Sie sind auf Seite 1von 13

Journal of Abnormal Psychology

1975, Vol. 84, No. S, 462-474

The Contextual Nature of Psychiatric Diagnosis


David L. Rosenhan
Stanford University
Psychiatric diagnoses are powerfully influenced by the contexts in which
patients are found and the expectations of diagnosticians. Many of the com-
ments by Millon, Spitzer, and Weiner underscore these facts. Their observa-
tions are examined for the implications they hold for the meanings of sanity
and insanity, the "wastebasket" nature of the schizophrenia diagnosis, as well
as for the role of professionally sanctioned justification of diagnostic error.
Substantive criticisms of design and interpretation are answered. Finally,
guidelines for producing and evaluating any new diagnostic systems are offered.

One might imagine that the criticisms of sional, on whose overworked back the bur-
"On Being Sane in Insane Places" (Rosenhan, dens of mankind's anguishes fall, that even
1973 a) that have appeared here and else- the little he can do by way of diagnosis and
where had quite exhausted the matter, but treatment is unworthy and wrong. It even
that is not the case. There is, in my view, suggests that, given our current state of
yet another criticism that can be offered of knowledge, symptom diagnoses may be better
that work, one that may be harsher than those than syndrome diagnoses, although that sug-
printed here, and one that sets the current gestion is no better supported by research
reaction into a comprehensible context. Stated data than are traditional diagnoses. It sug-
vigorously, it is this: gests that the context created by the psychi-
''On Being Sane in Insane Places" is a atric hospital colors our perception of psychi-
negative work. It tells what is wrong with atric patients, but it does not tell us in what
treatment and diagnosis, without telling how way we can deal with that problem. It leaves
it might be improved. It asks us to abandon scientists and practitioners in the lurch,
traditional psychiatric diagnosis without tell- urging them to abandon the little they have
ing us what will replace it. It tells those who by way of hospital treatment and diagnosis,
have labored to improve psychiatric care without providing them alternative tools. It
that their efforts are grossly insufficient, would destroy a paradigm without providing
without offering alternatives of demonstrated an alternative. In short, it is work half done.
value. It tells the mental health profes- There is little defense against that criti-
cism, little comfort for the anguish it ex-
An earlier draft of this paper, entitled "The Para- presses and the anger it conveys. That the
digm Crisis in Psychiatric Diagnosis," was circulated implications of context are presently revamp-
to colleagues and friends, among them many who ing large segments of personality theory, so-
do not share my point of view. The present paper cial psychology, psycholinguistics, memory,
owes much to their comments and observations.
Without holding them responsible for the product, and perception is barely solace to the working
I acknowledge the comments of Lee J. Cronbach, clinician. The fact that my colleagues and I
William Dejong, Peggy Thoits Doyle, Leonard recognize that the work is not yet done, the
Eron, Floyd M. Estess, Laurie Klein Evans, Arnold fact that we have not rested, nor do we intend
J. Friedhoff, Raquel Gur, Ruben Gur, Dillon Inouye, to rest, is again no consolation for the cli-
Seymour S. Kety, Donald F. Klein, Perry London,
Theodore Millon, Loren R. Mosher, Martin T. Orne, nician who needs tools now. Until compelling
Jerome V. Rose, Mollie S. Rosenhan, Theodore alternatives are found, one can have little
Sarbin, and Jack Zusman, as well as one reviewer difficulty understanding those who fight
who requested anonymity. This work was supported mightily, even angrily, to retain current be-
in part by a grant from K. and H. Montgomery.
Requests for reprints should be addressed to D. L. liefs. Those beliefs were not earned without
Rosenhan, Department of Psychology, Stanford Uni- sweat in training, research, and on the clinical
versity, Stanford, California 94305. firing line.
462
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 463

Transitional eras are difficult. That seem- concerned with them. Kurt Lewin and his
ingly endless period of time that lies between intellectual heirs were absorbed by them. And
our awareness of serious shortcomings in our modern psychologists in such diverse fields as
current views and the discovery and applica- psycholinguistics, memory, social psychology,
tion of more fruitful conceptions is a breeding and personology have pursued matters of con-
time for intense and conflictful emotions. But text with considerable intellectual profit. Suf-
the fact is that our growing appreciation of fice it to say that the contexts created by
the role that contexts play in a variety of psy- such matters as person, place, gender, status,
chological areas—a role that I will elaborate and era, not to speak of relational and ana-
on shortly—promises improvement for the un- lytic contexts, have enormous impact on the
derstanding, diagnosis, and treatment of psy- way stimuli are perceived.
chological distress. In the final analysis, it is A few examples will make these matters
with that improvement that our aspirations clear to those whose interests have not been
lie. More than that, our personal appreciation in this area. Psycholinguists observe that even
of the role of context may serve to insulate us the words we use create significant contexts.
against the needless defensiveness that natu- The question "how short are you?" carries
rally arises during this transition period. It a different presuppositional load than the
was with this understanding in mind that I question "How tall are you?",, even though
earlier wrote: both have identical concrete meaning (Clark,
It would be a mistake and a very unfortunate one,
1969). Loftus and Palmer (1974) have shown
to consider that what happened to us derived from that the very questions we use in interrogating
malice or stupidity on the part of the staff. Quite someone may determine the kinds of answers
the contrary, our overwhelming impression of them we get, not merely regarding opinion but to
was of people who really cared, who were com- the very details of fact. Researchers in mem-
mitted, and who were uncommonly intelligent.
Where they failed, as they sometimes did painfully, ory and cognition find that the latency for
it would be more accurate to attribute those failures detecting "0" and "1" in a string of letters
to the environment in which they, too, found them- is considerably shorter if those stimuli are
selves than to personal callousness. Their perceptions defined as numbers (zero and one) rather
and behavior were controlled by the situation, rather
than being motivated by malicious disposition. In a
than letters (Jonides & Gleitman, 1972; see
more benign environment, one that was less attached also Jenkins, 1974).
to global diagnosis, their behaviors and judgments All stimuli seem amenable to contextual
might have been more benign and effective. influence, but some are more amenable than
(Rosenhan, 1973a, p. 2S7) others. Contextual influence is particularly
strong when stimuli are ambiguous. Stimuli
THE CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF
that are well articulated seem much more able
PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS to defy the influence of a surrounding field
The studies of diagnosis with which we are than those that are ill-defined. By way of
concerned are best understood in terms of the example, Figure 1, adapted from Selfridge
influence of contexts on perceptions. Contexts (1955), makes the matter very clear in the
shade and color meaning; in fact, they often area of visual perception. Most people have
t determine meaning. A short person among no difficulty in recognizing the upper part of
pygmies may seem to be a giant. One who is the figure as THE CAT, even though the A
IS pounds overweight seems stuffed on a and the H are identically shaped. Indeed,
beach but svelte at an obesity clinic. A person some readers respond so rapidly to context
whose hand is missing may look tragic among that they are surprised when the similarity
factory workers but nearly unimpaired among of the shape of the middle letter is pointed
paraplegics. Thus, contexts are powerful. out. That does not occur in the lower half
The influence of contexts of mind (sets) of the figure. There, the A is so well articu-
and contexts of natural objects and behaviors lated that perceivers see the phrase as a spell-
(settings) on perception and action has been ing error, and may spend some considerable
a constant theme of psychological research amount of time figuring out what the phrase
over the decades. Gestalt psychologists were was really supposed to say.
464 DAVID L. ROSENHAN

of individual diagnosis, is quite low 1 ), are

THECHT
commonly in the range of .5, and can descend
as low as .2. (For a recent summary of such
studies, see Spitzer & Fleiss, 1974.) If any-
thing attests to the ambiguity of such be-
havior and suggests the possibility that such
behavior can be colored by contextual cues,
these studies of agreement do.
There is yet another reason for believing

TflE CflT
FIGURE 1. The influence of context on visual
that psychiatric diagnoses might be strongly
influenced by contexts. Unlike most medical
diagnoses, which can be validated in numer-
ous ways, psychiatric diagnoses are main-
tained by consensus alone. This is not com-
perception.
monly known to either the consumer or the
mental health profession. Spitzer and Wilson
These powerful effects occur because neither (in press) clarify the matter:
memory nor perception are passive processes. In 196S the American Psychiatric Association . . .
They are active, constructive ones in which assigned its Committee on Nomenclature and Sta-
the individual is swiftly and unwittingly tistics . . . the task of preparing for the APA a
processing, interpreting, construing, and re- new diagnostic manual of disorders. . . . A draft
construing events that are observed. Seem- of the new manual, DSM II, was circulated in 1967
to 120 psychiatrists known to have special interests
ingly small changes in context, conveyed by in the area of diagnosis and was revised on the basis
a word, an instruction, a setting, or even a of their criticisms and suggestions. After further
gesture, greatly alter understanding. They study it was adopted by the APA in 1967, and
affect what is retrieved from memory. They published and officially accepted throughout the
country in 1968.
affect judgment. They affect perception. And
they affect psychiatric judgment and percep- Nothing underscores the consensual nature
tion no less than judgment and perception in of psychiatric disorders more than the recent
other areas. action by the American Psychiatric Associa-
Psychiatric diagnoses imply that what the tion to delete homosexuality from the Diag-
diagnostician sees is descriptive of the pa- nostic and Statistical Manual on Mental
tient's condition. Much as a cancer patient Disorders (DSM-II, 1968). Whatever one's
has cancer, the psychiatric patient is schizo- opinion regarding the nature of homosexual-
phrenic or manic-depressive, no matter where ity, the fact that a professional association
he is seen. But human behavior, even dis- could vote on whether or not homosexuality
tressed human behavior, is no less ambiguous should be considered a disorder surely under-
than other ambiguous stimuli, and no less scores both the differences between psy-
amenable to context-dependent interpretation. chiatric/mental disorders and the context-
Moreover, with regard to distressed behavior, susceptibility of psychiatric ones. Changes in
there is particular reason to believe that how- informed public attitudes toward homosexual-
ever deep one's belief that what is perceived
1<(
is schizophrenia, that belief is by no means The acceptable risk depends on the type of
compelling. Another diagnostician, equally decision being made. In individual decisions (par-
ticularly counseling), it is generally desirable to be
sure of his skill, may arrive at a quite differ- conservative, seeking additional information rather
ent diagnosis. Indeed, if 35 years of studies than accepting a hazardous conclusion. When a
on agreement among diagnosticians have terminal decision is under consideration, it appears
taught us anything, it is that, despite subjec- reasonable to set the maximum risk as .10 or .OS
tive conviction and regardless of skill and meaning that 1 in 10, or 1 in 20 decisions could be
wrong. An even lower level might be desired for an
training, coefficients of diagnostic agreement important decision that could not be reversed should
(K) between psychiatrists viewing the same it prove to be wrong in the light of later experience"
behavior rarely exceed .8 (which, for purposes (Cronbach & Gleser, 1959, p. 233).
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 465

ity have brought about corresponding changes unmasked. Some of it had its source in a fear
in the psychiatric perception of it. of the familiar unknown: Although several
had worked in psychiatric hospitals, they had
SANE IN INSANE PLACES neither been there as patients nor spent much
time there at night or during the weekends.
Turning now to the studies under review, Their vantage point was commonly from
it should be clear that if the contexts created behind the desk or in the nurses' station.
by setting influence psychiatric perception, Nothing underscored their vulnerability to
then sane people who enter a psychiatric hos- forces outside their control more than their
pital should be diagnosed with the common impending hospitalization as pseudopatients.
psychiatric designation for hospitalized pa- Nervousness, then, was unintended but also
tients (schizophrenia) even though their pre- unavoidable.
senting symptoms in no way describe that For most of the pseudopatients, then,
disorder. Correspondingly, if the contexts these two symptoms—plus the fact that they
created by set color psychiatric perception, showed up at the hospital in the first place—
then mental health professionals who expect constitute the entirety of their deception.
to find pseudopatients on their ward should These symptoms, of course, do not in any way
diagnose many true patients as pseudopatients. constitute schizophrenia. That was not the
intention. They were simply intended to be
Presenting Symptoms sufficient to get them into the hospital.
Eight sane people2 gained admission to 12 Beyond the simulation of hallucinations and
psychiatric hospitals by simulating a single some concomitant nervousness, no further
symptom, hallucinations. These hallucinations alteration of history or circumstances was
had a special character. Their content had made. The significant events of the pseudo-
never been reported in the psychological patients' life histories were presented as they
literature. They were, by design, interesting had occurred. Relationships with parents and
auditory hallucinations that were perceived as siblings, with spouse and children, and with
a voice that said "empty," "dull," and people at work and in school were described
"thud." It was intended that these hallucina- as they were or had been. Despite the absence
tions might lead an observer to suspect an of abnormal indications beyond those de-
interesting existential problem, as if these scribed, 11 of the pseudopatients were diag-
people were looking back over their lives and nosed, initially and finally, paranoid schizo-
characterizing them as empty and dull. They phrenia, and the 12th was diagnosed manic
were designed primarily to get the pseudo- depressive psychosis.
patients into the hospital. Thus, set and setting, the contexts of mind
Hallucinations, however, were not the only and environment, heavily determine psychi-
symptom that was presented. Behavioral atric diagnosis. But insofar as set is heavily
nervousness was another. Some of the pseudo- permeated with expectation, it should prove
patients had had only fleeting prior con- at least partially reversible. An experiment
tact with psychiatric hospitals. Others, even was arranged at a hospital where the staff had
though they had been employed there, were heard these findings but doubted that such
nevertheless nervous. Some of the nervous- an error could occur in their institution. Each
ness appeared to arise from a fear of being staff member rated every patient who ap-
peared at admissions or on the ward accord-
2
The ambiguity of the term, mental illness, makes ing to the likelihood that the patient was a
it difficult to find an unambiguous term that denotes pseudopatient. Judgments were obtained on
its opposite. Mentally healthy, normal, and without 193 patients who were admitted for psychi-
severe psychological anguish all have difficulties of atric treatment. Forty-one patients were al-
their own. I have chosen the words sane and insane leged, with high confidence, to be pseudo-
to approximate the conditions I would describe.
Many writers have correctly observed that these patients by at least one member of the staff,
terms have legal connotations. But to my knowledge, 23 patients were considered suspect by at
all other terms have greater disadvantages. least one psychiatrist, and 19 were suspected
466 DAVID L. ROSENHAN

by one psychiatrist and one other staff mem- in the past given evidence of severe psycho-
ber. The pseudopatient who was designated logical disorders, and (e) who apparently
for this hospital became ill and never entered. have nothing to gain from malingering and
Thus the obtained data are for real patients. for whom there is no evidence of malingering?
Both studies confirm the view that the con- It should be noted that no party to this
texts of mind and setting color psychiatric debate denies that the diagnoses that were
perceptions, and there are others that make actually given to the pseudopatients were
the same point. Temerlin (1968), for exam- erroneous. Spitzer (1975) directly expresses
ple, has shown that comments about a patient the hope that, had he examined one of the
from a prestigious source have remarkable pseudopatients, "I would have been struck by
effects on how he is perceived. From a tape the lack of other signs of the disorder." Both
recorded interview, a doctor described a pa- Spitzer (1975) and Weiner (1975) go to
tient as interesting "because he looks neurotic, great lengths to exonerate the diagnosticians,
but actually is quite psychotic." The group but all agree that the diagnoses were wrong.
of psychiatrists, clinical psychologists, and I agree with them and with Millon (1975)
graduate clinical psychology students who that the fault lies not with the diagnosticians
heard this comment rated the interviewee as but elsewhere. We shall take up this matter
emotionally ill significantly more often than at greater length later. For the moment, let
the controls who had either not heard the us note our agreement that the diagnoses
suggestion or had heard it reversed. were wrong.
A study by Langer and Abelson (1974) The central issue regarding diagnosis needs
deals with the same issue. A videotaped inter- to be understood (see Rosenhan, 1973b,
view of a young man describing his job his- 1973c). The issue is not that the pseudopa-
tory and difficulties was presented to clini- tients lied or that the psychiatrists believed
cians who were known to have either a them. The pseudopatients should not have
behavioral or a traditional psychodynamic been diagnosed Munchausen disease or Ganser
viewpoint. Half of the clinicians were told syndrome—-diagnoses that imply that the psy-
that the young man was a job applicant, chiatrists understood that the patients were
whereas the remaining half were told that he feigning a symptom. Such diagnoses take
was a patient. The clinicians' evaluations of much more evidence than can typically be
the subject were quantified on a scale that assembled in an admissions interview. The
ranged from 1 (very disturbed), through a issue is not whether the pseudopatients should
midpoint, to 10 (very well adjusted). Those have been admitted to the psychiatric hos-
words, job applicant and patient, formed en- pital in the first place. If there were beds,
tirely different contexts for these judgments admitting the pseudopatients was the only
among traditional diagnosticians. Enormous humane thing to do.
differences were found in their judgment The issue is the diagnostic leap that was
of the subject's adjustment according to made between a single presenting symptom,
whether the identical tape was presented as hallucination, and the diagnosis, schizophrenia
a patient interview (^ = 3.47) or a job (or, in one case, manic-depressive psychosis).
interview (% = 6.2). The more traditional the That is the heart of the matter. Had the
orientation of the clinician, the larger the pseudopatient been diagnosed hallucinating,
difference was. there would have been no further need to
examine the diagnostic issue. The diagnosis
of hallucinations implies only that: no more.
Proper Diagnoses
The presence of a hallucination does not
What are the proper diagnoses for people itself define the presence of schizophrenia,
(a) who manifest some nervousness, complain and schizophrenia may or may not include
of hallucinations, and nothing else, (b) whose hallucinations.
personal histories betray no sign of severe Lest the matter reduce to one scientist's
psychological distress, (c) whose relationships word against others', let us examine the
are basically unimpaired, (d) who have never standard for diagnosis in psychiatry, the
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 467

DSM-II: He rules out alcohol, drug abuse, organic


295. Schizophrenia. This large category includes
causes, or toxic psychosis as the cause of the
a group of disorders manifested by charac- hallucination. He rules out affective psychosis.
teristic disturbances of thinking, mood, and The evidence, he says, does not support
behavior. Disturbances in thinking are "hysterical psychosis," and there was no
marked by alterations of concept formation reason to believe that the illness was feigned.
which may lead to misinterpretation of
reality and sometimes to delusions and hal- Spitzer writes:
lucinations, which frequently appear psycho-
logically self-protective. Corollary mood Dear reader: There is only one remaining diagnosis
changes include ambivalence, constricted and for the presenting symptom of hallucinations under
inappropriate emotional responsiveness and these conditions in the classification of mental dis-
loss of empathy with others. Behavior may orders used in this country and that is schizophrenia,
be withdrawn, regressive and bizarre. (p. 446)
295.3 Schizophrenia, paranoid type . . . charac-
terized primarily by the presence of perse- This is, of course, diagnosis by exclusion.
cutory or grandiose delusions, often associ- And it makes schizophrenia a wastebasket
ated with hallucinations. Excessive religiosity diagnosis, a designation to be applied when
is sometimes seen. The patient's attitude is
frequently hostile and aggressive, and his nothing else fits. One would not have judged
behavior tends to be consistent with his as much from the quotation offered above
delusions, (pp. 33-34) from the DSM-II, but perhaps in practice
(and with sanction) it is. If that is the case,
But what then is the proper diagnosis for readers will judge for themselves whether the
such complaints as the pseudopatients pre- designation is useful, whether it constitutes a
sented? I suggest the following: Hallucina- diagnosis in any sense of that term, and how
tions, hallucinations of unknown origin, ?, likely it is for misdiagnoses to occur under
or DD (diagnosis deferred). Millon points such conditions.
out that the diagnosis of hallucinations of
unknown origin is fraught with contextual It should now be clear that it is not the
psychiatrists who diagnosed the pseudopa-
difficulties. There is merit in his view, and I
tients but "the classification of mental dis-
hold no special brief for that diagnosis. Cer-
orders used in this country" (Spitzer, 197S)
tainly it is not the ultimate diagnosis. But it
that is being questioned by these data. That
may very well be the one that reflects the
question is supported by data from others.
present state of our knowledge better than
Ward, Beck, Mendelson, Mock, and Erbaugh
traditional nosology does. Indeed, at present,
(1962), in a study of diagnostic disagree-
my own preference runs to omitting diagnoses
ment, found that inadequacy of the diagnostic
entirely, for it is far better from a scientific
nosology accounted for 62.5% of the reasons
and treatment point of view to acknowledge
for disagreement, and another 32.5% was
ignorance than to mystify it with diag-
accounted for by inconsistency on the part
noses that are unreliable, overly broad, and
of the diagnostician. Despite the attempts of
pejoratively connotative.
the DSM-II to elaborate the symptomology
associated with each presumed disorder, be-
CRITICISMS
haviors are too variable and their meanings
Paranoid Schizophrenia: "The Most Likely too dependent on contextual perception for
Condition"? them to be captured under the rubrics pro-
Much of Spitzer's (197S) critique consists posed by the DSM-II. The very ambiguity
of the justification of the diagnosis of schizo- of behavior, the fact that its meanings are
not automatically transparent, defeats such
phrenia.
attempts at classification from the outset, at
Unfortunately . . . many readers, including psychi- least within the psychiatric hospital.
atrists, were, in my judgment, wrong in accepting If anything, Spitzer's comments regarding
Rosenhan's thesis that it was irrational for the
psychiatrists to have made an initial diagnosis of schizophrenia as "the most likely condition,"
schizophrenia as the most likely condition on the support the general views that were pro-
basis of a single symptom, (p. 445) pounded in "On Being Sane in Insane Places"
468 DAVID L. ROSENHAN

(Rosenhan, 1973a). Acknowledging that the is called paranoid schizophrenic, in remission.


diagnosis of paranoid schizophrenia was an Are both characterizations synonymous? Of
error in 11 out of 11 instances (recall that course not. Would it matter to you if on one
the 12th was diagnosed manic depressive occasion you were designated normal, and on
psychosis, a diagnosis that amounts to the the other you were called psychotic, in remis-
same error for these purposes), Spitzer offers sion, with both designations arising from the
some illuminating insights regarding how identical behavior? Of course it would matter.
such a patient error might nevertheless have The perception of an asymptomatic status
been made. I have no disagreement with him implies little by itself; it is the context in
on this score. Indeed, I concur heartily. But which that perception is embedded that tells
I emphasize, as I did in the original article, the significant story.
that "any diagnostic process that lends itself It is useful to observe here that the term
so readily to massive errors of this sort "in remission" was used as the most conserva-
cannot be a very reliable one" (Rosenhan, tive designation for patients' discharge diag-
1973a, p. 252). noses. Actually, eight of the patients were
Attribution and logical analyses. The fore- discharged in remission, three as improved,
going should clarify why neither attribution and one as asymptomatic. The latter two
theory nor logical analysis (Weiner, 197S) designations imply less of a perception of
justify the observed findings. Attribution change than does the phrase in remission.
theory is a theory of error. It is, as Heider But all three descriptors reify the original
(19S8) stated, a naive psychology, one that diagnosis. They do not imply that the diag-
accounts for why people might believe that nosis was wrong or questionable, or that over
the world is flat, that heavy stones fall faster the course of the hospitalization behaviors
than light ones, or that the sun rises in the that are inconsistent with the diagnosis of
east and sets in the west—even in the face schizophrenia were observed which suggested
of contrary evidence. But diagnosis should that the diagnosis might have been an error.
be based on scientific evidence and careful Nothing altered the original diagnosis. Diag-
assessment of facts, not on the attributional nostic labels, once applied, have a stickiness
inferences of naive observers. Indeed, Weiner's of their own.
observations, like Spitzer's, support the view It is, in fact, a very painful commentary
put forth in "On Being Sane in Insane on the state of this healing art that, at best,
Places" (Rosenhan, 1973a) by telling us pre- only a handful of patients are discharged
cisely how (and how easily) psychiatric from psychiatric hospitals in remission, no
diagnosis goes astray. The present system of longer ill, recovered, or asymptomatic. Be-
psychiatric diagnosis lends itself too easily to cause if these designations are rarely used,
attributional errors. It needs seriously to be how much rarer must the designation "cured"
questioned. be? And yet, one wonders. The literature on
reactive schizophrenia conveys the impression
In Remission Does Not Mean Sane of far greater success than is implied by
Spitzer (1975) points out that the designa- Spitzer's discharge data. Could it be that we
tion "in remission" is exceedingly rare. It are not seeing something? Could it be that
occurs in only a handful of cases in the hos- the psychiatric hospital holds many more
pitals he surveyed, and my own cursory in- recovered, improved, and no longer ill people
vestigations that were stimulated by his, con- who have been designated schizophrenic than
firm these observations. His data are intrinsi- our context-bound perceptions allow us to
cally interesting as well as interesting for the see? It is not a question that I can answer
meaning they have for this particular study. here, but it surely is one that is worthy of
How shall they be understood? careful consideration. '
Once again we return to the influence of
context on psychiatric perception. Consider Experimenter Bias
two people who show no evidence of psycho- Is it possible that experimenter bias in-
pathology. One is called sane and the other fected the admissions and hospitalization pro-
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 469

cedures in such a way as to guarantee one lating a florid pattern of symptomology


particular outcome over another? If that is throughout. He was consumed with guilt over
the case, then both Millon and Spitzer may deceiving his colleagues and his report of his
be correct in describing the findings as trivial. experiences was an excruciating warning to
Millon states it directly: subsequent scientific generations that such
elaborate deceptions can have enormous per-
At best, it supports the following rather trivial sonal consequences. All of the pseudopatients
finding: Confederates of an experimenter who know
the hypothesis being tested and who feign being knew of Caudill's work and were told that
psychologically disturbed, consistent with that hy- the simulation of a single symptom would
pothesis, will temporarily deceive unsuspecting cli- likely reduce these problems. Abandoning
nicians accustomed to working in mental institutions. even that symptom immediately on admission
(P. 4S7) would not only reduce further that potential
Spitzer says that the study: source of stress but also allow them to move
more freely on the ward and among the
proves that pseudopatients are not detected by psy- patients. Moreover, I was aware that the
chiatrists as having simulated signs of mental illness. simulation of a single symptom would facili-
This rather unremarkable finding is not relevant to tate discharge, which was a matter of no small
the real problems of reliability and validity of
psychiatric diagnosis and only serves to obscure them, concern when these studies were initiated.
(p. 4S1) The history and current direction of the
project then, make no presuppositions regard-
Are they correct? ing the effects of any diagnosis on patient
The possibility of experimenter bias cannot care. However, might there not have been
be dismissed. Its manifestations are legion, incidental departures from protocol on the
and many of the subtle ways by which it parts of the pseudopatients? Our inquiries,
is communicated are as yet unknown (cf. conducted immediately after the pseudopa-
Rosenthal, 1966). But both the history and tients were admitted, revealed only one such
conduct of this project, as well as an examina- incident. In that instance, a pseudopatient
tion of the notion of experimenter bias as it altered his personal history by denying that
might apply here, is reassuring in this regard. he was married and alleging that his parents
This project began as, and continues to be, were deceased. His data, however, were
an investigation of the care and perception omitted from the study (see Rosenhan,
of patients in the environments in which such 1973a, footnote 6), even though they were
care occurs. Utilizing the disciplined observa- consistent with the data from another pseudo-
tion technologies of social psychology and patient.
anthropology, its concern is not primarily with It is important, however, to ask some dif-
diagnosis but only with diagnosis as it affects ficult questions of experimenter bias in this
perception of patients and the nature and connection. Granting for the moment that
quality of their care. experimenter bias did affect these procedures,
In seeking admission to psychiatric hos- could it possibly have accounted for these
pitals, the pseudopatients did not simulate findings? I believe not, because although ex-
their single symptom to trap admission of- perimenter bias has been found to be an out-
ficers into making an erroneous diagnosis. come determinant of some power, it is not
Their use of a single symptom, and its aban- overwhelmingly powerful. In the present case,
donment after they were admitted, served the 12 out of 12 sane admissions were accorded
central purpose of minimizing their own a severe psychiatric diagnosis. To insist that
psychological burdens. Recall that we were all of them were misdiagnosed on the basis
not the first people to utilize pseudopatient- of experimenter bias places considerably more
hood to investigate the treatment milieu of weight on that variable than it possibly can
psychiatric hospitals. More than two decades bear. After all, not all of Rosenthal and
earlier, Caudill (19S8; Caudill, Redlich, Jacobson's (1968) late bloomers were subse-
Gilmore, & Brody, 1952) had spent consider- quently tested in the superior intelligence
able time in a psychiatric hospital simu- range, which would have been necessary for
470 DAVID L. ROSENHAN

experimenter bias to be as potent as Millon their hospitalization? Anyone who has served
alleges. as a pseudopatient, and most psychiatric pa-
Experimenter bias is a set, a member of the tients, will find that view untenable. Psychi-
class of sets that I have subsumed under the atric hospitals, even the best of them, are
notion of contexts. It is a context of mind, places as dull and difficult for people who
and as such it can cut two ways: It can favor do not belong there as they often are for true
or disfavor an hypothesis. Recall the chal- patients. It asks too much of ordinary people
lenge experiment that was arranged at a re- to remain locked into a psychiatric hospital
search and teaching hospital where the staff for as long as 52 days merely to provide a
had heard these findings but doubted that diagnostic point that was made well on
such an error could occur in their hospital. admission.
There we saw an instance of bias cutting in Demand characteristics. Millon (197S)
the direction of overdiagnosing sanity, at least questions whether, in addition to experimenter
according to the base rate of that particular bias, demand characteristics might have
hospital. The staff were quite confident of played a role in the obtained outcome.
their ability to use the DSM-II and the vari- Demand characteristics are powerful vari-
ants on it that they had invented, and indeed ables, as the history of hypnosis research at-
they engaged in this small study because they tests (Orne, 1969). It is, however, difficult to
were certain we were wrong. However, given discern from Millon's critique in what sense
a set in favor of detection, they overdetected. demand characteristics are being invoked
In this regard, I have been told that here. Often, demand characteristics are seen
pseudopatients would have been detected in to operate in the pact of ignorance that is
a military hospital, and quite possibly by made between an experimenter and his sub-
forensic psychiatrists. And that may be the jects, so that each will not reveal his secret
case. But observe that in the latter instances understandings of the experiment. Surely, that
bias cuts in favor of detection. Clearly, it could not have been the case here, at least
does not cut in that direction in the typical from the admissions officer's viewpoint. An-
psychiatric institution. other meaning of demand characteristics
Finally, discharge diagnoses are interesting refers to controlling the setting in such a way
because they occur after a lengthy period of that a particular outcome is more assured
observation, thus providing ample time for than it might ordinarily be. This is unlikely in
diagnostic errors to be corrected. Visitors' the present instance because we did not con-
notes (including notes written by concerned trol the setting. No other meaning of demand
members of the pseudopatients' families) pro- characteristics seems relevant to this experi-
vide no evidence that the pseudopatients ment. But the fact that the demand character-
were actively biasing their behavior in the istics of psychiatric hospitals lead its person-
direction of craziness. If anything, they were nel to believe that all those who are not staff
often attempting to impress the staff with are likely to be schizophrenic or manic-
their sanity, a complex matter to which I depressive is certainly consistent with our
shall return. Moreover, true patients com- view of these data.
monly recognized the pseudopatients as sane Could the experiment have been done dif-
during their hospitalization. Nevertheless, the ferently? Undoubtedly, the experiment could
discharge diagnoses were consistent with the have been conducted another way, and be-
admission diagnoses. Admitted in the main cause no single experiment ever fully eluci-
with the diagnosis of schizophrenia, they dates a phenomenon, surely there will be other
were discharged with the same diagnosis, work in this area that tightens these findings,
but in remission or improved. The argu- illuminates them further, replicates, and ex-
ment for experimenter bias becomes much tends them. The use of televised stimuli, such
less convincing over the length of these as those employed by Langer and Abelson
hospitalizations. (1974), offers clear control advantages that
Can it seriously be held with Millon (1975) may offset what is lost in ecological validity.
that because of their biases patients prolonged And as far as in vivo studies are concerned,
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 471

the use of new and different symptom sets with only one exception, were not hospitalized
might establish the limits of contextual inter- in their own communities, they indicated that
pretations of behavior in these settings. they did not have a personal physician in the
Both Millon and Weiner suggest that one community. (The single exception did not,
might simply have people come to the admis- in fact, have a personal physician.) More-
sions office and request hospitalization with- over, they indicated that they had heard that
out falsifying a symptom. This is an interest- "this is a good hospital" and had therefore
ing idea, but one that I doubt would work. come on their own initiative.
Diagnosticians, like anyone else, are not I have dealt with the problem of justifying
passive in the face of stimulus ambiguity. the presence of the pseudopatients, either at
They inquire. They search. They attempt to the admissions office or on the ward, by em-
obtain more data to reduce stimulus ambi- ploying a single symptom that does not
guity interpretively. And what might the qualify for a standard diagnosis. Such a
pseudopatient say regarding his desire to be symptom should, as I have earlier indicated,
admitted? What justification could he present? alert a paradox, an inquiry, or a deferral of
The same problem arises with the sugges- diagnosis. Given that the admitting and at-
tion that sane people be directly placed on tending staff are competently trained, the easy
the ward to see if they can be distinguished assignment of a standard diagnosis confirms
from insane ones. If such a differentiation is the view that the diagnostic system is not
intended to occur without talking to patients, working. Recall again that the central diag-
there would very likely be low capacity to nostic issue is the imaginative leap that was
detect. It was the common experience of made between a single presenting symptom
pseudopatients on wards where staff dressed and a global pejorative diagnosis.
casually that they could not determine who Sanity on the ward. Did the pseudopatients'
was staff and who patient for some time. behaviors on the ward fall within an accept-
(One gleans similar impressions from new able definition of sane behavior? The problem
interns and residents who enter an informal is fascinating, because it directly implicates
ward—it is difficult to tell the patients from the influence of context on meaning. Millon
the staff by merely looking.) Talking to the puts the challenge squarely. He asserts that
real and pseudopatients is a different matter. they did not behave sanely at all.
Again, one reduces stimulus ambiguity, but Quite the contrary. The behaviors they portrayed
one also encounters the problem of justifying were "standard" hospital patient behaviors. Though
the pseudopatient's presence on the ward. reported in cryptic fashion, it appears that the
Spitzer (1975) deals directly with reduction pseudopatients sat around quietly, acted coopera-
tively, said they were fine in response to staff in-
of stimulus ambiguity in my study when he quiries, and asked innocuous questions such as,
asks, "What did the pseudopatients say . . . "When will I be eligible for ground privileges?"
when asked, as they must have been, what None of these would characterize a sane person in
effect the hallucinations were having on their that situation, (p. 457)
lives and why they were seeking admission in Spitzer, quoting Hunter (Letters, 1973),
a hospital?" (p. 447). They responded that concurs enthusiastically in that view:
the hallucinations troubled them greatly at
the outset, but less so now. They denied The pseudopatients did not behave normally in the
hospital. Had their behavior been normal, they
being greatly distracted by them, but seemed would have walked to the nurses' station and said,
mainly puzzled and naturally concerned. They "Look, I am a normal person who tried to see if I
had been told by friends to come to the hos- could get into the hospital by behaving in a crazy
pital (or mental health center). The latter way and saying crazy things. It worked and I was
response often alerted considerable surprise admitted to the hospital, but now I would like to
be discharged from the hospital." (p. 443)
in the admitting psychiatrist, and several
pseudopatients were carefully queried about These are interesting observations because
why they had not first taken their problem to they demonstrate the degree to which con-
their personal physician or a psychiatrist in text colors both expectation and perception.
the community. Because the pseudopatients, Because patients are cooperative in a hospital,
472 DAVID L. ROSENHAN

because they say "fine" in response to staff ior in such circumstances should be. Which
inquiries, because they are quiet and ask psychology of behavior suggests that there
questions about their eligibility for ground is one and only one normal response to a
privileges, those behaviors, ipso facto, become given situation? Is it abnormal to stay in a
abnormal, without additional validation or hospital because one finds it interesting (or
further proof. How long might it take a true because one has made friends, or has nowhere
patient, behaving in this perfectly reasonable else to go), anymore thai! it is to stay at
manner to convince staff that he is indeed one's desk on a beautiful day because one is
sane? And at what point do both clinical staff absorbed in one's work? How might you know
and researchers take notice of the on-off whether such behavior is normal or abnormal
behavior of true patients and begin to ask if you didn't inquire carefully—and no one
serious questions about it? did. Is normal or abnormal behavior self-
In this connection it is useful to record evident from outside the person? Does one
some of the actions of the pseudopatients and not need to inquire into the reasons for stay-
the staff responses. They occasionally inter- ing in a hospital just as carefully as one
vened with staff on behalf of other patients. inquires into the reasons for wanting to leave?
They were friendly toward other patients, Finally, it was precisely on the basis of
helpful to them, active on the wards, com- such behaviors (the normality of which
forting to patients in their distress, and thera- Spitzer and Millon question) that the staff in
peutic with patients, but because all of this the challenge experiment detected pseudopa-
occurred on the ward, it was never seen as tients. Set in the direction of discovering
normal behavior. Indeed, two pseudopatients pseudopatients, they now used those very
who directly requested discharge from staff same standard hospital behaviors to arrive at
members were simply ignored, and treated as their conclusions. In isolation, such behaviors
yet another annoying request from another tell us little about patients' psychiatric status.
annoying patient. They essentially serve to confirm staff biases.
Given that patients are shorn of credibility Identical behaviors have vastly different
and are commonly held suspect in such meanings according to staff preconceptions
matters by staff, would it really have been that are acquired through set and setting.
normal to go up to the nurses' station and That is precisely the meaning of context
say, "Look, I'm a normal person?" Might dependency in psychiatric diagnosis.
that not be construed as precisely the insane The problem of what is normal and what
thing to do? I suspect that it might, and is abnormal behavior is a complicated one in
genuine patients have the same impression. any setting. Some would seriously question the
(Recall the poor soul in the film Titticut epistemological utility of such categorizations.
Follies who did insist on being discharged for But regardless, Spitzer's and Millon's fairly
these very reasons.) We commonly asked pa- arbitrary classification of these behaviors only
tients, "How do you get out of the hospital?" further reveals their context dependency.
Never did a patient advise, "Just tell them
you're fine now, and that you want to go THE FUTURE
home." They recognized that they would not It is natural to infer that what I have
be believed. More commonly they encouraged written here argues against categorization of
us to be cooperative, patient, and not make all kinds. But that is not the case. I have
waves. Sometimes they recommended a special been careful to direct attention to the present
kind of indirection: "Don't tell them you're system of diagnosis, the DSM-II. It may be
well. They won't believe you. Tell them you're useful to close this essay with a few words
sick, but getting better. That's called insight, on the conditions under which diagnosis may
and they'll discharge you!" prove useful and the requirements that we
Much as set and setting determine what must set for those who would produce new
Spitzer (1975) and Millon (1975) view as diagnostic systems.
abnormal behavior, so do they offer us an First, as long as differences exist between
especially narrow view of what normal behav- people, it is possible to classify and cate-
CONTEXTUAL NATURE OF PSYCHIATRIC DIAGNOSIS 473

gorize. The thrust of any rational argument reasonable person would protest psychiatric
cannot be against classification, per se, but classification. And until such requirements are
only against poor classification and mis- fulfilled, protests directed aginst classification
classification as it occurs with certain systems will seem reasonable indeed.
and affects patients' welfare.
Second, 'scientific understanding, if not REFERENCES
human understanding, proceeds on the basis American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and
of classification. Nothing that is said here Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-II).
is intended to deprive the researcher of his Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Associa-
classificatory system. He cannot proceed tion, 1968.
without it, but as long as his diagnostic data Caudill, W. The psychiatric hospital as a small
society. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
remain in his file until they are fully vali- Press, 1958.
dated, they can do patients and treatment Caudill, W., Redlich, F. C., Gilmore, H. R., &
no harm. Brody, E. B. Social structure and interaction
Third, with regard to new classification process on a psychiatric ward. American Journal
systems that are intended for clinical usage of Orthopsychiatry, 1952, 22, 314-334.
Cronbach, L. J., & Gleser, C. C. Interpretation of
with patients, we can require that evidence for reliability and validity coefficients: Remarks on a
their utility precede its promulgation. That paper by Lord. Journal of Educational Psychol-
has not hitherto been the case. Unlike psycho- ogy, 19S9, SO, 230-237.
logical tests, which need to be validated be- Cronbach, L. J., Gleser, G. C., Harinder, N., &
fore they are distributed, the Diagnostic and Nageswari, R. The dependability of behavioral
measurements: Theory of generalizability for scores
Statistical Manuals have been promulgated and profiles. New York: Wiley, 1972.
by the American Psychiatric Association be- Heider, F. The psychology of interpersonal relations.
fore being carefully validated. As I indicated New York: Wiley, 1958.
earlier, they rest heavily on consensus, rather Hunter, F. M. Letters to the editor. Science, 1973,
than fact. 180, 361.
What might we require of new diagnostic Jenkins, J. J. Remember that old theory of memory?
Well, forget it! American Psychologist, 1974, 29,
systems before they are published and offi- 785-795.
cially accepted? First, we should ask that Jonides, J., & Gleitman, H. A conceptual category
coefficients of agreements between diagnosti- effect in visual search: O as letter or as digit.
cians in a variety of settings commonly reach Perception and Psychophysics, 1972,12, 457-460.
or exceed .90. That figure, which is associated Langer, E. J., & Abelson, R. P. A patient by any
other name . . . ! Clinician group differences in
with a bit more than 80% of the variance in labeling bias. Journal of Consulting and Clinical
diagnosis, is a liberal one in terms of the pos- Psychology, 1974, 42, 4-9.
sible consequences of misdiagnosis and the Loftus, E. F., & Palmer, J. C. Reconstruction of an
reversibility of the diagnoses.1 The full rea- automobile destruction: An example of the inter-
action between language and memory. Journal of
soning behind that figure takes us away from Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 1974, 13,
the central thrust of this paper, but interested 585-589.
readers can confirm it for themselves in Millon, T. Reflections on Rosenhan's "On Being Sane
Cronbach, Gleser, Harinder, and Nageswari in Insane Places." Journal of Abnormal Psychol-
ogy, 1975, 84, 456-461.
(1972) and Cronbach and Gleser (1959). Orne, M. T. Demand characteristics and the concept
Second, we should require that the proven of quasi-controls. In R. Rosenthal & R. Rosnow
utility of such a system exceed its liabilities (Eds.), Artifact in behavioral research. New York:
for patients. Understand the issue. Syphilis Academic Press, 1969.
Rosenhan, D. L. On being sane in insane places.
and cancer both have negative social and Science, 1973, 179, 250-258. (a)
emotional overtones, but the treatments that Rosenhan, D. L. Letters to the editor. Science, 1973,
exist for them presumably exceed the personal 180, 365-369. (b)
liabilities associated with the diagnosis. We Rosenhan, D. L. Letters to the editor. Journal of
ask no less of psychiatric categorization: that the American Medical Association, 1973, 224, 1646-
1647. (c)
the diagnoses lead to useful treatments that Rosenthal, R. Experimenter effects in behavioral
cannot be implemented without the diagnoses. research. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts,
Under such conditions, I doubt that any 1966.
474 DAVID L. ROSENHAN
Rosenthal, R., & Jacobson, L. Pygmalion In the class- Spitzer, R. L., & Wilson, P. T. Nosology and the
room: Teacher expectation and pupils' intellectual official psychiatric nomenclature. In A. Freedman
development. New York: Holt, Rinehart & & H. Kaplan (Eds.), Comprehensive textbook of
Winston, 1968. psychiatry. New York: Williams & Wilkins, in
Selfridge, O. G. Pattern recognition and modern press.
computers. Proceedings of the Western Joint Com- Temerlin, M. K. Suggestion effects in psychiatric
puter Conference, Los Angeles, Calif., 1955. Cited diagnosis, Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease,
in Neisser, U., Cognitive psychology. New York: 1968, 147, 349-359.
Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1967. Ward, C. H., Beck, A. T., Mendelson, M., Mock,
Spitzer, R. L. On pseudoscience in science, logic in J. E., & Erbaugh, J. K. The psychiatric nomen-
remission, and psychiatric diagnoses: A critique clature: Reasons for diagnostic disagreement.
of Rosenhan's "On Being Sane in Insane Places." Archives of General Psychiatry, 1962, 7, 198-205.
Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 1975, 84, 442- Weiner, B. "On being sane in insane places": A
452. process (attributional) analysis and critique. Jour-
Spitzer, R. L., & Fleiss, J. L. A reanalysis of the nal of Abnormal Psychology, 1975, 84, 433-441.
reliability of psychiatric diagnosis. British Journal
of Psychiatry, 1974, 125, 341-347. (Received April 8, 1975)

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen