Sie sind auf Seite 1von 6

SparkNotes: Politics: Book I about:reader?url=https://www.sparknotes.

com/philosophy/politics/section1/

sparknotes.com

by: Aristotle
3 minutes

Summary

Aristotle defines the polis, or city, as a koinonia, or political


association, and he asserts that all such associations, like all
deliberate human acts, are formed with the aim of achieving some
good. He adds that political association is the most sovereign form
of association since it incorporates all other forms of association
and aims at the highest good.

The different kinds of associations that exist are founded on


different kinds of relationships. The basic unit of association is the
household, the next is the village, and the ultimate association is
the city, toward which end humans, seeking to attain the highest
quality of life, naturally move. Aristotle concludes, "man is by nature
a political animal." Only as part of a city can people fully realize
their nature; separated from the city, they are worse than animals.

Aristotle identifies the three kinds of relationships that make up the


household: master-slave; husband-wife; and parent-child. He also
identifies a fourth element of the household, which he calls the "art
of acquisition."

Aristotle views slaves as the means by which the master secures

1 of 2 10/06/19, 5:51 p.m.


SparkNotes: Politics: Book I about:reader?url=https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/politics/section1/

his livelihood. He defends slavery by noting that nature generally


consists of ruling and ruled elements: some people are slaves by
nature, while others are masters by nature. It is thus unjust to
enslave, through war or other means, those who are not slaves by
nature. Though being suited to mastery or slavery is generally
inherited, slavery is just only when the rule of master over slave is
beneficial for both parties.

Aristotle likens the relationship between master and slave to that


between soul and body: the master possesses rational,
commanding powers, while the slave, lacking these, is fit only to
carry out menial duties. He also likens the relationship between
master and slave to that between a monarch and his people and
that between a statesman and free citizens.

Aristotle examines the art of acquisition, which pertains to the


satisfaction of basic needs, distinguishing between natural and
unnatural acquisition. Different people go about satisfying these
needs in different ways, depending on their mode of life: some are
farmers, some hunter-gatherers, and some pirates or freebooters,
etc. This securing of food, shelter, and other necessities is called
natural acquisition because it is an indispensable part of the
management of a household.

2 of 2 10/06/19, 5:51 p.m.


SparkNotes: Politics: Book I, page 2 about:reader?url=https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/politics/sectio...

sparknotes.com

by: Aristotle
4-5 minutes

Unnatural acquisition, on the other hand, consists of accumulating


money for its own sake. Aristotle observes that goods such as food
and clothing have not only a use-value, but also an exchange-
value. In societies where trade is common, a monetary currency
naturally arises as a facilitator of exchange. The aim of exchange is
the accumulation of such currency—i.e., the production of monetary
wealth rather than the natural acquisition of goods. Aristotle further
dislikes this accumulation of currency because there is no limit to
the amount of currency one can accumulate, leading people to
indulge in an excess of enjoyment.

Aristotle addresses the household relationships of husband-and-


wife and father- and-child. The former relationship resembles that
of the statesman to his people in that the husband and wife share
the same free (i.e., not slave) nature; that the male, by his nature, is
more fit than the female to command, justifies the fact that it is the
husband, not the wife, who rules the household. The latter
relationship resembles that of the king to his subjects, as the father
rules by virtue of his children's love for him and their respect of his
age. The respective virtues of master, wife, child, and slave vary in
aim and measure according to the different roles these individuals
fulfill.

1 of 3 10/06/19, 5:51 p.m.


SparkNotes: Politics: Book I, page 2 about:reader?url=https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/politics/sectio...

Analysis

Much of Aristotle's political philosophy is based on the idea of


teleology—that everything in nature exists for a specific purpose.
His ##Nicomachean Ethics##, which in many ways parallels the
Politics, argues that the end goal of human existence is happiness
and that this happiness involves the human faculty of reason. The
Politics is largely an attempt to determine what kind of political
association is best suited for securing happiness for its citizens.

Ancient Greece was divided into small city-states, and these poleis
meant much more to their inhabitants than modern cities do to
theirs. The interests of a polis and those of its citizens were seen as
identical, since both city and man aimed for happiness. Thus, the
concept of an opposition between individual rights or freedoms and
the laws of city or state did not exist in ancient Greece.

Aristotle's belief that man can only become fully human when he
engages in the political association of the city is a strongly
communitarian view that would meet with heavy opposition from
libertarian thinkers. By asserting that man fails to fulfill his ultimate
purpose when he is disconnected from the state, Aristotle is not
simply arguing that the laws of the state should restrict man's
freedom; he is arguing also that life has no value outside the
confines of the state.

The polis that Aristotle so admires could only exist with the heavy
exploitation of slave labor, so Aristotle's defense of the institution of
slavery is not surprising. His arguments in support of slavery are a
bit confused and sometimes even contradictory, as he seems to
attribute some amount of rationality to slaves while simultaneously
denying that they possess any. His argument rests on the idea that

2 of 3 10/06/19, 5:51 p.m.


SparkNotes: Politics: Book I, page 2 about:reader?url=https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/politics/sectio...

there exist "natural slaves," people who lack rationality and so


cannot properly exercise their own freedom; it is beneficial for such
individuals to be enslaved, since their master can supply the
rationality that they lack. The problem with this argument, however,
is that slaves must necessarily have some kind of rationality if they
are to follow orders and respond to commands. Aristotle almost
admits as much at, though he doesn't seem to recognize the full
implications of this concession: if slaves have rational minds, then
they are not "natural slaves" and thus, according to Aristotle, should
not be enslaved.

3 of 3 10/06/19, 5:51 p.m.


SparkNotes: Politics: Book I, page 3 https://www.sparknotes.com/philosophy/politics/section1/page/3/

2 of 3 10/06/19, 5:52 p.m.