Sie sind auf Seite 1von 4

Analytic versus

Continental Philosophy
Kile Jones explains the differences between these ways of thinking
“What’s in a name? That which we call a rose write political philosophy or harvest the blessings of history is
By any other name would smell as sweet.” to be mistaken. One need only think of A Theory of Justice by
Romeo and Juliet John Rawls or The History of Western Philosophy by Bertrand
Russell. On the other side, it is not as if continental philosophy

S
hakespeare never met Wittgenstein, Russell, or Ryle, has nothing to contribute to logic or language; Hegel wrote
and one wonders what a conversation between them extensively on logic, and Heidegger extensively on language. In
would have been like. “What’s in a name, you ask?” fact, every philosopher, if they are at all comprehensive, can be
Wittgenstein might answer “A riddle of symbols.” found to make this line more blurry. Therefore, we must be
Russell might respond “An explanation of concepts,” watchful in our generalizations, realizing that any definitive
and Ryle might retort “Many unneeded problems.” What assertion is likely to be tentative at best.
might Hegel, Husserl, or Nietzsche reply? It seems odd to With this warning in mind it should equally be noted that
even ask such a question, but why? To answer that, we need to these generalizations contain partial truths. Philosophy of
look at the philosophical traditions which these thinkers mind, for instance, is strictly analytical: Hilary Putnam, Daniel
inhabit. This will reveal the differences at the heart of the divi- Dennett, David Chalmers, J.J.C. Smart are all analytic
sion between what have become known as ‘analytic’ and ‘conti- thinkers, and to look for this analysis in traditional continental
nental’ philosophy. I hope that by understanding these two philosophy is like looking for Prester John. Likewise, it is
philosophical camps we may better understand their differ- almost impossible to find analytic philosophers discussing phe-
ences and similarities, as well as how they might compliment nomenology. This reveals that these two camps are clearly
each other. divergent in emphasis and have different places in philosophy.
They have different trajectories, motives, goals, and tools, and
Typical Definitions must be understood in light of their independent and differing
In order to lay a general framework let’s start with some traditions. The question now is, how did these different tradi-
typical definitions that scholars give, despite the fact that these tions come about?
definitions tend towards over-generalization or over-simplifi-
cation. In his well-known collection of essays on this subject, A The Split of Traditions
House Divided, C.G. Prado begins with their difference in If we must start somewhere to find the beginning of this
methodology. He says: split, perhaps we should begin with the Sage of Königsberg,
the great Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). Kant constructed a
“The heart of the analytic/Continental opposition is most evident in method- theory of knowledge to explain how ‘synthetic cognition is pos-
ology, that is, in a focus on analysis or on synthesis. Analytic philosophers sible a priori’ [broadly, how there are some things, which aren’t
typically try to solve fairly delineated philosophical problems by reducing just matters of definition, that we can work out by reason alone
them to their parts and to the relations in which these parts stand. Continen- – Ed]. One crucial step in his process is the bifurcation
tal philosophers typically address large questions in a synthetic or integrative between two realms: the noumenal (things as they are in them-
way, and consider particular issues to be ‘parts of the larger unities’ and as selves) and the phenomenal (things as they appear to us). There is
properly understood and dealt with only when fitted into those unities.” (p.10.) a chasm, says Kant, between what is known in appearance, and
what is beyond any possible experience, and so unknowable (eg
So analytic philosophy is concerned with analysis – analysis God, immortality, freedom). However, there were two major
of thought, language, logic, knowledge, mind, etc; whereas backlashes against Kant’s doctrines.
continental philosophy is concerned with synthesis – synthesis The first of these came in the works of G.W.F. Hegel (1770-
of modernity with history, individuals with society, and specu- 1831), from whom many of the Continental philosophers of
lation with application. the 20th century directly or indirectly drew inspiration. Hegel’s
Neil Levy sees this methodological difference as well; in backlash was primarily against Kant’s separation of the noume-
Metaphilosophy, Vol. 34, No 3, he describes analytic philosophy nal from the phenomenal, ie of reality in itself from its appear-
as a “problem-solving activity,” and continental philosophy as ance. For Hegel there could be no such division, because he
closer “to the humanistic traditions and to literature and art... believed all of reality was united in one Idea. There could be no
it tends to be more ‘politically engaged.” Hans-Johann Glock epistemic chasm between the knowable and unknowable, for
remarks in The Rise of Analytic Philosophy that “analytic philoso- there’s nothing outside the Idea left to be unknown.
phy is a respectable science or skill; it uses specific techniques Hegel became the precursor of the traditional continental
to tackle discrete problems with definite results.” emphasis on grand overarching narratives and the inclusion of
Although these distinctions are helpful in understanding the everything (literature, history, art, etc) into philosophy’s quest.
larger picture, they can be overgeneralizations. To say for Speaking on this last aspect of continental philosophy, Michel
instance that there are no thinkers in analytic philosophy who Foucault noted that “from Hegel to Sartre [continental philoso-

12 Philosophy Now ! July/August 2009


phy] has essentially been a totalizing enterprise.” lytic philosophy. The revolutionary Tractatus Logico-Philosophi-
By the late 19th century Hegel’s idealist approach dominated cus by Russell’s student Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) led
philosophy right across Europe and even in Britain the leading it to focus on the philosophy of language. Wittgenstein had
philosophers – like F.H. Bradley, J.M.E. McTaggart and developed a theory which saw propositions as logical pictures
Thomas Hill Green – were Hegelians. But as the century of states of affairs in the world. This meant that sentences
closed, a second backlash against Kant was brewing both in were only meaningful if they painted such pictures. Thus,
Cambridge and in Vienna. along with Carnap and the Vienna Circle, Wittgenstein found
While Hegel had reacted to Kant’s two-tiered epistemic himself destroying metaphysics and God-talk. In a lecture in
reality, others now reacted against Kant’s synthetic a priori. 1929, Wittgenstein noted that:
G.E. Moore led the attack in Cambridge, rapidly convincing
his colleague Bertrand Russell. Moore insisted on the impor- “in ethical and religious language we seem constantly to be using similes.
tance of analysing concepts; Russell, who was a philosopher of But a simile must be the simile for something. And if I can describe a fact
mathematics, developed a reductionist approach to knowledge by means of a simile I must also be able to drop the simile and to describe
called logical atomism and a general focus on particular logical the facts without it. Now in our case, as soon as we try to drop the simile
problems in opposition to any sort of totalizing enterprise, and simply to state the facts which stand behind it, we find that there are
both of which things led him away from the Hegelians. Mean- no such facts. And so, what at first appeared to be simile now seems to be
while, Ernst Mach, a leading physicist and philosopher, saw mere nonsense.”
Kant’s joining of metaphysics and epistemology as hazardous
to science, and even referred to Kant’s epistemology as ‘mon- Not only was Wittgenstein a fulcrum in the long analytic
strous.’ A group of philosophers in Vienna eventually gathered tradition of anti-God-talk, he created in analytic philosophy a
around the philosopher Moritz Schlick, with the intention of mentality which saw the analysis of language as a tool whereby
furthering Mach’s philosophy. They first called themselves the ‘philosophical pseudo-problems’ could be deflated. What were
‘Ernst Mach Society’ but eventually became known as the once held to be conceptual or logical problems were, accord-
Vienna Circle. Among the many goals of this circle of philoso- ing to Wittgenstein, mere mistakes about language – problems
phers, were the eradication of metaphysics (Carnap), reclaim- created by stepping beyond the limits of language, or through
ing the supremacy of logic in philosophy (Gödel), linguistic semantically misguided statements that confused the logic of
conventionalism (Waismann), and also the debunking of Kant’s language, to be dissolved by an analysis of the propositions in
‘synthetic a priori’. Those in the Vienna Circle instead made question.
the Humean distinction between a priori (non-observable) and
a posteriori (dependent on observation) truths; and they said The Rise of Existentialism and Logical Positivism
that the only truths are either tautological (true by definition) In post WWII France, Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980) popu-
or empirical (verified by observation). larised ‘phenomenological ontology’, which is how he
Therefore, these two reactions to Kant led to the formation described existentialism. This has had decisive effects on Conti-
of two distinct schools of philosophy, each with their separate nental thought up to the present. For Sartre, human ontology
attitude towards metaphysics and epistemology, thus having is united in its complete subjectivity: we are what we choose
differing philosophical methodologies and trajectories. and what we experience. Picking up Heidegger’s teaching of
the Dasein (being-there), Sartre identifies humans as existential
Heidegger and Wittgenstein Widen the Split beings – we have been thrown into an uncaring world and we
As the continental post-Hegelians formulated their various find we are inescapably free and inescapably responsible for
dialectical metaphysics, and while the Vienna Circle con- our actions. Sartre famously remarks:
structed logically-oriented theories of knowledge, German
professor Martin Heidegger (1889-1976) was constructing his “I am abandoned in the world, not in the sense that I might remain aban-
theories of ontology [ontology means ‘the study of being’ – Ed]. doned and passive in a hostile universe like a board floating on the water,
For Heidegger philosophy is, and should be, essentially ontol- but rather in the sense that I find myself suddenly alone and without help,
ogy. He describes philosophy as “universal phenomenological engaged in a world for which I bear the whole responsibility without being
ontology” (Being and Time, p.62), placing Being in an elite able, whatever I do, to tear myself away from this responsibility for an
philosophical category because “it pertains to every entity.” instant.” (Being & Nothingness, p710.)
Contrary to the Vienna Circle, which saw philosophy as
mainly an epistemological project, Heidegger argued that His friend Albert Camus (1913-1960) would find genuine
Being precedes knowledge, and that phenomena (the contents absurdity in our existential state. For Camus, “the absurd is the
of experience) must be studied prior to any logical categoriza- essential concept and the first truth” and “accepting the absur-
tion or interpretation. This turn toward phenomenology cre- dity of everything around us is... a necessary experience” (An
ated in Heidegger a distaste for logical analysis in philosophical Absurd Reasoning, pp.15, 16.) Embracing and challenging the
problems: Richard Matthews describes Heidegger as “trying to absurd character of the world brought about true and authen-
place limits upon logic” and seeking “to free philosophy from tic experience. Yet there were two threats in embracing the
logic”, yet one could go further and say that Heidegger cancels absurd: it might lead to despair and possible suicide; or it could
out logic in favour of a pre-logical phenomenology. lead to idealism and ignorance. The goal is to balance between
Meanwhile there were numerous shifts in emphasis in ana- these extremes of idealism and despair.

July/August 2009 ! Philosophy Now 13


Continental philosophy was undergoing a shift while Sartre mind, introduced ideas that he thought would solve the prob-
and Camus were publishing their numerous works. No longer lem of how the mind and the brain relate. He became one of
were continental thinkers engaged in a totalizing project, but a the founders of functionalism, a theory which analyses mental
firm individualism. Hegel’s utopian ideas about the grand states in terms of their function. He also put forth a theory of
sweep of history had not foreseen WWII and the rise of ‘multiple realizability’, which posits that differing types of
National Socialism. Because of that war, continental philoso- physical entities could experience the same mental state if
phers realized that any enterprise which sought a power there were the right organisational similarities. By contrast,
monopoly, even philosophy itself, was to be mistrusted. Donald Davidson became the champion for a theory known as
Meanwhile, “the rise of analytic philosophy”, Robert Hanna ‘non-reductive physicalism’, which states that only physical
noted, “decisively marked the end of the century-long domi- objects can cause physical effects, but that the mind is not
nance of Kant’s philosophy in Europe” (Kant and the Foundation entirely reducible to the physical brain. David Chalmers,
of Analytic Philosophy, p.5). Logical Positivism brought the director of the Center for Consciousness at Australian
thoughts of the Vienna Circle to fruition while decisively National University, has argued that the mind cannot be
framing the focus of analytic philosophy. Bertrand Russell reducible to the physical brain because of various hypothetical
described his similar program of ‘logical analysis’ thus: arguments, including the possibility of zombies. All of these
theories are within the tradition of analytic philosophy.
“All this [religious dogma and metaphysics] is rejected by the philosophers
who make logical analysis the main business of philosophy… For this renun- Summary: The Story So Far
ciation they have been rewarded by the discovery that many questions, for- There were two distinct responses to Kant’s metaphysical
merly obscured by the fog of metaphysics, can be answered with precision.” and epistemological theories: one by Hegel and much later the
(The History of Western Philosophy, p.835.) other by the Vienna Circle. Hegel rejected Kant’s two-tiered
world by advocating a strict ontological monism, while the
The procedure he named ‘logical analysis’ was to focus on Circle rejected Kant’s synthetic a priori by dividing what can be
logical issues, philosophical problems and epistemology with known into tautologies and empirically verifiable data. Hei-
the tools of scientific testing and procedure, to avoid being degger translates Hegel’s idealist ontology into phenomenol-
caught in the unprofitable web of speculative metaphysics. ogy by placing strict emphasis on being-in-the-world.
This ethos became the trademark of analytic philosophy and Wittgenstein enters the philosophical scene with his analysis of
defined its methodology and trajectory. This was how analytic language, fueling the anti-metaphysical fire of the Vienna Circle
philosophy was truly defined as a separate way of doing philos- by postulating the criteria that language must mirror observable
ophy over and against the continental. nature and nature alone, if it is to be considered meaningful.
Over on the Continent, existentialism adopted many of the
Postmodernism as Modern Continental Philosophy teachings of the phenomenologists and added issues of exis-
On the continent of Europe, existentialism largely ended tence, freedom, angst and absurdity. In England, Logical Posi-
with Sartre and de Beauvoir, but a succession of other move- tivism continued the analytic tradition of the Vienna Circle;
ments there have continued a general trend of sceptical, anti- Russell and A.J. Ayer constructed various theories of knowl-
authoritarian philosophy. Structuralism gave way to post- edge and methods of logical analysis. In recent times post-
structuralism and, with Jacques Derrida, to deconstructionism. modernism has emerged as a dominant strand of continental
Foucault examined issues of government control, madness and philosophy. Postmodernism attacks absolutist views of truth,
sexuality; Baudrillard raised questions on hyper-reality and historical meta-narratives, idealistic metaphysics and linguis-
simulacra, and Vattimo resurrected nihilism. These various tic/semantic realism. On the analytic side, modern philosophy
developments are all loosely called ‘postmodernism’. It’s a hard of mind has emerged as a strong movement which incorpo-
term to define, but what can be said is that it is about the task rates analytic thinking with biology, neuroscience, and physics.
of deconstructing absolute views of reality, truth, value, and Thus, continental philosophy started with German idealism,
meaning. The meta-narratives of German Idealism come which was translated into phenomenology, reconstructed in
sharply under scrutiny in postmodernism, for these overarching existentialism, and is currently still in postmodernist mode.
systems of meaning have, in the postmodern view, only left Analytic philosophy started as a reaction to Kant’s epistemol-
their hopefuls sadly disappointed. Postmodernists view parts of ogy in the Vienna Circle, picked up its linguistic impetus
analytic philosophy as similarly too optimistic and overly self- through Wittgenstein, became strictly formulated by Logical
satisfied – for instance, analytic philosophy’s trust in logic and Positivists and others, and continues today strongly in philoso-
science can be seen as ignoring the big issues of meaning and phy of mind, among other disciplines.
existence. Postmodernism can now be seen as a main terminus What are we to do with analytic and continental philoso-
within continental philosophy for continuing many of its classi- phy, then? Neil Levy makes a great and simple wish when he
cal traditions. writes that we “could hope to combine the strengths of each:
to forge a kind of philosophy with the historical awareness of
Philosophy of Mind as Modern Analytic Philosophy continental philosophy and the rigor of analytic philosophy.”
In the late twentieth century philosophy of mind became (Metaphilosophy, Vol. 34, No.3.) If we are to keep a balance, we
one of the main concerns of analytic philosophy. Hilary must understand that both camps have methods, trajectories,
Putnam, one of the great pioneers of modern philosophy of and emphasis that can be honored and incorporated into a syn-

14 Philosophy Now ! July/August 2009


thesis. This is not to mean that we must believe everything. © KILE JONES 2009
Rather, we should realize that there are correct and incorrect Kile Jones studied philosophy and theology in Boston, and is now
starting points, methods and answers in both analytic and con- taking a PhD at Glasgow University.
tinental philosophy. What a philosopher is dealing with –
specifically, what question she’s trying to answer – largely
determines what emphasis she will have. Yet philosophy can
also be done interchangeably: there is a way of doing analytic
phenomenology, and of doing phenomenological analysis; sci-
entific history and historically-minded science; epistemological
ethics and ethical epistemology.
Although it may be possible to use both camps to construct a
balanced philosophy of life, it becomes quite difficult once one
gets into specialized fields. When anyone enters the philosophy
of mind, for instance, they necessarily find themselves using
the methods of analytic philosophy.

What to Learn from Both Traditions


Each camp has something unique to contribute to philoso-
phy. Analytic philosophy should be able to enter into phenom-
enology, existentialism, literature, and politics with the same
enthusiasm as continental philosophy. It should also realize
that philosophy is not without a history; philosophy is a histor-
ical movement which tackles social and political questions as
well as more technical problems of logic and epistemology. To
assume that analytic philosophy is above the social and histori-
cal currents of its time is to canonize a golden calf and ignore
the wider reality. Similarly, the average person may not care
about answering the Problem of Induction or the Liar Para-
dox, but may wonder what life, existence, and history means to
her. She may be questioning her political situation or her place
within society, and to presume that what she’s asking are not
philosophical questions belittles the scope of philosophy.
Continental philosophy may have some things to learn as
well. It might need to realize that all reasoning must assume
that logic is meaningful and necessary; that language is intri-
cately connected with our ability to convey meaning, and that
epistemology is one of the most crucial areas to investigate:
whenever we are making assertions or expounding propositions
we act as if our ability to know is correct and justified. It seems
obvious that existence and Being are vital to philosophy, yet
analytic philosophers might ask how we know that to be true.
Continental philosophy may be forgetting those basics neces-
sary for intelligible experience. Science, logic, and the analysis
of language are not the only things that matter, but neither are
literature, art, and history.
What is the difference between a philosopher and a philan-
thropist? One is questioning issues pertaining to the life of the
mind, while the other is engaging in social concern and virtu-
ous living. We must never negate one for the other: they both
have a role to fill, and to harmonize them is the greatest of
goals. The balance between love and knowledge, the knowing
and the doing of the good, is the philosopher’s ideal state, and
the promised land to which the modern sage must set her eyes.
There is a great hope standing before contemporary philoso-
phy, somewhere between skepticism and dogmatism, nihilism
and idealism, logic and art. There is a hope for a progress with
humility, which will aid humanity not only epistemically but
also ethically.

July/August 2009 ! Philosophy Now 15

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen