Sie sind auf Seite 1von 3

O

Olivecrona, Karl law thinking (Olivecrona 1969) and ancient


Swedish law.
Carla Faralli From a critical standpoint, Olivecrona’s theory
Alma Mater Studiorum – Università di Bologna, takes aim at both natural law theory and legal
Bologna, Italy positivism. The latter is found to be at fault for
continuing to rely on metaphysical notions, fore-
most among them that of will, for which reason its
Karl Olivecrona (1897–1980) is recognized, next theory of law, despite its pretenses, fails to be
to Alf Ross, to be among the leading exponents of scientific (Pattaro 1972).
Scandinavian legal realism (Bjarup 1978; In the positive, or constructive part, he con-
Castignone 1974; Hierro 2008; Strömholm and nects some brilliant but otherwise disconnected
Vogel 1975; Vogel 1972). He was a pupil of insights offered by Hägerström and Anders
Axel Hägerström, describing the latter as his Vilhelm Lundstedt, weaving them into a theory
“beloved and venerable teacher” and remarking based on an analytical method applied to the lan-
that his own inquiry into law “would not have guage of law (Spaak 2014, 2016).
been possible but for the foundation provided by The language of law, according to Olivecrona,
Hägerström’s speculation.” is a directive language: it uses terms, such as right
In fact, Olivecrona works Hägerström’s novel or duty, that have no semantic referent, in the
conclusions into what is properly a general theory sense that nowhere in the spatiotemporal world
of law developed from a realist point of view, a is there a phenomenon that can be pointed out as
theory that finds completion in the second edition corresponding to them. Thus there is no objective
of Law as Fact (Olivecrona 1971). This second reality corresponding to the concept of a right, and
edition is described by Olivecrona as an “entirely yet this is an operative concept, for on its basis
new book,” even as he retains the same title as the changes are made affecting the behavior and con-
first edition (Olivecrona 1939), signaling that his crete situations of those who are subject to the law.
basic approach to the study of law remains Hägerström explained this phenomenon by
the same. pointing to the magical and psychological origins
Olivecrona also embarks on historical inquiries of the concepts of rights and duties, understood as
along the lines suggested by Hägerström, seeking real powers and constraints. Lundstedt, the most
to trace the origins of the concepts of Roman radical among the authors who have denied that
law (Olivecrona 1949), at the same time as he there is any objectivity to rights and duties, did not
takes up other investigations, looking into natural manage to do away with the corresponding terms

# Springer Nature B.V. 2019


M. Sellers, S. Kirste (eds.), Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_291-1
2 Olivecrona, Karl

and settled for a solution that would have us use of metal or paper bearing a pound sterling or US
them in quotation marks. dollar design and denomination. In times past,
Olivecrona clarifies that – whatever origin when gold coins were in use, one might have
these concepts may have: be it magical or psycho- thought that the word currency stood for a certain
logical or both – they are so ingrained in our amount of gold as its semantic referent, but today
common way of thinking, and so entrenched in it works as an ordinary word used in accordance
the machinery of the law, that we can no longer do with well-established conventions, and it is in this
without them. way that it can carry out the essential function it
Their function is not descriptive – in a manner serves in economic and social life.
that even such natural lawyers as Hugo Grotius Norms are not commands but “independent
and Samuel von Pufendorf might have thought imperatives,” that is, representations of models
conceivable, for they explicitly believed in the of behavior expressed in the imperative form.
reality of powers and constraints of a spiritual Indeed, in contrast to an actual command –
kind created by the will – but is rather directive, which implies a face-to-face interaction between
in that they tend to influence behavior. The term a command issuer and an obeyer, as well as a
right, for example, functions as a sign and is relation of subordination between the two, and
almost unreplaceable in that respect, for it signals which is episodic – a norm is a “depersonalized”
a permission to the rightholder, while signaling a command, in that the commanding is done by an
prohibition to everybody else. The rightholder, in abstract entity (a legislative body) and the recipi-
other words, can behave in relation to a good in ents consist of the whole of the citizenry, and its
ways that all other legal subjects may not. validity lasts indefinitely, until the norm is
Even so, the terms right and duty cannot sim- amended. The coercive impulse to do what a
ply be considered as signs serving to replace a set norm requires is not directed at any single subject
concrete facts or reduce it to a condensed form, for but takes shape as an awareness of an objectively
they also contain an imperative element that acts existing duty.
psychologically to drive or rein in the behavior of Next to the norms prescribing that we do or not
legal subjects. do something, there are others that govern the way
It is a function entirely similar to the one in which we may gain, transfer, or lose rights or
performed by the red and green of a stoplight. have a certain status conferred on us (as when
Olivecrona revisits legal concepts born in someone enters into marriage, is appointed
social and cultural concepts quite different from judge, or is elected as a member of parliament).
ours, and pregnant with meanings that now appear These norms can take a declarative form without
unacceptable from a scientific standpoint, in what naming any addressees, and in order to account
seems like an effort to reuse and justify these for what they do, Olivecrona draws on the work of
concepts on a realist approach. J. L. Austin (1975), characterizing them as per-
In order for these terms to serve a directive formatory imperatives, examples of which are the
function as signs, they need not have any specific words uttered in christening a ship or marrying a
semantic referent: what matters is that we are couple. Even though these performatives are
accustomed to receiving a certain sign in a con- expressed in the indicative mood, they do not
stant and uniform way in keeping with commonly describe a situation but either prescribe or bring
accepted rules. it into being: their effect is not to create real
After all, examples of this kind abound in qualities or relations but to change the standing
ordinary language, where words are legion that of certain persons in relation to others. Outside the
no longer have a semantic referent and yet have legal and social context in which performatives
practical effects of great consequence. are used, they are no more than meaningless
A case in point is the word for currency such as words.
the pound sterling or the US dollar (Olivecrona The language of performatives, according to
1957): certainly it does not correspond to the piece Olivecrona, traces its origins to the magico-
Olivecrona, Karl 3

religious sphere: it was once thought that words perform their directive function as signs.
could change reality and that by describing events Olivecrona accordingly concludes that the lan-
yet to take place, they could turn these into reality guage of law is not descriptive but rather serves
proper through the power exerted by the utterance a directive function: it is a language capable of
of magical formulas. On a realist approach, words influencing behavior, and it functions as a tool of
are tools suited, not to modifying reality in virtue social control.
of an inherent power they supposedly possess, but
to carrying out functions of social control.
The theory of law outlined by Olivecrona can References
be qualified as realist-normativist (Pattaro 1980):
the law is conceived as a fact, that is, as a social Austin JL (1975) In: Urmson JO, Sbisà M (eds) How to do
mechanism, a psychosociological reality. Norms things with words, 2nd edn. Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA
are not the expression of a higher will but the
Bjarup J (1978) Skandinavischer Realismus: Hägerström,
resultant of a complex play of social forces, mean- Lundstedt, Olivecrona, Ross. Karl Alber, Munich/
ing that no de facto power creates norms, but, on Freiburg
the contrary, norms create powers. In the norms Castignone S (1974) La macchina del diritto: Il realismo
giuridico in Svezia. Edizioni di Comunità, Milan
that govern the exercise of power lies the founda-
Hierro LL (2008) El realismo jurídico escandinavo: Una
tion of the power exercised by certain people: if teoría empirista del derecho. Iustel Publicaciones,
lawmakers enact laws that are observed and Madrid
judges issue rulings that are enforced, it is because Olivecrona K (1939) Law as fact. Ejnar Munksgaard,
Copenhagen
they are lawmakers and judges according to the
Olivecrona K (1949) Three essays in Roman law. Ejnar
constitution, which in turn is observed for histor- Munksgaard, Lund/Copenhagen
ical, psychological, and social reasons. Olivecrona K (1957) The problem of the monetary unit.
A valid norm is one that is felt to be binding Macmillan Company, New York
Olivecrona K (1969) The concept of a right according to
and is observed by a given social group, especially
Grotius and Pufendorf. In: Noll P, Stratenwerth G (eds)
judges, but norms cannot be equated with the Rechtsfindung: Beiträge zur juristischen
behavior through which they are enacted: a legal Methodenlehre. Festschrift für Oscar Adolf Germann
norm is the cause; the behavior of its addressees is zum 80 Geburtstag. Stämpfli & CIE AG Verlag, Bern,
p 175–197
the effect. No norm can be valid if it is ineffica-
Olivecrona K (1971) Law as fact. Stevens & Sons, London
cious (i.e., if it does not cause its addressees to Pattaro E (1972) Il realismo giuridico come alternativa al
comply), but in order to be efficacious, it needs to positivismo giuridico. Introduction to Karl Olivecrona,
be perceived as socially binding. This psycholog- La struttura dell’ordinamento giuridico (trans: Pattaro
E). Etas Kompass, Milan, p 1–55
ical element (the sense of a norm’s bindingness) is Pattaro E (1980) In ricordo di Karl Olivecrona. Riv Trimest
what makes it possible to recover the normative Dirit Proced Civ 4:1520–1538
element, the distinctive trait of Scandinavian Spaak T (2014) A critical appraisal of Karl Olivecrona’s
realism. legal philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht
Spaak T (2016) Chap. 14, Karl Olivecrona’s legal philos-
Having shown that the legal concepts currently
ophy. In: Pattaro E, Roversi C (eds) Vol. 12.2 of Trea-
in use are not scientific, Olivecrona applies to tise of legal philosophy and general jurisprudence.
directive language the theory by which analytical Springer, Dordrecht, p 365–378
philosophy explains the functions of language. Strömholm S, Vogel H-H (1975) Le “réalisme Scandinave”
dans la philosophie du droit. Librairie Générale de
Concepts such as “norm,” “rights,” and “duty”
Droit et Jurisprudence, Paris
do not belong to a reality of their own distinct Vogel H-H (1972) Der skandinavische Rechtsrealismus.
from the social, empirical reality in which they Alfred Metzner Verlag, Frankfurt am Main

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen