Sie sind auf Seite 1von 10

In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.

18, 20)21

Oxford Review of
Books
Essays & Reviews Interviews Diaries Poetry Shop About

In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with


Stephen Yablo

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 1 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

‘A philosopher’, Stephen Yablo quips, ‘is someone who says here is the thing that’s happening everywhere, all the
time, throughout human history, but it’s really hard to think of a good example’. I have met Yablo, David W
Skinner Professor of Philosophy at MIT, at his home on Washington Street in Cambridge, Massachusetts. We are
sitting in a warmly-lit room next to the kitchen, featuring a comfortable but very sorry-looking couch that, as we
talk, I pick at incessantly. It is a very hot day in August, and Yablo is across the table from me, wearing a t-shirt,
shorts, and a messy hairdo. His expression tends towards the wry, but his hand gestures towards the expressive, at
the moment bordering on the Italian. The touch of irony and self-deprecation in Yablo’s de!nition of the
philosopher – he is one himself, of course, and married to another – are, if not par for the profession,
unsurprising for Yablo personally. In one article he cautiously suggests that some philosophical ponderings are
‘just a teensy bit ridiculous’; in a parenthetical aside elsewhere, he wonders if philosophers of his temperament are

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 2 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

of the self-hating kind; in a lecture, he calls a distinction ‘a little super!cial, so it’s… just right for me!’. The
lightness of these remarks, however, belies their depth: they are the re"ection not only of a certain personal
attitude, but a philosophical one as well. Take the lecture joke, for instance. A super!cial distinction might be
contrasted with one that, in Plato’s phrase, ‘carves nature at its joints’. But why think that philosophy should aim
at the latter? Might not concepts and distinctions that make sense of how the world seems to us, of its appearance
to observers who have our outlook, in the end, serve us better?

I !rst stumbled across Stephen Yablo towards the end of the second year of my degree, while taking philosophy of
mind. The essay was ‘Mental causation’, one of his earlier e#orts to account for how mental states – such as pain,
contempt, love, and belief – could cause physical events. It’s clear, if anything is, that they do. As Yablo himself
puts it elsewhere, ‘Smirking, beaming, moping about, shivering in anticipation, raising a skeptical eyebrow,
favoring a tender limb – these are just an inkling of the human phenomena making no sense in a world where
thoughts and feelings keep causally to themselves’. But philosophers have found it hard to explain how the mind
can be causally e$cacious. Isn’t it really the !ring of neurons that causes things to happen?, they ask. If all the
happenings in the world can be accounted for by physics, the problem runs, what work is left for mental states to
do? I’d like to say I was immediately convinced by Yablo’s answer to these questions – that the metaphysical
connection between mental states and physical states is tight enough to preclude causal competition between the
two – but in fact I didn’t make it that far. Yet, it now seems, a subconscious trace had been left by that early
exposure. I don’t remember how it happened, but I do know that several months later, by the time revision season
had rolled around, my desk and computer desktop were cluttered with Yablo’s writing.

Reading Yablo can be an electrifying experience, if electrical charges passed through you at the rate of several pages
per hour. His writing resembles to a remarkable degree Edgar Wright’s !lm Scott Pilgrim vs The World: it is
stylish, witty, energetic, unpretentious, original, fun. (Scott Pilgrim is even set in Toronto, where Yablo is from.)
One chapter of Yablo’s 2014 book, Aboutness, is a breathtaking example of this "air: in 18 fairly short pages,
Yablo discusses, amongst other things, (i) the point of uttering half-truths, (ii) the existence of numbers, (iii)
mental content, (iv) scienti!c laws and models, (v) the existence of !ctional entities, like Pegasus, and (vi)
metaphysical and logical impossibility. In fact this kind of point-to-pointing is rare for Yablo, who often lays down
objection after objection, even when his !rst is damning enough. More common, rather, is for the points
themselves to be expressed very tightly, or (at least initially) by way of metaphor. Causes shorten the path to their
e#ects; some aspects of meaning "oat free of truth-conditions; sentences acquire newly exposed "anks, or march
right up to sceptical possibilities; the technology for capturing a phenomenon instead strangles it in the cradle; a
theory’s problem is not only that it uses a cannon to kill a mouse, but that it misses the mouse and hits
neighbouring mice instead. One paper, in a ri# on Bertrand Russell, discusses the possibility that ‘an entire species
of much-beloved and frequently deferred-to entities, has been stolen away, leaving behind only persistent
appearances’. The sections following the quote are called ‘Means’, ‘Motive’ and ‘Opportunity’. The crime?
Getting the representational bene!ts of abstract objects – like numbers, properties, events, sets, and models –
without needing to say that such things exist.

Yablo by now has worked in most core areas of theoretical philosophy, including metaphysics, epistemology, mind,
logic, and language. The only notable exception is ethics (which Yablo at one point in conversation calls the
genuinely deep stu#). An online biography, however, says that he started as a logician, before branching out. But,
I !gure, no one starts as a logician. This, it turns out, is pretty near wrong. ‘My father’, Yablo tells me, ‘was

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 3 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

constantly calling me on alleged logical errors. I used to feel that can’t be right, so I did spend a fair bit of time
trying to catch my father in contradictions.’ He also remembers reading his mother’s old copy of Descartes’
Meditations. ‘I got interested’, he says, ‘in the question of possibilities that nobody takes seriously but were not
really defended against, and the peculiar horror of something happening that we hadn’t really thought about’.
The young Yablo proceeded to write a short essay about the possibility of gravity giving out. This wouldn’t just be
surprising to us, he !gured; it would upset us more deeply. On another occasion – still ‘embarrassingly young’ –
Yablo wrote a piece called ‘Individualism and the Masses’, in response to a book found on some basement shelf
about the Canadian national identity. ‘It made no sense’, Yablo admits. ‘It was this rhetorical blabber that I picked
up somewhere.’

Yablo’s philosophical development continued apace in high school, where he wrote a letter to an early idol, the
behaviourist BF Skinner, ‘partly to do with thinking he was making things too simple, which were really
complicated’. (Skinner wrote back, Yablo says, ‘which was really cool’.) He also ran into Quine, Carnap, and at
least one niche treatise on logic and fatalism, although, curiously, he didn’t know that the writers he was reading
were philosophers. ‘I don’t know how I could have failed to appreciate there was such a thing as philosophy, when
I had read Quine’s Philosophy of Logic’, Yablo says, ‘but fortunately I ended up going to the University of
Toronto, which, after Oxford at the time, and maybe even still, was the biggest English-speaking philosophy
department’. His initial idea of majoring in English was very quickly abandoned. At Toronto, Yablo says, of his
forty courses, about thirty-two were in philosophy. ‘And they had that many di#erent philosophy courses. I took
the philosophy of Bertrand Russell, et cetera. I was really interested.’ One of his professors, Hans Herzberger, was
especially in"uential; and it was in Herzberger’s class that Yablo was !rst exposed to Saul Kripke – the prominent
philosopher of language – who Yablo says has been his most signi!cant intellectual in"uence. Yablo recalls being
blown away, back in 1978, by Kripke’s now-famous ‘Outline of a theory of truth’. ‘I thought it was the most
amazing thing I had ever read in my life’, he says, ‘and I assumed everyone else thought so too’. Yablo’s exposure to
Kripke led him into an awkward encounter with an aging Alfred Tarski, the famous logician, two years later.
Spotting him at a party, Yablo asked Tarski what he thought of Kripke’s work on truth. ‘He basically just looked at
me’, Yablo says. ‘It seemed to be a contemptuous look. He didn’t answer, he just turned and walked away.’

Kripke’s in"uence on Yablo is indeed apparent, both philosophically and temperamentally. For one thing, Yablo
has sought in several papers to defend and deepen the theory of meaning that Kripke sets out in his seminal
Naming and Necessity, and has emerged as one of Kripke’s ablest interpreters (and, occasionally, critic). A recent
paper on nonexistence is a case in point. The problem discussed in the paper concerns what are called ‘empty
names’, names, like ‘Pegasus’ and ‘Sherlock Holmes’ that don’t seem to refer to anything – names, that is, which
fail to name. Such names are sometimes thought to be a terminal problem for ‘Millian’ views, like Kripke’s (and
John Stuart Mill’s), which take the meaning of a name to be exhausted by whatever the name refers to. For
example, the meaning of ‘Jane Austen’ is taken to be simply Austen herself. Crucially, on Millian views, the
meaning of a name does not involve any descriptive content: ‘Jane Austen’ does not in part express ‘the author of
Pride and Prejudice’. Millianism indeed seems to get a lot of the intuitive data right; for instance, as Kripke argues,
if ‘Jane Austen’ partly meant ‘the author of Pride and Prejudice’, then, amongst other problems, how could ‘Jane
Austen might not have written Pride and Prejudice’ be true? The issue, however, is that, if ‘Jane Austen’ means
Jane Austen, then ‘Sherlock Holmes’ must mean Sherlock Holmes… but there is no such person! So does
‘Sherlock Holmes’ therefore lack meaning? And, if it does, then wouldn’t sentences containing ‘Sherlock Holmes’
themselves be meaning-de!cient? Yet some such sentences, like ‘Sherlock Holmes does not exist’, are clearly not

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 4 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

only meaningful, but true.

To resolve the di$culty, Yablo seizes on an enigmatic remark Kripke makes in a paper on the topic, that ‘whatever
bandersnatches may be, certainly there are none in Dubuque’. Kripke claims this is heard as true because it really
says ‘that there is no true proposition to the e#ect that there are bandersnatches in Dubuque’. Although Yablo
rejects this particular claim about what the sentence says, his paper defends (what he takes as) Kripke’s underlying
idea that we should be looking for something the sentence can be heard as saying that is true, even if it fails to
express a proposition about Sherlock Holmes. Yablo’s own suggestion is that even though ‘Sherlock Holmes does
not exist’ cannot be true about Holmes, it might nevertheless be true about a di#erent subject matter: what does
exist. It is plausible, Yablo argues, to suppose that even if ‘Sherlock Holmes’ is itself strictly meaningless, the term
still functions evocatively, recalling certain properties that we know Holmes, if he existed, would have. The next
step lies in noticing that none of us – ‘us’ comprising you, me, the planets, and so on – has those properties; and
!nally, that each of us has properties that Holmes, on the hypothesis that he exists, doesn’t have (for instance, you
and I were born too late, and Venus weighs too much). It is this last claim that Yablo maintains is the content
asserted by ‘Sherlock Holmes does not exist’: the sentence says that each existing thing has distinctive properties –
di#erent in each case – such that, even if Holmes exists, he is at any rate not that particular thing. And since it is,
in point of fact, true that each of us has some such properties, we hear the sentence itself as true.

Yablo bills his argument as a development of Kripke’s position on nonexistence, one ‘making use of basically
Kripkean materials’. But even if that’s not true, it is certainly one that leverages distinctly Yablovian materials,
such as subject matter and the ‘even if’ locution itself. Indeed the paper, beyond its contribution to the
philosophy of language, doubles as a front in the war that Yablo has been !ghting over the last decade (Aboutness
being the dazzling blitzkrieg campaign) in support of taking seriously subject matter as a component of meaning
and reconciling philosophers to ways as a new primitive in metaphysics. Neither of these notions is complex: a
sentence’s subject matter is just what it’s about, and ways are, well, ways (as in ‘red is a way of being coloured’). Yet
they shed an astonishing amount of light on a wide range of familiar philosophical problems, including some of
the most ba%ing. As another example, take Wittgenstein’s question, ‘what is left over if I subtract the fact that my
arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm?’. It is at !rst very di$cult to get a handle on what Wittgenstein is
up to. But Yablo encourages us to think about it in the context of a host of more ordinary examples. To o#er a
few: we all agree, with the possible exception of Lizzy; he won, unless it turns out he cheated; the twins are
identical, ignoring their freckles; all was well, but for the cancer and impending divorce; his writing is exactly like
lightning, except in respect of speed. Each of these sentences involves logical subtraction (we start with perfect
agreement, then subtract Lizzy’s agreement); the peculiarity of Wittgenstein’s question is simply that the
implicated remainder – of ‘my raising my arm’ minus ‘my arming going up’ – isn’t well-de!ned. As for how to
calculate remainders: to heavily oversimplify, one !nds the part of the !rst sentence that’s silent on the subject
matter of the second. Other possible applications of the philosophy of aboutness include, to reel o# a few:
verisimilitude, partial truth, scepticism, parthood, modelling, con!rmation, vagueness, and permission.

In any case, Kripke and Yablo don’t just share similar views in the philosophy of language. Yablo also feels a strong
a$nity with a certain attitude he detects in Kripke’s writings, of thinking that – as Yablo writes in a review of
Kripke’s Philosophical Troubles – in philosophy, ‘there is no end to our troubles’. (Naming and Necessity
famously concludes, ‘I regard the mind-body problem as wide open and extremely confusing’.) ‘My feeling’, Yablo
tells me, ‘has always been one of !nding philosophy really hard’. He says he picked up this attitude when he was

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 5 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

still a student, and that it’s never left him. ‘Part of what happened’, he says, ‘was that I was taught by a lot of
people who thought it was almost de!nitional of philosophy that it should be really hard. People at Berkeley’ –
where Yablo attended graduate school – ‘had the idea that philosophical problems are part of the human
condition, and if you think you’ve solved one, that just shows you’ve misunderstood it’. Yablo gestures at Kant’s
line (as he does at the very end of Aboutness) that reason sets problems for itself that reason cannot solve. ‘So yes,
I do !nd it hard’, he says, ‘but one can de!nitely take this too far at times. I remember as a grad student at
Berkeley, when David Lewis came and gave a talk about causal explanation, that everybody, it wasn’t just me,
found it strange that he took himself to have “solved” something. I thought, well, then he’s basically just an
engineer, not a philosopher. I outgrew that attitude, let’s hope, but I do probably have more of a thing for the
mystery of philosophy than is common or popular these days. I think it should be hard. You should never really
feel you’ve got a grip on it.’

Yablo’s sense, not just that philosophy is hard, but that it is an important fact about philosophy that it is, in fact
pervades his work quite widely, sometimes in subtle ways. In the preface to Thoughts – the !rst of Yablo’s two
essay collections (the other is called Things) – Yablo writes that, like David Lewis, he ‘set out to be a piecemeal,
unsystematic philosopher’. He adds that, so far, he seems ‘to be doing a much better job of it’ than Lewis, who
ended up the greatest philosophical system-builder of the twentieth century. It is not until I talk to Yablo,
however, that it becomes clear to what extent this claim is not a confession or, perhaps, an apology; it is in a real
sense a statement of principle. It is understanding this that lets one start to see the connections between writings
that might otherwise not seem to hang together. ‘It’s always mattered to me’, Yablo says, ‘what’s worth worrying
about and what’s not worth worrying about. Two opposite things that bother me about a lot of philosophy is,
you know, trying to solve problems that are part of the human predicament – you shouldn’t have to, or want to,
solve them – and taking seriously problems that are just an artefact of​—’. At this point Yablo is interrupted by his
dog Daisy, who bursts yelping into the room. Daisy quickly takes a liking to me, or at least the taste of my hand,
and for the next hour, before Yablo’s son Isaac comes in and takes her, I never quite conquer the suspicion
(despite Yablo’s assurances) that at any moment Daisy might get hungry and take a bite.

Once things have settled, Yablo picks back up, grasping for the right way of putting his objection. ‘So most of my
upbringing was, certain problems are much more serious than people give them credit for, like scepticism’, he
says. ‘But then the other side of that is there are certain problems that just seem like they are artefacts of habits
that philosophers have got into, and they’re really just like…’ He trails o#. ‘Okay, here’s an example’, he says,
starting over. ‘Quine says, “you decide in favour of mathematical objects by realising you need to quantify over
them when you’re doing math”, and he goes, “I’m just deferring to what these practitioners of a much more
successful discipline are doing”.’ Here Yablo is referencing a classic argument, by Harvard philosopher WVO
Quine, for the existence of numbers, which supposedly takes as its starting point the simple observation that
scientists use numbers, and claims on this authority – the authority of science – that numbers exist. But physics
only uses sets up to a certain cardinality. So what does Quine say about discourse that makes use of higher-level
mathematical entities? That he regards it ‘only as mathematical recreation and without ontological rights’! Yet, as
philosopher of mathematics Penelope Maddy points out, no actual scientist attaches the slightest ontological
importance to the distinction between applicable sets and inapplicable ones; they don’t even try to look for the
line. ‘Basically what Quine does’, Yablo says, ‘is he goes around, locates some aspect of practice that he can
pretend to defer to, and then where it doesn’t actually have the form that he likes, he acts like the practitioners are
not applying their own principle consistently. There has to be a word for this… this self-serving, hypocritical, “I

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 6 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

just do what they say, unless it’s not what I want, in which case I correct in light of what they would have said if
they’d seen things as clearly as I do”.’

As Yablo goes on, the connection between this complaint – of, as one might have it, scientistic sanctimony – and
the earlier point, that philosophers tend to misrepresent the di$culty of problems, becomes clearer. One way of
putting it might be that both practices exhibit a peculiarly philosophical arrogance, involving, on the one hand,
the steamrolling of di$culties and complications that threaten one’s own view and, on the other, a blindness to
the merits of other positions. (Or as Bernard Williams and Michael Tanner once wrote about GEM Anscombe,
‘she combines a commonsense blu#ness against other people’s distinctions, with the most sensitive indulgence to
the niceties of her own’.) Another expression of this attitude, Yablo says, comes in the tendency to ‘pull down
linguistic facts from on high’, as if they univocally supported one’s own position. ‘There’s this pulling rank that
drives me completely nuts’, he tells me. ‘So !rst, you’re not supposed to play fast and loose and just make stu# up.
I get that and agree with it. But there’s an opposite danger, isn’t there, of getting unnecessarily dismissive and
carrying on like the only real grown-up in the room.’ Another manifestation is in the way some philosophers have
of declaring rival positions self-refuting or literally meaningless. Yablo references, for instance, one paper that says
a certain view about content involves a ‘transcendental contradiction’. ‘I just remember thinking’, he says, ‘that
there’s so much ingenuity wasted when things go that far. The idea that there are hidden contradictions in rival
views, in general, really bothers me. It’s not a bad enough fate for those views just to be seriously mistaken?’

This opposition to oversimpli!cation, of language and of the world, shines an interesting light on Yablo’s work.
Daniel Rothschild, another philosopher, wrote in a review of Aboutness that one could see the book in di#erent
ways. Some, Rothschild said, might see it as an extended defence of the non-existence of numbers and other
abstract objects, but he himself prefers to regard it as ‘an advertisement for a new way of thinking about meaning’.
When I quote this line to him, Yablo is very quick to say his view is much more Rothschild’s. ‘A lot of the
distinctions drawn in Aboutness’, he says, ‘are attempts to rehabilitate things that are held not to make sense’.
Indeed this focus on meaning Yablo takes to animate much of his earlier work on the meta-ontological question of
which !rst-order ontological debates (debates about what exists) are worth pursuing. In 1998, Yablo published a
paper ‘Does ontology rest on a mistake?’ that advocated ‘!guralism’ about certain abstract objects, like numbers.
He suggested that discourse involving abstract objects wasn’t to be taken literally, and that talk about numbers
doesn’t straightforwardly commit me to the existence of numbers any more than the sentence ‘the average star has
2.4 planets’ commits me to the existence of the average star, or the expression ‘he’s got a lot of smarts’ commits me
to the existence of smarts. The language of numbers, Yablo claimed, has presentational and representational
advantages: it lets us say things we perhaps couldn’t otherwise say; and it lets us represent the world more
e$ciently. As he points out in a di#erent paper, ‘That known truths cry out for numerical rearticulation could be
heard less as a theoretical argument for the objects’ existence, than a practical argument for postulating them quite
regardless of whether they exist’. (Numbers are, in that way, rather like God.)

This view has evolved over the last twenty years: from !guralism, to ‘presuppositionalism’, to, most recently, ‘if-
thenism’. The claim that numbers-talk is !gurative has been dropped; now the idea is that the existence of
numbers is presupposed by, so doesn’t enter into the assertive content of, sentences that refer to numbers.
Throughout all these iterations, Yablo says, ‘the issue has always been: what kind of talk involves you in what? It’s
really more about how to organise your intellectual resources, and when you’re committing yourself on this, while
not committing yourself on that.’ The project has also been to o#er up a positive account of what it might be for a

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 7 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

question to be objectively moot, for there to be no fact of the matter. He calls his position, in a catchy label,
quizzicalism. In an unpublished paper (‘do not quote or even think about too much’, its description reads), Yablo
suggests that the appropriate attitude towards mathematical ontology is one of insouciance: ‘don’t know and
don’t care, and come to think of it, don’t really see that there’s an issue here’. ‘Sometimes it seems’, he tells me,
‘that ontologists are just !ghting over the appropriate form of disdain to show towards ontological questions
about numbers’. He contrasts his view with the position of the ‘easy ontologist’, whose characteristic claim is that
it’s trivial that numbers exist. ‘I have taught seminars where I’ve tried to sort this out’, Yablo says, ‘and why I
thought even to say numbers obviously exist is to take the question too seriously, but to tell you the truth, I can’t
remember what my answer was’.

Understanding the quizzicalist project in these terms – as an e#ort, in the !rst instance, to make sense of linguistic
practice through a more realistic theory of meaning – also reveals a connection between the papers in Things
(which are mostly about the world) and those in Thoughts (which are mostly about the mind). There’s stu# in
Thoughts about mental causation and properties, but most of the collection concerns the mind-body problem,
which comes, in contemporary philosophy, to the question: what sort of relation does the mind bear to the
physical world? Descartes’ dualism – that mind and body are di#erent sorts of substances – is more or less out the
window, but the broadly physicalist view of the world that many of us !nd natural is still threatened by two
intuitions: !rst, that disembodied consciousness is possible; and second, that the world could have been exactly as
it is physically, but without any mental life. Kripke expresses the second intuition with characteristic clarity, saying
that one feels that when God created the world, he had to do more than simply !x all the physical facts; he had
also to make it the case that the neural state correlating with pain in humans should be felt ‘as pain, and not as a
tickle, or as warmth, or as nothing, as apparently would have been also within His powers’.

The issues here end up going very deep. A central problem is that of the relation between conceivability and
possibility. It seems that we have all sorts of modal knowledge – knowledge about di#erent ways things could have
been. For instance, I can know that I might never have been born, or that the Brexit vote might have gone the
other way. But the best, and seemingly only, evidence I have for these claims consists in my ability to conceive of
such things being the case; there’s no way of actually running the experiments. So if we’re not to be sceptics about
modal knowledge, it seems that we’re committed to conceivability evidence being accurate in most cases. The
exceptions we can allow ourselves are those where we have a good explanation of why, in that particular case, our
intuitions are apt to lead us astray. The alleged threat to physicalism, then, is that we don’t have the necessary
debunking explanations when it comes to the two non-physicalist intuitions mentioned; the standing policy,
therefore, should be to regard them as veridical. This, however, brings us to a prima facie peculiarity of the essays
in Thoughts, many of which spend time refuting the claim that philosophical zombies – persons who are just like
you and me, but for whom it is dark on the inside – are possible. Yablo’s papers on the theme, I !nd, are some of
the densest he’s written; and it can often appear as if he is exerting an awful lot of !repower in an e#ort to rescue
physicalism. Yet it would be strange if this were the case, because, as it happens, Yablo himself isn’t a committed
physicalist. The earliest of the essays in the collection in fact challenges the dismissal of the Cartesian intuition
that the mind could have failed to be physically realised. So what’s going on?

Unsurprisingly, Yablo’s central aim turns out to be defending a Kripkean theory of meaning against a rival view
called two-dimensionalism. According to two-dimensionalism, very roughly, to grasp the meaning of a term
involves the ability to work out a priori, given a canonical description of any possible scenario, whether that

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 8 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

scenario contains any instances of the term. So, for instance, some two-dimensionalists might claim that what’s
involved in understanding the term ‘umbrella’ is being able to say – without any empirical investigation –
whether, having been given a description of some world in the terms of physics, that world contains umbrellas.
But, Yablo asks me rhetorically, when has anyone, when asked to demonstrate they knew what a word meant, ever
been required to perform that computation? And how could they? ‘It’s not’, he says, ‘as though anyone ever
applied a word like “TV” by trying to infer its application from some lower-level description.’ So it is this
complaint that has led Yablo into the fray over physicalism. The standard arguments from the conceivability of
zombies to their possibility tend to rely on (something like) a two-dimensionalist conception of understanding
and meaning. They say we can imagine that everything is physically exactly like so – this is the part where we are
told how the world is in some canonical description – without being sure one way or another whether the world
we’ve imagined contains mental life. But what goes for umbrellas goes for mental predicates: if I wouldn’t be able
to infer the existence of umbrellas from such a description, why would I be able to infer the existence of pain? ‘If
you’ve got a concept’, Yablo says to me, ‘that you grasp via an ability to apply it, then you’re not necessarily going
to know whether it applies when you’re just given a description. It’s like, I can’t tell if someone is lovable-looking
by being told where all the molecules are in their face.’

More generally, the problem is with a certain mode of theorising, with philosophy that expends a great deal of
ingenuity to make simple what isn’t simple. Philosophical presumptiveness is once again a culprit. ‘It’s one thing’,
Yablo says, ‘to adopt a theory as a regulative ideal. My old supervisor, Bas van Fraassen, believes that an empiricist
is something you try to be. But it’s another thing entirely to say, “Oh yeah, this takes care of everything”. And
then, when it doesn’t, to engage in burden-shifting, or remake heaven and earth around the seeming
counterexamples. I don’t know, it just seems to get things backwards.’ Yablo !nishes this comment with
something of a sigh, and backtracks to clarify that he has very signi!cant admiration for the individual
philosophers – like David Chalmers and Frank Jackson – who push a two-dimensionalist line. ‘I don’t know why
I get a bee in my bonnet about these particular issues’, he says. ‘It just seems, sometimes, that a lot of intelligent
e#ort gets wasted.’ This observation segues into a broader point, in a similar connection, about philosophical
methodology. ‘Some people have made this remark, that there’s a bit of an analogy between scientism and
positivism’, Yablo says, in that they both seem to involve the stance ‘it’s very hard to !gure out what’s really going
on, but as luck would have it, we’re really good at !guring out how to !gure out – with observational testing, say
– what’s really going on. Whereas you’d think the second thing would be harder.’ He compares this with how
we’d react to someone who come along and said that she’d !gured out a general framework for determining the
quality of a poem, but was for technical reasons unable to use it to assess particular poems. ‘Everybody could see
how funny that is’, Yablo says. ‘But the same thing happens in philosophy all the time.’

This emphasis on the particular – on addressing problems rather than developing theories, thinking small (as,
Yablo says, is his preferred mode), paying attention to the nuances of language – is a !nal aspect worth
highlighting of Yablo’s approach. Or maybe it simply falls out once the rest has been established: the feeling that
philosophy is very di$cult, and ought to be; that one has to be careful not to run roughshod over important
distinctions; that the world contains complexities; that a characteristic failing of philosophy is a tendency to
oversimplify; that it is better to err on the side of humility than of self-satisfaction. But it is also perhaps worth
making another observation, familiar from some criticisms of JL Austin-style linguistic philosophy, that the
approach itself can’t take you all the way. ‘Do numbers exist?’ , for instance, has the ring of a very deep question; it
is hardly uncontroversial to claim, in e#ect, that, if the question seems to reverberate a long time, this is because it

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 9 von 10


In a Quizzical Spirit: An Interview with Stephen Yablo | Oxford Review of Books 19.10.18, 20)21

can be hard to hear the di#erence between the profound and vacuous. Mightn’t there be a tension then, between
the insistence on respecting the lay of the land, and the fairly bold claim about the way the land in fact lies? There
is, I think, but not in the approach itself. It is rather between an idealistic view of philosophy, as a universal,
democratic institution, and the reality of philosophical practice, which requires that one, not only reasons clearly,
but sees clearly as well.

ABOUT THE AUTHOR

DANIEL KODSI

Daniel is a founding editor of the Oxford Review of Books, and will be reading for a BPhil in
Philosophy from October 2018. He can be reached at daniel.kodsi@balliol.ox.ac.uk.

PREVIOUS POST

← Penelope

http://the-orb.org/2018/09/27/in-a-quizzical-spirit/ Seite 10 von 10

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen