Sie sind auf Seite 1von 11

Criticism

Volume 54 | Issue 4 Article 6

2012

Shame Now: Ruth Leys Diagnoses the New Queer


Shame Culture
J. Keith Vincent
Boston University, kvincent@bu.edu

Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.wayne.edu/criticism

Recommended Citation
Vincent, J. Keith (2012) "Shame Now: Ruth Leys Diagnoses the New Queer Shame Culture," Criticism: Vol. 54: Iss. 4, Article 6.
Available at: http://digitalcommons.wayne.edu/criticism/vol54/iss4/6
Shame Now: Ruth In From Guilt to Shame, Ruth Leys
follows up on her earlier work on
Leys Diagnoses the genealogy of trauma studies by
the New Queer tracing the emergence and even-
Shame Culture tual discrediting of theories of sur-
J. Keith Vincent vival guilt since the end of World
War II.1 In the process, she tells a
fascinating story of a gradual shift
From Guilt to Shame: Auschwitz
in trauma studies away from psy-
and After by Ruth Leys. Princeton,
chodynamic theories that empha-
NJ: Princeton University Press,
sized the subject’s uncontrollable
2007. Pp. 216. $25.95 paper.
mimetic identification with the ag-
gressor towards anti-­psychoanalytic
understandings of purely external
stressors and traumatic images as
the causes of trauma. In the book’s
latter chapters, however, the focus
shifts to a critique of recent work
in affect theory, including a highly
problematic reading of the work of
the late queer theorist Eve Kosof-
sky Sedgwick. Leys interprets the
work of Sedgwick “and her follow-
ers” not only as a further develop-
ment of the anti-psychoanalytic
tendencies that have conspired to
discredit the diagnosis of survivor
guilt, but also as symptomatic of
a larger, culturewide shift “from
guilt to shame,” away from “ques-
tions of agency and responsibility”
and towards what she misleadingly
characterizes as a disengaged and
solipsistic focus on identity. Since
the publication of this book in 2007,
Leys has continued to mount simi-
lar critiques, both of Sedgwick’s
work and of the whole enterprise
of shame-based affect theory. This
review attempts to address that
critique as it appears both in From

Criticism Fall 2012, Vol. 54, No. 4, pp. 623–632. ISSN 0011-1589. 623
© 2012 by Wayne State University Press, Detroit, Michigan 48201-1309
624 J. Keith Vincent

Guilt to Shame and in an interview not actually committed is a sign of


and article that have appeared in the permeability of the subject and
the interim.2 its vulnerability to immersive mi-
First I should make it clear that metic identification and the sway
Leys’s book does provide an im- of fantasy. Another way of saying
passioned, and I would say impor- this would be that the notion of
tant, defense of what she calls the survivor guilt is incomprehensible
mimetic school of trauma theory. without a psychoanalytic under-
In this way of thinking, traumatic standing of subjectivity. So the de-
experiences are marked and exac- nial of survivor guilt is tantamount
erbated by uncontrollable identi- to the repudiation of psychoanaly-
fication and merging with others, sis. One goal of Leys’s book, then, is
sometimes even the aggressor re- to remind us of the psychoanalytic
sponsible for causing the trauma. insight that we can think and desire
The founding instability of the things in our unconscious that we
subject that this reflects is one of the would find morally repugnant in
most fundamental tenets of psy- our waking lives, but that this does
choanalysis, so it is easy to under- not necessarily make us complicit
stand why Leys, as a thinker with with evil.
a strong psychoanalytic bent, might In chapter 4, however, which
be critical of the attempt to replace she describes as “arguably the heart
it with antimimetic theories like of my book,” Leys moves into more
that of Terrence Des Pres and oth- problematic territory. Here “the
ers for whom the cause of trauma theme of trauma . . . recedes,” and
is understood as entirely external to she draws a connection between
the subject and “uncontaminated the antimimetic critiques of survi-
by any mimetic, fictive, or fantas- vor guilt and contemporary shame
matic dimension” (15). The impor- theory, which she sees as having
tance of survivor guilt to Leys has “taken the place” of survivor guilt,
to do with the fact that we experi- replacing its “intentionalist para-
ence it over actions that occur only digm” with an “anti-intentionalist”
mimetically and in fantasy (like our and “material” one (16). In Leys’s
“murderous” wish that someone narrative, the rejection of survivor
else would die in our place), so it guilt gives rise to a culturewide
serves as a sort of proof of the mi- preoccupation with shame as “a
metic theory of trauma. As she puts dominant emotional reference in
it, “[T]he concept of survivor guilt the West” (4). She portrays this shift
is inseparable from the notion of “from guilt to shame” in alarmist
the subject’s unconscious identifica- terms as a shift “away from ques-
tion with the other” (10). Our abil- tions of human agency” (150),
ity to feel guilt over crimes we have leading to “an impulse to displace
On Leys’s From Guilt to Shame 625

questions about our moral respon- terms that seem so at odds with her
sibility for what we do  in favor of sophisticated psychoanalytic cri-
more ethically neutral or different tique of antimimetic trauma theory
questions about our personal attri- in the book’s earlier chapters?
butes” (131; emphasis in original),
and she predicts that the displace-
ment of guilt with shame will lead Shame Theory, Identity,
to a sort of narcissistic quietism that Subjectivity
entails nothing less than “giving up
disagreement about intention and Despite Leys’s argument to the
meaning” (13). contrary, shame theory (especially
This represents a crisis for Leys. Sedgwick’s) cannot be grouped
But rather than discuss this sup- alongside or seen as a logical devel-
posed shift in the same psycho- opment of those antimimetic theo-
analytic terms she used to critique ries that see trauma as a “purely
antimimetic trauma theory, Leys external event that befalls a fully
resorts to decidedly unpsychoana- constituted if passive subject” (9).
lytic notions of individual agency Shame may be about “who one is”
and responsibility to sound her more than “what one does,” but
warning. Whereas in chapters 1–3 that does not mean that shame the-
she advocates a complex and rigor- ory assumes the existence of a “fully
ously psychoanalytic understand- constituted subject.” In Sedgwick’s
ing of the psyche and critiques work, shame is “not at all the place
what she calls a “quasireligious idea where identity is most securely at-
of a conscience” (66) in the work tached to essences, but rather . . .
of Terrence Des Pres and “more the place where the question of
traditional notions of individual identity arises most originarily and
responsibility and consciousness” most relationally.”3
(14) in the work of Robert Lifton, Sedgwick is interested in iden-
in her treatment of shame theory tity and she sees shame as a crucial
in chapter 4 she seems almost to mechanism of its constitution, but
be channeling Des Pres and Lif- this does not mean that she sees
ton, becoming herself a defender shame as an “attribute of person-
of moralistic notions of personal re- hood” (131) as Leys claims. The
sponsibility, agency, meaning, and phrase “attribute of personhood”
intentionality. The question arises, suggests a static understanding of
why does Leys feel the need to por- the self that reverberates instead
tray the recent upsurge in interest with Leys’s own condescending
in shame as the consequence of the judgment of what she seems to
rejection of survivor guilt and to see as the naïve identitarianism of
do so in such alarmist, moralizing shame theory (and implicitly of
626 J. Keith Vincent

queer theory). Leys’s work, in other as if it were a synonym for “gay” or


words, is based on a fundamental “lesbian” identity. In the absence of
misunderstanding of queer theory any discussion of what exactly Leys
and the queer critique of identity. herself means by “queer identity,”
This is made very obvious early we are forced to assume that she
in chapter 4 when she describes sees queerness as another one of
Sedgwick’s work as being “focused those (or perhaps even the proto-
on questions of queer identity, not typical) “personal attributes” that
trauma” (125). Anyone who has shame theorists want to focus on
read any of Sedgwick’s work (see solipsistically.
especially her classic essay “How to It is remarkable that Leys says
Bring Your Kids Up Gay”) knows almost nothing about the context of
that, for Sedgwick, (a) being queer Sedgwick’s work on shame. Leys
does constitute trauma in a het- does describe her as a queer theo-
eronormative society and (b) queer rist but does little to explain how
identity is an oxymoron since queer that might inform Sedgwick’s in-
is a term invented precisely in order terest in shame. At one point, Leys
to critique and deconstruct identity.4 writes, “Normally we cannot be
Queer theorists like Sedgwick held responsible for who we are in
might use the term queer to modify the same way we can be held re-
people now and then, but they are sponsible for what we do—or what
always careful to insist that queer- we imagine we have done” (131),
ness does not designate any stable after which she proceeds to explain
set of subjective experiences or any how guilt and survivor guilt inevi-
easily defined demographic group. tably entail questions of responsi-
Often Sedgwick put it in scare bility and agency while shame is
quotes to signal that it is far from a “the affect of disempowerment”
self-evident term, or even in paren- (132). But this distinction between
theses and scare quotes in moments what you do and who you are is, in
when she might seem to be suggest- the case of queer theory, not at all
ing otherwise, as when she writes one that can be taken for granted in
that “at least for certain (‘queer’) the way that the word “normally”
people shame is simply the first, in this sentence so blithely suggests.
and remains a permanent, structur- As Sedgwick taught us long ago,
ing fact of identity” (64).5 Needless the distinction between “conduct”
to say, Sedgwick’s own position as a and “status” is nothing less than a
“straight” woman who considered constitutive double bind for queer-
herself queer made her exquisitely identified people. “Normal” people
aware of the shifty malleability (the “we” of Leys’s sentence) may
of the term. But Leys uses “queer not be held responsible just for who
identity” quite unproblematically they are, but minorities of all kinds
On Leys’s From Guilt to Shame 627

certainly have been and in many experience of pure difference,”


respects continue to be shamed for however, Leys produces a carica-
who they are. The oppression of ture of Sedgwick’s interest in dif-
queer-identified people derives its ference, reducing it to the level of
energy, moreover, not just from a simplistic fixation on “personal
shame but from a constant “heads- identity.” Sedgwick’s emphasis on
I-win–tails-you-lose” shifting back the ways in which people are dif-
and forth between guilt and shame. ferent from each other was never
This is made clear in the endless about passive resignation to the
“nature vs. nurture” debates about status quo or a navel-gazing inter-
what makes people gay, or lesbian, est in “personal identity.” It was a
or transgender, or otherwise queer. way of combating a cultural order
If being queer is a choice, then that she saw as aggressively, and
you’re guilty for having made it. sometimes murderously, enforc-
And if it’s a biological condition, ing consensus and uniformity. Far
then we ought to find a cure! If from being a way to avoid conflict
guilt is about “conduct” and shame or ignore “meaning and intention,”
is about “status,” it is the double it was a way to explore the most
bind between them that is espe- subtle and extreme forms of dif-
cially relevant to the experience of ference. This is not at all “ethically
queers. Or, rather, the specific way neutral.” It is the hard work of eth-
in which shame and guilt interact ics. Her interest in shame stemmed
around queerness is itself consti- from a deep interest in what it feels
tutive of the experience of being like to be minoritized. And while
queer. So no wonder Sedgwick, as she was really, truly, respectfully in-
a queer theorist, was interested in terested in how people are different
joining this debate. from each other, she also wanted
Leys writes that Sedgwick is to understand how the majority is
interested in shame because it is constituted by exploiting, distort-
a “technology for creating queer ing, and ignoring these differences.
identity as the experience of pure
difference” (154). This is a very
extreme way of describing what Objectless Emotions
is actually a very nuanced idea
with which Sedgwick does smart Another aspect of Sedgwick’s work
and beautiful things in her writ- that worries Leys is the way in
ing, including the notion of the which shame theory and other af-
“nonce taxonomy” with its tension fect theory supposedly strips the
between unclassifiable uniqueness emotions of their “meaning” and
and rigorous systematicity.6 With their proper objects. For Sedgwick,
the phrase “queer identity as the following Silvan Tomkins, affects
628 J. Keith Vincent

are distinguished from the drives order to understand why this the-
by their ability to attach to any kind ory of affects might be appealing to
of object. So while hunger, for ex- Sedgwick, we have to see her work
ample, has food as its only object, within the context of the longer his-
interest, enjoyment, rage, or shame tory of queer theory. In her interest
can be felt in relation to all kinds in the freedom of the affects, Sedg-
of objects, including other affects. wick is actually following the lead
This lack of an intrinsic connection of Freud, who first decoupled the
between the affects and their objects object from the “aim” of sexuality
means that they are much freer than in his Three Essays on the Theory of
the drives, and for both Sedgwick Sexuality (1905), arguing that they
and Tomkins this is what accounts were not connected by any natural
for the extraordinary richness and necessity, but “merely soldered to-
malleability of human motivation gether.”7 By denying any intrinsic
and experience. For Leys, however, connection between the aim and
this same freedom of the affects the object of the libido, Freud was
sounds impoverishingly arbitrary able to denaturalize heterosexual-
because it ity, a crucial first step in the theo-
rization of sexuality. “From the
makes it a delusion to say that point of view of psychoanalysis,” he
you are happy because your wrote, “the exclusive sexual inter-
child got a job, or sad because est felt by men for women is also a
your mother died, for the problem that needs elucidating and
simple reason that your child’s is not a self-evident fact based upon
getting a job or your mother’s an attraction that is ultimately of a
death are merely triggers for chemical nature.”8
your happiness or sadness, The affects, of course, are even
which are themselves innate freer than the Freudian libido,
affect programs that could in which is one reason why affect
principle be triggered by any- theory is so appealing to Sedgwick.
thing else. (147) Leys follows Sedgwick up until
this point, recognizing her appre-
This move is typical of Leys’s ciation of the lack of instrumen-
somewhat exaggerated rhetorical tality and freedom of the affects
strategy. Just because there is no as a way to critique the Freud-
necessary connection between an ian repressive hypothesis, according
affect and its object does not mean to which all human behavior is
that there is no connection at all or to be explained by the pulsations
that once that connection is formed of a single, end-oriented libidi-
it does not have any meaning or in- nal drive. But she draws the line
tentionality. But be that as it may, in at Sedgwick and Tomkins’s claim
On Leys’s From Guilt to Shame 629

that this freedom of object choice particular and the subjective, and
also implies that the affects can be the reader’s interpretation matters
autotelic in nature. “I consider this more than the author’s intention.
a mistake,” she writes: “It doesn’t In other words, she sees shame
follow that because the affects can theory like that of Tomkins and
have a multiplicity—even a vast Sedgwick as partaking in a (for her,
multiplicity—of objects they are dystopian) postmodern worldview.
inherently without any relation to Not surprisingly, she cites Walter
objects whatsoever. The mistake, in Benn Michaels here on the “end
other words, is thinking that hav- of history” and the “posthistoricist
ing multiple objects undoes objec- valuation of identity” and suggests
tality altogether.” This is another that this is where Sedgwick’s work
huge leap. It is one thing to say that is leading us.9
there is no inherent or intrinsically I am not in a position to judge
necessary relation between an affect whether Leys’s claim that the work
and its object, or even that affects of Tomkins and others such as Paul
can be self-amplifying (hence auto- Ekman on the universal and innate
telic), and quite another to say that (rather than culturally determined
this “undoes objectality altogether.” and cognitively driven) nature of
Leys puts the ostensibly disturbing the affect system on which much of
conclusion to be drawn from this Sedgwick’s work is based is scien-
“mistake” in italics: “In short, for tifically inaccurate. It must be said,
Tomkins and Sedgwick the affects are however, that for Sedgwick it mat-
nonintentional states” (135). ters much less whether it is right
It is by no means clear that Sedg- or wrong than whether it is use-
wick and Tomkins would actually ful and productive as a theoretical
go so far as this. But it is clear that ­paradigm—whether it is “good to
the idea make Leys very nervous. think with.” As Leys also points out,
The nightmarish conclusion that Sedgwick is quite open about her
she draws from it is that Sedgwick’s own position on this. She called it
“theory of affect therefore appears
to give primacy to the feelings of a moving from the rather fix-
subject without a psychology and ated question Is a particular
without an external world” (148). piece of knowledge true?
For Leys, the idea that affects and how can we know? to
would not mean anything leads the further questions: What
straight to a world where people does knowledge do?—the
are content just to feel their differ- pursuit of it, the having and
ences from one another rather than exposing of it, the receiving
argue over them, where the univer- again of knowledge one al-
sal and the true are eclipsed by the ready knows? How, in short,
630 J. Keith Vincent

is knowledge performa- emphasis on guilt alter our un-


tive, and how best does one derstanding of the construction of
move among its causes and queer identity?” Leys responds by
effects?10 saying, “[A]t least it would make
questions of meaning and agency
It may be simply that the per- of central interest because . . . guilt
formative effect and value of af- is tied to the question of one’s (real
fect theory in the context of literary or imagined) intentions to act in a
studies, where it is not in the major- certain way, whereas shame shifts
ity, is different from its effect and attention from questions of agency
value in the context of psychology, and meaning to questions of per-
where it is. Leys wants to back up sonal identity.”11
her own position with the author- It is hard to determine precisely
ity of scientific proof when in fact what Leys is suggesting here, al-
it seems that she herself may be though one might be forgiven for
motivated to defend the guilt side thinking that she is saying that
because she prefers to “think with queers are somehow evading re-
guilt.” Rather than being up front sponsibility (for their queerness?)
about this, however, she appeals to by focusing too much on shame
the authority of science. and too little on guilt. And yet she
hastens to add that she is not com-
pletely rejecting the “relevance of
*** shame” either. She assures us later
in the same paragraph that “noth-
But what is really a shame about ing I say critically about shame the-
Leys’s book is its refusal to en- ory today is meant to reject the view
gage with shame theory, especially that shame may be an appropri-
queer shame theory on its own ate response to certain situations.”
terms. She is so intent on recount- The wording here is nothing short
ing her own narrative of cultural of ­bizarre—as if the question ever
decline from guilt to shame that was, or ever could be, whether or
she misses almost everything that not shame was appropriate.
is valuable about what these writ- For myself, as a queer theorist
ers are doing. One has the sense in and a scholar of Japanese literature,
reading her work that she is simply I cannot help but be reminded in
not interested in it. In a recent in- reading Leys’s work of the tired
terview, she was asked a question and (one thought) discredited ar-
that, despite its potentially ominous guments that anthropologists used
implications, might actually have to make about so-called shame cul-
led in a productive direction. That ture versus guilt culture. This argu-
question was “How would your ment, which formed the backbone
On Leys’s From Guilt to Shame 631

of one of the most devastating the alarming story of what she calls
forms of Western Orientalism, was “shame’s revival.”13 So for Leys, it
most famously put forth in Ruth would seem, we are all in danger
Benedict’s wartime book The Chry- of turning Japanese. But it is simply
santhemum and the Sword (1946), a wrong to characterize the rise of an
work that, as Marylin Ivy has re- interest in shame among queer-af-
cently put it, “produced Japan as a fect theorists as what Leys describes
‘shame culture’ for American de- as “a means of avoiding the moral-
lectation.” Benedict argued (with- isms associated with the notion
out ever visiting Japan) that the of guilt.” This makes it sound as
Japanese had no sense of self strong though “Sedgwick and others” are
enough to experience guilt—the somehow trying to get away with
latter being the hallmark of more something that is morally suspect.
“advanced” Western cultures. As In my view, and I think in Sedg-
Ivy puts it, in Benedict’s book, wick’s, guilt and shame are not so
easily separated, and certainly not
Ashamed, shame appears as useful in isolation as descriptors ei-
less developed, less autono- ther of entire cultures or whole his-
mous, less evolved than guilt. torical moments, be they Japanese
Shame is felt always in rela- or queer, then or now.
tion to the Other, unlike guilt
with its sturdy, consistent J. Keith Vincent is an assistant professor
standards of morality (guilt is of Japanese and Comparative Literature
at Boston University. He is the author of
confessable). Shame is more Two-Timing Modernity: Homosocial
primitive. Shame allows the Narrative in Modern Japanese Fiction
most heinous deeds, and all is (forthcoming in the fall of 2012 from the
Harvard Asia Center). With Erin Murphy,
well, as long as these crimes he coedited “Honoring Eve: Essays on the
are not exposed to the gaze Work of Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick,” a special
of the world. Guilt does not issue of Criticism (52, no. 2 [2010]).
depend on crime’s revelation.
Guilt is internalized, autono- Notes
mous; shame is external-
ized, heteronomous. Guilt 1. See Ruth Leys, Trauma: A Genealogy
is fixed; shame is mutable. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
2000).
Guilt is American; shame is
2. Leys is apparently at work on a book-
Japanese.12 length critique of affect theory, which
she has previewed in this recent inter-
Leys herself cites Benedict’s work view and article: Ruth Leys, “Navigat-
and the notion of shame cultures ing the Genealogies of Trauma, Guilt,
and Affect: An Interview with Ruth
completely uncritically at the be- Leys,” interview by Marlene Goldman,
ginning of chapter 4, which tells University of Toronto Quarterly 79, no. 2
632 J. Keith Vincent

(2010): 656–79; and Leys “The Turn to Strachey, 24 vols. (London: Hogarth
Affect: A Critique” Critical Inquiry 37, Press, 1995), 7:123–245, quotation on
no. 3 (2011): 434–72. 148.
3. Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, “Shame, 8. Ibid., 146.
Theatricality, Queer Performativity:
9. See 154–56 for the discussion of Walter
Henry James’s The Art of the Novel,”
Benn Michaels.
in Touching Feeling: Affect, Pedagogy,
Performativity, Series Q (Durham, NC: 10. Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, “Paranoid
Duke University Press, 2003), 35–65, Reading and Reparative Reading,” in
quotation on 37. Sedgwick, Touching Feeling (see note 3),
123–51, quotation on 124.
4. Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, “How to
Bring Your Kids Up Gay: The War on 11. Leys and Goldman, “Navigating the
Effeminate Boys,” in Tendencies, Series Genealogies,” 677.
Q (Durham: Duke University Press,
12. See Marylin Ivy, “Benedict’s Shame,”
1993), 154–64.
Cabinet 31 (2008): 64>N>68, accessed
5. Sedgwick, “Shame,” 64. 16 April 2012, http://cabinetmagazine.
org/issues/31/index.php.
6. On this, see Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick,
Epistemology of the Closet, Centennial 13. In From Guilt to Shame Leys writes
Books (Durham, NC: Duke University “Benedict emphasized the public
Press, 1990), 22–23. dimension of shame, its dependence
on external rather than internal (or
7. Sigmund Freud, Three Essays of the
internalized) sanctions, and the absence
Theory of Sexuality (1905), in The Stan-
of confession and atonement in shame
dard Edition of the Complete Psychologi-
cultures” (123fn2).
cal Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. James

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen