Sie sind auf Seite 1von 5

Double effect: a useful rule that alone cannot justify hastening death

Author(s): J Andrew Billings


Source: Journal of Medical Ethics, Vol. 37, No. 7 (July 2011), pp. 437-440
Published by: BMJ
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23034697
Accessed: 28-09-2018 20:34 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

BMJ is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of
Medical Ethics

This content downloaded from 128.112.200.107 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 20:34:53 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Teaching and learning ethics

Double effect: a useful rule that alone cannot justify


hastening death
J Andrew Billings

Correspondence to ABSTRACT on justifying palliative sedation and related acts.


J Andrew Billings, 11 1/2
The rule of double effect is regularly invoked in ethical A monolithic moral framework deprives us of the
Hilliard Street, Cambridge, diversity of viewpoints that can inform and deepen
MA 02138, USA;
discussions about palliative sedation, terminal extubation
our ethical understanding.'
jandrew.billings@gmail.com and other clinical acts that may be viewed as hastening
death for imminently dying patients. Unfortunately, the The current essay focuses on application of the
Received 5 November 2010 literature tends to employ this useful principle in rule of double effect to clinical acts that may hasten
Revised 21 January 2011
a fashion suggesting that it offers the final word on the the death of an imminently dying patient. The rule
Accepted 6 February 2011
Published Online First moral acceptability of such medical procedures. In fact, regularly appears in ethical considerations of such
8 April 2011 the rule cannot be applied appropriately without invoking acts such as administering morphine to a dyspnoeic
moral theories that are not explicit in the rule itself. Four patient, preemptively sedating a patient who is
tenets of the rule each require their own ethical undergoing terminal extubation and palliative
justification. A variety of moral theories are relevant to sedation. The term 'hastening death' is not without
making judgements in a pluralistic society. Much of the important ambiguities, but is used here in its
rich moral conversation germane to the rule has been common clinical fashion. It, therefore, does not
reflected in arguments about physician-asssisted suicide include withholding or withdrawing life supports,
and voluntary active euthanasia, but the rule itself has but does apply to palliative sedation, and is also
limited relevance to these debates, and requires its own sometimes invoked with regard to physician
moral justifications when applied to other practices that assisted suicide (PAS) and voluntary active eutha
might hasten death. nasia (VAE) (although, as discussed below, the rule
does not universally apply to the debate on VAE
and PAS). These are situations often associated
with moral distress when clinicians wonder if their
Bioethical deliberations may reflect a variety of management is ethically justifiable.
moral theories and traditions, such as conse The major conclusion of this essay is that
quentialism, deontology, principlism, communitar applying the rule in such situations must be based
ianism, virtue ethics and so on. These tools or on further consideration of underlying moral
frameworks are regularly employed in clinical theories. Assumptions that the rule offers a solid,
decision making, sometimes simply through intui clear, or unassailable method of determining
tion or informal reflection, sometimes after formal appropriate practice overlooks its reliance on often
deliberation. An awareness of the relevance of
unstated moral tools and traditions, and this
multiple theories and traditions can enrich 'blocking' unfortunately turns attention away
our perspective on bioethical judgementfrom and the important tasks of reflecting on a range
enhance our appreciation of the variety of ethical
of ethical frameworks evident in a pluralistic
frameworks prevalent in a pluralistic society.1-3
society.
Respect for autonomy has become a dominant
principle for bioethical decision making in theAUSA.
BRIEF REVIEW OF THE RULE OF DOUBLE EFFECT
Daniel Callahan4 has noted that principlismThe rule of double effect applies only to situations
(as typified by the popular Georgetown quartet of
in which an act intended to do good runs the
autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficenceforeseeable
and danger of harm. In a simplified form, it
justice)5 has a 'blocking effect' on the appreciation
states that running the risk of a bad outcome is
of other relevant and important moral tools.
acceptable when we intend to produce a good
In reviewing recent ethical discussions on palli
outcome and when taking the risk of the bad
ative sedation, Larry Churchill and I observedoutcome
that seems sensible. For instance, in some
the rule of double effect has been applied as
circumstances, good can be secured for certain
a 'monolithic moral framework'(J A Billings, 2011,
people only if others experience harm.6 The rule is
work in submission). The rule is regularly treated as
consonant with familiar non-medical ethical
the normative and singular criterion fordistinctions
the (eg, between strategic bombing and
acceptability of such procedures, so that clinical
terror bombing) and legal distinctions (eg, between
acts apparently following it are assumed to be
accidental manslaughter and intentional homicide).
ethical, while those not justified by the rule are
In modern medicine and especially in palliative
euthanasia or some other illegal or unethicalcare, a common situation addressed by the rule is
procedure. We conclude our essay as follows: administering morphine to an imminently dying

'Our review of very recent articles on palliative patient with severe, irreversible pulmonary disease
and breathlessness. Appropriately administered
sedation reveals a poverty of ethical viewpoints. The
principle of double effect should not preempt morphine has the beneficial effect of alleviating
additional moral reflection or serve as the final word shortness of breath but may also have the

J Med Ethics 2011;37:437-440. doi:10.1136/jme.2010.041160 437

This content downloaded from 128.112.200.107 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 20:34:53 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Teaching
Teaching and
and learning
learning ethics
ethics

foreseeable, undesirable effect of diminishing respiratory drive from the bad effect. Thus, in the example of the severely
and hastening death. If the value of alleviating suffering dyspnoeic patient, morphine is given with the intention of
outweighs the harm of hastening death, the rule of double easing dyspnoea, not to alleviate that symptom by causing
effects justifies morphine use. death. The bad effect or side-effect is sometimes said to be
The rule of double effect has the important practical function 'indirectly voluntary.' (This component ofthe rule is not always
of sanctioning appropriate symptom relief, including palliative stated.) (5) There is a sufficiently grave reason for achieving the
sedation,7-9 while minimising fears of accusations of PAS or good effect, compensating for hazarding the evil effect. In other
VAE.10 Indeed, even the strictest applications of the rule allow words, a balance or assessment of proportionality between the
for what is almost universally now considered humane good and bad effect is required.20
symptom control near the end of life, and considerable In the following sections, tenets 1, 2, 3 and 5 are reviewed
consensus supports the practice of palliative sedation under the with regard to how they necessarily invoke moral framework
terms of the rule. The rule also corresponds to embedded atti that are not intrinsic to the rule. Many other issues relevant to
tudes among clinicians who distinguish foreseeable side-effects the use of the rule of double effect are not discussed, including
or complications that are unfortunate but consistent with good the nature of intention, situations that seem to suggest that the
medical practice from those that are avoidable or blameworthy rule does not adequately describe moral action, and various other
medical errors. While clinical decisions are often expressed in difficulties interpreting and using the rule. Necessarily, the ethics
terms of balancing benefits and burdens, the rule offers valuable of VAE and PAS will be touched upon, because they are the
refinements.11 As Sulmasy and Pellegrino12 point out, clinicians subtext of so much contemporary discussion of the rule of
have an 'unarticulated, intuitive grasp of the rule of double effect double effect, but neither of those procedures will be addressed
in almost all their therapeutic interventions.' with the intention of entering into ethical or policy debates.
Trepidation about the improper use of the rule of double effect
is also noteworthy, particularly whether it can be twisted to TENET 1: ESTABLISH WHETHER ACTS ARE MORALLY GOOD OR
become a justification for evil acts. A notably vigorous concern NEUTRAL
about such an application is provided in Elizabeth Anscombe's Modern explications of the rule typically stipulate that the act
memorable attack on Truman's decision to use the atomic bomb itself, as opposed to its effects, must not be morally objection
on Japan.13 Causing death to so many innocent civilians had able. Considerable good may arise from killing an innocent
been justified in terms of saving soldiers' lives: person or allowing one to die so that his or her organs can be
transplanted and can save many lives, but such an act is never
'We can now reformulate the principle of "doing evil that good may
permissible. Indeed tenet 1 is a fundamental ethical principle,
come". Every fool can be as much of a knave as suits him....
but can be interpreted differently by different moral traditions.
'...I mean that if you attack a lot of military targets, such as Therefore, the rule of double effect cannot be applied to
munitions factories and naval dockyards, as carefully as you can, questions about hastening death in imminently dying persons
you will be certain to kill a number of innocent people; but that iswithout ascertaining whether a particular act is or is not
not murder. On the other hand, unscrupulousness in considering permissible, a question not answered in any way by the rule
the possibilities turns it into murder....'13 itself. Very few contemplated familiar clinical actions are likely
to be unacceptable per se. Tenet 1 is most easily applied from the
The rule is usually attributed to St Thomas Aquinas,14 whose
viewpoint of the moral frameworks in which good and bad
13th century work, Summa Theologicae, states that killing in self
actions are clearly spelled out, as is typical of deontological
defence is permissible if the intention of the act is to save one's
schemes. Regardless of this, concern about the morality of the
life or rescue another person but there is no intention to harm
primary act is a feature of many moral frameworks and simply
the aggressor and only a necessary amount of force is used to
deserves attention and respect for its importance to some
achieve the the desired end.15 Worth noting, Aquinas was not
persons.11
opposed to all forms of killing; he allowed for the use of lethal
force by government in times of war or for administering civil TENETS 2 AND 3: ASSESSING WHICH EFFECTS ARE GOOD OR
justice.
BAD
The formulation of the rule and how to apply it, along with
Tenants 2 and 3 require that we identify and evaluate the good
an assessment of its value, has been the subject of extensive
and bad effects of an action. The rule does not define good and
philosophical discussion, disagreement and inconsistencies.
bad. The applicability of these tenets thus calls for further moral
Some of its most famous philosophical test cases, the Trolley reflection.
Problems, introduced by Phillipa Foot16 over 40 years ago and
Figuring out whether an intended or foreseen outcome is good
elaborated upon especially by Judith Jarvis Thompson,17 have
or bad is a fundamental question in ethics. Doing good is a basic
been an object of both ethical controversy and fascinating
ethical principle in any moral framework. Different persons
empirical research in cognitive neuroscience.18 19
using the same moral framework may come up with dissimilar
conclusions, while different moral frameworks may lead to
A MODERN FORMULATION OF THE RULE OF DOUBLE EFFECT a consensus or conflict.
As restated and refined in contemporary medical terms, the rule Insofar as the good or bad effect is hastening death for an
is a rather complex, ingenious and occasionally bewildering imminently dying person, considerable debate is familiar. In the
concept that requires that five conditions or tenets are met: Judeo—Christian tradition, the Ten Commandments say, 'Thou
(1) The act, by itself, must be morally good or at least indif shall not kill', yet exceptions exist. Even the definitions of killing
ferent. (2) The clinician must intend to cause a good effect. (3) A and hastening death may be debated; as mentioned above with
bad effect may be foreseen but not intended. (This implies that
regards to Aquinas, killing is often viewed as permissible under
the bad effect would have been avoided if the good effect could
selected circumstances, such as self-defence, rescue, a just war, or
otherwise have been achieved, and that a bad outcome is not civil defence. The notion of 'justified' killing21 lies at the heart of
inevitable.) (4) The good effect follows from the action, not some debates about palliative sedation, PAS and VAE.

438 J Med Ethics 2011;37:437-440. doi:10.1136/jme.2010.041160

This content downloaded from 128.112.200.107 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 20:34:53 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Teaching
Teaching and
and learning
learning ethics
ethics

We can imagine how different ethical frameworks might Clinical situations typically focus on the interests of one
address these issues. From the vantage of liberal individualism,4 person, so the operant values for achieving balance primarily
some argue a right to request a hastened death, similar to a right reflect the informed patient's values, goals and preferences
not to suffer when death is imminent.22 23 Others believe that (although much of the literature on double effect seems to focus
respect for patient autonomy trumps other ethical concerns, so primarily on professional integrity and the physician's viewpoint
a patient deserves help when requesting hastening of death. In of what is acceptable).
end-of-life care, many clinicians, patients and family members Balance is weighed in terms of ethical principles. How do we
have notions of a 'good' or 'peaceful' or 'timely' death; these are compare respecting dignity, valuing individual choice or feelings
legitimate ends for clinical care and a variety of acts may be of the family, religious precepts, and our sense of professional
viewed as justifiable for meeting these objectives. From a utili responsibility and personal values and that of other involved
tarian viewpoint,21 24 humane ends, such as avoiding suffering clinicians? As stated in the Neve Catholic Encyclopedia:
or achieving a sense of personal control, may justify hastening
'...an effect that benefits or harms society generally has more
death, and unwanted prolongation of dying may not make sense
weight than one that affects only an individual; an effect sure to
when quality of life is poor and death is imminent. In discus
occur deserves greater consideration than one that is only probable;
sions based on virtue ethics, VAE and PAS may sometimes be an effect of a moral nature has greater importance than one that
justified as loving, responsible acts.25 deals only with material things.'20
Of course, the ethical frameworks cited above, as well as
other moral systems, may support opposite conclusions. In Assigning a degree of goodness or badness to the various
addition to a strict prohibition against hastening death, viewed outcomes and deciding on proportionality, should thus bring us
as a form of unacceptable killing, the impact of such practices back to an awareness of moral frameworks. Importantly here,
may be seen as undermining public trust in the health the value may not be simply good or bad but how good and how
profession, subverting professional ethics, dereliction of duty, bad, how desirable and how unacceptable are outcomes relative
a failure of character, causing damage to surviving family to each other. In the language of decision analysis, we are
members, or putting us on the 'slippery slope' that leads to describing utilities,28 but utilitarian calculations necessarily
harm for the infirm or suggests an obligation to die when one is require (and sometimes conceal) decisions about how outcomes
no longer useful or appreciated by society. The psychological are valued. In the simplest cases, we might say that saving two
difference between directly causing death rather than allowing lives is better than saving one, but this assumes that each life is
a death is also relevant to this discussion and to the thinking equally valued rather than recognising schemes that distinguish
and feeling of clinicians. between the most and least socially valued, such as the very
A continuum in the array of acts that hasten death young and the very old.
is suggested in Justice Souter's comments in Washington Consequentialism or utilitarianism determine the choice of an
v. Glucksburg: action largely in terms of its effects. A common, perhaps
unstated and often utilitarian, consideration in offering pallia
'Furthermore, because physicians are already involved in making tive sedation or other measures that are likely to hasten dying is
decisions that hasten the death of terminally ill patients—through
to say that the patient is going to die soon anyway and that the
termination of life support, withholding of medical treatment, and
limited time for survival is only valuable if suffering is alleviated.
terminal sedation—there is in fact significant tension between the
traditional view of the physician's role and the actual practice in
Suffering may be immediate, terrible and unnecessary so it
a growing number of cases.'26 should be treated vigorously. The patient and family, as well as
the clinical team, may have relatively little concern about the
and is developed extensively in Brock's description of 'killing'.21 difference between a more immediate death and a potential
The key point here, similar to the discussion under tenet 1, is survival for a few hours, days, or weeks in misery or uncon
to ask whether hastening death is ever a good effect in clinical sciousness. For another patient, survival is highly important, so
practice? How does it differ from such apparently acceptable avoiding the sedative side-effect of pain-relieving medicines is an
acts as withholding or withdrawing life supports, which may acceptable strategy, while any shortening of survival becomes
not substantially differ from palliative sedation? What are the the bad effect.
situations, the safeguards and trade-offs (eg, between such values Proportionality can also be viewed in a deontological frame
as social justice, autonomy and mercy), if any, that might help us work. Some outcomes may be considered unacceptable in all
decide about the acceptability of such practices? Using the situations. If alleviating suffering near the end of life is always
rule of double effect conscientiously, we come back to a funda a higher priortiy than prolonging survival, then acts that may
mental discussion of whether 'Doctors should not kill'.21 26 27
have the effect of hastening death near the end of life are
regularly permissible under the rule of double effect, or the
TENET 5: DECIDING ABOUT PROPORTIONALITY OR BALANCE converse.

Having clarified that an act is morally good or neutral and that Another common point about these decisions is th
intended effects are good while only foreseen but unintended that is good for one patient must necessarily be vie
effects are bad, we need to decide whether the chance of perspective of broader social policy. Therefore, for e
achieving a good effect in this particular situation outweighs the reflecting the autonomous wishes of a single pati
risk of causing the bad effect. examined in the context of the larger community, m
Part of the decision about balance must reflect clinical judge on the wellbeing of others.
ment about the odds of producing various outcomes from the
proposed action—the probabilities. A tiny chance of a bad BEYOND THE RULE OF DOUBLE EFFECT
outcome may be worth risking when there is almost a certainty Proponents and opponents of PAS and VAE have fought some of
of a good outcome. Conversely, if the bad effect is almost sure to their battles by arguing about the rule of double effect. Timothy
occur while the good effect is highly unlikely, clinical judgement Quill and others,29-31 in favouring the liberalisation of policies
might rule against the act. that currently forbid such practices, have thoughtfully pointed

J Med Ethics 2011;37:437-440. doi:10.1136/jme,2010.041160 439

This content downloaded from 128.112.200.107 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 20:34:53 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Teaching and learning ethics

out problems with the rule and its applications.32 Some impor Competing interests None declared.
tant concerns are worth noting, especially about how propor Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
tionality is judged and how the rule relies on intentions or
motives that may be difficult to ascertain, but these issues
are peripheral to the argument here.33 Some strongly stated REFERENCES
assertions from this camp seem to preempt more nuanced ethical 1. Arras JD, Steinbock B. Moral reasoning in the medical context. In: Steinbock B,
London J, Arras J, eds. Ethical issues in modem medicine, 7th edn. Boston:
deliberation and respect for other moral traditions, for instance:
McGraw-Hill, 2008:1-39.
'...One of the most important ethical principles in medicine is 2. Churchill LR, King NMP, Schenck D. Ethics in medicine: an introduction to moral
tools and traditions. In: King NMP, Straus RP, Churchill LR, etal, eds. Social medicine
respect for each patient's autonomy... when this principle conflicts
reader: patients, doctors, and illness, 2nd edn. Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
with others, it should almost always take precedence.'34 2005:169-85.
3. Berlin IS. Two concepts of liberty. In: Four essays on liberty. New York: Oxford
Among the most articulate and rigorous opponents of the University Press, 1979:118—72.
legalisation of PAS and VAE, Daniel Sulmasy has convincingly 4. Callahan D. Principlism and communitarianism. J Med Ethics 2003;29:287-91.
5. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics, 5th edn. New York:
rebutted some common objections to the rule.12 35 This essay is
Oxford University Press, 2001.
largely inspired by Sulmasy's demand that we use the rule 6. Quinn WS. Actions, intentions, and consequences: the doctrine of double effect. In:
properly and his warning not to call upon the rule in situations Quinn W, ed. Morality and action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993:175-93.
in which it simply is not meant to apply. Sulmasy35 reminds us:
7. Jansen LA, Sulmasy DP. Sedation, alimentation, hydration, and equivocation: careful
conversation about care at the end of life. Ann Intern Med 2002;136:845-9.
The rule of double effect is only 1 moral rule among many. It is
8. Rousseau P. Terminal sedation in the care of dying patients. Arch Intern Med
only designed to cover certain kinds of actions, while other rules
1996;156:1785-6.
cover other kinds of actions.'
9. Truog RD, Berde CB, Mitchell C, ef al. Barbiturates in the care of the terminally ill.
N Engl J Med 1992;327:1678-82.
He points out that when hastening death is considered
10. Supreme Court of the United States, Dennis C. Vacco, Attorney General of New York,
a morally acceptable act, there is no need to invoke the rule of et al, Petitioners v Timothy E Quill et al. Docket No. 95-1858. Opinion 521 U.S. 793
double effect. He thus indicates that the rule is only useful in (1997).
11. Brody H. Double effect: does it have a proper use in palliative care? J Palliat Med
situations when hastening death is considered a foreseen and 1998;1:329-31.
undesired effect, not the direct and intended effect of the action. Sulmasy DP, Pellegrino ED. The rule of double effect: clearing up the double talk.
Arch Intern Med 1999;159:545-50.
'It goes without saying that those who accept the moral 13. Anscombe GEM. Mr. Truman's degree self-published. 1956.
permissibility of euthanasia and assisted suicide have no need for 14. Rovie E. Reevaluating the historical evolution of double effect: Anscombe, Aquinas,
and the principle of side-effects. In: Studies in the History of Ethics, 2006:1—24.
a rule of double effect. For them, hastening the patient's death is
not a "bad" effect to be avoided.'12 http://www.historyofethics.org/022006/RovieDoubleEffect.pdf (accessed 1 Apr
2010).
15. Aquinas T. The Summa Theologies of St. Thomas Aquinas, 2nd and revised edn,
These assertions diminish the importance of the rule and of 1920. In: Fathers of the English Dominican Province, Translators: The Catholic
how PAS and VAE may be viewed as permissible yet undesirable Encyclopedia, www.newadvent.org/summa/ (accessed 10 Mar 2010).
options of last resort. Favouring, for instance, the legalisation
16. Foot P. The problem of abortion and the doctrine of the double effect. Oxford Rev
1967;5:5-15.
of PAS or VAE in specified situations does not mean that all 17. Thomson J J. Killing, letting die, and the trolley problem. Monist 1976;59:204-17.
acts that may hasten death are viewed as desirable or Hauser MD. Moral minds: the nature of right and wrong. New York: HarperCollins,
acceptable; no familiar moral framework or notion of a 'good 2006.
Greene JD, Sommerville RB, Nystrom LE, etal. An fMRI investigation of emotional
death' leads to a belief that a speedy, painless death is desirable
engagement in moral judgment. Science 2001;293:2105-8.
in all situations.
Connell FJ. Double effect, principle of. In: New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2nd edn.
Detroit: Gale, 2003.
CONCLUSION 21. Brock DW. Moral rights and permissible killing. In: Life and death: philosophical
essays in biomedical ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993:95—122.
Concepts can take on a life of their own, becoming reified Annas GJ. The bell tolls for a constitutional right to physician-assisted suicide.
shortcuts to critical thinking. This has happened with the rule N Engl J Med 1997;337:1098-103.
of double effect, perhaps because it is typically applied in the Burt RA. The Supreme Court speaks — not assisted suicide but a constitutional right
to palliative care. N Engl J Med 1997;337:1234-6.
emotion-laden and often troubling context of end-of-life deci
Singer P. Rethinking life and death: the collapse of our traditional ethics. Melbourne,
sion making—a time when clarity is most urgently desired, and Australia: The Text Publishing Company, 1994.
when moral deliberation might drag us into the grey area Fletcher JF. Morals and medicine: the moral problems of: the patient's right to know
the truth, contraception, artificial insemination, sterilization, euthanasia. Princeton, NJ:
between, on the one hand, ethically and legally accepted clinical
Princeton University Press, 1954.
procedures and, on the other, clinical actions that may not 26.beSupreme Court of the United States. Washington et al. v Glucksberg et al. Docket
legal or acceptable to all our colleagues or our community. Some 96-110. Opinion: 521 U.S. 702 (1997).
alternatives may just feel wrong or very troublesome to us. We 27. Pellegrino ED. Doctors must not kill. J Clin Ethics 1992;3:95-102.
Raiffa H. Decision analysis: introductory lectures on choices under uncertainty, 1st
know and feel that life is sacrosanct, yet prolonging life is not edn. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1997.
always humane. Hopefully, we pay attention to these tensions. 29. Quill TE. The ambiguity of clinical intentions. N Engl J Med 1993;329:1039-40.
The rule has its shortcomings but is generally an excellent Quill TE. Principle of double effect and end-of-life pain management: additional
myths and a limited role. J Palliat Med 1998;1:333-6.
guide that fits our intuitive approach to dealing with clinical
31. Quill TE, Dresser R, Brack DW. The rule of double effect — a critique of its role in
situations. Attention to the moral basis of the rule's tenets
end-of-life decision making. N Engl J Med 1997;337:1768-71.
should lead us to consider relevant moral traditions and tools as Goldworth A. Deception and the principle of double effect. Camb Q Healthc Ethics
they pertain to the varieties of palliative sedation36 and related2008;17:471-2.
Scanlon T. Moral dimensions: permissibility, meaning, blame. Cambridge, MA:
practices, such as preemptive sedation for terminal extubation. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2008.
When the rule is applied without attention to the underlying
34. Kamm FM. Intricate ethics: rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. Oxford,
moral tenets or principles on which it must be based, however, New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Sulmasy DP. Commentary: double effect—intention is the solution, not the problem.
we use it improperly and without the appropriate ethical
J Law Med Ethics 2000;28:26-9, 2.
deliberation that we owe to our profession, patients and families
Quill TE, Lo B, Brock DW, etal. Last-resort options for palliative sedation. Ann Intern
and personal integrity. Med 2009;151:421-4.

440 J Med Ethics 2011;37:437-440. doi:10.1136/jme.2010.041160

This content downloaded from 128.112.200.107 on Fri, 28 Sep 2018 20:34:53 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen