Sie sind auf Seite 1von 20

Science Studies 2/2011

In Silico Experiments in Scientific Papers on


Molecular Biology
Sabrina Moretti
This article explores the role of the so-called in silico experiments used in
molecular biology. It is based on the analysis of some papers that present
scientific applications which rely on in silico experiments. By means of this
study I found two basic ways of viewing them. According to the first view,
the in silico experiment is a computer program that realizes some specific
operations: it constitutes some particular experimental conditions, which
allow us to investigate biological phenomena, and which complement those
present in in vivo and in vitro experiments. According to the second view, in silico
experimentation has a different meaning, which corresponds more closely to
the meaning of “simulation”: its identity is linked to that of the “model” used to
construct such simulation. The authors of the analysed papers never express
an intention to standardize a model, so its meaning remains contingent, and
cannot be turned into a technical object.0

Keywords: Molecular biology, in silico experiment, simulation modelling

Introduction scientific practice. Simulation gives rise to


many epistemological discussions, both at
In the last fifty years, the use of computer a general level (cf. Hughes, 1999; Sismondo,
simulation in the field of scientific research 1999; Dahan Dalmedico, 2000; Knuuttila
has become more frequent. Simulation et al., 2006) and in the various scientific
has been used for making predictions, disciplines (cf. Rohrlich, 1991; Galison,
for training purposes, for developing and 1997; Merz, 1999; Keller, 2000; Sunberg,
verifying scientific theories − in particular, 2008; Wieber, 2009).
theories of non-linear, dynamic systems My work will focus on the role of in silico
− by means of the creation of a new experimentation in the field of molecular
interdisciplinary scientific discipline for biology. The term in silico was coined at the
studying complex systems. The results end of the 1980s, to refer to “virtual” exper-
of simulations appear more recurrent in iments existing only “inside” computers.
scientific discussions, political decision- It complements the terms in vivo and in
making processes and the mass media, vitro, characterizing experiments that are
which is why there is now a requirement accomplished, respectively, within a living
for better understanding of their role in

Science Studies, Vol. 24 (2011) No. 2, 23-42 23


Science Studies 2/2011

organism and outside the organism, in a of a systematic study of the textual organi-
controlled environment. zation; the positions that in silico experi-
In the last two decades, the use of in sil- ments take up in the papers and the rela-
ico experimentation has grown consider- tionship they have with the other elements
ably in the field of biology. This growth has that form the text. The starting point of this
been further accelerated by the Human analysis is Rheinberger’s distinction (1997)
Genome Project, which has inspired the between “epistemic things” and “techni-
strategy of recording all structural and cal objects”, two different but insepara-
functional information regarding numer- ble components of experimental systems.
ous biological phenomena, thus creating For Rheinberger, experimental systems
an integrated set of bioinformatics data- are the “smallest integral working units of
bases, many of which are made available to research” (Rheinberger, 1997: 28). They are
everybody via the World Wide Web. Molec- “irrevocably local and situated in space
ular biologists now have at their disposal a and time”, and they allow us to “material-
huge mass of electronically stored data to ize” scientific events. They include “scien-
which a biological meaning must be given. tific objects and the technical conditions
Thus bioinformatics has developed as a of their coming into existence”, which
discipline, with the aim to furnish some Rheinberger calls, respectively, “epistemic
important computational tools with which things” and “technical objects” (Rhein-
to analyse the genome, and to formulate berger, 1997: 28).
new hypotheses about the evolutionary Epistemic things are those entities upon
and functional relationships of biological which the researchers’ questions are con-
elements (Valle et al., 2007). centrated. They function essentially as
The earliest databases containing “question-generating machines” (Rhein-
sequences of nucleic acids date back to the berger, 1997: 32). Epistemic things appear
1980s. These were soon followed by data- with an irreducible vagueness, which is
bases of protein sequences. There is now a inevitable because they incorporate what
huge proliferation of databases gathering we do not know. They are those hidden
the results of many types of research being things that we must bring to light by means
carried out both in the laboratory (in vivo of some sophisticated manipulations.
and in vitro analysis) and through the use Technical objects are those objects that
of computational tools (in silico analysis). form experimental conditions: they func-
The online review Nucleic Acids Research, tion, in essence, as “answering machines”
which each year publishes a list of all data- (Rheinberger, 1997: 32), and belong to the
bases containing molecular biology infor- technical repertoire of an experimental
mation, lists 179 of them in January 2009, setting.
as compared to 84 in January 2008 (Galp- In a particular experimental system,
erin & Cochrane, 2009). both types of things are linked by an inter-
My work is intended to help in under- action and inter-conversion that develop in
standing how the in silico experiment is both time and space. “The technical con-
regarded in the scientific literature of the ditions determine the realm of the possi-
field of molecular biology. It is based on the ble representations of an epistemic thing;
analysis of some papers that propose a sci- and sufficiently stabilized epistemic things
entific application which relies on in silico turn into the technical repertoire of the
experimentation. I will try to understand experimental arrangement” (Rheinberger,
the role of the virtual experiment by means 1997: 29). Therefore, the difference between

24
Sabrina Moretti

an epistemic thing and a technical object that the oscillation among these different
is functional, not structural. It is not pos- places does not follow a temporal dynamic.
sible to define once and for all a distinc- Event generators are not things that are
tion between these two components of a initially epistemic things, which then turn
system. The function of an object depends into technical objects after their use is con-
on the position or “node” (Rheinberger, solidated. They can be, at one and the same
1997: 30) that it takes up in an experimen- time, “the question generating machines”
tal setting. In scientific practice this dis- (Rheinberger, 1997: 32) in a particular set-
tinction of roles is evidently organized, so ting, and “the technical repertoire of the
the text of scientific papers is often divided experimental arrangement” in another
into “materials and methods” (technical (Rheinberger, 1997: 29). Like Knorr Cetina,
things), “results” (halfway-hybrids) and Merz maintains that event generators are
“discussions” (epistemic things) (Rhein- characterized by the “unfolding ontol-
berger, 1997: 30). ogy of knowledge objects. [Because they]
Knorr Cetina (1997) maintains that are always in a process of being materi-
Rheinberger’s equation of instruments ally defined, they continually acquire
with technological objects is not fair. new properties and change the ones they
Indeed, advanced technologies, such as have” (Knorr Cetina, 2001: 180). Event gen-
computers and computer programs, “are erators can be perceived by the physicists
simultaneously things-to-be-used and using them as objects with a multiplicity of
things-in-a-process-of-transformation” aspects.
(Knorr Cetina, 1997: 10), thus placing them Sundberg (2008) analyses the use of
in the class of epistemic things. Knuuttila simulation models in meteorology. She
and Voutilainen argue, in turn, that “mod- maintains that the role of simulation is
els can be treated as epistemic artifacts related to the relationship between the
from the scientific practice point of view. object and the people engaging with it.
As epistemic artifacts, scientific models She distinguishes two types of relation-
are open to different interpretations and ship: the development and the use of a
uses, functioning as both tools and objects simulation model. In the first case, such a
of inquiry” (Knuuttila & Voutilainen, 2003: model takes the role of an epistemic thing,
1485). because it is in a process of transformation,
Merz (1999) and Sundberg (2008) use the and is consistently changed and improved.
concepts of “epistemic things” and “tech- In the phase of utilization, the simulation
nological objects” to analyse the role of can take the role of either a technological
computer simulations in particle physics object or an epistemic thing.
and meteorology respectively. Merz (1999) Keller (2000) discusses the role of
focuses on “event generators” used by models in molecular biology, consider-
physicists: types of software that simulate ing the dichotomy between theoretical
mechanisms of particle production. She and experimental science. She focuses, in
maintains that event generators accom- particular, on a computational model for
plish different tasks depending on differ- gene regulation, derived from the experi-
ent work settings and different actors. Each mental work of Eric Davidson and his col-
local setting requires, of these objects, a leagues at Caltech (Yuh et al., 1998). The
specific function, meaning or viewpoint, model is based on the metaphor of the
to enable them to occupy different places. “genetic computer”. Such a metaphor has
But, unlike Rheinberger, Merz insists a conceptual role, not only in the sense of

25
Science Studies 2/2011

directing the attention and perception of functions of the so-called in silico experi-
the researchers, but also in the sense of ments. In particular, my objective is to
guiding the material manipulation in the understand the different roles of in silico
different types of laboratories (biological, experimentation as they are presented in
computational and industrial), and for var- the scientific papers on molecular biol-
ious types of aims (theory development, ogy. These roles depend on the objectives
laboratory tools and commercial prod- of each paper, and on the way in which in
ucts). Keller concludes that the theoreti- silico experiments relate to all other ele-
cal propositions in the applied sciences, ments of the discussion. I am interested
such as molecular biology, concern mainly in the identity of in silico experiments
means and ends rather than the “truth”. emerging in these papers. In particu-
Such means and ends are specific, local lar, I wish to analyse the level of detail in
and specialized. Attention is shifted away which they are described, how they are
from the validity of the different represen- related to more traditional experiments,
tations of reality, and towards questions and how their usage is justified. Usually, a
regarding the preference for certain types scientific paper is subdivided into various
of intervention rather than others (Keller, parts, each of which has a precise role. The
2000: S85). central part generally shows results, while
Wieber (2009) deals with simulation the final part focuses on discussions. The
in the field of protein structures. He calls “methods” section lists all methods and
simulation technologies “theoretical tech- techniques used in the work. Some supple-
nologies”, and maintains that, thanks to mentary files may report certain technical
their nature, they have been added to the details, figures, tables, etc. The analysis of
traditional toolbox used by experiment- the structure of a paper can be useful for
ers to analyse and interpret empirical data understanding the position of the given in
relating to molecular structures, leading to silico experiment in relation to other ele-
a focus on dynamic, as opposed to static, ments, and the meaning that it can assume
structures. in the presented work.
Hine (2006) describes an ethnographi- Obviously, document analysis has its
cal research on the use of databases in limits, and it does not allow us to evaluate
molecular biology. The research has the fully the use of simulation in biology. A sci-
objective of understanding how data- entific paper is not a research report, even
bases influence the scientific practices though it is often considered as such. That
and modes of communication. She con- is to say, it is not a faithful and detailed
cludes that databases do not cause a radi- account of the activities in the laboratory.
cal transformation in scientific practices, It hides the “contingent situational logic”
but instead make small-scale changes to of the laboratory. Indeed, it represents a
working practices. They do not give rise to genuine process of transformation and
a new and distinct epistemic culture, but recontextualization that misrepresents the
can be considered as additional resources reality of the research (Knorr Cetina, 1981).
that enter into an already existent research Document analysis does not reveal how
culture. this transformation process is realized,
In what follows I will study the link and therefore does not allow us to under-
between epistemic questions and needs stand completely just how in silico experi-
of application, suggested by the aforemen- ments are incorporated in the contingent
tioned studies, in the field of computa- day-to-day activities of the laboratory.
tional biology. I will focus on the various However, the scientific paper is paramount

26
Sabrina Moretti

in scientific practice, not because it col- My initial intention was to analyse all
lects and imparts information, but because papers in the field of biology that make ref-
it represents “institutionally authorized erence to in silico experiments, but I dis-
enunciation of scientific truth” (Frohm- covered that most of these papers relate
ann, 1999: 72). The scientific paper repre- to molecular biology, and that the use of
sents the public face of scientists, and so, in silico experiments in other branches
through the analysis of its formal commu- of biology – such as systems biology and
nicative modalities, it is possible to identify genetics – is presented in a very different
these aspects. Through my work, I intend way. This seems to be due to the fact that,
to understand how the in silico experiment compared with other fields, molecular
is received and accepted by the scientific biology is much more closely linked to the
community, and what role it plays in the epistemic culture based on conventional
public conception of molecular biology; laboratory experimentation. Because of
what is assumed in a non-problematic this, I took into consideration only molecu-
way within a scientific culture, and what lar biology.
are the aspects that lead us to consider The papers were selected by means of
an assertion valid (in the sense of being the search facility provided by the website
shared by the scientific community). of the journal: www.nature.org. I used the
My analysis shows that the in silico following search expressions: “molecular
experiment is accepted whenever it is in biology” and “in silico”, and I chose only
keeping with the practices already in use, those papers published between January
and that there are essentially two different 2000 and October 2008. The search facility
ways in which it is linked to the traditional revealed 120 papers that matched the cri-
activities of the laboratory. Moreover, in teria. I initially selected only “articles” and
silico experiments allow scientists to work “letters”, before eliminating all papers in
on particular “disposable” arrangements which the expression “in silico” appeared
of epistemic things that are used locally to only in the bibliography or in captions. I
generate new theoretical reflections con- then added another four papers found by
sidered as useful in a specific context. We means of bibliographical references. I was
thus see a continuous de-contextualiza- thus left with 48 papers actually present-
tion and re-conceptualization of epistemic ing applications that use so-called “in silico
things that generate a multiplicity of new experiments”.
and provisional epistemic formations. Most of these papers can be subdivided
into two classes:
In Silico Experiments
Type 1 applications using bioinformatics
This work is based on the analysis of 48 technologies, in order to analyse
papers, published in the years 2000–2008, the DNA of some organisms;
presenting some applications in the field of Type 2 applications aiming to study
molecular biology based on in silico exper- metabolic networks and networks
iments. Because I wish to analyse how they of genomic regulation.
are received by scientists, I have chosen,
as my source, the journal Nature, which The papers of Type 1 present some applica-
is considered prestigious and authorita- tions that analyse the DNA of some specific
tive by the scientific community, and used chromosomes of living organisms, in order
by scientists who wish to be recognized to find or compare genomic sequences for
widely. analysing the causes of given diseases. In

27
Science Studies 2/2011

simple terms, these applications are devel- the biological material. The plausibility of
oped on the basis of the results of a series the use of these techniques rises directly
of in vivo and in vitro experiments on some from the assumption that working with
fragments of biological DNA that produce sequences of nucleic acids is exactly the
some sequences of nucleic acids repre- same thing as working with sequences of
sented by a set of symbolic codes. These corresponding symbolic codes. The fact
sequences of symbols are explored heu- that a gene can be considered a sequence
ristically by means of algorithms that find of information-carrying symbols auto-
patterns, motifs or statistical regularities, matically enables the application of
or similarities and homologies with some some operations for working on symbols.
genomic sequences of other organisms These operations are defined and used
already recorded in public databases. In in non-biological contexts; they are usu-
spite of the complexity of these processes, ally instruments supplied by mathemat-
some methods of exploration have been ics, statistics and computer science. All
defined, based on statistical algorithms or experiments on genome sequences work
some typical artificial intelligence tech- simultaneously both on a living organism,
niques, giving rise to a set of programs or a part of it, and on its digital represen-
used by numerous researchers. The choice tation. So, we see that the outputs of an in
among different methods depends upon vivo or in vitro manipulation, using mark-
the results that they produce; often almost ers, X-rays or other particular instruments,
all of the methods are used simultaneously. often become the inputs of a program that
In the text of these papers some phases will filter the data, delivering the final
of sequencing are described, and all tech- results in an electronic format. In silico
niques used both in vivo and in silico experiments allow scientists to work on
are listed. Generally, there is some dis- a “symbolic” gene, whereas in vivo and in
cussion about specific characteristics of vitro experiments work directly on a mate-
the genome, and about how this knowl- rial object. Indeed, the function of digital
edge could be used in a medical field. In computation in an experimental context
the “methods” section, authors refer to is precisely to infer new knowledge from
some web sites for technical details – for symbolic sequences constituting DNA.
example, methods for the construction of All the papers of Type 2 that I have
sequence-ready maps and for sequencing analysed are based on the definition of
large insert clones by shotgun cloning, use a model of the metabolism of some liv-
of selectable markers – where it may also ing organisms – generally Escherichia
be possible to find some programs used to Coli, Drosophila and yeasts. Metabolic
conduct in silico experiments. structures are conceived, in the mod-
In spite of the frequent use of the words els, as networks composed of nodes and
in silico and simulation in Type 1 papers, links. The elements of these networks are
these applications cannot be said to be certain selected elements of molecular
true simulations as such, if by “simula- biology – genes, enzymes, proteins, etc.
tion” we intend the reproduction of a proc- – linked together by means of mathemati-
ess or a mechanism that causes a specific cal relationships. Often, these models are
empirical phenomenon. The authors of constraint-based, derived from the laws of
these papers mention in silico experiments thermodynamics, the law of mass action,
because their analysis is based on an “arti- or other deterministic or stochastic mod-
ficial” element, rather than directly on els. Sometimes these models are defined

28
Sabrina Moretti

by a set of differential equations express- An in silico experiment is the simulation


ing the rate of change of a given concentra- of a model. In these papers there are two
tion as the sum or product of more or less different modalities to refer to simulations:
empirical terms (for example, the power
law terms, or the law of mass action terms). 2.1 Some papers base their discussion on
The definition of a model always begins comparison between the results of
with an exploration of various databases simulations and the results of in vivo
and of the specific literature, in order to or in vitro experiments. What is impor-
identify those biological elements that are tant in a model is its forecasting capa-
interesting, and to define all the logical or bility by means of interpreting results
mathematical functions representing their obtained from simulations, and their
links. For example, if we need to define a agreement with some data from in vivo
metabolic network of a particular organ- or in vitro experiments: if there are
ism, we must find the list of metabolites some inconsistencies between predic-
and enzymatic reactions, and also identify tions and experimental data, it means
and consult the literature that deals with that this model, which furnishes a
flux balance analysis. Generally, several theoretical interpretation of biological
sources are used, sometimes of various systems functioning, is wrong, and so
types, which must always be readapted to also are the theoretical concepts that
construct the specific model. form the basis of its definition; if its
The construction of a model is based on results are consistent, this model can
a series of choices that depend upon the be used to make some counterfactual
application in hand. This process might experiments and, more generally, to
be likened to the solving of a jigsaw puz- infer new knowledge. On the basis of
zle, putting together theoretical concepts its predictive capability, it is possible
and pieces of other models that some- to indicate knowledge gaps and iden-
times have very different properties. Each tify previously unknown components
researcher has at his or her disposal a large and interactions in the regulatory and
quantity of databases and models describ- metabolic networks that the model
ing different aspects of biological proc- represents. These papers, then, focus
esses by means of stochastic techniques, above all on the performance of a
differential equations, Boolean networks, model.
neural networks, and so on. There are sev- 2.2 In other papers, authors focus on
eral formalisms and meta-models availa- the structure and the characteris-
ble, so the final work is a hybrid originating tics of a model. In essence, a model
from various different approaches. is explored; all resulting remarks are
In essence, there are no established then used to obtain new informa-
rules to define the construction of a model. tion about the functioning of cells.
All choices made by researchers depend As we have already seen, all models
on various, often contingent, factors: the use the concept of “network” to rep-
objectives, the available data, the previous resent the fundamental functions
research, the results of other experiments. of metabolism. The characteristics
Frequently no justification is put forward of this abstract structure, formed by
for these choices. nodes, links, pathways, flows, etc., can
help scientists to better understand
some biological functions. All papers

29
Science Studies 2/2011

assigned to this category describe the and handled by a computer. Beginning in


model by means of a graphical visu- the 1970s, cloning and sequencing tech-
alization of a network. Therefore, in niques led to the representation of molecu-
these papers, the models’ structure lar structures in general, and genes in par-
is of principal interest, and not their ticular, as a “literal open reading frame of
performance. In essence, we have sequence – digitized data, in other words”
moved one step forward from case (Searls, 2010: 2). The possibility of rep-
2.1. Here, the representative capabil- resenting biological data in digital form
ity of a model is not discussed directly, has allowed their storage and circula-
although it may be mentioned briefly. tion through databases that have caused
The authors begin with the presup- a “change in how biological knowledge
position that the model is able to rep- is constructed”; a database makes “data
resent a given biological object. So, accessible to other research contexts and
results obtained from its simulations therefore potentially reusable as evidence
can be meaningfully associated with for new claims, and it associates data with
the system that it represents. a broader range of phenomena” (Leonelli,
2009: 746).
These two distinct ways of referring to in Another important concept is “model”,
vivo or in vitro experiments sometimes in the specific sense of a simulation model.
appear together in the same paper. In According to Morgan and Morrison, mod-
such cases, at the beginning they focus els serve “both as a means to and as a
on the relationship between in silico and source of knowledge” (Morgan & Morri-
in vivo, or in vitro, results, and then, when son, 1999: 35). Scientists work on certain
the model is validated, they show some representations defined by means of some
virtual experiments used to obtain new tools that impose an interpretation, from a
knowledge. particular point of view, of their objects of
study: “the model functions as representa-
Epistemic Things and tive of one or more phenomena as well as
Technical Objects representative for a given theory” (Leonelli,
2007: 17). Both data and model are rep-
From the analysis of these papers, it resentations. Data represent a structure,
emerges that the expression “in silico something that can be identified with a
experiment” denotes a scientific practice list of all properties that characterize it,
that performs some manipulations on a whereas a model represents also a mech-
computational representation, rather than anism that is able to transform data. A
directly on a material object. It is a vir- model is made in such a way that it can be
tual experiment that does not substitute, translated into a code by means of a pro-
however, but instead supports traditional gramming language.
experiments. The model not only has a representa-
An in silico experiment is fundamentally tive function, but also provides “the kind
a computational object, and it is worth- of information that allows us to intervene
while examining the meaning of some of in the world” (Morgan & Morrison, 1999:
its underlying concepts. 23). Indeed, models have numerous practi-
We may begin with the concept of “data”. cal functions, such as suggesting possible
In computer science, data are objects that experiments, helping to predict conse-
codify information that can be described quences of given interventions and sug-

30
Sabrina Moretti

gesting new questions to ask (Keller, 2000: Papers refer to them only by means of their
S78). name and the type of processing they are
Finally, a simulation is the elaboration able to make. We know the type of calcula-
of a program that translates a model. Its tion they make, but nobody is interested in
input is a set of data, and it produces other all the modalities through which they real-
output data that constitute the results ize their result. They constitute some par-
of this simulation. According to Parker ticular experimental conditions, more or
(2009), computer simulation studies – less standardized, that allow us to investi-
studies based on a series of simulations gate the structure of DNA. Such conditions
– have all the characteristics of the tradi- complement those present in in vivo and in
tional experiment in as much as they imply vitro experiments. The identity of an in sil-
an intervention activity. They allow us to ico experiment is determined by programs
study the consequences of changes applied that realize some specific operations. Ele-
to a system. For Parker, they are “mate- ments that come into play are input data
rial” experiments in the real sense of the and functions that allow us to acquire
word, because they involve the behaviour new output data. The definition of these
of a physical/material system – namely, functions agrees with the software that
the programmed digital computer. The realizes them; in fact, whenever papers
observed behaviour of the system is the mention some computational operations,
result of such experiments. That is to say, they always refer to the name of a com-
the material/physical system of the com- puter program, both in their “methods”
puter constitutes the experimental setting. sections, where experimental conditions
If we consider the relationship between are described in detail, and in their main
data, model, program and simulation, we part. The validity of these programs is not
can say that for each model we may have questioned. There are no bibliographic ref-
several programs, because the transla- erences to papers that describe the model
tion of a model into a code can occur in that forms the basis of their definition, or
different ways. A program, in its turn, can which discuss their potentiality or limita-
give rise to numerous simulations, each tions. For the most part there is only a ref-
of which is its elaboration with a distinct erence to a web site where it is possible to
set of input data. The description of each download the program1. These programs
model specifies the types of data on which do not define actual experimental proc-
the model works, whereas each simulation esses, but are, rather, types of tool, used
has specific data as its input. in experimental practice, along with other
My analysis of the papers reveals that tools necessary for material manipulation.
papers of Type 1 never refer to simulation In all papers of Type 2, the expression “in
models. Data are the representation of the silico experiment” has a different meaning,
epistemic thing; they are interpreted as a and it agrees with the meaning of “set of
sequence of DNA. In silico experimentation simulations”. Each paper refers to a partic-
involves manipulation of data by means ular model, different from all the others. In
of some computer operations. Programs reality, each model is complex, because it
are chosen on the basis of some particular is a composition of other, simpler, models,
objectives. Generally these programs are following a hierarchic structure. Discus-
not based on a model of a target system, but sion mostly concerns the definition of the
are, rather, algorithms for analysing data; complex model, whereas the simpler mod-
they are black boxes that transform data. els that compose it are only mentioned,

31
Science Studies 2/2011

and their description is deferred to other The core of the paper does not regard the
papers. For example, in a model describ- theoretical principles that form the basis
ing a series of metabolic pathways, chemi- of each model, but is concerned, instead,
cal reactions are represented by means of with the degree of the model’s agreement
stoichiometry, but often stoichiometric with inscriptions obtained in other ways.
equations are not shown; only reagents Usually, in this type of discussion the
and products that constitute the nodes of model is not described in a detailed man-
this network are specified. In these papers, ner; some bibliographic references are
models are representations of some meta- included, where it is possible to find some
bolic networks, and are therefore inscrip- details and justifications of the choices of
tions that allow us to visualize the invis- authors. Therefore these papers focus on
ible. Unlike simple “maps”, simulation “simulations” rather than on “models”.
models are “dynamic”. They show those parameters associated
As above, a reference to a model can fol- with a model that represents some specific
low two different modalities. In case 2.1. of initial conditions; they obtain outputs and
the foregoing paragraph, a model repre- then compare them with data originating
sents some assumptions of a theory, and from in vivo or in vitro experiments. This
simulation has to verify them by means of comparison is realized by means of some
a comparison with data obtained through charts that contain, simultaneously, the
other experimental conditions – namely, representations of results of both a simu-
in vivo or in vitro experiments. Papers that lation and some in vivo or in vitro experi-
follow this modality focus mostly on an ments. In essence, the objective is to estab-
analysis of the relationship between simu- lish a relationship between the “in silico
lation results and experimental results. experiment”, on the one hand, and the “in
vivo or in vitro experiment”, on the other,
[T]he simulations show significant so as to consider the former a valid substi-
agreement with experimental results, tution of the latter and then to render the
thus establishing the utility of the model theoretical model underlying the “in silico
(Alvarez-Vasquez et al., 2005: 429). experiment” legitimate. In “methods” sec-
tions and in “supplementary” files, the
As can be seen in Fig. 3b–g, the agree- structure and the construction of a model
ment between the behaviour predicted are described, but often in a very generic
by the model and the experimental manner. Normally, databases, mathemati-
results is very good, validating the cal and statistical functions and programs
bottom-up approach to understanding are listed, or some bibliographic references
gene regulatory networks (Guido et al., are given, to enable the reader to find a
2006: 858). detailed description elsewhere. In these
sections, descriptions are always found,
Comparison with the growth pheno- both of simulations with regard to initial
types showed that experimental and conditions and some particular situations
computational outcomes agreed in of each application of model, and of in vivo
10,828 (78.7%) of the cases examined, or in vitro experiments.
which is roughly the same success rate In modalities shown in case 2.2., mod-
achieved in previous studies in E. coli els again represent some assumptions of
and yeast that considered only a few a theory, but simulations aim to infer new
hundred phenotype (Covert et al., 2004: theoretical propositions. Papers focus on
94). some intrinsic characteristics of models.

32
Sabrina Moretti

Their elements are always described in a The identity of the in silico experiment
rather detailed manner in the central part depends on the model rather than on the
of the text, almost always with accompa- simulation; it is the referent of the meta-
nying graphical visualizations that render bolic network of a particular living system.
their understanding more intuitive. In Papers of Type 2.2 discuss, above all, some
“methods” sections and, above all, in “sup- elements that constitute the model, and
plementary” files, some details of models how the in silico experiment allows us to
are described – functions used to repre- analyse the theoretical mechanisms that
sent the links between the components of a underlie a particular process. In papers of
network, objective functions, linear equa- Type 2.1, by contrast, the discussion cen-
tions for constraints systems, logical rules tres on the performance of the simulation,
in logico-mathematical systems (such as on its results, and on the correspondence
Boolean networks), and so on – and the with results obtained by means of in vivo
list of databases from which authors have and in vitro experiments.
extracted data and programs to define and To conclude, we maintain that in papers
simulate models. Simulations assume dif- of Type 1 the in silico experiment is a
ferent roles in cases 2.1 and 2.2. In case 2.1., “technical object”, an experimental con-
authors focus on “results” that the simu- dition that is added and mixed with other
lation produces, whereas in case 2.2. they conditions that are part of traditional
concentrate on its internal mechanisms. It experiment.
becomes an experiment on the theory that By contrast, in all situations described
underlies the definition of the model. in papers of Type 2, the in silico experiment
is used to analyse metabolic networks in
Using an in silico representation of the order to find new knowledge on them. The
metabolic network of Escherichia coli, experiment consists of the manipulation
we examine the role of contingency by of a model, in an experimental setting pro-
repeatedly simulating the successive vided by the computer system. A model
loss of genes while controlling for the arises from a reconfiguration of some epis-
environment (Pál et al., 2006: 667). temic things in a new context. It allows
scientists to generate new questions, and
Under laboratory conditions 80% of thus becomes a new “question-generating
yeast genes seem not to be essential machine”.
for viability. This raises the question of In case 2.1., authors wish to create a
what the mechanistic basis for dispen- relationship between a new object and
sability is, and whether it is the result another well-known and well-established
of selection for buffering or an inciden- object; they seek to prove that the in silico
tal side product. Here we analyse these experiment is representative of the in vivo
issues using an in silico flux mode of the or in vitro experiment. In essence, they
yeast metabolic network (Papp et al., aim to represent an epistemic thing in a
2004: 661). new way, and then to define the shift from
a graphematic space to another one (cf.
Here, we devise a theoretical method for Rheinberger, 1997: 102–13). Mathemati-
simultaneously predicting key aspects cal, statistical and computational tools –
of network functionality, robustness such as linear equations, the Montecarlo
and gene regulation from network method, stoicometric equations, program-
structure alone (Stelling et al., 2002: ming language, and so on – allow the defi-
190).

33
Science Studies 2/2011

nition of models and their simulation, in The network that resulted is a func-
turn allowing this new representation. tional description of the eukaryotic pro-
In case 2.2., the in silico experiment has teome at a higher level of organization.
to analyse metabolic networks and find Such higher-order maps will bring an
new knowledge about them. The result- increasing quality to our appreciation
ing epistemic thing, now reconfigured of biological systems. It is expected that
in a new context, allows the generation this may provide drug discovery pro-
of new questions. The representation of a grammes with a molecular context for
metabolic network by means of a model the choice and evaluation of drug tar-
involves a reconfiguration of this object, gets (Gavin et al., 2002: 146).
so that it can then be manipulated by com-
puter simulations. The in silico experiment The reprogramming of DNA-binding
allows scientists to query epistemic things specificity is an important challenge for
in new contexts. computational protein design that tests
As observed above, the authors in my current understanding of protein-DNA
sample never express an intention to recognition, and has considerable prac-
standardize a model. It therefore remains tical relevance for biotechnology and
contingent and short-lived, and it cannot medicine (Ashworth et al., 2006: 656).
be turned into a technical object.
Each model is a partial point of view [W]e hope to elucidate biological func-
of a specific phenomenon; one among all tion as well as predict the effect of inter-
possible points of view. Therefore a way of nal perturbations (for example, genetic
identifying a modality of selection that is mutations) or external perturbations
convincing to the scientific community is (for example, drugs) so that disease
needed. The pragmatic function accom- treatments are more precise and effec-
plishes this task. The rhetorical strategies tive. Similarly, understanding biological
used by authors to justify the use of in silico modules and being able to engineer new
experiments try to show that a simulation ones will pave the way for re-engineer-
has some meaning if it pursues a prag- ing of organisms and cells for numerous
matic objective. A model presents a par- applications (including medical, agri-
ticular interpretation of a target system. It cultural and ecological situations) (Di
does not have the same aim as that of the Ventura et al., 2006: 532)2.
universal laws of physics, for example, but
it is valid if it is able to intervene usefully in The epistemic value of models derives
empirical reality. The pragmatic objective from their capacity to increase the future
determines the level of observation, allow- “manipulability” of biological material.
ing the isolation of its essential function Each model and its simulations allow us to
(Negrotti, 1997). In particular, frequent ref- analyse some particular aspect of an epis-
erences appear regarding the contribution temic thing, and to obtain new informa-
to medical and pharmaceutical research: tion, some of which can then be used in in
vivo or in vitro experiments. We may add
[I]t is possible that discriminating that the validity of a model or a simulation
between date and party hubs might also does not depend on its capacity to repre-
help to define new therapeutic drug tar- sent an exemplar well, but rather on its
gets (Han et al., 2004: 92). ability to manage and modify living mat-
ter. That is why authors often try to demon-

34
Sabrina Moretti

strate that the manipulation of models by practices, considering, in particular, the


means of simulations can be reproduced in case of the in silico experiment. To do this,
the corresponding physical objects, or can I considered the concepts of “epistemic
be a useful guide to physical handling (in thing” and “technical object” defined by
the sense that the simulation gives some Rheinberger (1997). I discovered that in
information about structures and proc- silico experiments are regarded in sev-
esses of epistemic things). eral different ways that are fundamentally
reducible to two basic types. In papers of
Concluding Remarks Type 1, the in silico experiment allows us to
operate on it by means of some tools that,
The studies on the use of databases and in some cases, are simply new experimen-
simulation models in biology indicate that tal conditions that we can place alongside
these new technologies need not lead to traditional conditions, in order to obtain
the birth of new epistemic cultures, they new data of a functionally equivalent type.
rather add new resources inserted into the In essence, the scientists use new tools in
already consolidated research practices. order to be able to work on data presented
The use of the metaphor of “information” in digital form. Such tools supplement
has led to the construction of new repre- those that characterize the traditional
sentations of nature, which involve also experimental setting. As Wieber (2009)
the discursive and material practices (Kay, says, the in silico experiment has become a
2000). This transformation, though, does part of the toolbox used by molecular biol-
not spark a revolution that brings about ogists to elaborate and interpret empirical
new visions of the world, but instead tends data.
to reflect the natural and social orders that In Type 2 papers, the in silico experi-
already exist (Hine, 2006; Wieber, 2009). ment is introduced with many different
The use of simulation models is, how- functions: it is the set of simulations that
ever, always orientated towards material manipulate a model, given the experimen-
manipulation, following practical aims. tal conditions provided by the computer
For this reason, scientists are interested system. A model has the role of locally
in demonstrating, not the “validity” of the reshaping some different epistemic things
models, but their “utility” (Keller, 2000). and creating new ones. The meaning of
Scientists choose their models on the basis such a model is contingent, as is, a forti-
of their ability to satisfy particular practi- ori, the meaning of “simulation”. A model
cal and theoretical exigencies, and to reach is the product of a theoretical reflection of
specific objectives. The models are tools to researchers regarding a particular biologi-
aid “thinking” and also “doing”, allowing cal phenomenon. This reflection can give
scientists to reflect upon and modify the rise to a visible object that can act and cre-
theory, and also to intervene materially. In ate new question-generating machines. In
my analysis, this aspect is confirmed by the this way, we observe a proliferation of epis-
fact that the authors of the papers justify temic things that make the scientific con-
the validity of their models by their ability text most varied and non-standardized.
to manage and modify living systems. As a matter of fact, each model is only
Analysing the scientific papers on partial. It embodies only one particular
molecular biology may help us to under- vision of a biological phenomenon. The
stand better how the new computational objective of researchers is not to create a
technologies may be inserted into research standard model that they can use and re-

35
Science Studies 2/2011

use in different contexts, but only to rear- multiplicity of new and provisional forms
range locally various epistemic things, when they are recombined.
following a theoretical reflection. Indeed, The aforementioned points arise from
only rarely are models recorded in a shared the analysis of how scientists present their
database. They always constitute some work for the scientific audience, reflect-
partial visions of an object, and we do not ing the public face of molecular biology. A
come across any work aiming to stand- deeper understanding of in silico experi-
ardize models. Each paper begins with a ments in molecular biology should take
particular problem, and it defines a model into account also the processes that gen-
relating to this problem, starting from a erate and define their criteria of inclu-
series of assumptions that will render the sion, acceptance and validity. This would
model just one of many possible models require the use of other methods that ana-
able to represent the object in question. lyse the everyday practices of scientists,
In this sense, models do not follow the and study how in silico experiments are
dynamics described by Rheinberger, who inserted into the existing social and episte-
sees objects as oscillating between epis- mological contexts.
temic things and technical objects (Rhein-
berger, 1997). This depends not only on the Notes
open nature of the object, as Merz (1999)
maintains, but also on its contingency; 0
This article was edited and approved for
it is accepted for the moment for its prag- publication by Tarja Knuuttila.
matic value, because it is useful in some 1
Only in one of the papers analysed did
particular type of application, but then it the authors use a program specifically
disappears, and never reappears as a tech- created for their application. Yet even in
nical object. The modelling of a system this case there was no discussion about
is not intended to lead to the discovery of the definition of the algorithm that
the truth, and therefore to the construc- formed the basis of this program; in the
tion of mutually coherent models, but must “methods” section it was described very
be useful for the material manipulation. perfunctorily in a few lines.
The pragmatic function, as Keller (2000) 2
This paper is not one of the 48 papers ana-
says, guides the use of models. In silico lysed, because it does not describe an
experiments allow us to work on particu- application using in silico experimenta-
lar arrangements of epistemic things that tion, but presents, rather, a review of the
we can define as “disposable”, because use of in silico experiments in molecular
they are partial and subjective “interpre- biology.
tations” of the object that we are studying.
Consequently, in silico experiments are References
used locally to generate new theoretical
reflections that are useful in a specific con- Alvarez-Vasquez, F., K.J. Sims, L.A. Cow-
text. This new knowledge will successively art, Y.O. Okamoto, E. Voit & Y.A. Han-
be redefined and used in other contexts, nun (2005) ‘Simulation and validation
through the definition of new models and of modelled sphingolipid metabolism in
new simulations. We thus see a continuous Saccharomyces cerevisiae’, Nature 433:
de-contextualization and re-conceptual- 425-30.
ization of epistemic things that generate a Ashworth, J., J.J. Havranek, C.M. Duarte,
D. Sussman, R.J. Monnat, B.L. Stoddard

36
Sabrina Moretti

& D. Baker (2006) ‘Computational rede- Elston & J.J. Collins (2006) ‘A bottom-up
sign of endonuclease DNA binding and approach to gene regulation’, Nature
cleavage specificity’, Nature 441: 656-9. 439: 856-60.
Covert, M.W., E.M. Knight, J.L. Reed, M.J. Han, J.J., N. Bertin, T. Hao, D.S. Goldberg,
Herrgard & B.O. Palsson (2004) ‘Inte- G.F. Berriz, L.V. Zhang, D. Dupuy, A.J.M.
grating high-throughput and compu- Walhout, M.E. Cusick, F.P. Roth et al.
tational data elucidates bacterial net- (2004) ‘Evidence for dynamically organ-
works’, Nature 429: 92-6. ized modularity in the yeast protein–
Dahan Dalmedico, A. (2000) ‘Between protein interaction network’, Nature
Models as Structures and Models as Fic- 430: 88-93.
tions: Computer Modeling Practices in Hine, C. (2006) ‘Databases as Scientific
post World War II’, paper presented at Instruments and Their Role in the
the Princeton Workshop on Model Sys- Ordering of Scientific Work’, Social
tems, Cases and Exemplary Narratives, Studies of Science 36(2): 269-98.
12 February 2000, in Princeton, N.J. Hughes, R.I.G. (1999) ‘The Ising Model,
Di Ventura, B., C. Lemerle, K. Michalodim- Computer Simulation, and Universal
itrakis & L. Serrano (2006) ‘From in vivo Physics’, in M.S. Morgan & M. Morrison
to in silico biology and back’, Nature (eds), Models as mediators: perspectives
443: 527-33. on natural and social science (Cam-
Frohmann, B. (1999) ‘The Role of the Scien- bridge: Cambridge University Press):
tific Paper in Science Information Sys- 97-145.
tems’, in M.E. Bowden, T.B. Hahn & R. Kay, L.E. (2000) Who Wrote the Book of
Williams (eds), History of Information Life?: A History of the Genetic Code
Science: Proceedings of the 1998 Con- (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University
ference on the History and Heritage of Press).
Science Information Systems (Medford Keller, E.F. (2000) ‘Models of and Models
NJ: Information Today): 63-73. for: Theory and Practice in Contempo-
Galison, P. (1997) Image and Logic: A Mate- rary Biology’, Philosophy of Science 67,
rial Culture of Microphysics (Chicago, Supplement. Proceedings of the 1998
IL: University of Chicago Press). Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of
Galperin, M.Y. & G.R. Cochrane (2009) Science Association. Part II: Symposia
‘Nucleic Acids Research annual Data- Papers: S72-S86.
base Issue and the NAR online Molec- Knorr Cetina, K. (1981) The manufacture of
ular Biology Database Collection in knowledge: An essay on the construc-
2009’, Nucleic Acids Research 37, http:// tivist and contextual nature of science
nar.ox fordjournals.org/cgi/content/ (Oxford: Pergamon).
abstract/37/suppl_1/D1 (accessed 20 Knorr Cetina, K. (1997) ‘Sociality with
December 2009). objects: Social relations in postsocial
Gavin, A., M. Bösche, R. Krause, P. Grandi, knowledge societies’, Theory, Culture
M. Marzioch, A. Bauer, J. Schultz, J.M. and Society 14(4): 1-30.
Rick, A.M. Michon, C.M. Cruciat et al. Knorr Cetina, K. (2001) ‘Objectual prac-
(2002) ‘Functional organization of the tice’, in T.R. Schatzki, K. Knorr Cetina
yeast proteome by systematic analysis of & E. von Savigny (eds), The practice
protein complexes’, Nature 415: 141-7. turn in contemporary theory (London:
Guido, N.J., X. Wang, D. Adalsteinsson, Routledge): 175-88.
D. McMillen, J. Hasty, C.R. Cantor, T.C. Knuuttila, T. & A. Voutilainen (2003) ‘A
Parser as an Epistemic Artifact: A Mate-

37
Science Studies 2/2011

rial View on Models’, Philosophy of Sci- Sismondo, S. (1999) ‘Modeling and Simula-
ence 70(5): 1484-95. tion’, Science in Context, Special Issue
Knuuttila, T., M. Merz & E. Mattila (2006) 12(2): 247-60.
‘Productive and Contested: Computer Stelling, J., S. Klamt, K. Bettenbrock, S.
Models and Simulations in Scientific Schuster & E.D. Gilles (2002) ‘Meta-
Practice’, Science Studies 19(1): 3-11. bolic network structure determines key
Leonelli, S. (2007) ‘What Is In A Model?’, in aspects of functionality and regulation’,
M. Laubichler & G.B. Müller (eds.), Mod- Nature 420: 190-3.
eling Biology. Structures, Behaviours, Sunberg, M. (2008) ‘The Everyday World of
Evolution (Vienna Series: MIT Press): Simulation Modeling. The Development
15-36. of Parameterizations in Meteorology’,
Leonelli, S. (2009) ‘On the Locality of Data Science, Technology, & Human Values
and Claims about Phenomena’, Philoso- 20(10): 1-20.
phy of Science 76(5): 737-49. Valle, G., M. Helmer Citterich, M. Attimo-
Merz, M. (1999) ‘Multiplex and Unfolding: nelli & G. Pesole (2007) Introduzione alla
Computer Simulation in Particle Phys- bioinformatica (Bologna: Zanichelli).
ics’, Science in Context 12(2): 293-316. Wieber, F. (2009) ‘Theoretical Technologies
Morgan, M.S. & M. Morrison (eds.) (1999) in an “Experimental” Setting: Empirical
Models as mediators: perspectives on Modeling of Proteinic Objects and Sim-
natural and social science (Cambridge: ulation of their Dynamics Within Sci-
Cambridge University Press). entific Collaborations Around a Super-
Negrotti, M. (1997) La terza realtà (Bari: computer’, in: [2009] SPSP 2009: Society
Edizioni Dedalo). for Philosophy of Science in Practice
Pál, C., B. Papp, M.J. Lercher, P. Csermely, (Minnesota, June 18-20, 2009).
S.G. Oliver & L.D. Hurst (2006) ‘Chance Yuh, C.H., H. Bolouri & E.H. Davidson
and necessity in the evolution of mini- (1998) ‘Genomic Cis-regulatory Logic:
mal metabolic networks’, Nature 440: Experimental and Computational Anal-
667-70. ysis of a Sea Urchin Gene’, Science 279:
Papp, B., C. Pál & L.D. Hurst (2004) ‘Meta- 1896-902.
bolic network analysis of the causes and
evolution of enzyme dispensability in Appendix: Lists of the
yeast’, Nature 429: 661-4. analysed papers
Parker, W.S. (2009) ‘Does Matter Really
Matter? Computer Simulations, Experi- 1. H. Jeong, B. Tombor, R. Albert, Z.N.
ments, and Materiality’, Synthese 169(3): Oltvai, A.-L. Barabási (2000) ‘The
483-96. large-scale organization of metabolic
Rheinberger, H.J. (1997) Toward a His- networks’, Nature 407: 651-4 (Letter).
tory of Epistemic Things: Synthesizing 2. Human Genome (2001) ‘A physical
Proteins in the Test Tube (Stanford, CA: map of the human genome’, Nature
Stanford University Press). 409: 934-41.
Rohrlich, F. (1991) ‘Computer Simulation’, 3. Human Genome (2001) ‘Initial
Physical Sciences. Proceedings of the sequencing and analysis of the human
1990 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy genome’, Nature 409: 860-921.
of Science Association 2: 507-18. 4. S.T. Cole, K. Eiglmeier, J. Parkhill, K. D.
Searls, D.B. (2010) ‘The Roots of Bioinfor- James, N.R. Thomson, P.R. Wheeler,
matics’, PLoS Computational Biology N. Honoré, T. Garnier, C. Churcher, D.
6(6): 1-7.

38
Sabrina Moretti

Harris et al. (2001) ‘Massive gene decay 12. J.W. Thomas, J.W. Touchman, R.W.
in the leprosy bacillus’, Nature 409: Blakesley, G.G. Bouffard, S.M.
1007-11. Beckstrom-Sternberg, E.H. Margulies,
5. A.C. Gavin, M. Bösche, R. Krause, M. Blanchette, A.C. Siepel, P.J.
P. Grandi, M. Marzioch, A. Bauer, Thomas, J.C. McDowell et al. (2003)
J. Schultz, J. M. Rick, A.M. Michon, ‘Comparative analyses of multi-species
C.M. Cruciat et al. (2002) ‘Functional sequences from targeted genomic
organization of the yeast proteome regions’, Nature 424: 788-93 (Letter).
by systematic analysis of protein 13. E. Almaas, B. Kovács, T. Vicsek, Z. N.
complexes’, Nature 415: 141-7. Oltvai & A.L. Barabási (2004) ‘Global
6. S.D. Bentley, K.F. Chater, A.M. organization of metabolic fluxes in the
Cerdeño-Tárraga, G.L. Challis, N.R. bacterium Escherichia coli’, Nature 427:
Thomson, K.D. James, D.E. Harris, 839-43 (Letter).
M.A. Quail, H. Kieser, D. Harper et al. 14. M.W. Covert, E.M. Knight, J.L. Reed,
(2002) ‘Complete genome sequence of M.J. Herrgard & B.O. Palsson (2004)
the model actinomycete Streptomyces ‘Integrating high-throughput and
coelicolor’, Nature 417: 141-7. computational data elucidates
7. R.U. Ibarra, J.S. Edwards & B.O. Palsson bacterial networks’, Nature 429: 92-6
(2002) ‘Escherichia coli K-12 undergoes (Letter).
adaptive evolution to achieve in silico 15. J.J. Han, N. Bertin, T. Hao, D.S.
predicted optimal growth’, Nature 420: Goldberg, G.F. Berriz, L.V. Zhang, D.
186-9 (Letter). Dupuy, A.J.M. Walhout, M.E. Cusick,
8. J. Stelling, S. Klamt, K. Bettenbrock, S. F.P. Roth et al. (2004) ‘Evidence for
Schuster & E.D. Gilles (2002) ‘Metabolic dynamically organized modularity in
network structure determines key the yeast protein–protein interaction
aspects of functionality and regulation’, network’, Nature 430: 88-93 (Letter).
Nature 420: 190-3 (Letter). 16. P. Oh, Y. Li, J. Yu, E. Durr, K.M. Krasinska,
9. P. Szabó, I. Scheuring, T. Czárán & E. L.A. Carver, J.E. Testa & J.E. Schnitzer
Szathmáry (2002) ‘In silico simulations (2004) ‘Subtractive proteomic mapping
reveal that replicators with limited of the endothelial surface in lung
dispersal evolve towards higher and solid tumours for tissue-specific
efficiency and fidelity’, Nature 420: 340- therapy’, Nature 429: 629-35.
3 (Letter). 17. B. Papp, C. Pál & L.D. Hurst (2004)
10. The mouse genome (2002) ‘A gene ‘Metabolic network analysis of the
expression map of human chromosome causes and evolution of enzyme
21 orthologues in the mouse’, Nature dispensability in yeast’, Nature 429:
420: 586-90. 661-4 (Letter).
11. R. Heilig, R. Eckenberg, J.L. Petit, N. 18. J. Jaeger, S. Surkova, M. Blagov, H.
Fonknechten, C. Da Silva, L. Cattolico, Janssens, D. Kosman, K.N. Kozlov,
M. Levy, V. Barbe, Véronique de M.E. Myasnikova, C.E. Vanario-Alonso,
Berardinis, A. Ureta-Vidal et al. M. Samsonova et al. (2004) ‘Dynamic
(2003) ‘The DNA sequence and control of positional information in the
analysis of human chromosome’, early Drosophila embryo’, Nature 430:
Nature 421: 601-7. 368-71 (Letter).

39
Science Studies 2/2011

19. X. She, Z. Jiang, R.A. Clark, G. Liu, Z. 26. Y. Zhao, E. Samal & D. Srivastava (2005)
Cheng, E. Tuzun, D.M. Church, G. ‘Serum response factor regulates a
Sutton, A.L. Halpern & E.E. Eichler muscle-specific microRNA that targets
(2004) ‘Shotgun sequence assembly Hand2 during cardiogenesis’, Nature
and recent segmental duplications 436: 214-20.
within the human genome’, Nature 431: 27. E. Dekel & U. Alon (2005) ‘Optimality
927-30. and evolutionary tuning of the
20. J.T. Wade, D.B. Hall & K. Struhl (2004) expression level of a protein’, Nature
‘The transcription factor Ifh1 is a key 436: 588-92 (Letter).
regulator of yeast ribosomal protein 28. International Rice Genome Sequencing
genes’, Nature 432: 1054-8 (Letter). Project (2005) ‘The map-based
21. F. Alvarez-Vasquez, K.J. Sims, L.A. sequence of the rice genome’, Nature
Cowart, Y. Okamoto, E.O. Voit & 436: 793-800.
Y.A. Hannun (2005) ‘Simulation and 29. N.J. Guido, X. Wang, D. Adalsteinsson,
validation of modelled sphingolipid D. McMillen, J. Hasty, C.R. Cantor, T.C.
metabolism in Saccharomyces Elston & J.J. Collins (2006) ‘A bottom-
cerevisiae’, Nature 433: 425-30 (Letter). up approach to gene regulation’, Nature
22. D.B. van Rossum, R.L. Patterson, S. 439: 856-60 (Letter).
Sharma, R.K. Barrow, M. Kornberg 30. R. Broadhead, H.R. Dawe, H.Farr, S.
& D.L. Gill, S.H. Snyder (2005) Griffiths, S.R. Hart, N. Portman, M.K.
‘Phospholipase Cγ1 controls surface Shaw, M.L. Ginger, SJ. Gaskell, P.G.
expression of TRPC3 through an McKean et al. (2006) ‘Flagellar motility
intermolecular PH domain’, Nature is required for the viability of the
434: 99-104 (Letter). bloodstream trypanosome’, Nature 440:
23. L.W. Hillier, T.A. Graves, R.S. Fulton, 224-7 (Letter).
L.A. Fulton, K.H. Pepin, P. Minx, C. 31. C. Pál, B. Papp, M.J. Lercher, P. Csermely,
Wagner-McPherson, D. Layman, S.G. Oliver & L.D. Hurst (2006) ‘Chance
K. Wylie, M. Sekhon et al. (2005) and necessity in the evolution of
‘Generation and annotation of the DNA minimal metabolic networks’, Nature
sequences of human chromosomes 2 440: 667-70 (Letter).
and 4’, Nature 434: 724-31. 32. J. Ashworth, J.J. Havranek, C.M. Duarte,
24. L. Eichinger, J.A. Pachebat, G. D. Sussman, R.J. Monnat, B. L. Stoddard
Glöckner, M.A. Rajandream, R. & D. Baker (2006) ‘Computational
Sucgang, M. Berriman, J. Song, R. redesign of endonuclease DNA binding
Olsen, K. Szafranski, Q. Xu et al. (2005) and cleavage specificity’, Nature 441:
‘The genome of the social amoeba 656-9 (Letter).
Dictyostelium discoideum’, Nature 435: 33. K. Horikawa, K. Ishimatsu, E.
43-57. Yoshimoto, S. Kondo & H. Takeda (2006)
25. C.S. Sullivan, A.T. Grundhoff, S. ‘Noise-resistant and synchronized
Tevethia, J.M. Pipas & D. Ganem (2005) oscillation of the segmentation clock’,
‘SV40-encoded microRNAs regulate Nature 441: 719-23.
viral gene expression and reduce 34. M. Alleman, L. Sidorenko, K. McGinnis,
susceptibility to cytotoxic T cells’, V. Seshadri, J.E. Dorweiler, J. White, K.
Nature 435: 682-6 (Letter). Sikkink & V.L. Chandler (2006) ‘An

40
Sabrina Moretti

RNA-dependent RNA polymerase is 41. The Wellcome Trust Case Control


required for paramutation in maize’, Consortium (2007) ‘Genome-wide
Nature 442: 295-8 (Letter). association study of 14,000 cases of
35. O. Shlyk-Kerner, I. Samish, D. Kaftan, seven common diseases and 3,000
N. Holland, P.S. Maruthi Sai, H. Kless shared controls’, Nature 447: 661-78.
& A. Scherz (2006) ‘Protein flexibility 42. B. Qian, S. Raman, R. Das, P. Bradley,
acclimatizes photosynthetic energy A.J. McCoy, R.J. Read & D. Baker (2007)
conversion to the ambient temperature’, ‘High-resolution structure prediction
Nature 442: 827-30 (Letter). and the crystallographic phase
36. D. Chourrout, F. Delsuc, P. Chourrout, problem’, Nature 450: 259-64.
R.B. Edvardsen, F. Rentzsch, E. Renfer, 43. The International HapMap Consortium
M.F. Jensen, B. Zhu, P. de Jong, R.E. (2007) ‘A second generation human
Steele et al. (2006) ‘Minimal ProtoHox haplotype map of over 3.1 million
cluster inferred from bilaterian and SNPs’, Nature 449: 851-61.
cnidarian Hox complements’, Nature 44. Drosophila 12 Genomes Consortium
442: 684-7 (Letter). (2007) ‘Evolution of genes and genomes
37. S. Leininger, T. Urich, M. Schloter, on the Drosophila phylogeny’, Nature
L. Schwark, J. Qi, G.W. Nicol, J.I. 450: 203-18.
Prosser, S.C. Schuster & C. Schleper 45. K.A. Henzler-Wildman, M. Lei, V. Thai,
(2006) ‘Archaea predominate among S.J. Kerns, M. Karplus & D. Kern (2007)
ammonia-oxidizing prokaryotes in ‘A hierarchy of timescales in protein
soils’, Nature 442: 806-9 (Letter). dynamics is linked to enzyme catalysis’,
38. A. Sigal, R. Milo, A. Cohen, N. Geva- Nature 450: 913-16 (Letter).
Zatorsky, Y. Klein, Y. Liron, N. 46. E. Segal, T. Raveh-Sadka, M. Schroeder,
Rosenfeld, T. Danon, N. Perzov & U. U. Unnerstall & U. Gaul (2008)
Alon (2006) ‘Variability and memory ‘Predicting expression patterns from
of protein levels in human cells’, Nature regulatory sequence in Drosophila
444: 643-6 (Letter). segmentation’, Nature 451: 535-40.
39. E.S. Lein, M.J. Hawrylycz, N. Ao, M. 47. J.M. Carlton, J.H. Adams, J.C. Silva, S.L.
Ayres, A. Bensinger, A. Bernard, A.F. Bidwell, H. Lorenzi, E. Caler, J. Crabtree,
Boe, M.S. Boguski, K.S. Brockway, E.J. S.V. Angiuoli, E.F. Merino, P. Amedeo et
Byrnes et al. (2006) ‘Genome-wide al. (2008) ‘Comparative genomics of
atlas of gene expression in the adult the neglected human malaria parasite
mouse brain’, Nature 445: 168-76. Plasmodium vivax’, Nature 455: 757-63.
40. T.S. Mikkelsen, M.J. Wakefield, B. Aken, 48. H. Zheng, H. Ying, H. Yan, A.C.
C.T. Amemiya, J.L. Chang, S. Duke, M. Kimmelman, D.J. Hiller, A.J. Chen, S.R.
Garber, A.J. Gentles, L. Goodstadt, A. Perry, G. Tonon, G.C. Chu, Z. Ding et al.
Heger et al. (2007) ‘Genome of the (2008) ‘p53 and Pten control neural and
marsupial Monodelphis domestica glioma stem/progenitor cell renewal
reveals innovation in non-coding and differentiation’, Nature 455: 1129-
sequences’, Nature 447: 167-77. 33 (Letter).

41
Science Studies 2/2011

By means of the text analysis, these papers The papers 27, 38, 42 describe some
are classified in two types. The papers 2, particular applications that we can not
3, 4, 5, 6, 10, 11, 12, 16, 19, 20, 22, 23, 24, classify in any defined typology.
25, 26, 28, 30, 34, 35, 36, 37, 39, 40, 41, 43,
44, 47, 48 belong to Type 1. Sabrina Moretti
Universiy of Urbino
The papers 1, 7, 8, 9, 13, 14, 15, 17, 18, 21, 29, Via Saffi, 15, 61029 Urbino, Italy
31, 32, 33, 45, 46 belong to Type 2. sabrina.moretti@uniurb.it

42

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen