3 of Table 1 as upper bounds on the vari- IV. Risk Aversion
ance that could have been removed from output
and hours at different horizons under some The estimate of the potential gains from sta-
monetary policy other than the one actually bilization reviewed in Section II rests on as-
pursued. The table gives no information on sumed consumer preferences of the constant
what this variance-minimizing monetary policy relative risk aversion (CRRA) family, using but
might have been, and there is no presumption two parameters—the subjective discount rate r
that it would have been a policy that does not and the risk-aversion coefŽ cient g—to charac-
respond to real shocks. terize all households. This preference family is
Shapiro and Watson applied the theoretical almost universally used in macroeconomic and
idea that nominal shocks should be neutral in public Ž nance applications. The familiar for-
the long run to obtain an estimate of the fraction mula for an economy’s average return on capital
of short-run output variability that can be attrib- under CRRA preferences,
uted to such shocks. Prescott (1986a) proceeded
in a quite different way to arrive at an estimate (6) r 5 r 1 g g,
of the fraction of output variability that can be
attributed to technology shocks. He used actual where g is the growth rate of consumption,
Solow residuals to estimate the variance and makes it clear why fairly low g values must be
serial correlation of the underlying technology used. Per capita consumption growth in the
shocks. Feeding shocks with these properties United States is about 0.02 and the after-tax
into a fully calibrated real-business-cycle model return on capital is around 0.05, so the fact that
resulted in output variability that was about 84 r must be positive requires that g in (6) be at
percent of actual variability.9 In a complemen- most 2.5. Moreover, a value as high as 2.5
tary study, S. Rao Aiyagari (1994) arrived at an would imply much larger interest rate differen-
estimate of 79 percent for the contribution of
10
For example, Shapiro and Watson attribute a large
9
Questions of measurement errors are discussed in the share of output variance to a shock which they call “labor
paper and by Summers (1986) in the same volume. In supply” [and which I would call “household technology,”
Prescott (1986b), estimates of 0.5 to 0.75 for the contribu- following Jess Benhabib et al. (1991) and Jeremy
tion of technology shocks to output variance are proposed. Greenwood and Zvi Hercowitz (1991)].
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 7

tials than those we see between fast-growing of the supply-side gains cited in Section I, and
economies like Taiwan and mature economies two orders of magnitude larger than the estimate
like the United States. This is the kind of evi- I proposed in Section II.14 As Maurice Obstfeld
dence that leads to the use of g values at or near (1994) shows, this result is basically the for-
1 in applications. mula (4) with a coefŽ cient of risk aversion two
But the CRRA model has problems. Rajnish orders of magnitude larger than the one I used.
Mehra and Prescott (1985) showed that if one Fernando Alvarez and Urban J. Jermann
wants to use a stochastic growth model with (2000) take a nonparametric approach to the
CRRA preferences to account for the entire evaluation of the potential gains from stabiliza-
return differential between stocks and bonds— tion policy, relating the marginal cost of busi-
historically about 6 percent—as a premium for ness-cycle risk to observed market prices
risk, the parameter g must be enormous, per- without ever committing to a utility function.
haps 50 or 100.11 Such values obviously cannot Their estimation procedure is based on the ob-
be squared with (6). This “equity premium puz- servation that consumption streams with a wide
zle” remains unsolved, and has given rise to a variety of different risk characteristics—or
vast literature that is clearly closely related to something very nearly equivalent to them—are
the question of assessing the costs of available for sale in securities markets. They
instability.12 use a mix of asset-pricing theory and statistical
One response to the puzzle is to adopt a methods to infer the prices of a claim to the
three- rather than two-parameter description actual, average consumption path and alterna-
of preferences. Larry G. Epstein and Stanley tive consumption paths with some of the uncer-
E. Zin (1989, 1991) and Philippe Weil (1990) tainty removed. They call the price differentials
proposed different forms of recursive utility, so estimated marginal welfare costs, and show
preference families in which there is one pa- that they will be upper bounds to the corre-
rameter to determine intertemporal substitut- sponding total cost: my compensation parame-
ability and a second one to describe risk ter l. The basic underlying hypotheses are that
aversion. The Ž rst corresponds to the param- asset markets are complete and that asset-price
eter g in (6), and can be assigned a small differences re ect risk and timing differences
value to Ž t estimated average returns to cap- and nothing else.
ital. Then the risk-aversion parameter can be The gain from the removal of all consump-
chosen as large as necessary to account for tion variability about trend, estimated in this
the equity premium. way, is large—around 30 percent of consump-
Thomas D. Tallarini, Jr. (2000) uses prefer- tion.15 This is a re ection of the high risk aver-
ences of the Epstein-Zin type, with an intertem- sion needed to match the 6-percent equity
poral substitution elasticity of 1, to construct a premium, and can be compared to Tallarini’s
real-business-cycle model of the U.S. economy. estimate of 10 percent. But the gain from re-
He Ž nds an astonishing separation of quantity moving risk at what Alvarez and Jermann call
and asset price determination: The behavior of business-cycle frequencies— cycles of eight
aggregate quantities depends hardly at all on
attitudes toward risk, so the coefŽ cient of risk 14
James Dolmas (1998) uses still another preference
aversion is left free to account for the equity family, obtaining much higher cost estimates than mine.
premium perfectly.13 Tallarini estimates a wel- Like Tallarini, Christopher Otrok (1999) develops and an-
fare cost of aggregate consumption risk of 10 alyzes a complete real-business-cycle model. He uses a
percent of consumption, comparable to some preference family proposed by John Heaton (1995). His cost
estimates are close to mine. A recent paper by Anne
Epaulard and Aude Pommeret (2001) contains further
results along this line, and provides a very useful quantita-
11
See also Lars Peter Hansen and Kenneth J. Singleton tive comparison to earlier Ž ndings.
15
(1983). Alvarez and Jermann offer many estimates in their
12
Two especially informative surveys are John H. Tables 2A–2D. My summary is based on Table 2D, which
Cochrane and Hansen (1992) and Narayana R. Kocherla- uses postwar (1954 –1997) data and requires that consump-
kota (1996). tion and dividends be cointegrated. From this table, I follow
13
Similar results, obtained in a closely related context, the authors and cite averages over the columns headed “8
were reported by Hansen et al. (1999). years” and “inf.”
8 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

years or less—is two orders of magnitude that the welfare costs of cycles are not so high
smaller, around 0.3 percent. Most of the high on average, but may be very high for, say, the
return on equity is estimated to be compensation very poor or currently unemployed members of
for long-term risk only, risk that could not be society.” Several recent studies have pursued
much reduced by short-run policies that are this possibility.16 Doing so evidently requires
neutral in the long run. models with incomplete risk sharing and differ-
Accepting Shapiro and Watson’s Ž nding that ently situated agents.
less that 30 percent of output variance at Krusell and Smith (1999, 2002) study a
business-cycle frequencies can be attributed to model economy in which individual families
nominal shocks, the lower Alvarez and Jermann are subject to three kinds of stochastic shocks.
estimate of 0.3 should be reduced to 0.1 if it is There is an aggregate productivity shock that
to serve my purpose as an estimate of the value affects everyone, and employment shocks that
of potential improvements in stabilization pol- differ from person to person. Families are inŽ -
icy. But it is important to keep in mind that this nitely lived dynasties, but every 40 years or so
estimate is not smaller than Tallarini’s because a family draws a new head, whose subjective
of a different estimate of risk aversion. Tallarini’s discount rate is drawn from a Ž xed distribution.
estimate of g 5 100 is the parametric analogue Dynasties with patient heads will accumulate
of Alvarez and Jermann’s “market price of wealth while others will run their wealth
risk,” based on exactly the same resolution of down.17 The sizes of these shocks are chosen so
the equity premium puzzle. The different cost that the model economy experiences realistic
estimate is entirely due to differences in the GDP  uctuations, unemployment spells have
consumption paths being compared. realistic properties, and the overall wealth dis-
Resolving empirical difŽ culties by adding tribution matches the U.S. distribution: In the
new parameters always works, but often only by model, the wealthiest 5 percent of households
raising more problems. The risk-aversion levels own 54 percent of total wealth; in reality, they
needed to match the equity premium, under the hold 51 percent.
assumption that asset markets are complete, It is essential to the substantive question that
ought to show up somewhere besides securities motivates this study that neither the employ-
prices, but they do not seem to do so. No one ment shocks nor the uncertainty about the char-
has found risk-aversion parameters of 50 or 100 acter of the household head can be diversiŽ ed
in the diversiŽ cation of individual portfolios, in away. Otherwise, the individual effects of the
the level of insurance deductibles, in the wage aggregate productivity shocks would be the
premiums associated with occupations with same as in the representative agent models I
high earnings risk, or in the revenues raised by have already discussed. One may argue over
state-operated lotteries. It would be good to why it is that markets do not permit such diver-
have the equity premium resolved, but I think siŽ cation, but it seems clear enough that they do
we need to look beyond high estimates of risk not: Where is the market where people can be
aversion to do it. The great contribution of insured against the risk of having irresponsible
Alvarez and Jermann is to show that even using or incompetent parents or children?
the highest available estimate of risk aversion, These exogenous forces acting differentially
the gain from further reductions in business- across households induce different individual
cycle risk is below one-tenth of 1 percent of choices, which in turn lead to differences in
consumption. The evidence also leaves one free individual capital holdings. The state space in
to believe—as I do—that the gain is in fact one this economy is very large, much larger than
or two orders of magnitude smaller.

V. Incomplete Markets and Distribution Effects 16


For example, Ayse Imrohorog lu (1989), Andrew
Atkeson and Christopher Phelan (1994), Krusell and Smith
The calculations I have described so far treat (1999, 2002), Kjetil Storesletten et al. (2001), and Tom
Krebs (2002).
households as identical and individual risks as 17
This way of modeling wealth changes within a Ž xed
diversiŽ able. But as Per Krusell and Anthony A. distribution across families was introduced in John Laitner
Smith, Jr. (1999) observe, “it is quite plausible (1992).
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 9

anything people were working with numerically this particular application, removing the vari-
15 years ago, and without the method developed ance of the aggregate shock is estimated to
in Krusell and Smith (1998) it would not have reduce the standard deviation of the individual
been possible to work out the predictions of this employment shocks by 16 percent.19
model. A key simpliŽ cation comes from the fact The Ž rst such thought-experiment Krusell
that the impact on any one family of the shocks and Smith describe involves a comparison be-
that hit others has to work through two prices, tween the expected utility drawn from the
the real wage and the rental price of capital. steady state of the economy with aggregate
These prices in turn depend only on the total shocks and the expected utility from the steady
stock of capital, regardless of the way it is state of the economy with aggregate shocks and
distributed, and total employment, regardless of their indirect effects removed in the way I have
who has a job and who does not. By exploiting just described. The welfare gain from eliminat-
these features, solutions can be calculated using ing cycles in this sense turns out to be negative!
an iterative procedure that works like a dream: In a model, like this one, in which markets for
For determining the behavior of aggregates, risk pooling are incomplete, people will engage
they discovered, realistically modeled house- in precautionary savings, overaccumulating
hold heterogeneity just does not matter very capital in the effort to self-insure. This implies
much. larger average consumption in the more risky
For individual behavior and welfare, of economy. Of course, there are costs to accumu-
course, heterogeneity is everything. In the lating the higher capital stock, but these costs are
thought-experiments that Krusell and Smith run not fully counted in a steady-state comparison.
with their model, removal of the business cycle In any case, as Krusell and Smith emphasize,
is deŽ ned to be equivalent to setting the aggre- there is nothing really distributional about a
gate productivity shock equal to a constant. It is steady-state comparison: Every inŽ nitely lived
important to be clear on what the effect of such dynasty is assigned a place in the wealth distri-
a change would be on the behavior of the em- bution at random, and no one of them can be
ployment shocks to which individuals are sub- identiŽ ed as permanently rich or poor. The
ject, but the magical character of the experiment whole motivation of the paper is to focus on the
makes it hard to know how this question is best situation of people described as “hand-to-mouth
resolved. I will describe what Krusell and Smith consumers,” but a steady-state comparison
did, and deal with some other possibilitieslater on. misses them. This observation motivates a sec-
Suppose that a shock y 5 az 1 « affects an ond thought-experiment— one with much more
individual’s behavior, where z is the aggregate complicated dynamics than the Ž rst—in which
shock and « is idiosyncratic. We project the an economy is permitted to reach its steady-
individual shock on the aggregate, « 5 cz 1 h , state wealth distribution with realistic aggregate
where the residual h is uncorrelated with z, and shocks, and then is relieved of aggregate risk.
then think of an ideal stabilization policy as one The full transition to a new steady state is then
that replaces worked out and taken into account in the utility
comparisons. In this experiment, we can iden-
y 5 az 1 « 5 ~a 1 c!z 1 h tify individuals as “rich” or “poor” by their posi-
tion in the initial wealth distribution, and discuss
with the effects of risk removal category by category.
The average welfare gain in this second ex-
ŷ 5 ~a 1 c!E~z! 1 h . periment is about 0.1 of 1 percent of consump-
tion, about twice the estimate in Section II of
Not only is the direct effect of the productivity this paper. (Krusell and Smith also assume log
shock z removed but also the indirect effects of utility.) But this Ž gure masks a lot of diversity.
z on the individual employment shocks «.18 In Low wealth, unemployed people—people who

18 19
This is a linear illustration of the more generally Here and below, the numbers I cite are taken from
deŽ ned procedure described in Krusell and Smith (1999). Krusell and Smith (2002).
10 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

would borrow against future labor income if ence in the way reductions in the variance of
they could—enjoy a utility gain equivalent to a aggregate shocks affect risks faced at the indi-
4-percent perpetual increase in consumption. vidual level. In the Storesletten et al. simula-
Oddly, the very wealthy can also gain, as much tions, a bad realization of the aggregate
as 2 percent. Krusell and Smith conjecture that productivity shock increases the conditional
this is due to the higher interest rates implied by variance of the idiosyncratic risk that people
the overall decrease in precautionary savings face, so aggregate and individual risks are com-
and capital. Finally, there is a large group of pounded in a way that Krusell and Smith rule
middle wealth households that are made worse out. A second difference is that idiosyncratic
off by eliminating aggregate risk. shocks are assumed to have a random walk
These calculations are sensitive—especially at component, so their effects are long lasting. A
the poor end of the distribution—to what is as- bad aggregate shock increases the chances that
sumed about the incomes of unemployed people. a young worker will draw a bad individual
Krusell and Smith calibrate this, roughly, to cur- shock, and if he does he will suffer its effects
rent U.S. unemployment insurance replacement throughout his prime working years.
rates. If one were estimating the costs of the de- The effects of these two assumptions are
pression of the 1930’s, before the current welfare clear: They convert small, transient shocks at
system was in place, lower rates would be used the aggregate level into large, persistent shocks
and the cost estimates would increase sharply. 20 It to the earnings of a small fraction of house-
would also be interesting to use a model like this holds. Whether they are realistic is question of
to examine the trade-offs between reductions in fact. That individual earnings differences are
aggregate risk and an improved welfare system. highly persistent has been clear since Lee
Storesletten et al. (2001) study distributional Lillard and Robert Willis’s pioneering (1978)
in uences on welfare cost estimates with meth- study. The fanning out over time of the earnings
ods that are closely related to Krusell and and consumption distributions within a cohort
Smith’s, but they obtain larger estimates of the that Angus Deaton and Christina Paxson (1994)
gains from removing all aggregate shocks. They document is striking evidence of a sizeable,
use an overlapping generations setup with 43 uninsurable random walk component in earn-
working age generations, in which the youngest ings. The relation of the variance of earnings
cohort is always credit constrained. In such a shocks to the aggregate state of the economy,
setting, the young are helpless in the face of also emphasized by N. Gregory Mankiw (1986)
shocks of all kinds and reductions in variance in connection with the equity premium puzzle,
can yield large welfare gains. But if the age has only recently been studied empirically.
effects are averaged out to re ect the impor- Storesletten et al. Ž nd a negative relation over
tance of intrafamily lending (as I think they time between cross-section earnings means and
should be) the gains estimated by Storesletten et standard deviations in Panel Studies of Income
al. under log utility are no larger than Krusell Dynamics data. Costas Meghir and Luigi
and Smith’s.21 In contrast to earlier studies, Pistaferri (2001) obtain smaller estimates, but
however, the Storesletten et al. model implies also conclude that “the unemployment rate and
that estimated welfare gains rise faster than the variance of permanent [earnings] shocks
proportionately as risk aversion is increased: appear to be quite synchronized” in the 1970’s
From Exhibit 2, for example, the average gain and 1980’s.
increases from 0.6 of a percent to 2.5 as g is These issues are central to an accurate de-
increased from 2 to 4. scription of the risk situation that individual
Two features of the theory interact to bring agents face, and hence to the assessment of
this about.22 First, and most crucial, is a differ- welfare gains from policies that alter this situ-
ation. The development of tractable equilibrium
20
models capable of bringing cross-section and
See Satyajit Chatterjee and Dean Corbae (2000). panel evidence to bear on this and other mac-
21
Based on Exhibits 2 and A.3.1.
22
Storesletten et al. do a good job of breaking the roeconomic questions is an enormous step for-
differences into intelligible pieces. I also found the example ward. But Krusell and Smith Ž nd only modest
explicitly solved in Krebs (2002) very helpful in this regard. effects of heterogeneity on the estimates of wel-
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 11

fare gains from the elimination of aggregate average level of investment. He obtains welfare
risk, and even accepting the Storesletten et al. gains as large as 7 percent of consumption in
view entails an upward revision of a factor of models based on this idea, but everything
only about 5. hinges on a curvature parameter on which there
The real promise of the Krusell-Smith model is little evidence. This is a promising frontier on
and related formulations, I think, will be in the which there is much to be done. Surely there are
study of the relation of policies that reduce the others.
impact of risk by reducing the variance of
shocks (like aggregate stabilization policies) to VII. Conclusions
those that act by reallocating risks (like social
insurance policies). Traditionally, these two If business cycles were simply efŽ cient re-
kinds of policies have been studied by different sponses of quantities and prices to unpredict-
economists, using unrelated models and differ- able shifts in technology and preferences, there
ent data sets. But both appear explicitly in the would be no need for distinct stabilization or
models I have reviewed here, and it is clear that demand management policies and certainly no
it will soon be possible to provide a uniŽ ed point to such legislation as the Employment Act
analysis of their costs and beneŽ ts. of 1946. If, on the other hand, rigidities of some
kind prevent the economy from reacting efŽ -
VI. Other Directions ciently to nominal or real shocks, or both, there
is a need to design suitable policies and to
My plan was to go down a list of all the assess their performance. In my opinion, this is
things that could have gone wrong with my the case: I think the stability of monetary ag-
1987 calculations but, as I should have antici- gregates and nominal spending in the postwar
pated, possibilities were added to the list faster United States is a major reason for the stability
than I could eliminate them. I will just note of aggregate production and consumption dur-
some of the more interesting of these possibil- ing these years, relative to the experience of the
ities, and then conclude. The level of consump- interwar period and the contemporary experi-
tion risk in a society is, in part, subject to ence of other economies. If so, this stability
choice. When in an economy that is subject to must be seen in part as an achievement of the
larger shocks, people will live with more con- economists, Keynesian and monetarist, who
sumption variability and the associated loss in guided economic policy over these years.
welfare, but they may also substitute into risk- The question I have addressed in this lecture
avoiding technologies, accepting reduced aver- is whether stabilization policies that go beyond
age levels of production. This possibility shows the general stabilization of spending that char-
up in the precautionary savings—overaccumu- acterizes the last 50 years, whatever form they
lation of capital—that Krusell and Smith (1999, might take, promise important increases in wel-
2002) found. As Garey Ramey and Valerie A. fare. The answer to this question is “No”: The
Ramey (1991) suggested, this kind of substitu- potential gains from improved stabilization pol-
tion surely shows up in other forms as well. icies are on the order of hundredths of a percent
In an endogenous growth framework, substi- of consumption, perhaps two orders of magni-
tution against risky technologies can affect rates tude smaller than the potential beneŽ ts of avail-
of growth as well as output levels. Larry E. able “supply-side” Ž scal reforms. This answer
Jones et al. (1999) and Epaulard and Pommeret does depend, certainly, on the degree of risk
(2001) explore some of these possibilities, aversion. It does not appear to be very sensitive
though neither study attributes large welfare to the way distribution effects are dealt with,
gains to volatility-induced reductions in growth though it does presuppose a system of unem-
rates. Gadi Barlevy (2001) proposes a convex ployment insurance at postwar U.S. levels. I
adjustment cost that makes an erratic path of have been as explicit as I can be on the way
investment in knowledge less effective than a theory and evidence bear on these conclusions.
smooth path at the same average level. In such When Don Patinkin gave his Money, Interest,
a setting, reducing shock variability can lead to and Prices the subtitle “An Integration of Mon-
higher growth even without an effect on the etary and Value Theory,” value theory meant, to
12 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

him, a purely static theory of general equilib- and Supply Disturbances.” American Eco-
rium. Fluctuations in production and employ- nomic Review, September 1989, 79(4), pp.
ment, due to monetary disturbances or to shocks 655–73.
of any other kind, were viewed as inducing Brock, William A. and Turnovsky, Stephen J.
disequilibrium adjustments, unrelated to any- “The Analysis of Macroeconomic Policies in
one’s purposeful behavior, modeled with vast Perfect Foresight Equilibrium.” International
numbers of free parameters. For us, today, value Economic Review, February 1981, 22(1), pp.
theory refers to models of dynamic economies 179 –209.
subject to unpredictable shocks, populated by Chamley, Christophe P. “The Welfare Cost of
agents who are good at processing information Capital Income Taxation in a Growing Econ-
and making choices over time. The macroeco- omy.” Journal of Political Economy, June
nomic research I have discussed today makes 1981, 89(3), pp. 468–96.
essential use of value theory in this modern Chatterjee, Satyajit and Corbae, Dean. “On the
sense: formulating explicit models, computing Welfare Gains of Reducing the Likelihood of
solutions, comparing their behavior quantita- Economic Crises.” Federal Reserve Bank of
tively to observed time series and other data Philadelphia Research Working Paper No.
sets. As a result, we are able to form a much 00/14, November 2000.
sharper quantitative view of the potential of Christiano, Lawrence J.; Eichenbaum, Martin
changes in policy to improve peoples’ lives than and Evans, Charles. “The Effects of Monetary
was possible a generation ago. Policy Shocks: Evidence from the Flow of
Funds.” Review of Economics and Statistics,
REFERENCES February 1996, 78(1), pp. 16–34.
Cochrane, John H. and Hansen, Lars Peter. “As-
Aiyagari, S. Rao. “On the Contribution of Tech- set Pricing Explorations for Macroeconom-
nology Shocks to Business Cycles.” Federal ics.” NBER macroeconomics annual, 1992.
Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Re- Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992, pp. 115–65.
view, Summer 1994, 18(3), pp. 22–34. Deaton, Angus and Paxson, Christina. “Intertem-
Alvarez, Fernando and Jermann, Urban J. “Us- poral Choice and Inequality.” Journal of Po-
ing Asset Prices to Measure the Cost of Busi- litical Economy, June 1994, 102(3), pp. 437–
ness Cycles.” Working paper, University of 67.
Chicago, 2000. Dolmas, James. “Risk Preferences and the Wel-
Atkeson, Andrew and Phelan, Christopher. “Re- fare Cost of Business Cycles.” Review of
considering the Costs of Business Cycles Economic Dynamics, July 1998, 1(3), pp.
with Incomplete Markets.” NBER macroeco- 646 –76.
nomics annual, 1994. Cambridge, MA: MIT Epaulard, Anne and Pommeret, Aude. “Recur-
Press, 1994, pp. 187–207. sive Utility, Endogenous Growth, and the
Auerbach, Alan J. and Kotlikoff, Laurence J. Dy- Welfare Cost of Volatility.” International
namic Ž scal policy. Cambridge: Cambridge Monetary Fund Working Paper No. WP/01/
University Press, 1987. 05, 2001.
Bailey, Martin J. “The Welfare Cost of In ation- Epstein, Larry G. and Zin, Stanley E. “Substitu-
ary Finance.” Journal of Political Economy, tion, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Be-
April 1956, 64(2), pp. 93–110. havior of Consumption Growth and Asset
Barlevy, Gadi. “The Cost of Business Cycles Returns I: A Theoretical Framework.”
Under Endogenous Growth.” Working paper, Econometrica, July 1989, 57(4), pp. 937–69.
Northwestern University, 2001. . “Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the
Benhabib, Jess; Rogerson, Richard and Wright, Temporal Behavior of Consumption Growth
Randall. “Homework in Macroeconomics: and Asset Returns II: An Empirical Analy-
Household Production and Aggregate Fluctu- sis.” Journal of Political Economy, April
ations.” Journal of Political Economy, De- 1991, 99(2), pp. 263–86.
cember 1991, 99(6), pp. 1166– 87. Friedman, Milton. “The Role of Monetary Poli-
Blanchard, Olivier J. and Quah, Danny. “The cy.” American Economic Review, March
Dynamic Effects of Aggregate Demand 1968, 58(1), pp. 1–17.
VOL. 93 NO. 1 LUCAS: MACROECONOMIC PRIORITIES 13

Greenwood, Jeremy and Hercowitz, Zvi. “The Eliminating Business Cycles.” Working pa-
Allocation of Capital and Time over the Busi- per, Carnegie Mellon University, 2002.
ness Cycle.” Journal of Political Economy, Kydland, Finn E. and Prescott, Edward C. “Time
December 1991, 99(6), pp. 1188–214. to Build and Aggregate Fluctuations.”
Hall, Robert E. and Rabushka, Alvin. The  at tax, Econometrica, November 1982, 50(6), pp.
2nd Ed. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution 1345–70.
Press. 1995. Laitner, John. “Random Earnings Differences,
Hansen, Gary D. “Indivisible Labor and the Lifetime Liquidity Constraints, and Altruistic
Business Cycle.” Journal of Monetary Eco- Intergenerational Transfers.” Journal of Eco-
nomics, November 1985, 16(3), pp. 309–27. nomic Theory, December 1992, 58(2), pp.
Hansen, Lars Peter; Sargent, Thomas J. and 135–70.
Tallarini, Thomas D., Jr. “Robust Permanent Lillard, Lee and Willis, Robert. “Dynamic As-
Income and Pricing.” Review of Economic pects of Earnings Mobility.” Econometrica,
Studies, October 1999, 66(4), pp. 873–908. September 1978, 46(5), pp. 985–1012.
Hansen, Lars Peter and Singleton, Kenneth J. Lucas, Robert E., Jr. Models of business cycles.
“Stochastic Consumption, Risk Aversion, New York: Basil Blackwell, 1987.
and the Temporal Behavior of Asset Re- . “In ation and Welfare.” Economet-
turns.” Journal of Political Economy, April rica, March 2000, 68(2), pp. 247–74.
1983, 91(2), pp. 249– 65. Mankiw, N. Gregory. “The Equity Premium and
Heaton, John. “An Empirical Investigation of the Concentration of Aggregate Shocks.”
Asset Pricing with Temporally Dependent Journal of Financial Economics, September
Preference SpeciŽ cations.” Econometrica, 1986, 17(1), pp. 211–19.
May 1995, 63(3), pp. 681–717. Meghir, Costas and Pistaferri, Luigi. “Income
Imrohorog lu, Ayse. “The Cost of Business Cy- Variance Dynamics and Heterogeneity.”
cles with Indivisibilities and Liquidity Con- Working paper, Institute for Fiscal Studies,
straints.” Journal of Political Economy, 2001.
December 1989, 97(6), pp. 1364– 83. Mehra, Rajnish and Prescott, Edward C. “The
Jones, Larry E.; Manuelli, Rodolfo E. and Equity Premium: A Puzzle.” Journal of Mon-
Stacchetti, Ennio. “Technology (and Policy) etary Economics, March 1985, 15(2), pp.
Shocks in Models of Endogenous Growth.” 145–61.
National Bureau of Economic Research Meltzer, Allan H. “The Demand for Money: The
(Cambridge, MA) Working Paper No. Evidence from Time Series.” Journal of Po-
7063, April 1999. litical Economy, June 1963, 71(3), pp. 219–
Judd, Kenneth L. “The Welfare Cost of Factor 46.
Taxation in a Perfect Foresight Model.” Jour- Obstfeld, Maurice. “Evaluating Risky Consump-
nal of Political Economy, August 1987, tion Paths: The Role of Intertemporal Substi-
95(4), pp. 675–709. tutability.” European Economic Review,
Kocherlakota, Narayana R. “The Equity Premi- August 1994, 38(7), pp. 1471–86.
um: It’s Still a Puzzle.” Journal of Economic Otrok, Christopher. “On Measuring the Welfare
Literature, March 1996, 34(1), pp. 42–71. Cost of Business Cycles.” Working paper,
Krebs, Tom. “Growth and Welfare Effects of University of Virginia, 1999.
Business Cycles in Economies with Idiosyn- Prescott, Edward C. “Theory Ahead of Business
cratic Human Capital Risk.” Working paper, Cycle Measurement.” Federal Reserve Bank
Brown University, 2002. of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, Fall
Krusell, Per and Smith, Anthony A., Jr. “Income 1986a, 10(4), pp. 9 –21.
and Wealth Heterogeneity in the Macro- . “Response to a Skeptic.” Federal Re-
economy.” Journal of Political Economy, serve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review,
October 1998, 106(5), pp. 867–96. Fall 1986b, 10(4), pp. 28–33.
. “On the Welfare Effects of Eliminat- . “Richard T. Ely Lecture: Prosperity
ing Business Cycles.” Review of Economic and Depression.” American Economic Re-
Dynamics, January 1999, 2(2), pp. 245–72. view, May 2002 (Papers and Proceedings),
. “Revisiting the Welfare Effects of 92(2), pp. 1–15.
14 THE AMERICAN ECONOMIC REVIEW MARCH 2003

Ramey, Garey and Ramey, Valerie A. “Technol- Economics and Statistics, August 1957,
ogy Commitment and the Cost of Economic 39(3), pp. 312–20.
Fluctuation.” National Bureau of Economic Storesletten, Kjetil; Telmer, Chris I. and Yaron,
Research (Cambridge, MA) Working Paper Amir. “The Welfare Cost of Business Cycles
No. 3755, June 1991. Revisited: Finite Lives and Cyclical Varia-
Rosen, Sherwin. “Public Employment and the tion in Idiosyncratic Risk.” European Eco-
Welfare State in Sweden.” Journal of Eco- nomic Review, June 2001, 45(7), pp. 1311–
nomic Literature, June 1996, 34(2), pp. 729– 39.
40. Summers, Lawrence H. “Capital Taxation and
Sargent, Thomas J. and Sims, Christopher A. Accumulation in a Life Cycle Growth Mod-
“Business Cycle Modeling without Pretend- el.” American Economic Review, September
ing to Have Too Much A-Priori Economic 1981, 71(4), pp. 533–44.
Theory,” in New methods in business cycle . “Some Skeptical Observations on Real
research. Proceedings from a Conference, Business Cycle Theory.” Federal Reserve
Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, 1977, Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, Fall
pp. 45–109. 1986, 10(4), pp. 22–27.
Shapiro, Matthew D. and Watson, Mark W. Tallarini, Thomas D., Jr. “Risk-Sensitive Real
“Sources of Business Cycle Fluctuations.” Business Cycles.” Journal of Monetary Eco-
NBER macroeconomics annual, 1988. Cam- nomics, June 2000, 45(3), pp. 507–32.
bridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988, pp. 111–48. Weil, Philippe. “Non-Expected Utility in Macro-
Solow, Robert M. “Technical Change and the economics.” Quarterly Journal of Econom-
Aggregate Production Function.” Review of ics, February 1990, 105(1), pp. 27–42.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen