Entdecken Sie eBooks
Kategorien
Entdecken Sie Hörbücher
Kategorien
Entdecken Sie Zeitschriften
Kategorien
Entdecken Sie Dokumente
Kategorien
H E G E L- S T U D I E N 4 4 ( M A R Z O 2 0 1 0 )
1CINZIA FERRINI
F R O M G E O L O G I C A L TO A N I M A L N AT U R E
I N H E G E L’ S I D E A O F L I F E *
in Hegel’s private library (see: Neuser 1987, 480–95): indeed, among others,
Hegel owned works by Ackerman, Autenrieth, Bichat, Blainville, Buquoy,
Cuvier, Damerow, Ideler, Meyer, Pohl, Robinet, Schelver, Schultz, Spix,
Trommsdorff, Werner, Winterl.
22 See: TWA 9, § 344Z: 374; § 349Z: 429. – On the animal organism as the
‘truth’ of organic nature because it fulfills all the logical determinations of the
idea of life, see: Bach 2004,181; cf. also Ilting 1987, 349–51 and Bach 2006a,
442.
3 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
2002, 168). As Annette Sell puts it, at the conclusion of her entry on
‘life’ (Leben) in the Hegel-Lexikon, life is the movement
characterised by division and reintegration into unity, which
expresses the moving relationship of individual and universal [das
bewegte Verhältnis von Einzelnem und Allgemeinen]” (Sell 2006,
305). This syllogistic reintegration into unity is distinctive of both
conceptual and living processes, for it is nothing but the very form
of ‘conceiving’ or the very type of pure conceptual thinking
(Burbidge 22008, 50–51).
In his 1823/24 Berlin Lectures on the Philosophy of Nature Hegel
states that “the concept is the master that keeps singularities
together” (Hegel 2000, 90), since even if the qualitative individual
natural existences have the basic form (Grundform) of mutual
independence, extrinsicality and indifference, their mutual
externality is only a semblance (Schein). This is why Hegel contends
that the syllogistic linkage is in general “a universal [i.e. conceptual]
form of all things [eine allgemeine Form aller Dinge]” (TWA 8, §
24 2Z: 84).33 The idea of the inner, essential, unity of universality
and activity that on Hegel’s views constitutes the ‘true’ life of
empirical natural bodies as well as their different parts or
apparatuses, therefore, is only of spiritual and conceptual nature,
resting on human consciousness and for our thought (Ferrini 2002,
72 and 2009, 106), whereas immediate nature as such does not bring
the necessity of its rational connection (the nous) to consciousness
(TWA 8, § 24 1Z: 82). In the speculative consideration of nature,
Hegel’s task is then to bring to consciousness, that is, to recognise,
the pure and abstract determinations of thought, which were his
object in the Logic, in the conformations of mind-independent
natural beings (TWA 8, § 24 2Z: 84).
33 For instance, chemistry is understood as the last extreme of the syllogism
of shape (Gestalt) which has as its first term only the abstract activity of
magnetism (the mere concept of the totality of form: the moment of
universality), then the middle term of electricity (the moment of
particularity), split into the two ‘moments’ of the particularization of the
Gestalt within itself (positive electricity), and of the opposition to its other
(negative electricity), and finally the concrete reality (the singularity) of the
self-realizing dynamic of the chemical process (TWA 9, § 326Z: 288). Given
the externality of nature in respect to the logic and within itself, note that the
conformity of chemistry to the thought-movement of the concept in turn
requires (TWA 9, § 328Z: 295–8) that we have a squared middle term, or a
tetrad in the whole, because of the particularization of the first abstract
extreme within itself (inner side) and against another (external side).
4 CINZIA FERRINI
Consider first the case of ‘Mechanics,’ a sphere that opens with the
simplest starting point possible: the mere ‘self-externality’
(Außersichsein) of space, which represents the abstract universal
determinateness of nature. Space, however, is only where the self-
external being differentiates itself through the generation of point,
line, surface; that is, through the negation of its immediate, abstract
lack of difference: a movement that contradicts its uninterrupted
continuity. The negativity of the self-differentiation of space that
gives rise to its dimensions is only formal or logical, however,
because point, line and surface are just ‘moments,’ devoid of any
44 Compare Hegel’s definition of the organic in 1805/06: “the organic is the
self, the force (Krafft), the unity of its own self and its negative. Only as this
unity has it force (Krafft) upon that one, and the connection (Beziehung)
makes actual what is in itself (an sich)” (GW 8, 109.21–24).
5 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
principle of motion within itself.55 This sphere ends with the solar
system, as a system of self-moving matter, where matter is “free” –
meaning that it appropriates determinations as its own. As in the
1801 Dissertation on the orbits of the planets, Hegel states that for
us the solar system “is the primary knowable system of real
rationality (reale Vernünftigkeit) within the heavens” (TWA 9, §
268Z: 80). A syllogistic treatment of the solar system as the
manifestation of a thorough-going unity, however, may only occur
with the overcoming of external relations and the transition to the
individuality (quality) of matter in ‘Physics,’ that is, only when
matter is no longer conceived of as essentially composite, consisting
of discrete parts which all tend towards a centre but as inwardly self-
determining, and the sun is no longer regarded just as a body “which
on account of the predominance of its […] mass is the approximate
embodiment of the system’s centre of gravity” (Falkenburg 1993,
539), but according to its radiating nature of a star, which consists of
luminous matter.
‘Physics’ deals with ‘real’ matter, that is, in Hegel’s terms, with
matter that has a certain inner form and comes to manifest that form.
This inner form endows bodies with an individuality (and distinctive
quality or specificity) that bodies lack in so far as they are
understood as purely mechanical bodies (or mere quantities of
matter). At the outset of ‘Physics,’ therefore, matter already has
“individuality” (Individualität), in so far as it is determined and
formed “within itself” (an ihr) and has essentially the immanent
form of being-for-self (TWA 9, § 272: 109). ‘Physics’ begins with
what Hegel calls “matter in its first qualified state”: that is, light as
matter’s general and abstract appearance to and for others (not for
itself: TWA 9, § 275, § 275Z: 109, 113).66 Yet Hegel claims that light
is implicitly ‘self-determining,’ thus announcing a dimension
characteristic of the concept of life.77 In the Philosophy of Nature of
1805/06 (GW 8, 108.5–8) we find a clear assessment of how and
why with the physical dimension of light we reach the universal
form of ‘life:’ the key notion is the thorough co-penetration of all
parts by a unity of presence and actuality. In the case of light,
however, this unity is still that of space, externality and generality
(Falkenburg 1993, 539).
In the sphere of its qualitative particularization (Besonderung),
hetereogeneity and finitude, matter develops as its ‘self-form’
determines it to an increasing degree and comes to be more
explicitly the point of unity of all the material components of a body.
The highest point achieved in this process is the fully individual
matter (V 16, 139.6–7), that is, the individual material totality of the
single, independent body. This is why in ‘Physics’ Hegel offers a
reappraisal of the solar system, which in ‘Mechanics’ is treated
according to its free movement and material self-determination but
not yet as manifestation of the unity of substance. Indeed, “since
light is identified with luminous matter, it is embodied in the sun”
(Falkenburg 1993, 539); therefore, only at the level of ‘Physics’ have
66 Cf. also V 15, 107.22–29 and pp. 232–3; Hegel 2000, 136 and TWA 9, §
275Z: 112 ff.
77 See: TWA 1, 382–83 for the spiritual and religious (Joh. 12,36) significance
of the identity of light and life. In the Logic the colorless light, together with
the pure self-identity of the Ego, is a determinate example of pure indifferent
(abstract) sameness in spatial extension, that is, of pure quantity (TWA 5,
214). It is worthy of note that, speaking of the “division of the original forces
of the soul from abstract self-consciousness,” the physician, anthropologist
and psychiatrist Ideler, who in his work explicitely acknowledges his debt
only to Kant, though departing from him, claims that the form of ‘light’ is the
simplest representation of the purest spiritual activity (Intelligenz, Erkennen)
by which the subject, the Ego, can grasp its being object to itself, for it is
unable to decompose this sameness into parts as with any other concept
(Ideler 1827, 23). Within this context, Ideler makes clear that in no way is
light a form of intuition of the external sense; rather he regards it as “the
purest and immediate expression of spirit […] the free self-representing
spiritual force, which as formative capacity takes up the alien material and
shapes it according to its highest laws, as it were, just as electricity, through
its irradiation, orders in determinate figures the dust on a resin disk” (ibid., p.
24, footnote). Hegel owned Ideler’s book: see: Neuser 1987, entry 104, 487.
8 CINZIA FERRINI
1111 Original text quoted in Engelhardt 1976, 122. – Indeed, the two main
features which Hegel appreciates in Pohl’s researches were the keen
awareness of the living activity of nature and the capacity to grasp the
general progression of the galvanic and chemical process as a totality of
natural activity (see: Petry 1986, 28). For a thorough comparison of the 1817,
‘27 and ‘30 versions of Hegel’s systematic treatment of chemistry see:
Engelhardt 1976, 137–83.
1212 The point returns in the ‘Organic,’ when Hegel contends that categories
adequately employed to the investigation of the case of a simple mechanical
cause-effect arrangement are not adequate to the case of that arrangement
considered as functionally subordinated to the organism-environment
relationship to which it belongs: “An important step forward to the true
representation (Vorstellung) of the organism is the replacement of the
operation of external causes by the determination of stimulation
(Erregtwerden) through external potencies” (TWA 9, § 359: 469).
11 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
1314 Renault 2002, 128–35 has shown how Hegel supports the autonomy of
chemistry against the attempts to integrate it into a physics of molecular
attraction (Berthollet) or into a general theory of the dynamical process
(Schelling) when he conceives chemistry as the synthesis of magnetism and
electricity and as the “moment of totality,” thus rejecting any natural
transition among the stages of the section Physics. Engelhardt has pointed
out how Pohl (who taught mathematics and physics) shared with Hegel this
general interpretation of magnetism, electricity and chemism as different
forms of divided and conjoined activities (Engelhardt 1976,122–23).
1415 See: Burbidge 1996, 186; Houlgate 22005, 164; Burbidge 2007, 115. –
According to Filion 2007, 313, the “defect” of the inorganic nature consists in
the impossibility of assembling and coordinating the chemical process into
one unity.
12 CINZIA FERRINI
1516 See: Kisner 2008–09, 26: “Purposive activity is then seen as being one
and the same thing as the self-negating mechanico-chemical process itself:
in purposive activity the self-negating character of mechanism becomes
explicit as such, and so such activity consists in letting the self-negating
mechanico-chemical process show itself to be that, viz. a self-negating
process whose truth is life, thereby establishing a semblance of its
independence and then canceling that semblance. With the full identity of
purposive activity and the self-negating mechanico-chemical process in the
living organism, we get a full identity of form and content”.
1617 See: Cuvier 1800, 7: “La vie ne naît que de la vie.”
13 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
2021 Hegel quotes from Schultz 1823 in TWA 9, § 343Z: 373. Hegel owned a
series works by Schultz published during 1822–31 (Neuser 1987, entries
204–09, 493–94).
2122 See Petry’s notes to 12.33 and 23.8 in Hegel 1970b III, 215–16 and 229–
32. See also Fritscher 2009, 245–9 for the modern state of art of mineralogy
and crystallography at Kant’s time (Wallerius, Cronstedt, Zedlers, Gehler). In
particular, Fritscher recalls the so-called Gesetz der Winkelkonstanz,
according to which the geometrical distinctive figures of the crystals do not
(externally) depend upon the number and magnitude of the single surfaces
but upon the angles which together form (internally) these surfaces (247).
2223 Interestingly enough, Robinet, in the name of the “law of uniformity”
between inorganic and organic nature, had spoken in 1761 of a suc, a
solution of minerals and salts in ground water as the universal fluid that
caused transportation, deposit, alluvional beds, evaporation etc. (Robinet
1761, Ch. XIV: 286–90), as well as of the “generation” of stones from stones
and from metals to metals (in this regard in perfect analogy with plant and
animal reproduction) in terms of “development of intussusception,” thus
claiming the existence of the germes fossiles (Robinet 1761, Ch. XIV: 290–
91). Hegel owned Robinet’s work (Neuser 1987, entry 183, 492).
16 CINZIA FERRINI
the Idea results from the dialectical movement in which the concept
determines itself both to objectivity and to the antithesis, and then
takes back the totality of the particularizations and returns into itself
negatively as real subjectivity (§§ 213, 215). Indeed, Hegel warns
the reader not to take the systematic division of his philosophical
science to constitute a temporal sequence (TWA 8, § 18: 64), i.e. as if
the second part of the Encyclopaedia were simply ‘juxtaposed’ to
the first. Rather, the ‘Idea as nature’ is posited together conceptually
with its opposite, the ‘Idea as finite spirit,’ and expounded as the
first, ‘lower’ part of the twofold real section that in its entirety is the
outcome of the first, merely ideal (closed within thought) section of
the science of the Idea in and for itself. This is the case because:
the Idea proves itself to be as thought simply identical with itself
and this proves to be the activity of positing itself over against
itself to be for-itself – [the Idea in its being-other, Nature] – and
in this other to be only at home with itself [as philosophy of
spirit].” (TWA 8, § 18: 63)
As “Idea in the immediacy of being,” life is essentially purposive
self-mediating, self-grounding activity as subject and process that
establishes its own presupposition in order to be what it is. This kind
of reference can help us to explain the change of terminology from
the “mineralogical organism” of the Jena period to the “geological
nature” of the later philosophy of nature. In the 1804-05 Logic,
living organisms were conceived within the frame of the
“metaphysics of objectivity” and in terms of a movement from
absolute cognition to self-cognition; consistently, in the 1805/06
philosophy of nature, plastic organic nature immediately generates
“organic” mineral formations in the element of being as dead forms,
in contrast to the representational form of consciousness, which
mediates between concept and thing (GW 8, 119.5–8). In the
Encyclopaedia, the first immediate determination of Life is the
determination of its own relative and specific otherness: otherness
ceases to have the significance of an alien conditioning externality,
for externality is brought about as the means through which life
immediate, and thus nature (and in a determinate way is life), though this
immediacy is the Urteil (that is, both judgment and inner original self-
division) of the Idea: it is the Idea in its own externality, with life as the
highest degree of this being-out-of-itself.
18 CINZIA FERRINI
determines and sustains itself: it falls under the power of life as the
inorganic, geological nature that is necessary to its process.
One may well ask at this point: what empirical research does Hegel
want to ground here by regarding it as conforming to this atemporal
conceptual necessity? In the Additions to § 339 and § 340 Hegel
praises Werner’s scheme of “precipitation,” that is, his physical and
chemical theory of the deposition of strata, according to which the
origin and sequence of such strata are determined by the law of the
internal differentiation of the essential determinations of rocks
(Levere 1986,104); and he dismisses as “external” any manner of
explanation in geology that aims at determining only the temporal
succession of the order of stratification (with the granitic primitive
rocks as the deepest strata, and the “fletz-formations” having been
deposited at a later, more recent time). The order of stratification is
certainly capable of a purely temporal, mechanical explanation,
starting as it does with the conception of a series of parts existing
outside of and independent of one another. If this were the whole
truth of the matter, however, the external system of the earth in the
first part of ‘Organics’ would not be a ‘terrestrial organism,’ but a
mere aggregate of parts with no teleology at work.2625 On Hegel’s
view, this approach fails to recognise that the deep meaning and
rationality of the sequence (its Sinn und Geist) is Werner’s internal
‘organic,’ conceptual bond or necessary relation between these
inorganic formations (TWA 9, § 339Z: 348). This internal connection
“must depend upon the characteristic” (Beschaffenheit), the essential
qualitative content of these formations themselves, which governs
their occurrence in time, which as mere chronological (historical)
sequence of production would be of no philosophical significance
and interest (Kolb 2008, 101). Hegel’s judgment is thus in accord
with Cuvier’s assessment in his 1812 Preliminary Discourse (Cuvier
1997, 204):
The purely mineral part of the great problem of the theory of the
earth has been studied with admirable care by de Saussure, and
2627 The editor’s note warns the reader that the word “metamorphoses”
here is employed in the sense of the modern term “metamorphism.”
2728 On Voigt’s contribution to zoology, under the influence of Blumenbach
and Cuvier and in contrast to Oken, see: Robin 2006, who cites the following
sentence from Voigt’s 1816 Von dem Werth der Naturgeschichte: “To draw
knowledge from nature there is a threefold route. Either one regards the
matter, or the form, or the spirit (Geist) and the life in nature” [Robin 2006,
181 misquotes ‘Seift’ instead of ‘Geist.’ I thank Thomas Bach for checking
the correct version in the original text].
20 CINZIA FERRINI
2930 In TWA 9, § 341, p. 360 Hegel speaks of der totliegende Organismus der
Erde.
3031 Heim, who at the outset aims to consider the entire bed (Lager) of the
Thuringian Mountains as a proper totality (ein eignes Ganzes) (Heim 1803,
Sect. III, § 1: 6), writes: “in general an entire proper manner of transition and
change of form governs [herrscht] the entire mountain chain – namely a
universal tendency to a dense granular shape [dichtkörnigte Gestalt]” (Heim
1803, Sect. III, § 10: 120).
22 CINZIA FERRINI
3132 See: TWA 9, § 340, p. 354. See Petry’s note to 27,33 in Hegel 1970b III,
235–36. The end of the Addition § 340 (see: TWA 9, 359–60) presents the
same text of GW 8, 118–19.
3233 The discovery was first published in Aloysii Galvani, De Viribus
Electricitatis in Motu Musculari Commentarius. Bononiae, 1791.
23 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
3839 Retracing the same orientation in an 1801 text (Hegel’s first Jenaer
Systementwurf), two years before Schelver’s arrival in Jena, Bach
underscores that there is no reason to speak of any immediate dependence
of Hegel’s position on Schelver’s theories and sees the origin of the former in
an independent philosophical appraisal of Linné (Bach 2006b, 75–76).
Illetterati 1995a, note 166, 393 remarks the accord with Aristotle’s view on
the sexuality of the plants in De gen. an. I, 731a 1 and 731a 25–29.
3940 In the early years of the XIX century, Schelver had addressed an early
criticism to Linné’s clavis systematis sexualis, but did not publish it until
1812, on Goethe’s advice (Bach 2004: 187). Both Schelver and Hegel,
however, may have drawn from a common earlier source: W. Smellie’s
account of the sexuality of plants (translated into German by E. A. W.
Zimmermann in 1791), which reports the experimentally controlled
objections of Dr. Hope of the botanical garden of Edinburgh to Linné’s
criterion of classification (Ferrini 2009, note 35, 120). Hegel owned many
works by Schelver published during 1803–1823 (Neuser 1987, entries 189–
97, 492–93).
26 CINZIA FERRINI
4041 Buquoy 1822, § 36: 123 stresses that the “vegetative sphere” does not
reach the “purpose of activity.” By contrast, the vital activity of the living
beings urges to dominate (strebt […] zu beherrschen, beherrschen is
emphasized in the original text) chaos and lack of form according to its own
formative impulse. Hegel owned a series of works by Buquoy published
during 1817–25 (Neuser 1987, entries 38–41, 482–83), among which Buquoy
1817 and 1822.
4142 Goethe advances his notion of Typus based on comparative anatomy in
the 1795 Erster Entwurf einer allgemeinen Einleitung in die vergleichende
Anatomie, ausgehend von der Osteologie, where he takes partial distance
from Kant, polemizing against final causes in the light of Spinoza (Giacomoni
1998, 200–10). See: Moiso 1998b, 317–25 on his discovery of os
intermaxillare based on the principle of the continuity and metamorphosis of
the living forms one into the other. Moiso underscores the accord between
Goethe’s principle of ‘useful harmony’ among functionally interrelated organs
and Cuvier’s principle of the correlations of organic forms (321–22).
27 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
4243 Gattung: see: V 15, 281–82 (editorial note to 143.17–22); cf. Breidbach
2004, 212–14, 219–20.
28 CINZIA FERRINI
might arise who would explain organic life through natural laws
unordered by any intention (AA V, § 75: 400, my italics). 4443
Famously, in 1755 Kant had regarded just as “highly problematic”
the full explanation of a simple organism by conceiving its parts as
effects of (blind) mechanical causes, projecting it into an
indeterminate future (AA I, 230.14–20). After 1763, Kant felt
increasingly uneasy about the basic inadequacy of mechanical causal
explanations of the generation and the inner structure of plants,
animals and also crystals (AA II, 114.5–6; Ferrini 2000). The
“absurdity” Kant notes in 1790 marks a radicalization of his pre-
critical view, also due to his reappraisal there of Blumenbach’s
formative power (Bildungstrieb).4544 Kant argues that we must
judge something to be an organized product of nature only when:
“everything [within it] is end and reciprocally means as well.
Nothing in it is gratuitous, purposeless or to be ascribed to a blind
mechanism of nature” (AA V, § 66: 376). Kant admits that parts of
an animal body could be understood according to purely mechanical
laws, yet the cause which provides the appropriate matter, modifies,
forms and deposits it in the proper place, “must always be judged
teleologically” (AA V, § 66: 377). In an organized and self-
organizing being, which is also able to repair itself when disordered,
the connection of efficient causes could at the same time be judged
as an effect through final causes, as being in itself a natural end. This
is because the organism has a self-reproducing, formative power
(sich fortpflanzende, bildende Kraft) and so, unlike a machine, does
not just have a motive force within itself (AA V, § 65: 374).4645
4344 For an extensive study of Kant’s critical interpretation of Blumenbach’s
notion and the influence it had, in turn, on Blumenbach himself, cf. Fabbri
Bertoletti 1990, 10–47.
4445 Look has pointed out how Kant rejects important features of the
formative drive (Bildungstrieb), such as its vitalistic aspect of being a form of
energy that acts as an efficient cause of reproduction, its being constitutive
of matter, its not being anything like a Kantian ‘supersensible ground’ for
both mechanical and teleological modes of explanation. Look concludes that
“Yet from Kant’s perspective, Blumenbach could not be the ‘Newton for a
balde of grass’ – for there still can be no such a figure” (Look 2006, 371–72;
see also: Chiereghin 1990, 204–05).
4546 The English translators of the third Critique render Kant’s adjective
fortpflanzend with propagating (Kant 2000, 246). This rendering may sound
misleading against the background of the scientific use of the term at
Hegel’s time. Note that e.g. Schultz translated propagatio sive evolutio by
Vermehrung, while Fortpflanzung rendered generatio (Schultz 1828, § 3.3).
29 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
4647 Chiereghin also points out the aporetic implications of the Kantian
paradigmatic notion of techne in the First Introduction to the Critique of
Judgment: its failure to account for the formative power, its reconstruction,
from the outside, of the connection among analytically isolated elements of
the organism – so that the activity governing the organic process falls again
under the heading of external purposiveness (cf. Chiereghin 1990, 136–38,
142–45, 152–53, 201–07; 225–26).
4748 A classification of the three mineral, plant and animal kingdoms based
on the criterion of the Fortpflanzungsvermögen (reproductiveness) is to be
found in Willdenow 1792, § 3: 2: minerals have no reproductive parts
(Willdenow calls Zeugungstheile what 36 year later were called
Generationsorgane: Schultz 1828, § 2: 2), they can generate only mixtures
and not their own kind; vegetables are endowed with a great lot of them, but
they lose these parts before death; by contrast, animals keep their
Zeugungstheile until they die. Michelet’s edition of the 1830 Encyclopaedia
reports extensive quotations from the 6th edition (1821) of Willdenow 1792 in
the Additions to §§ 344–348; see: Petry 1986, p. 20.
30 CINZIA FERRINI
4849 Cuvier makes these claims in the First article (‘General sketch of the
functions exerted by the animal bodies’) of the First Lecture (‘Preliminary
considerations on animal economy’), of Volume I of his Leçons d’anatomie
(Paris, 1800–1805).
4950 In the 1807 Phenomenology, Hegel carries out the transition from
‘Perception’ to ‘Force and Understanding’ when consciousness moves to an
unconditioned, supersensible, self-identical universality as the inner,
productive ground of the manifold properties of the object. That is,
consciousness moves to ‘force’ as ‘form that is purposive activity,’ which
makes itself into what the thing is in itself, developing its parts and
properties, bringing the inner nature of perceived things to actuality (on the
implicit anti-Kantianism of this move see: Ferrini 2005, 340–45).
31 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
5051 The text continues: “Just as taking each property separately as the basis
for a particular equation, one would find both the ordinary equation and all
the other properties of any kind, so likewise the claw, the shoulder blade, the
condyle, the femur, and all the other bones taken separately, determine
[donnent] the teeth, and each other reciprocally.” In his 1792/93 Der Versuch
als Vermittler von Obiect und Subiect Goethe had taken the mathematical
method of the algebraic formulas à la D’Alembert as the method which could
follow the continuity of nature, avoiding the extremes of the arbitrary unity
and the analytical fragmentation, see: Moiso 1998b, 298–311.
5152 Spix also sets the limits of the new anatomy: it takes into account only
the most visible organs (this criticism will be also levelled at Cuvier by
Blainville 1847 III, 398) and does not think of the properties of the soul
(Seeleneigenschaften) of the animals (in the same vein as Linné), that is of
the integration of the functions by the nervous system which coordinates the
active relations of the animal body to externality. Hence, one should progress
towards a new conception of zoology, constituted by physiology and
32 CINZIA FERRINI
chaos, where vegetable and animal life, organic and inorganic had
been in one unity,”5655 and reacts vehementely against the
presupposition of the temporal existence of something like a “living-
in-general” that then divides itself into plants, animal and human
races; he criticizes this view in terms of “a representation of the
empty force of imagination” (TWA 9, 349).5756
In the logic of ‘life’ in § 165 of the 1817 Encyclopaedia Hegel
recasts Kant’s view in an Aristotelian, speculative frame, pointing
(in a manner characteristic of post-Kantian thought) to the
constitutive, not merely subjectively reflective, dimension of the
transience, negativity or ideality of the parts as ‘moments’ of the
process of life.5857
In the 1830 Remark to § 360 Hegel reaffirms his appreciation of
Kant’s revival of the Aristotelian idea of the inner purposiveness of
the living being, though he still hints at the insufficiency of its
merely heuristic status in the Critique of Judgment,5958 and develops
5556 See Petry’s note to 23,8, Hegel 1970b III, 229: Petry sees here a
reference to Caspar Wolff’s Theoria generationis, not to Herder’s Ideen.
5657 Rühlig 1998, 360 remarks that Hegel distances himself from
metaphysical philosophy of nature which holds that all matter is alive in the
vein of Jacobi’s pronouncement “Everything in nature lives. Nothing is
completely dead”. In the Jena period Hegel had already supported the view
that “the concept […] is not the discourse on a general life of nature in the
sense that [dass] nature is living everywhere; rather it speaks of the essence
of life. Nature is to be grasped [begreiffen] and explained in the moments of
its actuality or totality, and these moments have to be shown” (GW 8,
119.10–13). In my forthcoming paper in S. Houlgate & M. Baur, The Blackwell
Companion to Hegel, I have argued that the transition from inorganic to
organic nature hinges on conceptual inner necessity, not directly on what
nature does, and that Hegel holds neither the vitalistic view that life
‘emerges’ from an essentially lifeless matter by means of the sudden
appearance of a natural productive power of generation (Lebenskraft), nor
the hylozoic view that in temporal existence nature is everywhere really
alive.
5758 Bach 2004, 180 draws attention to the comparison between §§ 165–168
of the 1817 Encyclopaedia and §§ 64–66 of Kant’s third Critique from the
standpoint of the genus process, analysing Kant’s example of the tree.
5859 As Zammito puts it, “Kant remained adamant that the ultimate origin of
“organization” required a metaphysical, not a physical account” (Zammito
2006, 349; cf. AA VIII, 179). On how Hegel develops against this critical
background his own concept of life as “speculative ontology” see:
Stanguennec, 1990. In the Science of Logic Hegel counterbalances the
insufficiency of Kant’s appraisal with the “position” he gives to teleology: a
connecting middle (being ascribed to a judgment) between the universal of
34 CINZIA FERRINI
6869 Chiereghin has pointed out the aporetic implications of the Kantian
paradigmatic notion of techne in the First Introduction to the Critique of
Judgment: its failure to account for the formative power, its reconstruction,
from the outside, of the connection among analytically isolated elements of
the organism, so that the activity governing the organic process falls again
under the heading of external purposiveness (cf. Chiereghin 1990, 136–38,
142–45, 152–53, 201–07; 225–26).
6970 See Cuvier’s assessment of the principles of identification in his 1812
Preliminary Discourse: “if the intestines of an animal are organized in such a
way as to digest only flesh – and fresh flesh – it is also necessary that the
jaws be constructed for devouring prey; the claws, for seizing and tearing it;
the teeth, for cutting and dividing its flesh; the entire organs, for detecting it
from afar; and it is even necessary that nature should have placed in its
brain the instinct necessary for knowing how to hide itself and set traps for
its victims. Such are the general conditions of the carnivorous regime; every
animal adapted for this regime unfailingly combines them, for its species
could not have subsisted without them” (Cuvier 1997, 217).
40 CINZIA FERRINI
7071 See ibid., 217–18: “But within these general conditions there exist
particular conditions, relative to the size, species, and habitat [séjour] of the
prey to which the animal is adapted, and each of these particular conditions
results in some detailed circumstances in the forms that result from the
general conditions. Thus it is not only the class that finds expression in the
form of each part, but the order, the genus, and even the species.”
7172 See Buquoy’s comment on the “unmistakable Typus” (Buquoy 1817,
289–90): “The phenomenon of life [Lebenserscheinung] not only escapes
comprehension [unbegreiflich], is inexplicable according to its ultimate
principles and motive causes, but it is also indescribable, escaping any
definition. It can only be grasped [aufgefaßt] as Idea.”
7273 On Schelling’s relation between organism and external environment as
drawn from the basic relation of opposition-complementarity between
outwardness and inwardness, receptivity and activity, see: Moiso 1998a, 76–
79.
41 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
7374 The term is used at each stage of the Philosophy of Nature: with regard
to magnetism (§ 314), vegetable nature (§§ 345–46), animal process of
assimilation (§ 354, §§ 364–65), animal disease (§ 371) and in the § 402
Philosophy of Spirit with the significance of ‘magic dominion’ over the world.
42 CINZIA FERRINI
its own means from without: “life is where inner and outer, cause
and effect, end and means, subjectivity and objectivity etc. are one
and the same” (TWA 9, § 337Z: 339). With this position Hegel
distances himself from attempts to extend the distinctive characters
of organic life (to be a unitary, indivisible co-ordinated whole which
is constantly maintaining and reproducing itself in an external
world), indifferentiately to the whole of nature, inorganic and
organic (à la Treviranus), as well as from the attempt to see an
analogy and continuity between the activity of the magnetic and
chemical process of inorganic nature and the process of life (à la
Oken).
536).
7576 See: Poggi 2000, 471–84 on Kieser’s works; 512–6 on the kind of research
behind the review Archiv für den thierischen Magnetismus (Kieser,
Eschenmayer and Nees von Esenbeck); 485–88, 490–93, 495–96 on the use of
relations of polarity to understand the internal and external structures of the
plants in botanics (C. G. Nees von Esenbeck). On the problem of the
experimental procedures of the Romantic science see: Schulz 1993.
7677 See Petry’s note at p. 140,20 in Hegel 1970b, III 328–29.
45 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
8081 See: TWA 9, § 355Z: 455–59; cf. Hegel 1970b III, 126–27. D’Hondt has
shown that Hegel quotes from the first edition of Bichat’s Recherches and
does not use the 1822 edition with the notes of his pupil Magendie, who
challenged exactly Bichat’s distinction between organic and animal nature. It
was Michelet who referred to the later edition; see: D’Hondt 1986, 143. On
the methodological problem represented by Michelet’s 1842 editing of the
Addition to Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, “who simply conflated all the
material he had available, some of which dated as early as 1805, and some
from as late as 1830,” see: Petry 1986, 18.
8182 Bichat 1955, 84; see: Illetterati 1995b, 201–02.
8283 “Incompréhensible” is not in italics in the original text.
47 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
8586 Schultz, who earned his Habilitation in Berlin in 1822, may have
attended Hegel’s 1819/20 course (his first in Berlin) on Naturphilosophie.
49 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
8687 Engelhardt 2005, 110 recalls that a general feature of the time (he
refers to a period that runs from M. A. Weickard’s Der Philosophische Arzt
(1773–75, 21798) to W. Griesinger’s 1845 Pathologie und Therapie der
psychischen Krankenheiten is that the evaluation of mental disease always
implied also a philosophical judgment.
8788 In Ferrini 2009, 110–11. I made the point that Hegel clearly endorsed
key features of Trommsdorf’s (a chemist) criticism of the Schellingian
approach (charged with mixing idealism and materialism and substituting
50 CINZIA FERRINI
§ 3 Conclusions
REFERENCES
8990 In Ferrini 2009 I have provided further references to scientists who had
begun to conceptualize experience around 1800. I wish to thank Peter
Mclaughlin to have pointed to my attention von Engelhardt’s research on
Hegel and Müller.
53 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
ABBREVIATIONS
AA
Immanuel Kant: Gesammelte Schriften. Herausgegeben von der
Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Berlin 1900 ff.
AA I: Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels
(1755). – In: Vorkritische Schriften I (1747–1756), 215–368.
AA II: Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration
des Daseins Gottes. – In: Vorkritische Schriften II (1757–1777),
63–164.
AA IV: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaften
(1786), 465–566.
AA V: Kritik der Urtheilskraft (1790), 165–486.
AA VIII: Kleine Schriften (1784–1800).
AA XX: Erste Einleitung in die Kritik der Urtheilskraft (1790),
195–281.
De part. anim.
Aristotle: Parts of Animals. Engl. tr. by A. L. Peck. London /
Cambridge, Ms. 1955.
GW
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Gesammelte Werke. In Verbindung
mit der Deutschen Forschungsgemeinschaft herausgegeben von der
Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Hamburg
1968 ff.
GW 8: Jenaer Systementwürfe III (1805/06). Herausgegeben von
Rolf-Peter Horstmann, 1976.
GW 9: Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807). Herausgegeben von
Wolfgang Bonsiepen und Reinhard Heede, 1980.
HSW
Johann Gottfried Herder: Sämtliche Werke. B. Suphan (Hg.).
Hildesheim 1967 (repr. 1881).
HSW XIII: Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit.
Part I, 1784; Part II, 1785.
54 CINZIA FERRINI
SSW
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling: Sämmtliche Werke. Karl
Friedrich August Schelling (Hg.). Stuttgart 1856–1861.
SSW 1: 1792–1797, 1856.
V
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Vorlesungen. Ausgewählte
Nachschriften und Manuskripte. Hamburg 1983 ff.
V 8: Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie. Teil 3.
Griechische Philosophie. II. Plato bis Proklos. Herausgegeben
von Pierre Garniron und Walter Jaeschke. Hamburg 1996.
V 10: Vorlesungen über die Logik. Berlin 1831. Nachgeschrieben
von Karl Hegel. Herausgegeben von Udo Rameil unter Mitarbeit
von Hans-Christian Lucas (†). Hamburg 2001.
V 15: Philosophische Enzyklopädie. Nürnberg 1812/13.
Nachschriften von Christian Samuel Meinel und Julius Friedrich
Heinrich Abegg. Herausgegeben von Udo Rameil. Hamburg
2002.
V 16: Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Natur. Berlin
1819/20. Nachgeschrieben von Johann Rudolf Ringier.
Herausgegeben von Martin Bondeli und Hoo Nam Seelmann.
Hamburg 2002.
V 17: Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Natur. Berlin
1825/26. Nachgeschrieben von Heinrich Wilhelm Dove.
Herausgegeben von Karol Bal, Gilles Marmasse, Thomas
Siegfried Posch und Klaus Vieweg. Hamburg 2007.
TWA
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Werke in zwanzig Bänden. Werke in
zwanzig Bänden. Auf der Grundlage der Werke von 1832–1845 neu
edierte Ausgabe. Redaktion Eva Moldenhauer und Karl Markus
Michel. Frankfurt a. M. 1970.
TWA 1: Frühe Schriften
TWA 5: Wissenschaft der Logik I.
TWA 6: Wissenschaft der Logik II.
55 From Geological to Animal Nature in Hegel’s Idea of Life
WORKS CITED
Frigo, G. F. (2002). Die Welt der lebenden Natur bei Hegel. – In: O.
Breidbach / D. v. Engelhardt (Hgg.): Hegel und die
Lebenswissenschaften (pp. 107–20). Berlin.
Moiso, F. (1986). Die Hegelsche Theorie der Physik und der Chemie
in ihrer Beziehung zu Schellings Naturphilosophie. – In: R.-P.
Horstmann / M. J. Petry (Eds.): Hegels Philosophie der Natur (pp.
54–87). Stuttgart.