Sie sind auf Seite 1von 8

Cladistics

Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8


10.1111/j.1096-0031.2009.00266.x

Species and kinds: a critique of RieppelÕs ‘‘one of a kind’’ account of


species
Thomas A.C. Reydon
Leibniz Universität Hannover, Center for Philosophy and Ethics of Science (ZEWW), Im Moore 21, Hannover D-30167, Germany
Accepted 22 April 2009

Abstract

A major issue in philosophical debates on the species problem concerns the opposition between two seemingly incompatible views
of the metaphysics of species: the view that species are individuals and the view that species are natural kinds. In two recent papers in
this journal, Olivier Rieppel suggested that this opposition is much less deep than it seems at first sight. Rieppel used a recently
developed philosophical account of natural kindhood, namely Richard BoydÕs ‘‘homeostatic property cluster’’ theory, to argue that
every species taxon can be conceived of as an individual that constitutes the single member of its own specific natural kind. In this
paper I criticize RieppelÕs approach and argue that it does not deliver what it is supposed to, namely an account of species as kinds
about which generalized statements can be made.
 The Willi Hennig Society 2009.

Introduction Richard BoydÕs ‘‘homeostatic property cluster’’ theory


(henceforth HPC theory), to develop his account of
One of the main issues arising in the context of the species as natural kinds. However, as I argue in the
species problem concerns the opposition between two present paper, RieppelÕs approach does not yield what it
seemingly incompatible views of the metaphysical is intended to deliver, namely an account of species as
nature of species. On the one hand there is the natural kinds over which inferences can be made that
traditional view that species are natural kinds of convey knowledge about the member organisms of
organisms. On the other hand there is the much more species. My aim in this paper is not to criticize HPC
recent view that species are individuals, that is, concrete, theory in general, or to question its applicability to the
particular entities that have organisms as their principal case of species, but only to point to some problems with
constituent parts. Commonly, these views of species are the particular way in which Rieppel used HPC theory to
thought of as fundamentally incompatible: either species construct an account of species as natural kinds. (To
are natural kinds, or they are individuals, but they avoid any misunderstanding of my position, I should
certainly arenÕt both. emphasize that I think there may well be good ways to
In two recent papers in this journal, Rieppel (2007a, conceive of species as natural kinds under HPC
2008; see also Rieppel, 2009) suggested that this oppo- theory—I just do not think that RieppelÕs ‘‘one of a
sition is much less deep than it seems at first sight. kind’’ approach is one of these.)
Rieppel suggested that species names such as Panthera
tigris should be conceived of as denoting both individ-
uals and natural kinds. Rieppel used a recently devel- Rieppel on species
oped philosophical account of natural kindhood,
The species problem encompasses a number of
Corresponding author: different questions, including which are the relevant
E-mail address: reydon@ww.uni-hannover.de criteria to use when ranking taxa as species, and whether

 The Willi Hennig Society 2009


2 T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8

a criterion of monophyly should be imposed on species apply across natural kinds. But biological research has
taxa. At the heart of the problem, however, lies the shown that there are no laws of nature that pertain to
metaphysical question concerning what species are. Are particular species, at least not in the sense in which laws
they merely groupings of organisms constructed by us of nature are generally conceived. This situation, Ghis-
for various purposes and in relation to our various elin and Hull argued, was precisely what was to be
interests, or are they real entities that exist objectively expected when species were not kinds at all, but
‘‘out there’’ in nature? And if species are real entities, are spatiotemporally limited entities—that is, individuals.
they best conceived of as natural kinds of organisms, in As individuals with organisms as their constituent parts,
the same way as the chemical elements are thought of as species are just not the sort of thing that have kind
natural kinds of atoms, or should they be conceived of essences (species could still have individual essences,
as concrete material entities of which organisms are the though) or that feature in statements of laws of nature.
basic constituent parts? Both philosophers and biolo- Moreover, this view of species fits better with what
gists have long been concerned with this issue, and all biology tells us about species (that species have unique
the aforementioned positions have been advocated in origins, undergo evolutionary change, etc.) than does
the ongoing debate on the topic (for overviews see e.g. the natural kinds view.
Stamos, 2003; Reydon, 2005; Ereshefsky, 2007). Commonly, the metaphysical views that species are
In the context of the present paper, one aspect of the individuals and that species are natural kinds are
discussion on the nature of species is particularly thought of as fundamentally incompatible. After all,
important. According to a commonly accepted view in individuals are spatiotemporally limited, concrete enti-
philosophy, things can belong to either of two meta- ties that can feature in processes of change over time,
physical categories: any given thing is either a concrete while natural kinds are spatiotemporally unlimited,
particular (that is, an individual), or a collection (a set, abstract entities that cannot undergo any change over
class or kind) of things. Analysis of a particular case time. (Of course, new instances of a natural kind can
may show that some things have been allocated to the come into being, and old instances can go out of
wrong metaphysical category, but it is not very likely existence, but this does not involve the change of the
that we find that something belongs in both categories. natural kind itself, as kinds are defined intensionally in
In recent history, biological species have been discussed contrast to sets, which are defined extensionally.) Hence,
as a case in which things were allocated to the wrong if biological species are indeed individuals, they cannot
category: species have traditionally been counted as be natural kinds. At present, most biologists and
natural kinds of organisms, until it was suggested in the philosophers of biology opt for the individuals view of
1960s–1970s that they are better conceived of as species.
concrete particulars than as natural kinds. Credit for Rieppel (2007a, 2008) also subscribed to the individ-
the suggestion is usually placed with Ghiselin (1966, uals view of species; as he put it: ‘‘On grounds of
1974), who proposed the idea, and Hull (1976, 1978), spatiotemporal boundedness, any biological entity at
who propagated it; however, the idea is also found in any level of complexity subject to evolutionary processes
earlier works by Ernst Mayr and Willi Hennig. is an individual’’ (Rieppel, 2007a; p. 373). But, Rieppel
Ghiselin and Hull observed that traditional philo- added, there are good reasons also to conceive of species
sophical accounts of natural kinds did not fit the role of as natural kinds. For one, species names are commonly
species in biology on at least two counts. First, natural featured in predicative statements in biological reason-
kinds are traditionally linked to essentialism, that is, the ing (Rieppel, 2005; pp. 473–474; Rieppel, 2006; p. 194;
claim that every natural kind is associated with a kind Rieppel, 2007a; p. 374ff.; Rieppel, 2007b; pp. 357–358;
essence (an intrinsic microstructure, a set of intrinsic Rieppel, 2008; p. 599). We can identify a particular
properties, etc.). This essence explains the observable organism as a Panthera tigris, attribute a particular
properties of all the kindÕs members, in the sense that an predicate (the predicate of being a Panthera tigris) to it,
entityÕs kind essence causally underlies their observable and in so doing make a statement that conveys some
properties. In addition, possession of a particular kind knowledge about it. After all, when we know that an
essence constitutes a necessary and sufficient condition organism is a Panthera tigris, we can reliably infer that it
for membership of the kind associated with this essence: will very probably exhibit numerous properties and
all and only the members of a particular natural kind behaviours that organisms of that species typically
instantiate this kindÕs essence. In the case of species, exhibit: ‘‘token tigers inherit the largest upper canines
however, it has become clear that there are no species amongst all living cats from their parents […]. It is such
essences in the aforementioned sense. On the second causally efficacious properties that render generaliza-
count, theories of natural kinds usually link natural tions across tigers […] possible, and it is by virtue of
kinds to laws of nature: natural kinds are supposed to be these shared, causally efficacious properties that tigers
those kinds that feature in laws of nature; conversely, […] are tokens of natural kinds’’ (Rieppel, 2007b;
laws of nature are supposed to be those regularities that p. 357; also Rieppel, 2006; p. 194). An important
T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8 3

epistemic role of species names in biological reasoning, readings it does not yield a useful account of species as
then, is to function in generalizations about the prop- natural kinds, while on the third reading the account is
erties and behaviours of the organisms that belong to not novel (rather, it is precisely the account that Boyd
the species denoted by the species names that feature in proposed), and is internally not consistent in that it
these generalizations—and this is an epistemic role that conflicts with RieppelÕs assertion that species are
is typically performed by natural kind terms. In addi- uniquely instantiated natural kinds. But in order to be
tion, Rieppel (2005, pp. 469–470; Rieppel, 2006, 2008) able to assess the usefulness of RieppelÕs account of
maintained, it must be possible for species names to species as natural kinds, two issues need to be clarified
change their extensions in taxonomic revisions. If new first.
data become available that compel us to exclude a group
of organisms from a species in which it was included
before (or the other way around), the extension of the Two questions
species name changes. But if species names are proper
names of individuals, Rieppel argued, such a change of The first of these questions concerns the precise
extension isnÕt possible; hence species names need also to nature of the individuals that, on RieppelÕs account,
be conceived of as referring to kinds. There seems, then, constitute the sole members of species as natural kinds.
to be a need to come up with an account of species as As, in philosophy, there are different ways of conceiving
natural kinds to accommodate the epistemic roles of of individuality, it is important to achieve clarity about
species names in biological reasoning. what exactly species-as-individuals are on RieppelÕs
Rieppel found the required account of natural kinds account.
in BoydÕs HPC theory, which I discuss in more detail in RieppelÕs suggestion is that species-as-individuals are
the next section. According to Rieppel, a species can be ‘‘spatiotemporally located (i.e., historical) and causally
conceived of as a spatiotemporally located system (an integrated open or closed processual systems’’ (quoted
individual) that instantiates a particular natural kind, above; for an elaboration of this view, see Rieppel,
with the proviso that every species-as-system instantiates 2009). In this formulation, two common ways of
its own specific natural kind (Rieppel, 2007a, 2008). On conceiving of individuals—as causally integrated sys-
this view, the particular system that is denoted by the tems or as historical entities—seem to be conflated. (A
name Panthera tigris, for example, is the one single recent extensive discussion of these different ways of
member of the natural kind that is also called Panthera thinking about individuality, paying specific attention to
tigris. In RieppelÕs own words: ‘‘Species are best viewed the case of species, can be found in Reydon, 2008). On
as spatiotemporally located (i.e., historical) and causally the former view, a species is thought of as a spatially
integrated open or closed processual systems that also (but not temporally) extended population or metapop-
instantiate a homeostatic property cluster natural kind. ulation, that is, as a population-level system of organ-
[…] Set theory allows for singleton sets; why should isms that are parts of the system because they stand in
biology not allow for historical natural kinds that are causal relations with other parts (organisms) of the
uniquely instantiated, such that a species becomes ‘‘one system. On this view, of which the most prominent
of its kind’’ […]?’’ (Rieppel, 2008; p. 601; emphasis representative is MayrÕs biological species concept, a
added; see also Rieppel, 2007a; p. 380). Rieppel, how- species basically is a breeding population of organisms
ever, immediately qualified this statement by adding that (that are integrated into a whole—an individual—by
‘‘[i]f that is deemed unacceptable, take the parts of a means of reproductive relations) that participates as a
species to be members in transient historical kinds’’ whole in evolutionary processes. On the latter view, a
(Rieppel, 2008, p. 601), thus suggesting that he is not species is a spatially and temporally extended (historical)
committed to the strict view that species are kinds with entity that is composed of organisms that stand in the
precisely one single member each. (An anonymous same ancestor-descendant lineage. On this view, a
reviewer pointed out that RieppelÕs writings can also species basically is a branch on the Tree of Life,
be interpreted in a charitable manner as not necessarily delimited on one end by a speciation event and on the
implying the position that every species-kind has just other end by a speciation or extinction event. While,
one single member. Of course, if Rieppel intended such a from RieppelÕs formulation, it is not immediately clear
charitable interpretation, his repeated talk of species as which conception of individuality is meant, from other
being one of a kind is profoundly misleading. Never- passages in his writings it can be inferred that the
theless, in this paper I examine both strict and charitable historical notion of individuality is the relevant one (e.g.
interpretations of RieppelÕs work.) Rieppel, 2007a; p. 375; Rieppel, 2007b; p. 357). Rieppel
One may wonder, though, whether this approach wrote, for example, that what makes an object a
yields a useful account of species as natural kinds. In historical entity ‘‘is the fact that it has a beginning and
what follows, I consider three different ways of reading an end in time, the fact that its parts can be arranged in
RieppelÕs position, and argue that on two of these a spatiotemporal series, that adjacent parts in that series
4 T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8

are similar […], and that succeeding parts are causally to be expected that the identity assumption will not hold
connected’’ (Rieppel, 2007a, p. 380). As this is precisely for them. Furthermore, there is no good reason to
the case for species, on RieppelÕs view species-as- assume the assumption necessarily holds for all natural
individuals are conceived of as historical individuals. kinds on the most basic level, as neither of the two major
(The distinction between the two kinds of individual is theories of natural kindhood (traditional essentialism
often framed metaphysically as a distinction between and HPC theory) specifically requires the members of a
three-dimensional objects that extend in the three spatial natural kind to be identical. On the traditional essen-
dimensions, and four-dimensional objects that also tialist view, for example, all member entities of a
extend in the temporal dimension; see Reydon, 2008 particular natural kind are the same in that they all
for details.) share the same set of properties that are necessary and
By conceiving of species as historical individuals, sufficient for kind membership. Things of one kind do
Rieppel places emphasis on the fact that species are not need to be the same in each and every way; they need
unique individuals: every species has a unique evolu- to be the same only in their essential properties. And, as
tionary origin in a particular historical speciation event will be explicated in the next section, the HPC view of
and, as such, is a unique individual distinct from all natural kinds (which Rieppel explicitly endorsed) is even
other species. This emphasis on the uniqueness of less strict in its requirements for kind membership than
species is what leads Rieppel to claim that every is traditional essentialism. To conceive of species taxa as
species-as-individual instantiates its own specific natural historical individuals, then, does not imply that every
kind. One—comparatively strict—way to reconstruct species taxon must be the sole member of its own
RieppelÕs argument for this ‘‘one of a kind’’ view of natural kind.
species is the following. Immediately following the But there is also a less strict—and perhaps more
preceding quotation, Rieppel stated that ‘‘[t]o call such charitable—way to reconstruct RieppelÕs argument. As
an entity an individual […] means that it is one of its anonymous reviewers pointed out, RieppelÕs concern
kind’’ (Rieppel, 2007a, p. 380; emphasis added). Riep- does not seem to be with kinds the members of which
pelÕs reasoning, then, rests on the observation that are identical in every respect, but with kinds the
historical individuals are unique entities (as each has its members of which just have some properties in common.
own unique spatiotemporal points of origin and end), so But on this weaker reconstruction, it remains unclear in
that there can be no two identical historical individuals: what way conceiving of entities that have a beginning
no two historical individuals can have exactly the same and an end in time, the parts of which can be arranged
properties. But as there can be no two identical in a spatiotemporal series, of which adjacent parts in
historical individuals, there can be no kinds that contain that series are similar, and succeeding parts of which are
more than one historical individual—kinds, after all, causally connected as individuals would mean that they
encompass entities that have the same properties. are one of their kinds. If historical individuals are
Therefore every historical individual must be the sole unique in the weak sense that they have at least one or a
member of its own kind. few unique properties (that they can have many prop-
However, this argument does not hold. What lies at erties in common with other historical individuals, as
its basis seems to be the assumption that all natural long as they donÕt share all their properties with others),
kinds contain only member entities that are identical in this doesnÕt imply that every historical individual is to be
every respect (as, for example, electrons are usually allocated to its own natural kind. A charitable reading
thought of as identical in all their properties). If this of RieppelÕs writings, then, would involve simply
were so, then indeed a natural kind could not encompass accepting that species as individuals are ‘‘one of a kind’’
multiple unique entities. But there are at least two while acknowledging that Rieppel didnÕt provide com-
reasons for which the validity of this assumption in the pelling arguments to support this claim.
particular context of RieppelÕs argument should be While the above discussion already provides reasons
doubted. First, if the assumption holds, it holds only for to doubt the feasibility of RieppelÕs account of species as
the most basic natural kinds. If one recognizes that natural kinds, an additional—and stronger—argument
entities typically are members of multiple natural kinds can be made, which I develop in the remainder of this
that form a hierarchical system, as many philosophers paper. In what follows, for the sake of the argument I
do, and Rieppel does too, then only the most basic shall simply accept RieppelÕs claim that every species-as-
natural kinds in the hierarchy (presumably the kinds of individual instantiates its own specific natural kind and
elementary particles) will consist of completely identical show that, even if this claim were correct, still RieppelÕs
member entities. The member entities of higher-level account of species as natural kinds would not do the
kinds are the same in some, but not all respects—that is, work he wants it to do. For if RieppelÕs claim were
higher-level natural kinds can contain non-identical correct, it would entail a second question: if every
entities. And as species presumably are not kinds on the species-level natural kind indeed is uniquely instantiated,
most fundamental level of biological organization, it is how are meaningful generalizations over these natural
T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8 5

kinds possible? After all, if a species-level natural kind that are found to cluster together repeatedly plus the
such as Panthera tigris has one single member entity (the underlying factors that cause this clustering.
historical entity that is also called Panthera tigris), then In order to do justice to the messy state of affairs in
any ‘‘generalization’’ over the kind will convey infor- the world, in which entities are hardly ever exactly alike
mation about precisely one single entity, namely the and the properties of things may change in time, HPC
historical entity in question, or at most about the theory conceives of the property clusters and the sets of
temporal stages from which this historical entity is made underlying causal factors that, in combination, define
up. It would therefore not be a generalization at all, but natural kinds in an open-ended manner: no property is
a statement that tells us something about a concrete, necessarily unique to one property cluster, no causal
particular entity (a species-as-individual with organisms factor is necessarily unique to one set of causal factors,
as its constituent parts) or about its several temporal the property cluster of a kind may come to include new
stages. But what is required from an account of species properties and present properties may cease to be
as natural kinds is an explication of how generalizations members, causal factors may begin or cease to operate,
that convey knowledge about the individual member and there are no ‘‘core sets’’ of properties or underlying
organisms of a species are possible. RieppelÕs account of causal factors that all and only members of the
species as natural kinds does not deliver this. In order to corresponding kind exhibit or are affected by. This
get the problem clearly in focus, I shall first give a brief yields an account of natural kinds that is sufficiently
overview of HPC theory (which, after all, constitutes the flexible—or, in RieppelÕs terminology, ‘‘appropriately
basis of RieppelÕs account) and then develop my weak’’ (Rieppel, 2006; p. 195; Rieppel, 2007b; p. 357;
argument further. Rieppel, 2009)—to accommodate all the various kinds
that feature in the special sciences, such as biology, as
well as the traditionally recognized natural kinds. In
HPC theory and RieppelÕs ‘‘one of a kind’’ account of particular, it yields an account that allows for natural
species kinds with fuzzy boundaries (where it may be unclear
for some putative members of a given kind, whether or
Homeostatic property cluster theory was developed not they actually belong to the kind in question) and in
by the philosopher Richard Boyd in a series of papers which the clustering of properties is often imperfect. In
published from the late 1980s onward. It was intended this way, HPC theory promises to be able to accommo-
as an alternative to traditional essentialist theories of date the case of biological species.
natural kindhood, and attempted to take seriously the In the light of the considerations presented in this
epistemic roles that kinds play in the special sciences, paper, it is important to note that HPC theory begins
regardless of whether or not they could be made to fit from empiricist considerations. HPC theory accounts
the essentialist picture of natural kinds. HPC theory for cases in which we notice that ‘‘[t]here is a family (F)
starts from the recognition that most kinds that feature of properties that are contingently clustered in nature in
in scientific reasoning are not groupings of things with the sense that they co-occur in an important number of
exactly the same (microstructural, causal, etc.) proper- cases’’ (Boyd, 1999; p. 143). We can then attach a kind
ties, but groups of things that bear resemblances to each term to this phenomenon of repeated clustering—the
other without being precisely the same. In addition, phenomenon of repeated co-occurrence of entities with
scientific kinds group together things that are similar for largely similar properties—and assume that the cluster-
a reason, that is, that exhibit largely similar properties ing is due to the operation of particular causal factors in
due to largely the same causes (Boyd, 1999, pp. 142– nature. We can move on to investigate the causal
144). Accordingly, kinds should not be defined by means structure of nature to see whether the causal factors
of separately necessary and jointly sufficient essential underlying the kind can be uncovered. If we succeed, we
properties that all and only the members of the kind have obtained a natural kind that can be investigated
exhibit without exception, but by (i) the cluster of further, over which we can gain new knowledge, and
properties found to cluster together regularly (but not over which we can make generalized statements. In the
without exceptions) in entities in the world, in combi- case of species of organisms, this seems to be exactly
nation with (ii) the set of causal factors (Boyd speaks of what happens. We have noticed the repeated co-occur-
‘‘homeostatic mechanisms’’) that underlie this clustering rence of particular traits in a large number of organisms,
of properties. Because for any given natural kind there and we have found causal factors that underwrite these
is no set of properties unique to the members of that clusterings (common descent, largely faithful copying of
kind, the property cluster can be only one part of the genetic material, and ontogeny in a largely stable
kindÕs definition. Accordingly, HPC theory includes the environment—see Boyd, 1999; p. 167; Millikan, 2000;
set of underlying causal factors in the definition and pp. 19–20; Rieppel, 2007a; p. 378). Accordingly, a
assumes the combination of the two to define a kind number of authors have suggested that biological
uniquely: a kind is uniquely defined by the properties species are to be thought of as natural kinds in the
6 T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8

sense of HPC theory (Boyd, 1999; Griffiths, 1999; species, its properties and propensities. Theoretically
Wilson, 1999, 2005; pp. 110–111; Millikan, 2000; Keller relevant generalizations can then be made about the
et al., 2003; Rieppel, 2005, 2007a,b, 2008; Brigandt, ‘‘nature’’ of a species, i.e., about the way of life that is
2009; Wilson et al., 2009). pursued by its parts (the individual organisms that make
With respect to RieppelÕs account, the question up the species)’’ (Rieppel, 2008; p. 600; emphasis
arises as to what exactly are the entities in which we added). While in this quotation the ‘‘its’’ in ‘‘its
observe the above-mentioned repeated co-occurrence properties’’ refers to ‘‘species’’, it is clear that this does
of particular properties—that is, which are the entities not mean the properties that can be attributed to a
over which we formulate generalizations by means of species as a spatially or spatiotemporally extended
natural kind terms. As already mentioned, there are individual (such as the number of organisms of which
three different ways of reading RieppelÕs position. it is composed, the geographical range over which it is
First, RieppelÕs statement that species are uniquely currently spread, the speciation event in which it
instantiated natural kinds can be taken literally. On originated, etc.). Rather, the properties over which
this reading, a species as natural kind includes a theoretically relevant generalizations can be made are
spatiotemporally extended species-individual (a branch those of individual organisms, namely the properties
of the Tree of Life) as its sole member—it is thus a that members of the species tend to exhibit with respect
natural kind encompassing a single four-dimensional to their particular way of life. Elsewhere, Rieppel (2005,
entity (see Reydon, 2008). Second, one can emphasize pp. 480–481, Rieppel, 2009) suggested that the relevant
RieppelÕs statement (quoted earlier) that a species- mechanisms are those that operate to maintain organ-
individual has parts that can be thought of as ism-level properties (e.g. genetic and developmental
members in a transient historical kind. On this constraints, developmental modularity, stabilizing selec-
reading, a species as natural kind includes multiple tion, population structure), leading to the impression
member entities, each of which is a population-level that for him, too, species should be thought of as HPC
entity that constitutes the species-individual at a natural kinds of organisms. However, such a conceptu-
particular time. It is thus a natural kind encompassing alization of species as natural kinds would not be novel
a multitude of three-dimensional entities, each being and, more importantly, would conflict deeply with
the unique instantiation of the kind at one particular RieppelÕs claim that every species is one of its kind.
time. Third, one could emphasize RieppelÕs use of Natural kinds of organisms, after all, are not typically
BoydÕs HPC theory of kinds, and examine which uniquely instantiated—rather, at any time, a natural
homoeostatic mechanisms are supposed to support kind of organism is instantiated as many times as it has
species as HPC natural kinds. In the case of BoydÕs living member organisms at that time.
(1999) own account of species, and the accounts of The third reading of RieppelÕs position, explicated
most other authors who follow Boyd in this respect above, can therefore be rejected as inadequate to what
(including those authors listed in the previous para- Rieppel intended. But while the first and second
graph), the relevant homeostatic mechanisms operate readings can be thought of as ‘‘one of a kind’’ accounts,
on and between individual organisms, thus causing the they fail to meet RieppelÕs intentions on another count.
individual member organisms of a species to be Recall that an account of species as natural kinds was
similar to one another, and leading to an account of supposed to specify how reference to species names in
species as natural kinds with individual organisms as biological reasoning could perform the epistemic role of
their members. (In MillikanÕs account, for example, supporting generalizations about the properties and
the relevant mechanisms comprise the ‘‘copying’’ of behaviours of the organisms that belong to the species
descendant organisms from their ancestors and the denoted by the names that feature in these generaliza-
development of descendant organisms in largely the tions. But on the first and second readings of RieppelÕs
same environment as that in which their ancestors position, no such account is forthcoming. On the first
developed.) reading, a species as natural kind has merely one
This third reading seems the most natural account of instantiation. HPC theory was intended to explain the
species as natural kinds. The repeated co-occurrence of repeated co-occurrence of properties in an important
certain traits in which we are interested, after all, occurs number of cases. While it may be debated exactly how
in distinct organisms of the same species and the large the number of cases of property co-occurrence
generalized knowledge statements that hold over the would need to be to count as an ‘‘important number’’, it
kinds that Boyd (1999), Millikan (2000) and others seems clear at least that the number should be larger
wrote about are generalizations over the properties of than one. A natural kind that consisted of precisely a
the organisms that are counted as members of the same single member entity therefore could not be conceptu-
kind. Indeed, Rieppel acknowledged this: ‘‘[w]hat Boyd alized as a natural kind under HPC theory, as it would
[…] argued was that taking species as HPC natural kinds not encompass a number of repeated co-occurrences of
provides a basis for inductive generalizations about the the same properties in distinct members of the kind.
T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8 7

Moreover, it is not possible to generalize over a kind are non-existent. This means that if RieppelÕs account
that has just one instance—that is, the generalization of species were accepted, a definition of species would
that all members of a given kind, K, have the same need to be elaborated that unified an individuals view
properties is trivial and uninteresting if K has just a of species with a natural kind view of species. As, on
single member. On the second reading, the situation is RieppelÕs account, species-as-individuals are conceived
somewhat better, as here a species as natural kind has of as unique historical individuals, a phylogenetic
multiple sequential instantiations—one at a time. But species definition seems called for (as pointed out to
these instantiations arenÕt organisms: they are popula- me by an anonymous reviewer). Thus the challenge
tion-level entities that constitute the tips of branches on would be to explore the possibility of wedding a
the Tree of Life that are extant at a particular time. The phylogenetic view of species to a useful view of species
generalizations that can be made over such natural kind as kinds. At least one attempt in this direction has
thus are generalizations not about the properties of been made, but much remains to be done before an
organisms, but about the properties of these population- acceptable notion of species as HPC natural kinds
level entities. that are also historical individuals is achieved. (Grif-
RieppelÕs (2007a, p. 380) statement that historical fiths (1999) has given the most extensive elaboration
entities are entities whose ‘‘parts can be arranged in a of this idea; GriffithsÕ account was criticized by
spatiotemporal series […] adjacent parts in that series Reydon (2006)).
are similar’’ and that this ‘‘means that it is one of its This issue is related to a more fundamental philo-
kind’’ (ibid., emphasis added) strongly suggests that the sophical question: in which respects are the views of
second reading of RieppelÕs position explicated here species as natural kinds and as individuals compatible
should be taken as the correct one. It is a reading and incompatible? Rieppel (2007a, 2009) repeatedly
according to which every species is uniquely instantiated suggested that the views of species as individuals and
at every point in time, and that at least logically allows as natural kinds are not mutually exclusive, referring
generalizations (over the set of entities that sequentially to a number of other authors who made the same
instantiate the species through time). But the problem suggestion. What philosophers usually mean when
with this reading is that these generalizations arenÕt asserting this is that from an epistemological point of
about organisms. view the two views are compatible, in the sense that
What was sought after is an account of kinds at the reference to species names in biological reasoning can
organizational level of individual organisms (that is, function to denote kinds or individuals. Most authors
kinds of organisms), but what was achieved on both the who endorse the compatibility of the two views also
first and second readings of RieppelÕs position was an do not hold that the two views as metaphysical
account of kinds at the higher level of species as kinds of statements are compatible—that species are both
supraorganismal systems. individuals and natural kinds. Similarly, in earlier
work Rieppel (2003: 184) admitted that a species
taxon cannot be both an individual and a natural
Conclusion kind, as individuals and kinds metaphysically are
different kinds of thing. But, Rieppel went on to say,
I have argued that RieppelÕs account of species as the real question is whether the same collection of
HPC natural kinds does not do the work that he entities can constitute both the extension of a kind
wants it to do, as it does not yield kinds over which term and the constituent parts of a larger individ-
generalized knowledge statements that convey infor- ual—and this is clearly possible. This, then, indicates
mation about the properties of organisms can be how Rieppel conceives of the compatibility of the two
made. But RieppelÕs account faces still other difficul- views of species: he thinks of them as incompatible on
ties. Consider, for example, RieppelÕs suggestion that the level of metaphysics (a species is either an
biological species should be thought of as both individual or a natural kind, but cannot be both),
individuals and natural kinds. If this suggestion were but compatible on the epistemological level (a species
correct (for reasons of space I shall not assess its name can function to refer to both an individual and a
correctness here), which of the numerous available kind, where the parts that constitute the individual
definitions of ‘‘species’’ (or ‘‘species concepts’’) would also constitute the members of the associated kind). A
be the appropriate one? The available thirty-odd main good definition of ‘‘species’’ should therefore be able
definitions of the notion of species can be divided into to wed the two epistemological views of species
definitions that conceptualize species as individuals together, but is not compelled also to bridge the
and those that conceptualize species as classes or different metaphysical views.
kinds (for a list of the main species definitions see e.g. The considerations presented here do not imply that
Mayden, 1997). Definitions that conceptualize species HPC theory is fundamentally inapplicable to the case
simultaneously as both individuals and classes ⁄ kinds of species. At first sight, it may seem that any
8 T.A.C. Reydon / Cladistics 25 (2009) 1–8

conception of species as natural kinds (be it from the References


viewpoint of traditional essentialism or under HPC
theory) is squarely opposed to the fact that species are Boyd, R.N., 1999. Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson,
subject to evolutionary change: while natural kinds are R.A. (Ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. MIT Press,
Cambridge, MA, pp. 141–185.
usually thought of as entities that do not change in Brigandt, I., 2009. Natural kinds in evolution and systematics:
time, one of the hallmarks of biological species is that metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheor.
they do change. However, as explicated in the 57, 77–97.
previous section, HPC theory offers a view of natural Ereshefsky, M., 2007. Species. In: Zalta, E.N. (Ed.), Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007). http://plato.stan-
kinds that is more flexible than the traditional view.
ford.edu/archives/spr2007a/entries/species
From the perspective of HPC theory, natural kinds Ghiselin, M.T., 1966. On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic
can undergo change, as their defining factors (the controversies. Syst. Zool. 15, 207–215.
property clusters and sets of underlying causal factors) Ghiselin, M.T., 1974. A radical solution to the species problem. Syst.
are essentially open-ended. Thus, conceived of as HPC Zool. 23, 536–544.
Griffiths, P.E., 1999. Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical
natural kinds species can evolve, and there is nothing
essences. In: Wilson, R.A. (Ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary
in HPC theory (or in RieppelÕs application of HPC Essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 208–228.
theory to the case of species, for that matter) that is Hull, D.L., 1976. Are species really individuals? Syst. Zool. 25, 174–
incompatible with evolutionary theory. An account of 191.
species taxa as HPC kinds of organisms might thus Hull, D.L., 1978. A matter of individuality. Philos. Sci. 45, 335–360.
Keller, R.A., Boyd, R.N., Wheeler, Q.D., 2003. The illogical basis of
still be feasible. While, on RieppelÕs account, a species- phylogenetic nomenclature. Bot. Rev. 69, 93–110.
level HPC natural kind has only one single member (a Mayden, R.L., 1997. A hierarchy of species concepts: the denouement
system composed of organisms, be it a spatially in the saga of the species problem. In: Claridge, M.F., Dawah,
extended population or a spatiotemporally extended H.A., Wilson, M.R. (Eds.), Species: The Units of Biodiversity.
historical entity), a number of authors have offered Chapman & Hall, London, pp. 381–424.
Millikan, R.G., 2000. On Clear and Confused Ideas: An Essay About
accounts of species-level HPC natural kinds as kinds Substance Concepts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
with individual organisms as their members (Boyd, Reydon, T.A.C., 2005. On the nature of the species problem and the
1999; Griffiths, 1999; Wilson, 1999, 2005; pp. 110–111; four meanings of ÔspeciesÕ. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 36,
Millikan, 2000; Keller et al., 2003; Brigandt, 2009; 135–158.
Wilson et al., 2009). In addition, the species category Reydon, T.A.C., 2006. Generalization and kinds in natural science: the
case of species. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 37, 230–255.
might be conceived of as an HPC natural kind with Reydon, T.A.C., 2008. Species in three and four dimensions. Synthese
the various individual species taxa as its members. 164, 161–184.
This latter idea has also recently been developed Rieppel, O., 2003. Semaphoronts, cladograms and the roots of total
(Wilson, 2005; p. 111; Wilson et al., 2009). The evidence. Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 80, 167–186.
Rieppel, O., 2005. Monophyly, paraphyly, and natural kinds. Biol.
merits of these applications of HPC theory to
Philos. 20, 465–487.
the case of species still remain to be evaluated, and Rieppel, O., 2006. The PhyloCode: a critical discussion of its
I must leave their evaluation for elsewhere. My aim, theoretical foundation. Cladistics 22, 186–197.
after all, was only to show that RieppelÕs particular Rieppel, O., 2007a. Species: kinds of individuals or individuals of a
application of HPC theory was not a fruitful one—it kind. Cladistics 23, 373–382.
Rieppel, O., 2007b. The metaphysics of HennigÕs phylogenetic
was not to offer a general assessment of whether HPC systematics: substance, events and laws of nature. Syst. Biodiv. 5,
theory might be fruitfully applied to the species 345–360.
problem. Rieppel, O., 2008. Origins, taxa, names and meanings. Cladistics 24,
598–610.
Rieppel, O., 2009. Species as a process. Acta Biotheor. 57, 33–49.
Stamos, D.N., 2003. Biological Species, Ontology, and the Metaphys-
Acknowledgements ics of Biology. Lexington Books, Lanham, MD.
Wilson, R.A., 1999. Realism, essence, and kind: resuscitating species
I am indebted to two anonymous reviewers who made essentialism? In: Wilson, R.A. (Ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary
helpful comments on previous versions of this paper. Essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 187–207.
Research for this paper was conducted with support Wilson, R.A., 2005. Genes and the Agents of Life: The Individual in
the Fragile Sciences – Biology. Cambridge University Press,
from the German Research Council (Deutsche Fors- Cambridge.
chungsgemeinschaft, grants RE 2613 ⁄ 1-1 and RE Wilson, R.A., Barker, M.J., Brigandt, I., 2009. When traditional
2613 ⁄ 1-2). essentialism fails: biological natural kinds. Philos. Topics, in press.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen