Sie sind auf Seite 1von 10

What Is Political Obligation?

Author(s): Richard K. Dagger


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 71, No. 1 (Mar., 1977), pp. 86-94
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1956955
Accessed: 01-09-2017 07:43 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/1956955?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The American Political Science Review

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
What Is Political Obligation?*

RICHARD K. DAGGER
Arizona State University

It is sometimes said that the problem of solved in principle, although this solution holds
political obligation is the fundamental or cen- no immediate promise of eliminating our the-
tral problem of political philosophy. This may oretical and practical difficulties.
or may not be true: it depends on what we take What I shall offer, then, is less a theory of
"political obligation" and "political philoso- political obligation than a preface to such a
phy" to mean. Questions concerning obligation theory. Since "political obligation" is a com-
are, of course, important to political philoso- pound of two distinct concepts, I shall begin by
phers and citizens alike. But beyond this we looking at "obligation." This alone should
find neither a consensus on how the problem of suffice to show that the question "Why should
political obligation is to be solved nor even an I obey the law?" is an improper statement of
agreement that it can be solved.1 Indeed, one the problem of political obligation; the implica-
writer has recently gone so far as to suggest that tions of this demonstration may not be evident,
we can do without the very concept of political however, until we examine "political obliga-
obligation.2 tion."
This proposal is certainly extreme, but such
suggestions are to be expected when important The Concept of Obligation
problems are clouded by conceptual confusion.
If we are to understand what "obligation"
I hope in this essay to dispel some of this
means, we must see how the word is used in
confusion. Unlike those who would dissolve the ordinary language. A catalogue of uses, though,
problem of political obligation by abandoning will not serve the purpose, for the propriety
the concept, I propose to examine the concept of certain uses is a matter of controversy. In
to see if the problem is properly stated. I shall what follows, therefore, I argue for a restricted
advance two theses: (1) the problem of political conception of obligation on the grounds that
obligation is fundamentally misconceived when such a conception preserves important distinc-
it is (taken to be) expressed by the familiar
tions which wider conceptions of obligation
question, "Why should I obey the law?"; and
destroy. These distinctions, or conceptual rela-
(2) the problem of political obligation can be tionships, provide both the foci for my explica-
tion and a pair of questions which must be
answered by anyone hoping to come to terms
with the concept of obligation. The questions
*1 am indebted to Terence Ball and Rolf Sartorius are (1) what is the relationship between
for their encouragement and for their comments on
"obligation" and "ought"? and (2) how is
drafts of this essay.
obligation related to coercion?
'See Marparet Macdonald, "The Language of Politi- (1) "Obligation" and "ought." There is a
cal Theory,' in Logic and Language, ed. A. G. N. Flew
(Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1965); Thomas tendency, especially noticeable in philosophical
McPherson, Political Obligation (London: Routledge discourse, to treat certain uses of "obligation"
& Kegan Paul, 1967); H. A. Prichard, "Green: Political and "ought" as interchangeable. This is most
Obligation," in Prichard's Moral Obligation, ed. J. O.
clearly the case in statements which address
Urmson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968); and
T. D. Weldon, The Vocabulary of Politics (London: moral considerations, where one may find, for
Penguin, 1953) for the argument that the problem of example, claims that we have an obligation to
political obligation is impossible to solve because there contribute to charity, to aid those in distress,
can be no general theory of political obligation. For a
and so forth. "Obligation" here supplants
defense of the "traditional" position, see Carole
Pateman, "Political Obligation and Conceptual Analy- "ought" in an attempt to strengthen the im-
sis," Political Studies, 21 (June, 1973), 199 -218. perative-to say that "one ought to be chari-
2This is McPherson's judgment. He says (Political table" seems to leave matters open in a way
Obligation, pp. 84-85) that 'we may well feel justified which "one has an obligation to be charitable"
in dispensing with the concept of political obligation" does not. For this reason, "obligation" has
for this reason: "it is so general a notion as to do little
often been regarded as the principal subject of
or no useful work, and if interpreted in terms specific
enough to be useful it is . . . no longer the satisfyingly moral philosophy, much as it has been con-
general thing that [theorists] wanted in the first sidered the central concern of political philoso-
place." phy.

86

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
1977 What Is Political Obligation? 87

In recent years, however, several philoso- give Smith $5?", of course, but this questions
phers have argued that such usage overextends the soundness of the advice (on either moral or
"obligation" by conflating it with "ought."3 prudential grounds), not the fact that advice
The arguments vary, but the main objection to has been given.
the extended use of "obligation" is simply that The core of the distinction between "obliga-
the two concepts have different functions-this, tion" and "ought" is to be found in the
after all, is why we have two concepts rather grounds for accepting or rejecting obligation
than one. As Joel Feinberg points out, one of and ought claims. The fact that there are
the tasks of "ought" is "to prescribe or give different grounds for each concept underscores
advice. When the word 'ought' occurs in a the importance of resisting the temptation to
sentence which gives advice, we can call it the conflate them. In the case of obligation, two
'ought of final judgment, all things con- conditions must be met in order to warrant an
sidered.' "4 But "obligation," which has func- obligation claim. First, when someone con-
tions of its own, is not prescriptive in this fronted with such a claim demands to know
sense: "If I tell you what your obligations are, I why he is obligated, we point to some "previ-
do not necessarily give you advice of any kind; ous committing action" of his.6 This is what
I simply report that you stand in certain happens, for instance, when we say, "You have
relations to other people, relations of commit- an obligation to pay Smith $5 because you
ment and trust."5 promised to do so." To show why or that
An example may help to clarify this distinc- someone has an obligation, we show how he
tion. Consider the following propositions: came to have it. Not all instances of previous
committing action are as unproblematical as
(a) Jones has an obligation to pay Smith $5. promises, certainly, but the point remains: one
(b) Jones ought to pay Smith $5. becomes obligated by committing himself to
pursue or to desist from pursuing a course of
Let us assume that Jones is not disposed to
action. This is borne out by the way we speak
accept these claims. In the case of (a), Jones
about our obligations: we "undertake," "as-
may respond in two ways: he may deny the
sume," "acquire," and "incur" them, on the
existence of the obligation; or he may admit to
one hand, and "meet," "fulfill," and "dis-
the obligation but hold that he ought not
charge" them, on the other.
discharge it. This second response is legitimate
even if one believes that ceteris paribus we The second condition which obligation
ought to fulfill our obligations, for the ought, claims must meet has to do with a second
as Feinberg says, is "the 'ought of final judg- party. "Obligation" is a relational concept, and
ment, all things considered.' " Advising Jones the party under the obligation is always obli-
of his obligation does not necessarily involve gated to someone or some group. Con-
advising him to do or forbear from doing sequently, whenever we charge someone with
anything. This is not true of (b). Jones may having an obligation, we must be able to answer
respond to (b) by asking, "But ought I really the question, "An obligation to whom?" This is
clearly true of such obligating devices as con-
tracts, promises, marriage vows, etc. One who
3See H. L. A. Hart, "Are There any Natural has an obligation owes something or is indebted
Rights?", Philosophical Review, 64 (April, 1955), andto another party. We justify obligation claims,
"Legal and Moral Obligation," in Essays in Moral then, by demonstrating that (1) x has com-
PhiRosophy, ed. A. I. Melden (Seattle: University of
Washington Press, 1958); also Joel Feinberg, "Super- mitted himself to do or forbear from doing
erogation and Rules," Ethics, 71 (July, 1961), something and that (2) he has committed
276-288; David Gauthier, Practical Reasoning (Ox- himself to y.
ford: Oxford University Press, 1963), chap. 12; E. J.
Ought claims, however, may be warranted
Lemmon, "Moral Dilemmas," Philosophical Review,
71 (April, 1962), 139-158; and Rolf Sartorius, "Utili- without an appeal to either of these features of
tarianism and Obligation," Journal of Philosophy, 66 obligations. This is true whether the claim is
(February, 1969), 67-81. An extended use of "obliga- moral-"You ought to be honest"-or pru-
tion" is defended by R. B. Brandt, "The Concepts of
dential-"You ought to eat your spinach." In
Obligation and Duty," Mind, 73 (1964), 374-393, and
Kurt Baier, "Moral Obligation," American Philoso- neither of these cases do we require either a
phical Quarterly, 3 (July, 1966), 210-226. previous committing action-"What have I done
4Feinberg, "Supererogation and Rules," p. 278. that makes you think that I ought to be honest
51bid., p. 278. This does not mean that "obliga- (or eat my spinach)?"-or a second party-
tion" is in no sense prescriptive; it is consistent with "With whom ought I be honest? To whom do I
the belief that ceteris paribus one ought to fulfill one's owe it to eat my spinach?" Instead, ought
obligations. For an analysis of "political obligation"
which regards obligation as a "conduct-guiding" con-
cept, see Richard Flathman, Political Obligation (New 6The phrase is E. J. Lemmon's in "Moral Dilem-
York: Atheneum, 1972), esp. pp. 29-30 and 34. mas," P. 14 1.

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
88 The American Political Science Review Vol. 71

claims are justified by an appeal to principles or Brandt's reasons for "striking out" these
desires or consequences. I ought to be honest features are remarkably weak. He dismisses the
because it is simply right to tell the truth or requirement that obligation is an, obligation to
because better consequences follow from hon- someone by producing the following examples
esty than from dishonesty? I ought to eat my where "it seems hardly sensible to attempt to
spinach because it is good for me, because it is identify any individual to whom obligation is
in my interest to do so. Here again the owed":
testimony of language indicates the distinction Citizens have an obligation to observe the
between "obligation" and "ought": We are laws of their country;
obligated to do a because we "incurred,,"
"undertook," etc., the obligation, but we ought Citizens in a democratic country have an
to do (or refrain from doing) b because it is obligation to vote;
''right" (or "wrong") or "'good" (or "bad") to Mentally gifted people are under an obliga-
do so. To justify an obligation claim we point tion to develop their capacities. 1 3
to a commitment; to justify an ought claim we
Similarly, his justification for denying the need
refer to the content of the claim.7
for a previous committing action is that "the
This position on the relationship of "obliga- obligations to give help to one in dire need or
tion" and "ought," I should note, is not to make some contribution to charitable enter-
uncontested. R. B. Brandt, for one, has argued prises are sufficient reason for elimination of
that "obligation" may be used correctly even this restriction."14 But these examples are not
where there has been neither a previous com- enough to establish Brandt's position. No one
mitting action nor a second party to whom the disputes that these are intelligible and not
obligation is owed.8 Brandt distinguishes a altogether uncommon uses of "obligation"; the
"paradigm" from an "extended" use of "obliga- question is whether these are appropriate uses
tion." The "paradigm" use-when "there is no of the word. To use "obligation" when "ought"
better word for the occasion and there are no is called for is inappropriate precisely because it
better occasions for the word"9 -corresponds leads to confusion in two areas: confusion
with the account of obligation I have set out. about what is being claimed, on one hand, and
The "extended" use, which involves what I about what needs to be done to warrant that
have called the conflation of "obligation" and claim, on the other. Brandt himself ack-
"ought," is exemplified in such statements as, nowledges this-but fails to recognize its sig-
"'Jane Addams thought that people are under nificance-when he says that the "extended"
an obligation to affirm their own vision [sic] of use of "obligation" is "harmful only in blurring
truth' " and " 'students are morally obligated our sense of how language is ordinarily
to report infractions of college rules which they used."1 5
observe'."'10 Since the "extended" use of t"obli- "Obligation" and "ought" are certainly
gation" is intelligible, Brandt reasons, the ques- closely related concepts; but the relationship
tion is, "What must we strike from the para- will become insignificant if their separate iden-
digm use of 'obligation' in order to arrive at tities are not preserved. The fact that I am
elements common to correct uses?"51 1 Brandt's under an obligation to do a is a reason for
answer is that the two features which I have saying that I ought to do a, but the converse is
maintained are essential to "obligation" must not true. The "ought of final judgment" may
be eliminated: "First, we must strike out the override an obligation, but again the converse
notion that obligation is an obligation to does not hold: there is no such thing as an
someone.... Second, we must strike out the "obligation of final judgment." When we ask,
idea that the bond derives from some prior act "What am I obligated to do?" we are not also
or event, such as an agreement or the accep- asking, "What is it that I ought to do?" The
tance of a benefaction." 12 two concepts have different functions, and the
"extended" use of "obligation" only confuses
7This distinction is drawn from Hart, "Legal and
Moral Obligation," p. 100 ff. "Promises," Hart says, what is already complex.
"have pre-eminently the feature 1 have called indepen- (2) Obligation and coercion. In his essay on
dence of content: the obligation springs not from the"Legal and Moral Obligation," H. L. A. Hart
nature of the promised action but from the use of the
procedure by the appropriate person in the appropri-
ate circumstances" (p. 102). 13Tbid., p. 379. It should be noted that even in
8 "The Concepts of Obligation and Duty." these cases we can still point to someone or some
group to whom the obligation may be owed-e.g.,
9Ibid., p. 385. 'Citizens are obligated to their fellow citizens to pay
OIbid., p. 376 (emphasis in the original). taxes."
I IIbid., p. 390. 14Ibid., p. 390.
12Ibid., p. 390 (emphasis in the original). l Ibid., p. 391.

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
1977 What Is Political Obligation? 89

identifies the following as features of obliga- even clearer when we look at another situation.
tion: "(1) dependence on the actual practice of Smith, my creditor, may threaten to take legal
a social group, (2) possible independence of action against me if I do not pay him promptly.
content, and (3) coercion."l 6 The first two In this case I may be obliged to pay Smith, but
features have to do with previous committing I am only obliged because I have an obligation
action. The second, as I have already noted, to pay him: the sanction can be invoked only
deals with the commitment/content distinction, because the obligation exists to validate it. But
while the first is concerned with specifying when obligation is reduced to coercion, the
what is to count as a committing action. The distinction between gunmen and creditors van-
third feature, however, introduces another kind ishes.
of problem, that of the connection between The connection between obligation and
obligation and coercion. coercion can best be understood by observing
Hart points out that whenever we fail to when the possibility of coercion can and does
meet our obligations we are subject to certain arise in disputes concerning our obligations. We
pressures or sanctions. If I fail to pay my do not attempt to coerce those who fulfill their
income tax, for example, I may be fined or obligations to us-there is no reason to do so.
jailed; if I break a promise, I expose myself to a The prospect of coercion is only invoked when
variety of moral pressures-censure, ostracism, someone fails or gives evidence of failing to
etc. Not all cases of failed obligation result in discharge, or even recognize, an obligation; and
such pressure being brought to bear, of course, in many of these instances there is no actual
but the invocation of sanctions is always coercion because excuses are offered and ac-
possible in these circumstances. cepted. Coercion is justified,20 however, when
This connection between obligation and the obligated party simply refuses to acknowl-
coercion has been the source of a good deal of edge his obligation, as the following dialogue
confusion in legal and political philosophy. "If illustrates:
we have an obligation to do something," as Jones: Why should I give you $5?
Hart says, "there is some sense in which we are Smith: Why? Because you borrowed $5
bound to do it, and where we are bound there from me and promised to pay me back.
is some sense in which we are compelled to do Jones: So? Why should I keep my promise?
it."1,7 The question is, how, or in what sense, Smith: Because a promise is a promise! And
are we bound? Some writers-notably Hobbes if you don't give me my money I'll tell
and Austin (as Hart demonstrates)1 have everybody that you can't be trusted!
failed to distinguish between different senses of
Coercion, as related to obligation, is a
being bound and have argued, as a result, that
response to one whose abuse threatens the
obligation originates in coercion. They have
practices through which we undertake obliga-
taken the relationship of obligation to coercion,
tions and conduct our lives. The existence of a
in other words, to mean that we are obligated
promise is, ceteris paribus, sufficient reason for
because we are bound and not that we are
keeping the promise. One who does not ac-
bound because we are obligated.
knowledge this and who seeks to use the
The extremity of this position is apparent
institution of promising to his own advantage
when we consider that from this perspective,
makes himself liable to coercion. Coercion acts
keeping a promise and paying ransom to a
to guarantee, so to speak, that those who would
kidnapper are equally obligatory actions. What
voluntarily fulfill their obligations are not
happens here, as Hart has shown, is that the
notions of "having an obligation" and "being
sacrificed to those who would not.21 Obliga-
obliged" are conflated. 1 9 If I am accosted by a tion is secured by coercion, but it is not rooted
in it.
gunman, to borrow Hart's example, I may be
obliged to hand my money over to him, but I
surely do not have an obligation to do so. The
difference between the two concepts becomes
20I am not suggesting that all forms and all degrees
of coercion are always justified. The sanction must fit
16Hart, "Legal and Moral Obligation," p. 100.
the abuse, as it were.
7Ibid., p. 95. 2 lThis borrows from Hart, who (in a slightly
different context) says: " 'Sanctions' are ... required
18Ibid., pp. 95-99. See also Hart's extended
notcri-
as the normal motive for obedience, but as a
tique of the "coercive theory of law" in The Concept guarantee that those who would voluntarily obey shall
of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961), esp.
not be sacrificed to those who would not. To obey,
chaps. 2 and 4 and pp.79-89. I am "much obliged" to without this, would be to risk going to the wall. Given
Hart for what follows.
this standing danger, what reason demands is volun-
19Ibid., p. 96, and The Concept of Law, pp.79-89; tary co-operation in a coercive system." The Concept
also Gauthier, Practical Reasoning, pp. 174-176. of Law, p. 193 (emphasis in original).

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
90 The American Political Science Review Vol. 71

The concept of obligation, then, involves According to those who would dissolve the
these elements: a commitment to someone (or problem of political obligation, political obliga-
some group) to do (or not do) something which tion is best understood as what has come to be
one may justifiably be coerced into doing or called an institutional obligation, i.e., an obliga-
punished for failing to do. "Obligation" is not tion which is presupposed by the rules of an
coextensive with "ought"; and obligations are institution and incurred by those who partici-
supported by, but not derived from, the threat pate in its practices. Anyone, then, who partici-
of coercion. With this understanding of "obliga- pates in the practices of a political society
tion" it becomes evident that the question incurs an obligation to obey the laws of that
which supposedly expresses the problem of society, just as anyone who joins in a game of
political obligation, "Why should I obey the basketball undertakes an obligation to obey the
law?", is not at all a proper statement of the rules of the game.
problem. This is because the question is put in The chief significance of this institutional
terms of "ought" rather than "obligation." In model for the present discussion is that it tends
turn, this means that "Why should I obey the to moot the question of obedience. Hans
law?" fails to come to grips with obligation in Kelsen, for instance, deals with "Why should I
two different ways. First, it may be that I am obey the law?" in this fashion:
obligated to obey the law even though, all We ought to obey the decisions of a judge or
things considered, I ought to disobey it. The administrator, ultimately, because we ought to
fact that I have in some way committed myself obey the constitution. If we ask why we ought
to obedience may not, in a particular case, to obey the norms of the existing constitution,
constitute a (morally) sufficient reason to obey. we may be referred to an older constitution
Second, "Why should I obey the law?" may be that has been replaced in a constitutional way
answered with considerations of expediency or by the existing constitution; and in this way we
arrive finally at the historically first constitu-
prudence. Thus some have argued that we
tion. To the question why we ought to obey its
ought to obey the law because we will benefit
provisions a science of positive law can only
by doing so or we will suffer if we do not. This answer: the norm that we ought to obey the
is an entirely reasonable answer; but this is also provisions of the historically first constitution
the reason for rejecting "Why should I obey the must be presupposed as a hypothesis if the
law?": the question can be answered in terms coercive order established on its basis and
which fail to justify obligation claims. actually obeyed and applied by those whose
What we need to do is to recognize two behavior it regulates is to be considered as a
distinct kinds of questions: questions of politi- valid order binding upon these individuals; if
the relations among these individuals are to be
cal obligation, on the one hand-"Am I obli-
interpreted as legal duties, legal rights, and legal
gated to obey the law?"-and more general, and
responsibilities, and not as mere power rela-
perhaps more important, questions of political tions; and if it shall be possible to distinguish
obedience, on the other-"Why should I obey between what is legally right and legally wrong
the law?"22 and especially between legitimate and illegiti-
mate use of force. This is the basic norm of a
The Problem of Political Obligation positive legal order, the ultimate reason for its
validity ... 23
My second thesis is that the problem of
political obligation can be solved-at least in Kelsen's argument amounts to something like
principle. This has been an article of faith with this: "If we want a legal system, with the
many political philosophers, but in the years safeguards and advantages law provides, we
since World War II it has become the subject of must realize that we will have to pay a certain
dispute. Several commentators, in fact, have price. And that price is that we must consider
dismissed the problem of political obligation as ourselves obligated to obey the law." In this
a pseudo-problem which cannot be solved and fashion the "basic norm" presupposes an obli-
need not be posed in the first place. Since those gation to obey the law as the conditio sine qua
who hold this view explicitly deny my second non of legal systems.
thesis, it seems appropriate to turn to an Kelsen's position is similar to that taken by
examination of their position. T. D. Weldon in The Vocabulary of Politics.
Weldon answers "Why should I obey the law?"
in this manner:
22There are other objections to "Why should I
obey the law?" which remain, I take it, even if we
consider this to be a question of obedience rather than
obligation-e.g., the single question hides a cluster of
distinct questions. See Hanna Pitkdn's valuable essay 2 3Hans Kelsen, "Why Should the Law be
"Obligation and Consent-I," American Political Sci- Obeyed?" in his What Is Justice? (Berkeley and Los
ence Review, 59 (December, 1965), 990-999,esp. p. Angeles: University of California Press, 1960), p. 262
990-991. (emphasis added).

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
1977 What Is Political Obligation? 91

Suppose . . . the objector goes on to say "Even ing to rules; this is what "political society"
if it is the law, I don't see why I should obey means. It is therefore absurd to ask for a
it." The only further comment possible is general justification of the obligation to obey
"Well, this is Great Britain, isn't it?" the law. Our attention is better directed to
The position is exactly parallel to that of the
particular questions of obedience and obliga-
cricketer who asks "Why should I obey the
tion-"Am I obligated to obey this law in these
umpire? What right has he to give me out?"
One can answer only by expounding the rules circumstances?"-and not to general questions
of cricket, the position of the M.C.C., and so which cannot be answered.
on. Beyond that there is nothing to be done But Macdonald and others who accept the
except to say "This is a game of cricket, isn't institutional model dismiss the general question
it?" 24 of political obligation too hastily. I say this for
Like the obligation to obey the rules of cricket, two reasons. First, contrary to what Weldon
the obligation to obey the law is presupposed says, the position of one who questions his
by the rules of the game. And there is some obligation to obey the law is not "exactly
sense to this notion-after all, why play a game parallel" to that of one who questions his
if one does not intend to follow the rules? obligation to follow the rules of the game.
Indeed, it may be said that one who fails to While it is sometimes helpful to look upon
follow the rules does not even play the game. political life as a game, the analogy must not be
The advantages of the institutional (or game) taken too far. When we play games we partici-
model are clear. The model allows us to trace pate voluntarily; we accept and undertake an
the obligation to a committing action, i.e., the obligation to obey the rules. But in most cases
act (or acts) of participating in the practices of we do not choose to participate in a political
the institution. It also provides an answer to the society or legal system-this is usually a matter
question, to whom is the political obligation of the accident of birth.27 Therefore, if we do
owed? The obligation is owed to the other have an obligation to obey the laws of the
players, i.e., to one's fellow citizens. Thus, as political society into which we are born, this
one commentator puts it, "the game philoso- obligation cannot be accounted for by the game
pher has found a way of relating political analogy alone.
obligation to the individual's role as a citizen- The second reason is that the institutional
subject rather than leaving it hanging as an model attaches far too much significance to the
external, accidental feature, say, of his conceptual link between "obligation" and
"political society." There is a bit of sleight-of-
birth."'25
hand in the arguments of Macdonald and in
But there is also a crucial disadvantage.
those of Thomas McPherson, who claims that
From the point of view of the game model it is
senseless to ask either "Why should I obey the any general question of the form 'Why should
law?" or "Am I obligated to obey the law?" we accept obligations?" is misconceived. 'Why
should I (a member) accept the rules of the
This tendency to deny that there can be any
club?" is an absurd question. Accepting the
kind of general answer to the questions of
rules is part of what it means to be a member.
obedience and obligation is best exemplified by
Similarly, "Why should I obey the govern-
Margaret Macdonald. In "The Language of ment?" is an absurd question. We have not
Political Theory" Macdonald declares that "to understood what it means to be a member of
ask why I should obey any laws is to ask political society if we suppose that political
whether there might be a political society obligation is something that we might not have
without political obligations, which is absurd. had and that therefore needs to be justified.28
For we mean by political society, groups of Macdonald and McPherson may well be correct
people organized according to rules enforced by in arguing that anyone who belongs to a
some of their number."26 Macdonald, like political society is necessarily obligated to obey
Kelsen and Weldon, takes the obligatory nature
of laws for granted. A political society consists 27Weldon disputes the significance of this point.
of groups of individuals living together accord- "It is argued," he says, "that if I do not like my
cricket club or my trade union or even my Church, I
can resign from it and join a different one. But I
cannot escape from my State. There seems to me to be
24T. D. Weldon, The Vocabulary of Politics, p. 57. very little in this.... Resigning from any institution
I owe this reference to Alan Gewirth, "Obligation: involves some inconvenience.... But to say that one
Political, Legal, Moral," in Nomos XII: Political and cannot escape from one's State is simply untrue.
Legal Obligation, ed. J. Roland Pennock and John Normally emigration is possible, though it is some-
Chapman (New York: Atherton Press, 1970). times so difficult as to be practically out of the
25John Ladd, "Legal and Moral Obligation," in question. But there is always suicide, and it is not in
Pennock and Chapman, pp. 21-22. these days so very uncommon." The Vocabulary of
26Macdonald, "The Language of Political Theory," Politics, p. 48.
p. 192. 28Thomas McPherson, Political Obligation, p. 64.

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
92 The American Political Science Review Vol. 71

the laws of that society, but this begs a crucial the relationship between obligation and coer-
question: what is a political society? And: how cion. There are two choices: either we dis-
is belonging signified and membership marked? tinguish political societies from societies where
The implication of those who adopt the institu- naked power reigns or we deny that a member
tional model is that only the Crusoes are not of a political society is necessarily obligated to
members of political societies. This simply obey the laws. Otherwise, we are once again in
dodges one of the most troublesome issues of the untenable position of deriving obligation
political philosophy, viz., the problem of legiti- from coercion. Whichever of the two alterna-
macy. If we recognize the powers-that-be in tives one accepts, the ultimate question remains
Xenotania as the legitimate government of the same: what are the characteristics of a
Xenotania, then the general questions of obedi- regime to which I may be obligated? What
ence and obligation are senseless; but how do remains, in other words, is the general question,
we know that their rule is indeed legitimate? "Am I obligated to obey the laws of this
The powers-that-be may issue directives and regime?"
enforce obedience, but this does not distinguish This approach to the problem of political
them, as St. Augustine pointed out, from a obligation resembles what Hanna Pitkin has
band of robbers. called "the doctrine of hypothetical consent."
Responses to these questions are unlikely to "For a legitimate government," as Pitkin says,
be satisfactory, for political society-like art, "a true authority, one whose subjects are
religion, science, and democracy-is an essen- obligated to obey it, emerges as being one to
tially contested concept.29 That is, we can which they ought to consent, quite apart from
neither define the concept in terms of necessary whether they have done so.... Legitimate
and sufficient criteria nor stipulate a generally government is government which deserves con-
acceptable definition. The reason for this is that sent."30 The mere fact that one's life is
political society is a concept which informs and governed in important respects by others is not
constitutes our action and behavior. "Political enough to establish an obligation to obey the
society" can be, and is, used in a descriptive governors. The government must also be wor-
sense, but since the use of the concept both thy of obedience-it must be a just state.
affects and reflects what we believe and what Anyone, therefore, who attempts to develop a
we do, the criteria for its use are in dispute. I theory of political obligation must at the same
may consider Xenotania to be a political time present a conception of a just state, and
society, for example, but someone else may anyone who wishes to develop a theory of
consider it to be an unfortunate land ruled by justice will also present a conception of a state
naked coercion; and I may consider myself which ought to be obeyed. This connection
obligated to obey the laws of Xenotania, while between justice, obligation, and obedience is
another denies that the dictates of those in explicit in the work of John Rawls and implicit
power are, properly speaking, laws at all. in that of Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Green, and
It is important to notice that the dispute others.3 1
here is not like that between a batter, who The notion of "hypothetical consent" is not
judges a pitch to be a ball, and an umpire, who sufficient, however, as a response to the ques-
calls it a strike. The batter and umpire accept tion of political obligation. It may be that we
the same criteria for distinguishing balls from ought to obey any government which deserves
strikes, but they disagree about whether this our consent, but this is not to say that we are
particular pitch meets the criteria for a strike. obligated to such a government. To "hypo-
In the case of political society, the contest
centers directly on the criteria: what are we to
take "political society" to mean? The concept 30Pitkin, "Obligation and Consent-I," p. 999
is essentially contestable because the debate (emphasis in the original).
about when the concept may be properly used 31Peter Singer seems to be working along these
is inescapably normative. lines in Democracy and Disobedience (Oxford: Oxford
When we strip the apparent neutrality from University Press, 1973), where he argues that there are
reasons for obeying the laws of democratic states
"political society" (or "legal system," or which do not hold for nondemocracies. There are,
"state," or even "government"), we find that according to Singer, two reasons for this claim to
we have returned, in a sense, to the problem of obedience: "firstly, that one ought to accept a
decision-procedure which represented a fair compro-
mise between competing claims to power. 'Accept'
29The notion of "essentially contested concepts" is here involves both participating in and abiding by the
developed by W. B. Gallie, Philosophy and the results of the decision-procedure. Secondly, ... that
Historical Understanding (New York: Schocken, participation in a decision-procedure, when others are
1966), chap. 8. See also Alisdair MacIntyre, "The participating in good faith, creates a prima facie
Essential Contestability of Some Social Concepts," obligation to accept the results of the procedure" (p.
Ethics, 84 (October, 1973), 1-9. 59).

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
1977 What Is Political Obligation? 93

thetical consent" we must also add participa- every man that hath any possessions, or enjoy-
ment of any part of the dominions of any
tion. The reason for adding this requirement is
government, doth thereby give his tacit con-
simple but significant. Political obligation and
sent, and is so far forth obliged to obedience to
citizenship are correlative: one can only have a
the laws of that government during such enjoy-
political obligation to a state of which he is a ment as anyone under it; whether this his
citizen. There may be numerous political soci- possession be of land to him and his heirs for
eties which deserve obedience, but we are not ever, or a lodging only for a week; or whether it
politically obligated to all of them. It is also be barely travelling freely on a highway; and in
possible, conversely, that someone may be effect it reaches as far as the very being of any
sufficiently displeased with even a just society one within the territories of that govern-
ment.33
to leave it; and when one ceases to be a member
of a society, when he renounces his citizenship, One of the problems with this argument is that
his political obligation ends as well.32 Locke leaps from an obligation to obey particu-
By thus combining the emphasis on partici- lar laws to a general obligation to obey all the
pation (from the institutional model) with the laws of a country-as if one could be obligated
"nature of the government" or "hypothetical to perform all actions of a certain class because
consent" doctrine, we arrive at the two con- he is obligated to perform some actions of that
ditions necessary and jointly sufficient to vali- class. But does this mean that, on the other
date a political obligation claim. We are poli- hand, we can have no obligations to obey
tically obligated to (obey the laws of) a state particular laws unless we have a general political
when (1) we are citizens of that state and (2) obligation? Do we, as one philosopher has said,
the state deserves our obedience. This means
want to say that a system like that of Nazi
that the question of political obligation, "Am I Germany, since obviously immoral, was there-
obligated to obey the laws of this regime?", fore not a legal system? It is hard to see any
remains an open question: we must always temptations in such a view. For this would
determine whether the state is deserving of our entail such absurdities as that no binding
obedience. There is no social contract which, contracts were ever made in Nazi Germany,
once signed, obligates us for all time. that all children born under Nazi "marriages"
A political obligation, on this view, is a are bastards, and so forth.34

systemic obligation; that is, the obligation is A brief examination shows that this argu-
not to obey any particular law of the polity, ment does not hold. If we grant that Nazi
but to obey all its laws. This obligation, of Germany was an unjust regime, then, given my
course, is not absolute. It may be that in some conception of political obligation, the Germans
circumstances we ought to disobey a law under the Nazi regime had no political obliga-
despite our political obligation. Nevertheless, a tion. This does not entail, however, that they
political obligation provides a prima facie rea- were never obligated to obey any "laws"
son for obedience which is absent in a state to enforced by that regime. As long as two parties
which we have no political obligation. In this willingly entered into a contract, that contract
sense political obligations are like promises: if was binding. Similarly, anyone today who
there are no overriding considerations, they drives a car undertakes an obligation to obey
ought to be honored. the traffic regulations no matter what the
But what if the situation is turned around? character of the regime which enforces those
What if the society is not ruled justly? Do we regulations. The point is that there are some
then have no obligation to obey any of the rules which we are obligated to obey because
commands of the rulers? Or what if the state is we have undertaken the obligation, as we do
just, but we are simply visitors, not citizen- when we sign a contract. These are what Hart
subjects; are we then not obligated to obey any calls "power conferring" rules. Laws of this sort
laws of the state we are visiting? empower private persons to do certain things,
This challenge to the conception of political but, unlike "duty imposing" laws, they do not
obligation as a systemic obligation reverses the require performance.35 The laws governing
charge often brought against Locke. Locke marriage, for instance, do not require us to
extends the notion of tacit consent to the point
where
33The Second Treatise of Government, ed. J. W.
Gough (Oxford: Blackwell's, 1966), s 119, p. 61.
34Jeffrie Murphy, "Allegiance and Lawful Govern-
320ne remains liable, of course, for obligations ment," Ethics, 79 (October, 1968), 56-69, at 57. This
incurred before he renounced his citizenship; so that if quotation is somewhat out of context-Murphy is
one has a political obligation to a state which requires arguing against natural law theorists who claim that a
an income tax, he may not legitimately avoid payment legal system cannot be immoral-but I think it fits the
by renouncing his citizenship just before the tax is present discussion well enough.
due. 35The Concept of Law, pp. 26-48.

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
94 The American Political Science Review Vol. 71

marry, they simply confer the power to do so. and just state must be supplied. This means, in
Those living in Nazi Germany, therefore, may turn, that it is necessary either to develop a full
have had neither a political obligation nor political theory or to work within the frame-
specific obligations to serve in the army or pay work of an elaborated tradition of political
taxes, but there certainly were occasions on discourse.36 In the end, therefore, the solution
which they were obligated to obey the law. does not guarantee that there is only one
Unless there are extraordinary circumstances, correct answer in any particular situation in
the immorality of a regime does not justify, for which the question of political obligation arises.
example, reckless driving. We may be legally This is not to say that the distinctions I have
obligated, in other words, even when we are not drawn are worthless. Much of the ambiguity in
politically obligated. theories of political obligation can be traced to
the failure to distinguish questions of obligation
Conclusion from questions of obedience-Hobbes is a good
The problem of political obligation can be example. If we keep this distinction in mind,
solved. If I am a citizen of a just state, then I we can better understand, and avoid, the
have a political obligation to-and a reason for confusion which has plagued discussions of
obeying the laws of-that state. But this is a political obligation. And even if we cannot
modest solution, one that is hardly likely to reach final agreement on troublesome ques-
resolve all the practical and theoretical dif- tions, we may nevertheless benefit from know-
ficulties usually associated with the notion of ing how and why we disagree.
political obligation. To determine that one has
a political obligation, in the first place, is to
provide a reason for obeying the laws of the
36That is, different conceptions of citizenship and
state; but it is not necessarily a conclusive just state are associated with different traditions in
reason. If I satisfy myself that I am (not) political theory. On this point, see Michael Walzer's
obligated to obey the law, I may still have to essay, "The Problem of. Citizenship," in his Obliga-
satisfy myself that I ought (not) to obey the tions: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship
(New York: Simon & Schuster, 1971). In The Logic of
law.
the Social Contract (Ph.D. dissertation, University of
This solution, moreover, is purely formal. Minnesota, 1976) I argue that the social contract can
Before it can serve as a guide to action, it must be used to provide satisfactory conceptions of citizen-
ship and the just state.
be given content: conceptions of citizenship

This content downloaded from 157.50.9.213 on Fri, 01 Sep 2017 07:43:32 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen