Sie sind auf Seite 1von 8

What Is Public Art?

: Time, Place, and Meaning


Author(s): Hilde Hein
Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 54, No. 1 (Winter, 1996), pp. 1-7
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/431675
Accessed: 29-10-2018 14:31 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Symposium:
Public Art

Hilde Hein
What is Public Art?:
Time, Place, and Meaning

I. A PUBLIC ART OF PLACE AND TIME struction of freedom based on the possession of
libertarian rights. In its defense, partisans, from
Public art is an oxymoron according to the stan- Kant to the present, have endowed art with a lib-
dards of modernist art and aesthetic theory. eratory function conceptually constructed out of
Modern philosophical aesthetics focuses almost a fusion of artistic independence (the unregu-
exclusively on subjective experience and a com- lated genius) with political autonomy (the ab-
modified work of art. Art is taken to be the sence of heteronomous coercion). The au-
product of an individual and autonomous act of tonomous individual, glorified in the person of
expression, and its appreciation is, likewise, a the artist and secondarily in the created object,
private act of contemplation. By contrast, as a transcends the public, whose emancipatory ben-
public phenomenon, art must entail the artist's efit is vicarious and derivatives The art de-
self-negation and deference to a collective com- noted, however, is explicitly not that of the self-
munity. It is interesting to observe that the rec- effacing tribal or (public) artist who reflects the
ognized art of nearly all cultures, including that culture of the community, but that of the self-af-
of the western European tradition prior to the firming (private) individual.
late Renaissance, embraces just such a collec- Strictly speaking, no art is "private." Even
tive model, indulging the differences among in- those abortive essays consigned to flames in frus-
dividuals as variant manifestations of a common tration by their authors were, presumably, made
spirit. The celebrated treasures of Greece and for, but withheld from, publication. But neither
Rome, as well as the Christian works of the does art become "public" simply in virtue of its
Middle Ages and the age of the fresco that suc- exposure and accessibility to the world. Public-
ceeded them, do not exalt the private vision of ity has social and political connotations that are
individual artists so much as they bespeak the untranslatable to public access. Conventionally,
shared values and convictions of cultural com- the term "public art" refers to a family of condi-
munities, and are accordingly to be found in tions including the object's origin, history, loca-
those edifices and open places where people tion, and social purpose. All of these conditions
regularly gather to commemorate those same have changed their meanings in a world of evolv-
values and convictions. Privacy was for cen- ing technology, secularization, cultural migra-
turies a privative concept, demarcating the dis- tion, and economic restructuration. Yet today's
sociated and limited experience of persons cut off public artworks still have conceptual links with
from and below the level of full social humanity. 1 such traditional art forms as the medieval cathe-
Modernism, with its glorification of the indi- dral and the mural and temple ruins of ancient
vidual, has reversed that order, investing person- Mexican and Latin American civilizations.3
hood with uniqueness and regarding the social Like many complex social ideas, the concept
as a derivative aggregate. Its representation of of public art has undergone radical changes, and
art, correspondingly, gives pride of place to that recent public quarrels which focus on an in-
which is irreducibly personal. The aesthetic of stance at hand-a current scandal or judicial
modernism has yoked art with subjective con- decision-scarcely reveal the pluralization and
sciousness and expression, and with a new con- polarization that both art and the notion of pub-

The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54:1 Winter 1996

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

lic art have withstood. The monolithic cultural licly funded, they might have been able to inter-
assumptions implicit in Roman forum statuary vene more destructively. Instead, (also at private
or an altar triptych or even the typical town expense) the opposition succeeded only in win-
square equestrian statue are no longer viable. ning the installation of a conventionally realist
The supposition that a visual form, an anthem, representation, complete with flagpole, nearby.
or a text might express its deepest values or Tilted Arc was publicly funded and was also
unify a coherent social group has become a relic placed on a federally owned site. But, Serra's
of romantic history.4 Instead, the concept of a claims to First Amendment protection notwith-
public has become so problematized that puta- standing, the fact that the Arc was initiated by
tive works of public art demand justification in the government did not ensure against its de-
terms of qualitatively unrelated analyses of pub- struction. Both its erection and its subsequent
lic space, public ownership, public represen- demise were presided over by decisions of the
tation, public interest, and the public sphere. United States General Services Administration.
Rarely does a work satisfy in all of these dimen- Although the sculpture belonged to the United
sions. Indeed, few works address or embody all States government and was displayed on gov-
of these aspects of publicity, and their selective ernment property, the judge who condemned the
attention to one or more of them-frequently sculpture to removal declared it a privatization
conflict-ridden-accounts for the baffling vari- of public space.8 Neither location in a public
ety of items proffered as public art. place nor inception by a state agency suffi-
What, then, remains to render an object a ciently identified it as public art in Judge Pol-
work of public art, if neither collective origin lack's estimation. That alone might not have
nor spiritual cohesiveness nor central placement warranted its removal, but many critics from
nor even popularity serves to determine it? A within and without the artworld agreed with
crudely pragmatic and narrow definition of him that, whether or not that was tantamount to
public art equates it with art installed by public its destruction, the sculpture should be removed
agencies in public places and at public expense.5 from its site.9
But this is hardly sufficient to encompass the Public art today seems to engage more ab-
explosion of non-traditional projects that now stract concerns and more ephemeral interpreta-
lay claim to designation as public art. The two tions of site, memory, and meaning. Space and
cases discussed in this symposium by Horowitz time continue to play a definitive part, but like
and Kelly, though superseded by more recent most philosophical categories, their meaning
examples, lay the ground of disputation over has grown attenuated. They no longer refer sim-
contemporary public art. Both Richard Serra's ply to "where" and "when," but have become
Tilted Arc and Maya Lin's Vietnam Veterans symbolic and relational indicators, far removed
Memorial were produced by artworld figures from the coordinates that once sufficed to situ-
whose design proposals were selected from ate things. Today's public artworks may be im-
among other submissions by boards of artworld permanent and discontinuous, like the installa-
judges; thus from the vantage of the Institu- tions of Suzanne Lacy. They may subsist only
tional Theory of Art, both indisputably qualify momentarily or in multiple instantiations, im-
as works of art.6 The Vietnam Veterans Memo- materially suspended, like the projections of
rial's construction was funded entirely by pri- Krzysztof Wodiczko. They may be unheroically
vate donations (solicited from individual vet- unspectacular, like the neighborhood sculptures
erans); only its (public) placement on the of John Ahearn or like the local landscapes of
Washington Mall required Congressional ap- Sondquist. And they may be realized exclu-
proval. Its location and explicit memorializing sively in discrete mental spaces, like some of the
mission, however, would surely warrant its pub- exhortations of the Guerrilla Girls. How then do
lic designation by traditional standards. they qualify as public art?
Ironically, the memorial's formal independence
of government is what protected it from official II. A PUBLIC ART OF MEANING
intervention when a group of opponents ob-
jected to what they perceived to be its dis- Modernism and its formalist aesthetic dictated a
respectful and negative tone.7 Had it been pub- stripped-down public as well as a minimalist

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Symposium: Public Art Hein, What is Public Art? 3

private art. Site-specificity took on a spatial and ing what he calls the "modest populism" of Siah
architectural rather than occasional meaning, Armajani with the "bleak puritanism" of Lauren
and with the demise of content, public art be- Ewing, "The very techniques [s/]he chooses to
came first an object in public space, and then a represent commonality can also represent the
sculpting of that space as objects too evapo- conformity that [the artist] means to expose."12
rated, leaving only relations behind. And, since It is interesting that opposite reasons can be
relations exist in the eye of the beholder, the au- given for identical judgments of a single work,
dience (before it too was eliminated) became a just as different works may be oppositely judged
necessary ingredient in the work of art, render- for the same reasons. The cases discussed by
ing it public in a new and non-ceremonial sense. Horowitz and Kelly involve just such interpre-
Public art became vernacular, having to do not tive ambiguity. Tilted Arc, avowed by its author
with a spirit that magnifies as it collectivizes, to be politically motivated, was denounced by a
but with ordinary, unmythicized people in ordi- number of critics for its elitist aestheticism;
nary places and with the ordinary events of their while the overtly apolitical Vietnam Veterans
mundane lives.10 Memorial narrowly avoided destruction by op-
At the same time that it became more ab- ponents who called it a subversive "wailing wall
stract, public art also became more explicitly for anti-draft demonstrators." Both works are
communitarian. The audience no longer figured formally abstract, minimalist in design, and
as passive onlooker but as participant, actively both were selected by artworld juries, presum-
implicated in the constitution of the work of art. ably on the basis of their aesthetic merit alone.
Effectively, the work's realization depends on Both works profess a site-specificity that is
the audience's bestowal of meaning upon it, a neither purely spatial nor locally commemora-
contentious social and political undertaking. tive. Serra maintained that the site-specificity
The integration of the public into the work of art of Tilted Arc was determined as much by mate-
is inherently political, and is as such equally rial social conditions as by aesthetic exigency.
congenial to both conservative and revolution- He meant to confront the public in behavioral
ary ideology. Public art has been used to great space "in which the viewer interacts with the
effect promotionally and oppositionally by all sculpture in its context. ... to engage the public
political persuasions. Nazi architecture, de- in a dialogue that would enhance, both percep-
signed by Albert Speer and gorgeously dis- tually and conceptually, its relation to the entire
played in Leni Riefenstahl's film Triumph of the plaza." The sculpture would not literally inter-
Will complements the political bon mot of dict movement, but it would (and did) cause the
Joseph Goebbels: ""'The statesman is an artist viewer to feel blocked. The experience of op-
too. For him the people is neither more nor less pression was real enough, but Serra wanted it to
than what stone is for the sculptor.""' "I IThe redirect attention to its actual source in the
same sentiment, directed toward more benign mechanisms of state power. He hoped that the
ends, is intended in the work of Vito Acconci, sculpture would redefine the space in terms of
Siah Armajani, Beverly Pepper, Mierle Ukeles, itself; and so it did-even beyond his expecta-
and Christo, among many others who strive to tion. The crusade for the removal of the sculp-
arouse and capture the social conscience of a ture was initiated by a federal judge and federal
passive public. Sometimes despairing, some- employees who protested the affront committed
times hortatory, and sometimes uplifting, all by the Arc and the aggression it might inspire,
these artists agree in stating that human beings but in their testimony some revealed a deeper
are not and shall not be detached from the social sensibility-a consciousness raised and smoth-
and natural world. Hostile or harmonious, the ered by oppression from elsewhere. Far from
world resonates with the human presence, in- letting aesthetic considerations recede into irrel-
trudes upon it, and will not be denied. evancy, they had read them rightly as insepara-
Perhaps the very lability of social and aes- ble from deepest values. Tilted Arc evoked the
thetic interactions and their receptivity to multi- pressure of coercion. Only the source of that un-
ple interpretations accounts for the difficulty the welcome feeling was ambiguous.13
public sometimes experiences "reading" public In their analyses for this symposium, Horo-
works. As Michael North points out in compar- witz and Kelly disagree over the meaning of

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
4 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

site-specificity. Kelly holds that


always be decorated Tilted
by mass ornaments, Arc
no matter fails
to be site-specific, since "the public" is reduced what sort of art is put into it.16
to the abstraction of "traffic" and was excluded
from consultation regarding the sculpture's se- Despite its nonrepresentational modernist aes-
lection. In other words, the piece does not in- thetic, the Vietnam Veterans Memorial is not a
habit the public sphere. Horowitz, on the other "mass ornament"; neither is it "nihilistic."
hand, claims that the managed opposition to It is clear that location and accessibility are
Tilted Arc was a cynical subversion of its delib- misleading parameters of publicity. Sizable
erately achieved menace, converting the aes- works of art are now commonly commissioned
thetic dis-ease it provoked into mistrust of the for such semipublic places as university grounds,
work as an actual threat. His survey of circula- hospitals, housing developments, and bank lob-
tion notwithstanding, Serra certainly did mean bies. Government subsidy often mandates the
to disrupt the specious openness of Federal inclusion of artworks under percent-for-art reg-
Plaza, but the dialogue that ensued did not have ulation, and private corporations receive tax
the political outcome he anticipated. benefits for the cultural contribution they make
It may be that, whether with persons or with in the form of artistic embellishment. But the
places, dialogue does not always end happily. If sheer presence of art out-of-doors or in a bus
the aim of site-specific art (which, by the way, terminal or a hotel reception area does not auto-
is not coextensive with public art) is to evoke matically make that art public-no more than
"critical adjustment" to a place, that can end placing a tiger in a barnyard would make it a do-
with its acceptance or rejection. Another alter- mestic animal. The object, artwork or animal,
native is that it sustain attention to a subject that does not derive its identity from the character of
is enlightened but remains unresolved.14 the place in which it is found. Public placement
The Vietnam Veterans Memorial seems to en- does, however, make the work available to more
gage its visitors in just such a critical colloquy. people than might otherwise experience it, and,
Constrained by the conditions of the contest she depending upon the extension of legal coverage
won to make a design that was contemplative, to it, the freedom of expression of the artist(s)
harmonious with its site and surroundings, and who made it is more or less protected.'7
that would make no political statement about No more than does its location, the mere inte-
the war, Maya Lin produced a work that evokes gration of art into the ordinary life of people
profound emotions in viewers, whatever their fails to bestow social meaning upon it and does
political sympathies.15 The Vietnam Veterans not render it public. Collaborations that include
Memorial manages to work as public art both artists along with architects and engineers in the
in the traditional sense that it occupies public landscape design and planning of office or hous-
space and memorializes a public event, and in ing projects often end with what have been called
the current sense that it questions the meaning"corporate baubles." These are public in the
of that space and that event and draws the pub- sense that they are inscribed in spaces not usually
lic into intelligent discourse with it. In doing set aside for private art experiences; and they are
this, it brings an additional aspect of publicity art in the sense that their function is chiefly aes-
into focus, that it is multiform and multivalent, thetic, but they neither satisfy the traditional
recalling that the forum is a place for debate- memorializing criteria of public art nor engage
and not just a site for communion or collective citizens in any but the most superficial social
affirmation. Speaking of the work of Lin (and and aesthetic interactions of the public sphere.18
Hans Haacke), Michael North says: It must be recalled that the very places para-
digmatically designated for private aesthetic
[L]t is not the public experience of space but rather viewing, museums and galleries, are public in
public debate that becomes a work of art. They makethat, discounting the increasingly prohibitive
manifest an important truth about public space, that price of entry, they are open to anyone. Yet, even
unless it is embedded in a larger public sphere that were this to guarantee universal access to their
values debate, a public sphere like that defined by contents, the items contained in museums would
Jurgen Habermas in which private people use their not be public art. Although museums were
reason to discuss and reach conclusions, then it will founded to liberate objects previously confined

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Symposium: Public Art Hein, What is Public Art? 5

in private treasuries and to place them in the have a practiced eye and the ability to speak in a
public sphere by declaring them national prop- rich variety of languages-verbal, visual, con-
erty, those objects became "privatized" and ex- ceptual, sensual, serious, humorous, figurative,
tracted from the public sphere by virtue of the and rational. Sometimes and somehow they
very aesthetic appropriation that made them break through ordinary expectation and cause
"museum pieces."19 people to venture upon new perspectives. This is
Being museum art, with all the artworld not because they have made an orbital leap from
anointment that this entails, appears to bar the private to public, but because their insightful ex-
way to an object's having public art status, but pression ignites response. Public art cannot
even that qualification is dissipating. There is promise public understanding, any more than
burgeoning interest now among private muse- private art assures private salvation, whatever
ums and publicly funded art institutions to dis- these might be. We have turned to artists in mo-
play self-designated public art. The exhibits are ments of distress as we formerly turned to reli-
mostly descriptive and conceptual, involving gion, and then to science, for public enlighten-
verbal or pictorial records and documentation of ment and private satisfaction. Each has stirred
ephemeral events that are somewhere else, did up its own problems and given us some gratifi-
happen, or cannot be reproduced. Their public- cation in return. We should not expect consen-
ity is a matter of faith and Xerox machines. Do sus. To cite Patricia Phillips's appreciation of
these representations become private art when public art: "It is an art which is absolutely en-
they are mounted on the walls of the Whitney gaged with the world and this engagement often
Museum or the Institute of Contemporary Art? invokes spirited disagreement.... Absolute con-
Has the public sphere lost its claim to them or sensus is not necessarily a happy state."22 But
has it too been assimilated into the sanctum of perhaps it is a better state than one that con-
the private?20 structs mutual destruction or mutual avoidance
The presence or absence of walls, doors, and as the only alternatives.
columns no longer separates private from public To revert to my initial dilemma, I suggest that
space.21 Indeed, space itself no longer attaches it is private-not public-art that evokes con-
to materiality; and thus whatever material dis- tradiction. Exceeding even the error of aesthetic
placement might have marked their difference enshrinement is the political wrong of negating
no longer distinguishes public from private art's publicity as a site of multiple meaning and
space. Meanings occupy virtual spaces, and communicative exchange. But art is escaping its
traffic through them is subject only to the limits confinement to private sensibility. It is descend-
of fantasy. In fantasy, as Horowitz suggests, a ing into the streets once more and reclaiming its
space can represent powerlessness or liberation, place in the public realm.23
and an ambiguous object can challenge power
or dissolve a dream. The creative display of ob- HILDE HEIN
jects and their deployment for aesthetic pleasure Department of Philosophy
are revealed as politically significant acts. This College of the Holy Cross
is no less true of art heretofore cordoned off as Worcester, Massachusetts 01610-2395
private than of avowedly public art. Both share
as art in a designation meant to depoliticize the INTERNET: HEIN@HCACAD.HOLYCROSS.EDU

concept. By declaring itself "public," public art


points to the impropriety of that characterization
and reclaims the political status of all art. 1. Hannah Arendt describes the public realm as conceived
in antiquity as the common world of reality, in which human
Who speaks for the public? There are many
beings coexist in freedom, a world of politics, history, and
who position themselves in that role-judges,
continuity. The private realm is privative. To enter it is to be
government officials, corporate moneymakers, imprisoned in the subjectivity of singular experience (no
social scientists, and philosopher-critics. Art- matter how often it is replicated by the identical experience
ists, despite their professed asocial status, are of others.) It is to be "deprived of things essential to a truly
human life ... of the reality of being seen and heard by oth-
as deeply engaged in the public sphere as those
ers ... to be deprived of the possibility of achieving some-
whose civic function is ordained by definition. thing more than life itself." See Arendt, The Human Condi-
Artists do not have privileged vision, but they do tion (University of Chicago Press, 1958), p. 58.

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
6 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Jtirgen Habermas describes a later (seventeenth century) art preserves the heroic sublation of "the folk." It was the ge-
sense of public realm that refers to permanent structures of nius of Leni Riefenstahl to create of film an art form that ex-
communication and authority. In this sense, "public" con- alted the ordinary to heroic proportions, inspiring people to
notes state related and controlling, while "private" is a cor- identify with a non-individuated ideal whose magnificent
relative concept referring to those socially significant func- "uebermenschlichkeit" did not seem a contradiction.
tions (and persons who enact them) that are regulated. "The 11. From Goebbels's novel, Michael (1929), cited by
relationship between the authorities and the subjects thereby Michael North, in "The Public as Sculpture: From Heavenly
assumed the peculiar ambivalence of public regulation and City to Mass Ornament," from a prior citation in Elizabeth M.
private initiative." As with Arendt, privacy is conceived pri- Wilkinson and L. A. Willoughby's introduction to Friedrich
vatively. The private person lacks perspective and knowl- Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man (Oxford: Claren-
edge, and is therefore unqualified to take part in social de- don Press, 1982), p. cxlii. See "The Public as Sculpture," in
cision-making. Habermas, The Structural Transformation of Mitchell, ed., Art and the Public Sphere, pp. 9-28.
the Public Sphere. An Inquiry Into a Category of Bourgeois 12. North, "The Public as Sculpture," p. 23.
Society, trans. Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence 13. Douglas Crimp, "Redefining Site Specificity," in On
(MIT Press, 1989), p. 24. the Museum's Ruins (MIT Press, 1993). Another discussion
2. Possibly the most explicit and stirring expression of of a similar instance of site-displaced hostility may be found
this view appears in Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Ed- in James E. Young's account of Sol Lewitt's Black Form, an
ucation of Man, trans. Reginald Snell (Yale University installation in Germany's "Skulptur Projekte 87" to com-
Press, 1954). memorate the missing Jews of MUnster. Like Tilted Arc, this
3. The Bulgarian artist, Christo, likens his wrapping of work attracted graffiti and political slogans and many com-
public buildings and landscapes to the construction of the plaints that it obstructed traffic, and it too was removed
cathedrals. See his video interviews in "Islands," produced barely a year after its dedication. See Young, "The Counter-
by the Maysles Brothers. See also Timothy W. Drescher, San Monument: Memory against Itself in Germany Today," in
Francisco Murals. Community Creates Its Muse, 1914-1990 Mitchell, ed., Art and the Public Sphere, pp. 49-79.
(St. Paul: Pogo Press, 1991) for an analysis of contemporary 14. This, after all, is how most of Plato's dialogues do end.
Latino mural art. 15. Charles L. Griswold, "The Vietnam Veterans Memo-
4. Emblems such as these have been displaced by the rial and the Washington Mall: Philosophical Thoughts on
purely visual logo, unencumbered by historical associations Political Iconography," in Mitchell, ed., Art and the Public
or significance. Sphere, pp. 79-111.
5. W J. T. Mitchell, "The Violence of Public Art," in Art The response is sometimes unsympathetic to Lin. Freder-
and the Public Sphere, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell (University of ick Hart, the producer of the "counter" memorial Three
Chicago Press, 1992), p. 38. Fighting Men. which was installed a year afterward, said of
6. Maya Lin, though only twenty-one at the time and as Lin's memorial that it is "intentionally not meaningful. ... a
yet unknown, was an art student at Yale University, well- serene exercise in contemporary art done in a vacuum with
versed in the same modernist tradition as her older and more no knowledge of the subject. It's nihilistic-that's its ap-
established compatriot, Richard Serra. peal," 'An Interview with Frederick Hart," inset in Elizabeth
7. Detractors took umbrage at its black color, the fact that Hess, 'A Tale of Two Memorials," Art in America 71, no. 4
it "sinks" into the ground, its "unheroic" mass, and the re- (1983): 124.
flective surface that confronts viewers with their own im- 16. North, "The Public as Sculpture," p. 28.
ages superimposed upon the names of the dead. 17. Courts do not regard all places where people gather as
8. "The sculpture as presently located has features of a equally public. Streets and parks have "immemorially been
purpresture ... [:] 'An inclosure by a private person of a part held in trust for the use of the public," but even where the-
of that which belongs to, and ought to be free and open to aters or other assembly sites are owned by governments,
the enjoyment of the public at large,"' Judge Milton Pollack, courts have found that public communication in them may
Richard Serra v. United States General Services Administra-be controlled by different standards. Not every open plaza is
tion, 667 F. Supp. 1042, 1056, n. 7 (S.D.N.Y. 1987), cited also a public forum and not every form of expression is
in Barbara Hoffman, "Law for Art's Sake in the Public equally permitted (Hoffman, "Law for Art's Sake").
Realm," in Mitchell, ed., Art and the Public Sphere, p. 1 6. 18. There are, of course, exceptions to this superficiality.
9. Arthur Danto is a case in point. Writing in favor of the The waterfront development of New York's Battery Park
removal of Tilted Arc, he says: "The public has an interest in City enlisted artists to create an environment that would fos-
the existence of museums, but it also has an interest in not ter neighborly interaction, and a community of sorts has in
having all of its open spaces treated as though they were mu-fact been produced.
seums, in which esthetic [i.e., private] interests rightly dom- Another example of a project that builds civic conscious-
inate. The delicate architectural siting of Tilted Arc in Fed- ness is New York City's Arts for Transit program. Estab-
eral Plaza ignores the human realities of the place. Were he lished in 1985, this program renews a principle intended by
not blind to everything but the esthetic, Serra could learn the planners of the transportation system in 1899: "The rail-
something about human orientation to space and place. way and its equipment ... constitute a great public work. All
Standing where it does, Tilted Arc is the metal grin of the artof the structure where exposed to public sight shall
parts
world having bitten off a piece of the public world, which it therefore be designed, constructed and maintained with a
means to hold in its teeth forever, the public be damned." view to the beauty of their appearance, as well as their effi-
Danto, The State of the Art (New York: Prentice-Hall Press, ciency" (cited from the initial construction contract in the
1987), pp. 93-94. brochure for the Art en Route exhibition, PaineWebber Art
10. Of course there are exceptions. Much of fascist public Gallery, New York, 1994). The contemporary mandate is to

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Symposium: Public Art Hein, What is Public Art? 7

provide the public with an experience that is "interesting, tus of a museum, but is a privately owned corporation, e.g.,
stimulating and aesthetically pleasing." The public is in fact PaineWebber, which opens its reception space to the public
involved in a variety of ways: for an artistic display of artworks-models, maquettes,
a) By sometimes taking part in the selection of projects photographs, and drawings of works of (public) art whose
from among those submitted by artist proposals. realized embodiment as public art can be discovered simply
b) By sometimes contributing to the creative design or by taking a ride on the (public) transportation system.
participating in its execution. 21. The critic, Patricia Phillips, observes that the millions
c) Through commemorative reference to local inhabi- of television viewers of the lighted apple's descent in New
tants, culture, history. York's Times Square New Year's Eve celebration are as much
d) By responsiveness of the art to expressed neighbor- a part of the public spectacle as are the thousands of wit-
hood needs and interests (environmental, political, educa- nesses on the street. Only the meaning of the word "public"
tional). has changed, becoming more "psychologically internalized"
e) Through promotion of public awareness of the art and as a result of developments in urban and information sys-
identification with it. tems. See Phillips, "Public Art's Critical Condition," On
19. Napoleon created the first public museum, the Louvre, View 1, no. 1 (1990): 12.
by nationalizing the formerly private palace and declaring 22. Cited in Pam Korza, "Evaluating Artistic Quality in
its treasures national property. Citizens thereby gained ac- the Public Realm: A Report of the On View Symposium
cess to the collection and could take pride in it, but it was the on Public Art, May 1989, Harvard University," On View 1,
museum and not the art that was rendered public. If any- no. 1 (1990): 76.
thing, the privacy of the aesthetic experience was intensified 23. I would like to thank my co-symposiasts Gregg
by the new emphasis on aesthetic sensibility and the educa- Horowitz and Michael Kelly, as well as the anonymous
bility of individual taste. readers and the editor of this journal for their helpful and in-
20. The complexity of this question is multiplied when cisive criticism.
the exhibiting institution does not even have the public sta-

This content downloaded from 83.56.176.0 on Mon, 29 Oct 2018 14:31:31 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen