Sie sind auf Seite 1von 41

Greek Ethics

PAMELA M. RUBY, M.A.


Lecturer in Philosophy, University of Liverpool

MACMILLAN

ST MARTIN'S PRESS

-
~ \~ t~ L,) r£
~. q/f?!2
r
© Pamela M. Huby 1967 CONTENTS
First Edit/on 1967 Editor's Preface page vi
Reprinted 1969
I. INTRODUCTION 1
Published try
MACMILLAN AND CO LTD II. THE BEGINNINGS 3
Little Essex Street Londolt w C 2
and also at Bombay Calcutta and Madras (i) Background 3
Macmillan South Africa (Publishers) Pry LJd Johannesburg (ii) The Sophists 7
The Mamtillan CompallY of Australia Pry Ltd MelbourI1c
The Macmillan Company of Canada Ltd Toronto (iii) Democritus 13
Sf Martin's Press Inc New York
Gill and Macmillan Ltd Dublin III. SOCRATES 15
Printed ilt Great Bdtalit by IV. PLATO 26
RICHARD CLAY (THE CHAUCER PRESS) LTD.
Bunga)'. Suffolk Note on Platds treatment of Love and Friendship 39

Library of Congress catalog card no. 67-II4oI V. ARISTOTLE 41


Note on Aristotle's treatment of Friendship 62

VI. AFTER ARISTOTLE 64


(i) Background 64
(ii) Epicureanism 65
(iii) Stoicism 67
Notes 70
BibliograplrJ 74
EDI'TOR'S PREFACE
1. INTRODUCTION

N~w Studies in Ethics is a series of monographs by modern


phl!osophers, drawn from universities in Great Britain the
Umted States a~d Australia. Each author has been ask~d to Greek philosophy traditionally begins with Thales of Miletus in
expound and ctlncall y examine the thought of a phil h the sixth century B.C., but the first philosophers are not known to
or h 1 f hil osop er, have been interested in ethics. Ethical problems first became
sc 00 0 p osophers, representative of one type of ethical
theory. The series as a whole Covers the main types of theory prominent among the sophists, a class of professional teachers of
from Greekantiqnity to the present day and meets the need for a 'wisdom', who flourished in the fifth century. We possess only
comprehensive surv.ey of ethics from the point of view of fragments of their writings, but there is enough to show that
contemporary analyncal philosophy. Protagoras of Abdera (c. 485-415), Hippias of Elis (somewhat
The Greeks wer~ the Brst to conduct what is recognizable younger than Protagoras), and Antiphon of Athens (active about
today as a systematic philosophical discussion of the nature of 420) discussed ethical problems, and where so little remains we
morality..Mrs Huby has produced a comprehensive account of are grateful for two anonymous texts, the Ano1tJmus Iamblichi, i.e.
;h~ tn~an!ngs which they gave to such expressions as 'good', a writer whose works were later used by Iamblichus (c. 4'0 ?), and
virtue ~ voluntary action', 'justice', etc.; and where there the Dissoi Logoi (some time after 400), a roughly written summary
were differences among them concerning the correct definition of sophistic teachings, and for a fragment of the dramatist and
of the.se terms, she has brought these to light. Greek thinkers politician Critias of Athens (c. ,460-403). Gorgias of Leontini
s~met1~es gave the same answers as our contemporaries, sorne- (c. 483-375) did not claim to teach ethics, but his speeches Helena
nmes differ~nt ones, both to the practical question: how are and Palamedes contain some views on moral psychology. We may
men t~ attam the good life? and to the philosophical question: fairly assume, too, that some of the arguments put into the mouths
what 1S ,the ~est method .of arriving at an understanding of of individual sophists by Plato are fair accounts of their views.
morality. This study Illuminates the differences and similarities Democritus of Abdera (460-378) produced a sensible rule of
on both counts in a discussion which is at once scholarly and life in his ethical works, but only fragments are left.
readable. Socrates of Athens (469-399)' after a lifetime of active moral
W. D. HUDSON
teaching, was put to death on being convicted of impiety and
corrupting the young. He wrote nothing himself, but is portrayed
in a long series of works by Plato, of which the earlier ones
probably give a faithful picture of his methods, and in the
Memorabilia and other works of Xenophon.
Plato, also of Athens (427-347), was a disciple of Socrates and
wrote a large number of dialogues, in most of which Socrates is
the chief speaker; among them the Alcibiades I - perhaps not
written by Plato, but a good introduction to his doctrines-
Hippias Major and Minor, Charmides, Laches, Lysis, Eutfoidemus,

I
Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Gorgias, Meno, Phaedo, Symposium,
Protagoras, Republic, Philebus, and Laws all contain somethinO' of
importance for ethics. b THE BEGINNINGS
Aristotle of Stagira (;84-;22) came to Athens in ;67 and studied
under and worked with Plato for twenty years. His writings cover
a wide field. The Nicomachean Ethics is his greatest ethical treatise,
BACKGROUND
and the Eud,mialt Ethics is probably also his, but the Magna
MoraNa attributed to him is in fact of later date. His Politics is also Greeks are the only philosophical moralists commonly
relevant. stu!di"d by the Western world who were not influenced by
The Cyrenaics were followers of Aristippus (c. 4;5-;60), but Glristianity, for the compelling reason that all their major ethical
only fragments of their teachings remain. systems were developed long before the birth of Christ. We have
Epicurus of Mytilene (341-27°) came to Athens in 306 and to remember that their basic moral and religious outlook was
set up a school. His influence later spread throughout the Roman different from ours, and that what they valued and admired was
Empire. We have a Letter to Mello,cus on ethical theory and two sometimes very different from what we value and admire. At the
sets of doctrines, the Kyriae Doxae and Sententiae Vaticaltae written same time these differences must not he over-emphasised; the
by him. ' Greeks, like us, were human beings, and shared the common lot of
The Cynics were followers ofDiogenes of Sinope (c. 400-3 2 5). humanity, which must provide the raw material for all ethical
Only fragments of their work remain. systems. Further, in some ways their views have greatly affected
The Stoics were followers of Zeno of Citium (333-264), who Christian thinking; their tradition is not so much an alien as an
came to Athens in about 310 and studied with the Cynics, but ancestral one, which shows differences from our own only because
started a less radical school of his own in about 300. This flour- the latter contains other elements as well. We can usually enjoy a
ished and developed until Roman times. Chrysippus of Tarsus Greek tragedy in a straightforward way, and understand the
(280-204) reorganised the movement and systematised its teach- passions and the moral issues involved; the attitudes of an Orestes,
ings, and Panaetius of Rhodes (I80-IIO) organised Stoicism in an Antigone, or an Oedipus, are comprehensible to us even when
Rome. Posidonius of Apamea (c. I ;0-46) introduced some we do not share them, and equally we are seldom really puzzled
Platonic elements. Unfortunately we have only fragments of these by the outlook of the historians or the orators.
earlier writers, though we have complete works by the later But differences do exist, and there are times when we are
Stoics - Seneca (4 B.C.-A.D. 65), Epictetus (A.D. 50-130), and genninely at a loss to understand what we read. An outstanding
Marcus Aurelius (A.D. 121-180) - and can learn much from example of this is in Aristotle's Ethics, where he describes a virtue
Cicero (106-4; B.C.), in particular from his De Finibus. foreign to us, hut which he regarded as one of the highest. Here is
what he says:
'It would be equally out of character for the great-souled man
to run away with his arms swinging and to commit an act of
injustice. For what reason would he have to do anything un-
seemly, when nothing seems to him of great importance? ... He
is chiefly concerned with matters of honour; he is pleased, but
only to a moderate extent, when he is honoured for good reasons

2 ;
and by good men, because he thinks he is getting his due, or at In cases like tllese the difficulties of understanding are obvious,
least something approaching it ... but he will wholly despise but there are other and more subtle problems as well. Many of
honour from the common herd and for trivial reasons. For they these lie in translation, for there are several Greek terms that can-
are not on the same plane as he is .... He is the kind of man to do not be translated adequately by anyone English expression, and
good to others, but to be ashamed at receiving benefits, for the which introduce concepts at least slightly different from any of
latter is the mark of an inferior, the former of a superior man. ours. In the course of this study such terms will be discussed as
And when he repays a benefit he will give more than he has the occasion arises.
received, so that his original benefactor will now be in his debt To fill in the background we also need some knowledge of the
and be in the position of a beneficiary. They appear to have better political systems of the Greeks and of their religious outlook.
memories for favours they have given than for those they have Politically, they lived in many small independent communities. 3
received, for the recipient is in an inferior position to the donor, Each community formed a polis, a term which we usually translate
and they wish to be superior, and they enjoy being reminded of as 'city-state'. Each of these city-states consisted of a city, with
the one, but not of the other... .' I some kind of fortification, and a small piece of surrounding
These passages from Aristotle's description of the man he says territory which might contain a number of lesser towns. Thus
he regards as being perfect in virtue are enough to show the Athens consisted of the walled town of Athens and the land of
difficulty. Can Aristotle really have admired a man like that, or was Attica, covering about a thousand square miles and including
he just joking? Scholars are divided about this, and not sur- places like Eleusis and Marathon. This small independent state
prisingly. was flanked by others equally independent, and wars between
Another example is Socrates' statement, in Plato's Crito, of them were frequent. So while all Greeks spoke a common lan-
the reasons why, when he had been condemned to death, he re- guage and shared a common culture, and regarded tllemselves,
fused to flee from Athens but remained to face execution.' It was being Greeks, as superior to all other races, a man's primary
agreed by Socrates and his friends that his condemnation had been allegiance was to his own small city-state, which was tlle centre of
unjust, and it was known that his opponents had no wish for him his economic, religious, social, and cultural life. The inhabitants of
to be put to death, but would have been satisfied to see him go such states fell into three classes: the slaves, who were usually
into exile. Socrates, however, was determined to stay, arguing that not Greek; the resident foreigners, who were free but took no
it was a law of Athens that the decision of the judges must be part in political life ; and the free citizens. Of these free citizens,
final, and that it was wrong to harm Athens by transgressing her only the men had any political function, but in many states, during
laws in any way. For a man's country was more deserving of long periods of their history, all male citizens could play an active
honour than his parents or ancestors, and one ought to bow to the part in governing their community by speaking and voting in the
wishes of a wrathful country even more than to those of a wrath- sovereign assembly, serving as jurymen in the courts, and from
ful father, and to do whatever it commanded, even to the point of time to time holding office. They also paid taxes and served in the
facing death. army as reqnired. Even in less democratic constitutions a large
Here again we are all at sea. Was Socrates merely employing fraction of the free male population had an active part to play,
arguments which he thought would appeal to the respectable and there was frequently a lively opposition. Hence nearly all
Crito? Or is Plato trying to clear his name in the eyes of the Greeks were politically conscious from childhood onwards, and
Athenian public by means of arguments which Socrates never in the distinction between a man's public and private life was much
fact used? Or did he in fact accept them? less clear-cut for them than it is for us. And this explains why the

4 j
distinction between political theory and moral tbeory was also
blurred for the Greeks, and why it so often seems to be taken for (il) THE SOPHISTS
granted that the highest virtue for a grown man is tbe ability to The Greeks first became self-conscious about moral problems
govern. At the same time some distinction was made, as we can when tbey came into contact witb peoples whose views differed
see from the fact that Aristotle wrote separate works on ethics from tbeir own. They themselves colonised almost the whole of
and politics. the Mediterranean basin and parts of the Black Sea coast, and tbus
In religion the Greeks had a superabundance of deities of had dealings with peoples of all levels of civilisation and of widely
various kinds.4 At tbe top weretbe gods of Olympus, Zeus and diJfering codes of conduct, from the Egyptians witb their already
his colleagues, immortal, gifted with superhuman powers, but all ancient culture to tbe barbarous tribes of the north and west.
too human in their behaviour. They came close to individual And in turn tbey were threatened by the Persian expansion of the
Greeks because each city had its own patron god or goddess, who first half of the fifth century, which culminated in two invasions of
was particularly worshipped there, as Atbena was at Athens. Greece - tbose repulsed at Maratbon in 490 and Salamis in 480
Some had wider scope, like Apollo of Delphi, whose oracle was _ and made even those who stayed at home acutely aware of an
consulted by states and individuals from far and wide. These alien culture. There were also many differences of outlook among
beings could and did arouse genuine devotion, but their example the Greeks themselves: Athenians differed from Spartans, and
was not such as to inspire anyone to a highly moral way of life. both from Corinthians, and as time passed tbere were great up-
There were also numerous lesser and more shadowy beings, like heavals of opinion even witbin a single community, as traditional
the nymphs and river-gods of the countryside, worshipped by the ways of tbought came under attack for a variety of economic and
local people. And finally there were the gods of the mystery political reasons.
religions, like Dionysus, who was worshipped in a frenzied way Two early works illustrate the kind of information educated
and witb a personal enthusiasm quite different from the worship men had at their disposal. In his Journ0' Round the World, Hecataeus
of tbe calmer Olympians. With such a mass of material it would of Miletus described tbe customs of a vast number of peoples
not be surprising if tbe individual's views were a trifle confused; throughout tbe known world, from India to Spain; and the
what is surprising is that in spite of it all the gods were generally starting-point of the famous study of the medical man Hippo-
regarded as the guarantors of morality, in tbe sense that both in crates (or one of his followers), Airs, Waters and Places, was tbe
this life and the next tbey were ready to punish misdeeds and fact tbat peoples living in differefit geographical situations differed
reward the good. And tbere was enough of positive good in in many respects, botb physical and mental. Among otber things
popular ideas about tbe gods to enable tbinkers like Socrates and it became clear tbat much tbat one set of people believed to be
Plato to develop tbe idea of a perfectly good divinity, stripped of right anotber thought wrong, and this led men witb enqniring
anthropomorphic accidents and caring for tbe welfare of mankind. minds to ask whetber all such beliefs were just a matter of
A related topic is that of what happens after death, and on this opinion and convention. Sexual practices and metbods of dis-
too there seems to have been considerable uncertainty, but enough posing of tbe dead differed in striking ways from one community
positive material for Socrates and Plato to develop their idea tbat to anotber: Egyptian kings by custom married their sisters; many
the soul was immortal. Greek states regarded homosexuality as normal; tbe Parsees
exposed their dead on high towers and the Massagetae of Scythia
tbought it right to eat tbem.' Could anyone of such practices be
regarded as more right tban anotber in an absolute sense? And if

6 7
in these matters what a community thought right was just what standing intellectual issue of the sophistic period, the pf;ysis versus
happened to be the age-old custom of that community, what of nomos debate. This was a wide-ranging argument over whether
right and wrong in general? Might not all moral judgments be characteristic human institutions sum as language, law and
matters of mere convention? So clever men argued, and stirred morality were natural or man-made; for instance, whether there
others to argue against them, and with these arguments moral was only one name for a thing which was its right name (pf;ysis),
philosophy may be said to have begun. or whether all names were equally good, provided only that
This first big argument is associated chiefly with the sophists, some group of men agreed to use them in a particular way
though they were not the only people who took part in it. The (nomos).
sophists were itinerant teachers who, in the fifth century, supplied The terms pf;ysis and nomos have been discussed at length by
the need in Greece for some form of higher education. They were scholars, but for our purposes they can be explained fairly easily.
ready to train young men who could pay their fees in the arts of The word physis, whatever its origin may have been, can be
public speaking and debate which were so important to the rising rendered ahnost exactly by our word 'nature'; it has the same
generation of democratic politicians, and the successful ones range and vagueness and gives rise to the same jJhilosophical
passed from city to city with growing reputations and fuller and problems. Nomos is slightly more difficult, because it covers both
fuller purses. written laws and unwritten custom, but for us the translation
The best sophists were men of probity and considerable intelli- 'convention' is good enough. 6
gence who interpreted their task of teaching in the widest possible As a background to the dispute there were a number of theories
sense. They did not limit themselves to elocution and persuasive about the origins of civilisation probably taken over from the
speaking, but strove to give their pupils a cultured background, physical philosophers, particniarly, as far as our knowledge goes,
which might include the study of such subjects as law and history from Anaximander in the sixth century. Certainly the idea that
as well as grammar and etymology. In particular they touched men had been savages and that the arts of civilisation had been
on ethics and political theory; hence their interest for us. How- acquired slowly was a familiar one, though our knowledge of how
ever, it is also at this point that their peculiar position becomes it was worked outis extremely fragmentary. It was totally opposed
most apparent. Unlike Plato and Aristotle they were not, and to the theory, familiar from the poets, that mankind's present
could not afford to be, scholars dedicated to the pursuit of truth, state was a sad decline from the original Golden Age.
and their interest in ethics was subordinate to their main purpose Once the initial step has been taken of seeing that legal and
of teaching success. Not all sophists were men of the calibre of moral codes differ from people to people, a variety of further
Protagoras, for whom even Plato showed some respect, and some moves becomes possible. We may minimise the differences, and
of them scandalised the more sober Greeks by their apparent argue that any code is better than no code, and that what is
readiness to undermine all moral restraint. Any and every method important is to have a settled system of law and morals of one
that would help their pupils to succeed was valid, and some openly kind or another; or we may stress the differences, and conclude
boasted that they could make the worse cause appear the better. that something is seriously amiss. But here again the roads fork.
They defended themselves by claiming that the man who suc- We may argue that by nature the strong man would be aII-power-
ceeded, by whatever means, deserved to succeed. fuI, but legal and moral codes are devices of the weak for control-
This 'might is right' attitude fits in well with the general ling him; or tl1at by nature all men are equal and that these codes
scepticism aroused by reflection on the great differences in moral are the instruments by which the ruling class imposes its will on
codes found throughout tile world. It is one aspect of the out- the rest of the commuuIty. And even that is not the end, for what
8
9
course of action we recommend will depend on whether we re- (iv) the party in power makes laws in its own interests;
gard ourselves as strong or weak, ruler or ruled. (v) therefore justice is the interest of the stronger.
The:e. are two main points here. One is the notorious difficulty
of decldlUg what ought to be from a knowledge of what is. For The only trick in the argument is in (i). If we add the portion in
instance, even if we decide that nature's laws are ruthless, it does brackets the statement seems to be true, but not if we omit it. But
not follow directly that men ought to be ruthless too. That is only it is only the shorter version, without the words in brackets, that
so if we accept that nature's ways are best. The other is that it is allows us to draw the conclusion at (v).
anyhow very difficult to decide what really are nature's ways. Are After (v) Thrasymachus probably ceased to argue, but the cry
we to look at primitive man, or the animals, or argue in some 'Down with justice' is his obvious final step.
more complicated way, as we shall see later Aristotle did? The Callicles of Acharnae, however, took the argument a stage
~ifficulty has persisted into modern times. It is easy enough, for further. We know nothing of him beyond what Plato tells us in
lUstance, to argue that existing sexual morality is in some ways the Gorgias. 9 He was not a sophist but a young Athenian politi-
unnatural, but extremely difficult to reach agreement about what cian who had absorbed to the full the teachings of some of the
code would be natural. sophists. He argues that (in a democracy) the laws and the moral
It is not surprising, in view of all tllese complications that code are made by the multitude of (individually) powerless men
different sophists should have interpreted their basic the~es in who are satisfied if they can ensure that all are on a dead level of
very different ways. And for us there is the further difficulty that equality. But it is nature's law that the better and more powerful
we have only fragmentary knowledge of their views. Because of should rule over and fare better than the weaker, and this we can
this, there is a temptation to attribute to them more profound and learn both from animals and from the behaviour of the sovereign
consistent theories tllan they are at all likely to have held. We need states of men. Outstanding men at present are deceived from
not suppose that most of them preached doctrines that would childhood by being told that equality is right and fine, but one day
stand up to close examination: the persuasive power of an argu- a superman may arise who will throw off the shackles of morality
ment, and not its objective validity, was what interested them.7 I and obey only nature's dictates - and good luck to him!
will try therefore not to go beyond what is justified by the evi- The sophist Antiphon of Athens, in his book on Truth, probably
dence, at the cost of being rather scrappy. written about 430, attacks the laws in a slightly different way. He
First there are the views that preach nature's way, but interpret points out that often obedience to the laws may be harmful to the
it in different fashions. Probably the most famous of these is the man who obeys, and so be against nature, which urges every man
one put into the mouth of the sophist Thrasymachus of Chalcedon to further his own interests. This is a criticism of the actual work-
by Plato in Book I of the Republic. The whole account has been ing of the law, because it punishes those who break it but does
much chewed over, 8 but we may assume that Tbrasymachus really nothing to reward those who obey it to their own disadvantage.
did say that justiceis the interest of the stronger, and that he meant Conclusion - down with the law I
by it something like this: Critias, later notorious as one of the thirty tyrants who ruled
Athens for a short period at the end of the fifth century, and one of
(i) in any community (men say that) it is just to obey the laws the less satisfactory followers of Socrates, added to this an attack
of that communlty;
on religion, saying that it was a device for making people obey the
~~) in any con:munlty the laws are made by the party in power; law even when they were not being observed, because they
(111) the party lU power is the stronger party; thought the eyes of the gods were upon them.
10
B II
All these views amount to no more than an attack on existing The anonymous writer quoted by Iamblichus, who probably
laws, and advice to disobey them when it is possible and advanta- wrote shortly before 400 B.C., reflects the views of Protagoras and
geous to do so. The relativity of laws and moral codes is not a may have been his pupil. He replies roundly to thinkers like
prominent idea in these thinkers, but it was certainly presupposed, Callicles that superman does not and could not exist: any indivi-
and it is given a thorough airing in the Dissoi Logoi, a curious dual is at the mercy of his fellows and ought in his own interests
work of sophistic inspiration whose author is unknown. It was to obey the laws of his community. He then gives a straight-
written some time after 400. forward account of the benefits of the rule of law and the evils of
It is possible that Hippias of Elis, another sophist of the second its absence. '
half of the fifth century, held a physis theory of a more constructive There is one sophist who stands apart from the rest because
kind. He may have taught that by nature all men are equal and he made no claim to teach virtue, but only rhetoric. This is
should treat each other as brothers, but this is exceedingly Gorgias of Leontini, whose long life is said to have lasted from
conjectural, and it was a long time before theories of that Idod 483 to 375. He has left us some model speeches, which till recently
took root. have been dismissed as mere exercises. But with works of this
The great defender of the opposite view, that laws and moral period it is probably a mistake to do this: the arguments may be
codes ought to be observed, was Protagoras, the first of the treated as seriously as, for instance, the bombastic displays of
sophists. He argued that it is in the interests of all men that laws men like Thrasymachus. In the Helena and the Palamedes Gorgias
should be observed, because the state of nature where there are no makes an incursion into moral psychology, using arguments to
laws is a terrible one. Unfortunately his views have to be re- show that wrongdoing is always involuntary, and that neither
constructed from evidence that is not at first sight consistent. Helen nor Palamedes are to blame for their midseeds. Helen, for
Plato gives us two very different aspects of his teaching in two instance, might have been charmed by specious argument or
dialogues, the Protagoras and the Theaetetus. But it is probable overcome by the passion of love, and in neither case was she the
that he was held in sufficient esteem by Pericles to be asked to cause of her wrongdoing. It is all somewhat superficial, but it
draw up a constitution for Thurii, a new colony founded in 444 does raise questions that need an answer. Further, there is a close
by Athens but open to all Greeks, and we may reasonably con- similarity between the Palamedes and Plato's Apology of Socrates,
clude that his views were moderate. which suggests that Plato must have been seriously interested in
He started from the fact that there was a great difference the former work. 1O
between savages and civilised men. He said that the state of nature
was an evil one and that men achieved a good life, or something
approaching it, only by living in a community under laws and (iii) DEMOCRI"rUS
conventions of behaviour handed on from one generation to There are also similarities to Socrates in another figure of this
another. Hence all laws and moral codes were civilising and period, the rather puzzling Democritus of Abdera, a younger
improving influences, and it was right for each man to obey the contemporary and indeed a fellow townsman of Protagoras.
laws of his own community. At the same time one constitution or Although he was a voluminous writer our knowledge of him is
moral code might be rather better than another, and the wise limited to a collection of fragments, from which he emerges as a
man would be able to appreciate such differences and to teach positive thinker who had no dealings with sophistry but taught a
them to others. As such a wise man himself, he claimed to instruct way of life which recognised the importance of the soul and of
others. virtue.
He is not primarily famous for his ethics, but for his atomic
theory of the constitution of the universe, which is the distant
ancestor of modern atomic theories and must be understood by III. SOCRATES
us as the background to his ethics. He taught that matter was made
up of innumerable small, hard indivisible bits, called atoms,
combined together in various ways, and that the soul itself, being
material, was made up of extremely fine atoms. These would be The sophists had an .unsettling influence, but this was only one
dispersed at death, so that there need be neither fear nor hope of a factor in the decay of morals and decency which we observe at
life after death. Since this life was the only one, it is not surprising the end of the fifth century. Another factor was the long and
that Democritus' chief concern was to tell men how to enjoy it. disastrous war between Athens and Sparta, which lasted on and off
In doing so he raised the next great topic of Greek ethics, the from 431 to 404 B.C., and involved nearly the whole of the Greek
nature of happiness. The essence of this was a tranquil state of world. The Golden Age of Pericles, in which Athenian culture
mind, and to attain it a man needed to take thought, to limit his reached its highest peak, was succeeded by war, plague, and
aspirations to his abilities, to think little of worldiy goods which disillusionment. Moral standards, both public and private, slipped,
are at the mercy of fortune, and to take pleasure in friends he has and men were uneasily aware that something had gone badly
chosen, rather than in having children whose characters he cannot wrong. Sober citizens blamed the new intellectuals, including, in a
choose. blanket condemnation, physicists and physiologists, sophists, and
All this is on a straightforward prudential footing, but there a man of quite a different stamp, Socrates of Athens. Socrates did
are also some fragments which bear a close resemblance to the indeed resemble the sophists in his influence on the young and the
kind of thing that Socrates was saying at about the same time. power of his intellect, but he differed by his refusal to accept pay-
'Ignorance of what is better is the cause of doing wrong'; 'The· ment for his work and his pure moral fervour.
man who does wrong is more unhappy than the man who suffers It is, however, very difficult to get a clear picture of his life and
wrong'. These fragments are tantalising, for it is not at all clear work. He wrote nothing himself, and it is one of the puzzles of
how he reached such conclusions; but we must assume that it history to reconcile the accounts of him left us by Plato and
was without the hard reasoning that brought Socrates to the same Xenophon with the comic portrait in the Clouds of Aristophanes
point." It is also rather mysterious that though Aristotle made a and the evidence of a number of lesser or more remote writers.
careful study of Democritus, Plato does not mention him, parti- The Clouds" shows him as a representative of the intelligentsia,
cularly as he anticipated one of the points discussed in the Philebus, studying the heavens like the physical philosophers, but also
the recognition of a calm middle state between violent pleasures educating the young to bandy words, and worse, with their ciders,
and pains. as the sophists did. Xenophon shows us a kindly, but rather prosy
Democritus is important, however, chiefly for another reason: old moraliser, and Plato a man of intellectual and moral genius.
his physical system and a good deal of his ethics were taken over Even on the factual level there are difficulties. For instance, both
bodily by Epicurus. He used them as the foundation of one of the Xenophon and Plato wrote an account of his Apology, the speech
two great practical philosophies of the age which followed he was supposed to have made at his trial, and these accounts are
Alexander's epoch-making conquests. entirely different; both cannot be true, and it is probable in fact
that neither is intended to be an accurate account of what was
said. The conventions of the time would allow much freedom of

14
15
invention, and it even became fashionable to write Socratic very beginning. As given to us by Plato, much of Socrates'
Apologies. Hence we have to do the best we can with admittedly teaching was negative and ended with the discomfiture of his
untrustworthy material. Points to remember are that ti,e Clouds smug and respectable respondent, who went off muttering against
was produced when Socrates was a middle-aged man, whereas the 'yet another sophist'. Socrates' band of youthful followers were
works of Plato and Xenophon were probably all written after his of course delighted, but it was not only this that drew them to
death, and some very long after it; that Plato was a philosophical him. Undoubtedly he had a magnetic personality; probably, too,
genius, and Aristophanes a comic genius who may well have he held certain more positive views about life and death, and was
transmuted their material in different ways; that Plato probably ready to discuss these with his intimates, among whom were some
had the most intimate knowledge of Socrates; that Plato gives of the outstanding young men of his time. Here, however, we are
many other brilliant portraits of historical figures in his dialogues on very uncertain ground. We know that he thought much about
which would lose their point if they were not lifelike, even if a the gods, and much about life after death, and I cannot myself
littie larger than life, whereas Aristophanes might make a joke doubt that he had certain experiences - trances and an inner
either out of a wild fantasy or out of a close-to-life caricature,l3 voice - which would nowadays be called psychical. What he
One point is clear, that for a detailed account of Socrates as a made of all this is, however, far from clear.
philosopher we have to go to Plato or nowhere. But the particular The key to Socrates' character is perhaps this: that he had
difficulty about taking Plato as our source is that he was a great reached certain tentative conclusions about the nature and pur-
philosopher in his own right, and we can seldom be sure that the pose of life by non-rational means and then sought to justify and
views he puts into Socrates' mouth are in fact Socrates' own and amplify them by reasoned argument. Argument for him meant
not Plato's. I propose, however, to assume that the earlier dia- arguing with people, not the abstract setting out of proofs in a
logues give us a reasonably faithful picture of Socrates' methods, treatise, and his first aim was to bring about conviction in indi-
and to treat ti,em as my main authority. viduals, including himself, not to lay down a body of timeless
Socrates was a man with a mission, who in Christian times truths. This is another reason why we must approach him with
would probably have achieved fame as saint or heretic. From an caution. When we read a dialogue by Plato we have first to allow
early age he was puzzling over large questions, the nature of the for the fact that it is Plato writing and not Socrates speaking, and
universe and how men ought to live in it. He seems to have won then remember that Socrates himself would suit his arguments to
some renown and attracted a body of devoted admirers, one of his company, arguing now on one level and now on another,
whom asked the Delphic oracle if any man was wiser than accepting at different times different sets of tacit premises, and
Socrates. 'No man is wiser,' the oracle replied; but Socrates was seldom setting forth his own views at length. Some of his argu-
too humble to believe that he had any outstanding share of wis- ments seem to us incredibly bad; he may have recognised this, and
dom. I4 Instead he set out to prove the oracle correct by showing may not have cared, if only they appealed to others. Another
that all other men were as ignorant as he was, with the additional complicating factor is his well-known irony; it is always open to
handicap that they did not know how ignorant they were. us to dismiss anything that he says which we do not want to accept
Politicians, sophists, poets, and tradesmen all received his atten- literally as being said ironically, and unfortunately different people
tions; he would engage a man in conversation, ask him some see his irony in different places.
question to which the man was convinced he knew the answer, We need not press too far his own description of himself as
and then show, by cunning questioning, that the answer was full nothing but a midwife to other men's ideas, for only a man of the
of inconsistencies. Knowledge must be sought again from the strongest convictions could have lived and died as he did. But the

17
fact remains that we can have greater confidence in our reconstruc- There are, of course, various kinds of ignorance, and it is easy
tion of his teaching on its lower levels, where he explores difficul- enough to show that some wrong acts are due to simple mistakes
ties in his own and other people's views, than when we try to about the facts. A case that would spring readily to the Greek
understand his more positive thought. This is not perhaps sur- mind was that of Oedipus, who committed parricide and incest
prising. It seems likely that Socrates himself never reached the because he did not know that the man he killed in fair fight was
point where he was able to explain his position comprehensively, his father and the woman he later married was his mother. But
and that it was left to Plato to produce a complementary philo- this is straightforward, and Socrates was more concerned with the
sophy which would, for Plato at least, do so; though we may think kind of ignorance that is ignorance of good and evil. A man might
that Plato was not in all respects faithful to his master. know all the relevant facts, but still do wrong because he was
Socrates was himself a good man, and exemplified all the five ignorant of what was truly good. However, when we ask what
great Greek virtues - wisdom, courage, temperance, justice, and Socrates meant by knowledge of good and evil, his answer is
piety. The Delphic oracle recognised his wisdom, he showed his not very clear. This is not surprising in view of Socrates' fre-
courage by saving the life of Alcibiades at the battle of Potidaea, quent protestations of his own ignorance, but it does add to the
his temperance by his behaviour in love and his strong head for difficulties of understanding him. What we have is a series of
drink," and his justice in his general dealings with his fellows, approaches to the problem, in which suggestions put forward
and in particular in his refusal, at some personal risk, to take part by others are examined by Socrates and in most cases found
in illegal actions at the behest of either political party.16 Finally, he wanting.
was pious in fearing the gods and trying to obey the divine will. A great many of his explorations were attempts to find a satis-
If we are to understand his ethical views we must remember his factory defiultion of a particular moral term like 'courage' or
righteousness and his consciousness of it. And lastly, we must not 'justice'. He would get one of his audience to propose a definition,
forget his death. The reasons for this have been much disputed, which was then scrntinised with great care, and nearly always
but the simplest account seems the best. By his untiring devotion rejected. It was rejected either because it was not, in form, a
to his mission Socrates had incurred the wrath of the political satisfactory definition, for example, Meno's list of different kinds
leaders of Athens at a time when tempers were easily frayed; they of virtue, in the dialogue named after him, or because on examina-
brought him to trial on charges of impiety and corrupting the tion it was found to be in conflict with certain propositions which
youth of the city in the hope of frightening him away into exile. Socrates and the company were convinced were true, as when
But when condemned to death at the age of seventy, he refused to Cephalus suggests in the first book of the Republic that justice is
flee and remained to face execution, believing that only so could paying one's debts, but then agrees that particular cases of paying
he carry out his duty. one's debts, like returning a-sword to a homicidal maniac, are not
Socrates' basic assumption was that all men, if they could, just. From all this one gets the impression that Socrates was
would do what was right, and that the sole reason for their not seeking a certain kind of definition, which would be illuminating
doing so was some kind of ignorance. He knew perfectly well that enough to give a man true knowledge of justice or virtue, but
his famous paradox, 'No man does wrong willingly', was indeed somehow he never managed to find it. We shall see later what
a paradox, and that if true it had to be proved so by lengthy Plato did with the assumption that such definition could be found.
argument. The man in the street believed that one might know Another suggestion is explored in the Protagoras, that the know-
what was right but do what was wrong. Socrates tried to show ledge needed is knowledge of how to estimate pleasures and pains
that this was an illusion. accurately. If, as many people think, hedone (pleasure) is the only

18
truly good thing in life, and pain the only bad, we want to do the Not only is virtue knowledge, but each individual virtue is
actions that will produce the greatest possible amount of pleasure knowledge, and from this it would seem to follow that all virtues
and the least possible amount of pain. But men are deceived by are ultimately one. But this is in opposition to the popular view
temporal perspective: they are misled, for instance, by a prospect that a man may be, for instance, brave without being just, or
of immediate pleasure so that they fail to see that by pursuing this generous without being self-controlled. In the Laches Socrates
they will miss the chance of greater pleasure in the future. They tackles the particular case of courage, on which even popular
need to learn to perform a hedonic calculus. This suggestion is thought leads to paradoxes. Is it the man who faces danger un-
found, however, here and here alone and it does not seem to have afraid who is truly brave, or the one who feels afraid but stands
been Socrates' final thought.'7 his ground even so? Socrates argues that the brave man is the man
The most attractive suggestion is that what is needed is know- who feels no fear, but not on the one hand from lack of imagina-
ledge of oneself. The motto of the Delphic oracle was 'Know tion nor on the other through mere technical knowledge, like the
thyself' and Socrates clearly took it to heart. But this advice may trained fireman, but because he has the knowledge of what is or is
be interpreted in at least two ways. On a mundane level, it may not rightly to be feared. This comes down to the knowledge of
mean, as Critias in the Charmides suggests, knowing oneself as an good and evil and such knowledge is also at the heart of all other
individual, with all one's strengths and weaknesses. Xenophon, virtues.
also, shows Socrates giving advice to Euthydemus on exactly In the Hippias Minor we meet another Socratic paradox: that a
these lines. But this does not take us far enough. To know what man who does wrong on purpose is better than one who does
you can do does not by itself tell you what you ought to do, and wrong unintentionally. This, again, is in complete contrast to
so the other possibility must be explored. Here we must treat popular morality. But Socrates argues that if someone deliberately
ourselves not as individuals but as members of the species Man, does wrong, he is capable of doing right, but chooses not to do
and ask ourselves what we as men ought to do. The answer to so. For only if he knows what is right can he be sure of avoid-
this takes us deep into Socrates' positive thought, and so I pro- ing it. But the man who makes an involuntary mistake has not
pose to leave it for the moment and turn to a number of topics the ability to correct it, and is therefore inferior. It is, however,
connected with his original search for the knowledge that is the clear that Socrates does not mean that anyone does in fact do
basis of virtue. wrong willingly, and on his own theory this is impossible; all he
If virtue is knowledge, we would expect it to be teachable. But claims is that if there were a man who did wrong on purpose he
Socrates is far from happy about this. Against the view that would have to be a good man.
it is teachable he can point to a number of facts: that rich men who It is now time to say something about what Socrates meant by
have their sons taught other skills do not have them taught virtue; 'virtue'. To begin with, the English word has some misleading
that there do not appear to be any teachers of virtue, though associations, and the Greek word are!e would sometimes be more
possibly the sophists and the older members of the community aptly translated by' excellence' or even' success'. The emphasis of
may each in their different ways claim to be such teachers; and 'virtue' tends to be on good intentions, but that of are!e is on good
that the Athenians in the assembly are ready to take advice on non- results; the English word is almost, though not quite, limited
technical matters of policy from anyone who cares to speak, to moral goodness, but the Greek covers goodness of many
because they do not believe that there are any experts in political different kinds. A knife that cut well, and a horse that ran well,
virtue. And yet in the MenD, from which these arguments are taken, both had are!e, and the are!e of a man was displayed as much by
Socrates is still hankering after the view that virtue is teachable. his achievement in any kind of human endeavour as in his upright

20 2'
behaviour towards others. In particular, arete often means skill in recognised that pleasure was regarded by many people as the only
governing. In the Meno (9,a), for instance, Socrates asks about 'the really good thing, and the goal of human life. He was not satisfied
wisdom and virtue (arete) by which men can run the affairs of a about this, but it is by no means clear what he himself regarded
household or a city well, and take care of their parents, and receive as the goal. It is at this point that his intultion probably out-
and send off visitors from home and abroad in worthy fashion'. stripped his powers of analysis: he could show by example what
And the typical 'good men' referred to again and again in the true virtue was, but he seems to have encountered grave difficult-
dialogues are the leading politicians of Athens - Themistocles, ies in explaining his positive thought to the full. This is indicated
Aristides, Thucydides the son of Melesias, and Pericles - to not only by the difficulty we have in finding it in the pages of
all of whom, except perhaps Aristides, who was nicknamed Plato, but also by the fact that his followers developed many
'the Just', we would be more ready to give the title' great' different lines of thought, all of which they claimed to be Socratic.
than 'good'. Antisthenes taught that virtue was the sole good, but Aristippus
Both arete and 'virtue' are words with a complex meaning. founded the pleasure-seeking school of the Cyrenaics. Socrates
Both refer on the one hand to a disposition of the individual, and on thought hard about life and death and the gods; he believed that
the other to certain things that he does. A man could have neither the gods were good and would care for a man who himself was
arete nor virtue if he was not of a certain kind, and if he did not do good; and he had at least some faith that man had a soul which
certain kinds of things. Where the terms differ is in regard to the was itself divine and immortal. It followed that the welfare of a
kind of person and the kind of action required. And it is peculiarly man lay in the welfare of his soul, but here again we are in doubt.
difficult to say exactly how they differ because neither for the Wherein lies the soul's welfare?
Greeks nor for speakers of English is there complete agree- There is a passage in the Euthydemus that gives us some indica-
ment about what the virtuous person is or does, and much of tion of Socrates' difficulties. The immediate question is, 'What is
Socrates' enquiry was concerned with elucidating this very the techne - the skilled lmowledge - that will make men
point. happy?' The argument proceeds thus: the art of ruling - which,
What does the virtuous man do? The superficial answer is that as we have seen, was frequently equated with virtue - can make
he does good deeds. Or, in particular, the brave man does brave men prosperous and free, but prosperity and freedom in them-
deeds, the just man just deeds, and so on. But, as Socrates saw, we selves are neither good nor bad. To achieve a good end we must
will, at least on reflection, only call a deed brave or just if we also also make men wise and give them knowledge. But what kind of
regard it as good, so the basic question is, 'What are good deeds?' Imowledge must they be given? It seems that it is the kind that
Good deeds are frequently, though not always, taken to be those makes other people virtuous. But if virtue is the art of making
that produce good results. If so, what are good results? Many, other people virtuous, it makes them acquire the knowledge of
though not all, would say they are the achieving of conventional how to make people virtuous, which gives those people the
good things like riches, pleasure, power, knowledge, and health. knowledge of how to make people virtuous - and so on. Clearly
But are all these things really good? Is there anything else of a we have not reached a satisfactory account of what virtue is, and
different kind that is good in this sense? Is virtue itself good in we may conclude this section with the suggestion that Socrates
this sense? firmly believed that virtue was knowledge of something, but was
Socrates had no difficulty in showing that some conventionally not sure what.
good things, such as health and riches, could be abused, in the Let us return to the other aspect of virtue, that of what a man is.
sense that they may harm their possessor. On the other hand, he Here again Socrates' answer is the same, the virtuous man is the

zz
man who has a certain kind of knowledge. But here again diffi- for the first time stated in detail the view that the soul is a non-
culties arise. If we draw an analogy between this kind of know- material but fully real entity, identified with the reasoning and
ledge and other Idnds, for example, the knowledge possessed by morally responsible part of man. It is in the Phaedo that the theory
the physician or the accountant, one big difference leaps to the eye. of the soul as immortal is worked out in detail, and much of the
The physician, by his special skill, is uniquely in a position to kill elaboration is probably due to Plato, but the basic thought is
as well as to cure, and the accountant can make a better job of surely that of Socrates. 'S
cooking the books than the man who is not an accountant. But, as
we have already seen in connection with the Hippias Minor, it is
paradoxical to suppose that the just man is particularly well-
fitted to be unjust. Socrates plays on this difficulty again and
again, without producing any solution to it. We are left to con-
clude only that we are looking for a very peculiar kind of know-
ledge.
The answer Socrates may have given is the one mentioned
earlier, that what we need is knowledge of ourselves as men. If we
really understand the nature of men, we may gain insight into
what we, as men, ought to do. There is again a logical difficulty
here; that of passing from what is to what ought to be. But by
itself I do not think it would have troubled Socrates. The argu-
ment is psychologically satisfying, even if it is not formally
valid.
Man is a soul imprisoned in a body. At death the soul will be
freed, but its destination will depend on how pure it has kept it-
self from contamination by the body. Contamination arises from
the influence of bodily desires, and the wise man will try to free
himself from these. He will view life as a preparation for death and
what comes after death, and the knowledge he needs is knowledge
of immortality. This in itself was a contribution of great impor-
tance in the history of thought. It is true that the Greeks before
Socrates had some notions of survival after death, but he was
probably the first to put them in reasoned form. Homer spoke of
phantoms dwelling in Hades which drifted aimlessly and longed
only for life under the sun. Some of the mystery religions, like that
of Bleusis in Attica, of which we know deplorably little, probably
believed in something much more satisfying, but the beliefs were
couched in picturesque language and lacked complete develop-
ment. Socrates amplified and clarified these lines of thought, and

2)
the only works of Plato that we have are the dialogues, and in most
of these Socrates is the leading speaker. They were written over a
IV. PLATO period probably of about fifty years, from soon after Socrates'
death in 399 to Plato's own death in 347. We cannot give them
exact dates, or even arrange them in an accurate chronological
order, though we are reasonably sure which are late and which are
Plato was intellectually the greatest of Socrates' followers, and earlier." If we regard the earlier dialogues as being truly Socratic
resembled his master in his enthusiasm for virtue. If the force in the sense that they give us a faithful picture of Socrates' ways of
of his personal moral character is not as great as that of Socrates, thinking, we may go on to assume that in the later works there is
that may be explained on the grounds that he was more of a poli- more of Plato's own thought, in which Socrates' views are ampli-
tician than Socrates ever was. He was born, in 427 B.C., into a lead- fied and given certain metaphysical and political twists which are
ing Athenian political family, and was expected to take an active alien to him. It is impossible to be sure where Socrates' thought
part in politics himself. But standards of political behaviour ends and Plato's begins: even Plato himself could not have
declined during the long war with Sparta that occupied most of distinguished between the two. But in what follows I give what I
his childhood and early manhood, and he became disgusted with take to be most probably Plato's own contribution.
both parties for their unworthy treatment of Socrates. He there- Plato began by accepting nearly all that Socrates had taught,
fore devoted himself to interpreting Socrates' message in his but he soon became aware that there were gaps and loose ends
writings, and to improving political life at one remove by which had to be dealt with somehow. Most of the earlier dia-
educating others to become good rulers. For this purpose he logues may be taken as attempts at setting out Socrates' views
founded the Academy, a school for young men which has been clearly and getting to know where the difficulties lay. Starting
described as the first university. Since he agreed with Socrates from Socrates' claim that virtue is knowledge, we may see Plato
that virtue must have an intellectual basis, he tried to work out a developing the concepts of both virtue and knowledge beyond
system of education that would lead to Socrates' goal, the know- anything that Socrates had achieved.
ledge of goodness. His personal qualities are shown chiefly in Let us take knowledge first. Plato produced a highly sophisti-
his activities as administrator, teacher, and thinker, but there is cated theory, which takes us far from the realm of ethics, and we
one episode that shows that he also bad considerable courage. cannot therefore go into it in detail. But we must have some
At the age of sixty, in 367, he was invited to undertake the educa- understanding of it if we are to grasp Plato's ethical position.
tion of the young ruler of Syracuse, Dionysius II, who controlled Socrates had been constantly asking questions like 'What is
the most powerful Greek state in Sicily. Dionysius, being already courage?' and 'What is beauty?', and it was but a short step to
thirty, but completely uneducated, was hardly good material for a assume that there really were things called courage and beauty,
philosophical education, and Plato koew this, but he felt that distinct from courageous acts and beautiful objects, about which
the opportunity to put his own principles into practice should such questions could be asked. Plato postulated a world of Ideas
be taken, poor as it was. The venture was a risky one, and in fact which were more real than the things of the world of sense and
failed, but not before Plato had suffered considerably from were the patterns and origins of all the things in that world, and
it.I9 he believed that these were the sale possible objects of koow-
The difficulty we met with in deciding what Socrates' views ledge. In particular there were Ideas of courage, justice, tem-
really were has its counterpart in Plato. Apart from a few letters,20 perance, and all other virtues, and if one could attain koowledge

26 c
bf these one would become brave and just and temperate and so on the personal level about the nature of virtue in the Republic,
on; if one went further, and achieved knowledge of the Idea of which shows him grappling with the same problems as Socrates.
Goodness, which was the greatest and best of these Ideas, one One of the big questions raised is 'Why ought a man to be right-
would be virtuous in every respect and would know how to lead eous ?', and for all its political trimmings the work does give an
others to virtue. answer which holds good for individuals.
This argument was criticised at length by Aristotle, and I First we must say something about the word here translated
propose to leave discussion of it until we reach Aristotle. But we 'righteous'. It is dikaios, and there is a related noun dikaiosyne,
may see now how Plato used it to answer Socrates' problems. He which is sometimes translated 'justics', sometimes 'righteous-
believed that knowledge of the Ideas was only to be achieved by ness'. It covers that very large part of virtue that is concerned with
men who started out with great gifts of character and intellect our general dealings with others, including keeping the law. Of all
and were then given an immensely long training in mathematics virtues, with the possible exception of courage, this is the one that
and philosophical reasoning. At the end of this, some few might most obviously brings disadvantage to its possessor, as the
reach the highest point of all, the vision of goodness, and they, sophists had so clearly seen. The unscrupulous tyrant flourished,
and they oniy, would be qualified to be rulers 'of the rest and to while the upright Socrates was sent to his death. On what grounds
lead them in the paths of goodness that they could not find for could justice be defended?
themselves. Details of the kind of education Plato thought neces- Plato's answer to this shows him to be the true pupil of his
saryare to be found in the Republic, and it is reasonable to suppose master. Only the righteous man can be happy, because only the
that he taught something on these lines in the Academy. righteous man has his soul in such a condition as to be happy. To
Plato~s answer to Socrates is a discouraging one in two respects: prove this, Plato had to give an analysis of the soul; this he does,
on the one hand, it meant that very few could be virtuous in the but unfortunately his account is probably adjusted to the general
fullest sense, and, on the other, that few could have even a political theory of the Repttblic. It is not very plausible in itself, and
theoretical understanding of what goodness was. In particular does not seem to have survived into his later thought,22 However,
we ourselves, who can only read the Republic and do not have the it remains an interesting theory, and a number of the points made
benefit of a full course of Platonic education, cannot hope to are valid. He divides the soul into three parts,>' reason on the one
understand what is meant, and all we can do is to try to reconstruct hand and the passions and an intermediate part which he calls the
a general outline of what Plato had in mind. It seems to have been 'spirited element' on the other. With the distinction between
something like this: knowledge of goodness involves knowledge reason and the passions we are all familiar, and there is nothing in
of how and why the world is constituted as it is, and also of how Plato's account that need detain us, but the spirited element is
men ought to act in order to fit in with the goodness of the whole. more difficult to understand. Plato tells us that children too young
The knowledge needed to be virtuous is knowledge of this to reason and many animals possess it, and gives two examples of
metaphysical kind, and lesser men have to be guided by others it in action: the first when a certain man had a ghoulish desire to
because they are incapable of it. Again, as with Socrates, we are look at some freshly executed corpses, but was restrained for a
left unsatisfied, for we cannot say, for all to know, what a man time by the feeling that it was an indecorous thing to do: and the
must do to be good. second when someone thinks he is being treated unjustly, and
Plato's general theory has had immense influence, but it is and bears all kinds of suffering to attain justice. The term cannot be
must be essentially a political theory, and as such is beyond the translated adequately by any single English word: suggestions
scope of this study. He does, however, have a great deal to say include' mettle', 'anger', 'righteous indignation', and 'sense of

28
honour'. But I think we have to accept the fact that this concept is attain knowledge, must control us; or, again like Socrates, we
not really a viable one.>4 may argue that reason is that part of us that is most divine, and
In the Republic, however, the spirited element forms part of a therefore it ought to be in control. Probably Plato accepted both
neat pattern. To begin with, Plato analyses three of the main lines of thought.
Greek virtues as virtues of the three parts of the soul, wisdom of We have then a tidy scheme in which the virtues are linked and
reason, courage of the spirited element, and temperance of the all are dependent on reason and knowledge; and the accounts of
passions. Before we continue we should notice another difficulty wisdom, courage, and temperance are unexceptionable. But justice
of translation: the word sophro[Yne, here translated' temperance'. is very odd. The definition Socrates is made to accept is 'minding
Ids sometimes equally well translated' self-control', being in fact one's own business', and this, as applied to the individual, means
rather narrower than the latter term, but wider than the former as having each part of the soul doing its proper job. Now this is not
it is commonly used in English. Although exact translation is at all the kind of definition of justice that one would expect,
impossible, the concept is a fairly easy one to grasp. because justice appears to be a virtue that is particularly concerned
The remaining great virtue which Plato now wants to place is with one's relations with others, and this definition deals entirely
justice, and this he finds in the individual who has the three parts with the inner make-up of a single person. What Plato is giving us,
of his soul in a proper relationship, with reason controlling the as he realises himself, is an account of what the just man is, com-
passions and being alded by the spirited element. It follows, of pletely ignoring what he does. He therefore has to claim indepen-
course, that a man cannot be just without also being wise, brave, dently that a man of this kind will not in fact commit typical un-
and self-controlled, and so Socrates' view that virtue was a unity just actions like embezzling money or committing sacrilege, but he
is vindicated. But we may still ask why a man whose soul is in this gives no proof of this."
condition should be happy, and Plato's answer to this is perhaps It is clear, however, why Plato has to take this line. He has cut
more complicated than convincing. Shortly, it amounts to the himself off, during the course of the argument, from defending
fact that only so is the soul as it should be, in a state of mental justice on any external grounds, such as that it helps one to avoid
health, and only so can a man be happy. punishment after death or to acquire a good reputation. And it
There are two big unexamined steps in the argument, and a would have appeared nonsensical to the Greeks to argue, as Kant
third point which must be stated at length. The big steps are might have done, that there is an absolute duty to be just. So he is
(i) that it is a good reason for being just that it makes a man happy, left with the task of defining justice as a disposition, and showing
and (il) that happiness depends on mental health. Plato does not that this disposition is a condition of happiness.
really attempt to prove either, the first because it would seem to In the Republic, then, we have Plato's answer to two of the
him to need no proof, and the second perhaps because he cannot big questions raised by his predecessors. He claims to have found
prove it. However, both may reasonably be accepted. The third the kind of knowledge that Socrates was seeking as the basis of
point is concerned with the relations between the parts of the soul. virtue, and he claims to have replied to the sophists that justice is
Plato maintains that they must be related correctly, but how are profitable to the man who practises it. We must now turn aside to
we to decide what is the correct way of arranging them? It was look at a curious dialogue which reflects Platonic influence
quite clear to Plato that reason must be supreme, but it is less clear though it was probably not written by Plato himself. This is the
to us why this must be so. Here are, however, two possible A!cibiades 1. It is a remarkable tour de force, weaving together
approaches. We may argue, like Socrates, that virtue is know- practically every topic to be found in the earlier dialogues of
ledge, and it will follow that reason, the part of us by which we Plato. But on one point it goes beyond them: the question of the

;0
meaning of knowing oneself has again been raised, and with great thought if he derived no pleasure from thinking. Possibly, he says
clarity the point is made that the body is only a tool used by an later, the life of a god might be like this, but it is not the best life
agent, the soul, which is the real self. How, then, does one get to for a man. On the other hand, what would be the satisfaction
know the soul? The eye cannot see itself, but can see other eyes, gained from a life of continuous pleasure, if there were neither
or itself in a mirror; so the soul can learn about itself either by consciousness of present pleasure nor memory nor anticipation
gazing at the soul of a friend or at the brightest mirror of all, God. of pleasure to accompany it? He concludes that the best life will
It would take us too far from our main theme to work out this be one in which both pleasure and thought are found. But that
point in detail, but it introduces a note which we shall meet again does not take us far enough. We want to know more exactly how
in Aristotle. Here we may treat it as a variation on the theme of the the two are to be combined.
Idea of the Good; by gazing on God we learn about the divine Plato has now admitted that some pleasure is good, but he
nature and about our own souls, and so learn what we ought to do. does not want to go all the way with the hedonists and say that all
Besides the discussions of pleasure in the Protagoras and the pleasures are good. He has therefore to make a close study of
Gorgias, which we have already mentioned, Plato devoted some pleasure in order to draw distinctions, and to show that while
attention to it in the Republic, but his great dialogue on pleasure is some kinds of pleasure are good, others are bad, and not fit to be
the Philebus. This is one of the very latest of the dialogues, and found in the good life. First, however, he points out something
its background seems to be this: the Academy had attracted men that all pleasures have in common: that they, and their opposite,
of learning from all parts of the Greek world, who shared Plato's pains, can be more or less intense. A big question in what follows
interests but held widely differing views on some topics. In parti- is how this intensity is to be estimated.
cular there seems to have been a lively debate on the nature of the Pleasures and pains may first be divided into two groups, those
good for man. The astronomer Eudoxus maintained that pleasure that are of physical, and those that are of mental origin. In the
was the sale good, but others, like Speusippus, that both pleasure first class are the pleasures of eating and drinking. The body is an
and pain were evil. 26 The young Aristotle, as we shall see, must organism which contains ingredients of many kinds, and there is a
have taken a great interest in this discussion, and Plato himself, certain optimal proportion of these ingredients. If this is dis-
now an old man, wrote the Philebus as his contribution to the turbed, as it is when a man's body has too little liquid in it, he will
controversy. This is one of the most thorough studies of pleasure feel thirsty, and if he is able to drink the drinking will give him
ever made by a philosopher, and in some respects has never been pleasure. It would be a mistake, however, to suppose, as some
superseded. philosophers have done, that all pleasures are like this. The second
Unlike the Republic, and unlike Plato's very last work, the class is one of purely mental pleasures and pains, as when a man
Laws, the Philebus has nothing to do with politics but is concerned who is now free from bodily pains is yet expecting to be hurt, and
solely with the good of the individual. 27 And although it has a therefore suffers mental pain. Here it would be inappropriate to
metaphysical setting, the ethical arguments may be detached speak of depletion and repletion, as one can of the body, but the
fairly easily from it. The question at issue is, 'What is the good for pleasures and pains are true pleasures and pains none the less.
man?', which may be interpreted as 'What is it that each man Further, in both cases there is an intermediate state between
really desires, and will give him complete satisfaction if he attains . pleasure and pain which is itself neutral. This may be the condi-
it?' The main candidates under discussion are pleasure and tion of the gods who live a life of thought without feeling, and is
thought, and Plato begins by showing that neither is sufficient by also that of a man whose pain has been relieved and who is back
itself. On the one hand, no one would be satisfied with a life of to his normal state of equilibrium.
The mental pleasures considered so far are those of anticipation, most profligate pleasures, because they are pleasures, are good.
and anticipation is closely linked with desire. Plato now gives an Arguments of some kind or other, then, Plato had to find. The
analysis ofhoth. Both depend on memory. When a man is thirsty, particular form he chose may have been due to previous discussion
he feels a desire for drink, but this is only because he has heen in a in the Academy of his treatment of pleasure in the Republic. There,
similar physiological state in the past, and found the pain then to too, he had spoken of false pleasures, arguing that since the body
be relieved by drinking. He now has memories of such ex- is less real than the soul, so the pleasures of the body are less real,
periences, and, when thirsty, has a mental image of drinking and the man who is the slave of his passions will make even his
accompanied by the desire to do so. Without memory there could reason pursue false pleasures that are alien to it. Possibly what he
be no desire, and it follows that all desires are mental. Plato is said here had been taken up and criticised, and he may have hoped
making a distinction here between conscious desire and the mere to clarify its meaning while at the same time producing an argu-
state of depletion. The first time a body is short of water, for ment which might convince even Eudoxus that some pleasures
instance, no desire for drinking will be felt, but merely a state of are bad.
pain without any idea of what will relieve it. What he does in the Philebus is to try to show that there are a
What are we to say of those states in which a man is, for number of ways in which pleasures may be false. All are mental
instance, in pain because he is thirsty, but at the same time is pleasures, and in each case there is some kind of judgment or
confident that he will soon be able to drink, and so has pleasure in estimate that is mistaken. The first example he gives is of a bad
the thought of drinking to come? Is his state painful or pleasant, man who dreams of possessing great riches, and takes pleasure in
or what? Plato's reply is that it is a mixed state, in which he is the thought. But the pleasure is false because it rests on a false
feeling both pleasure and pain at once. Similarly, when he is judgment. Unfortunately it is not entirely clear what the false
thirsty but has no hope of drinking, he will feel two pains, one judgment is supposed to be about. Some scholars believe that the
physical and one mental. man is indulging in idle day-dreams of riches he will never in fact
So much by way of preliminaries. Plato has been stating a attain, but others that even if he attains them he will not derive
number of points necessary to his argument, most of which we can from them the pleasure he anticipates. Whichever it is, Plato does
accept as soon as they are stated. His further points are both not dispute that some pleasure is felt, but he maintains that it is a
difficult to understand and difficult to accept, and there is still false pleasure and therefore a bad one because of the falsity of tl,e
considerable disagreement among scholars about some of them. judgment.
His stated aim is this: to show that there are some pleasures that The second example is of a man who is in a mixed state of
may fairly be described as false, and that these pleasures at least are physical pain and mental pleasure, due to desire for relief and the
bad. He seems to realise that this is a claim that most people will expectation that relief will soon come. Now the pleasure of
reject out of hand, and goes to considerable trouble to state, and anticipation ought to be proportionate to the intensity the future
make, his case. We can only guess at why he chose this method, pleasure actually will have. But it is very difficult to estimate
but the following is perhaps relevant: it would not be enough this, owing to the pain the man is now feeling, which makes the
to state that some pleasures, or even some named pleasures, pleasure of relief seem greater than it will in fact be. 28 In this sense
are bad. There was a school of thought in the Academy that the pleasures, and equally the pains, of anticipation may be false.
would have denied this. Aristotle notes the paradox that its leader, A third kind of illusion occurs when men mistake the neutral
Eudoxus, was a man of virtuous life, but that would not have state between pleasure and pain for either pleasure or pain. This
prevented him from claiming, in theory at least, that even the may occur, for instance, when relief follows great pain; the change

34 35
is so great that a man helieves he is now feeling pleasure. This case 'There is one final argument against pleasure of any kind being
is slightly different from the other two: there some pleasure was the good for man. Pleasure has been described as a process in
indeed felt, hut it was, for one reason or another, inappropriate. which something is coming into being, not a stable existent. Now
Hete there is no pleasure, only a false helief that one is having it." for Plato, as for most men, it seemed a truism that what is most
Then follows a general argument, the point of which is not valuable must be most real, and what is most real must be a
entirely clear. Plato no longer speaks of false pleasures and pains, substance, an unchanging thing. For this reason pleasure cannot
hut of mixed states in which hath pleasure and pain are found. He be the most valuable thing. We will see later the comments Aris-
may still he developing the theme of false pleasures, or he may he totle had to make on this argument.
making another point, that the most violent states of feeling are Plato is now ready for his final answer to the question about
those in which pleasure and pain are mixed. In any case, his general the composition of the good life. It will contain knowledge and
aim is clear: hath false pleasures and mixed states are to he shown skills of all kinds - no one, he says, wants to argue about this-
up for what they are, different from the ideal pleasures which alone and a selection of pleasures. All pure pleasures will be admitted,
are truly good. and any others that are necessarily bound up with the normal
There are violent emotional states of the hody, of the soul, conduct of life. But violent pleasures that interfere with the
and of hath. A man in a fever gets intense enjoyment from activity of thought are to be excluded. Plato leaves us in no doubt
drinking, and a man with an itch, from scratching, hut only about his conviction that the highest life for man is one of intel-
hecause of the contrast with the discomfort or irritation he is also lectual activity, tempered with such other activities as are desirable
feeling. Mixed states in which hodily pleasure or pain is accom- for man as a biological creature. He still hankers, like Socrates,
panied hy anticipation of the opposite we have already discussed. after the disembodied and passionless life of a god, but has come
There remain the states of mental pleasure mixed with pain, as to realise that this is an impossibility for man, who must make do
when we wallow in our grief, or laugh at a comic situation while with the second-best.
at the same time feeling distress for the man who is making a fool After the Philebus comes the Laws. This was Plato's last work of
of himself. all, left unrevised at his death. It is a great contrast to the Philebus,
Whatever one may feel ahout Plato's method of arguing here, which for mildness and sober good sense reminds us of the works
there is no douht that he has succeeded in producing a very mixed of John Stuart Mill. Mill could never have written the Laws, with
hag of apparent pleasures which one might well hesitate to call its passages of savage illiberality and despair of mankind. And yet
good. It is no longer possible, after Plato, for the philosophical the difference between the Philebus and the Laws is not in-
hedonist, as distinct from the rake, to pursue an unexamined life comprehensible. By setting his sights lower for the individual,
of pleasure. Plato abandoned his hope of an ideal state ruled by godlike
There are a few pleasures left which may he called pure and individuals - godlike in knowledge if not in body - who could
true. These include the pleasures gained from sight, hearing, and guide the rest of mankind to the best possible way of living. The
smell, by seeing beautiful colours and shapes, smelling pleasant dream was abandoned, and a different constitution had to be
scents, and so on, and also the pleasures of acquiring knowledge. devised, in which the baser elements in man were more fully
In these there is no admixture of pain, and so, even if less intense, recognised than in the Republic. A further link is that the Laws is
they are more truly pleasures than the mixed kind. If it is pleasure much concerned with the use of pleasure and pain to guide men's
that is good and beautiful, then a small pure pleasure will be better actions, and the Philebus would have helped to clear his mind on
and mote beautiful than a more intense mixed one. these topics. The Laws is mainly concerned with political ques-
...,

tions which we cannot deal with here, but it has some sections of fear, or again when he is overmastered by desire and the search for
ethical interest. pleasure, or, finally, by ignorance, which may either be simple
One great innovation is the attempt to give some account of ignorance, or ignorance accompanied by the conceit of know-
the notion of moral and legal responsibility, which had so far been ledge.
ignored by Plato and Socrates. This is understandable, because if Now this seems to land Plato in a mess. Where passion or desire
it is true, as Socrates maintained, that no man does wrong are responsible for crime, he seems to imply that a man may know
willingly, it seems to follow that no man is responsible for wrong what is right but be unable to do it. To blame these things is to
actions, because they are done unwillingly. In the Laws Plato has return to the position of Gorgias in the Helena, and give up
to face this paradox because he introduces laws which distinguish Socrates. Plato may still maintain that all wrongdoing is in-
between voluntary and involuntary wrongdoing. This distinction voluntary, but he cannot still claim that it is all due to ignorance.
was a commonplace of the legal systems of the Greece of Plato's The difficulty arises, of course, from an attempt to come to terms
time, though at an earlier period any wrong act, however in- with the accepted way oflooking at crime and punishment in the
voluntary, had been considered culpable. The Laws contains very legal codes of his time. He could not do this and be faithful to
carefully worded provisions covering homicide of many different Socrates. As we shall see, Aristotle took up the same point and
kinds in all its details. Unintentional killing, unpremeditated developed it further.
killing, and deliberate killing are dealt with separately, with many
subdivisions for each. Plato bad therefore to justify such distinc-
tions, while still maintaining the Socratic paradox. NOTE ON PLATO'S TREATMENT OF LOVE AND FRIEND-

Unfortunately his account contains some obscurities, and SHIP

scholars differ over its interpretation. The first step, however, Friendship and love are not often discussed by modern moral
seems straightforward enough: we must distinguish the guilt philosophers, but both Plato and Aristotle wrote on them, and
incurred by someone who does wrong, from the harm inflicted by our study would not be complete without some account of what
his action on someone else. One would like Plato to say that the they said. Plato devoted the dialogue Lysis to friendship, and the
loss or harm must be made up as far as possible, but that no other Symposium to love, and the Phaedrus is also relevant. 'Friendship'
punishment is called for. This, however, is not what he says. and' love' are not exact equivalents of the Greek terms philia and
Compensation is adequate in the case of what most people would eros, but they are near enough to indicate the kind of problems
regard as involuntary wrongs, which are not really wrongs at all, Plato chose to tackle. Eros referred to a passionate relationship;
but punishment is necessary, in spite of Socrates, where the philia to something less intense. 30 The main problem with regard
wrongdoing is regarded as voluntary. There must be some kind of to both, at least for a Greek, is that there are two terms to the
penalty that will improve the soul of the criminal. Punishment is relationship, and that when a man loves (in the widest sense)
not therefore to be retributive, inflicted simply and solely because something else, this suggests that there is some deficiency in him
there is guilt, but deterrent or reformative, aimed at ensuring that which he hopes to remedy by means of the object of his love. If so,
a similar crime will not be committed in the future. Plato's point he cannot be perfectly good himself, and this seems to rule out the
seems to be that a man only does wrong when his soul is not in the possibility of love and friendship between those who are perfectly
state in which he would really wish it to be, and this is again good.
Socrates' position. Plato adds a careful analysis of the causes of In the dialogues Plato explores with great thoroughness the
this: a man may do wrong when he is carried away by anger or various kinds of deficiency which might be relevant. The first

39
question is whether friendship arises between those who are alike
or those who are unlike. One might expect like to cleave to like,
but equally one might expect opposites to fill each other's V. ARISTOTLE
deficiencies. Plato's final conclusion, in the Laws, is that both
kinds of friendship exist, as a matter of common observation. In
the case where there is some deficiency, is the deficient man a bad
man? Plato struggles hard to avoid this conclusion. It may be, he Aristotle was born in 384 B.C. at Stagira, a city on the northern
says in the Lysis, that the lover is neither good nor bad, but is outskirts of the Greek world, but at the age of seventeen he came
sufficiently affected by evil to desire its good opposite without to the Academy in Athens to study under Plato. For the next
being so far gone as to be indifferent to goodness. This is de- twenty years, from 367 to 347, when Plato died, he was a member
veloped in the Symposium into the view that the lover desires what of the Academy, and took part in its research and teaching. After
is good and beautiful at various levels, according to his philo- a period away from Athens, during which he made some serious
sophical development, and that what he is ultimately seeking is biological studies, and also, for a time, was tutor to the future
that which is denied to mortals, immortality. By love he can get Alexander the Great, he returned to found his own school, the
near to it by the procreation of children or by producing and leav- Lyceum. Like Plato, he wrote a number of works for publication,
ing behind him other, more enduring, beautiful things. but all these have perished, though the main outlines of some can
be reconstruCted. What we have left to us is a vast collection of
'Aristotelian papers', connected with the lectures which Aristotle
gave to students at various periods of his life. These papers were
edited in ancient times and given the form in which we now have
them, and it is a matter of conjecture how much was written by
Aristotle himself, and how much by editors or pupils. It is also
difficult tQ make any chronological arrangement of them, because
it is probable that passages written at very different dates are
found next to each other in many works.
Three ethical treatises have come down to us in the collection.
One of these, the Magna MaraNa," is certainly not by Aristotle,
but must have been written by a member of his school some time
after his death. The other two, the Nicomachean Ethics and the
Eudemian Ethics, have three of the central books in common, and
there is still no agreement among scholars about their proper
relationship, about the time at which they were written,3. or even
about the authenticity of the Eudemian Ethics, though the majority
now accept it as genuine. Fortunately, however, these points afe
not of great importance to us, as on most subjects the philo-
sophical outlook is the same in both works. They might be
described as collections of essays, not particularly well arranged.

4I
iI.
!)
,
',I
There are, for instance, two differing and unconnected discussions other men as ignorant and confused, Aristotle felt that there must
of pleasure in the NicofJJachean Ethics. But their disjointedness be at least a grain of truth·..ln every sincerely held opinion. In
must not be over-emphasised. It is a fair assumption that Aristotle particular we must take account of -our own moral intuitions,
gave courses of lectures in a definite order, and that the present provided that we have. received a sound moral training. From
arrangement of his works largely reflects that order. Over a period these we draw statements that are true but unclear. It is the busi-
of years changes would be made, and old presentations be replaced ness of the philosopher to proceed from these to something
by new, both of which were later piously preserved. But the basic clearer; but we cannot hope for the same exactness in ethics as we
structure remains. can in mathematics.
By temperament Aristotle was a very different man from Plato, This in itself is a criticism of Plato's methods, or at least of the
though he was profoundly affected, both emotionally and intel- hope he had of achieving a scientific knowledge of good and evil.
lectually, by the latter's views. Perhaps because he spent the But Aristotle also gives us a detailed criticism of Plato's Idea of
greater part of his life in a city of which he was not a citizen, and the good. This is an excursion into meta-ethics, the study of the
where he could take no active part in politics, he had no burning use and function of ethical terms. Plato had argued something
interest in political reform. At the same time his intellectual like this: there are a great many things which we call' good', and
interests ranged widely, and he was the editor of a collection of we do so because we recognise in them a common characteristic.
constitutions of Greek and non-Greek states, which provided To explain how they came to share in this characteristic, he
material for the Politics. This, like the Ethics, is a collection of postulated an Idea of goodness which existed independently of
essays, and contains a certain amount of material which is of them, but in which they somehow participated. To know what
interest to us. It is surprising that, for all their attraction for the , good' meant one needed to get to know the Idea of goodness,
romantic makers of legend, the years spent with Alexander seem and this, as we have seen, could only be done by a few gifted
to have had singularly little effect on either Aristotle or Alexander, souls after years of rigorous study.
though they probably remained on terms of distant friendship. Aristotle attacked this theory on a number of grounds, for
Aristotle had probably taken part in the debate which led up to example, that it was unhelpful and. unnecessary, but his most
the writing of the Phi!ebus, and had certainly read and pondered compelling argument depends on making distinctions between
on that work, as indeed he had all the other dialogues of Plato. various uses of the word' good'. Some things are good in them-
There is hardly a question raised in the Ethics, or an answer given, selves, but others good only in relation to something else. For
that cannot be found somewhere in Plato, but Aristotle's method instance, one knife may be good for spreading butter, and another
of approach is so different that the work still has great originality for sharpening a pencil, but neither is good in itself. These, then,
and freshness. By the use of the dialogue form Plato had been are two different though related meanings of the word. Again,
able to give expression to a number of differing views on the things of many different kinds are called good: God is good in
subjects under discussion, but his aim was to refute most of them, one sense, virtue is good in another, the right moment is good in a
and the very success of his characterisation tended to limit the third, and so on. It is hard to believe that one Idea of goodness can
range of his argument. By giving formal lectures, on the other CQver all these. The Idea might be saved, it is true, if we confined
hand, Aristotle was able to cover as many views as he wished, and ourselves to one single use of the word, that describing things
he aimed to bring out what was true in the theories of other that are pursued and desired on their own account. But when we
thinkers and also in the less explicit views held by the majority look at the different kinds of things that are called good in this
of mankind. Whereas Socrates and Plato tended to think of most sense, it is difficult to pick'Qut any one common element. What

D 43
have pleasure and honour and wisdom in common, for instance? clarification of our moral ideas. Aristotle's work does not have the
At the same tiine it is not a mere coincidence that all these things tremendous impact that Socrates achieved, and it leaves many
are called good. At this point Aristotle drops the argument, with a difficulties unsolved, but as a scholarly exercise it is unrivalled.
few undeveloped suggestions, saying that it is more suited to We will begin, as Aristotle himself does, with a study of the
another branch of philosophy. He does, however, produce his term 'good'. Men are active creatures, constantly doing things,
own answer in the next chapter, saying that things are called good and most of their activity has some purpose. Sometimes we are
because they are the things at which men aim. making things, as when we build a house or sew a garment, and
The background of all this is some quite complicated theories sometimes we are aiming at something less tangible, as when we
of meaning that Aristotle was engaged in working out." I-Ie no walk to be healthy or again when we walk for the sake of walking.
longer believed, as Plato had, that a word must either mean exactly Many of our purposes can be arranged in a hierarchy: we make
the same thing on every occasion when it is used or else be plainly needles and thread in order to sew, and sew in order to make
and simply ambiguous, as is the word 'bar' used of chocolate and clothes to wear. If nobody wanted clothes we would not need to
of music. There are more complicated cases in which the meanings sew, and if nobody wanted to sew, there would be no need to
are not identical, but are related. For instance, a man and fresh make needles and thread. Each activity aims at producing some-
air are healthy in different but related ways. It is the same, he thing good, and some things will be good if they serve a purpose:
suggests, with' good '. And if so we can perhaps select a primary a good needle is one that is suitable for .ewing, and a good gar-
usage from which all the others are derived. ment one that fits its wearer and is suitable for his activities.
Now in one sense Plato had already done this. He was certainly When we say that health is good, however, or that we have just
fully aware of the disrinction between good as means and good as had a good walk, we cannot name some particular purpose which
end, and was not such a rigorous formalist as to exclude Aristotle's health or that walk has served. Here the disrinction between
approach. Unless he committed himself more deeply in his un- means and ends come in. Needles and clothes are good if they are
pu~lished lectures than he does in the works we still possess,
suitable means to other ends. Of health or a pleasant walk we
Arlstotle's attack here seems misconceived. But he is on firmer tend to say that they are ends in themselves. But if the hierarchy
ground with the final criticism, that when we gather together all is to be complete there must be one further end still, which is the
the things that are good in themselves they are a heterogeneous final good. In fact we can discover one such thing, happiness.
lot, and their only common factor is their relationship to men's Health and a pleasant walk may both be treated as means to happi-
desires. Such a common factor is not enough to form a basis for ness, but happiness itself is not a means to anything else.
the kind of science of goodness Aristotle thinks Plato had in The /ioal good for man has thus been discovered by considering
mind. how man in fact behaves.
This criticism of Plato gives us some idea of Aristotle's method. However, the word 'happiness' does not take us very far, for
It is a method that has a considerable resemblance to the methods while all men are agreed that the aim of life is happiness, they do
?f mo.dern linguistic analysts. He takes a term which is important not agree about what it consists in. People say that it is money, or
~n ethics, and studies how it is in fact used. He then tries to classify
pleasure, or health, and change their minds from time to time. The
lts usages, and show how they are related. He also sometimes difficulty Aristotle recognises here can be explained if we see
recommends changes in common usage, because he does not think that there is a two-way relationship between the terms' good' and
that the latter quite fits the facts; for instance, in his treatment of 'happiness'. It is true that the good for man is happiness, but that
voluntary and involuntary actions. The result achieved is a great is only half the story: it is also the case that happiness consists in

D2 45
44
having and keeping the good for man, whatever that may be. activity of soul in accordance with virtue'. It may well be asked at
'Happiness' is a blanket term covering any and every thing that is a this point how Aristotle manages to bring virtue in here. The
part of the good for man. And so we are enclosed in a .circle that answer lies in the peculiar meaning of that term, which we have
can only be broken by finding some other method of discoverIng already discussed. If arele is expressed in doing something well,
what either the good for man or happiness is. and happiness also lies in this, then arele naturally finds its place in
This brings us to a slight difference between the word 'happi- the definition." But we are again far from a statement, in terms of
ness' and the Greek word eudaimonia which it is used to translate. a.ctual deeds, of what man's arete is.
'Happiness' tends to cover two different things, which we may Aristotle is not unaware of the difficulty, and does later in the
describe as a state of well-being and the consciousness of well- Ethics give accounts of the various aretai a man may have, but
being. So we may say tbat a man is happy if he feels happy. But at present he remains on tbe level of generalities and turns to
this is not so with the Greek word. In the story of Solon and consider what other things are necessary to happiness. His list is
Croesus, Croesus believed that he was happy, but this was no a common-sense one, except for the provision we have already
evidence for Solon. 'Call no man happy till he is dead,' he said, referred to, that happiness cannot be achieved in less than a
for only a complete life could be judged. This was indeed an complete lifetime. Prosperity is needed, passable good looks,
extreme view, but it is echoed in Aristotle. Again, there is a ten- reasonable birth, relatives and children who are alive and of good
dency in English to use the terms 'happiness' and 'pleasure' character. These are things that in the Eudemian Ethics he regards
indiscriminately. This would be much less likely to happen in as necessary conditions, but not parts, of happiness.
Greek. We may regard a lunatic as bappy, and call the euphoria After this it cannot be denied that Aristotle havers. He tackles
produced by some drugs happiness, but all this would be impos- the crucial question as to whether a man crushed by misfortune,
sible with the Greek term. like Priam in his old age, can be said to be happy. At first he denies
Aristotle approaches the problem of the content of happiness it, but later says that the happy man can never become unhappy,
by asking about the function of man, a topic in which as a man 'though he can hardly be supposed to enjoy supreme felicity if his
with a biological training he would be particularly interested. sorrows are like those of Priam'. We need not be driven here to
There are functions at various levels: each organ, like the eye or the view that these two passages were written at different times,
the stomach, has its peculiar function, and each man who is a for Aristotle's method made him liable to inconsistencies of this
skilled professional has a function, the flautist to play the flute kind. They are the inconsistencies inherent in common ways of
and the shoemaker to make shoes. It is reasonable to assume thought and speech. We do, on the one hand, believe that a great
, man has a function too, and what this is is to be
that man aua many external Circumstances can affect a man's happiness, and
discovered by finding out what it is that is unique to man and we do, on the other hand, have faith in a kind of inner and per-
not shared with other creatures. Life is shared with animals and haps more real happiness that is independent of changes of
plants, and even sensation with animals. The only thing not shared fortune.
is reason, and we conclude that the peculiar function of man is to So we come to the final definition: 'The happy man is one who
exercise his reason. Now any function can be exercised well or is able to realise perfect virtue in action, and is snitably furnished
badly, but satisfaction follows only when it is done well: we may with external goods, and that for a complete lifetime. And his
conclude that man will only be completely satisfied when he is death shall be in accordance with his life'.35 This is not an inspir-
exercising his reason well, and that in tbis he will find his happi- ing definition, but it is the result of careful thought about all the
nesS. A definition of happiness or the good for man will be 'an relevant facts.

47
T

The next step is to study virtue in greater detail. First, we must danger, because there are some risks that it is stupid to run. The
understand human psychology. The soul has two parts or aspects, brave man faces danger on those occasions when it is right to do
the rational and the irrational. The irrational may again be sub- so, and thus on fewer occasions than the foolhardy man does and
divided into a vegetative part concerned with nutrition and on more occasions than the coward. In every moral virtue,
growth, which is most active in sleep and is also found in all other Aristotle claims, it is possible to find some aspect that makes of it
living things, and an appetitive part in which the desires and pas- a mean between two extremes, and he works out this doctrine
sions are to be found. It is this that is of particular interest to us. with some thoroughness. It cannot be denied that sometimes his
On this basis virtues may be classified into two groups, the treatment seems artificial and he has to strain hard to make his
intellectual, which are virtues of the rational part of the soul, and point, even to the extent of inventing names for non-existent
the moral, which are of the irrational. Wisdom and prudence, for. vices to fill out his table of virtues and vices neatly. 'Insensitive-
instance, are intellectnal virtues, generosity and self-control moral ness', for instance, is the name of the supposed vice that goes with
ones. The moral virtues are particularly connected with p.leasure the virtue of temperance and the opposite vice of self-indulgence,
and pain in various aspects, and the following discussion is con- but Aristotle admits that it is unlikely that there are in fact
cerned solely with these. Pleasure and pain pervade human life, any insensitive. men. Further, Aristotle does not make much
and men seek the one and avoid the other, but the virtuous man use of the Mean once he has worked it out in detail. It is indeed
is one who is able to resist them when it is right to do so. Moral a link between the moral and the intellectual virtues, but this
education consists in giving the child practice in this by adding point is treated rather superficially. His discussion does, however,
further pleasures and pains as rewards and puulshments for have a value of a different kind. He produces with gusto sketches
behaviour. :In this way virtuous habits are formed, and a man of virtues and vices that give us a unique insight into Greek moral
becomes virtuous, Aristotle says, by doing virtuous acts. This sentiments. From them we learn with more certainty than we can
account owes much to Plato's Laws, but it deserves some study anywhere else what kinds of characters the Greeks, or at least
here. If a child is frightened and runs away, we must inflict pain to the more cosmopolitan Greeks of the fourth century, admired.
counter the pain he is afraid of, and so induce him to face the He does not in fact feel himself bound to keep too strictly to a
dreaded thing. If we do this often enough, he will form a habit discussion of the Mean. He adds to his study of courage, for
of facing things he is afraid of, for fear of being punished if he instance, a survey of five related states that are sometimes also
does not. And by facing things he is afraid of, he will become called courage. As a result, we feel much more at home with the
brave But for Aristotle bravery involves not merely facing Greeks.
dange~, but feeling pleasure in so doing, and there is a gap in his I do not propose to study this section of the Ethics in detail.
account which will not cover this. We might fill it by using the • In the Introduction we glanced at one of the most controversial
idea of the conditioned reflex, but the full answer must be that for parts, the description of the 'great-souled' man. Many have
Aristotle good habits were an essential part of virtue but not the claimed that Aristotle's account must be ironical, because they
whole, and that reason had also its part to play. cannot see how this quality can possibly be treated as a virtue." I
It is at this point, and with regard to moral virtues alone, that would venture to suggest that we should forget about its being a
Aristotle introduces his famous doctrine of the Mean, elaborating virtue in our sense, and think that it is rather something that we
a hint thrown out by Plato in the Philebtls. Let us take an example. may admire in another way. If we call the quality concerned
We regard some men as brave, others as cowards, and yet others 'greatness', and think of the characteristics referred to when we
as foolhardy. The brave man is not one who ignores any and every !;lay of someone, for instance, 'She was a very great lady', we may

49
come nearer to understanding. We may admit that there are sly is part of the general catalogue of virtues, and need not detaln
touches of malice in the portrait, but we need not doubt Aristotle's us here. After it Aristotle returns to the old question raised by the
general sincerity. Humility is a Christian virtue, and was not sophists, whether justice is natural or conventional. By his method
admired by the Greeks. of making distinctions Aristotle is able to answer that it is both.
A virtue to which Aristotle devotes much attention is the one Unfortunately what he says is brief and rather obscure. He
which we usually call 'justice'. We have already seen in our dis- recognises that where legal systems differ, the basis of the laws
cussion of Plato that the word dikaios and its derivatives are not which differ must be conventional, but he also allows for the
only difficult to translate lnto English but also rather elusive in existence of natural justice, though he is not very clear as to where
Greek. Aristotle makes a masterly attempt to cover its various it is to be found. Some light may be thrown on this by a passage
uses and show what its basic meaning is. This is one of the places at the beglnning of the Politics, where Aristotle tries to demon-
where there is a clear difference between Aristotle's method and strate that the state is natural. Individual men are not self-
that of Socrates. Socrates and Plato were never pleased when sufficient, and they have a social lnstinct which leads them to
presented with a list in place of a definition: all these things, they combine. It would seem to follow that law and justice are natural
would say, have something in common, and what we are interested in the sense that they arise in this way.
in is just that common feature, and nothing else about the list. Aristotle has claimed that the purpose of studylng ethics is
Aristotle, belng more aware of the possible complexities of mean- not to learn what goodness is but to become good. But there are
lng of a single word, looked at different applications of the word many passages where he forgets this, and lndulges in the pleasant
'just' and tried to classify them. He found, for instance, that a man logic-chopping of the professional philosopher in a way far
who wanted more than his fair share of good things In his dealings removed from the spirit of Socrates. The paradoxes that were
with others was called unjust, and his opposite just, and again matters of deadly earnest for Socrates become for Aristotle
that these terms were used In a strictly legal connection of those opportunities for a display of virtuosity. Can a man suffer wrong
who broke or observed the law. And here we may look back at voluntarily? Can a man wrong himself? Such questions provoke a
Thrasymachus. 'The laws aim at the advantage of allln common, dazzling display, but on the level of head rather than heart.
or of the best, or of those who have power or something of this In the first part of Book III of the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle
kind,' says Aristotle. This is what Thrasymachus claims, except takes up the question of moral responsibility already broached
that he picks out the case where only the lnterests of the party in by Plato in the Laws. He studies a range of cases and tries to
power are fostered. Aristotle goes on to say that the law requires decide which types of action are voluntary and which not. At the
of us a great many virtues such as courage and self-restraint, one extreme are acts done through physical compulsion, which
which we display In obeylng one or other of the laws, and for this are entirely lnvoluntary, and also acts done through ignorance.
reason justice covers all the other virtues. This is a bit artificial, But there are different klnds of situations In which ignoranoe
but it makes the connection needed to explaln Thrasymachus' plays a part, and further distinctions must be made. If a man
argument. There is only one difference between justice in the does somethlng in ignorance, i.e. not Imowlng the full nature and
broad sense and arete. Arete is primarily a state of soul, but when circumstances of what he is doing, but does not regret havlng
we use the term 'justice' we are thinklng also of relations with done it when he later discovers his mistake, he cannot be said to
other people. And the fact that both types of justice are concerned have acted lnvoluntarily In the technical sense In which we are
with other people is another link between them. now uslng that word. We ought rather to use a different term,
The palnstaking discussion of particular justice which follows . 'non-voluntary'. Then there is the distinction between acts done

50 )I
in ignorance, and those done through ignorance. A man may be within the sou~ and the soul itself acts voluntarily. He seems to
ignorant of what he is doing because he is drunk or blind with he on the verge of saying that we apply the terms 'voluntary'
rage. But as his ignorance is due to these conditions he is not and 'involuntary' only metaphorically when we use them of the
acting throtl,gh ignorance pure and simple, only in ignorance, and parts of the soul, and that the primary use must be of the soul as a
his act cannot fairly be considered as involuntary. Nor is ignorance whole. That is, he treats' voluntary' as meaning by definition' that
of right and wrong enough to make an action involuntary and which originates from a man's soul' and any application below
therefore blameless. The only kind of ignorance that will do this that level is therefore ruled out.
is the simple ignorance of some fact about what is being done, Aristotle now passes to a related question. Voluntary acts may
like not knowing that the gun is loaded, or that the person with be further subdivided, including, for instance, actions done on
whom you go through a ceremony of marriage is married already. impulse and those done after considerable deliberation. In the
Next there are some tricky cases where a man does something latter case there seems to be some kind Cif deliberate choosing,
he would not normally choose to do through fear or some other and Aristotle tries to say something about this. The Greek term
inner compulsion. He does choose to do it, and yet he does it he uses is proairesis. It has often been said that the Greeks had no
unwillingly, as when a man betrays his country for fear of what his idea corresponding to our 'will', but we have here, in proairesis,
children in enemy hands may suffer otherwise. It would he a something very similar. It is usually translated by a word like
mistake to call such actions involuntary, since they are chosen, 'choice', but it is a special kind of choice that has much in
hut they can hardly be called voluntary without qualification. common with our 'will'. The latteris itself a confused and difficult
Aristotle in effect suggests apart from the others a new classifica- notion, and philosophers and psychologists have long since
tion that they need. abandoned the view that there is in us any element or aspect that
Finally, Aristotle dismisses the suggestion that acts done from can strictly be called the will, but the term does at least point
anger or desire are involuntary. Throughout it has been clear that to something in human nature that deserves to be isolated and
he has been writing with the question of legal responsibility at the studied if we are to have a full understanding of moral
back of his mind, and on that basis it would be impossible to behaviour.
admit that acts of these kinds were involuntary. If we refuse to It is clear from what Aristotle says that the question of the
punish actions that are involuntary, and then say that anything nature of proairesis was an old one which had already been much
done in anger or from a desire for pleasure is involuntary, our discussed, possibly even in the Academy. Aristotle considers and
whole legal system will collapse. There may be room for argument dismisses four views, that it is desire, passion, wish, or opinion
over details, and perhaps the recognition of a special status for the of some kind. His method is'to show that there is some character-
crime passionel, for instance, but the majority of such actions must istic of each of these things which makes it impossible that it
be treated as voluntary. 1 should be what we a~e seeking. We can, for instance, wish for
In the Etddemian Ethics Aristotle amplifies his treatment by ask- what we believe to be impossible, but we cannot choose it.
ing why it is that we say that both the man who gives way to Aristotle's own suggestion is that cl,oice is a voluntary act pre-
desire and the man who refuses to give way are acting voluntarily. ceded by deliberation. Voluntary acts we have already discussed,
He answers that in each case the soul as a whole acts voluntarily so the next step is to look at deliberation.
'.
and is the spring of action, though one part of it is under con- We deliberate about things that are in our power to do or to
straint from the other. In the first case desire overcomes reason, refrain from doing, and about the means by which we may attain
and in the second reason overcomes desire. But these are episodes ends that are already given. A number of possible courses are open

52 53
to us, and it is not at once obvious which of these is most likely to always so; he has become depraved by a series of actions of which
achieve the desired end. We have therefore to work out in the earlier ones at least were fully voluntary, and we may still
imagination the best way of proceeding. This is deliberation. blame him now for what he did then, and for what he has become
After that we make our choice. as a result.
Choice, then, is concerned with means, and with actions that it At this point, as at some earlier ones, the twentieth-century
is in our power to take. Wishes, on the other hand, are concerned reader is bound to feel dissatisfied. By taking one further step, it
with ends, and we must now look at wishes. What kind of ends seems, Aristotle would have been brought face to face with the
are they concerned with? Good ends, or only those that appear to question of free will and determinism as it ls familiar to us, but he
be good? There are difficulties in both views. It is clearly not true blandly refuses to take that step. What makes it even odder is that
that all the things we normally call wishes are aimed at ends that all the materlals appear to have been there. Gorgias and others
are truly good: on the other hand, Aristotle is still sufficiently had suggested that some at least of the actions we normally call
under the influence of Socrates and Plato to feel uncomfortable voluntary are really involuntary; the iniluence 'of heredity on a
about saying that a man can really wish for something bad. His man's character was well known to Plato, who even in the
solution is to draw a distinction between the good man and the Republic wanted to breed children suitable to be trained as rulers;
bad man, which he takes to be similar to the distinction~between a and the effect of environment was also appreciated sufficiently
healthy man and a sick one. The healthy man has a taste for food for both Plato and Aristotle to work out detailed schemes for
that is truly wholesome, while the sick man may fancy other training children in virtue. To suppose that all actions are in-
things. In the same way, the good man wishes for what is trnly voluntary because they are entirely controlled by a man's heredi-
good, but the bad man has a variety of wishes, and in particular tary make-up and past experience seems a very simple advance
is led astray by pleasure. on all this. But, whatever the reason, Aristotle did not argue along
What Aristotle says at this point is superficial and needs much this line. The line he did take resembles very closely that of some
more analysis than he is here able to give it. At present it is but a modern philosophers who regard the whole freewill controversy
step in a deceptively simple argument to prove that virtue and as misconceived. There are, for instance, great similarities between
vice are in our power. Virtues are exercised in choosing the right his discussion of voluntary and involuntary actions and Moore's
means, and choice of means is within our power: therefore virtue study of the meanings of 'could have' in his Ethics. Both take
is within our power. What this amounts to is that virtues are their stand on common usage, and their readers will feel satisfied
exercised in choosing means, because when we act virtuously we or maddened according to their own temperaments.
are doing something, and what we do is always in some sense a I-- In Book VII of the Nicomachean Ethics we have a study that
means to an end, and as we are choosing to do it, we might equally shows the gap between Aristotle on the one hand, and Socrates
well have chosen not to do it, and so in this sense virtue is ln our and Plato, on the other, at its widest. It is a study of acrasia-
power. another term which is difficult to translate but which is generally
Let us leave this for the moment and consider Aristotle's rendered by 'incontinence', using that term in a broad sense 37 , It
final remarks on this topic. While he holds that in general people refers to a very general condition, not connected with any
are responsible for their actions, Aristotle does realise that there particular vice, and might perhaps better be translated' weakness
are some conditions in which this ceases to be true. The man far of will'. It is the state that Socrates declared to be impossible,"
gone in vice no longer has the power, even if he had the wish, to where a man knows what is right and yet does what is wrong. In
reform; his ways are set and cannot be changed. But this was not spite of Socrates, popular Greek opinion recognised it, and

54 55
Aristotle's first step, as so often, was to make a survey of common says in so many words that' Sweet things are bad for one', and yet
views about it. As he gives them, they are not completely con- goes on to eat them.
sistent: he notes for instance that some assert and some deny that So far, the examples he gives enable us to understand what he is
the continent man is always temperate, and that some say that it is getting at. But we now come to something much more puzzling,
impossible for the prudent man to be incontinent, while others say the doctrine that goes by the name of the Practical Syllogism. 39
that some prudent men are in fact incontinent. In spite of these This he discusses in s-ome separate and not entirely consistent
discrepancies, he takes common opinions as his starting-point, passages ill the Nicomachean Ethics, and also in the De Motu
examining them closely and trying to extract such truth as they Animalium, one of the minor biological works which may not be
contain. The most important belief is that the incontinent man by Aristotle himself but certainly comes from his school.
does what is wrong, knowing it to be wrong, because he cannot When we are presented with the major and minor premiss of a
control his passions. Aristotle wants to reconcile this with syllogism on some theoretical matter, we have by the logic of the
Socrates' position, for which he still has some sympathy, and case to draw a certain conclusion. If, for instance} we are told that
suggests that this can be done if we distinguish different senses of all birds are winged and that thIs is a bird, we have to conclude
knowing. Unfortunately what he says is not entirely clear. He that this has wings. In practical matters, however, we have to do
appears to make two separate suggestions, or perhaps even more, whatever it is that the syllogism leads to. If we know that all
but it is not easy to tell how his suggestions are related and sweet things should be tasted, and that this is sweet, we have to
whether they are all to be taken as independently valid or taste the thing. The minor premiss refers directly t9 a particular
whether they are alternative ways of putting his case. object, and so forms a bridge between the major premiss and the
The general lines of the argument are, however, clear: Aristotle things we actually see and touch. Aristotle's point seems to be that
agrees with Socrates to the extent that he does not think that men our moral knowledge, and any other kind of knowledge as well,
who have full knowledge and who are aware of the relevance of is expressed in generalisations and is thus one degree removed
that knowledge to the given situation could still do wrong. It from action. Only when it is linked to the world around us by a
follows that when they do wrong they must either have something suitable minor premiss does it lead to action. Now the problem is:
less than full knowledge, or the relevance of their knowledge to suppose we know both the major and the minor premiss of a
the situation cannot be fully appreciated. There are a number of practical syllogism and yet do not perform the conclusion, what
situations in which we may be said to have knowledge, and yet has gone wrong? Suppose that one minor premiss is connected
not be in a position to use it; in the extreme case, when we are with two different majors, like 'It is wrong to taste sweet things'
asleep, but also when we are drunk or insane. This first distinction and 'Sweet things are pleasant'. The minor premiss, 'This is
concerns what we would nowadays call dispositional knowledge. sweet', can be connected with both of these, but there is a conflict
But Aristotle seems to be trying to make another point as well because two different actions would result. In the incontinent
when he says that drunkards, for instance, may be able to reel off man, desire, roused by the first major premiss, will lead to action.
geometrical proofs without understanding them, in the same way As the text stands, Aristotle's concluding remarks are obscure
as a beginner might do. The distinction here is the different one and seem perilously near to being nonsense. What he surely needs
between knowing something parrot-fashion and really under- to say is that in this condition, when desire ousts morality, the
standing its meaning. moral major premiss is put out of action, and if we know it at all
Now both these distinctions are relevant to the incontinent man we know it only in the way that a drunkard knows a piece of
because Aristotle wants to cover even the case of the man who poetry. He can say the words, but he does not understand their

57
meaning. Unfortunately this is not what Aristotle says, and it and that this can be an end. The difference between the two is not
does not seem possible to make him say it by any manipulation of immediately obvious, but can perhaps be thought of on these
the text, but it may be what he was getting at in a roundabout Ilnes, that a process is passive, but an activity something initiated
way. by a living being. Some of men's activities, such as the pursuit of
He concludes by agreeing with Socrates, having turned a chal- knowledge, are ends in themselves, and pleasure may be one too.
lenging paradox into a complicated piece of psychology. As a However, in his later treatment he abandons the view that plea-
way of saving the paradox it is brilliant, but it may be doubted if it sure is an activity, and claims rather that it is somethino- o that
advances our understanding much further. Perhaps the most accompanies certain activities. The change may be connected with
suggestive point is one he throws out in passing, that there may an ambiguity found equally in the Greek word hedone and the
be some physiological reason, when people are transported by rage English word 'pleasure'. Both may refer either to things which
of lust, for their being unable to use the knowledge they have, give pleasure, for example, gambling, or to the pleasurable feeling
just as there is in drunkenness. But he does not follow this th~t ensues. In the first sense pleasures may be activities, in the
up. second sense not. He adds further arguments against its being a
Incontinence, properly so called, Aristotle says, is found when process, the upshot of which is that processes must have begin-
a man is overcome by the desire for pleasure. (There are other uings, middles, and ends, and are not complete or perfect in a
things called incontinence by analogy, but we are not concerned moment, whereas a momentary pleasure may be just as complete
with them now.) He is therefore led to take a closer look at plea- and perfect as one that lasts much longer.
sure. We are in some difficulty here because there are, in fact, two Aristotle's conclusion is essentially that of the Phi/ebus, that
sections on pleasure in the Nicomachean Ethics, and they are not pleasure is a good, but not the good, and that not all pleasures are
entirely consistent. It is usual, however, and seems best, to treat to be desired. What he adds is his characterisation of pleasure as
the section in Book X as giving Aristotle's final views. something extra, like the bloom of youth, which accompauies
As with the Phi/ebus, the background of the discussion is the activIties and makes them perfect. Any activity may have its
debate among the leading members of tl,e Academy over whether accompanying pleasure, both in men and in animals , and the
pleasure was the good for man. In Book VlI Aristotle recounts a pleasure accompanying a particular activity makes us want to
number of different theories, and replies to them in a ratl,er continue in it, and hinders us from doing anything else, while the
haphazard way. His own contribution is short and not fully corresponding pain makes us want to abandon it. Hence we must
worked out. It receives a much fuller treatment in Book X. give each kind of pleasure the moral value of the activity it
We learned in the Phi/ebus that one of the arguments employed accompanies, and the pleasures of vicious activities will themselves
by those who did not believe that pleasure was the good was that be bad. Different men will find pleasure in different activities, some
pleasure is a process. All processes have some end, and the end is bad and some good, but the truly good pleasures will be those
better than the process. Therefore there must be something better that seem to the good man to be so.
than pleasure. This argument could clearly be met in two ways, This conclusion may well seem unsatisfactory. Why should the
eIther by denying that pleasure was a process, or by denying that a judgment of the good man be preferred to that of others, and
process could not be the final good, because it was in the rele- how, anyway, are we to decide who is the truly good man? But
vant sense, an end in itself. Aristotle chooses to demonstrate that Anstotle would not have seen the force of objections of this kind.
pleasure is not a process. He does this by distinguishing between Believing as he did that each man, as a man, has a function
activities and processes, and claims that pleasure is an activity, allotted to him by nature - we need not here ask how meta-

)8 )9
phorically that view is to be understood - and believing that he return to the Socratic paradox that virtue is knowledge and that
knew how to discover what that function was, he would feel no all virtues are one. He thinks that Socrates was wrong in making
difficulty about discovering the good man, and no difficulty about the relationship between virtue and knowledge one of identity,
accepting his judgments. And it can hardly be claimed that later but agrees that it is impossible to have any virtue fully without
philosophers have had anything very satisfactory to add. MIll phro"es;!. A distinction must be made between natural virtue and
reached much the same conclusions by even less satisfactory true virtue. Natural virtue is a disposition towards certain kinds of
methods, while those who have maintained that all pleasures are good behaviour, and it is clear that men differ in their inborn
good or that no pleasure is good have seldom produced arguments dispositions. One will be naturally more inclined to generosity,
at all. and another stouter hearted, than his fellows. But such disposi-
So far we have said nothing about the intellectual virtues, but tions need to be guided by phrones;s if they are to develop into true
they play an important part in Aristotle'~ the~ry. We .have seen virtues. Otherwise the brave man will become rash, and the
that Plato regarded wisdom as the crowmng Vlrtue whIch should generous one a spendthrift. So, in the sense that they all share
guide men to the good life, and Aristotle.accept~d. this view, .with phro"es;s, all true virtues have a common element.
significant modifications. His first step IS to divIde the ratlO.nal At the end of the whole work Aristotle returns to the question
part of the soul into two sections, which we may call theoretlcal of happiness. Plato had shown, neatly enough on his own premis-
and practical reason. It is practical reason or phronesis 40 that ses, that the good man is the happy man and that no bad man can
Aristotle regarded as important in moral action. This is clearly a be happy. But Aristotle, with his division of reason into theoreti-
profound change,4' involving a great split in the field of know- cal and practical, and his view that virtue depended in practical
ledge. For Plato the road to knowledge of goodness lay tllrough reason, phro"es;s, was in a difficulty. It was no longer possible
deep theoretical studies, but Aristotle, while recognising. the to link wisdom, virtue, and happiness in the simple way that
importance of these in their own field, thinks that the subJect- Plato had. For Aristotle could not deny that theoretical reason,
matter of ethics is so different that another faculty must be con- or sophia, was the highest activity of man, and he also held that
nected with it. It is unfortunate that we carulot find in Aristotle's man's happiness lay in the exercise of sophia. It followed that a life
ethical writings as we have them a detailed account of how of pure contemplation, remote from politics and mundane
phronesis is supposed to work. We may link it with t.he doctrine affairs, was the best of all. And Aristotle pours forth a eulogy on
of the Mean, and say that its job is to find that POlnt betwe~n this godlike existence. But where, then, didarete come in? He could
excess and defect which is right. Virtue is a practical matter, In not say shortly that this was arele, because too many of the tradi-
which a variety of external circumstances, which cannot be dealt tional virtues, such as courage and generosity, would find little
with with mathematical exactness, have to be taken into account, place in it. He therefore had to add that the life of moral virtue is
and so phroncs;s will include at least sound judgment on practical also a happy one, though only in a secondary degree; he finds
matters. But it must also include more than this: it must not only many reasons for saying that it is a less satisfactory life, few for
enable us to choose the right means to achieve our ends but it saying that it is happy at all. But he does seem to regard this life
must also guide us in the right choice of ends. It must make us as one in which the human aspects of man, as distinct from his
want what is good, as well as be able to attain what we want. And godlike reason, are given full play: in exercising them, therefore, a
this it does presumably because it involves some knowledge of the man may be happy.
nature of man and of his place in the world. There is a passage right at the end of the Ememiall Ethics that
In the light of his discussion of phrones;s, Aristotle is able to differs considerably from anything he says in the Nicomacheall

60 6,
Ethics. He roundly declares that the end of man'is the contempl,,- husbands and wives, and associates' of many different kinds, and
tion of God. To this statement he adds no amplification, but leaves he touches on kindred notions like goodwill and unanimity. There
it as the culminating point of his work. This has been taken ,as an is much good sense in his treatment of the incidental problems of
indication that the Eud.mian Ethics is by far the earlier work, but friendship, like how to return favours and whether one should
it is perhaps best to treat the difference on this point as just another limit the number of one's friends, but it is all very straightforward
illustration of an uncertainty at the heart of Aristotle's thought. and contains little of philosophical importance.
He accepted from Plato that the life of thought was the highest,
but the question still remained what one was to think about. He
had abandoned Plato's Idea of the good, and the alternatives left
were the contemplation of God or scientific and philosophical
enquiry. Aristotle was enough of a theologian, as we know from
Book Lambda of the Metaplqysics, to appreciate the importance of
the former, but his heart was rather in the scientific and logical
studies which form so great a part of his work. There is a magnifi-
cent defence of the study of biology in the, first Book of the D.
Partibus Animalitlm, and it is no surprise that he should have put
in the first place the activity he so much loved.

NOTE ON ARISTOTLE'S TREATMENT OF FRIENDSHIP

Eros or love is mentioned only in passing by Aristotle, but two


books are devoted to friendship in its broadest sense, treated in a
down-to-earth fashion very different from Plato's. There are three
kinds of friendship, aimed respectively at utility, pleasure, and
goodness; A good man loves his friend because he is good and
also wishes him to fare well. All men may have friendships in
which the goal is some profit or pleasure, but only good men can
have the best kind, based on the pursuit of goodness. Aristotle
makes a final break with the tradition that the good man is self-
sufficient by showing that even a good man needs friends to be
happy, because man is a social animal and there is therefore a
natural basis for friendship. Even so, he resorts to some rather
forced arguments to confirm his point, such as that a friend is a
second self, and something that belongs to one, and therefore one
benefits from contemplaring the existence, goodness, and welfare
of one's friend, as one does one's own.
In addition, Aristotle surveys the love of parents and children,

6. E
immoral way of life, Aristippus going as far as to say that if all the
restraints of law were abolished he would still go on living in the
VI. AFTER ARISTOTLE same way. It is not impossible to imagine how he might have
reached this conclusion: we could invent a Socratic dialogue to
show that only virtue gives real pleasure and that therefore virtue
is desirable, but our actual information is scanty.
(i) BACKGROUND At the opposite pole were the Cynics, followers of Diogenes of
As we have seen, Aristotle's ethical teaching, though it claimed Sinope,46 who acquired this name probably because their way of
to be practical, is strikingly 'academic' compared with that of life was thought to resemble that of a dog - onos in Greek.
Socrates. The tradition of such teaching continued in the Academy Exiled from Sinope, he, too, spent much of his life in Athens, and
and the Lyceum, and these must not be entirely ignored because was an outstanding character of his time. Plato is said to have
we know so little of them. It is quite likely that some of the ideas described him as 'Socrates gone mad', for his uncompromising
later adopted by the Stoics, for instance, were first worked out way of life which was indeed a caricature of that of Socrates.
in them. 42 However, the main interest of this period lies in the Taking up the sophists' distinction between nature and conven-
growth of philosophies of a different kind, specially adapted to tion, he led a 'back to nature' campaign that involved a minimum
equip men for life in a rapidly changing world; for it was at this level of subsistence and scorn for all the decencies of life. His ideal
time that the Greek political system collapsed, and the conquests was self-sufficiency, which was to be achieved by such mastery of
of Alexander destroyed the sovereignty of the city-states and made one's feelings and desires that one could face unflinchingly any-
them insignificant parts of much vaster units. The question as to thing fortune might bring, and this mastery was to be obtained by
how a man ought to live assumed a new significance, and recipes a course of severe training in self-discipline. A more positive side
of many kinds were produced to give the answer." Athens, of Cynicism is found in the life of Diogenes' follower Crates,
however, remained the centre even for these new philosophies, whose more cheerful nature enabled him to undertake pastoral
and most of them claimed to be inspired by the spirit of Socrates duties among the Athenians with such success that he was wel-
- a fact which indicates not only the breadth of his views but comed everywhere. He particularly specialised in settling family
also how variously they were understood. quarrels, and probably gave homely advice like the Socrates of
There were two extreme sects which were too odd to have any Xenophon. Exactly how this philanthropic work was connected
very great following, and about which we know comparatively in theory with Cynic self-sufficiency we do not lmow, but we do
little. They are the Cyrenaics and the Cynics. The Cyrenaics know that even Crates did not satisfy Zeno of Citium founder of
derived their name from the fact that their founder, Aristippus, the Stoics for long, and he was driven to think out a new philo-
came from Cyrene, though he was one of the company of Socrates' sophy for himself.
admirers in Athens. 44 He taught that the goal of life was pleasure, Cynicism had a long history after Crates,47 lasting well into
and he and his followers seem to have developed theories about Christian times, but we must leave it now and turn to the two
the nature of pleasure along lines similar to some of those dis- major philosophies of this period, Epicureanism and Stoicism.
cussed by Plato and Aristotle. Accepting that there was a neutral
state between active pleasure and active pain, they taught that only (ii) EPICUREANISM
active pleasure was good and to be pursued. 45 At the same time Epicurus,48 though born on the island of Samos, was an
they did not preach what would normally be regarded as an Athenian citizen, and in 306 set up a school of his own in Athens.
He had early come under the influence of the teachings of Demo- recogrusmg two different kinds of pleasures, active or kinetic
critus, and took over almost the whole of them into his system. pleasures and other stable ones which he called katastematie." He
The greatest difference was one of emphasis. Democritus was held, in fact, that there was a positive feellng attached to those
primarily interested in theory, but Epicurus used theory entirely states in which the body is healthy and unstirred by desire and the
as a guide to practice. According to the atomic theory, the soul mind is tranquil and not affected by emotion. As an animal, man
was mortal and the gods lived remote from the world and took no cannot stay permanently in these states, though the gods can,
interest in the affairs of men. There was no need, therefore, to but he must use desires and active pleasures in such a way as to
fear punishment or hope for reward after death, nor to expect any achieve the maximum possible tranquillity. This can best be done
intervention by the gods during our lifetime. An ethical system by aiming at self-sufficiency, and here Epicurus resembles the
must be concerned solely with how one should live this present Cyuics. Desires can be divided into natural and vain desires, and
life. the natural ones can be subdivided into necessary and unnecessary.
But before we look at Epicurus's moral teaching, a word must The necessary ones are those that conduce to self-preservation, to
be said about one alteration that he made to the system of peace of body and to happiness. Although all pleasures are good,
Democritus. The latter's system was a strictly determinist one, in not all are to be chosen, because some have painful consequences:
which, given the initial position and direction of movement of all on the other hand, we should accept some pains, because they
the atoms, everything else necessarily followed according to the bring great pleasures in their train. In this section, as in parts of
laws of physics. Epicurus introduced the possibility of an atom's Aristotle, we can see the effect of the ambiguity of the word
making an unpredictable swerve at any time, which would bring 'pleasure'. It is pleasurable feellng that is good, but it is pleasure-
about new and unforeseeable relationships.49 This, he claimed, bringing activities that may lead to pain. The upshot is that we
would introduce the possibility of freedom of action, and personal should try to live a frugal life in which necessary desires are
responsibility, so that it would be fair to puuish men for wrong- satisfied, and natural but not necessary desires given some place,
doing. If their actions were entirely determined, punishment while vain desires are outlawed. Such a life would naturally be
would not be justified. Now the swerve clearly will not do the virtuous. Wisdom will be found in a knowledge of Epicurean
job it is intended to do. We cannot be held more responsible for theory, temperance in the restraiuing of desires, and courage in
our actions because they are due to unpredictable swerves in the attaining freedom from fear, but justice is on a different footing.
atoms that compose our minds, than if they were entirely deterc Justice is defended in a sophistic way as being based on the mutual
mined by the motions of unswerving atoms. The interesting agreement of sensible people not to harm each other or to suffer
thing, however, is that Epicurus saw that there was a problem harm in return.
here, and made the first attempt to face up to a strictly determinist In practice, Epicureans led quiet lives in 'friendly societies'
system with the difficulties for theories of responsibility and of their own, for a high value was placed on friendship, partly
punishment that it raises. so for its own sake and partly for the mutual help and support it
Epicurus noted that from birth all living creatures seek pleasure could bring.52
and avoid pain. He concluded that pleasure was the good for
man, as well as for other creatures, but his views on pleasure
were not those of the Cyrenaics. Instead of active pleasure, he (iii) STOICISM

recommended the calm middle state, which he called ataraxia - The Stoics were founded by Zeno of Citium, a city of Cyprus,
which we may perhaps translate 'tranquillity'. This must involve who came to Athens in 310 at the age of twenty-two, and studied

66
there for some years before setting up his own school in 300. He tion which is a commonplace nowadays. One of our difficulties
came under the influence of the genial Cynic Crates, but seems to in interpreting earlier Greek writers is that they tend not to make
have wanted a philosophy with a more complicated theoretical this distinction between moral and non-moral value. And when
basis, and took over many terms and ideas from the other we meet it after studying them, the Stoic distinction itself seems
Athenian schools. His followers are known as Stoics because he odd. But if, as the Stoics did, we put moral virtue squarely in the
taught in a hall called the Stoa Poikile or Painted Porch. It is centre of the picture, it is a perfectly natural development.
difficult to disentangle Zeno's teachings from those oflater Stoics, Another momentous development is the Stoic conception of the
particularly the formidable Chrysippus, because none of their natural equality of men, and of man's subjection to a universal
works have come down to us except in fragments. Further, law. On the one hand, this led to complete determinism: as part of
Stoic ethics are set against a background of Stoic physics which is the natural order man was subject to the laws of nature - in our
a complicated and not entirely coherent structure. 53 modern sense - and his life was completely determined: his only
Like the Epicureans, the Stoics abandoned the view that the choice was between submitting willingly or being compelled. On
soul was incorporeal; the whole Universe was a single substance, the other, Universal Law was something behind and better than
endowed with a soul that was God or reason, which, being the laws of individual states: the Stoic could imagine and aim at an
material, was spread through the universe and made man a being ideal community in which all distinctions of rank or race were
endowed with reason, too. The life according to nature for man abolished. These ideas go beyond anything envisaged by the great
was, therefore the life of reason, and it was man's business to Greek philosophers, and had much influence on Roman law and
adapt himself to the universe around him. Christian thought. 54
It is possible to trace many of the elements of Stoic ethics back It is appropriate that our survey should end, as it began, with
to earlier philosophers. They argued, like Plato and Aristotle, that questions about nature and law. Both are themes that run right
reason set man apart from the animals, and that in the exercise of through Greek ethics. The other great topics are virtue and the
reason lay man's peculiar function and his virtue. Because it good for man, together with careful thinking about the nature
depended on reason, all virtue was one, and at the same time a man and place of pleasure .. All these derive from Socrates, and it is
was either perfectly virtuous or not virtuous at all. This led on impossible to imagine what Greek ethical thinking would have
to the notion of the Stoic Sage, a self-sufficient being resembling been like if Socrates had never existed.
in some ways Aristotle's godlike man of contemplation, and in
some ways the self-sufficient Cynic like Diogenes. The trouble
was that few men could aspire to be sages, and so Stoic morality
tends to operate on two levels. On the one hand is the un-
compromising statement that only virtue is good and only vice is
bad, and all other things, including life and death, are indifferent:
on the other is the admission that among the things that are in-
different some may be 'preferred'. Indifferent things are all those
that may be put to good or bad uses, according to the intention
of the user. But there is still a sense in which beauty is better than
ugliness, and health than disease, though this may not be a moral
sense. This is perhaps the point at which we first meet a distinc-

68
thoughts of the real Socrates (Gigon). (v) Aristotle's evidence is valu-
able (Ross).
NOTES For a detailed survey, see V. de Magalhaes-Vilhena, Le Probleme de
Socrate (paris, 1952).
'4. For a discussion of the historical background of the Delphic
I. Nicomachean Bthics, excerpts from Book IV, chap. ,.
response, see H. W. Parke and D. E. W. Wormell, The Delphic Oracle
z. See L. Pearson, Popular Ethics in Ancient Greece, pp. 199-202. (Oxford, '956), vol. i, pp. 401-5.
3. For a description of Greek city life, see A. Zimmern, The Greek '5. This would be an example of Greek sophrosyne, though not of
Commonwealth (Oxford, 1931). English temperance.
4. Greek religion is a very complicated subject. See, for instance, 16. For details see A. E. Taylor, Socrates, pp. 97-102.
W. K. C. Guthrie, The Greeks and their Gods (London, 1950); M. P. 17. There has been much discussion as to how seriously Socrates'
Nilsson, Greek Piety (Oxford, 1948), and H. J. Rose, Ancient Greek hedonism should be taken. His attitude in the Gorgias is quite different,
Religion (London, 1948). and many have argued that in the Protagoras he is only assuming for the
5. For a long list of similar differences, see the Dissoi Logoi. moment that popular views are true. But I am inclined to think it went
6. See Lovejoy and Boas, Primitivism and Related Ideas in Antiquity, a little deeper than that. For a close study, see J. P. Sullivan, 'The
chap. III. Hedonism in Plato's Protagoras', Phronesis, vi (1961).
7. It is on this point that many who try to reconstruct the arguments 18. The classic paper on Socrates and the soul is J. Burnet, 'The
of the sophists go wrong. Socratic Doctrine of the Soul', Proc. Brit. Academy (1915-16).
8. There is a considerable literature on the Thrasymachus problem: 19. For Plato's own account of this, and other episodes, see his
for a summary, see Cross and WoozIey, Plato's Republic, chap. ii. It is Seventh Letter. See also G. C. Field, Plato and his Contemporaries,
important to remember that there are two different questions: (i) What chap. ii.
was Thrasymachus' own line of argument, if any? and (ii) What is 20. The genuineness of these has been doubted, but it is probable
the point of Thrasymachus' argument as presented by Plato in the that at least the most important ones are authentic.
Repnblic? 21. There is a useful account in W. D. Ross, Plato's Theory of Ideas
9. Some scholars deny that he was a real person, but if so he is (Oxford, 1951), chap. i. Since that was written the position of the
unique in Plato's earlier dialogues. Timaeus has been questioned by G. E. L. Owen, 'The Place of the
10. See G. Calogero, 'Gorgias and the Socratic Principle, NelJlo Sua Tin/aeus in Plato's Dialogues', Class. Quart., N.S. iii (I9J3), but the
Sponte Pecrat', j.H.S., Ixxvii (1957), and A. W. H. Adkins, Merit and general picture is unaltered.
Responsibility (Oxford, 1960), pp. 125-7. 22. Scholars are much divided over whether Plato argued from soul
I I. See G. Vlastos, 'Ethics and Physics in Democritus' , Phil. Rev.,
to state or state to soul. I favour the latter view.
Iiv (1945), and Iv (1946). W. K. C. Guthrie, in A History of Greek 23. There has been much argument about whether Plato regards
Philosoplij, vol. ii, pp. 489-97, expresses doubt about the genuineness of them as parts o,r as aspects of the soul, but clearly his usage is meta-
the ethical fragments of Democritus. phorical, so the question does not arise.
12. Produced in 423. The version we have, however, is a revised 24. See D. A. Rees, 'Bipartition of the Soul in the Early Academy')
version of about 418 which seems to show greater hostility to Socrates. ].I-I.S., !xxvii (1957).
13. There is a vast literature on the Socratic problem. Views include: 25. See D. Sachs, 'A Fallacy in Plato's Republic', Phil. Rev., Ixxii
(i) Plato's conscious aim was to give a faithful portrait of Socrates, and (1963), and R. Demos, 'A Fallacy in Plato's Republic?', Phil. Rev., !xxiii
he largely succeeded in doing so (A. E. Taylor, J. Burnet). (ii) Aristo-
(19 64). . . .
phanes, interpreted correctly, is also a good witness (A. E. Taylor). 26. Hackforth, Plato's Examination of Pleasure, p. 4, thinks It pOSSIble
(iii) Plato tried to give a faithful picture of Socrates, but was too that this view had not yet been formulated and that it is not referred to
powerful a thinker himself to do so. Xenophon, being nnhampered by in the Phi/ebus.
genius, is to be trusted (von Arnim, Gomperz). (iv) The convention 27. Hackforth (ibid.) suggests that it was written between 360 and
of the Socratic dialogue was such that it was used as a vehicle for their 354, when Plato was thoroughly disillusioned with politics after the
own views by thinkers of all kinds, and bore no relation to the actual Sicilian episode.
7'
2.8. Interpretations differ. See Hackforth, pp. 77-78, for another view. 42. For an example, see C. O. Brink, 'Theophrastus and Zeno on
29. See a series of articles by J. Gosling and A. Kenny in Phronesis, Nature in Moral Theory', Phron,sis, i (1956).
iv-vi (1959-6I), and D. Gallop, 'True and False Pleasures', Phil. 43. For a lively description of the background, see A. J. Festugiere,
Quart., x (I960). A defence of Plato's usage in modern terminology is Epicurus and his Gods, chap. i.
in I. Thalberg, 'False Pleasures', J. Philos., lix (1962). 44. For a recent defence of the view that Aristippus the elder was
30. For interesting comments on eros and philia, see A. H. Armstrong indeed the founder of the Cyrenaics, and not his grandson of the
and R. A. Markus, Christian Faith and Greek Philosophy (London, 1960), same name, see P. Merlan, Studies in Epicurus and Aristotle (Weisbaden,
pp.81-93· 19 60), pp. 33-35·
3I. See D. J. Allan, 'Magna MoraNa and Nicomachean Ethics', j.H.S., 45. The evidence for the Cyrenaics has been studied by Erich
!xxvii (1957). Mannebach (Aristippi et Cyrenaicorum Fragmenta, pp. 106 if.), who
32. Some views are: (i) Eudemian much earlier (Jaeger), (ii) Eudemian concludes that the elder Aristippus founded the school, the younger
slightly earlier (Gauthier and Jolif), (iii) Eudemian later than Nico- Aristippus, also known as Metrodldactus, built it up, and Anniceris
machean (D. J. Allan). restored it after a lapse. The elder Aristippus believed that as long as
33. Much of interest on this point can be extracted from G. E. L. they were conscious, men were feeling either pleasure or pain, but the
Owen, 'Logic and Metaphysics in Some Earlier Works of Aristotle' in younger accepted that there was a neutral state. When Epicurus claimed
Aristotle and Plato in the Mid-Fotlrth Century (Goteborg, 1960), ed. that in this state lay man's greatest felicity, Anniceris replied that it was
During and Owen. a state like sleep or death. Pleasure depended on activity. The younger
34. P. Glassen, 'A Fallacy in Aristotle's Argument about the Good', Aristippus had taught that one should seek a life of happiness composed
Phil. Quart., vii (I957), suggests that Aristotle is confused between the of many pleasures and few pains, but the Cynics criticised this on the
good of a man and the goodness of a man, but A. Mace. Armstrong, ground that all lives contained more pain than pleasure, and so the goal
'Aristotle's Conception of Human Good', Phil. Quart., viii (1958), was an impossible one. Hegesias therefore took the line that the goal
replies convincingly. For Aristotle's method see R. Bambrough, should be to avoid pain and trouble, and Anniceris that one should
'Aristotle on Justice: a Paradigm of Philosophy' in New Essays on pursue only the pleasure of the moment.
Plato and Aristotle, ed. R. Bambrough (London, 1965). 46. Antisthenes was widely claimed to be the founder of the Cynics,
35. Nic. Ethics, IIOIa, '5-,8 (Book I, chap. 10). but this seems unlikely. See G. C. Field, Plato and His Contemporaries,
36. The great-souled man is taken very seriously by Dorothea Krook, pp. 160-3·
Three Traditions of Moral Thought (Cambridge, '959), chap. iii. 47. See D. R. Dudley, A History of Cynicism.
37. There is a full study in J. J. Walsh, Aristotle's Conception of 48. For Epicurus's life, see A. J. Festugiere, Epicurus and his Gods,
Moral Weakness. chap. ii, and N. W. De Witt, Epicurus and his Philosophy.
38. See R. Bambrough, 'Socratic Paradox', Phil. Quart., x (1960), 49. The swerve probably had two functions, to allow free will, and
for a discussion of the issues between Socrates and Aristotle. to arrange for an original collision of the atoms. For if all were falling
39. For a clear account of the difficulties of the passage, see Mary in the same direction at the same speed, they could never collide, as
Warnock's review of Gauthier and Jolif's Commentary in Phil. Quart., the system required them to do.
xi (1961), pp. 370-2. For a wider survey of the Practical Syllogism see 50. See P. M. Huby, 'The First Discovery of the Freewill Problem',
D. J. Allan, 'The Practical Syllogism' in Autour d'Aristote, Receuil forthcoming in Philosophy, '967.
rEtudes . .. offert d Monseigneur A. Mansion (Louvain, 1955). See also R. 51. See P. Merlan, Studies in Epicurus and Aristotle, pp. 1-19'
Robinson, 'L'Acrasie, Selon Aristote', Rev. Philosophique, cxlv (1955), 52. For Epicurean friendship, see A. J. Festugiere, Epicurlls and his
and G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford, 1957), pp. 57 if. Gods, chap. iii.
40. For the development of the notion of phronesis from Plato to 53. For a brave attempt to grasp Stoicism, see J. Christensen, An
Aristotle, see W. Jaeger, Aristotle, trans. Robinson 2 , pp. 81-84. Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy (Copenhagen, 1962).
41. An earlier stage in Aristotle's ethical thought is to be found in his 54. For the ethical views of the heretical Stoic, Posidonius, see L.
fragmentary earlier works, particularly the Protrepticus. Unfortunately Edelstein, 'The Philosophical System of Posidonius', Amer. J. Philol.,
space prevents us from studying it here. lvii (1936), pp. 305-16.

73
text and translation of the Nicomachean Ethics, the Eudemian
Ethics, and the Magna MoraNa.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
OTHERS

The Stoic and Epicurean Philosophers, ed. W. J. Oates (New York,


1957), contains translations of Epicurus, Epictetus, Lucre-
(i) TEXTS
tius, and Marcus Aurelius. Epicurus, the Extant Remains, by
GENERAL
C. Bailey (Oxford, 1926), has the text and translation of all
Vogel, C. J. de. Greek Philosophy, A Collection oj Texts, 3 vols. the remains of Epicurus. See also Aristippi et Cyrenaicorum
(Leiden, '950-9). Fragmenta, ed. E. Mannebach (LeidenJKoln, 1961), and
Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, ed. H. von Arrum (Leipzig,
THE SOPHISTS
190 3- 2 4).
Translations of the fragments are to be found in K. Freeman,
Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers (Oxford, 1948), a (ll) OTHER WORKS
translation of the texts in Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, II. i, ed, GENERAL AND BACKGROUND
Diels-Kranz (Berlin, 1961).
Adkins, A. W. II. Merit and Responsibility, A Stu4J in Greek Values
(Oxford, 1960).
PLATO
Dodds, E. R. The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley, '95 I).
There are many English translations, from the five-volume set of Ferguson, J. Moral Values in the Ancient World (London, 1958).
Jowett to the modern paperbacks. We may mention the Greene, W. C. Moira (Harvard, 1948).
Republic, trans. H. D. P. Lee, the Protagoras and Meno, trans. Pearson, L. Popular Ethics in Ancient Greece (Stanford, 1962).
W. K. C. Guthrie, and the Gorgias, trans. W. Hamilton,
Cornford's translation of the Republic (Oxford, 1941), and SOPHISTS
R. Hackforth's Plato's Examination of Pleasure (Cambridge, Lovejoy, A. 0., and Boas, G. Primitivism and Related Ideas in
1945), a translation of the Philebus. The Philebus (London, Antiquity (Baltimore, '935).
1956) and the Lall's (London, '934) have been translated by
A. E. Taylor. Socratic Discourses (London, '954), ed. A. D. SOCRATES
Lindsay, includes several dialogues of Plato and the Socratic
Taylor, A. E. Socrates (London, 1932).
works of Xenophon. The Loeb Classical Library contains
the texts of Plato's dialogues in several volumes, with PLATO
English translations facing.
Crombie, 1. M. An Examination oj Plato's Doctrines, vol. i, Plato
on Man and Society (London, 1962).
ARISTOTLE
Cross, R. c., and Woozley, A. D. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical
The Nicomachean Ethics has been translated many times. There is Commentary (London, '964).
a paperback by J. A. K. Thompson, and others by J. Warring- Gould, J. The Development oj Plato's Ethics (Cambridge, 1955).
ton and W. D. Ross. The Loeb Classical Library contains the Grube, G. M. A. Plato's Thought (London, '9350 1958).

74 75
Hall, R. W. Plato and the Individual (The Hague, '96,).
Murphy, N. R. The Interpretation of Plato's Republic (Oxford, 1951).
Shorey, P. What Plato Said (Chicago, "9, ,).
Taylor, A. E. Plato, The Man and His Work (London, 1952).
See also G. C. Field below.

ARISTOTLE

Allan, D. J. The Philosop", of Aristotle (Oxford, 1952).


Aubenque, P. La Prudence chez Adstote (Paris, 196,).
Gauthier, R. A. La Morale d' Aristote (paris, 1958).
Jaeger, W. Aristotle, trans. R. Robinson (Oxford, 1948).
Ross, W. D. Aristotle (London, "92,).
Taylor, A. E. Aristotle (London, '9II-15).
Walsh, J. J. Aristotle's Conception of Moral Weakness (New York,
"9 6,).

OTHERS

Bevan, E. Stoics and Sceptics (Oxford, 191,).


De Witt, N. W. Epicurus and His Philosop", (Minneapolis, 1954).
Dudley, D. R. A History of Cynicism (London, 1937).
Festugiere, A. J. Epicurus and his Gods (Oxford, 1955).
Field, G. C. Plato and his Contemporaries (London, 1948).
Hicks, R. D. Stoic and Epicurean (London, 1910).

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen