Sie sind auf Seite 1von 6

Proceedings of the 9th Vienna International Conference on

Proceedings
Mathematical
MathematicalofModelling
the 9th Vienna International Conference on
Modelling
Proceedings
Mathematical
Vienna, ofModelling
the 9th Vienna International Conference on
Vienna, Austria, February
Austria, February 21-23,
21-23, 2018
2018 Available online at www.sciencedirect.com
Mathematical Modelling
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018
ScienceDirect
IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504
A
A mathematical model of modelling –
A mathematical
mathematical model model of of modelling
modelling –

epistemology
Aepistemology
mathematicaland and model natural
natural sciences
of modelling
sciences –
epistemology and natural sciences
epistemology and natural sciences
Dirk Langemann ∗∗ Cordula Reisch ∗∗ Janina Dierkes ∗∗
Dirk Langemann ∗ Cordula Reisch ∗ Janina Dierkes ∗
Dirk Langemann Cordula Reisch Janina Dierkes
Dirk
∗ Langemann ∗ Cordula Reisch ∗ Janina Dierkes ∗
∗ Inst. Computational Mathematics, Technische Universität
∗ Inst. Computational
Inst.
Computational
Mathematics, Technische Universität
Mathematics, Technische Universität
Braunschweig, Germany (e-mail: d.langemann@tu-bs.de).
∗Braunschweig, Germany (e-mail: d.langemann@tu-bs.de).
Inst. Computational
Braunschweig, Germany Mathematics, Technische Universität
(e-mail: d.langemann@tu-bs.de).
Braunschweig, Germany (e-mail: d.langemann@tu-bs.de).
Abstract:
Abstract: Here, Here, a a theoretical
theoretical framework
framework is is proposed
proposed whichwhich enables
enables us us to
to formalize
formalize the the process
process
Abstract:
of mathematical Here, modelling
a theoretical andframework
to discuss is the
proposed which
recurrent enableswhether
question us to formalize
a chosen themodel
process is
of mathematical
Abstract: Here, modelling
a theoretical and to
frameworkdiscuss the
is the recurrent
proposed which question
enables whether a
us to formalize chosen model
themodel
process is
of mathematical
appropriate, accuratemodelling and
or comprehensiveto discuss
comprehensive with recurrent
respect to a question
certain whether
application. a chosen
Thereto, episte- is
appropriate,
of mathematical accuratemodellingor and to discusswith the respect to
recurrent a certain
question application.
whether a Thereto,
chosen episte-
model is
appropriate,
mological accurate
problems in or comprehensive
philosophy are with respect
separated from to a certain
modelling application.
questions in the Thereto,sciences.
natural episte-
mological problems
appropriate, accurate in philosophy
or are separated
comprehensive with from modelling
respect to a certainquestions in the natural
application. Thereto, sciences.
episte-
mological
The problems in philosophy are separated from modelling questions in the natural sciences.
The background
background
mological problems
of
of inthe
the investigations
investigations lies
lies in
in life-science
life-science applications,
applications, their
their inherent
inherent qualitative
qualitative
The
and background
quantitative of thephilosophy
investigations
uncertainties and aretheir
separated from unclear
liesoftentimes
in life-science modelling questions
applications,
hierarchy their
of in
the the natural
inherent
mechanisms sciences.
qualitative
under
and quantitative
The background uncertainties
of the and their
investigations liesoftentimes
in unclear
life-science hierarchy their
applications, of theinherent
mechanisms under
qualitative
and quantitative
consideration. The uncertainties
The resulting and
resulting description their
description of oftentimes
of mathematical unclear
mathematical modelling hierarchy
modelling as of the
as aa general mechanisms
general approximation
approximationunder
consideration.
and quantitative uncertainties and their oftentimes unclear hierarchy of the mechanisms under
consideration.
problem is still The resultingrich
sufficiently description
to study of mathematical
model families, modelling as
inheritance of amodel
general approximation
properties, model
problem is stillThe
consideration. sufficiently
resulting rich to study of
description model families, inheritance
mathematical modelling of amodel
as general properties, model
approximation
problem is stillminimal
identification, sufficiently richand
models to study
the model families, inheritance of model properties, model
identification,
problem minimal
is stillminimal
sufficiently models and
richand the optimality
to study optimality of
of models
model families, models under
under different
inheritance different
of model
objective
objective
properties,
functions.
functions.
model
identification, models the optimality of models under different objective functions.
© 2018, IFAC (International
identification, minimal models Federation
and the of Automatic
optimality Control)
of modelsHostingunder by Elsevier
different Ltd. All rightsfunctions.
objective reserved.
Keywords:
Keywords: Model Model selection,
selection, model model families,
families, reduction
reduction of of complexity,
complexity, optimality,
optimality, sensitivity,
sensitivity,
Keywords:
approximate Model
analysis,selection, model families,
epistemology, reduction
life-science of complexity, optimality, sensitivity,
applications.
approximate
Keywords: Model analysis, epistemology,
selection, life-science
model families, applications.
reduction of complexity, optimality, sensitivity,
approximate analysis, epistemology, life-science applications.
approximate analysis, epistemology, life-science applications.
1.
1. INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION fulfilling
fulfilling thethe hypothesis,
hypothesis, cf. cf. Grimm
Grimm (1994),
(1994), and and of of course,
course,
1. INTRODUCTION fulfilling
unsuccessful
unsuccessful the hypothesis,
models
models are
are cf.
seldom
seldom Grimm (1994),
published.
published. and of course,
Hypothesis-free
Hypothesis-free
While 1. INTRODUCTIONmodelling from a unsuccessful fulfilling the hypothesis,
models arelikecf.inGrimm
seldom (1994),
published. and of course,
Hypothesis-free
While thinking
thinking aboutabout mathematical
mathematical modelling from a modelling modelling approaches
approaches like in proteomics
proteomics or genomics
genomics lead
orHypothesis-free lead
While
rather thinking
abstract about mathematical
viewpoint, the community modelling
of researchers unsuccessful
from a modelling
to very models
approaches
large systems. are seldom
like
The in published.
proteomics
restriction or
to genomics
these systems lead
rather abstract
While thinking viewpoint,
about the community
mathematical of researchers
modelling from a to very large systems. The restriction to these systems
rather abstractsciences
viewpoint, theto of researchers modelling approaches like in proteomics or genomics lead
in
in the
the natural
rather natural
abstractlikesciences
viewpoint,
seems
seems thetotocommunity
be
be convinced
convinced
community
that
that theo-
of researcherstheo- to very large
contains
contains systems.too.
aa hypothesis,
hypothesis, TheThey
too. restriction
They use
use rather
ratherto these
strongsystems
strong simpli-
simpli-
in
riesthe
in natural
physics sciences
classical seems mechanics be convinced
or that theo- contains
thermodynamics to very large
fications a
like systems.too.
hypothesis,
a Boolean TheThey restriction
description. useIn ratherto these
general, strong
they systems
simpli-
are
ries
in in
the physics
natural like classical
sciences mechanics or thermodynamics fications like a Boolean description. In general, they are ex-
ex-
ries in physics
describe
describe the
the like
reality
reality in seems
classical
in a good
a good tomanner
mechanics be convinced
manner or and
and thatantheo-
thermodynamics
that
that an ap-
contains
ap- fications
tremely a hypothesis,
like a Boolean
expensive, and too.
the They
description. use
distinctionInrather
general,
between strong
they simpli-
are ex-
causation
ries in physics like classical mechanics or thermodynamics tremely
fications expensive,
like a Boolean and the distinction between causation
describe
propriatethe
propriate reality
choice
choice of in a good
of model
model manner generates
components
components and that aaangood
generates ap- tremely
good expensive,
and correlation
and correlation anddescription.
remains
remains the distinction
problematic,
problematic,
In cf.
general,
cf.between
Leonelli
Leonelli
they are ex-
causation
(2014).
(2014).
describe
propriate
approximationthe reality
choice of of
the inreality.
model a good manner
components
The parallel and that aangood
generates
development ap-
of tremely
and expensive,
correlation and the
remains distinctioncf.
problematic, between
Leonelli causation
(2014).
approximation
propriate choice of themodelreality. The parallel development of The mathematical model of modelling presented here,
approximation
physics
physics and
and of of
the reality.
mathematics
mathematics
components
over
overThe parallel
centuries
centuries
generates
development
has
has tought
tought
a good of and
the
the The correlation
mathematical remainsmodel problematic,
of modelling cf. Leonelli
presented (2014).
here,
approximation
physics
researchers’ of the reality.
and community
mathematics over
about The parallel
centuries
the development
has
hierarchy tought
of of The
the
mecha- mathematical
provides
provides a conceptual
a conceptual model
framework
frameworkof modelling
to discuss
to discuss presented
the here,
the occurring
occurring
researchers’ community about the hierarchy of mecha- The
the provides mathematical model of modelling presented here,
physics
researchers’
nisms
nisms under
and mathematics
under community
consideration
consideration
over
about
in centuries
the hierarchy
in general
general and
and in
has atought
in a of mecha-
particular
particular questionsaa like
questions
provides
conceptual
like model
conceptual
frameworkaccuracy
model selection,
selection,
framework
to discuss
accuracy and
and
to consideration
discuss
thesensitivity,
occurring
sensitivity,
thesensitivity,
occurring
researchers’
nisms under
mathematical community
consideration
model, cf. about
in
Wigner the
general hierarchy
(1960). and in a of mecha-
particular questions
the hierarchy
the hierarchy like ofmodel
ofmodel selection,
mechanisms
mechanisms under
underaccuracy and
consideration and
and thethe
mathematical model,
nisms under consideration cf. Wigner
in general(1960). and in a particular optimality questions
the hierarchy like
of of selection,
mechanisms
models under underaccuracy
different and
consideration
objective sensitivity,
and the
functions.
mathematical model, cf. Wigner (1960). optimality
the hierarchy of models under
of mechanisms different objective
under consideration functions.
and the
Already
Already in
mathematical in life sciences
life model, like
sciencescf.like biology
Wigner
biology and medicine
(1960).
and medicine with with the
the optimality of models under different objective functions.
Already
growing in
use life
of sciences
mathematical like biology
and and medicine methods
computational Until
with the optimality
Until now,
now, most
of
most work
models
work on
under
on the
the modelling
different
modelling process
objective
process originates
functions.
originates
growing in
Already use of sciences
mathematical and computational methods the Until now, most work studies on the modelling process originates
growing
in the
in uselife
the recent
recent of years, it like
mathematical
years, it is not
is
biology
not andclear
clear
and medicine
computational
whether
whether the
with
themethods
present
present
from
from epistemological
Until epistemological
now, most work studies
on the
with
with aa philosophical
modelling philosophical
process
focus,
focus,
originates
growing
in the use
recent of mathematical
years, it is not andclear computational
whether the methods
present from
cf. epistemological
Godfrey-Smith studies
(2003) and with a
Machamer philosophical
and focus,
Silberstein
modelling
modelling techniques
techniques are
are appropriate
appropriate for
for a
a description
description of
of cf.
from Godfrey-Smith
epistemological (2003)
studies and Machamer
with a and
philosophical Silberstein
focus,
in the recent
modelling
systems
systems related
related
years,
techniques
to
to life.
itOn
life.are
is the
not clear
Onappropriate
the oneone hand,
whether
hand,forthere the
a description
there is
is a
present
a consid-
consid-of cf. Godfrey-Smith
(2002).
(2002).
cf.
The modelling
The
Godfrey-Smith
modelling(2003)
(2003)
and Machamer
process
process itself is
itself
and Machamer
and Silberstein
is rarely
rarely discussed
discussed
and Silberstein
modelling
systems
erate techniques
related
qualitative to life.
and are
On appropriate
the
quantitative one hand,for a
there
uncertainty description
is a
about consid-of
sys- (2002).
from
from a
a The
natural
natural modelling
scientific
scientific process
viewpoint.
viewpoint. itself Of
Ofis rarely
course,
course, discussed
there
there areare
erate qualitative
systems related toand
life. quantitative
On the one uncertainty
hand, there about
is a sys- from
consid- (2002).
numerous The
a natural modelling
scientific
collections of process
viewpoint.
mathematicalitselfOfismodels
rarely and
course, discussed
theremod-are
erate qualitative
tems from
from life-science and quantitative
life-science applications.
applications. They uncertainty
They areare less about
less accessiblesys-
accessible from numerous collections of mathematical models and mod-
tems sys- numerous a natural scientific
collections viewpoint.
of mathematical Of course, and theremod-are
erate
tems
for qualitative
from
for experiments
experiments
and quantitative
life-science
than applications.
than systems
systems from fromThey
uncertainty lessabout
are and
physics
physics and
accessible
engineer-
engineer- elling
elling
elling techniques
numeroustechniques like
like Murray
collections Murray (2008). models
(2008).
of mathematical models and mod-
tems
for from life-science
than applications.
systems They
from physics are less accessible
andquantified. techniques like Murray (2008).
engineer- The paper is organized as follows: Sec. 2 separates philo-
ing.experiments
ing.
for
Most
Most of of the
experiments
system
the than
system parameters
parameters
systems from
are
are rarely
rarely
physics quantified.
engineer- elling
anddescription techniques
The paper like Murray
is organized (2008).
as follows: Sec. 2 separates philo-
ing.
The Most
conceptsof the andsystem parameters
quantities in the aresystem
rarely quantified. The paper
sophical is organized
problems from as follows: questions
modelling Sec. 2 separatesbefore philo-3
The
ing.
The
concepts
Most
concepts
are formed
formed forof theand
and
quantities
system parameters
quantities
for requirements
requirements of
in
in
of the
the
the
system
are rarely
system
the particular
particular life
description
quantified.
description
life science, sophical
The
science, sophical paper problems
is from
organized modelling
as follows: questions
Sec. before Sec.
2 aseparates Sec.
philo- 3
are formalizes problems
the from
concepts modelling
of a system questions
and beforefor
model Sec. 3
this
The concepts and quantities in the system description formalizes the concepts of a system and a model for this
are
and formed
and
are usuallyfor
usually
formed
requirements
they
they
for
are
are not
requirements
of the particular
not approved
approved for
for a
of the particular simple math- sophical
life science,
a simple math-
life science,
formalizes
system. problems
system. General
the concepts
General
from modelling
model of a system
model properties
properties
questions beforefor
andreducibility,
like
like
a model
reducibility,
Sec.this3
sepa-
sepa-
and usually
ematical they
description. are not
The approved
hierarchy for
of a
the simple
mechanisms math- formalizes
system.
rability the
General concepts
model of a system
properties and
like a model
reducibility, for this
sepa-
ematical
and
ematical
under usuallydescription.
they arewith
description.
consideration
The hierarchy for
not respect
The approved
hierarchy to
of the
their
mechanisms
a importance
of the simple
mechanisms math-or rability and
system. and
General
causal
causal
model
dependences
dependences
properties
are
arelike
discussed
discussed
reducibility,
in
in Sec.
Sec.
sepa-
4,
4,
under consideration with respect to their importance or rability
where
where a
a and causal
transport
transport dependences
equation
equation is
is are discussed
constructed
constructed as
as in
a
a Sec.
model-
model- 4,
ematical
under description.
consideration
sensitivity is oftentimes Theunknown.
with hierarchy
respect to of theimportance
their
Furthermore, mechanisms
we or where
are rability and causal dependences are discussed in Sec. 4,
sensitivity is oftentimes unknown. Furthermore, we are a transport
system-link
system-link for
for exact
exactequation
models.
models. is Then
constructed
Then Sec. 55as
Sec. a model-
deals
deals with
with
under
sensitivity
faced consideration
to theis occurence
oftentimeswith of respect
unknown.
several toFurthermore,
their importance
redundant we are
mechanisms or system-link
where a transport
for exact equation
models. is Then
constructed asdeals
Sec. 5models a model-
with
faced to
sensitivity theis occurence
oftentimes of several
unknown. redundant
Furthermore, mechanisms
we are the
the determination
determination of
of parameters
parameters in
in inexact
inexact models from
from
faced
and to the occurence
and feedback loops
loops in of several
in living systems, redundant
cf.
cf. Lazebnikmechanisms
(2002).
(2002). the system-link
determination
an abstract
abstract for exact
point models.
of view.
of parameters Then
Finally, in Sec. Sec.
inexact 5models
deals some
with
from
faced
and
On
feedback
toother
the occurence
feedback
the loops
hand, in
living
living
there
systems,
of isseveral
systems,
an redundant
enormous cf.
Lazebnik
mechanisms
Lazebnik
amount of(2002).
data, an
the determination point of
of view.
parametersFinally, in Sec.
inexact 66 presents
presents
models some
from
On the other hand, there is an enormous amount of an abstract
extensions to point of
experiments view.
data, extensions to experiments and random influence. Finally,
and random Sec. 6 presents
influence. some
and
On
a feedback
the loops
other hand, in living
there systems,
is an enormous cf. Lazebnik
amount of(2002). an abstracttopoint
data, extensions of view.and Finally, Sec.influence.
6 presents some
a huge
On huge
the
number
number
other
of
of experimental
hand, experimental
there is an
outputs
outputs and
enormous and a
a widespread
amount widespread
of data,
experiments random
aexpert
huge
expert number
knowledge
knowledge of experimental
about diverse
about diverseoutputs outputs and
sub-systems,
sub-systems, a widespread
which
which wait wait extensions
2. to experiments
2. EPISTEMOLOGICAL QUESTIONS AND
EPISTEMOLOGICAL and random
QUESTIONS influence. AND
a huge
expert
for number
knowledge
mathematical of modeling
experimental
about diverse and for the and a widespread
sub-systems,
extraction which of wait
more 2. EPISTEMOLOGICAL
NATURAL QUESTIONS AND
SCIENCES
for
expertmathematical
knowledge modeling
aboutsystems, and
diverse for the extraction
sub-systems, which of more
wait 2. EPISTEMOLOGICALNATURAL SCIENCES
QUESTIONS AND
for mathematical
structure
structure in modeling
in life-science
life-science and for
systems, cf. the
cf. extraction
Ingalls
Ingalls (2013).of
(2013). more
There-
There- NATURAL SCIENCES
for
fore,mathematical
structure in
hypothesis modeling
life-science
driven and for
systems,
modeling cf.
is the extraction
Ingalls
oftentimes (2013). ofThere-
more If we accept thatNATURAL
confronted SCIENCES
fore, hypothesis
structure driven modeling
in life-science systems, is oftentimes
cf. Ingalls confronted
(2013). There- If we accept that there is something outside
there is something outside ourselves
ourselves or or
fore,
with hypothesis
the critique driven
that themodeling
particular is oftentimes
model is confronted
built just for If we
outside accept
our that there
consciousness, is something
then we outside
call this ourselves
exterior or
the
with the
fore, the critique
hypothesis that the particular model is built just for outside our consciousness, then we call this exterior the
with critique driven
that the modeling
particular is oftentimes
model is built confronted If we accept
just for outside that there is something
our consciousness, then we call outside ourselvesthe
this exterior or
with the critique that the particular model is built just for outside our consciousness, then we call this exterior the
Copyright
Copyright © 2018
2018 IFAC
© 2018, IFAC 1
1 Hosting by Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
2405-8963 ©
Copyright IFAC (International Federation of Automatic Control)
© 2018 IFAC 1
Peer review under responsibility
Copyright © 2018 IFAC of International Federation of Automatic
1 Control.
10.1016/j.ifacol.2018.03.084
Proceedings of the 9th MATHMOD
500
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018 Dirk Langemann et al. / IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504

reality. The first difficulty in making any assertation about


the reality lies in the analytic statement that we do not
know any thing what is not real – at least in the sense that theories
we have a notation and an imagination of that thing.
Nevertheless, the natural sciences describe the world by
”real” reality
theories. These theories are the a-priori knowledge to de-
velope models on their base. Theories theirselves consist model
of widely accepted models which are connected to each hope Ẏ = G(Y )
other by common structures and additionally of idealiza- Ẋ = F (X) constructed
tions and abstractions of these models. We hope that our reality
theories and models describe the reality, but there is no Ẋ = F (X) concept
selection
concept
answer whether they do so or not, cf. BonJour (1988). formation

Since the question for the relation between the reality and
our theories and models cannot be answered, the natural
sciences investigate rather a construction of the reality observations and measurements
ϕ : X �→ Y, ψ : X �→ Z ≈ χ(Y )
than the reality itself. This constructed reality contains
some very fundamental assumptions which defy any prov-
ability: The constructed reality is deterministic (even if Fig. 1. Reality, constructed reality, theory and model. The
it is sometimes appropriately described by stochastics), relation between reality and constructed reality seems
it obeys superordinate laws, and it is quantifiable if ap- to be a genuinely philosophical problem (dashed lines)
propriate concepts are chosen. Furthermore, we assume whereas the relation between model, theory and con-
that causality holds true in the constructed world (as a structed reality (solid lines) is still sufficiently rich.
whole, not necessarily in a sub-system with exogeneous in-
fluences), and that temporal inductivity allows us to make observations and measurements say anything about the
predictions about future states of the constructed reality. reality or only about the constructed reality. Using their
We resume the basic assumption of science that reality basic assumptions, the natural sciences act as if the obser-
can be described by science. Of course, this assumption, vations and measurements would be real. Therefore, Fig. 1
already due to its reflexity, cannot be proven by exper- shows two ways how models are linked with observations,
iments like no experiments are imaginable which would which conform if the coincidence of reality and constructed
support or disprove the single fundamental assumptions. reality is assumed.

The denomination of the constructed reality separates Finally, the generation of knowledge in the natural sciences
two completely different questions. The first philosophical can be regarded as the seek for consistency within a
question is whether it is possible to make any statement for feedback loop between the constructed reality, theories and
the relation between the reality and our constructed real- their concepts and models. Let us see, that the remaining
ity, and if so, what kind of statements. The second question how-questions of modelling are still sufficiently numerous
is how the natural sciences describe the reality under the to form a rich and interesting theory.
assumption that the reality and the constructed reality
are conformable or at least closely related. Since nearly 3. FORMALIZATION OF THE MODELLING
ever, the natural sciences consider their how-question in PROCESS
a manner if the answer to the philosophical whether-
question would be yes. The time-dependent states of the constructed reality as
described in Sec. 2 may be quantified in an object X.
Example: The radio in Lazebnik (2002) is an example for
In general, the system state X = X(t) ∈ U from a
a constructed reality or a part of it. It is built by engineers
vector space U may contain scalar variables, functions
and its functionality is deterministic and detectable. It
or random variables belonging to the different concepts
fulfils all above assumptions. But, the models presented
of the constructed reality. Conditions like positivity may
there are absolutely unhelpful to detect the superordinate
limit the admissible system states to X ∈ Uadm ⊆ U.
electrical laws and the functionality of the radio.
Due to shortness, here we restrict ourselves to vectors
Example: A beaker glass with chemical reagents contains a X ∈ Rn = U , and each component Xi ∈ R quantifies a
variety of intermediate reaction products. The description certain but maybe unknown concept.
of the chemical reactions selects certain known reagents
The rate of change of the system states is denoted by
and forms concepts which include similar sub-forms. There
is the belief that the reactions obey some kinetic laws and Ẋ which can be regarded as time derivative. In more
that models using the formed concepts can say something general settings an appropriate definition for the change
about the reality inside the glass. rate of system states is needed. The superordinated laws
in the deterministic constructed reality are collected in
Fig. 1 gives a scheme of the interactions between reality, the function F : Uadm → Uch where Uch is a suitable
constructed reality, theories and models. Additionally to space for the changes. In the discrete case U = Rn , we can
the named concepts, the ideas of observations and mea- use Uch = Rn . Together with initial conditions, we note
surements are affiliated. Both, observations and measure- the governing equation of the constructed reality, which is
ments are strongly affected by our theories and the selected hereinafter called the system, by
concepts. Therefore in epistemology, it is critical whether
Ẋ = F (X), X(0) = X ini . (1)

2
Proceedings of the 9th MATHMOD
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018 Dirk Langemann et al. / IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504 501

In the case U = Rn , Eq. (1) is a system of ordinary We note this situation for a model depending on param-
differential equations. Possible algebraic constraints can eters collected in a. The idea is that the structure of the
be differentiated, comp. index of differential algebraic model equation is fixed in the function G and that the pa-
equations. Strong causality of the system in Eq. (1) is rameters a still have to be adapted. Again, in the discrete
assured by the Lipschitz continuity of the function F , cf. case, we simply use a ∈ Rq , and the function G = Ga as
Perko (2000). Due to the temporal inductivity, the solution well as the flux Γ = Γa depend on the parameter a. We
of Eq. (1) would allow predictions if F and X ini would be note the modelling task in finding a tuple (ϕ, Ga , a) so that
known. In the following, we regard system (1) as existent Φ(t)
but unknown. The modelling task consists in finding U: X ini −−−−−−−−→ X(t)
models providing good approximations of the system. The ↓ϕ 
modelling task can be seen as abstract modelling goal, Γa (t) 
V: Y ini −→ Y (t) ψ (4)
cf. Sira-Ramı́rez et al. (2014), althought the concept of a 
modelling goal is at least debatable on an abstract level. ↓χ
A model is given by a vector Y = Y (t) ∈ Vadm ⊆ V W: Z(t) ≈ ψ(X(t))
quantifying the model states and by a function G : is approximately commutative after an identification of the
Vadm → Vch mapping the model states to their changes. parameter a. This situation will be particularly discussed
We get the model equation in Sec. 5 under the aspect of parameter and model identi-
Ẏ = G(Y ), Y (0) = Y ini . (2) fication.
Let us remark that there is no need for the assumption
that the concepts describing the model state in Y have 4. NON-PARAMETRIC MODELS
anything to do with the concepts in the system states X.
In fact, it is thinkable that a model uses concepts which Here, we discuss the consequences of the above formaliza-
are completely unrelated to concepts from the constructed tion of the modelling process. We restrict ourselves to the
reality. By the way, similar notations are used in control case U = Rn which implies V = Rm and W = Rr with
theory, cf. Sontag (1998), but here, no control is included. r ≤ m ≤ n. Then Eq. (1) is a system of ordinary differ-
ential equations and we can apply the related theory. The
The relation between the model to the system is a link-
extension of the following investigations to more general
function ϕ : Uadm → Vadm with ϕ : X → Y . If Vadm
states X requires an extension of the used concepts like
is assumed to be a domain of validity of the model, we
use the same notation Uadm for related admissible system the change Ẋ and the gradient ∇F etc. but it works with
states without loss of generality. In the case U = Rn , we analogous ideas.
use V = Rm with m ≤ n. First, we consider the adjacency structure of the gradient
ini
We introduce the fluxes Φ(t) : X → X(t) and Γ(t) : A = ∇F ∈ Rn×n which depends on X in general. The
Y ini → Y (t) for system (1) and model (2), respectively. introduction of Eq. (1) as constructed reality allows us
Usually, we know the flux Γ by solving the model equation to define a causal dependence of the component Xi on
and use Γ for making predictions, and we do not know the the component Xj by a non-vanishing entry Aij (X) =
flux Φ. The modelling task is now formulated to find a pair 0, because that means that a change of Xj implies a
(ϕ, G) so that the diagramme change of Ẋi . Thus, it is possible to distinguish causation
from correlation which would not be possible if we would
Φ(t)
U: X ini −−−−−−−−→ X(t) consider the “real” reality only.
↓ϕ ↓ϕ (3)
Γ(t)
The adjacency structure of the gradient ∇F depends on
V: Y ini −−−→ Y (t) ≈ ϕ(X(t)) the choice of the concepts in the state X. A coordinate
is approximately commutative. Let us mention that the transformation, i. e. a bijective σ : X → X  with X  = σX
modelling task becomes an approximation problem to an and X = σ −1 X  , which coincides with a transformation of
unknown system equation. The use of the constructed the concepts in the system states, gives
world allows us to study the modelling task while we Ẋ  = ∇σ(X)Ẋ = ∇σ(σ −1 X  )F (σ −1 X  ) = F  (X  ). (5)
presume some knowledge about the system (1). Without
Now, the same system as in Eq. (1) is described by another
the system which represents the constructed reality, it is
function F  and in different concepts in X  . Eq. (5) is
impossible to discuss the relation of the model in Eq. (2)
already a model (σ, F  ) of system (1) with Y = X  and
to something real simply because there would not be any
G = F  . Of course, this is a model without any reduction
information about anything real.
of complexity.
We distinguish the concepts occurring in the model from
The changed adjacency structure of ∇F  compared to
the quantities which can be measured because oftentimes
∇F reminds us to theories where separated concepts and
only derived quantities Z = χ(Y ) ∈ W = χ(V) are
single-cause explanation are preferred. We can say that
accessible for measurements. Again, in the discrete case,
theories try to choose concepts so that the mechanisms
the vector space of the measured values is W = Rr with
have separated causes and effects and therefore the gradi-
r ≤ m. Now, a measurement or an observation method is ent ∇F  has a simple adjacency structure.
a map ψ : Uadm → W. Consequently, we cannot check
the approximation Y (t) ≈ ϕ(X(t)) in Eq. (3) but only the Let us note the choice of k components described by a
proximity of the measurements χ(Y (t)) ≈ ψ(X(t)) can be tuple K = {i1 , . . . , ik } ⊆ {1, . . . , n} from the state X by
achieved. the projection π ∈ Rk×n : X → (Xi1 , . . . , Xik )T .

3
Proceedings of the 9th MATHMOD
502
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018 Dirk Langemann et al. / IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504

We call system Eq. (1) reducible if there is a set K with modelling, we are usually seeking for a pair (ϕ, G) fulfilling
k < n and a function F π so that Eq. (7).
F π (πX) = π Ẋ, (6) We prove an interesting fact about the characteristics of
i. e. the components πX form a sub-system of Eq. (1) the transport equation (7) for given G.
which is independent from the other components. We Theorem 3. The characteristics of Eq. (7) are the trajec-
call a system separable if there is a set K so that the tories of system (1). In particular, a solution ϕ of Eq. (7)
system is reducible with respect to K and with respect exists as long as the trajectories do not intersect to each
to {1, . . . , n}\K. A separable system decomposes into two other in the phase space.
completely independent sub-systems.
A system which is reducible after the application of a Proof. With f (∇ϕ, ϕ, X) = ∇ϕ · F (X) − G(ϕ) = 0, we
coordinate transformation σ is called σ-reducible, and find the characteristics ξ = ξ(s) ∈ Rn by
respectively σ-separable systems are separable after the ∂f (∇ϕ, ϕ, ξ)
ξ  (s) = = F (ξ(s)),
application of σ. ∂(∇ϕ)
The concept formation in theories can be seen as an ap- cf. Evans (2010), what is just the system in Eq. (1).
propriate choice of the transformation σ. Let us remark
That means that any model function G belongs to a –
that many classical theories in physics have ordered the
possibly rather crazy – link-function ϕ in some initial time
concepts. Physical laws and relations are oftentimes ba-
interval. For example, a harmonic oscillator has the time
sically mono-causal. Life-science applications mainly use
t as exact model Y = t with G(Y ) = 1 for all Y as long
concepts which have approved for biological or medical
as t is smaller than a period of the oscillator, because the
considerations, and they frequently lead to multi-causal
map ϕ from the system states X(t) ∈ R2 at the particular
dependencies in mathematical models of these applica-
trajectory to the time t is bijective. Okay, this seems to be
tions.
a rather useless model. But by a similar argument, we see
Definition. The model (ϕ, G) is called exact if it makes that every one-dimensional system (1) has exact models
the diagramme in Eq. (3) commutative by Y (t) = ϕ(X(t)). (ϕ, G) with an arbitrary bijective ϕ : R1 → R1 because
Eq. (7) transforms into an ordinary differential equation
There is a formulation with the fluxes, too. An exact model which can be solved by separation of variables. Similarly,
obeys Γ(t)Y ini = ϕ(Φ(t)X ini ) for all admissible initial we see that every Eq. (2) with m = 1 is a model for every
states X ini . We get the commutativity Γ ◦ ϕ = ϕ ◦ Φ. one-dimensional system in Eq. (1).
Theorem 1. An exact model fulfils the transport equation
∇ϕ(X)F (X) = G(ϕ(X)) for all X ∈ Uadm . (7) Linear case. In the case F (X) = AX with A ∈
Rn×n , the spectral decomposition A = SΛS −1 grounds
Proof. The proof consists in the application of the chain a transformation σ : X → X  = S −1 X. If the matrix
rule to Y = ϕ(X), namely Ẏ = ∇ϕ(X)Ẋ = ∇ϕ(X)F (X) A is diagonalizable, then the system Ẋ = AX is σ-
and Ẏ = G(Y ) = G(ϕ(X)). separable, and it separates into the spectral components
by Ẋ  = ΛX  , i. e. Y = π{i} σX ∈ R1 with ϕ = π{i} ◦ σ
Let us remark that exact models are rare in practical provides an exact model for every projection π{i} to a
applications. Limit cases are the null model ϕ : X → single component i ∈ {1, . . . , n}. If A is a single Jordan
0 = Y ∈ R1 with every function G with G(0) = 0 and box, then Λ is reducible by cutting off the lower right sub-
the full model ϕ = id. with X = Y . Also, every bijective matrix, and every Y = π{i,...,n} σX ∈ Rn−i+1 generates an
map ϕ = σ generates an exact model with G = F  , comp. exact model. Of course, linear combinations of these linear
Eq. (5). exact models are linear exact models, too.
An interesting class of exact models with m = 1 are If the link-function ϕ is also linear, i. e. it is a projection
conservation laws, comp. Noether’s theorem, cf. Scheck π = P ∈ Rm×n , then the model is also linear, namely
(2010). Then Y is the conserved quantity and it holds G(Y ) = BX with BP X = P AX. This condition assures
true G(Y ) = 0 for all feasible values of Y ∈ Vadm . Also the commutativity of the diagramme in Eq. (3).
reducible systems have exact models:
Let us remark that linear models can have exact models
Theorem 2. A σ-reducible system with respect to the with non-linear link-functions ϕ, e. g. the harmonic oscil-
component set K has an exact model with the composition lator has the total energy as an exact model.
ϕ = π ◦ σ of the map σ and the projection π.
Example. The harmonic oscillator with the state X ∈ R2
Proof. Then Y = πσX = πX  obeys the model equation
(2) with G = F π with F  from Eq. (5) and its projection and Ẋ1 = X2 and Ẋ2 = −X1 has one-dimensional linear
defined in Eq. (6). models with Ẏ = iY and Ẏ = −iY thanks to the
spectral decomposition in C but not in R. Furthermore,
Theorem 2 expresses the attempt to develope theories the conservation of energy provides the real exact model
which seperate causes. A choice of concepts σ which allows Y = c(X12 + X22 ) for every c ∈ R.
the projection π to give an exact model, separates all We finish this section by mentioning that models can be
concepts in Y and their relation to each other from other regarded as systems having sub-models. We get a model
influences. family. For instance, in the simplest case of a system
The partial differential equation (7) is a standard trans- Ẋ = ΛX with a real diagonal matrix Λ ∈ Rn×n , every
port equation in ϕ if the function G is given. But in projection πK to a set of components K ⊆ {1, . . . , n}

4
Proceedings of the 9th MATHMOD
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018 Dirk Langemann et al. / IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504 503

generates an exact models. All these models – possibly with the infection rate α and the immunization rate .
together with some non-linear models – form a model The model has the form G(Y ) = αG1 (Y ) + G2 (Y )
family. with the parameter vector a = (α, )T ∈ R2 . Oftentimes
observations are available only for the sum I + R and
5. MODELS WITH PARAMETERS TO DETERMINE not for the single quantities, i. e. χ : Y → Y2 + Y3 .
So, the measurement function ψ maps to Z = I + R =
The formalism presented in Sec. 4 can be used to dis- ψ(X). Parameter identifications means the determination
cuss models with parameters to determine, like shown in of the optimal parameter aopt with respect to an objective
Eq. (4). Now, we regard models Ẏ = Ga (Y ) with the function J based on the measurements. Here, the objective
parameter a ∈ Rq . We get the set of possible solutions function J typically has a long smooth valley with steep
Ya (t) = Γa (t)Y ini depending on a. We denote the propa- flanks, it reacts sensitively to a change of the immunization
gation matrix, cf. Perko (2000), by rate and less sensitively to a change of the infection
rate α. The smallest sensitivity is found along a linear
∂Ya ∂Ga ∂Ga
U= ∈ Rm×q with U̇ = U+ . (8) combination of both of them, expressing a pay-off. This
∂a ∂Y ∂a linear combination directs parallel to the eigenvector of
The propagation matrix expresses the sensitivity of the ∇∇J(aopt ) with the smaller eigenvalue.
value Ya (t) with respect to changes of the parameter a.
The sensitivity ∇∇J(a) depends namely on the propa-
Parameter identification now aims in minimizing an error gation matrix U in Eq. (10). But again unfortunately, a
between the measurements ψ(X(t)) for a set T of time simple propagation matrix U for t = 0 does not remain
instants t ∈ T . In many realistic applications, T is a set simple, see Eq. (8). That is the reason, why we discuss
of discrete time instants, but theoretically, we can think a particular objective function J which will give simple
about a continuous time interval, too. An error functional sensitivity matrices at least in the case
J : W × W → R+ is of the form
a Ga (Y ) = a1 G1 (Y ) + . . . + aq Gq (Y ), (11)
J(a) = J({χ(Γa (t)Y ini )}t∈T , {ψ(X(t))}t∈T ) −→ min .
i. e. in the case when the model can be stated as a linear
(9)
combination of several mechanisms G1 , . . . , Gq . We find
Often used error functionals are the squared sum of the
this situation in models with chemical standard reaction
differences between the model output χ(Γa (t)Y ini ) and the
kinetics, in predator-prey models etc. Let us remark that
measurements ψ(X(t)), sometimes with weights w(t) > 0.
the solutions Y (t) = Γa (t)Y ini may depend on the param-
If T is a continuous interval, the integral over the squared
eter a in a much more complicated manner even if the
difference is the continuous analogue.
model function Ga can be written as linear combination
Eq. (9) simplifies in the case χ = id., when all model com- of mechanisms G1 , . . . , Gq like in Eq. (11)
ponents are measurable, and it holds ϕ = ψ. Then in every
A large variety of models can be written in the form given
optimum aopt with ∇J(aopt ) = 0 ∈ Rq , the sensitivity of
in Eq. (11), and particulary, all models, the equations
the objective function J(a) against parameter changes is
 of which are a combination and composition of terms
∇∇J(a) = 2 U T U + ∇a ∇a Ya · [Yaopt − ψ(X)] dt, (10) g2 (g0 (Y )+f (as )g1 (Y )) with strictly monotonous functions
T g0 , g1 , g2 and a strictly monotonous dependence f (as )
where · denotes the tensor contraction with respect to on a single component of the parameter vector a. The
the direction of Ya ∈ Rm . Near the optimum aopt , the idea is simply introducing a new model component Yn
objective function J is well approximated by a paraboloid for this term and differentiating the resulting algebraic
with the Hessian ∇∇J(aopt ). Its half-axes say something condition to (g2−1 ) (Yn )Ẏn = ∇g0 (Y )Ẏ + as ∇g1 (Y )Ẏ with
about the sensitivity of the optimal parameter to changes the transformed parameter as = f (as ). Replacing the
of the measurements. A short half-axis means that every derivative Ẏ by the existing model equations including the
change in that direction is penalized by a considerate new component Yn yields the form in Eq. (11).
increase of the error functional J, and a rather long half-
axis means that the error J does not depend to strongly After the application of the transformation sketched
on changes in that direction. We regard such less sensitive above, we get an extended model in form of Eq. (11) with
direction as hierarchically subordinated. So, a coordinate a longer state vector. Nevertheless, the minization of an
transformation σ can be applied locally to separate the error functional compares the same measurements ψ(X)
differently sensitive directions of the half-axes. with χ(Y ) or derived quantities of them.

Unfortunately, J is not a paraboloid in general, even not Now, we formulate an error functional JD = JD (a), s.
if the optimal parameter aopt makes the model to be an Eq. (10), which is a strict paraboloid in the parameter
exact one by Yaopt − ψ(X) = 0 ∈ Rm for ψ = ϕ. a ∈ Rq whenever the model function G has the form in
Eq. (11). The idea is to compare the derivatives of the
Example. An infection in a population may obey the model output and the measurements. Then, we get
system Ẋ = F (X) and may be modelled by hands of the JD (a) = JD ({∇χ(Y )Ga (Y )}t∈T , {Dψ(X)}t∈T ) (12)
epidemic SIR-model, cf. Murray (2008), i. e. Y = G(Y ) with an approximation D of the derivative of ψ(X). This
with Y (t) = (S(t), I(t), R(t))T ∈ R3 where S denotes might be a difference quotient if T is a set of discrete time
the amount of susceptible individuals, I the amount of instants. If the measured quantities χ(Y ) depend linearly
infected ones and R the amount of removed individuals. on the model concepts in Y , then ∇χ is independent of
The equations of the SIR-model are the particular solution Y = Ya (t), and the structure of
Ṡ = −αSI, I˙ = αSI − I and Ṙ = I Ga , e. g. from Eq. (11), is refound in the first argument in

5
Proceedings of the 9th MATHMOD
504
Vienna, Austria, February 21-23, 2018 Dirk Langemann et al. / IFAC PapersOnLine 51-2 (2018) 499–504

Eq. (12). Again, let us specify JD to be the usual squared 7. MODEL IDENTIFICATION VERSUS
sum of the differences. Then for a fixed parameter a, e. g. PARAMETER IDENTIFICATION
a = aopt , the functional JD is a q-dimensional paraboloid
JD (a) = JD (aopt ) + (a − aopt )T H(a − aopt ) with a positive A parameter identification in a model of the form Eq. (11)
definite symmetric matrix H ∈ Rq×q . is a model identification at the same time because a
vanashing parameter component ak coincides with the
The eigenvectors of H define a coordinate transformation neglection of the mechanism Gk in the model. So, every
a → a ∈ Rq of the parameter, and the related mechanisms selection L ⊆ {1, . . . , q} stands for a model, and they all
G1 , . . . , Gq in G(Y ) = a1 G1 (Y ) + . . . + aq Gq (Y ) separate form a hierarchically model family. This setting fits to
from each other. Then the transformed sensitivity matrix our procedure of constructing models because we choose
a
H  is diagonal, and the minimization JD (a) −→ min mechanisms to be considered in a model.
separates into q independent one-dimensional optimization
problems. The eigenvalues of H in relation to their charac- The introduction of the constructed reality in form of an
teristic scales give a hierarchical order of the mechanisms unknown system, which is equipped with basic properties
G1 , . . . , Gq . however, in Eq. (1), gives us a conceptual frame to study
the modelling process. It would be desirable to communi-
A considerate drawback of transforming the model states is cate this selection process together with the models.
that fact that the objective function J is not invariant un-
der coordinate transformations. A coordinate transforma- The proposed framework may serve in developing concepts
tion of the model concepts can be expressed by a bijective for models in life-science which separate the effects and
function χ : Y → Z which need not to be linear. Then, mechanisms and make some progress on the way to clarify
weights w containing the factor proportional to ∇χT ∇χ, multi-causal explanations of observations about living sys-
enter the objective function J with respect to Z. There- tems. Furthermore, the proposed framework can be used
fore, different concepts lead to different computations of to formalize other model and system properties like e. g.
optimal parameters aopt . Of course, the replacement of an emergent behaviour.
error functional J by JD changes the optimal parameter.
REFERENCES
A separable model provides the advantage that every
separated sub-system has an independent contribution BonJour, L. (1988). The Structure of Empirical Knowl-
to the error functional and can be handled separately. edge. Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge.
This property is widely – and oftentimes unmentionedly – Evans, L. (2010). Partial Differential Equations. AMS,
used when different influences are separately discussed in Providence.
models in physics and engineering. Otherwise, life science Godfrey-Smith, P. (2003). Theory and Reality: An Intro-
applications with a lot of multi-causal explanations suffer duction to the Philosophy of Sciences. Univ. Chicago
of a lack of separated mechanisms until now. Press, Chicago.
Grimm, V. (1994). Mathematical models and understand-
ing in ecology. Ecol. Model., 74/75, 641–651.
6. EXPERIMENTS, RANDOM INFLUENCES AND Ingalls, B. (2013). Mathematical Modeling in Systems
MEASUREMENT ERRORS Biology. MIT-Press, Cambridge.
Lazebnik, Y. (2002). Can a biologist fix a radio? – or,
An experiment in this formalism is the initiation of a what i learned while studying apoptosis. Cancer Cell,
parallel system Ẋ = F (X) with initial values planned by 2, 179–182.
the experimentator. But, we do not have any access to the Leonelli, S. (2014). What difference does quantity make?
system itself but only to the concepts Z we are able to On the epistemology of big data in biology. Big Data &
measure. Society, I-II, doi 10.1177/2053951714534395.
If the measurement Z ini is fixed, the system may start in Machamer, P. and Silberstein, M. (2002). The Blackwell
any state X ini ∈ ψ −1 ({Z ini }) ⊆ U in the preimage of the Guide to the Philosophy of Science. Wiley-Blackwell,
fixed value. This uncontrolled influences can be regarded Malden.
as hidden states which are not recognizable within the Murray, J. (2008). Mathematical Biology. Springer, New
present theory, model and measurement. The experiment York.
generates a trajectory Φ(t)X ini with one of these possible Perko, L. (2000). Differential Equations and Dynamical
initial values, and we would measure ψ(Φ(t)X ini ). The Systems. Springer, New York.
variability of the initial value X ini leads to variable mea- Scheck, F. (2010). Mechanics. Springer, Berlin.
surements and is one source of measurement errors. Sira-Ramı́rez, H., Rodrı́guez, C.G., Romero, J.C., and
Juárez, A.L. (2014). Algebraic Identification and Es-
The variability of the initial state X ini is mostly unwanted timation Methods in Feedback Control Systems. Wiley,
in an experimental setup. Concepts which diminish the Chichester.
influence of hidden states to our measurements, separate Sontag, E. (1998). Mathematical Control Theory. Springer,
the mechanisms and allow quite accurate experimental New York.
measurements like found in physics and engineering. Op- Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of
positely, life-science systems on higher levels include a lot mathematics in the natural sciences. Comm. Pure Appl.
of quantitatively and qualitatively unknown mechanisms, Math., 13 No. 1, 1–14.
redundant mechanisms, feedback loops and multi-causal
cross influences, and the researchers’ community is faced
to uncertain and unclear measurements.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen