Sie sind auf Seite 1von 11

The Behavior Analyst 2013, 36, 239–249 No.

2 (Fall)

A Behavioral Analysis of Morality and Value


Max Hocutt
University of Alabama
Morality has long been conceived as divinely instituted, so otherworldly, rules meant not to
describe or explain behavior but to guide it towards an absolute good. The philosophical
formulation of this theory by Plato was later grafted onto Christian thought by Augustine and
Aquinas. The equally ancient theory of the Greek sophist Protagoras (that the good is relative to
personal preferences and morality to man-made social customs) was forgotten until revived in
the 18th and 19th centuries by such empiricists as David Hume and J. S. Mill. Then it was
dismissed again in the 20th century by G. E. Moore and W. D. Ross as naturalistic fallacy, that
is, conflation of what is with what ought to be. However, those who took this dismissive attitude
themselves made the reverse mistake of conflating what ideally ought to be with what actually is.
In other words, they mistook ideals for actualities. As B. F. Skinner (1971) said in Beyond
Freedom and Dignity, sorting things out requires behaviorist parsing of the good (the personally
reinforcing) and duty (the socially reinforced).
Key words: duty, morality, naturalistic fallacy, relativity, scientism, utilitarianism, value

Know then thyself, presume not God to scan; prestige of philosophers depended on
the proper study of Mankind is Man. pretending to have expertise in these
Alexander Pope (1688–1744) supposedly indisputable truths. Dis-
pute them and you will be told that
Scientific naturalism, which is not you are undermining not merely a
to be confused with uncritical scien- theory of morality but morality itself.
tism, has now triumphed in every field Much tedious verbal digging will
of inquiry except moral philosophy be needed to expose and disarm this
and the separate but related field of delusion. I’m here to provide the
value theory. I think it is time that tedium.
naturalism won in these fields too, but That is the bad news. The good
powerful enemies remain to be defeat- news is that I have an alternative.
ed. Who are these enemies? Other- Against the widely accepted dogma
worldly thinkers such as Plato, Thom- that doing right and pursuing the
as Aquinas, Immanuel Kant, and G. good are conforming conduct to
E. Moore. Fortunately, the weapons otherworldly standards, I shall claim
needed for the contest are ready to that pursuing what we deem good is
hand. What weapons are these? Def- seeking to satisfy personal preferenc-
initions of the good and the right by es, whereas doing what we deem right
empirically minded thinkers such as or just is conforming to established
Protagoras, Thomas Hobbes, David social conventions. Granted, this is
Hume, J. S. Mill, and B. F. Skinner. not usually what people have in mind,
I propose here to defend the latter but it is the rule that governs standard
thinkers from their critics, but many word usage.
centuries were needed to set in place The reply will be that I am com-
the otherworldly ideas and fallacious mitting the naturalistic fallacy. Ac-
reasoning that dominate thought cording to the usual definition, this is
about this subject. These ideas and the fallacy of trying to deduce ought
fallacies will not be easy to dislodge. So from is. There is a widespread myth
entrenched are they that many people that this so-called fallacy was first
regard them as truths on a par with two exposed and discredited by the Scot-
plus two equals four. For centuries, the tish empiricist David Hume. In the
third book of his youthful Treatise on
Address correspondence to the author at Human Nature, Hume did caution
mhocutt@comcast.net. that, because the two words have

239
240 MAX HOCUTT

different meanings, one should not Moore defined this so-called fallacy
infer ought from is without explaining not as the error of deducing ought
the deduction.1 What Hume was from is but as the mistake of trying to
opposing was not inferring ought explain the good in empirical terms.
from is but the dogma that judgments His prototype of a philosopher who
about what ought to be done are had made this alleged mistake was
deducible from principles of a priori the utilitarian J. S. Mill, who had
reason instilled in the human mind by defined the good as anything capable
God. No, he explained, moral judg- of eliciting desire. To this definition,
ments are rooted in socially inculcat- Moore’s obfuscating reply was that
ed sentiments (Hume, 1978).2 the good is what is worthy of being
The inventor of the term naturalis- desired; whether it ever is desired in
tic fallacy was not Hume but G. E. actual fact is neither here nor there
Moore, a colleague of Bertrand (Moore, 1962).
Russell at Cambridge University What made this reply obfuscating
more than a century after Hume. was that Moore offered no measure of
worth. He thought there could be
1
The relevant passage is ‘‘In every system of none. In his view, the worthy would
morality, which I have hitherto met with, I be evident to a select few with the
have always remark’d, that the author pro- capacity to recognize it, but they would
ceeds for some time in the ordinary way of know it by intuition, as mathemati-
reasoning, and establishes the being of a God,
or makes observations concerning human cians know the axioms of geometry
affairs; when, of a sudden, I am surpriz’d to and landscape painters know the colors
find, that instead of the usual copulations of of the summer sky. If the rest of us
propositions, is and is not, I meet with no want to know what is worth desiring
proposition that is not connected with an
ought or an ought not. This change is and pursuing, we will have to take their
imperceptible; but is, however, of the last word for it; it cannot be defined (i.e.,
consequence. For as this ought, or ought not, spelled out in so many words), only
expresses some new relation, ‘tis necessary that pointed out. Or so Moore said (1962).
it should be observ’d and explain’d [emphasis
added]; and at the same time that a reason It was an Oxford contemporary of
should be given, for what seems altogether Moore named W. D. Ross (again,
inconceivable, how this new relation can be a not David Hume) who redefined the
deduction from others, which are entirely naturalistic fallacy as the error of
different from it’’ (Hume, 1978, p. 469). conflating what is with what ought
2
I apologize for citing texts without giving
specific page numbers, but the reader is morally speaking to be, then charged
begged to remember that this is philosophy, both Mill and Moore with commit-
not science; and the present essay was ting this error by defining the morally
commissioned as an introductory talk on right as what has good results. No,
moral philosophy, not a research report on
documented facts. As such, it makes large said Ross, to do right is to do your
generalizations about an exceedingly wide duty, never mind the consequences
variety of topics and texts. Because each of (Ross, 1930).
these topics and texts would need a volume for As you can see, this is a tangled
full treatment, any serious attempt to justify
every possibly contentious claim about them
issue. I will try to sort it out by taking
would turn the present essay into a multivol- things in turn. First, I shall criticize
ume treatise that would still fail of the Moore’s idea of the good as an
purpose. Because philosophy consists of dis- indefinable but evident quality, like
cursive and dilatory arguments that need to be the color blue. Against Moore, I’ll
read and interpreted in context, doubts about
my readings, some of which are certainly come out on the side of a slightly
disputable, are best resolved by recurring to revised Mill, holding that goodness,
whole texts. I therefore advise the reader to or value, is not a quality, like blue,
take my references as invitations, or provoca- but a power, like gravity. Roughly,
tions, to examine the documents I cite more
closely than can be done here. (For a more the good is what has the power to
elaborate and detailed treatment of these please. In Skinner’s jargon, it is what
topics, see Hocutt, 2000.) reinforces preference.
MORALITY AND VALUE 241

Next, I shall examine Ross’s Kan- can teach us means to our ends and tell
tian idea of duty as conformity to us how we came by these ends. It can
a moral law known intuitively by even be used to shape our ends or
means of a priori reason. Here, I will make them more consistent with other
agree that duty is not reliably found ends and the facts, but it cannot
out by considering consequences, as supply them; they are given us ready
Mill and Moore had mistakenly made by nature and shaped by nur-
believed. But I shall reject Ross’s ture. In short, despite my opening
belief that duty is self-evident, known endorsement of scientific naturalism, I
intuitively just by thinking about it. am not a devotee of scientism, which I
Instead, I suggest, doing your duty regard as more religion than science.
is conforming to man-made rules
known by observing behavior. THE GOOD
In making my case, I will use the
psychological vocabulary of colloqui- So much for general remarks. For
al English, but you may interpret my details, let us begin with the good, or,
terms behaviorally. When I speak of to speak more precisely, with what it
desire, you will understand not a is our practice to call good.
private feeling but a publicly observ- To this procedure, Moore objected
able preference function, a measur- mightily and indignantly. Protesting
able disposition to choose one thing that he was a philosopher, not a
rather than others. When I speak of lexicographer, he declared himself
morals, you will understand neither not at all interested in what is merely
invisible norms nor personal beliefs called good but only in what is in fact
but informal regulations made bind- good whether it is ever so called or
ing by observable social sanctions. not. Moore wanted to define the
And so on. I will make no appeal to thing, not its name. Also, he wanted
esoteric entities. I seek strictly empir- a definition that preserved not just
ical definitions (see Hocutt, 1977). denotation but connotation too.
That said, I can now state my two- Having made these demands, Moore
part hypothesis with some precision. then declared them impossible to
First, the goodness, or value, of a satisfy; the good could not be defined
thing x for a person y is x’s power to (Moore, 1962).
reinforce y’s preference for it. Sec- It was no wonder! Moore had
ond, the morally correct, right, or just demanded that we square the circle.
practice is the one that comports with This demand was misconceived in three
the mores (or, if you prefer, the mos) ways. First, although we can in a
that happen to be in force in the particular case distinguish what a thing
agent’s social group. In Skinner’s is called from what it is, the distinction
argot, the good is the personally cannot be the rule. Someone might
reinforcing and the right is the mistakenly call heifer Bessie a horse,
socially reinforced. In plain speech, but no sense can be made of saying
the good is what you will want to ‘‘Although Bessie is the sort of animal
repeat, and the right is what others that it is our rule to call a cow, she is
will want you to repeat. in fact not a cow but a horse.’’
Please do not take my defense of Likewise, one might describe as good
these two theses as an argument for something that turns out on exami-
the proposition that behavioral science nation to be not good but bad.
can tell us what to value. I do not However, it would be senseless to
believe that. Like John Staddon, and declare, ‘‘Although this is the very
unlike Skinner, I hold that the proper sort of thing we usually describe as
role of science is the limited and good, it is in fact not good but bad.’’
subordinate one of helping us to Moore’s second mistake was to
achieve what we already value. Science think that we can define things or
242 MAX HOCUTT

their qualities. The truth is, rather, hornswoggled by a trivial analogy of


that we define words. Despite tenden- grammar, Moore countered that,
tious talk in some precincts about when used properly, the word desir-
defining marriage as prostitution, able connotes not a mere capacity
freedom as power, and political to be desired but worthiness to be
opponents as crooks, one can no desired. Misguidedly, as we have
more define things than one can spell seen, Moore demanded a definition
them. Thus, we can define and spell of the good that preserved this
the adjective ‘‘square,’’ but we cannot connotation of worth (Moore, 1962).
define, or spell, squares. Nor can we As already noted, Moore proffered
define the quality square, whatever no measure of worth himself. Instead,
that is supposed to be. True, we he made two attempts at reducing
normally define a word by describing Mill’s metric to absurdity. First, he
the things it denotes, but the idea that said, Mill’s metric implies that a thing
this defines the things themselves, or will be both unqualifiedly good if
their properties, confuses them with desired by A and unqualifiedly bad if
their names. abhorred by B. Second, Mill’s mea-
Moore’s third and perhaps most sure implies that torture must count
grievous mistake was to think that a as good if desired by sadists. Moore
definition must preserve connotation, thought the first implication logical-
or sense. This is a common mistake, ly, the second morally, absurd. Noth-
but it is a mistake. Connotation is ing can be both absolutely good and
too subjective to concern scientists, absolutely bad, and desiring evil
whose definitions need only fix refer- cannot make it good. To think it
ence, denotation. The aim of a good can is to praise what is not praise-
definition should be to identify the worthy (Moore, 1962).
objects to be talked about, not to say Moore, who had been trained as a
what is thought or felt about them. Greek classicist, was here quoting
Do we want to talk about squares? Plato, who had made essentially the
Then we had better have a definition same reply to the sophist Protagoras
that describes squares and squares two and a half millennia earlier.
only. Do we like or dislike squares? Reportedly declaring ‘‘Man is the
The geometer never asks, because it measure,’’ Protagoras had apparently
does not matter. contended that what is called good is
The same is true of the good. relative to personal preferences and
Granted that we approve of it, what what is called just is relative to social
we feel about it is beside the point. customs or laws. Replying that peo-
So, our definition of it need not, and ple often prefer what is not good and
should not, embody our feelings societies often have practices that are
about it. Presumably, we have come not just, Plato had averred that
here to understand the good, not to preferring evil can no more make it
praise it. If so, we should talk about it good than believing a falsehood can
in the detached and unemotional way make it true, and custom can no
butchers talk about pork shoulders more make injustice right than can
and financiers about credit deriva- arbitrary power (Plato, 1961, The
tives. Call that attitude reductionist if Sophist).
you like; it is the way of good science. Plato’s premises were true, but his
Mill knew this. Noticing that the conclusion was not. We’ll come back
words good and desirable are used to justice later. For now, let us stick
more or less interchangeably, he to value. It is indeed true that value,
reasoned that, as the visible is what or goodness, does not vary with
can be seen, so the desirable must be opinions, but it does vary with tastes.
what elicits desire (Mill, 1979). Scorn- Why does that distinction matter?
fully replying that Mill had been Because, as the Latin saying has it, de
MORALITY AND VALUE 243

gustibus non disputandum est. Opin- value of a thing is not absolute but
ions are true or false, so can be is relative to persons, not subjectively
disputed and perhaps disproved. But as a matter of opinion, but objective-
merely liking something is not ven- ly as a matter of fact. This strikes
turing an opinion about it. So, it is a some people as puzzling, but it is no
matter of logic that, although tastes more so than is the fact that the Eiffel
can be deplored or developed, they Tower is near Jacques in Paris but far
cannot be disputed or disproved. from Jack in New York, not as a
Unfortunately, Plato had paid no matter of their subjective opinions
attention to this truth, and neither but as a matter of objective fact. It is
did Moore. this fact, the objective relativity of
Neither, if I may be permitted to value, that makes trade possible, and
say so, does my learned and acute it is trade that makes the world go
friend John Staddon (2013). Staddon around. If what you possess has less
regards values as beliefs. In fact, value for you than it would have for
values are preferences, which differ me and conversely, we can swap, to
from beliefs in being neither true nor our mutual benefit. Good economists
false. That is why, as Staddon cor- now recognize this fact. It is time
rectly affirms, values cannot be de- philosophers did too.
duced from facts, our name for What about torture? Must we
beliefs that are thought to be true. admit that it has value? Yes, but
Of course, values are real, and it is a calling torture a good for sadists is
fact that people have them. But not praising it. However much plea-
lacking truth and falsity, the values sure the sadist gets out it, you and I
that people have cannot without are at liberty to condemn it as
solecism be themselves counted as vehemently as we wish. It may be a
facts. But from facts one can deduce good for him; it is an evil for us.
only other facts. Hence, as Staddon Most people realize this when they
says, you cannot deduce values from are thinking concretely, but they
facts. Belief to the contrary embodies forget it when they start juggling
a category mistake. About that, philosophical abstractions. Then they
Staddon is surely correct. get tangled in words and revert to the
Staddon’s mistake is to think this simplistic idea that what has no value
means you can never deduce ought for them must have none for any-
from is. If that were true, you could body else. Give them the power to
never provide factually based advice, impose this prejudice on others and
the only kind worth having. Howev- they will set up a dictatorship. Plato
er, there is nothing amiss in advising wanted to make philosophers kings.
‘‘That is a rattlesnake; so you ought Philosophical mistakes are usually
not to play with it,’’ or ‘‘That is a the products of bad logic. The logical
profitable enterprise; so you ought to foundation of Plato’s hankering for
invest in it,’’ or ‘‘Going to your royalty was a faulty theory of pred-
friend’s funeral is your duty; so you ication, the fundamental concern of
ought to do it.’’ In all of these, an logical grammar. Taking geometry as
ought is validly deduced from an is. his paradigm, Plato held that predi-
Nor, because there is no inference cation is comparison with other-
in it, is it a fallacy to define the good worldly ideals. Calling something
as what will reinforce preference, square means that it resembles the
though there is a complication in this ideal Square, a model laid up in
definition that calls for a qualifica- heaven; and calling something good
tion. Evidently, what will reinforce means that it resembles the ideal
A’s preferences might discourage B’s. Good, another model laid up in the
So, even though an individual’s same realm. It is because philoso-
evaluations can be mistaken, the phers can recognize these otherworld-
244 MAX HOCUTT

ly ideals that they should rule (Plato, even if nobody thought so (Moore,
1961, Phaedo). 1962). Moore was right about the
This primitive theory, which is earth, but his idea of value was not
encouraged by elliptical speech, intelligible. One might as well say
works okay for logically simple prop- that irritating noises would be irritat-
erties like shape and number, but ing even if there were nobody to be
even Plato suspected it could not irritated.
explain relative comparisons or other Moore’s problem was that he had
relations. Thus, he was completely unwittingly confused intrinsic good-
flummoxed by the fact that A might ness with inherent goodness. Calling
be tall by comparison with B and a thing intrinsically good means not
short by comparison with C. How, he that it is good apart from desire for it,
wondered, can something resemble as Moore thought, but only that it is
both the absolutely Tall and the desired for itself alone, in disregard
absolutely Short? One might as well of its benefits and detriments. The
wonder how the Eiffel Tower can be simple fact of the matter is that
both near and far; near to Jacques in nothing is valuable in itself, apart
Paris, far from Jack in New York. from actual or potential desire for it.
The logic of relatives was not As George Santayana once observed
worked out satisfactorily until the in this connection, the whiskey does
late 19th century, when the American not stand there in the bottle dead
logician Charles Peirce treated rela- drunk. That it is intoxicating means
tions as ordered pairs, triples, and so that it can make you drunk.
on. As we all know, however, the Suppose you want to eat bon bons
solution to Plato’s puzzle is simply and smoke cigarettes while remaining
that height is relative and so is value. indifferent to the damage they do to
Thus, ‘‘x is tall’’ means ‘‘x is taller your health. Then bon bons and
than some y,’’ not ‘‘x is tall absolute- cigarettes have intrinsic value for
ly,’’ and ‘‘x has value,’’ means ‘‘x has you. They have this value neither
value for some y,’’ not ‘‘x is valuable because they are useful for other
period.’’ As 17th century English purposes nor because they are valu-
philosopher Thomas Hobbes would able apart from your desire for them
eventually observe, the word good is but precisely because you want them.
an indexical term that everyone uses That others may not value them as
‘‘in relation to himself’’ (Hobbes, you do is true but irrelevant.
1958). Thus, ‘‘Licorice tastes good’’ The moral of the story is that Mill
is usually ellipsis for ‘‘Licorice tastes was essentially right. It is not true
good to me,’’ and this does not that everything capable of being
always imply that it will taste good desired is good, but it is true that
to you too. the good is what, having tried it, you
Moore acknowledged that, be- will desire again. Thus, good golf
cause what benefits A might not swings are the kind you want to
benefit B, instrumental value is rela- learn, good friends are the kind you
tive. However, his topic was intrinsic want to keep, and good food is the
value, and he thought, like Plato, that kind you want to eat. Despite Moore
describing a thing as intrinsically and Plato, the goodness of these
good means that it is good in itself, things is not a simple, fixed quality.
so good independently of tastes, as As B. F. Skinner was perhaps the first
the earth is round in itself, indepen- to make precisely clear, goodness is a
dently of opinions. Accordingly, power, that is, the power to reinforce
Moore insisted that an intrinsically preference (Skinner, 1971).
admirable thing would be admirable We should not let that important
even if there were nobody to admire truth be obscured by priests, politi-
it, just as the earth would be round cians, or philosophers who plead for
MORALITY AND VALUE 245

power to tell other people what to so had need of another, which he


prefer. Their good might not be ours. found in the idea that an individual’s
conscience might substitute for the
THE RIGHT guidance of the Church. In theological
circles, this idea was commonly ratio-
That is all I can say here about nalized by the Platonic theory that,
Moore on the good. I will now turn to because God implants knowledge of
Ross on the right, and begin by moral law in every human soul before
noting that the word is treacherously birth, one might hope, given proper
ambiguous. training, to discover it simply by
What interested Ross was the right looking into one’s self. Ross gave
of rectitude; not the right of utility. voice to this theory when he said that
He was not talking about the right duty is a simple and self-evident
hammer to use in order to drive nails, quality, like the color blue (Ross,
the right stocks to buy in order to 1930). Of course, Ross knew that what
make money, or the right woman to is evident to the learned is not always
marry in order to be happy. He was evident to others. Indeed, he insisted
talking about what you are obliged to on the point, because it gave the
do even if it will not serve your ends. philosophers of Oxford University,
In short, he was talking about duty, where Ross held forth, greater moral
regarding which he had two pertinent authority than the common herd.
questions: First, what can make There was one niggling complica-
doing your duty right if it is not in tion. It had long been Christian
your interests? Second, how are you dogma that an infinitely wise and
to know your duty? benevolent God had so arranged
The theological tradition had things that, to do one’s duty is also
readymade answers to both ques- to do good, and vice versa. In short,
tions, but these answers had settled the good and duty were one thing
no disputes. The answer to the by two names. Uncritically accepting
metaphysical question had been that this equation, Henry Sidgwick, Moore’s
to do your duty is to obey the moral teacher at Cambridge and the author
law, a standard that is binding of a bestselling textbook on moral
because almighty God has command- philosophy, had naively concluded that,
ed obedience to it. For all I know, although the provisions of moral law
Ross may no longer have believed in can be known more or less intuitively
God when he said this, but he still by those with suitably trained con-
thought of moral conduct as conduct sciences, maximization of good is a
that conforms to an antecedently more scientific test (Sidgwick, 1981).
given moral law. In other words, he Sidgwick, who may have thought he
may have been one of that legion of was espousing Jeremy Bentham’s utili-
philosophers the French existentialist tarianism, did not notice that the
Jean Paul Sartre had in mind when he atheistic Bentham had regarded talk
spoke wryly of those English aca- of moral law as so much gibberish.
demics who still believed in a God- Ross had a quite different reason
given morality but no longer believed for objecting to Sidgwick’s Christian-
in the God who gave it. ized utilitarianism: He disliked equat-
The theological answer to the ing duty with the performance of
epistemological question had been good. So, he sided with Immanuel
that, to know the provisions of moral Kant, the German philosopher who
law with certainty, you should con- had insisted that the right and the
sult the officials of the Roman good are distinguishable things. As
Catholic Church, God’s representa- proof of this distinction, Kant had
tive on earth. Raised an English pointed out that such violations of
Protestant, Ross rejected this answer, morality as lying, reneging on your
246 MAX HOCUTT

promises, punishing the innocent, Admittedly, Thomas Aquinas, the


and torturing the guilty cannot be great theologian of the high Middle
made morally right by any good they Ages, had made a manly effort to
might be thought to do. Ross regard- bridge the divide between reason and
ed this observation as conclusive morality, and many think he suc-
refutation of all forms of utilitarian- ceeded. Identifying moral law with
ism, and many philosophers agree what the Roman Stoics had called
with him. But if utility is not the natural law, Aquinas defined that as
measure of duty, what is? the rational pursuit of happiness by
Kant had said reason, but when the the doing of good (Aquinas, 1988).
sage of Konigsberg spoke of what his But although Aquinas’s Aristotelian
translators call moral reason, he conception of reason as the servant
explicitly excluded Verstehen, figur- of natural needs and the pursuer
ing out means to desired ends. That of good was certainly much better
was not reason; it was merely the founded than Kant’s would be, it was
kind of understanding required for never the working test of God’s will.
prudence, which Kant wrongly equat- The test of that was always Holy
ed with unmitigated selfishness. For Scripture as interpreted by Thomas’s
Kant, moral reason was a species of church. Reason prevailed only when
Vernunft, the intuitive discernment of it did not conflict with the judgment
truth a priori, without concern for of the Church. Many, perhaps most,
results. On the basis of this idiolect, philosophers continue to believe that
reason can suffice as a faculty for
Kant is often described as a moral
discovering moral truth, but David
rationalist. In fact, as a disciple of Hume’s great achievement as a phi-
Martin Luther, who had famously losopher was to have demonstrated
derided reason as ‘‘the whore of what is wrong with that idea.
Babylon,’’ Kant preferred the fideism I know just one way to cut through
of Augustine, who had said that a this theological knot: Give up the
Christian should ‘‘believe in order to idea that doing your duty is comply-
understand’’ and obey the will of ing with a transcendent moral law
God unquestioningly. This reverence and understand instead that it is
for uncritical belief and unquestion- conforming to the conventions and
ing obedience is what Kant called customs of your society. Although
moral reason (Kant, 2002). these variable customs and conven-
Kant’s fideist usage has two salient tions are man-made, they grow out of
problems. First, there is no practical more or less successful attempts to
test of God’s will, because whatever serve basic needs. So, they are in
happens can be said to accord with it. Hume’s elegant phrasing ‘‘artificial
George dies; God’s will. George lives; but not arbitrary.’’ We may chafe at
still God’s will. This consistency with them, but we are bound to obey them
all logical possibilities deprives God’s while they are in force; and they are
will of determinate empirical mean- in force as long as they are being
ing. Second, as we normally under- enforced with sufficient reliability
stand it, behaving rationally is doing and vigor to promote more or less
what promises to serve personal, if regular compliance.
not always selfish, ends. By contrast, We call some of these rules laws,
behaving morally always requires others morals. When we use the word
showing due regard for the interests strictly, what we call law consists of
of other persons. It can even mean rules instituted and enforced by
putting their interests first. You officials of government who act in
cannot obliterate this distinction, their official capacities to control the
only blur and befuddle it, by calling behavior of citizens or subjects,
both things forms of reason. ostensibly for the benefit of those
MORALITY AND VALUE 247

ruled but invariably for the greater we talk of moral duties and moral
benefit of the rulers and their clients. justice, it is by analogy with legal
By contrast, morality and etiquette duties and justice, the prototypes of
consist of unofficial rules that have duty and justice. Because law comes
more widely dispersed and less clearly from higher up in the social order, we
identified origins and beneficiaries. tend to forget that morality and
No single person or group makes and etiquette come from the base of
enforces these unofficial rules; in- society and presume instead that the
stead, everybody has a part in creat- misnamed ‘‘laws’’ of morality and
ing them and encouraging compli- etiquette must have come from on
ance with them. high too. This belief is carefully
As the late Austrian economist nurtured by the lawmakers at the
Friedrich Hayek emphasized follow- top and by the intellectuals who serve
ing David Hume’s great friend Adam them, but it is a myth and a muddle.
Smith, this means that the unofficial Most people are comfortable with
rules of morality and etiquette are this myth, but I think it is time to
spontaneous orders, like language. In take a fresh look at the facts.
other words, nobody designed them. Forgetting that morality is supposed
Instead, they came into being without to be obedience to otherworldly
plan and are enforced in ad hoc ways commands, we need to notice what
by ordinary persons who seek in their it is in actual practice. When we do
daily intercourse to reduce mutually that, I think we see that what we call
harmful conflict and promote mutu- duties are simply socially imposed
ally beneficial cooperation, all with requirements. That we ought to com-
the ultimate purpose of serving bio- ply with these requirements means
logically rooted needs in a usually that we are obligated to do so. That
unfriendly and sometimes hostile we are obligated to comply means
world. Every working society has that we are subject to censure and
morality and etiquette. In fact, there punishment if we do not. Of course, a
can be no society without them duly socialized adult will have a
(Hayek, 1989). functionally autonomous conscience
By contrast, only politically or- that prompts him to do his duty
dered societies have laws, and these without coercion, but that conscience
came about only recently. It is now will be a product of identifiable social
accepted that for more than 99% of sanctions.
human existence, humankind lived in Another name for the performance
small hunter gatherer bands with of duty is justice, respect for rights. If
leaders and customs but without what I have said so far is correct,
political organization, government, justice must also be definable in
or law. If we can trust the archaeol- empirical terms, and it is. I do justice
ogists, the first polities came into when, respecting your rights, I give
being only about 5,000 years ago, you your due; and you get what you
about 5,000 years after the develop- deserve when you get your due. How
ment of settled agriculture in half a do you and I know what is due? We
dozen fertile and heavily populated learn the applicable rules. How do we
river valleys. Since these develop- learn them? As Skinner (1971) ob-
ments, perhaps the two most mo- served, they exist in the contingencies
mentous in human history, political of reinforcement. So, we learn them
organization has gradually become by noticing what is rewarded and
the rule. At present there is hardly a what is punished.
human society without it. That is all the space I have to talk
That is why, for better or worse, it about the ought of duty. Before
is from law that we derive our leaving the topic, however, I should
concepts of duty and justice. When remind you that the ought of reason
248 MAX HOCUTT

conforms to a different standard. The Kant and Ross had a valid point. If
ought of duty concerns what others utilitarianism is the proposition that
require you to do in order to satisfy doing your duty always means max-
their desires and promote their val- imizing utility, it just ain’t so. How-
ues; the ought of reason is about ever, the best explanation of this fact
what you should do to satisfy your is neither that God-made moral law
desires and promote your values. In nor that a priori reason commands
short, the ought of duty is about doing what won’t serve your personal
social requirements, and the ought of ends; it is that man-made morals and
reason is about personal desires. laws sometimes do so.
Having said so, I should explain Sidgwick did not know this, but
what I do not mean by it. I’ll make two Bentham certainly did. Talk of natu-
brief points. First, by personal desires, ral law having been exposed by Hume
I emphatically do not mean selfish as an anthropomorphic and mislead-
desires. I’m talking about the desires ing metaphor, Bentham also knew
of owners, not their beneficiaries. So, that man-made law and morality are
by declaring it rational to serve your all the law and morality there are. So,
desires, I’m not affirming that you he never claimed that doing your duty
should be an unremitting, much less a is maximizing general utility, the usual
psychopathic, egoist. Let a woman’s textbook oversimplification of utili-
desires be as unselfish as you please. If tarianism. What Bentham claimed
what she most wants to do is sacrifice was that it is rational to maximize
her life to the betterment of human- your personal utility, and it is your
kind, then it is rational for her to act duty to obey whatever rules happen to
accordingly. Mother Teresa was un- be applicable to you; but legislators
usual, but I know no reason to declare and moralists ought to take more care
her insane. Christian charity is not than they usually do to make rules
incompatible with reason. with an eye to promoting general
Second, by saying that doing your utility (Hocutt, 2005).
duty is conforming to social require- If Bentham had the right idea, as I
ments, I do not mean that it is always believe, we should look not to priests
or necessarily a good thing. On the or philosophers but to sociologists,
contrary, I believe that you can anthropologists, and (perhaps?) law-
perpetrate great evil doing what you yers to tell us what the rules are and
take to be your duty. If you want an to behavior analysts to tell us how to
example, think of the Nazis. They reinforce them. If we want to im-
reportedly talked incessantly and prove the rules, however, we will
passionately of their duties to the have to consider consequences, and
Fuhrer and the German race. Admit- to do that we will want to enlist not
tedly, they may have overlooked armchair dreamers and utopian mor-
more basic duties than these, but it alists with their heads in the clouds
is only on the dubious belief that the and their sights on distant ideals but
rules were made by an infallible deity the worldly thinkers called econo-
to promote an absolute good that mists. Of course, economic science
doing your duty can never be an evil. can by itself no more dictate how we
To be sure, there is little conflict ought to live than can behavioral
between duty and reason in well- science; but if we want to live well, we
ordered societies. In fact, infrequency will guide our behavior using all the
of such conflict is the definition of science we can get.
social order. Occasional divergence
between good and duty is inevitable,
CONCLUSION
however, given that the rules are
made by fallible human beings with It is certainly an error to mistake
desires that are often at odds. So what is for what ought to be, but a
MORALITY AND VALUE 249

more common error is to mistake known a priori or by divine revela-


what ought to be for what is. tion. It is biologically rooted, there-
Despite G. E. Moore, the intrinsi- fore empirically known, needs. Al-
cally good is not good apart from though science does not supply us
desire for it; it is just good indepen- with these needs, it can help us to
dently of any further utility it might discover them and figure out how to
be thought to have. As Plato insisted, satisfy them. In short, it can serve our
we can always make mistakes about values even if it cannot dictate them.
what should count as good. So the The bottom line? Moral transcen-
good cannot be identified with what dentalism is a deep, if pervasive and
is thought to be good. Nevertheless, long-standing, mistake. There is no
it can be defined as what, having been high or smooth road to a permanent
tried, reinforces preference. Because moral wisdom. It must be learned
this varies with persons, times, and the hard way, by trial and error,
circumstances, it follows that the then relearned when circumstances
good is relative. However, it is change.
objectively so, because whether some-
thing has the power in given circum- REFERENCES
stances to reinforce a person’s pref-
erences is an objective, empirically Aquinas, T. (1988). On law, morality, and
discoverable, fact or falsehood. politics. W. P. Baumgarth & R. J. Reagan
(Eds.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Contrary to conventional belief, Hayek, F. (1989). The fatal conceit: The errors
the right or just is not usefully of socialism. Chicago, IL: University of
defined as what comports with moral Chicago Press.
law, there being no undisputed test of Hobbes, T. (1958). Leviathan: Parts I and II.
that empirically nondescript entity. New York, NY: Library of Liberal Arts.
Nor is the right definable as what Hocutt, M. (1977). Skinner on the word
‘‘good’’: A naturalistic semantics for ethics.
maximizes good, though it would Ethics, 87, 319–338.
certainly be good if that were so. Hocutt, M. (2000). Grounded ethics: The
Rather, the right is what conforms to empirical bases of normative judgments.
man-made rules, the only rules that New Brunswick, Canada: Transaction.
can be proved to exist. These rules Hocutt, M. (2005). Was Bentham a utilitari-
an? Canadian Journal of Political Science,
vary with the society, with time, and 38(3), 697–717.
with circumstance; but the duty to Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature,
obey them is also an empirically Book III. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
verifiable fact of the matter that is Kant, I. (2002). Critique of practical reason.
not dependent on personal or group Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Mill, J. S. (1979). Utilitarianism. Indianapolis,
opinion. Although duty is not a IN: Hackett.
transcendent ideal, it is an objective Moore, G. E. (1962). Principia ethica. Cam-
reality. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
That duty is real, however, does Plato (1961). Phaedo and the Sophist: The
not mean that it is sacrosanct. After collected dialogues. E. Hamilton & H.
Cairns (Eds.). New York, NY: Random
all, if I am right, the rules that House.
constitute it are man-made. So, they Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good.
are subject to error and criticism, like Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
everything that human beings make. Sidgwick, H. (1981). Methods of ethics.
Though they deserve respect, there is Indianapolis: Hackett.
nothing sacred about them; they can Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and
dignity. New York, NY: Knopf.
always be improved. However, the Staddon, J. E. R. (2013). Faith, fact, and
test of their betterment is not confor- behaviorism. The Behavior Analyst, 36,
mity with otherworldly standards 229–238.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen