Sie sind auf Seite 1von 1

The heart of the dialogue opens with a challenge by Socrates to the elder and

revered Parmenides and Zeno. Employing his customary method of attack, the reductio
ad absurdum, Zeno has argued that if as the pluralists say things are many, then
they will be both like and unlike; but this is an impossible situation, for unlike
things cannot be like, nor like things unlike. But this difficulty vanishes, says
Socrates, if we are prepared to make the distinction between sensibles on one hand
and Forms, in which sensibles participate, on the other. Thus one and the same
thing can be both like and unlike, or one and many, by participating in the Forms
of Likeness and Unlikeness, of Unity and Plurality; I am one man, and as such
partake of the Form of Unity, but I also have many parts and in this respect I
partake of the Form of Plurality. There is no problem in demonstrating that
sensible things may have opposite attributes; what would cause consternation, and
earn the admiration of Socrates, would be if someone were to show that the Forms
themselves were capable of admitting contrary predicates.

At this point, Parmenides takes over as Socrates' interlocutor and dominates the
remainder of the dialogue. After establishing that Socrates himself has made the
distinction between Forms and sensibles, Parmenides asks him what sorts of Form he
is prepared to recognize. Socrates replies that he has no doubt about the existence
of mathematical, ethical and aesthetic Forms (e.g., Unity, Plurality, Goodness,
Beauty), but is unsure of Forms of Man, Fire and Water; he is almost certain,
though admits to some reservations, that undignified objects like hair, mud and
dirt do not have Forms. Parmenides suggests that when he is older and more
committed to philosophy, he will consider all the consequences of his theory, even
regarding seemingly insignificant objects like hair and mud.

For the remainder of the first part of the dialogue, Parmenides draws Socrates out
on certain The heart of the dialogue opens with a challenge by Socrates to the
elder and revered Parmenides and Zeno. Employing his customary method of attack,
the reductio ad absurdum, Zeno has argued that if as the pluralists say things are
many, then they will be both like and unlike; but this is an impossible situation,
for unlike things cannot be like, nor like things unlike. But this difficulty
vanishes, says Socrates, if we are prepared to make the distinction between
sensibles on one hand and Forms, in which sensibles participate, on the other. Thus
one and the same thing can be both like and unlike, or one and many, by
participating in the Forms of Likeness and Unlikeness, of Unity and Plurality; I am
one man, and as such partake of the Form of Unity, but I also have many parts and
in this respect I partake of the Form of Plurality. There is no problem in
demonstrating that sensible things may have opposite attributes; what would cause
consternation, and earn the admiration of Socrates, would be if someone were to
show that the Forms themselves were capable of admitting contrary predicates.

At this point, Parmenides takes over as Socrates' interlocutor and dominates the
remainder of the dialogue. After establishing that Socrates himself has made the
distinction between Forms and sensibles, Parmenides asks him what sorts of Form he
is prepared to recognize. Socrates replies that he has no doubt about the existence
of mathematical, ethical and aesthetic Forms (e.g., Unity, Plurality, Goodness,
Beauty), but is unsure of Forms of Man, Fire and Water; he is almost certain,
though admits to some reservations, that undignified objects like hair, mud and
dirt do not have Forms. Parmenides suggests that when he is older and more
committed to philosophy, he will consider all the consequences of his theory, even
regarding seemingly insignificant objects like hair and mud.

For the remainder of the first part of the dialogue, Parmenides draws Socrates out
on certain

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen