Sie sind auf Seite 1von 5

Reprinted from Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1.

© 2004 Carnegie Council on Ethics and International Affairs

RESPONSE TO WAR AND SELF-DEFENSE


Self-Defense in International Law
and Rights of Persons
Fernando R. Tesón

n War and Self-Defense David Rodin THE LIBERAL VIEW OF NATIONAL

I uncovers many flaws of current


thinking about war.1 Rodin correctly
points out that the justification of
SELF-DEFENSE

Rodin rightly rejects the attempt to reduce


national self-defense goes beyond the self-defense to a collection of individual
justification of individual self-defense. rights of self-defense. His main reason is that
He accurately rejects the standard notion armies acting in self-defense cannot abide by
of moral symmetry—the accepted view the proportionality rules of individual self-
that both just and unjust warriors can defense. Soldiers in a defensive war can do
permissibly kill enemies as long as they more than individual self-defense would
observe the laws of war. Rodin vindicates allow (for example, they can kill enemy sol-
the right view: if a war is unjust, each and diers who are sleeping or marching, whereas
every injury caused by the unjust warrior under criminal law people are not allowed to
is a criminal act. There are no morally kill those who do not threaten them). Yet I
justified killings by those who fight believe that some of those extra permissions
unjust wars. Further, Rodin rightly to kill in a defensive war can be grounded in
rejects various holistic theories of self- a richer version of liberalism, one that, unfor-
defense. Last but not least, he correctly tunately, Rodin overlooks. This is the view
denounces what I have called the that wars in self-defense are carried out by the
Hegelian Myth,2 the idea that tyrannical government as an agent of the citizens.4 The
governments are worth defending against
interventions aimed at deposing them 1
David Rodin, War and Self-Defense (New York: Oxford
because they are protected by the princi- University Press, 2003). All in-text citation references
ple of sovereignty. are to this book.
2
See Fernando R. Tesón, Humanitarian Intervention:
Despite these important achieve- An Inquiry into Law and Morality (Ardsley, N.Y.:
ments, which Rodin articulates in clear Transnational Publishers, 1997).
3
and penetrating prose, his rejection of a For the rest of this comment, when I use “self-defense” I
mean “national self-defense” unless otherwise indicated.
plausible version of national self-defense 4
See Michael Walzer, “The Moral Standing of States: A
ultimately fails. 3 I will concentrate on Response to Four Critics,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 9
liberal arguments for self-defense— (Spring 1980), pp. 209–29; and Fernando R. Tesón, “The
those for which the end of self-defense is Liberal Case for Humanitarian Intervention,”in J. L. Holz-
grefe and Robert O. Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Inter-
the protection of vital rights or interests vention: Ethical, Legal and Political Dilemmas (New York:
of individuals. Cambridge University Press, 2003), p. 99.

87
idea is simple. Citizens create a state to pro- by a government to defend citizens, then
tect their rights against potential internal and humanitarian intervention is simply an
external threats to those rights. Let us assume extension of self-defense thus defined. The
that there is a philosophically sound account difference would simply be that in humani-
of social contract theory that tells us when tarian intervention the government comes
and how a state is legitimate in this way. to the rescue of citizens other than its own.
Respect for the autonomy of persons requires Yet, Rodin continues, it is wrong to consider
foreigners to respect that social contract. If humanitarian intervention and self-defense
this is sound, then it follows that citizens are as having the same underlying rationale,
bound to one another to defend not just one because “common sense tells us that
another’s lives but the social contract itself. Let humanitarian intervention is a very differ-
us call this the liberal view. ent creature to national-defense.” They are
The liberal view indeed relies on more even “antagonistic” and “in deep tension”
than individual self-defense, as Rodin says. with each other (pp. 130–31). This is because
Citizens defend not merely one another but everyone knows that when a government
also the just institutions that they have cre- invades another country, say, to stop ongo-
ated together and under which they live. The ing domestic atrocities, “one of the moral
government is simply their instrument. The considerations weighed against this action is
justification of self-defense thus combines the defensive rights of the subject of the
principles from political as well as moral intervention.” He writes,
philosophy. This account, I believe, is nei- If there is a right to humanitarian interven-
ther purely reductionist nor does it resort to tion, then it is because the moral basis of the
the spooky communitarian views that right of national-defense can in certain cir-
cumstances be justly overridden, not because
Rodin rightly discards. The army of a justi-
the right of humanitarian intervention is, in
fied state defends the citizens’ lives and some sense, an application of those moral
property threatened by the aggressor, but it considerations. (p. 131)
also defends the liberal state itself, notably
its institutions. It also defends its territory, This is a strange reply to the liberal view. To
morally understood as the locus for the exer- begin with, as I noted above, it completely
cise of liberal rights and the functioning of ignores the contractarian element in the lib-
liberal institutions. This requires use of eral view. When liberals write about the duty
coercion that is not permitted in individual of governments to defend citizens against
self-defense simply because individual and aggression (and the assault to their rights
national self-defense cover quite different that it entails), they presuppose that the gov-
situations—despite the similarities in termi- ernment’s action is not simple defensive res-
nology. National self-defense is mediated by cue, but that it is based on the social
the concept of a legitimate state. contract. This gives self-defense additional
While Rodin concedes that the liberal grounding when compared to humanitarian
view is an improvement over the pure intervention. A government has an obliga-
reductionist view, he still rejects it. He gives tion to defend its citizens—that’s what it has
two reasons. The first is that the liberal view, been validly authorized to do. Rodin treats
he thinks, treats humanitarian intervention the liberal argument as if it were just an
(that is, war to defend human rights) as a application of our duty to defend people,
form of self-defense. If self-defense is action any people, in danger. Self-defense is more

88 Fernando R. Tesón
than that: our government is fiduciarily obli- chance to lawfully delegate authority to a
gated to defend us. It is a protection agency. government, including the authority to
In contrast, many people speak of the right, defend them against foreign attacks. Still,
not the duty, of humanitarian intervention, citizens have a right to defend their lives
because in that case the intervention is justi- and territory (I am assuming they have a
fied on general humanitarian grounds, not kind of collective title to the land and there
on a fiduciary relationship. is no international police to evict tres-
Further, and more important, if one passers), just as citizens in legitimate states
believes that humanitarian intervention is do. Because the tyrant commands the
morally justified, one also believes that a resources of the state, including its armies
drastic alteration of the defensive rights of and weapons, only he is in a position to
the state that is the target of humanitarian defend the state against aggression. There-
intervention is justified. Simply put: Tyrants fore, he has an obligation to the citizens to
do not have a right of self-defense against true defend them, notwithstanding the fact that
humanitarian wars—that is, wars aimed at he has not been authorized to do so. This
deposing them. By extension, soldiers of the obligation derives from the role the tyrant
tyrants’ armies cannot be exercising any occupies. A citizen would perhaps say:
morally justified right of national self-defense. “You are illegitimate, we do not recognize
Rodin overlooks this very important consid- your authority, but given that through
eration. Once it is acknowledged, there is no usurpation you have grabbed control of
tension between self-defense and humani- our resources and thus have de facto polit-
tarian intervention. Despotic rulers have no ical power, the least you must do is defend
defensive rights against justified humanitar- us against attacks.” The citizens have a
ian action. They, and their loyalists, must lay right to defend themselves (in the
down arms. expanded sense analyzed above), but the
Someone may object that this account dictator is the only one who can do it—and
cannot explain why we accord dictators the he must do it, because he has deprived cit-
right to use force in just wars. The liberal izens of the means to do so.5
view upholds both the defense of the lib- The second objection that Rodin presents
eral state and the legitimacy of genuine against the liberal view concerns the case of
humanitarian interventions against which a bloodless invasion. When an aggressor
the dictator and his supporters have no occupies a remote or uninhabited territory,
defensive rights. Yet it seemingly cannot the standard view of self-defense authorizes
explain the defensive rights that illegiti- deadly force to expel the invader. Yet, says
mate governments have against wars of Rodin, because this exercise of self-defense
aggression and other actions not sup- is not an action in defense of persons (the
ported by appropriate humanitarian rea- territory is uninhabited) the liberal view
sons. On the liberal view, in those cases the fails (p. 132). Again, Rodin is led astray by his
dictator, by definition, would not be misconstrual of the liberal position. The
defending liberal institutions. This is concept of territory in international law is
indeed a troubling case for the liberal, yet I
think that it can be explained. Citizens in 5
Someone who has unlawfully abducted a person still
states ruled by tyrants are, to put it mildly, has the moral duty to protect the person from harm,
in a bad position. They have not had the even if he is not the person’s lawful “protector.”

self-defense in international law and rights of persons 89


complex, but the least that can be said is that pointed out that this conclusion is extreme.
states exercise jurisdiction over territory There are many reasons to say, with Locke
based on some form of collective territorial and others, that in the “regulated” state of
title loosely analogous to property owner- nature we can make moral distinctions
ship of land in domestic law.6 Rodin does between justified and unjustified violence.
not dispute this. Rather, he claims that just If I understand Rodin correctly, he takes
as property owners whose lives are not the view that, if the standard account of
threatened may not use deadly force against self-defense really amounts to law enforce-
squatters, so defending armies may not use ment, then it cannot possibly be justified
deadly force against unlawful occupiers who because there can be no law enforcement in
threaten no lives. the absence of a sovereign. Self-help is
This objection vanishes, however, once we never justified.
identify the central feature of international This conclusion, however, is highly
relations: the absence of government. Con- implausible. Perhaps a world state would be
sider the intruder on my property who sim- better, but if all we have is a political system
ply trespasses to occupy, say, the shed in my in which there is no central government and
backyard. He is not threatening me or my yet actors are still governed by rules they
family, so, let us concede, I may not use deadly have created, I think it is implausible to con-
force against him. Yet surely I can call the clude that no self-help can ever be justified.
police to evict him from my property. If he We try to evaluate the justice of war under
resists he will be dragged out by force, and if applicable principles. And, while the lack of
he uses violence he may even be killed. Now compulsory jurisdiction and enforcement
consider the international example. The are major inefficiencies of the system, it does
defending government requests the invader not follow that normative evaluation of the
to leave and the latter refuses. Now, unlike behavior of states is nonsense. Moreover,
what happens in the domestic example, the Rodin’s suggestion that a liberal world gov-
victim of trespass, the invaded state, cannot ernment would eliminate the problems
call the police, for the good reason that there is associated with self-defense because it
no police. Because there is no international would provide law enforcement is mistaken:
enforcement agency, states must resort to there would still remain the issue of plane-
self-help, not as part of self-defense narrowly tary self-defense. Rodin would have to say
understood but as enforcement action.7 that we do not have self-defense against
Curiously, Rodin correctly sees that much invaders from another world, should we
of what is called self-defense is really law encounter them, because of the problems of
enforcement (ch. 8), but fails to draw the
consequences for the international system. 6
For discussions on territory, see Lea Brilmayer,“Seces-
International relations are regulated—that sion and Self-Determination: A Territorial Interpreta-
is, there is law (treaties and custom)—yet tion,” Yale Journal of International Law 16 (Winter 1991),
pp. 177–202; Allen Buchanan, Secession (Boulder, Colo.:
there is no superior authority. From this lack
Westview Press, 1991), pp. 38–45; and Fernando R.
of sovereign Rodin concludes, with Hobbes, Tesón, A Philosophy of International Law (Boulder,
that there can be no lawful self-help. As is Colo.: Westview Press, 1998), pp. 144–47.
7
well known, for Hobbes there can be no jus- UN Security Council action under Chapter VII of the
UN Charter is a partial exception to this. However,
tice in the absence of central adjudication under Article 51 (self-defense broadly understood)
and enforcement. Yet many people have states may unilaterally evict invaders.

90 Fernando R. Tesón
lack of proportionality that he mentions. imminent threats of life, plus acts that are
Furthermore, Rodin is committed to the best viewed as law enforcement. Of course,
view that unless the invaders intend to wipe the issue remains whether those acts can be
us out (in which case our defensive action morally justified. But it is no refutation of
would be identical to individual self- the right of self-defense to say that it does
defense), we would not have a right to use not meet the requirements of imminence,
deadly force. If they just wanted to conquer necessity, and threat to life that are typical of
us, abolish our democratic institutions, and individual self-defense.
establish an autocratic yet not genocidal Rodin is correct that the current interna-
government, according to Rodin we would tional law of self-defense is seriously
not have a right to resist. Whatever the flawed. He scores important points in his
proper justification of our resistance may criticism of moral symmetry, the defensive
be, this conclusion is surely wrong. rights of dictators, and holistic accounts of
self-defense. Rodin’s criticisms force a revi-
RETHINKING—NOT DISCARDING— sion of the standard account of self-
SELF-DEFENSE defense. Still, the implausible conclusions
that he reaches stem from two unwarranted
In general, Rodin takes the analogy between transitions in his argument: the move from
individual and national self-defense too individual self-defense to national self-
seriously. A morally justified right of self- defense, and the move from the absence of
defense in international law must include world government to the illegitimacy of
more than those acts analogous to the indi- self-help. Rodin jumps from a moral-
vidual counterpart. It encompasses acts of philosophical analysis of individual self-
self-help that do not fit the common defini- defense to criticize both reductionist and
tion of individual self-defense (certain communitarian versions of self-defense,
forms of reprisals, belated action to counter without pausing to consider applicable lib-
aggression, action against terrorists in for- eral political philosophy and the moral
eign nations, and so forth). So it is simply principles that govern state behavior in the
wrong to define self-defense tout court as absence of world government. I believe his
“the right to use necessary and proportion- effort fails for those reasons. But any seri-
ate lethal force against an imminent unjust ous philosophical account of the right of
threat to life” (p. 127) and then dismiss self-defense in international law must con-
national self-defense simply because some tend with the trenchant criticisms Rodin
acts that defensive soldiers can do under advances. And international lawyers might
current international law do not fit that def- start thinking about reforming the UN
inition. “Self-defense” in international law is Charter and the laws of war to address
a term of art. It includes acts in defense of some of the problems he identifies.

self-defense in international law and rights of persons 91

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen